Why do things look the way they do?

advertisement
Why do things look the way they do?
 Because that’s they way they really are!? That question is
misleading because “how things look” is ill defined in the
absence of further theoretical analysis.
 In this class we will look at a somewhat related question:
 What does the way things appear to us in our conscious
experience tell us about how vision and mental imagery
works and about the nature of the representations we
construct when we see or visualize?


La Grande Illusion is the belief that we have access to the
form of representation we construct in episodes of cognition
Recent example: Wegner, in The Illusion of Conscious Will,
Argues that what we are conscious of is not what causes our
voluntary acts
 ZP: “…the ‘illusion’ is really that the experience we have of
causing certain things to happen explains why it happened”
This is what our conscious experience
suggests goes on in vision…
This is what the demands of explanation
suggests must be going on in vision…
Subjective experience suggests that when
we see, we are examining an inner display
Are there any reasons (other than conscious
experience) for taking this view seriously?

The completion of percepts from partial information
Blind spot, resolution and color sensitivity
‘amodal completion’ (most scene objects are occluded)

Completions have real behavioral consequences
‘illusory contours’ and amodal completions act in many
ways like real figures

Visual representations appear to be panoramic,
stable, and in an allocentric frame of reference
The superposition theory has a lot of intuitive appeal
Completions
…
Where’s Waldo?
Standard view of saccadic
integration by superposition
The superposition view fails
O'Regan, J. K., & Lévy-Schoen, A. (1983). Integrating visual information from successive
fixations: Does trans-saccadic fusion exist? Vision Research, 23(8), 765-768.
Visual interpretation is local
Partly Ambiguous
Unambiguous #1
Unambiguous #2
Visual interpretation is local
Visual interpretation is local
Coordinating the interpretations among parts is more
difficult if they are not both visible at the same time
When temporal integration occurs
is shows the effect of memory load
Higher memory load
Lower memory load
When temporal integration occurs
is shows the effect of memory load
When temporal integration occurs
order of presentation is important
Errors in recall suggest how
visual information is encoded
Children have very good visual memory,
yet often make egregious errors of recall
 Errors in relative orientation often take a
canonical form

Errors in reproducing a 3D image preserve
3D information
Errors in recall suggest how
visual information is encoded

Children more often confuse left-right than
rotated forms

Errors in imitating actions is another source
of evidence
Ability to manipulate and recall patterns depends
on their conceptual, not geometric, complexity

Difficulty in superimposing shapes depends
on they are conceptualized
Look at first two shapes and superimpose them in your mind;
then draw (or select one) that is their superposition
Many studies have shown that memory for
shapes is dependent on the conceptual
vocabulary available for encoding them
e.g., recall of chess positions by beginners and masters
Finally, the phenomenology of seeing (including
its completeness, its filled-out details, and its
panoramic scope) turns out to be an illusion!



We see far less, and with far less detail and scope,
than our phenomenology suggests
Objectively, outside a small region called the fovea,
we are colorblind and our sight is so bad we are
legally blind. The rest of the visual field is
seriously distorted and even in the fovea not all
colors are in focus at once.
More importantly, we register surprisingly little of
what is in our field of view. Despite the subjective
impression that we can see a great deal that we
cannot report, recent evidence suggests that we
cannot even tell when things change as we watch.
What changes between flashes?
Harborside
Airplane
Helicopter
Dinner
Farm scene
Paris corner
Where does this leave us?


Should we conclude that seeing is a process of constructing
conceptual descriptions?
Most cognitive scientists and AI people would say yes,
although there would be several types of exception.
 There remains the possibility that for very short durations (e.g.
0.25 sec) there is a form of representation very like visual
persistence – sometimes called an ‘iconic storage’ (Sperling, 1960).
 From a neuroscience perspective there is evidence of a neural
representation in early vision – in primary visual cortex – that is
retinotopic and therefore “pictorial.” Doesn’t this suggest that a
‘picture” is available in the brain in vision?
 We shall see later that this evidence is seriously misleading and
does not support a picture theory of working memory or LTM
 A major theme of this course will be to show that an important
mechanism of vision is not conceptual but causal: Visual Indexes
 Many people continue to hold a version of the “picture theory” of
mental representation in mental imagery. More on this later.
Conceptual & Methodological Problems
in the study of Visual Perception

There is a problem about what it means to see: Ordinary usage
confounds: seeing X, seeing X as R, seeing that P, and believing
that P. Distinguishing these is a cottage industry in philosophy.
 Some examples of the prescientific sense of see and why it is a
problem (Droodles, “looks like”) Examples of droodles
 Ordinary language also confounds the content and the vehicle of
perception: what perceptual representations are about and what
properties the representations themselves have
 There is a serious problem about what to make of phenomenology
– about the conscious experience of seeing. In view of how
misleading subjective experience can be, and in view of the fact
that what progress there is cognitive science has been made by
ignoring the distinction between processes of which we are
consciously aware and those of which we have no conscious
experience. Cognitive Science, unlike philosophy, has tended to
shy away from the evidence of introspection.
Conceptual & Methodological Problems
in the study of Visual Perception

Part of the puzzle about vision rests on the failure to
make certain distinctions (such as those alluded to
earlier: between seeing and believing, between content
and form). These two distinctions will play a major role
in our later discussion.

The question posed at the beginning of this lecture, Why
do things look the way they do? asks why the
appearance is conceptualized (or described) a certain
way. The difficulty with this idea is dramatized by the
Wittgenstein story.
What does “how things look” mean?


We speak of someone “looking sick,” or “looking happy”
or of the weather “looking like it’s going to snow.” This
informal sense of looking is too diverse to be useful.
A story due to Wittgenstein (as told by Tom Stoppard), goes:
Meeting a friend in the hall, a philosopher says, “Tell me,
why do people always say it was natural for men to assume
that the sun went around the earth rather than that the earth
was rotating?” His friend said, “Well, obviously, because it
just looks as if the sun was going round the earth.” To
which the philosopher replied, “Well, what would it have
looked like if it had looked as if the earth was rotating?”

The problematic nature of How Things Look will become
even more apparent when we discuss mental imagery later.
As a take-home exercise you might think about “Why do
mental images look like what they are images of?”
Conceptual & Methodological Problems
in the study of Visual Perception

An important distinction that I will address only
briefly (but is covered in Chapters 2 and 3) is
between seeing and coming to have a belief about
what one is seeing. This is crucial to my claim
about the Cognitive Impenetrability of Vision or the
view of vision as an architectural module.
The development of Signal Detection Theory alerted
us to the fact that signal detection involves at least
two stages: a detection stage and a response selection
or decision stage, the latter of which is the only stage
that is cognitively penetrable.
Download