Ethics: What Are We Talking About? Some ethical questions: What is a good action? What is the good life? How should we live? What is the difference, if there is one, between goodness and rightness? Our first order of business should be to get clear about this (unexpectedly) vague, ambiguous term goodness. There are many senses of goodness: a good hammer is one which properly fulfills its function; a good hamburger is one that is pleasing to the senses; your parents know what is good for you because they know what steps to take to get you into a stable, comfortable situation. But in ethics we want to discuss moral goodness, specifically. What does it mean for something to be morally good? Well, this is one of the primary (and disputed) questions of ethics, so it is really up to you to determine what you think is the nature of moral goodness. For the sake of clarity and organization, however, we will provisionally state that if something is good, then it has moral value, either intrinsic or instrumental. Intrinsic goods are things that are good in themselves, are good for their own sake. Instrumental goods are things that are good in view of something else, because they are a means to something of intrinsic value. Plato 427 B.C. – 327 B.C. “The safest general characterization of the European philosophical tradition is that it consists of a series of footnotes to Plato.” – Alfred North Whitehead “Out of Plato come all things that are still written and debated about among men of thought.” - Ralph Waldo Emerson The Two Arcs of Euthyphro I What is the nature of goodness? II The Euthyphro Dilemma Setting the Scene Meletus is prosecuting Socrates for corrupting the youth of Athens by inventing new gods and discarding the ole ones. Euthyphro meets Socrates outside of the court and happens to be going there to prosecute his own father for homicide. At that time in Athens, prosecuting your parents was thought to be a reprehensible thing to do, so Socrates asks him… And So It Begins Socrates: Euthyphro, aren’t you afraid that you are doing something that is evil? Euthyphro: Not at all because I possess understanding about morality. Socrates: Excellent! I can learn from you! Euthyphro, what is good? Or should we even assume there is a single standard of goodness by which to measure all things? Euthyphro: First, yes, there is such a lone standard of goodness. Second… Failure At First Euthyphro: This is good, what I’m doing right now, namely prosecuting a criminal regardless of who he is. Neglecting this act would be evil…but look how I’m treated! Zeus justly imprisoned his own father, yet people praise and adore him. Here I am, doing the very same thing, and I am reviled by people! Act I: What is Virtue? The dialogue begins with a moral question but its content rapidly becomes epistemological. What’s the question again? Before determining anything about virtue, one surely has to know what virtue is. Meno first answers extensionally, that is, he provides a list of virtues. However, Socrates is looking for an intensional definition. He seeks a single quality or criterion that unifies the virtues and explains why they are virtues. In general terms, Socrates believes that, in addition to the many F’s, there is one thing, the F itself, that the many F’s posses and that explains why these F’s are F. The unity of virtue assumption is an important element of Plato’s work. Take A Step Back, Euthy Euthyphro commits the same error that Meno does by extensionally defining goodness. Socrates desires an intensional definition of goodness; he wants to know what feature or property do things have that make them good. Providing and explaining such a definition will allow us to use it as a kind of measuring stick for judging things. Again, we see the unity of virtue assumption in Plato. Answer #1 Euthyphro makes his first attempt at giving an intensional definition of goodness: What the gods love is good. What the gods hate is evil. In other words, the goodmaking feature of a thing is that the gods love it. Rebuttal The gods have disputes all the time. The origin of those disputes are differing opinions on what is just/unjust, good/bad, beautiful/ugly, etc. Such a dispute requires that the disputants value, care about or love different things. Thus, at least some of the gods love different things than some of the others. This leaves us with competing, conflicting accounts of goodness. Not only are there different itemized sets of what is good and what is evil, but also the same thing could be both good and evil. Answer #2 There are things that all the gods love, such as the principle that injustice should be punished. What all the gods love is good. What all the gods hate is evil. What the gods’ views differ about is morally neutral. In other words, there is some good-making feature of a thing that the gods identify and that causes them to love it. The Euthyphro Dilemma Is a thing good because the gods love it, or do the gods love a thing because it is good? This is a HUGE dilemma for any system of ethics that wants to incorporate the divine because both answers seem to have problems. You might be thinking that because the dilemma is couched in Greek religious terminology that it doesn’t apply to Christianity. Oh how wrong you are. We will return to this point later. Rebuttal Again If the gods love a thing because it is good, rather than making a thing good because they love it, then it seems that something else besides the gods is making things good. But, if we say that a thing is good because the gods love it, then the gods remain the only source of goodness. However, the problem pointed out above remains. Rerouting Euthyphro is stumped and claims that, though he knows the truth, he cannot explain it because once he states it, it runs around in circles and refuses to stay put. Socrates decides to take a different approach to the problem: by comparing the good to the just he attempts to isolate a boundary of goodness. This discovery would certainly assist the two in their quest to discern the nature of goodness. Answer #3…? Socrates: Is everything that is just also good or is goodness a division of justice? Euthyphro: Serving the gods is both just and good while serving human beings is not good but is just. Socrates: How do we serve the gods? Euthyphro: We serve the gods by sacrifice and prayer. Socrates: What exactly do the gods gain from our service? Euthyphro: They gain gratification and esteem. Socrates: Is such gratification or esteem of benefit to them or do they simply value it, care for it, love it? Euthyphro: They love it most of all but not because it is instrumental to something they could not get otherwise. The gods gain no benefit from anything that we do. Socrates: So, goodness, serving the gods, is good simply because the gods love it. But…didn’t we see a problem with that? Socrates wants to learn the truth and won’t be an intellectual “coward.” Euthyphro is frustrated, and gets the heck out of there. The dialogue ends in aporia. Euthyphro Dilemma and Christian Ethics Let us restate the dilemma and examine the problems that either answer entails for Christian theology. Is a thing good because God loves it, or does God love a thing because it is good? If you choose the former, then the sole criterion of a thing’s goodness is God’s will. The good is whatever God chooses it to be without restriction. Tomorrow, God could declare that bunny stomping or candy stealing are good, and they would be. Depending on what you believe about your conscience being in tune with the Holy Spirit, you would feel the moral conviction to stomp bunnies or steal candy. Morality becomes arbitrary. There is no rational basis for morality, and, therefore, the true moral code cannot be discovered by reason alone. This view is known as theological voluntarism. If you choose the later, then the criterion of goodness exists apart from God. The standard of good and evil is not located within God Himself, but it is something that He recognizes and adheres to (since He is omni-benevolent). Such a standard even applies to God. God’s thoughts and actions are judged to be good based on something beyond even Him. God judges us, not based on His laws and principles that originate with Him but according to some independent law. The difficulties for the orthodox Christian in maintaining either of these positions should be readily apparent. But…Is There A Third Way? I believe that there is. In my opinion there is an answer that avoids the problems of both horns of the dilemma. You can download it and read it at your leisure (it is only a couple of pages). If you do not, you will not be penalized in any way; however, those of you who do read it will certainly benefit in your soul…and you might even see tangible benefits in this class!