Journal of Public Economics A Coasean regulation 53 (1994) 459475. general North-Holland equilibrium model of Karen Clay* Department of Economics, Stanlord University, Stanford. CA 94305, USA Received June 1990, final version received July 1992 Although marginal cost pricing is necessary for welfare maximization, firms that produce under conditions of decreasing average cost incur losses if they price at marginal cost. In this paper, the Coase two-part tariN is extended to several cases of common costs by assessing surplus in order to recover the losses of the regulated natural monopolist; the existence of equilibria in these cases is demonstrated. Three models are considered in the context of an Arrow-Debreu private ownership economy: a model of the regulated monopolist who charges hookups to both households and iirms who use the good; a model of the regulated natural monopolist who is allowed to make positive economic profit; and finally a model where two or more monopolists are under the control of a single regulator. 1. Introduction During the marginal cost pricing controversy of the 1930s and 194Os, the issue of pricing in industries with declining average costs was hotly debated, because these firms could not price at marginal cost without incurring losses. Dominant in the discussion of pricing of decreasing average cost goods has been the view that prices should be set at marginal cost and the losses should be covered by the government through taxation; this view is evident in the works of Dickenson, Lerner, Meade, Lange, Hotelling, Troxel, Reder, and Vickrey.’ Not all of the participants in the early debate favored government taxation; prominent among this group were Lewis (1941) and Coase (1946). Coase was concerned with two-part pricing when the overhead was composed of individually assignable costs and vigorously attacked the notion of Correspondence to: Karen Clay, Department of Economics, Stanford University, Stanford, CA 94305, USA. *I am pleased to acknowledge the comments and remarks of Ken Arrow, Aaron Edlin, Mario Eppelbaum, Peter Hammond, Chiaki Moriguchi, participants in the General Equilibrium Seminar, and of two anonymous referees. I am indebted to Don Brown for many useful discussions. This research was supported in part by the National Science Foundation. ‘This debate is excellently surveyed by Nancy Ruggles in a pair of articles entitled ‘The welfare basis of the marginal cost pricing principle’ (1949) and ‘Recent developments in the theory of marginal cost pricing’ (1950). 0047-2727/94/$07.00 0 1994 Elsevier Science B.V. All rights reserved SSDI 0047-2727(93)01353-X 460 K. Clay, A Coasean general equilibrium model of regulation covering the losses through government taxation. Indeed, all of the modern general equilibrium literature on marginal cost pricing with government taxation has been put forth despite the damning criticism of marginal cost pricing found in Coase’s seminal paper. Coase’s objections to marginal cost pricing were threefold: it distorts resource allocation; it redistributes income; and it creates additional distortions by requiring taxation to cover the losses. Recall the problem that Coase considered. Assume that consumers are situated around a central market in which a certain product is available at constant prices. Assume that roads run out from the central market but that each road passes only one consumer of the product. Assume also that a carrier can carry on each journey additional units of the product at no additional cost (at least to a point beyond the limit of consumption of any individual consumer). Assume further that the product is sold at the point of consumption. It is clear that the cost of supplying each individual consumer would be the cost of the carrier plus the cost at the central market of the number of units consumed by that particular consumer of the product. The marginal cost would be equai to the cost of a unit of the product at the central market. The average cost would be higher than the marginal cost and would decline as the cost of the carrier was spread over an increasing number of units [Coase (1946, p. 171)]. Coase argued that the Hotelling-Lerner approach was subject to the above criticisms and suggested instead a two-part pricing structure where the consumer paid the assignable fixed costs for any units he chose to buy at marginal cost. Coase stated at the end of his article that the next step was to examine the problem of two-part pricing when there are common costs. The modern literature has examined existence and optimality of marginal cost pricing with government taxation and two-part pricing in economies where firms may exhibit decreasing average costs. Marginal cost pricing with government taxation was utilized in the sophisticated proofs of existence found in works by Mantel (1979), Beato and Mas-Cole11 (1985), Brown et al. (1986) and Bonniseau and Cornet (1988). In this class of Arrow-Debreu private ownership economies with one or more non-convex production sets, the lump-sum taxation is effected through unlimited liability holdings in the firms with non-convex technologies. Guesnerie (1975), Brown and Heal (1979) Dierker (1986) and Quinzii (1991) considered the issue of optimality. Results on optimality have been rather dismal, not only is marginal cost pricing not sufficient for allocative efficiency (Guesnerie, Brown and Heal), but there are efficient allocations which cannot be supported as marginal cost pricing equilibria without resorting to lump-sum transfers (Quinzii, Dierker). K. Clay, A Coasean general equilibrium model qfregulation 461 Another criticism beyond Coase’s criticisms can be levelled against the modern implementation of marginal cost pricing where losses are covered by lump-sum taxation. An allocation may not be individually rational in the sense that after the tax, the individual may no longer be able to afford his endowment, if he is endowed with goods, or a zero net trade vector, if he is endowed with production sets2 In examples given by Guesnerie and Brown and Heal, where marginal cost pricing is not efficient, one individual, the one who does not own the firm, is able to appropriate all of the gains from production and part of the endowment of the other agent by forcing him to cover the losses of the firm. In the Brown and Heal example, we note that lack of individual rationality precludes efficiency. In the production equilibrium, by returning the first individual, the owner of the firm, to his reservation utility level as defined by his original endowment, we can guarantee that the marginal cost pricing equilibrium is efficient. An example given in Vohra (1988) has production equilibria which, if actually implemented, would guarantee negative income to one individual; thus, it is not surprising that no marginal cost pricing equilibria are efficient. Two-part pricing avoids the problem of individual rationality by only imposing the costs of the firm on consumers of the product; thus, consumers always have the option of consuming their endowment. More recently the literature has turned to two-part pricing in an effort both to be more realistic and to avoid some of the undesirable properties mentioned above. Work on existence has been quite successful. Vohra (1990) provides a proof of existence for two-part marginal cost pricing equilibria in a two-good model where non-convexities are due to a fixed start-up cost. Brown et al. (1992) prove existence of two-part marginal cost pricing equilibria in a general equilibrium setting for general non-convexities. Work on optimality was initially far less successful. Early work by Quinzii demonstrated that some Pareto-efficient allocations cannot be supported as two-part marginal cost pricing equilibria. Brown et al. (1992) showed that the first and second welfare theorems fail in general, but that the second welfare theorem holds if there is sufficient willingness to pay. Vohra (1990) provided a variety of examples which illustrated important ways in which efficiency fails for two-part tariffs. However, recently Moriguchi (1991) has been able to demonstrate that for the case where the non-convexity is due to pure fixed costs and where no consumer is endowed with the monopoly good, first best is achieved. ‘We define individual rationality with reference to the individual being allowed to consume his endowment without taxation. We assume in our models that utilize two-part pricing and in the following discussion that no consumer is endowed with the monopoly good. If for some reason they are endowed with the monopoly good as in Vohra (1990). then individual rationality, as defined here, may not hold even under two-part pricing. However. for the types of goods that we have in mind, such as electricity, sewers, postal service, and telephone service, the assumption that the individuals is not endowed with the monopoly good is appropriate. 462 K. Clay, A Coasean general equilibrium model of regulation Despite the general lack of efficiency, except in the special case of pure fixed cost, we present this work on existence in these models because of its positive worth, and in the hope that subsequent welfare analysis might build upon it. This paper is a natural extension of Coase’s work to common costs in a general equilibrium framework. Similar to Coase, we use a two-part tariff structure where households and firms pay hookup fees to cover the losses of the decreasing average cost firms. However, unlike Coase, the costs in the models are common costs, and thus hookup fees are based on the surplus of each household or firm. In order to explore a Coasean model of regulation, we build upon earlier work by Brown et al. (1992). The models that we examine are standard Arrow-Debreu private ownership economies where convex firms maximize profits, and households maximize utility subject to a budget constraint. In addition, we have added non-convex firms that price at marginal cost. Nonconvex firms are assumed to be regulated natural monopolies and individuals are endowed with shares of the monopoly. These shares carry limited liability rather than the unlimited liability assumed when losses are covered by lumpsum taxation. Losses are covered by imposing assessments on the surpluses of the households and the convex lirms.3 The surplus is the compensating variation or willingness to pay for use of the monopoly good. The definition of consumer surplus that we utilize is from Brown et al. (1992) and is the same definition utilized by Roberts (1979) to define his license or hookup fee. This concept of consumer surplus is also implicit in the pioneering work of Oi (1971) on the Disneyland monopolist. Assessing consumer surplus in this manner has two desirable characteristics: it is both individually rational, a consumer can avoid the charge by not buying the good, and it is based on an unalterable characteristic of the consumer, consumer surplus. Furthermore, the assessment will be paid voluntarily by any consumer who has positive consumer surplus, because he is always left with positive surplus after the assessment has been paid. This paper presents existence results for three distinct models. The first is for a single non-convex firm that prices at marginal cost and charges hookups for both households and firms. The second is for a monopolist who is allowed to make positive economic profits. In the limiting case this monopolist behaves as an almost-perfectly-discriminating monopolist. The third case is a model with two monopolies under the control of a single regulator. None of the foregoing analysis is captured by the earlier work on two-part pricing. These models were constructed to reflect institutional arrangements that we observe in modern market economies of most OECD countries. Both households and firms pay hookups to telephone companies jThe word surplus here is used loosely. Surplus as we detine it below is a measure of the willingness to pay to use the monopoly good and not the standard delinition of consumer surplus. K. Clay, A Coasean general equilibrium model 01 regulation 463 for local service; a cable television company which contracts with a locality may be allowed to make positive economic profits; and many areas have electricity, water, gas and sewage under the control of a local utilities board. Section 2 contains the models and the proofs are found in the appendix. 2. The models The first model considers existence of a two-part marginal cost pricing equilibrium (TPMCPE) where the monopolist is allowed to charge hookups to both households and firms. Hookups are charged in proportion to the surplus that households and firms derive from use of the monopoly goods. The second model allows a single regulated monopolist to earn positive profits. The monopolist is regulated in two senses: first he is required to price at marginal cost; second he is only allowed to extract a fixed amount of surplus, which is used here as a proxy for rate of return. We consider the case where the natural monopolist is allowed to take all but E of each household’s willingness to pay. We demonstrate the existence of an equilibrium where the monopolist takes within 1 --F of the surplus, for all E which are sufficiently small. The third model extends earlier results for a single monopolist to a case where two monopolists with increasing returns operate in the market and each monopolist charges households an individualized hookup. In this model, a regulator divides the total surplus between the monopolists according to properties of willingness to pay for each good individually and for the two goods jointly. The model allows for production of both goods as long as the aggregate willingness to pay for each good, relative to its surplus, is sufficient to cover its losses. We show that because each consumer knows which goods she is consuming and each monopolist knows her surplus, an equilibrium exists. 2.1. Firms and households This paper builds on results found in work by Brown et al. (1992) who considered existence and optimality for a model where a single natural monopoly prices at marginal cost and charges only households for hookups. We present a model that is more descriptively accurate, because it incorporates hookups for both households and firms. The compelling reason to assess both households and firms is potential welfare gains. If we assess all consumers, more revenue can be generated than by assessing households alone. Consider a case where a firm is charged a hookup fee of one dollar. If we allow this dollar to be passed back to the household in the form of protits, she divides the expenditure between private and monopoly goods. By assessing the household, we can recover less than one dollar, because we are 464 K. Clay, A Coasean general equilibrium model of regulation restricted to levying benefits due to consumption of monopoly goods. If the monopoly good is only an intermediate good, not consumed by households, then the only means to cover the losses of the monopoly is to charge firms hookup fees. Thus, monopolies with higher losses can be sustained in our models by charging both firms and households hookup fees. Furthermore, supporting these monopolies may be efficient due to the fact that household willingness to pay is always less than or equal to total surplus; so, it may be desirable from a welfare viewpoint to use this additional mechanism to extract more surplus.’ Moreover, depending on how she measures welfare, a planner may also want to utilize differential assessment of households and firms as a policy tool. In the analysis to this point, we have assumed that when faced with hookups, consumers in fact pay the hookups and consume the monopoly good. As was noted above, if households and firms have positive surplus and the fractions of the surplus taken from the firms and from the households are strictly less than one, then households and firms are left with positive surplus after paying the hookup and would strictly prefer to consume. If households and firms have zero surplus, then they do not pay a hookup charge. Allowing surplus to be extracted from both households and firms makes it necessary to define surplus for the households in two ways. First we define household surplus given that all of the surplus from the firms has been extracted by the monopolist. We use this definition in condition (S) to ensure that there is sufficient surplus in the economy to cover the fixed costs of production of the monopoly good. Then we must define household surplus conditional on the amount of surplus extracted from the firms because this affects the profits that the consumers receive through their shareholdings. These surpluses define a one-parameter family of assessments on households and firms which will cover any losses. The first part of the proof demonstrates that the set of all production equilibria is non-empty. The second part shows that aggregate demand is continuous on the set of all production equilibria. Finally, we use a fixed-point argument to demonstrate the existence of an equilibrium. 2.1.1. Firms We begin by describing the production assumptions found here originated in Beato side of the economy. The and Mas-Cole11 and are the “Willingness to pay as detined below is equivalent to compensating variation. Compensating variation has been shown to underestimate true consumer surplus. As was rightly pointed out by a referee, one might inadvertently support enterprises that were not ellicient by effectively taking too much surplus. This point is a reason to exercise caution when supporting firms that are making losses and is not a reason to assess only households. K. Clap, A Coasean general equilibrium model same assumptions found in Bonniseau assume that the production possibilities tion sets Ys satisfying: (Fl) Y’=Kf-Ry’, (F2) K* is convex (F3) Output of firm 0, the monopoly other firm. (F4) and Cornet and may be described Brown by Ft 465 et al. We 1 produc- where K’ is compact. for 1 sf 5 F. firm, cannot be produced by any The pricing rule is given by @: 6Y/ + A, where A is the unit simplex in Re+l cone with the 4” is the intersection of the Clarke normal simplex, and 6Yf is the boundary of Y’. (Fl)+F4) (F5) qf regulation imply (F5). There exists an r>O such that for all f, K* is contained in the interior of {-re}+Ry’, where e=(l,l,...,l). If y{s-r and PEAR, then pk=o. Define a production equilibrium to be a pair ( y, p), where for all f, yf E 6 Ys and PE@“( yf). Let PE denote the set of all production equilibria. The single monopoly produces at a feasible production plan y” and sells good 0 to households and firms. We define the profits made by firm 0 at the production plan y” as UO( y”, P, 4) = .qh + w + P YO, (1) where q is the hookup fee paid by households and firms. However, the firm is only allowed to use q to recover losses. Thus U”( y”,p, q) = max(O,p. y”) and so we can drop the dependence on q and write lI”( yO,p). 2.1.2. Households Now we turn to the consumption side of the economy. There are H households that are fully characterized by their endowments wh, shareholdings in firms Oh’, consumption sets Xh, and utility functions Uh. We will make the standard neoclassical assumptions: (Hl) R$+’ 3 Xh is a non-empty, closed, convex (H2) No one needs monopoly goods (0, x’~) E Xh, where k 2 1 * xLh=x:. set which is bounded to survive. That below. is, for all xh~Xh, 466 K. Clay, A Coasean general equilibrium model of regulation (H3) Uh is continuous. (H4) Uh is strictly (H5) We assume the natural households quasi-concave. limited liability for shareholders in all firms. Any losses of monopoly will be recovered by hookup fees paid by and firms. Each household has Ohf shares in firm f for where CO hf = 1 and OhI 2 0 for all h, f. f=O,...,F, (H6) Households have no endowment of the monopoly good. Define A(w) as A(w)={((P),( yf))E17xh x 17yCZxh~Zwh+Cyf}. (2) We must show that A(w) is compact in order to show that the attainable consumption sets, proj A(w) n Xh, are compact. We need only show that (ZWh + Cy”) A Re,+ l is compact since Cxh sCwh + CyJ. By definition Yf = KS- R/;t ‘, CKJ is compact, and the intersection with Ryl is compact. Thus, A(w) is compact and the attainable consumption sets, denoted Xh, are compact. Define Xh as Xh n Q, where Q is a large compact ‘box’ which contains all of the attainable consumption sets, Xh, in the interior. 2.1.3. Willingness to pa) Define the firm’s willingness to pay for use of the monopoly good as s’( y, p) = Z7/( y, p) -IF/*( y, p), where I7/ is the maximum profit given that the firm may use the monopoly good in production and IT” is the maximum profit when the firm does not use the monopoly good. Define i as the fraction of surplus taken from the firms by the monopolist, where i E [0,1). Now we will define the household’s willingness to pay for the monopoly good. Define llh as total household dividends, P( y, p, A) = oh0 P( y”, p) + C@(( 1 - lL)Hf( y, p) + 3JIf’( y, p)). (3) Define income of household h as rh( y, p, A), where rh( y,p, A) = p. wh + IZh( y,p, 2). Define expenditures as qh +p’ xh, if xt >O, where qh is the hookup budget for the monopoly good, and as p. xh, if xt = 0. Define the household correspondence, Bh( y, p, q), as follows: Bh(y,p,ii)={~h~Xh(p.~h~p.~h+17h(y,p,I.)if~hg=0, orqh(y,p,A)+p~xhSp.wh+Z7h(y,p,A)ifx~>0}. The minimum expenditure at prices p necessary to (4) reach utility Oh is K. Claq’, A Coasean general equilibrium model @’regulation 467 denoted by _i?‘(p, a”), where oh is defined as utility maximized subject to xh E Xh, satisfaction of the budget constraint, and zero consumption of the monopoly good. Then willingness to pay, gh, is defined as sh( y,p, 2) = rh( y,p, A)-Eh(p, oh). The special case where all of the profits resulting from the use of the good are taken from the firm is defined as Sh( y,p) =gh( y,p, 1). Assume that there is always enough surplus at all production equilibria from households and firms to cover any losses of the non-convex firm, (S) 32~ [0,1) such that for all production y,p)> -min(p.y,,O). equilibria, ( y,p) E PE, CSh( y,p) + lCs’( Define /?( y,p, A) to be the fraction of surplus taken from the households, where jl(y,p,i.) =( -min(p.y”,O)-i.CsJ(y,p))/Cs”h( y,p, A). Note that a priori j3(y,p, 3.) could be either positive or negative. However, we are going to restrict attention to the case where both households and firms pay nonnegative hookups. This assumption constrains the choice of ~-E[O, 1) to 2 which satisfy Es/( y, p) 2 -min(p y”, 0), and therefore, /?( y, p, A) E [0,1). Assumption (S) guarantees that at least one such pair ()_,/I( y,p,3.)) exists. The hookup fee ftir household h is q”( J: p, A), where qh( y,p, 2) = b( y,p,2)sh( y,p,i.), and the hookup fee for ,jrm .f’ is q’( y,p, A), where qf( Y,P,4=@(Y>P). Assume that surplus (N) is increasing dSh/drh >O for all households with income, h and dsf/dUJ >O for all firms.’ This normality assumption rules out the case where, if we allow the households or firms to keep a positive fraction of their willingness to pay, their surplus could fall to the point where they are no longer willing to pay the hookup fee. This assumption is used in the last part of the proof to demonstrate that, even though we treated the hookup charges as lump-sum, consumers and firms would pay them voluntarily. We make the following assumptions on the set of production equilibria: (SA) For every production equilibrium ( y,p) E PE,p(Cy” + Zwh) > infp. Cgh. We assume that there is more than enough aggregate income to purchase consumption goods which will allow households to survive. (R) For every production equilibrium ( y, p) E PE, rh( y, p) > inf(p zh). Here we assume that each household has enough income to survive without consuming the monopoly good. ‘Thanks are due to Aaron Edlin and Mario Eppelbaum for pointing out that this assumption was necessary in order to prove existence. The interested reader is referred to Edlin and Eppelbaum (1990), where this notion of normality was developed to deal with similar problems. 468 K. Clay, A Coasean general equilibrium model of regulation A two-part marginal cost pricing equilibrium is defined as a vector of prices consumption plans and production plans (p,(Xh),( jf)) such that, (a) households are maximizing utility subject to their budget constraint, (b) firms 1,. . , F maximize profits at prices p, (c) p E +/( y’) for all S (d) - min(p . Y’, 0) = &“( (e) CXh = CJf + Cwh. Theorem 1. there exists Moreover, Y, P, 3.) + -Q/t Y, P, 3.L Given assumptions (Hl)-(H6), (Fl)+FS), (SA), (R), (S), and (N), a TPMCPE where both firms and households pay hookups. in this equilibrium the monopoly Proof: The proofs for this and are located in the appendix. 2.2. Monopoly is producing. all subsequent theorems and propositions profits Recall that both Roberts and Oi considered partial equilibrium models in which a perfectly-discriminating monopolist extracted all of the consumer surplus from each individual. We demonstrate that we can allow our regulated monopolist to act as an almost-perfectly-discriminating monopolist in much the same manner. There is a subtle difference between our monopolist and 02s Disneyland monopolist - we cannot allow the regulated monopolist to extract all of the consumer surplus. If the monopolist extracted all of the surplus, consumers would then be indifferent between entering and not entering Disneyland, and demand correspondences would be non-convex which would vitiate a proof of existence for any economy with a finite number of consumers. The reasons to allow our regulated monopolist to make positive profits are both positive and normative. We observe that natural monopolies, such as public utilities, are frequently allowed to have non-zero rates of return. Furthermore, if non-convex tirms are allowed to make positive profits, the profit level is an additional policy tool that can be utilized to effect the income distribution. These policy tools are especially relevant if we are trying to decentralize a Pareto-optimal allocation without resorting to lump-sum transfers. Now suppose that we allow the regulated monopolist to make a profit by acting as an almost-perfectly-discriminating monopolist. For ease of exposition, we consider the case where only the households pay hookups. We must account for the circular flow of income whereby the monopolist returns the profits to shareholders which further increases the amount of surplus. First, we show that by putting restrictions on the utility functions, there are K. Clay, A Coasean general equilibrium 469 model of regulation equilibrium levels of income. Then, we prove that for every E sufficiently small, if the monopolist takes 1 --E of the surplus, an equilibrium exists. If the monopolist is allowed to take all of the surplus, consumers will be strictly indifferent between consuming the monopoly good and not consuming it. However, for every E>O the consumers will strictly prefer to consume the monopoly good. Firms, households, willingness to pay Assume (Fl)+FS), (Hl)gH6), (SA), and (R). Note that the household surplus, sh( y,p), is just the case where ,I=0 from the previous model, i.e. sh( y, p) = gh( y, p, 0). Furthermore, assume (N’) dsh/drh > 0 for all households h. (S’) For all production ( y, p) E PE, Cs”( y,p) > -min(py’, equilibria 0). Define the hookup as a fraction 2~ [a, 1) such that ish( y,p) =qh. We only consider hookups over this set to guarantee that, for any production equilibrium in PE that we choose, there will be sufficient surplus to ensure production of the monopoly good. We demonstrate in Proposition 1 that a lower bound a exists. Proposition I. 3~ E [0,1) 3 V( y, p) E PE, crIsh( y, p) 2 - min(p . y”, 0). In order to ensure that a fixed point exists, we must define the upper limit on the amount of profits our natural monopoly can make. The upper bound is defined in Proposition 2. Proposition 2. The maximum possible profit of the natural monopoly, which we will denote IT*. is bounded. Theorem 2. Gioen assumptions (Hl)+H6), (Fl)<FS), (SA), (R), (S’), and (N’), for all AE [cr, l), there exists a TPMCPE where the monopolist extracts ,I of the surplus, and moreover, the monopoly is producing. 2.3. Two monopolists with a regulator Both descriptively and from a welfare standpoint it is attractive to have a model with more than one monopolist. Consider an economy of convex firms and no monopolists. Suppose that there are two candidate monopolists which we might permit to operate. We will define two goods as being complements (substitutes) if the aggregate amount of benefits is larger (smaller) than the sum of benefits to each good individually. Suppose thzt J.P.E. F 470 K. Clay, A Coasean general equilibrium model of regulation the two monopolies are complements, and while the sum of benefits to each good individually is not sufficient to cover their respective tixed costs, that the aggregate benefit is sufficient to support production. From a welfare standpoint, we would want to consider producing both goods. Similarly we can imagine situations where either of two monopolies could be selfsupporting, but, because the goods are substitutes, both cannot be supported. We consider the special case where there is sufficient surplus to produce both goods, although the goods many be either complements or substitutes. The model focuses on the allocation of surplus to the monopolists and the subsequent setting of hookup fees. The situation that we consider here is one where the natural monopolies are both under the control of a regulator who guarantees that both goods are produced if there is sufficient surplus to cover the fixed costs of both firms. One typical example is that the electricity, gas and water utilities in many communities are grouped together under the control of one agency. Another example was the control of both mail delivery and package delivery by the United States Postal Service prior to the entry of private firms such as United Parcel Service, Federal Express and others. 2.3.1. Firms, households, willingness to pay The assumptions on the production sector are analogous to above but now there are two monopoly firms which we denote firm 01 and firm 02. The assumptions on the consumption sector are the same as above. Now we define willingness to pay for the household. Recall that income is defined as rh( y”, p) =p . wh + COhoZ7’( y”, p) + COhfZI/(p), where Ill(p) is the maximized profits of firm f. The minimum expenditure at prices p necessary to reach utility 8:,, is denoted by Eh(p, i?:,,), where u:,, is defined as utility maximized subject to feasibility, the budget constraint, and x&=0 for i= 1,2. The minimum expenditure at prices p necessary to reach utility 0: is denoted by Eh(p, u!), where ir: is defined as utility maximized subject to feasibility, the budget constraint, and x&=0, where [i] denotes the other good. Define the surplus if both monopoly goods are consumed relative to consuming neither good as s: 2( y, p) = rh( y, p) - Eh(p, V”,, 2), where sh is willingness to pay. Define individual surpluses as before, i.e. consuming one good relative to consuming neither good as s:( y, p) = rh( y, p) - Eh(p, 0:) and similarly, s”,(y,p) = rh( y, p) - E:(p, 0;). Consider the following two cases: (1) s:2(y~P)2s:(Y>P)fsh2(Y~P). This corresponds to the case where the goods are complements. (2) s:,(Y,P)4(Y>P)+sh,(y,P). K. Clay, A Coasean general equilibrium model of regulation 471 This corresponds to the case where the goods are substitutes. We consider the cases of complements and substitutes separately and assume that a given good is either a substitute or a complement for all households and for all production equilibria. (MM) Assume that either (1) ~:~(y,p)Zs:( y,p)+sh,(y,p), Vh,V( y,p)ePE, or (2) s’L( Y, PI < $ ( Y, P) +s”,( Y, P), % W Y, PI E PE. 2.3.2. Complements Define the surplus s$, where that each monopolist s:*=s:+0.5(s:,-s: s;* = s; + 0.5($, can extract in case 1 as s:. and -&, -s: - s”,). This is a continuous division of the surplus such that each monopolist gets at least as much surplus as he would singly. Note that the individual will always consume both goods because even if neither of the goods is desirable by itself, (e.g. As:, >s:) the goods are jointly desirable because st2 >,I$. + AS”,.. Furthermore, if one good is desirable (e.g. L$.Zs:), then the second is always desirable because, by definition, ,L$ < st 2 - s:il. We define aggregate surplus as the sum of the individual surpluses, so s’ = cs:, and S2 = Cs’&. Thus we define the fraction of the surplus that monopolists 01 and 02 take as %(y,p) = -min(p, yy,O)/S’ and p( y,p) = -min(p2yi,0)/S2, respectively. Assume (SA) and (R). (N”) d.$/drh > 0 for i = 1,2 and ds: 2/drh > 0, for all households (S”) For all production S2(y,p)> equilibria, ( y, p) E PE, S’( y, p) > - min(p, yy, 0) and -min(p2y%W Define the hookups as qh’(yTp)=~(yTp)s?4y,p) p( y,p)s’&( y,p). Note that these hookups are continuous tinuous functions and are therefore continuous. 2.3.3. Substitutes This is a more difficult case following additional assumption. (C) h. The aggregate surpluses than complements. and qh2(y,p)= functions of con- We need S’( y,p) and S2( y,p) are continuous to make on ( y,p). the 412 K. Clay, A Coasean general equilibrium model of regulation As above, we need the aggregate surpluses to be continuous so that the hookups are continuous. Above we got this simply by having an excess of surplus. Here there are several possible ways to generate this outcome. First, we could always have consumers consume both goods even if they are nearly perfect substitutes. This assumption is counterintuitive and poses severe restrictions on the amount of surplus that can be extracted, as is noted in Edlin and Eppelbaum (1990). Second, we could have the consumer consume only one good but restrict the agent to consume the same good over all ( y,p). Again this restriction is very severe because agents might want to switch between goods, but would not be allowed to do so. The most natural way to motivate the assumption is to allow consumers to consume only one good, but to switch between goods over ( y, p). and to assume that there is a continuum of agents so that switching does not induce discontinuities in the aggregate surplus. Allowing consumers to switch between goods is more realistic than the first two assumptions. Furthermore, this assumption seems to be implicit in models such as telecommunication demand where a switch by the marginal customer in a large population is not significant. In any case, the hookups are well defined and are continuous. Theorem 3. Given assumptions (H l)+H6), (Fl)-(F5), (SA), (R), (S”), (N”), (MM), and (C) there exists a TPMCPE with two monopolies where the goods are either complements or substitutes. Moreover, in this equilibrium both of the monopolies are producing. Appendix This work is an extension of Brown et al. (1992). As such, we refer the reader to their paper for the details of the proof. We will only present details to the extent that our proof differs substantially from theirs. to show that the set of all Proof of Theorem 1. First, it is necessary production equilibria is non-empty. Next one must show that aggregate demand is continuous on PE. fih( y, p, A), the household budget correspondence, is defined for ( y, p) E PE as Bh(y,p,~)={.xh~Xh~qh+p~xh~rh(y,p,~)). B’(y,p,A) is a convex, compactvalued correspondence on PE. In fact, gh( y,p, A) is a continuous correspondence on PE. Recall that rh( y,p, A) and qh( y,p, A) are continuous on PE. on PE. If qh( y,p, A) =O, then the By assumption (R), rh(p, y) >infp.xh standard argument [Debreu (1959)] shows that fi’“( y,p,l) is continuous. Let Xh be the minimizer of the expenditure function. If O<qh( y,p,A) <sh( y,p, A), and Fh(y,p,A)=rh(y,p,A)-E(p,ii) then qh(y,p,;i)+p.Zh<sh(y,p,A)+p.Xh= d( y, p, A)+ E(p, 0). Thus, qh( y, p, A) +p . Xh < rh( y, p, A). Hence the minimizer K. Clay, A Coasean general equilibrium model of regulation 473 zh is in the interior of fih( y,p,E,), and again the standard argument shows that fih( y, p, 2) is a continuous correspondence. Now define the household demand correspondence as dh( y,p,A) = argmax( Uh(xh): xh E 8”( y, p, A)). By the Berge Maximization Theorem, dh is upper hemicontinuous. dh is a function from the strict quasi-concavity of Uh and convexity of fib; thus, it is a continuous function. Define the firm demand function as, df( y, p, 2) = argmax(pyf -4”: yJ E Y I). Aggregate demand is the sum of continuous functions dl and dh and is a continuous function on the closed set PE. PE is a closed subset of dxnP,,GYf, so by the Tietze extension theorem, d has a continuous extension 2 to all of dxnT,,GYf. If we utilize this demand function in place of the demand function used by Brown et al., their proof follows, and we have a fixed point which is an equilibrium. In the foregoing analysis, consumers are required to pay the hookups qs( y,p, jb) and qh( y,p, L). Given that households and firms have positive surplus, the fraction of the surplus taken from firms and from households is strictly less than one, and the normality assumption (N) holds, households and firms are left with positive surplus after paying the hookup. If households and firms do not have any surplus, they do not pay a hookup. Thus, households and firms will pay the hookups voluntarily. Proof of Proposition 1. - min(p. y”, O)/Csh( y, p) is a continuous the compact set of production equilibria, and therefore attains on the set which we will denote as ~1, where 0 < LX<1. Note function on a maximum that for all (Y?P)EPE, -min(p. y”, O)/Csh( y, p) S ~1. function on the compact set of Proof of Proposition 2. p’ y” is a continuous production equilibria and therefore attains a maximum on the set which we denote p.y”. There exists a ( y,p) which generates the largest value of the economy, p.(Cy’ +Zwh), which excludes any losses of the monopolist. p.(Zyf +Cwh) is a continuous function on the compact set of production equilibria, and hence attains a maximum on the set which we denote P’.(Z#+CW~). Th ere fore, the maximum profit of the monopolist cannot exceed p. y” +p' . (Cys + Zwh), which we denote as II*. 1. The Proof of Theorem 2. The proof is similar to the proof of Theorem PE is non-empty by the same argument found in Brown et al. (1992), where now the map is @n: AF+2 x [O,I7*] + AF+2 x [O,I7*]. The first F+2 equations are now functions of Zl and the last equation is cF+~ ((zJj,p, Iz) = Cqh+p.yO. Aggregate demand is continuous by an argument similar to the one found above. 474 K. Clay, A Coasean general equilibrium model of regulation The Beato and Mas-Cole11 map for the fixed point is Tj/ ((4, w = Z{+ maX(O,Pj-ggf(l(ZJ, P, fl))) 1+Cf+ max(O,P~-gi(rl(zf,n))) 64.1) (A.2) for f =F+ 1 and Osjs/; and T;+2((ZJ),P,n)=C 4h+P.vo(Y0) (A.31 h for f = F + 2 and 0 j js 8. This map has a fixed point; thus, we are assured that an equilibrium exists. The remaining arguments follow as in Theorem 1. 3. This proof is similar to the proof given for Theorem 1 and is left to the reader. Proof of Theorem References Beato, P. and A. Mas-Colell, 1985, On marginal cost pricing with given tax-subsidy rules, Journal of Economic Theory 37, 356365. Bonnisseau, J.M. and B. Cornet, 1988, Existence of equilibria when firms follow bounded losses pricing rules, Journal of Mathematical Economics 17, 103-l 18. Brown, D.J. and GM. Heal, 1979, Equity, efficiency, and increasing returns, Review of Economic Studies 46, 571-585. Brown, D.J., G.M. Heal, M. Ali Khan and R. Vohra, 1986, On a general existence theorem for marginal cost pricing equilibria, Journal of Economic Theory 38, 371-379. Brown, D.J. W.P. Heller and R.M. Starr, 1992, Two-part marginal cost pricing equilibria: Existence and efficiency, Journal of Economic Theory 57, 52-72. Coase, R.H., 1946, The marginal cost controversy, Economica 13, 169-189. Debreu, G., 1959, Theory of value (Wiley, New York). Dierker, E., 1986, When does marginal cost pricing lead to Pareto-efficiency?, Zeitschrift fur Nationaliikonomie Suppl. 5, 41-66. Edlin, A. and M. Eppelbaum, 1990, Existence and optimality in two-part pricing, Mimeo. Guesnerie, R., 1975, Pareto-optimality in nonconvex economies, Econometrica 43, l-29. Lewis, W.A., 1941, The two-part tarifl, Economica 8, 249-270. Mantel, R., 1979, Equilibrio con rendimiento crecientes a escala, Anales de la Asociation Argentine de Economia Politica 1, 271-283. Moriguchi, C., 1991, Two part marginal cost pricing in a general equilibrium model, Mimeo. Oi, W.Y., 1971, A Disneyland dilemma: Two-part tariffs for a Mickey Mouse monopoly, Quarterly Journal Economics 85, 77-90. Roberts, K., 1979, Welfare considerations of nonlinear pricing, Economic Journal 89, 6683. K. Clay, A Coasean general equilibrium model of regulation 475 Ruggles, N., 1949, The welfare basis of the marginal cost pricing principle, Review of Economic Studies 17, 2946. Ruggles, N., 1950, Recent developments in the theory of marginal cost pricing, Review of Economic Studies 17, 107-126. Quinzii, M., 1991, Efficiency of margin1 cost pricing equilibria, in: W. Brock and M. Majumdar, eds., Equilibrium and dynamics: Essays in honor and David Gale (Macmillan, New York). Vohra, R., 1988, Optimal regulation under tixed rules for income distribution, Journal of Economic Theory 45, 65-84. Vohra, R., 1990, On the inefficiency of two-part tariffs, Review of Economic Studies 57, 415438.