Cognitive Economics Miles Kimball University of Michigan Presentation at Osaka University Definition of Cognitive Economics: The Economics of What is in People’s Minds Named by Analogy to “Cognitive Psychology” • Cognitive Psychology = the area of psychology that examines internal mental processes such as problem solving, memory and language. • Cognitive Psychology was a departure from Behaviorism--the idea that only outward behavior was a legitimate subject of study. 2/65 How is “Cognitive Economics” Different from “Behavioral” or “Psychological” Economics? 1. Cognitive economics is narrower. 2. Much of cognitive economics is inspired by the internal dynamic of economics rather than by psychology. 3. Cognitive economics is a field of study, not a school of thought. 3/65 Areas of Economics by Distinctive Data Type • Standard Economics (including “Mindless” Psychological Economics a la Gul and Pesendorfer): actual market choices only. • Experimental Economics: choices in artificial situations but with real stakes. • Neuroeconomics: FMRI, saccades, skin conductance, … • Bioeconomics: genes, hormones • Cognitive Economics: mental contents (based on tests and self-reports) and hypothetical choices. 4/65 Four Themes of Cognitive Economics 1. 2. 3. 4. New Types of Data Heterogeneity Finite and Scarce Cognition Welfare Economics Revisited 5/65 1. Innovative Survey Data • • • • • fluid intelligence data crystallized intelligence data happiness data survey measures of expectations survey measures of preferences 6/65 2. Individual Heterogeneity • • • • heterogeneous expectations heterogeneous preferences heterogeneous emotional reactions heterogeneous views on how the world works (folk theories) 7/65 3. Finite and Scarce Cognition • Finite cognition=the reality that people are not infinitely intelligent. • Scarce cognition=some decisions required by our modern environment—at work and in private lives—can require more intelligence for full-scale optimization than an individual has 8/65 4. Welfare Economics Revisited • • • Scarce cognition means that people sometimes make mistakes. Thus, one can no longer use naïve revealed preference for welfare economics. Kimball and Willis, in “Utility and Happiness,” argue that happiness data is not a magical touchstone for diagnosing mistakes. Then, what does count as evidence of mistakes? – – – – Internal inconsistencies, such as lack of transitivity? But which choice then deserves respect? Regret? Modification of choices after experience? Differences in choices between those with high cognitive ability and those with low cognitive ability? • e.g., Dan Benjamin and Jesse Shapiro show that low IQ students had more low-stakes risk aversion and short-horizon impatience 9/65 Some Research Questions in Cognitive Economics • Seek to make innovations in economic theory and measurement to address: – What are people’s limitations in knowledge, memory, reasoning, calculation? – What is the role of emotion, social context, conscious vs. unconscious judgments and decisions? – What is the role of health as determinant, outcome and context for economic activity, decisions and well being? – What is connection between economic welfare and measures of well being? – Etc. 10/65 New Types of Data: Measurement of Cognition in the HRS • HRS has included cognitive measures from the outset, but mostly focused on memory in order to trace cognitive decline. • Re-engineering HRS cognitive measures – Led by Jack McArdle, a cognitive psychologist and HRS co-PI, we have begun a project to “re-engineer” our cognitive measures in order to improve our understanding of the determinants of decision-making about retirement, savings and health and their implications for the well-being of older Americans 11/65 New Types of Data: Measurement of Cognition in the HRS (cont.) • Separate HRS-Cognition Study – Begins with a separate sample of 1200 persons age 50+ who will receive about three hours of cognitive testing of their fluid and crystallized intelligence plus parts of the HRS questionnaire on demographics, health and cognition – Followed a month later by administration of an internet or mail survey of questions designed by economists on financial literacy, ability to compound-discount, hypothetical decisions about portfolio choice, long term care – Finally, telephone follow-up with HRS cognition items and subjective probability questions – Analysis of data will guide re-engineering of cognitive items for HRS-2010 12/65 New Types of Data: Survey Measures of Expectations What is the mapping between probability beliefs in people’s minds and the decisions they make? (Robert Willis, Charles Manski, Mike Hurd, Jeff Dominitz, Adeline Delavande) Direct Measurement of Subjective Probability Beliefs in HRS Probability questions use a format pioneered by Tom Juster and Chuck Manski (Manski, 2004) HRS Survival Probability Question: “Using a number from 0 to 100, what do you think are the chances that you will live to be at least [target age X]?” X = 80 for persons 50 to 70 and increases to 85, 90, 95, 100 for each five year increase in age 14/65 Two Key Findings From Previous Research on HRS Probability Questions 1. On average, probabilities make sense – Survival probabilities conform to life tables and are predictive of actual mortality (Hurd and McGarry 1995, 2002; Sloan, et. al., 2001 ) – Bequest probabilities behave sensibly (Smith 1999), Perry (2006) – Retirement incentives can be analyzed using expectational data (Chan and Stevens, 2003) – People can predict nursing home entry (Finkelstein and McGarry, 2006) – Early Social Security Claiming Depends on Survival Probability (Delevande, Perry and Willis, 2006) , (Coile, et. al., 2002) 2. Individual probabilities are very noisy with heaping on focal values of "0", "50-50" and "100“ (Hurd, McFadden and Gan, 1998) 15/65 10 Year Mortality Rate vs. Subjective Survival Probability to Age 75 3.00 2.76 2.49 2.50 Odds Ratio (50%=1.0) Odds Ratio of Death by t+10 2.00 1.47 1.50 1.43 1.22 1.00 1.00 0.86 0.85 0.79 0.68 0.70 80 90 0.50 0.00 0 10 20 30 40 50 60 70 100 Probability of survival to age 75 Subjective Survival Probability at Time t Source: Mortality Computations from HRS-2002 by David Weir 16/65 10 Year Mortality Rate vs. Subjective Survival Probability to Age 75 3.00 2.76 Strongest relationship between subjective and objective risks for people with low subjective survival beliefs 2.49 2.50 Odds Ratio (50%=1.0) Odds Ratio of Death by t+10 2.00 1.47 1.50 1.43 1.22 1.00 1.00 0.86 0.85 0.79 0.68 0.70 80 90 0.50 0.00 0 10 20 30 40 50 60 70 100 Probability of survival to age 75 Subjective Survival Probability at Time t Source: Mortality Computations from HRS-2002 by David Weir 17/65 . Histograms of Responses to Probability Questions in the HRS .3 .2 .2 F r a c tio n Social Security less generous Double digit inflation F r a c tio n A. General Events .1 .1 0 0 0 100 0 .3 .2 .2 0 0 0 0 50 W ill L iv e T o B e 7 5 100 .3 .4 .2 100 .1 .2 Leave inheritance Work at age 62 50 In c o m e W ill K e e p U p W ith In fla tio n F r a c tio n .6 F r a c tio n C. Events with Personal Control 100 .1 .1 Survival to 75 Income increase faster than inflation 50 D o u b le -D ig it In fla tio n F r a c tio n .3 F r a c tio n B. Events with Personal Information 50 S o c ia l S e c u rity T o B e L e s s G e n e ro u s 0 0 0 50 W ill L e a ve In h e rita n c e > = 1 0 ,0 0 0 100 0 50 W ill W o rk A t A g e 6 2 100 18/65 Are Benefits of Greater Individual Choice Influenced by Quality of Probabilistic Thinking? • Trend of increasing scope for individual choice in public and private policy, especially as it affects those planning for retirement or already retired – Private sector shift from defined benefit to defined contribution pension plans – Proposals for “individual accounts” in Social Security – Choice of when/whether to annuitize – Choice of medical insurance plans and providers by employers and by Medicare, new Medicare Prescription Drug program • Economists generally view increased choice as a good thing, but … – General public wonders whether people will make wise use of choice – Decisions faced by older individuals balancing risks and benefits of alternative financial and health care choices are genuinely difficult 19/65 Quality of Probabilistic Thinking and Uncertainty Aversion • Lillard and Willis (2001) began to look at the pattern of responses to probability questions as indicators of the degree to which they indicate people’s capacity to think clearly about subjective probability beliefs • We explored the idea that focal answers of “0”, “50” and “100” were perhaps indicators of less coherent or well-formed beliefs than non-focal (or “exact”) answers. 20/65 Index of Focal Responses We treated the probability questions like a psychological battery and constructed an empirical propensity to give focal answers of “0”, “50” or “100” number focal answers Index of Focal Answers = total number of probability questions We found that people who had a lower propensity to give focal answers tended to have higher wealth, had riskier portfolios, and achieved higher rates of return, controlling for conventional economic and demographic variables 21/65 Uncertainty Aversion • We hypothesized that people who give more focal answers are more uncertain about the true value of probabilities • If the uncertainty is about a repeated risk, such as the return to a stock portfolio held over time, we show that people who have more imprecise probability beliefs (i.e. are more uncertain about the “true” probability) will behave more risk aversely 22/65 Some Further Results on Subjective Probabilities • There is “optimism factor” common across all probability questions which is correlated with stock-holding and associated with being “healthy, wealthy and wise” • Kezdi and Willis (2003) • HRS has added direct questions on stock returns – stockholding is related to probability beliefs • Kezdi and Willis (2003) and Dominitz and Manski (2006) – most people do not believe that stocks have positive returns, despite the equity premium that economists know about • Persons who provide more precise probability answers also exhibit less risk aversion on subjective risk aversion questions in the HRS, and they save a higher fraction of their full wealth. • Sahm (2007), Pounder (2007) • In 2006, HRS added questions to those who answer “50” to see whether they mean “equally probable” or “just uncertain”. 75% indicate they are uncertain. 23/65 New Types of Data: Survey Measures of Preferences Based on Hypothetical Choices Examples: • Labor Supply Elasticities, • Altruism, • Social Rivalry, • Risk Aversion, • Elasticity of Intertemporal Substitution 24/65 Does Risk Tolerance Change? Claudia Sahm University of MichiganBoard of Governors 26/65 27/65 28/65 29/65 30/65 31/65 32/65 33/65 34/65 35/65 36/65 37/65 38/65 39/65 40/65 41/65 42/65 43/65 44/65 45/65 46/65 47/65 48/65 Measuring Time Preference and the Elasticity of Intertemporal Substitution Miles S. Kimball, Claudia R. Sahm and Matthew D. Shapiro September 6, 2006 Internet Project Meeting Behavioral Model log c s(r ) • c is consumption, • r is the real interest rate, • s is the elasticity of intertemporal substitution, and • ρ is the subjective discount rate 50/65 Research Design Vary Treatment : r Observe Response : c Estimate Parameters : s, ρ 51/65 Implementation • Vary Interest Rate – Vary cost of current consumption – Vary length of time periods • Measure Consumption Choice – Choose among small set of paths – Actively form a desired path • Infer Preferences – Summary statistics of responses – Statistical model with response error 52/65 Previous Survey Measures • HRS 1992 Module K, N = 198 – Analyzed by Barsky, Kimball, Juster, and Shapiro (QJE 1997) • HRS 1999 Mailout, N = 1,210 – Similar content to part of Internet Survey Questions explicitly vary the cost of current consumption and offer a discrete choice over a small set of consumption paths 53/65 MS Internet Survey Wave 2 (Fall 2004) Use graphics on Internet to test other measures: • Version 1, N = 350 – Vary cost of consumption – Choose from set of pairs • Version 2, N = 155 – Vary cost of consumption – Move bars to create pair • Version 3, N = 183 – Vary length of period – Move bars to create pair 54/65 Series Introduction - Version 1 - • Series includes four questions with varying interest rates55/65 Introduction – 0% Interest Rate • Sequence r = {0%, 4.6%, 9.2%, 13.8%} is random • Introduction repeated for each interest rate 56/65 Patterns – 0% Interest Rate • Asked to choose two patterns • Above screen (1 of 6) is identical to HRS Mail Out 57/65 Expansion Screen • Follow-up if first choice on boundary (A or E) • New feature on Internet 58/65 Randomize Pair C • Choice C positive, zero, negative growth rate • 3 values to the parameter • New feature on Internet • Top screen on mail out 59/65 Randomize Left-to-Right • Growth rates increase or decrease left-to-right • New feature on Internet • Top screen on mail out 60/65 Randomize Shifts with Interest Rate • Example with r = 9.2% • Choice of ($2750, $3900) moves from E to C to A • 3 values to the parameter • New feature on Internet • Middle screen on mail out 61/65 Summary of Innovations in Internet Question Series • 18 different screen groups • 6 different sequences of interest rates • 11 discrete choices per question Purpose of Innovations • Encourage active choices • Increase informative responses • Isolate framing effects 62/65 Response Statistics Internet Mail Any Responders Complete Sequence % 100.0 82.2 N 366 301 % 100.0 88.2 N 930 820 Complete Responders Second Choice Pairs All Extreme Pairs 100.0 77.1 2.0 301 232 6 100.0 90.6 17.2 820 743 141 • Internet lower completion rate • Internet fewer second choices • Internet fewer non-informative responses 63/65 Consumption Growth at 0% Interest Rate 45 40 35 Percent 30 25 20 15 10 5 13.9 11.6 9.2 6.9 4.6 2.3 0.0 -2.3 -4.6 -6.9 -9.2 -11.6 -13.9 0 Consumption Growth at 0% Interest Rate Internet Mail • Constant consumption is modal choice 64/65 Change in Consumption Growth as Interest Rate to 13.8% from 0% 60 50 Internet % Increase Growth 48.5 % Decrease Growth 25.9 Percent 40 Mail 26.5 17.2 30 20 10 23.1 20.8 18.5 16.2 13.9 11.6 9.2 6.9 4.6 2.3 0.0 -2.3 -4.6 -6.9 -9.2 -11.6 -13.9 -16.2 -18.5 -20.8 -23.1 0 Growth at r = 13.8% Minus Growth at r = 0% Internet Mail 65/65 • Interest rates change consumption more on Internet Change in Consumption Growth as Interest Rate Increases - Internet 45 40 35 % Increase Growth % Decrease Growth Percent 30 4.9% 34.2 22.9 13.8% 48.5 25.9 25 20 15 10 5 23.1 20.8 18.5 16.2 13.9 11.6 9.2 6.9 4.6 2.3 0.0 -2.3 -4.6 -6.9 -9.2 -11.6 -13.9 -16.2 -18.5 -20.8 -23.1 0 Consumption Growth - Growth at 0% Interest Rate r = 4.6% r = 13.8% • Decrease in growth is a sign of survey response 66/65 error Estimates of Parameters Average in Sample Growth at r = 0% : -sρ Internet 0.1% Mail 1.3% IES by Interest Rate : s 0% to 4.6% 4.6% to 9.2% 9.2% to 13.8% 0.13 0.14 0.05 0.004 0.01 0.04 • Responses reveal low time preference and IES • Median and modal values in both surveys equal 0 67/65 Effect of Changes in Choice Set 50 Growth Rates in Choice Set Choice Decrease Stable Increase % Increase 47.9 35.6 61.5 % Decrease 42.7 16.8 19.2 45 40 Percent 35 30 25 20 15 10 5 0 -23.1 to -6.9 -4.6 to -2.3 0 2.3 to 4.6 6.9 to 23.1 Growth at r=13.8% Minus Growth at r =0% Decrease Stable Increase 68/65 Estimates by Screen Group Average in Sample Growth at r = 0% : -sρ IES by Interest Rate : s 0% to 4.6% 4.6% to 9.2% 9.2% to 13.8% Respondents Interest Rate Increases, Growth Rates in Choice Set Decrease Stable Increase -0.14% 0.4% 0.15% -0.10 0.30 -0.31 96 0.16 0.00 0.12 101 0.32 0.14 0.33 104 69/65 More Graphical Questions - Version 2 - • Move bars to select a consumption path 70/65 More Graphical Questions - Version 3 - • Vary length of current and future periods 71/65 Extensions / Renewal • Measure complementary parameters – Diminishing marginal utility – Labor supply elasticities – Retirement elasticity 72/65 Four Themes of Cognitive Economics 1. 2. 3. 4. New Types of Data Heterogeneity Finite and Scarce Cognition Welfare Economics Revisited 73/65 “Bounded Rationality” vs. “Scarce Cognition” • • Same meaning, but “bounded rationality” seems a misnomer, since it is rational to recognize one’s own cognitive limitations. Two obstacles have prevented “Bounded Rationality” from becoming part of the mainstream – theoretical difficulties stemming from the importance of constrained optimization as a theoretical tool in economics – paucity of data • “Scarce Cognition” is meant to label a data-rich research agenda, using new theoretical tools. 74/65 The Reality of Finite Cognition • Computers beat us at chess • People don’t get perfect scores on tests, even after they have studied the material • For hundreds of years, we had no proof of Fermat’s last theorem 75/65 The Reality of Scarce Cognition Many people … • spend time and money learning math • pay others with higher wage rates to do their taxes • pay others to read law books for them • pay for financial advice 76/65 Modeling Scarce Cognition is Hard: The Infinite Regress Problem (Conlisk) • It is natural for economists to assume a cost of computation, just like any other cost—so why not more such models? • Answer: figuring out how hard to think about a problem is always a strictly harder problem than the original problem – Need the solution to the original problem to calculate the benefit – Need to know how to solve the problem to know how many computational steps it needs 77/65 Dodging the Infinite Regress Problem by Breaking Taboos 1. Ignoring computational costs at the outer level. (Maybe OK if the original problem is a repeated choice.) 2. Using limited information transmission capacity as a metaphor for limited intelligence. (“A thick skull.”) 3. Subhuman intelligence: --agent-based modeling --rules of thumb (adaptive expectations, consume income, statistical models) 4. Modeling folk theories ignorant of the maintained hypotheses 78/65 Modeling Unawareness Requires a Subjective State Space Distinct from the True State Space (Dekel, Lipman and Rustichini) • economic actor: subjective state space • analyst: state space maintained as true 79/65 Two Levels of Theory • Folk theory: economic actor’s theory modeled in the subjective state space • Metatheory: the analyst’s theory which includes a description of the relevant folk theories. – – – – – Preferences Technology Available Strategies Active Information Structure Folk Theories or Accounting Frameworks of Agents 80/65 Desirable Properties for a Model of a Folk Theory • Accuracy in describing how people actually view the world • Providing a clear prediction for how people will behave in various circumstances • Representing clearly how people are confused and what they do understand. NOT REQUIRED: deep logical consistency 81/65 An Example of Folk Physics • Many people believe that if they swing a stone around on a string and let it go, then the stone will curve sideways in the direction they were swinging it around. • Other than going up and down in the vertical direction, it actually goes straight once released. 82/65 An Example of Folk Finance max si 0 si 1 ( i / 2)( si s / 2) 2 i 2 i i i 83/65 84/65 85/65 86/65 87/65 88/65 89/65 90/65 91/65 Household Finance and Welfare Economics: The Possibility of Strong Normative Statements • Fungibility: money is money – At the end of the day, only the total value of the portfolio matters, not the separate value of its constituent parts. – Fungibility is a legal term: OK to pay back a different piece of currency as long as the value is the same. (Not like a diamond ring) – Very basic principle in economics: fungibility of money is assumed in standard treatments of revealed preference – Noneconomists do not always understand fungibility: “mental accounts” 92/65