Segregation and Tiebout Sorting: Investigating the Link Between Public Goods and Demographic Composition* H. Spencer Banzhaf† and Randall P. Walsh‡ March 2009 Support for this research was provided by the National Science Foundation, NSF SES-03-21566. Additional support for Banzhaf was provided by the Property and Environment Research Center (PERC). We thank Antonio Bento and participants in a 2008 ASSA Session and in seminars at Brown, Duke, Georgetown, PERC, the University of Wyoming, and Yale for comments on earlier versions of this paper. * † ‡ Associate Professor, Department of Economics, Georgia State University. Associate Professor, Department of Economics, University of Pittsburgh and NBER. Segregation and Tiebout Sorting: Investigating the Link Between Public Goods and Demographic Composition In the white community, the path to a more perfect union means acknowledging that what ails the African-American community does not just exist in the minds of black people; that the legacy of discrimination - and current incidents of discrimination, while less overt than in the past - are real and must be addressed. Not just with words, but with deeds—by investing in our schools and our communities…. —Barack Obama Introduction Racial segregation of one form or another has been a recurring social problem throughout human history. In the United States, substantial progress has been made since Brown vs. Board of Education of Topeka and the Civil Rights Act of 1964 ended de jure racial segregation. But despite the improvements in black educational achievement, the narrowing of black-white income gaps, and even the election of the first African-American President, de facto racial segregation continues to be one of the country’s most prevalent social issues. Commensurate with the topic’s social and political relevance, recently several prominent papers have modeled group segregation. Card, Mas, and Rothstein (2008) have shown that white households still flee neighborhoods once they become 5-20% minority. Cutler, Glaeser, and Vigdor (1999) and Kiel and Zabel (1996) show that white communities command a price premium in part precisely because of their whiteness. Becker and Murphy (2000) show that differences in willingness to pay for amenities can help drive group segregation. Hoff and Sen (2005) and Sethi and Somanathan (2004) show how positive externalities from the activities of richer households can drive such segregation. And Bayer, Fang, and McMillan (2005) and Sethi and Somanathan (2004) show that reducing income inequality between groups can actually increase neighborhood segregation, because richer minorities need no longer join whites to obtain high levels of public goods. These papers have made significant contributions to our understanding of the equilibrium properties of segregation. However, none of these papers has considered the impact of placebased policy shocks. This is unfortunate because, as the above epigraph illustrates, many of the policy remedies for reducing group inequity focus on investments in minority communities. 1 Investments in education are only one example. In addition, the U.S. Department of Housing and Urban Development (HUD) provides Community Development Block Grants (totaling $120B since 1974); the US EPA's Superfund and Brownfields Programs clean up contaminated sites and encourage redevelopment; enterprise zones lower effect tax rates; and the 1992 Federal Housing Enterprises Financial Safety and Soundness Act steers Fannie and Freddie investments to low-income and minority communities. Such place-based policies are some of our primary policy tools for reducing or compensating for segregation. Yet at the same time, some activists express concern that they may trigger gentrification that ultimately harms incumbent residents and benefits absentee landlords or gentrifying households (see e.g. the recent report by NEJAC 2006). Regrettably, the segregation literature to date is unable to speak to such effects. Additionally, while recent work with models of public goods has shown how exogenous improvements in public goods can trigger such gentrification effects (e.g. Sieg et al. 2004, Banzhaf and Walsh 2008) this analysis has ignored the role of group-based segregation. In this paper, we advance the literature by introducing an exogenous location-specific public good (to be manipulated by public policy) into the segregation-based model. In this sense, we combine features of the segregation and public goods literatures.1 First, following the tradition of Schelling (1969, 1971), we include preferences for the endogenous demographic make-up of the community.2 Working in this tradition, Schelling, Pancs and Vriend (2006), and Card, Mas, and Rothstein (2008) show how such preferences and the resulting neighborhood dynamics can create a “tipping point” that causes communities to become segregated (even when everybody prefers some degree of integration). Second, following the tradition of Tiebout (1956), we include heterogeneity in willingness to pay for public goods. Working in this tradition McGuire (1974) and Epple, Filimon, and Romer (1984) have shown how households can segregate themselves by groups or income strata according to their demand for local public goods.3 In particular, as with other recent papers (Banzhaf and Walsh 2008, Sethi and 1 Glaeser and Scheinkman (2003) show how these two models can be nested in a more general social interaction model. 2 Throughout our analysis a fundamental assumption is that individuals of a given type tend toward living together due to preferences to live with individuals of their own type. We note, though, that identical results would be obtained if the model assumed that concentrations of individuals of given type lead to social spillovers (i.e. concentrations of businesses, community networks, restaurants, non-profit services, etc.) that disproportionately benefit that type. 3 Bond and Coulson (1989) present a similar argument in the context of a “filtering” model of neighborhood housing stocks. 2 Somanathan 2004), we adapt Epple et al.'s model of vertically differentiated communities. In this paper, we combine both aspects into a general equilibrium model of sorting on demographics and an exogenous public good. We then characterize the equilibria of such a model and derive the comparative statics of policy shocks to the local public goods. The model generates several results regarding the importance of place-based amenities. First, we establish that, even when community sorting is driven by tastes for the exogenous place-based public good and not by demographic tastes, some racial segregation will result, with the poorer group enjoying lower levels of the public good. Second, we show that introducing tastes for an endogenous demographic composition can drive further segregation, as suggested by Schelling's “tipping model.” As a pragmatic matter, this is likely to further the differences in the average public good enjoyed by the two groups. Most importantly, we show that place-based interventions that improve the public good in a low-quality high-minority community may actually increase group segregation, as richer minorities are more likely to migrate into the community following the improvement. Essentially, when differences in public goods become less important, group-based sorting begins to dominate income-based sorting vis-à-vis the public good. In the final section of the paper, we use large changes in the distribution of air pollution from industrial facilities that occurred in California between 1990 and 2000 to test the predictions of the model. Consistent with our model’s predictions, we find that large scale improvements in the dirtiest sites are associated with increased racial sorting and decreased income sorting relative to exposure to toxic air pollution. Theory Model In this section, we develop an equilibrium model of the link between race, demographic composition, public goods and location choice. In the recent literature, the model is most similar to work by Becker and Murphy (2000), Sethi and Somanathan (2004) and Banzhaf and Walsh (2008), but differs from these papers in several important respects. It resembles Becker and Murphy (2000) in combining preferences for an exogenous public good with the endogenous demographic community, but differs in incorporating income distributions and heterogeneity in willingness to pay for amenities. Generalizing their model in this way is crucial for motivating income-based segregation. On the other hand, in adapting the vertically differentiated 3 framework of Epple et al. (1984), our model resembles Sethi and Somanathan (2004) and Banzhaf and Walsh (2008). But it differs from Banzhaf and Walsh (2008), who only consider the exogenous good, by including racial groups and demographic preferences. And it differs from Sethi and Somanathan (2004), probably the most general model to date, by including an exogenous public good.4 Including this public good is obviously essential to analyzing the kinds of policy shocks that motivate our paper. We consider a model with two communities, j ο {C1, C2}, each comprised of an identical set of fixed size housing stock with measure 0.5. There are also two demographic types, r ο {b, w}. Type-b has measure β < 0.5 and type-w has measure (1-β). There is heterogeneity in income within type which is described by the continuous distribution functions Fr. We impose the following assumption on the income distributions of type b and w individuals: ππMin = ππ€Min = 0 < πΉπ€−1 [ . 5 ∗ (1 − 2π½) ] < ππMax ≤ ππ€Max 1−π½ (1) Essentially, this condition says that the groups’ income distributions cannot be “too different.” In particular, this condition states that when individuals are stratified solely by income, there will be some mixing of groups. One obvious interpretation of these types is as racial groups (think w for white and b for blacks). However, in principle they could represent any pair of groups with a poorer minority and richer majority (e.g. high school drop-outs vs. graduates). Each individual is assumed to consume one unit of housing and to have preferences over a numeraire (price set to unity), an exogenous community public good level Gj and endogenous π community demographic composition π·π . Individuals of each type experience the same service flow of the public good. However, as we discuss below, they view the demographic composition differently, so that D is indexed by type r as well as by location j. Conditional on choosing location j, utility for an individual of type r and income y is given by equation (2): 4 We also provide a more general characterization of the equilibria of our model, including integrated and segregated equilibria. Sethi and Somanathan (2004) ignore segregated equilibria. 4 π π ππ = π[π − ππ , π(πΊ π , π·π )] = U[x, Vrj] (2) The function U(.) is increasing at a decreasing rate in both of its arguments and V(.) is increasing in both arguments. More compactly, let x be consumption and Vrj = V(Gj, Drj). We also require the Inada condition that Ux→∞ as x→0. Demographic preferences are captured by Drj = Dr(PCTrj), where PCTrj is the proportion of type r in community j. The only restriction on Dr( ) is that Dr(1) > Dr(α) for all α<1-β. Essentially, ceteris paribus, group-w individuals prefer an all-w community to filling out the remaining housing supply in the community in which all type b individuals reside. This assumption is consistent with a wide range of preferences including a general “bliss point” specification, Drj = g[abs(PCTrj-ρr)], where g’<0, 1-β ≤ ρw ≤ 1, and ρb > 2β. Additionally, without loss of generality, we assume that when public good levels differ that the level of the public good is higher in Community 2 than in Community 1: GC2≥GC1. Further, in order to close the model, we assume that the price level in Community 1 is equal to 0: PC1 = 0. This normalization will allow us to work with households' willingness to pay to live in C2, given Vrj and yi. Denote this willingness to pay as Bidry. Equilibrium in the model is characterized by a sorting of individuals across the two communities and a price level in Community 2, PC2, such that: E1. In each community, for each type, Drj arises from the sorting of individuals: ππΆππ π = ∫π∈π,π 1ππ ∫π∈π 1ππ E2. Each individual resides in his preferred community. That is, for all individuals of type r choosing to live in community j: U[Yir – Pj, V(Gj, Drj] ≥ U[Yir – P-j, V(G-j, Dr-j] E3. The measure of individuals choosing each community is equal to 0.5. The structure of the model allows us to simplify the characterization of the sorting of individuals across communities. Specifically, the concavity of U( ) in the numeraire and V( ) combined with the assumption that each household consumes an identical and fixed quantity of 5 housing implies that equilibria in the model will exhibit single crossing in income within each type.5 In other words, in equilibrium, for each type there exists a boundary income, π¦π , such that Μ π , choose to live in the community that type all individuals of type r with incomes greater than π views as more desirable (i.e. the community with the higher Vrj).6 In will be particularly useful to consider the willingness to pay of these boundary individuals. Define π΅πππΜ π to be the price level in Community 2 that makes these individuals indifferent. Recalling that PC1 is normalized to 0, π΅πππΜ π is implicitly defined by equation (3): π[πΜ π , π(πΊ πΆ1 , π·ππΆ1 )] = π[πΜ π − π΅πππΜ π , π (πΊ πΆ2 , π·ππΆ2 )]. (3) By definition, the bid makes these individuals indifferent between communities. We begin our analysis with a discussion of what demographic compositions are feasible given only condition (E3)—ignoring for the time being whether or not these can actually be supported as an equilibrium. We first note that the entire demographic profile of a given sorting of households can be expressed as a function of PCTwC1, the proportion of Community 1 that is white: PCTwC2 = 2 - 2β - PCTwC1, PCTbC1 = 1 - PCTwC1, and PCTwC2 = PCTwC1 + 2β - 1. Consequently, the demographic qualities can also be expressed as a function of PCTwC1, Drj = Drj(PCTwC1). Further, given that single crossing holds within each type, we can also identify the boundary incomes as a function of ππΆππ€πΆ1 , conditional on the relative levels of V(.): 5 See Epple et al. (1984) for a discussion of the single crossing property in locational equilibrium models. Formally, the boundary income is defined as that income at which (PC2-Bidy) is at a minimum. Often, this will be for an indifferent household, in which case (P2-Bidy) =0. However, there are equilibria where all type-b individuals locate in the same community. In this case πΜ π = πππππ when Vbj is higher in this community and πΜ π = πππππ₯ when Vbj is higher in the other community. Because β<0.5, there must always be type-w individuals living in both communities. 6 6 . 5 ∗ (ππΆππ€ πΆ1 + 2π½ − 1) ] π½ . 5 ∗ (1 − ππΆππ€ πΆ1 ) πΉπ−1 [ ] π½ πΉπ−1 [ πΜ π = { −1 πΉπ [ πΜ π€ = { ππ πππΆ1 > πππΆ2 , ππ πππΆ2 > πππΆ1 , . 5 ∗ (2 − 2π½ − ππΆππ€ πΆ1 ) ] ππ 1−π½ . 5 ∗ ππΆππ€ πΆ1 −1 πΉπ [ ] ππ 1−π½ ππ€πΆ1 > ππ€πΆ2 , ππ€πΆ2 > ππ€πΆ1 . We can similarly characterize the derivatives of these boundary incomes with respect to ππΆππ€ πΆ1: ππΜ π = πππΆππ€ πΆ1 ππΜ π€ πππΆππ€ πΆ1 0.5 >0 π½ππ (πΜ π ) 0.5 − <0 { π½ππ (πΜ π ) ππ πππΆ1 > πππΆ2 , ππ πππΆ2 > πππΆ1 , 0.5 < 0 ππ (1 − π½)ππ€ (πΜ π€ ) = 0.5 >0 ππ { (1 − π½)ππ€ (πΜ π€ ) − ππ€πΆ1 > ππ€πΆ2 , ππ€πΆ2 > ππ€πΆ1 . To build additional intuition with the model, consider momentarily the case where the public goods G are identical across communities. Panels 1 through 3 of Figure 1 illustrate the relationship between PCTwC1, demographic composition, V( ) and πΜ . The figure illustrates results for the following specification: β=0.25, Drj = (PCTrj-ρr)2, ρb=0.5, ρw=0.9, and Vrj = Drj + Gj. That is, V( ) is separable in D and G and D is defined by a quadratic function around a bliss point ρ, with type w preferring more segregation.7 The utility function U( ) is Cobb-Douglas in consumption and V, with an expenditure share of 0.75 on consumption. Incomes are assumed to be uniformly distributed with Yrmin=0, Ybmax=1, and Ywmax=1.1. Finally, GC1=GC2=1. In their recent work on tipping points, Card, Mas and Rothstein (2008) that ρw is around 0.9, which is also consistent with the survey literature. This literature also suggests that an appropriate level for ρb is around 0.5 Farley et al. (1978) and Farley and Krysan (2002). 7 7 Panel 1 shows the racial compositions in each community as a function of PCTwC1. (These are defined by an identity.) The figure shows that racial compositions are identical when PCTwC1 = PCTwC2 = 1-β = 0.75. Panel 2 shows the corresponding values of V( ). It demonstrates that our mild condition that Dr(1) > Dr(α) for all α<1-β, when combined with condition (E3), implies that—in equilibrium—both types always prefer the community with the larger percentage of their own type.8 For type-w individuals, V( ) is maximized at their bliss point of 0.9. Beyond this bliss point, VwC1 is decreasing in PCTwC1, but still remains higher than VwC2. Type-b individuals never achieve their bliss point and Vbj is always increasing in PCTbj. Because public good levels are identical across the two communities, for both types, the level of V( ) is equated across communities at the point where the communities have identical demographic compositions (PCTwC1 = 1-β). Panel 2 also shows that when the levels of G are identical across the two communities, the two types will have opposite rankings of the two communities: whenever PCTwC1 < 1-β, VbC1 > VbC2 but VwC2 > VwC1, whereas when PCTwC1 > 1β, the opposite holds. Panel 3 shows the link between PCTwC1 and the boundary incomes. Below 1-β, type-w individuals prefer Community 2. As a result, single-crossing implies that they will sort such that the richest type-w individuals locate in C2. Over this range, the boundary income is equal to that of the poorest type-w individual in C2 (alternatively the richest type-w individual in C1). As PCTwC1 increases, the number of rich type-w households living in C2 must decrease. Thus, the boundary income must increase. But when PCTwC1 increases above 1-β, the relative ranking of the communities changes and rich type-w individuals now locate in C1. Thus, the boundary income is now decreasing in PCTwC1. Because in this example the community switch occurs where type-w individuals are equally distributed between the two communities, there is only a kink in boundary income at the switch. As we shall see, in cases where public good levels differ and indifference between the two communities occur where PCTwC1 ≠ 1-β, there will be a discontinuity in the boundary income function. While the boundary income profile for type b looks similar to that of the type w, the underlying process is different. Below 1-β, type-b individuals prefer Community 1. Thus, by 8 We note that while the assumption that both types strictly prefer the community with more of their own type is sufficient for the findings that follow, it is by no means necessary. However, imposing this condition greatly simplifies the analysis. 8 single crossing, the type-b boundary income will be that of the poorest type-b individual in C1 (alternatively the richest type-b individual in C2). When PCTwC1 = 1-2β = 0.5, all type-b individuals are in C1 and πΜ π = YbMin = 0. From the foregoing analytical framework, we make the following observations about the model. Observation 1. Some type-w individuals always live in both communities. This must be the case because the measure of type-w individuals is greater than 0.5. More specifically, the share of type w in any community can never fall below 1-2β. In contrast, it is possible that there will be no type-b individuals in one of the two communities. Observation 2. When VwC1 ≠ VwC2, there will be some πΜ π€ at which type-w individuals are indifferent. All type-w individuals with income higher than πΜ π€ will reside in the more desirable (to w) community and poorer type-w individuals will live in the less desirable. Moreover, πΜ π€ can never drop below πΉπ€−1 (1 − 2π½). In contrast, it is possible that b's boundary income may fall to zero. Observation 3. The community that type w perceives as more desirable will be more expensive: VwC2 > VwC1 ↔ PC2 > 0. Moreover, PC2 = π΅πππΜ π€ . This must be so, for if a community was more desirable to type w and less expensive, all type-w individuals would choose to live in it, and the demand for housing would exceed supply. These observations are general to the model and do not depend on the assumption of equal public goods or the other features of the example associated with Figure 1. The discussion to this point demonstrates how all of the feasible allocations of individuals and associated boundary incomes are uniquely determined by PCTwC1. We now turn to an analysis of which allocations can be supported as equilibria. As noted in Observation 1, because β<0.5, it is possible for all type-b individuals to live in the same community. We will refer to equilibria where all type-b individuals live in the same communities as “segregated” and equilibria where some type-b individuals live in each community as “integrated.” We make the following observations about each of these cases. Observation 4. For segregation of types with all type-b individuals locating in C1 to be supportable as an equilibria, it must be the case that π΅πππΜ π ≤ π΅πππΜ π€ . (Otherwise, if BidYΜ b > BidYΜ w , then the boundary type-b individual would outbid the boundary type-w individual for housing in C2.) In particular, if VbC2 > VbC1 and VwC2 > VwC1 then π΅πππΜ π€ ≥ π΅πππΜ π > 0. If VbC1 > VbC2 and VwC2 > VwC1 then π΅πππΜ π€ > 0 > π΅πππΜ π . And if VbC1 > VbC2 and VwC1 > VwC2 then 0 > π΅πππΜ π€ ≥ π΅πππΜ π . Note also that if VbC1 > VbC2then πΜ π = YbMin = 0. 9 Otherwise, πΜ π = YbMax. The opposite and symmetrical case holds for equilibria where all type-b individuals locate in C2. Observation 5. In all integrated equilibria, both types agree on which community is more desirable and π΅πππΜ π€ = π΅πππΜ π . For integration, some members of each type must be willing to pay to live in the more desirable community, while others must be unwilling to pay the price and so live in the less desirable community. The upshot of these observations is that equilibria can be identified by an analysis of the bid functions of the boundary incomes for the two types. To illustrate this point, Panel 4 of Figure 1 plots the boundary income bid functions associated with the previously defined example. Type-w individuals prefer Community 2 when PCTwC1 < 0.75 and so the bid function is positive over this range. The situation reverses above PCTwC1 = 0.75 and the bid function becomes negative. When the demographic compositions are identical in the two communities, type-w individuals are indifferent and the bid function is 0 (recall that we have equal public good levels in this example). As PCTwC1 increases, the change in the boundary income bid function is represented by Equation (4): ππ΅πππΜ π ππΜ π ππ·ππΆ2 ππ·ππΆ1 1 πΆ2 πΆ2 πΆ1 1πΆ1 πΆ2 πΆ1 (π ) = [ − π + (π π − π π )] π₯ π₯ π π· π π· πππΆππ€ πΆ1 πππΆππ€ πΆ1 πππΆππ€ πΆ1 πππΆππ€ πΆ1 ππ₯πΆ2 (4) where Uxj is the derivative of the utility function with respect to the numeraire, evaluated in Community j at the appropriate income (i.e. Μ Yw in the case of type w) and all other derivatives are similarly defined. The expression shows two effects. The first term in the brackets captures the effects of the change in the boundary income associated with the change in PCTwC1. As is shown in Panel 3, for type w the boundary income increases over the range .5 to .75 and, because the positive value of the bid function implies (UxC2 -UxC1 ) >0, the effect of the change in the boundary income acts to increase the bid function. The second term in the brackets captures the effect of changes in the V( ) function as PCTwC1 increases. Given the functional form assumptions in this specification, the difference is decreasing over the range .5 to .75 in the figure, reducing the bid function. In the case of type-w individuals, the effect of closing the gap 10 in V( ) dominates the income effect over the entire range and thus the bid function is always negatively sloped. For type-b individuals, preferences are reversed. The bid function is always negative for PCTwC1 < 0.75 and always positive for PCTwC1 > 0.75. In terms of the slope of the bid function, the basic dynamics are the same as with type-w individuals, except that for very low or very high levels of PCTwC1 the change associated with the boundary income dominates the change associated with closing the gap in V( ). This result is driven by the steeper slope of the boundary income function, which arises from the fact that there are fewer type-b individuals. Evaluating the figure, we can see that there are three equilibria in this example. At the far left, type-w individuals are willing to pay to live in Community 2, type-b individuals are not, and C2 is all-w. At the far right is the opposite and symmetric segregated equilibrium. In the middle, there is an integrated equilibrium in which the two communities have the same composition and everybody is indifferent. In addition to the existence of such equilibria, we are also concerned with stability of equilibria. We adopt the following definition of local stability. Definition. An equilibrium is locally stable if, when a type-w individual with an income arbitrarily close to Yw switches communities with a type-b individual arbitrarily close to Yb , the relative levels of their bid functions are such that the marginal individual that was relocated from C2 to C1 now has a higher bid for C2 than does the marginal individual that was moved from C1 to C2.9 In this case, the individual moved from Community 2 will outbid the other individual and move back into Community 2, restoring the initial equilibrium. As discussed above, equilibria occur either at corners (the case of segregation) or in the interior (the case of integration). Whenever corner equilibria exist they will be locally stable. For interior solutions, it is straightforward to demonstrate that the local stability conditions are satisfied whenever the type-b boundary income bid function crosses the type-w boundary income bid function from above. 9 Note that in general we must consider two possibilities: first, moving a type-w individual from C2 to C1 and a type-b individual from C1 to C2; and second, moving a type-w individual from C1 to C2 and a type-b individual from C2 to C1. When either C1 or C2 is completely comprised of type w individuals, there will only be one possible perturbation. Note also that by Observation 4, with segregation πΜ π is equal to 0 or YbMax and the marginal individual will be confined to incomes above or below these levels respectively. 11 Thus, from Panel 4 in Figure 1, we see that while there are three equilibria, only the two symmetric segregated equilibria are stable. This result is not limited to the special case presented here. For any specification satisfying our general assumption, the following proposition holds. Proposition I. Whenever GC1=GC2, there will be three equilibria: two stable segregated equilibria with PCTwC1 = 1 and PCTwC1 = 1-2β and one unstable integrated equilibrium with PCTwC1 = 1-β. Proof: See Appendix We now turn to analysis of cases where public good levels differ across communities. To build intuition for how relationships change when public goods differ, Figure 2 replicates Figure 1 for a case with unequal public good levels (GC1=0.9 and GC2=1). Because the set of feasible racial compositions is independent of public good levels, the first panel of Figure 2 is identical to Figure 1. Panel 2 shows that, when GC1 falls, VrC1 shifts down for both types. As a result, type-b individuals are now indifferent between the two communities when PCTwC1 = 0.65. For type-w individuals the indifference point is now at PCTwC1 = 0.92. Panel 3 shows the impact of the differential public good levels on boundary income. When public goods were equated across communities, both types were indifferent at the point where PCTwC1=PCTwC2. As a result, even though relative preferences for communities switch at this point, reversing the income sorting, the boundary income functions were continuous (though kinked) at the indifference point. Differential public good levels separate the indifference point for the two types moving them away from equal sorting. As a result, there is now a discontinuity in the boundary income functions for each type at their indifference point. Finally, Panel 4 of Figure 2 presents the bid functions under the new public good levels. In this example, the situation remains qualitatively similar to the case where the public good levels were equal.10 There are still two stable segregated equilibria and one unstable integrated equilibrium, with the location of the unstable integrated equilibrium now shifted slightly to the right to where PCTwC1 = 0.76. Thus, for small differences in public good levels, it is possible to support a segregated equilibrium with all type-b individuals in the high public good community. 10 We do note that the boundary income functions are now non-differentiable at the value of PCTwC1 where the two communities are equally desirable. But the bid function approaches zero from both sides at this point, so the boundary income bid functions are still continuous (though kinked). 12 However, comparison of the bid functions in Figures 1 and 2 suggest that, at least for this example, as the public good gap increases this equilibrium will no longer be supported. As we shall see below, this result holds in general. As the public good gap increases, it becomes difficult to make general statements regarding the character of equilibria. This is because, as is clear from an examination of Equation 4, the slopes of the bid functions are highly sensitive to local variations in the density of the income functions and the relative curvatures of the utility functions. For instance, it is relatively straightforward to generate models with multiple segregated and multiple stable equilibria when the public good differentials are moderate in size. Nevertheless, the model does provide sharp predictions regarding equilibria for cases when there are “small” or “large” differences in public goods, and a comparison of these two cases provides important policy insights. We begin by considering the case where there are small differences in the public goods levels. As stated in Proposition 1, when the level of public goods in the two communities are identical, there will always be one unstable integrated equilibrium and two symmetric stable segregated equilibria. We can also extend this observation to a measure of Gj as stated in Proposition II. Proposition II For any given level of GC2, there will exist πΊΜ πΆ1 < GC2 such that for all GC2 > GC1 > πΊΜ πΆ1 there will exist exactly three equilibria, two symmetric stable segregated equilibria and one unstable integrated equilibrium. Further, there will exist πΊΜ πΆ1 < GC2 satisfying V[GC2, Db(1)] > V[πΊΜ πΆ1 , Db(1-2β)] such that for all GC2 > GC1 > πΊΜ πΆ1 there will exist a stable segregated equilibria with all type-b individuals locating in C1. Proof: See Appendix Proposition II addresses the case where differences between the public good levels are small enough that demographic preferences dominate in the determination of equilibria. It states that in this range, the stable equilibria are characterized by segregation of the types. Moreover, segregation with type-b in the low-public good community is guaranteed to exist over a wider range of G's. Consider now the opposite extreme, where differences in public goods are very large and effectively drive the sorting behavior, swamping any effect of the demographics. Intuitively, this case will resemble earlier results from Epple et al. (1984) and other related papers with only a 13 public goods component. In particular, individuals will be stratified by income instead of segregated by race. To operationalize this intuition in our model, assume that, for given levels of GC2, DrC1, and DrC2, BidYr→Y as GC1→-∞.11 Then, at the limit, the boundary income bid functions are equal to the boundary incomes themselves and both types view Community 2 as more desirable regardless of demographic sorting. By construction, the richest type-b individual is richer than the boundary type-w individual when PCTwC1 =1-2β and the poorest type-b individual is poorer than the boundary type-w individual when PCTwC1 =1. As a result, the boundary income of type-b individuals crosses the boundary income of type-w individuals exactly once from above. In this situation, there is a single equilibrium. The equilibrium is stable and integrated with all individuals with income above the population median income locating in Community 2. Proposition III formalizes this result. Proposition III Assume that, for given levels of GC2, DrC1, and DrC2, πΆ1→−∞ lim π΅πππΜ π = πΜ π . Then, there πΊ Μ C1 such that for all GC1<πΊΜ πΆ1 there is a single equilibrium which is integrated and exists G stable. Proof: see the appendix. That is, when public good differences are sufficiently large, the communities will be integrated by group but stratified by income. To summarize the discussion so far, when public good levels in the two communities are relatively similar the only stable equilibria will be segregated. At intermediate differences in public good levels it is difficult to make general statements about equilibria. However, the stable segregated equilibria with all type-b individuals in Community 1 will exist over at least part of this range. Finally, when differences in public good levels are high there will be a single stable equilibrium with integration. To further illustrate the implications of Propositions II and III, Figure 3 displays the bid functions for the model of Figures 1 and 2—fixing the level of GC2 at 1 and varying the level of GC1 from 0.25 to 1. When GC1 =0.25 the public goods difference is large enough that the 11 This condition is less restrictive than it might first seem. It is for example satisfied by Cobb-Douglass or CES preferences. We would also note that while this is a sufficient condition for the emergence of a single integrated equilibrium as public good differences increase, it is by no means necessary. 14 outcome resembles the limiting notion of proposition III where the bid functions equal the boundary income functions. Here there is a single stable integrated. As GC1 increases to 0.5, the bid functions no longer track the boundary income functions as closely, but there is still a single stable and integrated equilibrium. When GC1=0.7, the bid functions no longer cross and the only equilibria is a stable segregated equilibria with all type-b individuals located in the low public good community. In other words, closing the gap in public goods by improving the public good level in Community 1 causes a change from integrated equilibrium to segregated equilibrium. This stable segregated equilibria exists for all 1 ≥ GC1 > 0.6. When GC1=0.8, this stable segregated equilibrium continues to exist. In addition, two new equilibria appear, an unstable and a stable integrated equilibrium. Finally, once GC1=0.9, we are in the realm of proposition II with two stable segregated equilibria and one unstable integrated equilibrium. The figure illustrates the results of Propositions II and III. Namely, when public good differences are large, integrated equilibria (with income stratification) are especially salient. When public good differences shrink, segregated equilibria are especially salient. Figure 4 offers a schematic of these results, showing the stable equilibria at different qualitative values of GC1. Below, we confirm these patterns using data on pollution changes in California from 1990 to 2000. These results speak to three important policy and empirical issues in the literature. The first and most central to our application are policy concerns centered on the correlation between low-income and/or minority populations and the levels of local public goods like public school quality, public safety, parks and green space, and environmental quality. The “environmental justice movement,” for example, has highlighted such correlations with air pollution and local toxic facilities (see e.g. Been 1994, Ringquist 2006, Noonan 2008). Our model confirms the intuition that such sorting can be produced by income differentials. For example, given the correlation that exists between race and income in today’s society, this will be the case in regions A and A’ of Figure 4. Moreover, racial preferences can strengthen this result by driving even fairly rich minorities into the minority district, as they are not willing to pay the extra price for 15 the high public good community’s whiteness (a theme raised in the law literature by, e.g., Ford 1994).12 However, both advocates and analysts have raised concerns that improving public goods in low-quality neighborhoods may drive forms of gentrification (Sieg et al. 2004, Banzhaf and McCormick 2006, NEJAC 2006). While there may well be price effects, our model suggests that it is unlikely that public good improvements will lead to large turnovers in racial or other group compositions. To the contrary, Propositions II and III together imply that improvements in public goods may increase segregation (for example an improvement that leads to a move from region A to regions D in Figure 4).13 On the surface, this result resembles that of Bayer et al. (2005) and Sethi and Somanathan (2006), who find that improving the minority income distribution can increase segregation. They find that such people-based policies have this effect because richer minorities now have enough mass to form their own high public-good communities. Our results suggest that place-based policies pose the same dilemma, but for a different reason: group-based sorting becomes more salient when there is less reason to sort on the exogenous public good. It appears that segregation is a deep-rooted social problem. Second, our results may help explain some recent empirical puzzles. As noted above, the environmental justice literature shows that minority households are correlated with undesirable facilities like hazardous waste sites. But recently, both Cameron and McConnaha (2006) and Greenstone and Gallagher (2008) have found in a difference-in-difference context that improvements to such sites do not appear to reduce these correlations. They suggest this may be because of long-lasting “stigma” of the sites or the ineffectualness of cleanup. Our results suggest another explanation: the reduced form relationship may change after a cleanup, so that the correlation on race becomes even stronger. Figure 5 plots the relationship between Gj and PCTbj for our two communities for each value of GC1 used in Figure 3. The bottom panel shows the cross-sectional relationships. The top panel shows difference-in-differences for each successive improvement in GC1. It clearly shows that while the cross-sectional differences have the expected negative slope, the difference-in-differences have the opposite slope. This for instance is the case in the segregated equilibria supported in regions C and C’ in Figure 4. This of course depends on which of the two stable equilibria obtain. However, A move to the stable segregated equilibria with all type b individuals in the high public good community would require a much larger shift in populations than is required for a move to the stable segregated equilibria with all type b individuals in the low public good community. 12 13 16 One way to think about this problem is in terms of a mis-specification of the standard difference-in-differences regression. Our model suggests that the correlation between race and public goods increases as the low public good community sees increases in its public good level. If we have a reduced form relationship as in Equations (5) and (6). ππΆπππΌπππ πΌπππ0 = π‘0 + πΌπ + π½0 πππΏπΏπππΌπππ0 + ππ0 (5) ππΆπππΌπππ πΌπππ1 = π‘1 + πΌπ + π½1 πππΏπΏπππΌπππ1 + ππ1 , (6) with π½1 > π½0 > 0, then first differencing the equations leads to: ΔππΆπππΌπππ πΌπππ = Δπ‘ + π½1 ΔπππΏπΏπππΌπππ + (π½1 − π½0 )πππΏπΏπππΌπππ0 + ππ (7) If πππΏπΏπππΌπππ0 is omitted from equation (7), the estimate of β1 will be biased downward when ΔπππΏπΏπππΌππ and πππΏπΏπππΌππ0 are negatively correlated (i.e. if the dirtiest areas are being cleaned up). In this case, the problem may simply be one of omitted variables. Including baseline pollution levels is suggested as a control. A third application of our model is to the recent revival in the interest in “tipping models” of racial segregation (e.g. Pancs and Vriend, 2006, and Card, Mas, and Rothstein, 2008). However, although Schelling (1969, 1971) noted the link between public goods and demographic sorting in his early work, their role has generally been under appreciated in recent models of segregation. For example, Card, Mas, and Rothstein (2008) recently have conducted a study of "tipping" behavior in US Cities. They identify tipping points using tract level data, looking for break points in the change in the white population as a flexible function of the baseline minority composition of the tract. They assume tipping points are identical for all tracts within a metropolitan area. However, our model suggests this is unlikely to be the case. When two tracts have large differences in locational amenities, integration is supportable even with large proportions of minorities. When the tracts have small differences in amenities, however, more segregation results. In other words, one community with, say, 20% minorities and high public goods may continue to attract whites, while another even with 15% minorities and low public goods may not. This may be one reason why there appears to be more noise in their predictions around their estimated tipping point (see their Figure 4). Our model suggests more precise results can be obtained by adjustment for differences in public goods using multiple regression or other methods. 17 Empirical Illustration In a nutshell, our model predicts that an exogenous improvement in public goods that closes the public goods gap should in general change locational equilibria in such a way as to put more emphasis on sorting by race and less emphasis on sorting by income. We illustrate these effects with an application to 1990-2000 changes in demographics surrounding the dirtiest polluters in California. In particular, we use a data set previously assembled by Banzhaf and Walsh (2008). At the core of the data are 25,166 “communities” defined by a set of tangent half-mile diameter circles evenly distributed across the urbanized portion of California. This approach has the virtue of establishing equally sized communities with randomly drawn boundaries, in contrast to political and census boundaries which may be endogenous. These neighborhoods are matched to the presence of large industrial emitters of air pollution and their emissions levels, as recorded in the Toxic Release Inventory (TRI), in each year from 1990 to 2000. This is a commonly used metric in the literature on the relationship between environmental quality and demographic composition.14 Firms handling more than 10,000 pounds each year of certain hazardous chemicals have been required to report these emissions since 1987. This censoring at the reporting threshold gives rise to a kind of errors-in variables problem. As in the usual case, this is likely to have a “conservative” effect on our results, biasing them to zero, as some exposed communities are included in the control group. See de Marchi and Hamilton (2006) for further discussion of the data. We use a toxicity weighted index of all emissions in the TRI, developed by the US Environmental Protection Agency and available in its Risk Screen Environmental Indicators model (RSEI). We use a three-year lagged average, anchored respectively on 1990 and 2000, of the toxicity-weighted emissions of all chemicals reported since 1988.15 Emissions from each plant are assumed to disperse uniformly over a half-mile buffer zone, and are allocated to each residential community accordingly. The data are also matched to 1990 and 2000 block-level census data on the total populations of each racial group. They are similarly matched to block-group-level data including 14 E.g., Arora and Cason (1996), Brooks and Sethi (1997), Kriesel et al. (1996), Morello-Frosch et al. (2001), Rinquist (1997), Sadd et al. (1999). 15 The list of reporting chemicals greatly expanded in 1994. To maintain a consistent comparison of TRI emissions over time, we have limited the data to the common set of chemicals used since 1988. 18 average incomes. Block-group-level data are allocated down to blocks by population weights, and block-level data are aggregated back up to the circle-communities. See Banzhaf and Walsh (2008) for additional details including summary statistics. These data will provide a good test of our model if a) reductions in TRI emissions in California between 1990 and 2000 are “large” enough to lead to changes in the reduced form relationship between TRI emissions and demographic compositions, and b) reductions in emissions are targeted to the most polluted locations (i.e. a move from region A to regions C or D in Figure 4). Ten percent of our communities were exposed in the baseline period (19881990), with 4 percent of our communities (or approximately 40% of those exposed in 19881990) losing their exposure by 1998-2000. While it is hard to quantify how large a change is “large” enough to shift the reduced form relationship, it seems reasonable to assume that this level of improvement is at least a candidate for shifting the reduced form relationship. Figure 6 shows the link between baseline TRI exposure and the 10-year change in emissions. The figure clearly demonstrates that the largest improvements were targeted to the communities with the highest emissions. Using these data, we test for changes in the structural relationships between income and pollution and race and pollution over time. In particular, we estimate πππππΌπππππππ‘ = πΏ0π‘ + πΏπΌπ‘ πΌππ‘ + πΏππ‘ πππ‘ + πΏπΏ πΏπ + πππ‘ πππ‘πππππππ‘π¦ππ‘ = π0π‘ + ππΌπ‘ πΌππ‘ + πππ‘ πππ‘ + ππΏ πΏπ + πππ‘ where πΌππ‘ is an indicator for whether community j was “exposed” to TRI pollution (i.e. was within a half-mile of such facilities) in year t and πππ‘ is the continuous level of emissions from nearby facilities allocated to community j. The variable I captures the extensive margin and any nonpollution related disamenity of the polluting facilities (visual, noise, smell), while e captures emissions weighted by EPA’s toxicity index. Finally, to help control for confounding influences, we include controls for location effects, including distance to the coast and degrees latitude. However, our main approach to controlling for unobserved spatial amenities is to employ successively more stringent neighborhood dummies, including school district dummies, zip code dummies, and community fixed effects. These effects should capture unobserved public goods. School districts have the 19 advantage of mapping directly into an important but difficult-to-measure local public good. Table 1 displays the results, with income in the top panel and percent minority in the bottom panel. The table shows the estimated effects, in each year, of a plant with emissions ο¦ 1 equal to the 1990 average. That is, for each year, it shows ο€ˆet ο§ ο§ ο₯ 1(e1990 οΎ 0) ο¨ j j οΆ 1990 ο· e ο« ο€ˆIt .16 ο₯ j ο· j|ej οΎ0 οΈ The table clearly shows that as the public goods gap shrinks from 1990 to 2000, sorting on income diminished and sorting on race increased—precisely the predictions in the model. In the top panel, we see that an average plant is generally associated with poorer populations, but the effect is $1,000 smaller (in constant dollars) in 2000 than in was in 1990. This difference is highly significant and quite robust to different spatial controls, although the level effects in each year are quite different. As we use more local fixed effects for spatial controls, the sorting on income appears to disappear entirely in 2000. The lower panel similarly shows that an average plant is generally associated with more minorities, but the effect is about 12 percentage points higher in 2000 than 1990. Again, this difference is highly significant and quite robust to the level of spatial controls. These results are surprisingly consistent with the models predictions, suggesting that sorting on environmental amenities does drive correlations between those amenities and demographics. And yet, changes in those amenities can trigger feedbacks with the sorting on demographics, so that the demographic changes are counter-intuitive and do not reflect the structural (i.e. cross sectional) patterns. Conclusions Our model suggests that any analysis of the distribution of spatially delineated public goods across demographic groups must account for endogenous sorting on those demographics, while at the same time studies of spatial patterns in demographics must account for public goods. We show that when sorting includes demographics, changes in public goods can lead to counterintuitive results. In particular, improving public good levels in disadvantaged communities can actually increase segregation. This result has two important implications. For the empirical and econometric literature, it suggests that structural parameters can vary greatly over time, implying 16 Similar results are obtained by using the average of 2000 emissions. 20 caution is required when using difference-in-differences estimators. More importantly, it suggests that segregation may be a deeply ingrained feature that is difficult to shake. 21 References Arora, Seema, and Timothy N. Cason. 1999. “Do Community Characteristics Influence Environmental Outcomes? Evidence from the Toxics Release Inventory.” Southern Economic Journal 65(4): 691-716. Ash, Michael, and T. Robert Fetter. 2004. “Who Lives on the Wrong Side of the Environmental Tracks? Evidence from the EPA's Risk-Screening Environmental Indicators Model.” Social Science Quarterly 85: 441–62 Banzhaf, H. Spencer, and Eleanor McCormick. 2006. “Moving Beyond Cleanup: Identifying the Crucibles of Environmental Gentrification.” National Center for Environmental Economics Working Paper 07-02. http://yosemite.epa.gov/EE/epa/eed.nsf/WPNumberNew/2007-02?OpenDocument. Banzhaf, H. Spencer, and Randall P. Walsh. 2007. “Do People Vote with Their Feet? An Empirical Test of Tiebout’s Mechanism.” American Economic Review, forthcoming. Bayer, Patrick, Hanming Fang, and Robert McMillan. 2005. “Separate When Equal? Racial Inequality and Residential Segregation.” Mimeo. Durham, NC: Duke University. Becker, Gary S., and Kevin M. Murphy. 2000. Social Economics: Market Behavior in a Social Environment, Chapter 5. Cambridge, MA: Belknap Press. Been, Vicki. 1994. “Locally Undesirable Land Uses in Minority Neighborhoods: Disproportionate Siting or Market Dynamics?” Yale Law Journal 103: 1383-1422. Brooks and Sethi. 1997. “The Distribution of Pollution: Community Characteristics and Exposure to Air Toxics.” Journal of Environmental Economics and Management 32: 233-50. Cameron, Trudy Ann, and Ian McConnaha. 2006. “Evidence of Environmental Migration.” Land Economics 82: 273-290. Card, David, Alexandre Mas, and Jesse Rothstein. 2007. “Tipping and the Dynamics of Segregation.” Quarterly Journal of Economics, forthcoming. Cutler, David M., Edward L. Glaeser, and Jacob L. Vigdor. 1999. “The Rise and Decline of the American Ghetto.” Journal of Political Economy 107(3): 455-506. de Marchi, Scott, and James T. Hamilton. 2006. “Assessing the Accuracy of Self-Reported Data: An Evaluation of the Toxics Release Inventory.” Journal of Risk and Uncertainty 32: 5776. Epple, Dennis, Radu Filimon, and Thomas Romer. 1984. “Equilibrium among Local Jurisdictions: Toward an Integrated Approach of Voting and Residential Choice.” Journal of Public Economics 24: 281-308. Farley, Reynolds, Howard Schuman, S. Bianchi, Diane Colasanto, and S. Hatchett. 1978. "Chocolate City, Vanilla Suburbs: Will the Trend toward Racially Separate Communities Continue?" Social Science Research 7: 319-344. Farley, Reynolds, and Maria Krysan. 2002. "The Residential Preferences of Blacks: Do They Explain Persistent Segregation?" Social Forces, 80: 937-80 22 Ford, Richard Thompson. 1994. "The Boundaries of Race: Political Geography in Legal Analysis." Harvard Law Review 107: 1841-1921. Glaeser, Edward L., and Jose A. Scheinkman. 2003. “Non-Market Interactions.” In Advances in Economics and Econometrics: Theory and Applications, 8th World Congress, Vol. 1, ed. by M. Dewatripont, L.P. Hansen, and S. Turnovosky. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, pp. 339-69. Greenstone, Michael, and Justin Gallagher. 2008. “Does Hazardous Waste Matter? Evidence from the Housing Market and the Superfund Program.” Quarterly Journal of Economics 123: 951-1003. Hoff, Karla, and Arijit Sen. 2005. “Homeownership, Community Interactions, and Segregation.” American Economic Review 95: 1167-89. Kiel, Katherine A., and Jeffrey E. Zabel. 1996. “House Price Differentials in US Cities: Household and Neighborhood Racial Effects.” Journal of Housing Economics 5: 14365. Kriesel, Warren, Terence J. Centner, and Andrew G. Keller. 1996. “Neighborhood Exposure to Toxic Releases: Are there Racial Inequities?” Growth and Change 27: 479-99. McGuire, Martin. 1974. “Group Segregation and Optimal Jurisdictions.” Journal of Political Economy 82: 112-32. Morello-Frosch, Rachel, Manuel Pastor, and James Sadd. 2001. “Environmental Justice and Southern California's 'Riskscape': The Distribution of Air Toxics Exposures and Health Risks Among Diverse Communities.” Urban Affairs Review 36(4): 551-578. National Environmental Justice Advisory Council (NEJAC). 2006. Unintended Impacts of Redevelopment and Revitalization Efforts in Five Environmental Justice Communities. Report, August. Noonan, Douglas S. 2008. “Evidence of Environmental Justice: A Critical Perspective on the Practice of EJ Research and Lessons for Policy Design.” Social Science Quarterly 89 (5): 1154 - 1174. Pancs, Romans, and Nicolaas J. Vriend. 2006. “Schellings’ Spatial Proximity Model of Segregation Revisited.” Journal of Public Economics 91: 1-24. Rinquist, Evan J. 1997. “Equity and Distribution of Environmental Risk: The Case of TRI Facilities.” Social Science Quarterly 78: 811-829. Ringquist, Evan J. 2006. “Environmental Justice: Normative Concerns, Empirical Evidence, and Government Action.” In Environmental Policy: New Directions for the Twenty-First Century, ed. by Norman J. Vig and Michael E. Kraft. Washington, DC: CQ Press. Sadd, James L., Manuel Pastor, J. Thomas Boer, and Lori D. Snyder. 1999. “'Every Breath You Take…:' The Demographics of Toxic Air Releases in Southern California.” Economic Development Quarterly 13(2): 107-123. Schelling, Thomas C. 1969. “Models of Segregation.” American Economic Review papers and proceedings 59: 488-93. Schelling, Thomas C. 1971. “Dynamic Models of Segregation.” Journal of Mathematical 23 Sociology 1: 143-86. Sethi, Rajiv, and Rohini Somanathan. 2004. “Inequity and Segregation.” Journal of Political Economy 112: 1296-1321. Sieg, Holger, V. Kerry Smith, H. Spencer Banzhaf, and Randy Walsh. 2004. “Estimating the General Equilibrium Benefits of Large Changes in Spatially Delineated Public Goods.” International Economic Review 45(4): 1047-1077. Tiebout, Charles. 1956. “A Pure Theory of Local Expenditures.” Journal of Political Economy 64: 416-424. 24 Figure 1: , Community Sorting and Bid Functions ( Panel 1: Racial Composition ). Panel 2: V Function 1 2 Pct Pct Pct Pct 0.9 0.8 W1 W2 B1 B2 V1W V2W 1.95 V1B V2B 0.7 0.6 1.9 0.5 0.4 1.85 0.3 0.2 1.8 0.1 0 0.5 0.55 0.6 0.65 0.7 0.75 0.8 0.85 Proportion White Community 1 0.9 0.95 1 1.75 0.5 0.55 Panel 3: Y-Bar 0.6 0.65 0.7 0.75 0.8 0.85 Proportion White Community 1 0.9 0.95 1 Panel 4: Bid Functions 0.7 0.01 ybarw ybarb 0.6 Bid ybarw 0.008 Bid ybarb 0.006 0.5 0.004 0.002 0.4 0 0.3 -0.002 -0.004 0.2 -0.006 0.1 -0.008 0 0.5 0.55 0.6 0.65 0.7 0.75 0.8 0.85 Proportion White Community 1 0.9 0.95 1 -0.01 0.5 0.55 0.6 0.65 0.7 0.75 0.8 0.85 Proportion White Community 1 0.9 0.95 1 25 Figure 2: , Community Sorting and Bid Functions ( ). Panel 1: Racial Composition Panel 2: V Function 1 2 Pct Pct Pct Pct 0.9 0.8 W1 W2 B1 B2 1.95 1.9 0.7 1.85 0.6 0.5 1.8 0.4 1.75 V1W 0.3 V2W 1.7 0.2 V1B 1.65 0.1 0 0.5 0.55 0.6 0.65 0.7 0.75 0.8 0.85 Proportion White Community 1 0.9 0.95 1 V2B 1.6 0.5 0.55 Panel 3: Y-Bar 0.6 0.65 0.7 0.75 0.8 0.85 Proportion White Community 1 0.9 0.95 1 Panel 4: Bid Functions -3 0.7 20 x 10 Bid ybarw ybarw 0.6 Bid ybarb ybarb 15 0.5 10 0.4 0.3 5 0.2 0 0.1 0 0.5 0.55 0.6 0.65 0.7 0.75 0.8 0.85 Proportion White Community 1 0.9 0.95 1 -5 0.5 0.55 0.6 0.65 0.7 0.75 0.8 0.85 Proportion White Community 1 0.9 0.95 1 26 Figure 3: Impact of Changes in G on Bid Functions 0.12 0.06 Bid ybarw Bid ybarw Bid ybarb 0.1 0.08 0.04 0.06 0.03 0.04 0.02 0.02 0.01 0 0.5 0.55 0.6 0.65 0.7 0.75 0.8 0.85 Proportion White Community 1 0.9 0.95 Bid ybarb 0.05 1 0.035 0 0.5 0.55 0.6 0.65 0.7 0.75 0.8 0.85 Proportion White Community 1 0.9 0.95 1 0.025 Bid ybarw Bid ybarw Bid ybarb 0.03 Bid ybarb 0.02 0.025 0.015 0.02 0.01 0.015 0.005 0.01 0 0.005 0 0.5 0.55 0.6 0.65 0.7 0.75 0.8 0.85 Proportion White Community 1 0.9 0.95 1 -0.005 0.5 0.55 0.6 0.65 0.7 0.75 0.8 0.85 Proportion White Community 1 0.9 0.95 1 -3 20 x 10 0.01 Bid ybarw Bid ybarw 0.008 Bid ybarb 15 Bid ybarb 0.006 0.004 10 0.002 5 -0.002 0 -0.004 0 -0.006 -0.008 -5 0.5 0.55 0.6 0.65 0.7 0.75 0.8 0.85 Proportion White Community 1 0.9 0.95 1 -0.01 0.5 0.55 0.6 0.65 0.7 0.75 0.8 0.85 Proportion White Community 1 0.9 0.95 1 27 Figure 4: Schematic of Stable Equilibria (Propositions III and IV) 28 Figure 5: Difference in Difference and Cross Sectional Relationships Difference in Differences 0.25 Change in G 0.2 .25 to .5 .5 to .7 .7 to .8 .8 to .9 .9 to 1 Change in Percent Black 0.15 0.1 0.05 0 -0.05 -0.1 -0.15 -0.2 -0.25 -0.05 0 0.05 0.1 0.15 0.2 0.25 0.3 Change in G Cross Sectional Relationships 0.5 G1=.25 G1=.5 G1=.7 G1=.8 G1=.9 Percent Black 0.4 0.3 0.2 0.1 0 0.2 0.3 0.4 0.5 0.6 0.7 Level of G 0.8 0.9 1 1.1 29 Figure 6. Improvements in TRI Emissions, 1990-2000 (3-year average) 1988-90 to 1998-2000 Change 3.1e+08 -3.1e+08 3.1e+08 0 1988-90 Average Hazard-Weighted TRI Exposure 30 Table 1. Estimated Effect of Average TRI Exposure in 1990 and 2000 and Difference β2000 β1990 Δβ Latitude, Dist Coast -19,563*** (534) -20,059*** (403) 496 (623) School Dist dummies -15,168*** () -16,407*** (443) 1,239** (631) Zip Code dummies -6,444*** (423) -7,707*** (351) 1,263** (510) 238 (480) -1,259*** (368) 1,498*** (399) Latitude, Dist Coast 29.22*** (0.82) 16.31*** (0.63) 12.91*** (1.01) School Dist dummies 18.99*** (0.66) 6.71*** (0.55) 12.29*** (0.82) Zip Code dummies 11.49*** (0.58) -0.76* (0.46) 11.49*** (0.58) Community FE 2.95*** (0.67) -9.26*** (0.46) 12.21*** (0.52) Outcome/Spatial controls Mean Income (1990$) Community FE Pct Minority (pct points) ο¦ Estimates are for the effect of ο€ˆet ο§ 1 ο§ ο₯ 1(e1990 οΎ 0) ο¨ j j ο₯e j|ej οΎ0 1990 j οΆ ο· ο« ο€ˆ t . That is, they are the effect in year t of a plant ο· I οΈ with average 1990 emission levels. The effect accounts for the extensive margin of such a “typical plant” as well as the intensive margin of emission levels. Robust standard errors are in parentheses. ***Significant at 1% level, ** 5%, * 10%. 31 Appendix. Proof of Proposition I We begin by noting that when public good levels are equal: (a) (b) (c) π΅πππΜ π < π΅πππΜ π€ when PCTwC1 < 1-β, π΅πππΜ π > π΅πππΜ π€ when PCTwC1 > 1-β, and π΅πππΜ π = π΅πππΜ π€ = 0 when PCTwC1 = 1-β. (a) can is true because Drj is highest in the community with more of type j. With GC1=GC2, it follows that Vrj is also higher in that community. (b) follows by the symmetric logic. (c) also follows by similar logic: in this case, DrC1=DrC2 so VC1=VC2. The rest follows from Observations 4 and 5. Proof of Proposition II20 The first part of the proof follows directly from the continuity of the bid functions and the implicit function theorem. It states that the single unstable integrated equilibrium and the segregated equilibrium with all type-b individuals in C2 that are present when public goods are equal continues to hold and be the only possible equilibria for at least small perturbations in the G’s around this point. The second part of the proposition states that the stable segregated equilibrium with all type-b individuals in C1 is more robust. When public good levels are higher in Community 2, the boundary income bid function for type-w individuals will always be positive when PCTwC1 = 1-2β (the sorting with all type b individuals in C1), since type w perceives both the G and the D components to be higher in C2. Conversely, type-b individuals always prefer the demographic composition of C1 under this sorting. Thus, when PCTwC1 = 1-2β, their boundary income bid function will remain negative until the difference in public goods becomes large enough to offset these demographic preferences. As a result, the segregated equilibrium with all type-b individuals in C1 will continue to exist at least until GC1 becomes low enough that VbC2 > VbC1. 20 Note: Still need to flesh this out and show that a) that this equilibria survives longer than the segregated equilibria with type b in community 2, and b) that once this equilibirium disappears, it is gone for good. 32 Proof of Proposition III. Part (i). We begin by re-writing Equation 4 as follows: ππ΅πππΜ π ππΜ π ππ·ππΆ2 ππ·ππΆ1 1 πΆ2 πΆ2 πΆ1 1πΆ1 = + [(π π − π π ) − ππ₯πΆ1 ] πΆ2 π π· π π· πΆ1 πΆ1 πΆ1 πΆ1 πππΆππ€ πππΆππ€ πππΆππ€ πππΆππ€ ππ₯ By assumption, Bidy → y as GC1→-∞. Thus, by the Inada conditions ππ₯πΆ2 →∞. Therefore, for ππΜ π sufficiently low GC1, the entire term in brackets → 0 and we can focus on the first term πππΆππ€ πΆ1 . As shown in the text, ππΜ π 0.5 = − <0 πππΆππ€ πΆ1 π½ππ (πΜ π ) ππΜ π€ 0.5 = >0 πππΆππ€ πΆ1 (1 − π½)ππ€ (πΜ π€ ) whenever πππΆ1 > πππΆ2 . Therefore, ππ΅πππΜ π <0 πππΆππ€ πΆ1 and ππ΅πππΜ π€ > 0. πππΆππ€ πΆ1 In other words, the boundary income bid function is monotonically increasing for type w and monotonically decreasing for type b. Part (ii). 0.5−π½ Next, note that at PCTwC1=1-2β, πΜ π =πππππ₯ and πΜ π€ =πΉπ€−1 ( 1−π½ ) < πΉπ€−1 (1 − 2π½) given β<0.5. Again, since Bidy → y, it follows that π΅πππΜ π =πππππ₯ and π΅πππΜ π€ =πΉπ€−1 (1 − 2π½). Using Equation (1), we then have π΅πππΜ π > π΅πππΜ π€ . Note that by Observation 4, this cannot be an equilibrium. Part (iii) 33 0.5 Similarly, note that at PCTwC1=1, πΜ π =πππππ =0 and πΜ π€ =πΉπ€−1 (1−π½) > 0. Thus π΅πππΜ π€ > π΅πππΜ π = 0. Again, by Observation 4, this cannot be an equilibrium. Part (iv) We now combine parts (i) to (iii). By part (ii), we have that at PCTwC1=1-2β, π΅πππΜ π > π΅πππΜ π€ . By part (i), we know π΅πππΜ π is monotonically decreasing in PCTwC1 and π΅πππΜ π€ is monotonically increasing. By part (iii) we have that at PCTwC1=1, π΅πππΜ π < π΅πππΜ π€ . Therefore, the two boundary income bid functions cross once, with π΅πππΜ π crossing π΅πππΜ π from above. This is a stable integrated equilibrium. Moreover, as noted above the segregated equilibria are ruled out by Observation 4. Therefore, a single equilibrium exists, it is integrated, and it is stable. 34