Round 2 v. Liberty CE 1AC Plan: The United States should establish an interstate compact legalizing nearly all online gambling in the United States. 1AC – Advantage - Trade Intra-state legalization’s inevitable after the Wire Act reinterpretation- states are willing to issue licenses without threat of federal prosecution Rose 13 [I. Nelson Rose, J.D. Harvard Law School, is a Full Professor with Tenure at Whittier Law School in Costa Mesa, California and a Visiting Professor at the University of Macau. Professor Rose is an internationally known scholar, author, and public speaker, and is recognized as one of the world's leading experts on gaming law, Spring, 2013 UNLV Gaming Law Journal 4 UNLV Gaming L.J. 1, “The DOJ Gives States a Gift”, lexis//wyo-tjc] The impact of the announcement was felt across the nation. The American Virgin Islands and Nevada had already passed legislation allowing their regulators to issue licenses for Internet casinos . However, no licenses were issued because both jurisdictions received letters from the DOJ threatening to arrest any of their operators who dared take bets online. The threat is now gone. Even before the DOJ's reversal, the Nevada State Legislature had passed a bill ordering the state's regulators to prepare for licensing Internet poker. In June 2012, [*7] the Nevada Gaming Commission issued the first two licenses in the nation for Internet gaming to two of the largest slot machine manufacturers: International Game Technology and Bally Technologies, Inc. A week later, on June 28, 2012, Gov. Jack Markell (D.-DE) signed a bill allowing the Delaware State Lottery to operate full-scale casinos online. n46 Part of the money that will be raised will go to the state's racinos, to help them market and expand. The bill was rushed through because the racinos in Delaware were hurting from the increased competition from expanded casino gambling in Atlantic City, Maryland, New York, and Pennsylvania. In fact, more money is now bet on the slot machines in Pennsylvania than in New Jersey. n47 In addition, the state of New York takes in more gaming tax revenue than Nevada, helped mightily by the Aqueduct racino, the first legal casino in New York City. However, it will take some time for other state legislatures to react. The opening of Internet gambling in Delaware and Nevada, and, to a lesser extent, the American Virgin Islands, will push states near the tipping point. New Jersey will likely be first. The Democratic-controlled legislature approved intrastate online gaming in 2011, but the bill was vetoed by Gov. Chris Christie (R.-NJ). n48 Christie was afraid the Internet gambling storefronts would open throughout the state, which the Atlantic City casinos were not about to let happen. He did point out a true legal problem: the state's constitution limits all casino gambling to Atlantic City. Christie is working with the legislature's leading advocate, state senator Ray Lesniak (D.-Union), to correct these problems. Iowa may well be next. The Iowa legislature mandated a study concluding that intra-state Internet poker can be operated safely and will raise money, although not as much as many predicted. n49 A bill passed in the democratically controlled State Senate, but was not even brought up for a vote in the Republican-controlled House. n50 This was the third year the legislature had considered the issue. California and many other states are so desperate for any source of revenue that they will jump on the bandwagon once the political compromises are reached. Gambling is seen as a painless tax, and even economic conservatives like it because it can raise revenue without raising taxes. And that sends the perception that the United States is illegally discriminating against foreign online operators, destroying WTO credibility and threatening trade friction Murawski 8 [Mattia V. Corsiglia, J.D. Candidate 2008, Santa Clara University School of Law, Santa Clara Law Review, THE ONLINE GAMBLING WAGER: DOMESTIC AND INTERNATIONAL IMPLICATIONS OF THE UNLAWFUL INTERNET GAMBLING ENFORCEMENT ACT OF 2006, 2008, p. lexis//wyo-tjc] The passage of the UIGEA leads the United States down a number of problematic paths. The United States has a significant economic interest in the WTO. n274 By ignoring the WTO ruling, the United States hurts its relationships with its foreign partners and conveys the message that it is not bound by the rules of foreign regulatory bodies. n275 In addition, the UIGEA puts the United States in direct conflict with more economically powerful countries like Australia and the United Kingdom. n276 Australia has already legalized Internet [*467] gambling and is a "pioneer" in online gambling. n277 The United Kingdom has expressed its interest in legalizing and regulating online gambling sites and recently passed legislation supporting that interest. n278 Both countries have an increased interest in the global propagation of online gambling. n279 Inevitably their economic interests will collide with U.S. antigambling laws. n280 If and when that occurs, the United States will be under a greater obligation to consider changing its laws or be subject to trade penalties from some of their closest economic partners. n281 The UIGEA may also violate WTO principles. The WTO's ruling stands for the proposition that the United States can restrict gambling, but must do so without discriminating against foreign operators. n282 Therefore, any new U.S. law cannot allow domestic operators to run gambling sites without also permitting foreign operators to take part in the market. n283 The UIGEA, however, may violate this principle because it has carved out an exception for states n284 that the WTO may find discriminatory. n285 If the UIGEA violates WTO antidiscrimination laws, the U.S. government will be required to either amend the law or enter protracted discussions with the international community over ways to compromise. n286 For example, The UIGEA expressly allows operators in states that have legalized online gambling to be involved in intrastate gambling transactions. n287 This has the effect of allowing online gambling within a state to the possible exclusion of foreign operators. n288 Whether or not intrastate gambling exceptions have the effect of discriminating against foreign operators is debatable, n289 but past WTO rulings [*468] indicate that the argument has gravitational force. n290 Therefore, the WTO could rule the intrastate exception is discriminatory because it allows intrastate betting to take place while excluding foreign operators. n291 As of yet, most states are not expressly licensing and regulating online gambling beyond horse racing but it could occur in the not so distant future. n292 For example, Nevada could begin to license and regulate online gambling, as it has shown a desire to do. n293 In addition, states could also begin selling their lottery tickets on the Internet. n294 If this occurs, the argument that the United States is discriminating against foreign operators from a market that local operators enjoy might have better results. n295 Much of this opposes the United States' argument that legislation banning foreign operators is needed in order to exclude significant social harms. n296 The argument that online gambling threatens a fundamental societal interest is unlikely to carry great weight because virtually all U.S. states permit or promote licensed or commercial gambling and have no specific prohibition against some form of online gambling. n297 Instead, the perception is that the United States is more concerned with excluding foreign operators from the U.S. market than with upholding moral opposition to gambling. n298 Thus, the international community will view perceive the United States' actions as contradictory and self-serving . Continued non-compliance destroys DSM credibility, tanking the WTO causing runaway trade disputes and war Castel-Fodor 13 [Kennan J. Castel-Fodor, J.D. Candidate (2014) at Case Western Reserve University School of Law, CASE WESTERN RESERVE LAW REVIEW, “Providing a Release Valve: The U.S.-China Experience with the WTO Dispute Settlement System,” vol. 64, no. 1, pp. 201-238, 2013, accessed 6.5.2014: academic search premiere//wyo-tjc] As with any mechanism for resolving disputes between diverse parties, the efficacy and viability of the DSB is subject to limitations. One limitation is the particular political conditions that can prove to be extremely volatile. Another limitation is that the system can only be effective insofar as both the People’s Republic and the United States continue to subjectively believe the DSB is legitimate, fair, and impartial. The involved parties must have confidence in the dispute settlement process for the benefits discussed in Parts III.A and III.B to accrue and for the DSB to have long-term success. If either country begins to feel as though it is the target of arbitrary or capricious DSB determinations, the country’s willingness to utilize the dispute settlement mechanism may drastically wane. Furthermore, persistent noncompliance with DSB determinations, from either Washington or Beijing, may undermine the DSB’s legitimacy and cause a reciprocal pattern of noncompliance . Persistent noncompliance would have a rippling effect throughout the WTO as an effective enforcement mechanism is necessary to protect and ensure the commitments and expectations of member states. The extreme of these limitations is that either China or the United States could lose complete faith in the DSB. This result would diminish the DSB’s long-term effectiveness as countries refuse to resort to WTO litigation. Such diminishment would be evidenced by: (1) plummeting compliance rates, (2) more unilateral trade retaliations, and (3) increased potential for a full-blown trade war. While the extreme scenario is highly improbable, both countries should be wary of the potential for a slippery slope of system abuse. Although the increased litigation between the United States and China in the DSB has effectively managed trade frictions between the parties, bestowing both direct and indirect benefits, the operation of the DSB as an international dispute settlement mechanism is subject to potential erosions in legitimacy. Credible WTO dispute mechanism is key to manage U.S.-China relationsand facilitate CCP political and economic reforms Castel-Fodor 13 [Kennan J. Castel-Fodor, J.D. Candidate (2014) at Case Western Reserve University School of Law, CASE WESTERN RESERVE LAW REVIEW, “Providing a Release Valve: The U.S.-China Experience with the WTO Dispute Settlement System,” vol. 64, no. 1, pp. 201-238, 2013, accessed 6.5.2014: academic search premiere//wyo-tjc] The Sino-American relationship remains a salient political issue within the United States, with the People’s Republic often vilified. A number of subjects tend to ignite the ire of the American public and Congress, including human rights, currency manipulation, and trade frictions. The U.S. administration’s engagement of China through DSB litigation conveys a strong political stance position in instances of perceived violations of China’s international obligations. This litigation strategy toward China helps to placate the American public’s anger as well as the calls for tougher legislation from Congress. The saber rattling from Congress can prove potentially catastrophic for U.S.-Chinese relations as protectionist trade legislation can spark damaging retaliatory policies from China. The U.S. administration can use WTO litigation to address issues preemptively before protectionist elements in Congress can act. For the American government, WTO litigation provides a unique ability to diffuse political tensions that could have deleterious ramifications for the long-term benefit of the SinoAmerican relationship. While the Chinese government is not subject to the same democratic undulations, domestic pressure within China is of great concern to the Chinese Communist Party’s (CCP) political stability. Economic concerns are always at the forefront of the CCP’s domestic and foreign policy, as demonstrated through the maintenance of the currency policy that has caused much contention. Sometimes, China’s initiation of WTO litigation is the direct result of domestic concerns toward particularly prominent trading partners. Like the United States, the Chinese government can utilize DSB determinations to implement or speed up reforms that may not be particularly popular domestically. This is particularly true in situations in China where reform, without DSB determinations, would be untenable. The prospect of WTO litigation and the permeation of DSB norms throughout China can provide the CCP domestic credibility for instituting reformist policies. Increasing WTO litigation and improving Chinese legal savvy can also provide the indirect benefit of bolstering the Chinese public’s faith in not only the WTO and DSB but also other international organizations. This provides the CCP with a stronger trade dispute mechanism that would have more support from the Chinese domestic populace. A dedication to resolving trade disputes through the DSB provides the governments in Beijing and Washington both clout and political protection. Given the complex political landscape, using the DSB allows both the United States and China to vent domestic frustrations through an international legal forum. The use of the DSB as a third-party intermediary allows both governments to deflect losses while still resolving tense political frictions. The DSB allows the United States and the People’s Republic to diffuse political tensions that can arise within a domestic market, especially with the public, media, and political figures. Relations collapse goes nuclear Goldstein, 13 – Avery, David M. Knott Professor of Global Politics and International Relations, Director of the Center for the Study of Contemporary China, and Associate Director of the Christopher H. Browne Center for International Politics at the University of Pennsylvania (“First Things First: The Pressing Danger of Crisis Instability in U.S.-China Relations,” International Security, vol. 37, no. 4, Spring 2013, Muse //Red) Two concerns have driven much of the debate about international security in the post-Cold War era. The first is the potentially deadly mix of nuclear proliferation, rogue states, and international terrorists, a worry that became dominant after the terrorist attacks against the United States on September 11, 2001.1 The second concern, one whose prominence has waxed and waned since the mid-1990s, is the potentially disruptive impact that China will have if it emerges as a peer competitor of the United States, challenging an international order established during the era of U.S. preponderance.2 Reflecting this second concern, some analysts have expressed reservations about the dominant post-September 11 security agenda, arguing that China could challenge U.S. global interests in ways that terrorists and rogue states cannot. In this article, I raise a more pressing issue, one to which not enough attention has been paid. For at least the next decade, while China remains relatively weak, the gravest danger in Sino-American relations is the possibility the two countries will find themselves in a crisis that could escalate to open military conflict. In contrast to the long-term prospect of a new great power rivalry between the United States and China, which ultimately rests on debatable claims about the intentions of the two countries and uncertain forecasts about big shifts in their national capabilities, the danger of instability in a crisis involving these two nuclear-armed states is a tangible, near-term concern.3 Even if the probability of such a war-threatening crisis and its escalation to the use of significant military force is low, the potentially catastrophic consequences of this scenario provide good reason for analysts to better understand its dynamics and for policymakers to fully consider its implications. Moreover, events since 2010—especially those relevant to disputes in the East and South China Seas—suggest that the danger of a military confrontation in the Western Pacific that could lead to a U.S.-China standoff may be on the rise. In what follows, I identify not just pressures to use force preemptively that pose the most serious risk should a Sino-American confrontation unfold, but also related, if slightly less dramatic, incentives to initiate the limited use of force to gain bargaining leverage—a second trigger for potentially devastating instability during a crisis.4 My discussion proceeds in three sections. The first section explains why, during the next decade or two, a serious U.S.-China crisis may be more likely than is currently recognized. The second section examines the features of plausible Sino-American crises that may make them so dangerous. The third section considers general features of crisis stability in asymmetric dyads such as the one in which a U.S. superpower would confront an increasingly capable but still thoroughly overmatched China—the asymmetry that will prevail for at least the next decade. This more stylized discussion clarifies the inadequacy of focusing one-sidedly on conventional forces, as has much of the current commentary about the modernization of China's military and the implications this has for potential conflicts with the United States in the Western Pacific,5 or of focusing one-sidedly on China's nuclear forces, as a smaller slice of the commentary has.6 An assessment considering the interaction of conventional and nuclear forces indicates why escalation resulting from crisis instability remains a devastating possibility. Before proceeding, however, I would like to clarify my use of the terms "crisis" and "instability." For the purposes of this article, I define a crisis as a confrontation between states involving a serious threat to vital national interests for both sides, in which there is the expectation of a short time for resolution, and in which there is understood to be a sharply increased risk of war.7 This definition distinguishes crises from many situations to which the label is sometimes applied, such as more protracted confrontations; sharp disagreements over important matters that are not vital interests and in which military force seems irrelevant; and political disputes involving vital interests, even those with military components, that present little immediate risk of war.8 I define instability as the temptation to resort to force in a crisis.9 Crisis stability is greatest when both sides strongly prefer to continue bargaining; instability is greatest when they are strongly tempted to resort to the use of military force. Stability, then, describes a spectrum—from one extreme in which neither side sees much advantage to using force, through a range of situations in which the balance of costs and benefits of using force varies for each side, to the other extreme in which the benefits of using force so greatly exceed the costs that striking first looks nearly irresistible to both sides. Although the incentives to initiate the use of force may not reach this extreme level in a U.S. China crisis, the capabilities that the two countries possess raise concerns that escalation pressures will exist and that they may be highest early in a crisis, compressing the time frame for diplomacy to avert military conflict. Chinese internal instability leads to a catastrophic meltdown and World War III as it takes East Asia down with it Plate 3 [Thomas Plate, Professor at UCLA, STRAITS TIMES, “Neo-Cons a Bigger Risk to Bush than China”, June 28, 2003, p. lexis] But, while China's prosperity may be good for Americans, is it necessarily the same for the totalitarians running China? After all, having created a runaway economic elephant, will the Communist Party leaders be able to stay in the saddle? Before long, the Chinese middle class alone may approach the size of the entire population of America. It will want more freedom, not less - bet on it. But imagine a China disintegrating on its own, without neo-conservative or Central Intelligence Agency prompting, much less outright military invasion - because the economy (against all predictions) suddenly collapses. That would knock Asia into chaos. A massive flood of refugees would head for Indonesia and other places with poor border controls, which don't want them and can't handle them; some in Japan might lick their lips at the prospect of World War II Revisited and look to annex a slice of China. That would send Singapore and Malaysia - once occupied by Japan - into nervous breakdowns. Meanwhile, India might make a grab for Tibet, and Pakistan for Kashmir. Then you can say hello to World War III, Asia-style. That's why wise policy encourages Chinese stability, security and economic growth - the very direction the White House now seems to prefer. Next, solvency: American leadership on gambling is key to sustain the overall credibility of the GATS agreement- failure will cause states to opt out of the dispute settlement process and pursue unilateral trade remedies Codd 7 [Kathryn B. Codd, J.D. Candidate 2008, William & Mary School of Law, William & Mary Law Review, December, 2007 49 Wm. & Mary L. Rev. 941, “BETTING ON THE WRONG HORSE: THE DETRIMENTAL EFFECT OF NONCOMPLIANCE IN THE INTERNET GAMBLING DISPUTE ON THE GENERAL AGREEMENT ON TRADE IN SERVICES (GATS),” lexis//wyo-tjc] Over the past decade, Internet gambling has become a global force. In 2003, the projected industry revenues summed five billion dollars worldwide. n1 With the click of a button, bettors could link up with counterparts in other parts of the globe for a poker tournament or a game of blackjack. As other countries embraced the operators of this new recreational activity, recognizing it as an opportunity to spur economic growth and bring in valuable tax revenue, the United States began to crack down on the industry. n2 As part of this crackdown, the U.S. federal government and the states started to pass and enforce regulations prohibiting Internet gambling, resulting in the arrest and conviction of executives of foreign gambling operations who dared to set foot on U.S. soil. n3 This onslaught against the foreign gaming industry did not go unnoticed, however, and eventually, one small country, Antigua and Barbuda, attempted to fight back against what it perceived as unfair discrimination against one of its primary sources of income. Antigua brought a complaint against the United States to the World Trade Organization (WTO), alleging violations of U.S. obligations under the General Agreement on Trade in Services (GATS). n4 The WTO found the United States to be in violation of a specific provision of GATS and ordered the United States to bring federal law into [*944] conformity with its GATS obligations. n5 Though many scholars consider the violation to be minor and the fix relatively uncomplicated, n6 thus far the United States has failed to comply with the WTO's recommendations. n7 The Dispute Settlement Understanding (DSU) governs disputes, such as this one, that arise under GATS, as well as disputes under other WTO agreements. n8 The DSU vests adjudicatory power in the WTO for all disputes that arise under WTO agreements. n9 Although WTO member nations have failed to comply on occasion with WTO decisions involving violations under other agreements-such as the General Agreement on Trade in Tariffs (GATT) or TradeRelated Aspects of Intellectual Property Rights (TRIPS)-this lack of compliance has not proved fatal to these agreements. GATS, however , is a fairly young multinational trade agreement, and some scholars argue that GATS has struggled to shape its identity amidst problems with overly flexible provisions and lack of attention from WTO ministers. n11 Although most countries are likely to acknowledge that the agreement has been a relative success thus far, n12 it has yet [*945] to weather any serious tests to its legitimacy. Because it was instrumental in the formation of GATS, n13 other countries will likely look to the United States as an example when deciding whether to comply with WTO decisions under GATS. The outcome of the n10 gambling dispute may prove to be a bellwether for the success or failure of the agreement as a mechanism for regulating trade in services . This Note argues that if the United States fails to respond appropriately to the recommendations made by the WTO, the legitimacy of GATS as a mechanism for regulating trade in services disputes will be undermined. Without legitimacy, GATS becomes nothing more than symbolic lip service to the importance of liberalization in the service trade. Member nations will perceive the agreement as a weak guarantor of rights and, as a result, will be less likely to resort to the GATS dispute mechanism should a service trade dispute arise. This in turn may compel WTO members to take unilateral action to enforce their rights, leading to elevated hostilities and possible trade wars. To avoid these devastating results and to preserve GATS, the United States should adopt the WTO recommendations proffered in the gamblingdispute. Legalization restores compliance and wards off major trade conflicts. Carbajales 10 [Noe Hamra Carbajales, J.D. candidate 2011, Tulane University Law School, Winter, 2010 Tulane Journal of International and Comparative Law 19 Tul. J. Int'l & Comp. L. 397, “No More Bets: The United States Rolls the Dice One More Time Regarding International Relations and Foreign Internet Gambling Services,” lexis//wyo-tjc] An analysis of U.S. laws regarding Internet gambling demonstrates the past and future conflicts in this area of the law. The ambiguity of the laws and their interpretation by federal agencies caused the United States to be defeated in the WTO against Antigua. The WTO Appellate Body decision has opened the floodgates for future litigants, including major players such as the EU. Until now, the United States has utterly disregarded its GATS commitments regarding the crossborder supply of gambling and betting services, whether the United States admits this or [*419] not. An attitude of defiance and disregard for international law only fosters an environment of distrust, encouraging other member states to follow suit by refusing to comply with their own commitments. No one denies that the United States is a major, if not the biggest, player in the world economy and an essential pillar of the WTO. But with leadership also come responsibilities. Accordingly, the United States will have to reconcile the current situation by confronting the challenges ahead. A few options are available to the United States when addressing the mess created by its inept Internet gambling laws. First, the United States should acknowledge the problem that it has created by carving out exceptions for domestic providers of Internet gambling and betting services in the IHA and the UIGEA. The United States could address it by either leveling the playing field for all foreign Internet service providers or by banning these providers altogether without taking any discriminatory measures. n143 Second, the United States could modify or withdraw its commitments pursuant to article XXI of the GATS. The viability of this option would depend on how many members exercise their right to claim benefits for any loss they may suffer as a consequence of U.S. actions. It is no secret that the EU is considering the option to commence proceedings against the United States in the WTO should the United States decide to withdraw its commitments. This means that the United States could be exposed to potentially substantial damages should the EU and/or any other countries decide to sue for any loss. As a last resort, the United States has the option of ignoring the issue and maintaining the position of the DOJ regarding its compliance with the WTO. However, even this option is starting to crumble. A possible suit by the EU would pin the United States to the ropes. To be successful, the EC must simply avoid the same mistakes committed by Antigua. Considering the weight of the EU in the world economy, the United States might want to think twice before addressing the issue of Internet gambling. In today's modern society, it is almost unthinkable that a country could forbid the existence of a global Internet gambling market. Based on technology's role in the economy, it might be best to begin by regulating a future Internet gambling market rather than banning it outright. Past experiences with complete bans suggest that these measures only drive the targeted activity underground. n144 A policy of licensing and regulation, however, has proven to be a successful method [*420] of dealing with the issue of Internet gambling. n145 There is no doubt that the Internet has revolutionized the world we live in. With this new revolution also come new challenges. The manner in which the United States deals with these challenges will dictate the place it will occupy in the future. But in a world moving towards globalization, a position advocating protectionism and isolationism has no place . Now is key for WTO- a strong signal from the United States is necessary to re-inject momentum into multilateral trade liberalization Dieter 9 [Heribert Dieter, senior fellow at the German Institute for International and Security Affairs, Berlin, and teaches at the University of Potsdam, GLOBAL GOVERNANCE, “The Multilateral Trading System and Preferential Trade Agreements: Can the Negative Effects Be Minimized?,” vol. 15, 2009, pp. 393-408, accessed 6.5.2014: academic search premiere //wyo-tjc] It is widely recognized that preferential agreements are a suboptimal way to organize world trade. The discrimination that is endemic in these arrangements is economically inefficient. Moreover, the deepening of international production networks, through the sourcing of inputs from a broad range of countries, raises the costs of preferential agreements. Now that the WTO membership has been unable to reach an agreement on modalities that would have significantly progressed the Doha Round in July 2008,WTO members face a choice. They can either continue to observe the spread of preferential agreements without changing the rules, or they can address the problem by trying to minimize their negative effects. At a quite general level, one way of reducing the attractiveness of preferential agreements would be to further reduce most-favored-nation (MFN) tariffs. If these tariffs are below 5 percent, the costs associated with establishing origin in a preferential agreement are equal to or even greater than the tariff, so the interest in preferential agreements would probably fade away quickly. However, the uneven structure of tariff lines has to be considered. Although many tariff lines are already quite low today, there continue to be high tariffs on specific products in both developing and developed economies. Given the paralysis inaction in multilateral negotiations and the limited willingness of policymakers to unilaterally liberalize much further at this point, the question is whether a political initiative by important countries could send a signal against the further spreading of preferential agreements . The Warwick Commission has suggested that the major industrialized countries as well as large developing countries should refrain from establishing PTAs with each other. This recommendation was made with the worst-case scenario in mind in which the EU, United States, and major Asian economies negotiated PTAs among themselves. Were such a situation to eventuate, the WTO would face the prospect of irrelevance . Although not likely today, we have seen some developments in that direction, including South Korea’s bilateral negotiations with the United States and the EU, and negotiations for a transatlantic marketplace between the United States and the EU. 1AC – Advantage – Illicit Gambling First, There is a legal vacuum after the Wire Act opinion and Dicristina decision regarding online gambling and making a surge in unregulated gambling inevitable Rosomer 2013 [James Romoser, J.D. candidate at Georgetown University Law Center, Summer, 2013 American Criminal Law Review 50 Am. Crim. L. Rev., UNSTACKING THE DECK: THE LEGALIZATION OF ONLINE POKER, lexis//wyo-tjc] The legal landscape for online poker is now a clean slate. The Wire Act opinion, the Dicristina decision, and the limitations of the UIGEA interlock to make clear that no federal law directly criminalizes either playing online poker or running an online poker business. This reality creates both a risk and an opportunity. The risk is that unscrupulous foreign companies, unchecked by American oversight, may fill the void--just as the market was dominated by three apparently fraudulent companies before the 2011 indictments. n149 The opportunity is that Congress, the states, or both, can confidently set up a safe, licensed, revenuegenerating online poker regime. A well-regulated regime would have numerous benefits. First, government regulators can monitor for cheating and ensure that online poker games are fair. Second, a regulatory regime can prevent minors from playing by requiring strict age-verification software. Third, regulations can guard against compulsive betting by mandating in-game features that allow players to restrict their own play or limit excessive losses. Fourth, mandatory geo-location software can ensure that legal poker sites accept players only from jurisdictions in which online poker is legal. Fifth, government monitoring would prevent poker sites from becoming fronts for money laundering or other criminal activity. Sixth, U.S.-based poker companies would boost the economy--one study anticipates 10,000 new poker-based jobs. n150 Seventh, for the first time the government would be able to collect billions of dollars in tax revenue from online poker companies and from individual players' winnings. n151 And, online gambling is a game-changer for money laundering and terrorism Sparrow 9 [Malcolm K. Sparrow (Professor of the Practice of Public Management—Harvard's John F. Kennedy School of Government); “Can Internet Gambling Be Effectively Regulated? Managing the Risks”; December 2, 2009; http://financialservices.house.gov/media/file/hearings/111/sparrow.pdf] E. Money Laundering by Players A major concern of law-enforcement authorities is money laundering facilitated by online gambling . However, many financial analysts believe that the risks of money laundering in online gambling is low because electronic transactions are closely monitored and recorded. A combination of anti-money-laundering regulations, currently in place for bricks-and-mortar casinos as well as other financial institutions, and the use of technology would provide the online gambling environment with better opportunities for detecting money laundering by players than those available in land- and river-based casinos. 1. The Issue of Money Laundering by Players Money laundering is a process through which proceeds derived from illegal activity are legitimized. Money laundering is typically accomplished in three stages: (1) the placement stage, (2) the layering stage, and (3) the integration stage. The placement stage is defined as the first entry of illegal money into financial institutions or the retail economy. The layering stage consists of activities meant to hide the trail of money , generally involving the transfer of money among multiple entities. The final stage, the integration stage, is when the illegal funds are reintroduced into the economy to appear as though they were legitimate. It is difficult for law enforcement to detect this reintroduction of illicit funds into the economy without an audit trail established during the first two stages of the laundering process. The following (hypothetical) example demonstrates how online gambling websites can be used to launder money: A customer could establish an Internet gambling account under a false name and use illicit funds to conduct a minimal amount of betting. After a few losses, the customer could request repayment from the Internet gambling site and claim them as winnings, thereby creating a legitimate source for the remaining funds. The U.S. Department of Justice is concerned that online gambling offers criminals an easy vehicle for money laundering because of its anonymous nature, use of encryption, volume, speed, international reach, and offshore locations.142 In his testimony before Congress in 2003, Deputy Assistant Attorney General John G. Malcolm noted that e-casinos are an excellent vehicle for money laundering because in addition to using the gambling services offered to hide or transfer money, online gambling websites offer a wide variety of financial services to their customers, including credit accounts, fund transmittal services, check cashing services, and currency exchange services.143 There is little documentation by which to gauge the extent of actual money laundering in online gambling. In 2002, the U.S. General Accounting Office (GAO) examined the vulnerability of online gambling to money laundering and concluded that the "views on the vulnerability of Internet gambling to money laundering are mixed."144 Its report provides only hypothetical examples of how online gambling sites could be used to launder money and does not describe any actual cases. A 2005 report prepared for the Interactive Gaming Council in Canada calls evidence of the existence of money laundering in online gambling "scant" and claims that the Internet Crime Complaint Center had never logged a complaint of money laundering through gambling sites.145 It goes on to claim that "Internet gaming does not, in and of itself, contribute to money laundering. Rather, it is the financial transactions that are used to move money on the Internet that may be susceptible to money laundering."146 One can understand money laundering patterns that might occur in online gambling by extrapolating from the patterns of money laundering seen in bricks-and-mortar casinos. Various betting patterns associated with money laundering in bricks-and-mortar casinos have been identified, including the use of hedged bets by colluding players, light betting or minimal play (i.e., using bets that are small relative to the size of deposits and withdrawals), splitting transactions up into units smaller than reporting thresholds, splitting transactions across reporting "days," and pressuring staff to not problem related to money laundering is that of terrorist financing , in which funds that are intended for terrorist groups are moved through the financial system in an apparently legitimate way. Effective anti-money-laundering provisions must specifically address the risks of terrorist financing, although many techniques to combat money laundering comply with their reporting obligations.147 A are also effective against terrorist financing.148 The only known case of money laundering through gambling sites was related to terrorist financing: in 2007, a suspected terrorist named Al-Daour used stolen credit cards to deposit funds at 43 different gambling sites and then withdrew the winnings to various online bank accounts.149 2. Existing Controls in Other Jurisdictions Congress has enacted legislation to detect money laundering. Under the Bank Secrecy Act (BSA) of 1970, all U.S. financial institutions, including banks, credit unions, securities firms, and casinos, are required to report large currency transactions and suspicious activities.150 The Financial Crimes Enforcement Network (FinCEN) administers these regulations. The casino gambling industry has been covered by the BSA since 1985, and FinCEN has specific regulations that pertain to casino gaming. The BSA requires the reporting of any currency transactions exceeding $10,000 in a single gaming day on a Currency Transaction Report (CTR). 151 Because money launderers can structure transactions such that they never result in a CTR being filed, all land- and river-based casinos are also required to file Suspicious Activity Reports (SARs). Casinos have to file SARs if they know, suspect, or have reason to suspect that a transaction involving $5,000 or more meets certain criteria, including involvement of illicit funds, intention to avoid or prevent proper reporting, exhibiting of abnormal behavior, or use of the casino to facilitate criminal activity.152 The leading online gambling jurisdictions have created regulatory structures that resemble traditional regulation for land- and river-based casinos in the United States. These jurisdictions require some form of anti-money-laundering monitoring, ranging from restricting customers to a single account to identifying and reporting suspicious transactions or players' abnormal betting patterns.153 In addition to regulation that combats money laundering in its financial services sector, the Isle of Man has put in place the Anti-Money Laundering Code to prevent money laundering through gambling websites. 154 Operators are required to comply with strict anti-money-laundering procedures, which include identification of prospective customers, evidence of identity, changes to patterns of transactions, record keeping, records of transactions, retention of records, reporting suspicious transactions, and training. In addition, site operators are legally required to report any suspicious transactions to the Financial Crime Unit (FCU). Specialized software can flag these transactions. Similarly, to combat money laundering, Alderney requires operators of online gambling websites to implement business risk assessments, customer due diligence procedures, monitoring of transactions and other activity, suspicious activity reporting procedures, employee screening and training procedures, and record-keeping procedures. 3. Relevant Technologies for Risk Mitigation An anti-money-laundering regulatory regime for online gambling may be modeled on the current regulatory structure for traditional bricks-and-mortar casinos. A regulatory framework for online gambling may leverage the technological environment for online gambling and require (1) preservation of an audit trail of transactions for analysis by federal authorities; (2) implementation of customer identification standards; (3) controls to prevent anonymous , structured transactions; (4) establishment of an anti-money-laundering compliance program; (5) training for all appropriate personnel; and (6) compliance with all relevant BSA requirements. The IGC notes that "online gambling, with a combination of regulatory oversight and use of technology—while facing the same threats as real-world gambling facilities—is in a better position to address these risks." For example, all electronic fund transfers can be electronically recorded, thus providing a detailed and automatic transaction trail not currently available in land- and river-based casinos. The IGC further notes that a basic requirement to combat money laundering is to "know your customer." Stringent player registrations and ongoing verification processes combined with appropriate regulatory oversight and banking regulations help fulfill this requirement. Italy's regulatory regime, for example, requires a potential customer to submit a signed contract along with a copy of his or her identification. Tasmania requires strong identity verificationprocedures to be in place on player accounts. Moreover, technology can equip site operators with tools to scrutinize player behavior , and then capture and report the transaction. Another essential anti-moneylaundering measure noted by the IGC is to require that gamblers be paid any winnings in the same way in which the inconsistent money was originally deposited. This system allows an audit to track transfers of funds much more easily and removes the ability of launderers to use an account as a pass-through for funds. Also, care must be taken when allowing transfers of funds between players, which could potentially be a conduit for money laundering . Alderney's money laundering guidance suggests that transferred funds be allowed only for gambling and not for withdrawal or that site operators undertake further due diligence on players involved in transfers. In addition to a system modeled on requirements for bricks-andmortar gambling, a regulator can require the same procedures that are required of online merchants, banks, and payment providers. In Europe, online gambling operators have been bound by these requirements since 2003 under the Third European Money Laundering Directive. U.S. licensed operators would also be bound by relevant anti-money-laundering requirements. Most nations are also subject to the recommendations of the Financial Action Task Force, an international body formed to combat money laundering and terrorist financing. Each nation may also have its own money laundering regulations, such as the United Kingdom's Money Laundering Regulations, which cover both financial and nonfinancial businesses. Although financial businesses are still subject to the most of these regulations use a risk-based approach , in which the level of scrutiny of transactions is commensurate with the risk of money laundering in those transactions . The most important aspects of financial companies' stringent regulation, all risk mitigation involve three broad activities: (1) "know your customer" procedures, (2) monitoring for suspicious activity, and (3) procedures for reporting suspicious activity. Identity verification can involve both paper and electronic identification, and the level of additional identification required rises with the risk in the particular industry and transaction. Suspicious activity monitoring involves standard procedures that are designed to reveal signs of monitoring while retaining privacy protection. All suspicious activity must be reported to law enforcement, which takes over the investigation immediately . Suspicious activity reporting, as part of the regulations, is the responsibility of all company staff members, who must be trained in the signs of money laundering and be able to report their suspicions expeditiously. In the United Kingdom, not reporting suspected money laundering is a criminal offense with a maximum sentence of two years in prison.171 4. Conclusion Players or groups of players acting in concert may attempt to use legitimate gambling operations for money laundering. To curb such activities, regulators could subject online gambling operators to anti-money-laundering regulations that are currently in place for bricks-and-mortar casinos and for online merchants, banks, and payment providers. The online environment provides better opportunities for detecting money laundering by players or player groups than do bricks-and-mortar casinos. In an effective anti-money-laundering regime, site operators would be required to retain comprehensive data on all deposits, withdrawals, and betting transactions and to make these available to regulators for examination and analysis. Given complete data, most patterns related to money laundering (such as light betting or matched bets placed by collaborators) would be easier to detect than they are in a physical environment (where complete transaction histories are available only in the form of video recordings).172 Software for detecting anomalies and suspicious behavior may be operated easily and routinely on digital databases by operators, regulators, or both. The site operators' obligations with respect to their own detection of money laundering would form a part of their ordinary compliance obligations under such a licensing regime. Because of the absence of cash in online gambling transactions, the auditable record that is created, and the regulator-imposed reporting requirements for most transactions, it is likely that site operators can prevent money laundering as by players and terrorist financing at least effectively as can bricks-and-mortar casinos.173 In contrast, the current prohibitions related to online gambling force s players to use unconventional forms of payment that leave harder-to-follow audit trails, and may therefore increase the risk of money laundering . Cyberlaundering uniquely key to global terrorism Hunt 11 [John Hunt (Lawyer—Florida Fifth District Court Of Appeal); “The new frontier of money laundering: how terrorist organizations use cyberlaundering to fund their activities, and how governments are trying to stop them”; Information & Communications Technology Law Volume 20, Issue 2, 2011; http://www.tandfonline.com/doi/full/10.1080/13600834.2011.578933#.VBCPjfldWSo] For a terrorist organization seeking to launder money, the Internet and electronic currency provide excellent tools for committing the crime efficiently. 26 As one author has stated, ‘[ c]yberlaundering is the safest way for to launder dirty money if the government cannot reconstruct the transactions of an audit trail’. 27 The process of cyberlaundering mirrors the traditional methods, with the launderer ordinarily using the three stages discussed above (i.e. placement, layering, and integration). 28 In addition to efficiency , cyberlaundering presents other benefits as well. One such benefit is that electronic currency allows terrorists to avoid the problems associated with physically transferring large sums of money, and allows criminal organizations to make lightning fast transfers anywhere in the world. 29 Perhaps the greatest advantage cyberlaundering offers over traditional methods of money laundering is anonymity, since individuals may transfer electronic cash from one location to another without ever having to complete a transaction in person. 30 This section will examine the concept of criminals cyberlaundering, and discuss what role it will play in the future of money laundering. Before going into detail about cyberlaundering, it is helpful to provide a brief explanation of electronic currency, since the use of such currency is likely to increase in the coming years, and thus play an even more important role in future laundering schemes. 31 Electronic currency, as its name suggests, holds the same status as traditional hard currency in the world economy, except that it does not exist in a tangible form. 32 Some authors therefore call such currency the ‘greenback of the Internet’. 33 One method that allows individuals to take advantage of the benefits of electronic currency is through the use of stored value cards (SVCs), also known as ‘smart cards’, which are tangible cards (similar in appearance to phone cards) on which the user can store vast amounts of cash. 34 Individuals can load electronic currency onto their SVC at specialized vending machines, at the bank, at compatible ATMs, through the Internet, and even over the phone. 35 Electronic cash comes in three forms: one that operates within traditional financial institutions, such as banks; one that operates in a ‘tokenized’ system; and one that operates as a hybrid system. 36 Credit and debit cards continue to dominate online commerce in the US, but companies are beginning to develop a system for SVCs that could gain worldwide popularity. 37 Although this discussion provides only a cursory explanation of electronic currency and SVCs, it lays the foundation for a better understanding of cyberlaundering. In terms of the traditional three stages of money laundering, electronic currency and the Internet provide ideal conditions for cyberlaunderers. 38 At the placement stage, cyberlaunderers benefit from the anonymity of the Internet and electronic currency, as there is no need for face-to-face transactions. 39 Launderers may thus make it past the placement stage undetected, since they are able to avoid the strict reporting requirements imposed on traditional financial institutions. 40 At the layering stage, the cyberlaunderer has the biggest use for the Internet and its advantages over the traditional forms of layering in a laundering scheme. 41 If the criminal can find an institution (e.g. a bank or online gambling site ) that will permit him to set up an account without face-to-face contact or without providing documentary evidence of identity , then it would be extraordinarily difficult for the authorities to trace the account back to the cyberlaunderer. 42 The Internet provides an almost instantaneous method of transfer of electronic cash, and the transaction can occur anywhere in the world where there is an Internet connection. 43 If the launderer can transfer electronic currency between banks via the Internet, then authorities may find it nearly impossible to trace the funds back to the source. 44 Finally, the Internet also makes the integration of the cyberlaundered funds easier. For instance, an individual could establish an online gambling site and transfer funds from an online bank account (established using a false identity) to the online gambling site; any proceeds of the gambling website would thus appear legitimate to authorities tracing the audit trail of the profits. 45 This is the modern version of what the New York Mafia did in the 1920s when they opened Laundromats as fronts for their criminal activities. 46 The cyberlaunderer may also use legitimate bankers and lawyers to aid in the integration stage. 47 It is also possible that the cyberlaunderer could take advantage of debit cards issued by offshore banks, real estate transactions, and ‘fake loans from offshore companies’ to integrate the laundered funds back into the legitimate economy. 48 Once the laundered money passes through these stages, the criminal organization is free to use the funds to further its aims . The next section will focus on how terrorist organizations utilize the Internet and cyberlaundering techniques to fund their activities. This paper will then turn to the topic of how the US government, the UN, the G7, the OAS, and the COE have attempted to stem the laundering of money by terrorist organizations, and finally will discuss the future of measures aimed at stopping cyberlaundering. Given the threats posed by cyberlaundering to the financial industry and national security, it is vital that governmental organizations take steps to stem the use of new technologies by terrorist organizations. 49 4 Online terrorism: how terrorist organizations use the Internet and cyberlaundering to fund their activities Jump to section 1. Introduction 2 A brief history of money laundering and... 3. The new frontier of money laundering 4 Online terrorism: how terrorist organizations... 5 Attempts by national governments and... 6 The future of cyberlaundering: what... 7 Conclusion Despite efforts by the governments of the US and its allies, terrorist organizations such as al Qaeda, Hezbollah, and Hamas still maintain the ability to coordinate attacks and fund their activities. 50 One medium that terrorist organizations are increasingly taking advantage of is the Internet. 51 There is evidence that terrorist organizations rely on the Internet and related technologies laundering money to legitimize their funds. 52 Indeed, some observers believe that cyberlaundering and cyberterrorism may pose just as great a threat to the stability of the global economy and to conduct their activities, which likely includes global security as traditional weapons of mass destruction . 53 Although terrorist organizations may use the Internet for recruitment, training, and planning purposes as well, this section will focus on how such organizations raise funds and legitimize those funds through cyberlaundering. 54 The Internet, with its anonymity, ease of use, and accessibility, permits terrorist organizations to avoid some of the dangers of conducting financial transactions through traditional channels. 55 To take one example of how successful terrorist organizations are in raising funds, consider the case of al Qaeda. It is difficult to state with any certainty how much money al Qaeda raises every year; one estimate put the figure at $30 million in 2004, but that number is likely lower today. 56 Although certainly not all of the funds raised by al Qaeda pass through the Internet, it is likely that the organization significantly relies on the Internet and cyberlaundering to help distribute its wealth. 57 Al Qaeda and other terrorist organizations excel at adapting to changing circumstances, and of maintaining their core financial stability, despite the best efforts of authorities. 58 In order to make these adaptations and to take advantage of the Internet and other technologies, however, terrorist organizations must have reliable sources of funding. 59 Terrorist organizations rely on several sources to fund their activities. To provide some perspective, the CIA estimates that al Qaeda spent $30 million in the years leading up to the September 11 attacks for planning, recruitment, and other supportive purposes. 60 The CIA believes that much of the $30 million came from contributions from religious and charitable organizations. 61 One organization that provides a significant amount of support to al Qaeda is the Muslim Brotherhood, which ‘was founded in Egypt in 1928 as a religious organization’. 62 In addition to al Qaeda, the Muslim Brotherhood also has ties to the Tamil Tigers, the Afghan mujahidin, and is considered by the US Treasury to be the ‘parent’ of Hamas. 63 More recently, terrorist organizations have turned to conventional crimes such as extortion, the selling of narcotics, and arms trafficking to fund their activities. 64 According to Mr David S. Cohen, the Assistant US Treasury Secretary for Terrorist Financing, the move into traditional criminal activities makes terrorist organizations ‘more vulnerable to detection by international law enforcement agencies … ’ 65 Although terrorist organizations have different motives than those who traditionally take part in the drug trade, there are many similarities between the activities of the two groups when one looks at their reliance on drug trafficking for funding. 66 Terrorist groups also receive funds from investments in legitimate business. 67 Once the terrorist organizations receive the funds, they must ensure that they can spend the proceeds in economies around the world. Given that some of the funds obtained be terrorists come from legitimate sources, authorities may have difficulty in tracing the funds or proving that the groups are committing the crime of money laundering. 68 Cyberlaundering and the use of the Internet allow the organizations to launder and transfer money easily and quickly, and provide an alternative to traditional informal financial networks, such as hawalas. 69 The widespread availability of the Internet creates a convenient method for terrorist organizations to transfer funds, both illegal and legal, to cells across the globe. 70 Using the cyberlaundering techniques described above, terrorist groups can ensure that their coffers do not run dry . Although traditional informal financial institutions are fast, inexpensive, reliable, convenient, and discreet, they do not share the Internet’s relative lack of regulation and law enforcement observation. 71 In addition, the Internet allows terrorist financers to transfer funds from the location of their choosing, without ever having to make a face-to-face transaction . 72 It is difficult to say with certainty to what extent terrorist organizations use the Internet and cyberlaundering techniques to further their causes, but it is certain that the groups are taking full advantage of modern technology. 73 Although outside the scope of this paper, terrorist organizations may also use the Internet for cyberterrorist attacks on governmental and financial infrastructures. 74 As one author stated, ’[t]errorists are able to do more damage with a keyboard than a bomb ’. 75 That risks devastating cyber-attacks --- they’re highly motivated and it overwhelms defenses Bucci 9 Dr. Steven P. Bucci is IBM's Issue Lead for Cyber Security Programs and a part of the Global Leadership Initiative, the in-house think tank for IBM's public-sector practice. He most recently served as Deputy Assistant Secretary of Defense, Homeland Defense and Defense Support to Civil Authorities. Dr. Bucci delivered these remarks at a meeting of The Heritage Foundation's Cyber Security Working Group, The Confluence of Cyber Crime and Terrorism, http://www.heritage.org/research/lecture/the-confluenceof-cyber-crime-and-terrorism If a cash-rich terrorist group would use its wealth to hire cyber criminal botnets for their own use, we would have a major problem. A terrorist group so enabled could begin to overwhelm the cyber defenses of a specific corporation, government organization, or infrastructure sector and do much damage. They could destroy or corrupt vital data in the financial sector, cripple destroy communications over a wide area to spread panic and uncertainty. Similar to the nation-state attack scenarios discussed earlier, terrorists could use botnet-driven DDoS attacks to blind security forces at a border crossing point as a means of facilitating an infiltration operation, or a cyber attack in one area of a country to act as a diversion so a "conventional" kinetic terrorist attack can occur elsewhere. They could even conduct SCADA attacks on specific sites and use the system to create kinetic-like effects without the kinetic component. A good example would be to open the valves at a chemical plant near a population center, creating a Bhopal-like event. The permutations are as endless as one's imagination . The cyber capabilities that the criminals could provide would in short order make any terrorist organization infinitely more dangerous and effective. Some have opined that cyber attacks are not suitable as terror tactics because they lack the drama and spectacular effect of, say, a suicide bomber. This does not take into account the ability of the terrorists to adapt. As our intelligence and law enforcement agencies continue to effectively combat the terrorists, they will continue to evolve. The terrorists' old methods will be augmented and improved. They will need to develop more imagination and versatility if they are to conduct successful operations. This evolutionary capability has not been in short supply among the terrorist leadership. They will not define "spectacular" so narrowly. Imagine the operational elegance of simply hitting the return key and seeing thousands of enemies die a continent away, or watching a bank go under due to the destruction of all its data by an unknown force . This will be enormously attractive to terrorist groups. Additionally, the combination of cyber methods and kinetic strikes could be spectacular regardless of one's definition. Criminals, for their part, are motivated by greed and power. Few of the leaders of the enormous cyber organized crime world would hesitate at selling their capabilities to a terrorist loaded with cash. That fact, combined with the ever-growing terrorist awareness of cyber vulnerabilities, makes this set of scenarios not just likely, but nearly inevitable . Guarantees nuclear exchange Lawson 9 [Sean Lawson is an assistant professor in the Department of Communication at the University of Utah, MAY 13, 2009, “Cross-Domain Response to Cyber Attacks and the Threat of Conflict Escalation”, http://www.seanlawson.net/?p=477, Date accessed 9/20/14, wyo-jf] At a time when it seems impossible to avoid the seemingly growing hysteria over the threat of cyber war,[1] network security expert Marcus Ranum delivered a refreshing talk recently, “The Problem with Cyber War,” that took a critical look at a number of the assumptions underlying contemporary cybersecurity discourse in the United States. He addressed one issue in partiuclar that I would like to riff on here, the issue of conflict escalation–i.e. the possibility that offensive use of cyber attacks could escalate to the use of physical force. As I will show, his concerns are entirely legitimate as current U.S. military cyber doctrine assumes the possibility of what I call “crossdomain responses” to cyberattacks. Backing Your Adversary (Mentally) into a Corner Based on the premise that completely blinding a potential adversary is a good indicator to that adversary that an attack is iminent, Ranum has argued that “The best thing that you could possibly do if you want to start World War III is launch a cyber attack. [...] When people talk about cyber war like it’s a practical thing, what they’re really doing is messing with the OK button for starting World War III. We need to get them to sit the f-k down and shut the f-k up.” [2] He is making a point similar to one that I have made in the past: Taking away an adversary’s ability to make rational decisions could backfire. [3] For example, Gregory Witol cautions that “attacking the decision maker’s ability to perform rational calculations may cause more problems than it hopes to resolve… Removing the capacity for rational action may result in completely unforeseen consequences, including longer and bloodier battles than may otherwise have been.” [4] Cross-Domain Response So, from a theoretical standpoint, I think his concerns are well founded. But the current state of U.S. policy may be cause for even greater concern. It’s not just worrisome that a hypothetical blinding attack via cyberspace could send a signal of imminent attack and therefore trigger an irrational response from the adversary. What is also cause for concern is that current U.S. policy indicates that “kinetic attacks” (i.e. physical use of force) are seen as potentially legitimate responses to cyber attacks. Most worrisome is that current U.S. policy implies that a nuclear response is possible, something that policy makers have not denied in recent press reports. The reason, in part, is that the U.S. defense community has increasingly come to see cyberspace as a “domain of warfare” equivalent to air, land, sea, and space. The definition of cyberspace as its own domain of warfare helps in its own right to blur the online/offline, physical-space/cyberspace boundary. But thinking logically about the potential consequences of this framing leads to some disconcerting conclusions. If cyberspace is a domain of warfare, then it becomes possible to define “cyber attacks” (whatever those may be said to entail) as acts of war. But what happens if the U.S. is attacked in any of the other domains? It retaliates. But it usually does not respond only within the domain in which it was attacked. Rather, responses are typically “cross-domain responses”–i.e. a massive bombing on U.S. soil or vital U.S. interests abroad (e.g. think 9/11 or Pearl Harbor) might lead to air strikes against the attacker. Even more likely given a U.S. military “way of warfare” that emphasizes multidimensional, “joint” operations is a massive conventional (i.e. non-nuclear) response against the attacker in all domains (air, land, sea, space), simultaneously. The possibility of “kinetic action” in response to cyber attack, or as part of offensive U.S. cyber operations, is part of the current (2006) National Military Strategy for Cyberspace Operations [5]: (U) Kinetic Actions. DOD will conduct kinetic missions to preserve freedom of action and strategic advantage in cyberspace. Kinetic actions can be either offensive or defensive and used in conjunction with other mission areas to achieve optimal military effects. Of course, the possibility that a cyber attack on the U.S. could lead to a U.S. nuclear reply constitutes possibly the ultimate in “crossdomain response.” And while this may seem far fetched, it has not been ruled out by U.S. defense policy makers and is, in fact, implied in current U.S. defense policy documents. From the National Military Strategy of the United States (2004): “The term WMD/E relates to a broad range of adversary capabilities that pose potentially devastating impacts. WMD/E includes chemical, biological, radiological, nuclear, and enhanced high explosive weapons as well as other, more asymmetrical ‘weapons’. They may rely more on disruptive impact than destructive kinetic effects. For example, cyber attacks on US commercial information systems or attacks against transportation networks may have a greater economic or psychological effect than a relatively small release of a lethal agent.” [6] The authors of a 2009 National Academies of Science report on cyberwarfare respond to this by saying, “Coupled with the declaratory policy on nuclear weapons the United States will regard certain kinds of cyberattacks against the United States as being in the same category as nuclear, biological, and chemical weapons, and thus that a nuclear response to certain kinds of cyberattacks (namely, cyberattacks with devastating impacts) may be possible. It also sets a described earlier, this statement implies that relevant scale–a cyberattack that has an impact larger than that associated with a relatively small release of a lethal agent is regarded with the same or greater seriousness.” [7] Regulations solve- safeguards D'Addario 12 [Shylene B. D'Addario, J.D. Candidate, 2012, Rutgers School of Law – Newark, Rutgers Computer and Technology Law Journal, THE LEGALIZATION OF INTERNET GAMBLING: WHY THE CLOCK IS TICKING ON PROHIBITION, 2012, p. lexis//wyo-tjc] There are currently millions of Americans who engage in Internet gambling with illegal offshore operators "with no oversight, no regulation, or no consumer protections." n119 Protecting consumers against abuses can be effectively controlled and regulated. n120 Legalization and regulation appears to be the only [*108] way to ensure that players are not cheated and that vulnerable citizens are protected. n121 With websites being run from all over the world, Americans who take it upon themselves to gamble on international sites are exposed to great abuses, such as game rigging, the house unfairly winning and non-payment of winnings. One way to effectively regulate and protect against fraud is through the payment systems. n122 Congress aimed to do just that through the UIGEA, although it hasn't exactly worked as planned. The credit card system in the United States is well established and effectively policed to thwart fraudulent and criminal behavior. n123 Because money laundering and corruption are major concerns for the legislature, Congress has also made it a goal to work with foreign nations to help identify occurrences of criminal operations involving Internet gambling. n124 Ironically, one way to help foster criminal behavior is by not regulating an industry that many Americans are involved with. n125 Under recently proposed legislation, licensed operators would be required to comply with mandated safeguards to help combat fraud and money laundering. n126 Some of these safeguards include: tracing the money used on licensed Internet gambling websites to a bank account; cross-checking transactions with existing databases used in antimoney laundering, anti-fraud, and anti-terrorism [*109] efforts; and holding payments in escrow to allow consumers time to contest unauthorized transactions. n127 By imposing these safeguards for gambling website operators, Americans will be better protected from fraud. The concerns for protections against fraud apply to both federal and state regulation. In New Jersey, the Attorney General makes it very clear that Internet gambling is illegal and if a person is defrauded in any way there will likely be no remedy. n128 With the veto of the recent New Jersey bill, New Jersey citizens are left to their own devices when it comes to Internet gambling, as is the case with the citizens of every other state. There is significant public interest in protecting Americans from being defrauded and the only way to do that is through effective regulation. Until new legislation is enacted, Americans will continue to be subjected to fraud from unregulated website operators as well as have no legal course of action to remedy any potential problems. Legalization solves money-laundering- moves revenue into safer domestic sites Abovitz 8 [Ian Abovitz, Associate and member of Stark & Stark’s Accident & Personal Injury Group in the Yardley, Pennsylvania office and J.D. Temple University, Fall, 2008 Temple International & Comparative Law Journal 22 Temp. Int'l & Comp, WHY THE UNITED STATES SHOULD RETHINK ITS LEGAL APPROACH TO INTERNET GAMBLING: A COMPARATIVE ANALYSIS OF REGULATORY MODELS THAT HAVE BEEN SUCCESSFULLY IMPLEMENTED IN FOREIGN JURISDICTIONS, lexis//wyo-tjc] The final social concern raised by those in opposition to internet gambling is the potential for the use of money laundering to facilitate terrorist activity, as well as a variety of other crimes. n174 "Money laundering is a process through which criminals legitimize proceeds derived from illegal activity." n175 Offshore internet gambling operations make it easy for criminals to launder their money simply by depositing illegally obtained funds onto a gambling website, then using the funds to gamble and cashing out the remaining funds. n176 The internet provides the protections of encryption and anonymity, n177 allowing criminals to use this method to disguise the origin of their money so that it does not appear to have been obtained through illegal activity. n178 The internet is conducive to money-laundering activities in part because of the inherent anonymity of the internet, and a lack of uniform oversight and regulation. n179 As a commentator has explained, "the challenge to oversight authorities remains to find ways to prevent illicit activities while allowing legitimate gambling operators and players to conduct their business in If regulations were put into place and reputable U.S. operators were permitted to enter the market, they would have a much greater incentive to protect themselves from money-laundering activity than offshore operators. n181 an open and potentially lucrative setting safeguarded by a sound and comprehensive regulatory regime." n180 1AC – Solvency In 2011, the DOJ re-interpreted the Wire Act, dropping any federal barrier to iGambling as long as it is not sports-related. Rose 13 [I. Nelson Rose, J.D. Harvard Law School, is a Full Professor with Tenure at Whittier Law School in Costa Mesa, California and a Visiting Professor at the University of Macau. Professor Rose is an internationally known scholar, author, and public speaker, and is recognized as one of the world's leading experts on gaming law, Spring, 2013 UNLV Gaming Law Journal 4 UNLV Gaming L.J. 1, “The DOJ Gives States a Gift”, lexis//wyo-tjc] The United States Department of Justice ("DOJ") gave states and the online gaming community a big present, made public two days before Christmas 2011. President Barack Obama's administration declared that the Wire Act, n2 the major federal anti-gambling statute used against Internet gambling, applies only to bets on sports events and races. n3 Additionally, the DOJ no longer cares if a communication wire carrying legal intra-state wagers happens to cross temporarily into another state. n4 This opens the door for states to legalize almost every form of Internet gambling for their residents and to authorize online wagers from residents of other states and nations. The Wire Act was enacted in 1961 as part of Attorney General Robert F. Kennedy's war on organized crime. n5 It was designed to aid the states in their public policies, which, at the time, were almost entirely prohibitory against all commercial gaming. For example, in 1961 only Nevada allowed any form of off-track betting. n6 The Wire Act was consciously designed to aid the states in fighting illegal bookmaking. n7 The statute's purpose was to cut "the Wire" - the name organized criminals gave to the telegraph wire used by illegal bookies to get race results before their bettors. n8 The target of the Wire Act was so specific that prosecutors were fortunate Congress had included the words "sports events," thus allowing the Act to be used against illegal sports books as well. n9 The 2011 Christmas announcement allows states, which are desperate to find ways to raise revenue without raising taxes, to legalize almost any form of intra-state gambling. However, this does not include sports betting because of [*2] another federal statute, the Professional and Amateur Sports Protection Act ("PASPA"). n10 Under PASPA, sports betting cannot be introduced into a state that does not already have it. n11 However, New Jersey is challenging PASPA in court, n12 and the California State Senate has already passed a bill to legalize sports betting. n13 Historically, it has always been up to individual states to decide their own public policies toward gambling. For example, Utah and Nevada share a common border; yet they have completely different gaming laws. n14 Until recently, the role of the federal government was limited to helping states enforce their public policies. Congress only acts when it has to, as with interstate horseracing and tribal gaming, or when the states have asked for federal assistance, as with the Wire Act and other statutes designed to fight organized crime. The federal anti-gambling statutes are enforcement statutes; they do not change the substantive laws of gambling. With the exception of PASPA, no act of Congress makes illegal any form of gambling that is legal under state law. PASPA is limited to sports betting n15 and is of questionable constitutionality. n16 All other federal statutes, with only two exceptions, are facially limited to gambling that is illegal under federal or state law. n17 For example, the Travel Act n18 makes it a federal crime to travel or use any facility in interstate or foreign commerce to carry on "unlawful activity," which is defined as a business enterprise involving gambling "in violation of the laws of the State in which they are committed or of the United States." Only the federal anti-lottery statutes n19 and the Wire Act can apply to gambling that is legal under state law. The federal anti-lottery laws have not proven to be much of a barrier to state lotteries. Long before Powerball, states found ways of getting around the federal prohibitions on interstate lotteries, by having only information, not money, cross state lines. n20 The Wire Act, on the other hand, scared the states out of legalizing other forms of gambling online, or linking games across state [*3] lines. After the DOJ's 2011 Christmas announcement, the threat of the Wire Act to state-legal gaming is limited to sports betting. The only barrier blocking states from legalizing Internet poker and other non-lottery games was the DOJ's expansive view of the Wire Act. Thus, now that the DOJ has limited the scope of the Wire Act to cover only cross-border sports bets, there is no federal law preventing a state from authorizing intra-state online games. It is even likely that states may now enter into compacts with other states and nations to pool players interstate and internationally. The DOJ opinion requires that gambling be legal under state laws. n22 It will take some time for legislatures to react to this gift from the Obama Administration, but many of the state lotteries can set up online games quickly. The 2011 Christmas announcement stemmed from the Illinois and New York state lotteries' request for clarification from the DOJ. Those state lotteries - along with the state lotteries of Minnesota, New Hampshire, North Dakota and Virginia - had been selling intrastate subscriptions online for years. n23 The Illinois and New York lotteries wanted to know if they could use out-of-state payment processors for those Internet purchases. Technically, the only question being decided was, "whether proposals by Illinois and New York to use the Internet and out-of-state transaction processors to sell lottery tickets to in-state adults violated the Wire Act." The DOJ's answer was far beyond what they were hoping for. Now, states can not only sell lottery ticket subscriptions over the Internet and use out-of-state payment processors, but they can also operate any game legal under state law, so long as it is not considered sports betting. n24 Interstate compacts are a superior option- they create sustainable gambling pools, removes barriers to foreign operators, raise revenue, and don’t require Congressional consent. Rosomer 2013 [James Romoser, J.D. candidate at Georgetown University Law Center, Summer, 2013 American Criminal Law Review 50 Am. Crim. L. Rev., UNSTACKING THE DECK: THE LEGALIZATION OF ONLINE POKER, lexis//wyo-tjc] A better option is for states to enter interstate compacts to form large, online poker networks covering multiple states. Article I of the U.S. Constitution contemplates the power of states to form compacts, n171 and states routinely use this power. In fact, perhaps the most familiar examples of present-day interstate compacts are the massive "Powerball" and "MegaMillions" lotteries in which many states participate. Just as they do with these lottery games, states could create a multi-state online poker network that would be available to the inhabitants of all member states. The network could be subject to a unified regulatory and taxsharing plan, according to the terms of the "compact," and it could expand the size of the player base far beyond what any individual state can attract on its own. n172 Two experts have even suggested that a multi-state network could be open to poker players from foreign countries. To be sure, the language of the Compact Clause expressly requires that Congress consent to interstate agreements. But the Supreme Court has held that congressional consent is necessary only in narrow circumstances— namely, when "the prohibition is directed to the formation of any combination tending to the increase of political power in the States, which may encroach upon or interfere [*542] with the just supremacy of the United States." n174 The Court has never invalidated an interstate compact for lack of congressional consent, and a multi-state poker agreement almost certainly would not trigger the consent requirement. Existing multi-state lottery agreements, for instance, did not need the approval of Congress. n175 Very recently, Nevada regulators latched onto the compact idea. In January 2013, the state's Gaming Control Board submitted a bill to the state legislature that would allow the governor to enter agreements with other states in which online poker is legal. n176 A key reason cited for the proposal is to supplement Nevada's nascent poker network with an influx of new players. n177 If states cooperate with Nevada, an expansive, wellregulated online poker network could be imminent. By joining a compact to regulate online poker, they can avoid having to wait for the calcified Congress to act, and they can solve the balkanization problem of states acting on their own. In addition, they can reap billions of dollars in new revenue and ensure that their poker-playing citizens do business with legitimate American companies. V. CONCLUSION Americans have been playing online poker for fifteen years. All evidence suggests they will continue to do so, regardless of whether their government tells them it is illegal. On Facebook--that trusty gauge of generational appetites--the third-party application with the most total "Likes" is "Texas HoldEm Poker." n178 Its popularity is especially telling given that the application does not even offer "real" poker: people can play the game, but only using digital chips with no monetary value. The app's parent company, Zynga, is poised to start offering online poker for real money--as soon as lawmakers allow it. n179 The legal trend certainly points in that direction. The Department of Justice has reinterpreted the Wire Act as irrelevant to online poker. A federal district court has ruled that the Illegal Gambling Business Act also does not apply. The Unlawful Internet Gambling Enforcement Act is ineffectual without an applicable statute on [*543] which to rely. And the states, despite historically treating poker as an illicit "game of chance," are beginning to move toward explicit legalization. The best path forward is an interstate compact to create a robust multi-state online poker network. A compact, as envisioned in this Note, would take advantage of the emerging judicial certainty that online poker is legal under federal law. And it would, for the first time, allow American online poker to be fully regulated, guaranteed safe, and properly taxed. As Mark Twain wrote, "There are few things that are so unpardonably neglected in our country as poker." n180 Under a well-regulated interstate compact, the digital iteration of America's pastime would no longer be neglected by America's policymakers. States are only forging ahead with INTRA-state gambling, which is now inevitable. Nevill 13 [Andrew M. Nevill, J.D., University of Illinois College of Law, Spring, 2013 University of Illinois Journal of Law, Technology & Policy 2013 U. Ill. J.L. Tech. & Pol'y 203, FOLDED INDUSTRY? BLACK FRIDAY'S EFFECT ON THE FUTURE OF ONLINE POKER IN THE UNITED STATES, lexis//wyo-tjc] As a federal statute, the UIGEA only governs interstate activity. n176 This has allowed state legislatures to make their own laws regarding Internet gambling within their own borders. Many states that are struggling to balance their budgets are looking for new sources of revenue and are turning to the possibility of legalizing intrastate online gambling . n177 Despite the federal crackdown on online poker, President Obama has recognized this right of the states to determine whether it wants to permit online poker between its own residents. n178 In April 2011, the District of Columbia passed the Lottery Modernization Amendment Act of 2010. n179 This law defined a lottery as being "both games of skill and games of chance" and allowed these games to be offered over the Internet, so long as they are only played within the District. n180 Since poker falls within the definition of lottery provided by the act regardless of whether it is determined to be a game of skill or a game of chance, the District of Columbia had planned on creating a website that would allow people to play online poker for money. n181 Revenue generated from the poker website would be used to supplement other areas of the District's budget. n182 Although the law allowing Internet gambling was repealed about a year after it was passed, this should not be seen as vindication that online gambling is not desired in Washington, D.C. n183 The reason for appeal was that some District of [*221] Columbia council members opposed the way in which it was added to a lottery contract without proper notice to legislators. n184 Not surprisingly, Nevada has also considered allowing intrastate Internet gambling, including online poker. n185 In December 2011, the Nevada Gaming Commission approved regulations for intrastate online gambling. n186 The regulations allow casinos in the state to operate websites that would be limited to play by people within the state. n187 Some of the larger casinos in Las Vegas, like Bally's and Caesars, have already filed applications for licenses to start online gambling websites. n188 These websites could represent a lucrative source of revenue as it is estimated that they could provide $ 180 million in extra money for the state. n189 Although some states want to pass laws to legalize online gambling within their borders, others have taken action to keep their citizens from gambling on the Internet. In 2006, the Washington legislature passed a law that made online gambling a criminal offense. n190 The law was challenged in the Washington Supreme Court in the case Rousso v. State. n191 Rousso challenged the Washington law on the grounds that it violated the Commerce Clause, but the court held that the law was constitutional. n192 Washington is currently the only state that has a law that prohibits online poker by its residents, but Utah is also considering passing a similar law. n193 2AC counter-interp: “the United States” is the 50 states plus D.C. Parsons 13 [Chancelor, Delaware State court, SMARTMATIC INTERNATIONVAL V DOMINION VOTING SYSTEMS, May 13, p. http://courts.delaware.gov/opinions/download.aspx?ID=188720] The narrow issue before me is whether the term ―in the United States,‖ as used in Section 3.4(b) of the License Agreement, includes or excludes Puerto Rico. Section 3.4(b) states in relevant part: ―Smartmatic shall not develop, market or sell any Licensed Products in the United States at any time during the term of this Agreement.‖ 29 I consider first the plain and ordinary meaning of the term ―United States Delaware courts ―will look to dictionaries for assistance in determining the plain meaning of terms which are not defined in a contract.‖ 31 The Random House Webster‘s Unabridged Dictionary defines the United States as ―a republic in the N[orth] Western Hemisphere comprising 48 coterminous states, the District of Columbia, and Alaska in North America, and Hawaii in the N[orth] Pacific.‖ 32 Black‘s Law Dictionary defines the United States a s ―a federal republic formed after the War of Independence and made up of 48 coterminous states, plus the state of Alaska and the Di strict of Columbia in North America, plus the state of Hawaii in the Pacific.‖ 33 Webster‘s New World Dictionary provides that the United States of America is a ―country made up of the N [orth] American area extending from the Atlantic Ocean to the Pacific Ocean between Canada and Mexico, together with Alaska & Hawaii.‖ 34 Similarly, the New Oxford American Dictionary defines the Unites States as ―a country that occupies most of the southern half of North America as well as Alaska and the Hawaiian Islands.‖ 35 The American Heritage 13 College Dictionary of the English Language, however, provides this definition of the United States : ―A country of central and northwest North America with coastlines on the Atlantic and Pacific Oceans. It includes the non - contiguous states of Alaska and Hawaii and various island territories in the Caribbean Sea and Pacific Ocean.‖ 36 Thus, the cited dictionary definitions, although not unanimous, overwhelmingly suggest that the ordinary meaning of the United States includes only the for ty - eight contiguous states, the District of Columbia, Alaska, and Hawaii. I consider next how the courts have defined the United States. And we-meet: state legalization can specify whether the bill allows compacting OR if it’s intra-state. Poker News Report 13 [staff, Pennsylvania Online Gambling Proposal Progressing, March 11, http://www.pokernewsreport.com/pennsylvania-online-gambling-proposal-progressing-11950] Pennsylvania Online Gambling Proposal Progressing. A bill to legalize online gambling in Pennsylvania is likely to be proposed this week by Rep. Tina Davis. Davis may propose the measure perhaps as soon as Wednesday before the House Gaming Oversight Committee. The bill calls for online license fees of $10 million, with generated revenue to be taxed at a 20 percent clip. Licenses would be restricted to Pennsylvania casinos that are already licensed for slots and table games. Davis told philly.com that since she made it known last month that her proposal would be forthcoming, she got quite a bit of feedback from casinos and has made some changes that reflect the input received. She believes that Pennsylvania needs to keep pace with the neighboring states of Delaware and New Jersey, who are moving forward with their recently-enacted online gambling legislation. "If we do not protect our casinos and money in Pennsylvania," Davis said, "we will be hurt by all the competition." Davis’ bill includes a unique concept to protect problem gamblers. Players who consistently lose in short periods of time would trigger a software mechanism that would automatically lock their accounts. The proposal is not without its detractors. Rep. Paul Clymer is reportedly opposed to any gambling expansion plans and is considering drafting a measure that would make Internet gambling illegal. Thus far, only Utah has such a statute in place. The Pennsylvania House of Representatives is controlled by the Republican party, which leans against gambling. In order for Davis’ bill to win support, GOP lawmakers must be swayed to change their views. Pennsylvania recently surpassed New Jersey as the nation’s no. 2 ranked gaming market behind Nevada. The Silver State passed an online poker interstate compact bill last month that allows for increasing player pools by partnering with other states. Currently, Pennsylvania’s proposal is limited to intrastate Internet gaming and includes a full menu of casino games. counter-interp- nearly all is 60-80% of an activity SACRAMENTO BEE 98 [staff, “Fight over bilingual ed may play out in court”, http://wwwrcf.usc.edu/~cmmr/SacBee_Oct12.html] Proposition 227, which passed with 61 percent of the vote in June, sought to scrap bilingual education by dictating that limited-English speakers be put in a one-year immersion program taught "nearly all" in English. Parents were allowed to ask that their children be put back in bilingual education after 30 days if they were over 10, already spoke English or had "special needs." The law took effect Aug. 2, but some schools have kept bilingual education alive by interpreting the phrase "nearly all" to mean anywhere from 20 percent to 40 percent of instruction can be in a second language. Second, we meet- Sports betting is only 20% of global iGambling market share Church-Sanders 12 [Rachel Church- Sanders, staff, Special Report: Online Poker – Industry Trends, IGB Affiliate, http://www.igbaffiliate.com/resources/articles/special-report-online-poker-%E2%80%93-industrytrends] Gaming sites by genre, August 2012: Sportsbooks: 20.20% <graph image- switch to online or reading view> a- Contextual support- leaving sports betting illegal would still legalize nearly all Platzer 12 [Michaela D. Platzer, Specialist in Industrial Organization and Business, “Remote Gambling: Industry Trends and Federal Policy,” November 8, 2012, CRS RESEARCH SERVICES] Another change affecting remote gaming is DOJ’s recent determination on the Wire Act.35 In its clarification made public in December 2011, the department isolated the Wire Act to be applicable only to sport-related gambling activities. According to this clarification eliminated nearly all federal anti-gaming laws . Furthermore, it appears that its stance not only opens the door to intrastate Internet activity, but possible interstate activity as well. Even though legal questions remain, there are a number of indications that companies and states are poised to expand remote gaming as part of a larger trend toward online entertainment and communications. According legal gambling experts, to the Pew Internet & American Life Project, 85% of all adults now use the Internet and the same percentage have a cell phone, two-thirds of U.S. households have access to a high-speed broadband connection, 45% have a smartphone, and 18% have a tablet computer. All of these platforms could be used for gambling.36 Soon, interactive television is expected to become widely available, offering even more potential platforms for betting. Nelson I. Rose, a professor at the Whittier Law School, argues that UIGEA and the regulations to implement it may have paved the way for expansion of remote gaming: By issuing these [regulations] federal agencies have now made it clear that some forms of gambling on the Internet are legal in the United States. This creates opportunities for existing or expanding legal state gaming, and for bolstering faltering state budgets. But, mostly it opens some doors for creative Internet gaming operators … The result will be a major expansion of Internet gambling. The major obstacles facing legal online gaming are the customers’ fear that they might be breaking the law and their difficulty in getting money to sites they trust. Individual patrons will now be able to use their credit cards to make bets. And they will know that they are not breaking the law and the gaming operation is honest when the gambling site is operated by a state lottery or licensed by a state racing or gaming board, or has a reasoned legal opinion.37 b- it’s bad for a legal topic- There is no agreement on legal definitions of “nearly all” Struempf 05 [Dona, undergraduate in English education at Cal Poly Pomona http://cla.calpoly.edu/~jbattenb/Papers/struempf.html, November 2] The law does not define what "nearly all" means exactly. Therefore, school districts are in disagreement as to what percentage constitutes compliance. The Los Angeles Unified school district, the largest and most diverse school district in the state, offers two programs for LEP students: Model A, where most of the instruction is provided in English, and Model B, where English instruction constitutes 65-70 percent of instruction (Terry 7). According to Elena Soto-Chapa, the statewide education director for the Mexican American Legal Defense and Education Fund, there is a great deal of confusion; some districts are using a 60-40 English-foreign language formula while others are using 70-30 or 80-20 (Terry 7). Reps shape reality is wrong Wendt 99 Alexander Wendt, Professor of International Security at Ohio State University, 1999, “Social theory of international politics,” gbooks The effects of holding a relational theory of meaning on theorizing about world politics are apparent in David Campbell's provocative study of US foreign policy, which shows how the threats posed by the Soviets, immigration, drugs, and so on, were constructed out of US national security discourse.29 The book clearly shows that material things in the world did not force US decision-makers to have particular representations of them - the picture theory of reference does not hold. In so doing it highlights the discursive aspects of truth and reference, the sense in which objects are relationally "constructed."30 On the other hand, while emphasizing several times that he is not denying the reality of, for example, Soviet actions, he specifically eschews (p. 4) any attempt to assess the extent to which they caused US representations. Thus he cannot address the extent to which US representations of the Soviet threat were accurate or true (questions of correspondence). He can only focus on the nature and consequences of the representations.31 Of course, there is nothing in the social science rule book which requires an interest in causal questions, and the nature and consequences of representations are important questions. In the terms discussed below he is engaging in a constitutive rather than causal inquiry. However, I suspect Campbell thinks that any attempt to assess the correspondence of discourse to reality is inherently pointless. According to the relational theory of reference we simply have no access to what the Soviet threat "really" was, and as such its truth is established entirely within discourse, not by the latter's correspondence to an extra-discursive reality 32 The main problem with the relational theory of reference is that it cannot account for the resistance of the world to certain representations, and thus for representational failures or m/'sinterpretations. Worldly resistance is most obvious in nature: whether our discourse says so or not, pigs can't fly. But examples abound in society too. In 1519 Montezuma faced the same kind of epistemological problem facing social scientists today: how to refer to people who, in his case, called themselves Spaniards. Many representations were conceivable, and no doubt the one he chose - that they were gods - drew on the discursive materials available to him. So why was he killed and his empire destroyed by an army hundreds of times smaller than his own? The realist answer is that Montezuma was simply wrong: the Spaniards were not gods, and had come instead to conquer his empire. Had Montezuma adopted this alternative representation of what the Spanish were, he might have prevented this outcome because that representation would have corresponded more to reality. The reality of the conquistadores did not force him to have a true representation, as the picture theory of reference would claim, but it did have certain effects - whether his discourse allowed them or not. The external world to which we ostensibly lack access, in other words. often frustrates or penalizes representations. Postmodernism gives us no insight into why this is so, and indeed, rejects the question altogether.33 The description theory of reference favored by empiricists focuses on sense-data in the mind while the relational theory of the postmoderns emphasizes relations among words, but they are similar in at least one crucial respect: neither grounds meaning and truth in an external world that regulates their content.34 Both privilege epistemology over ontology. What is needed is a theory of reference that takes account of the contribution of mind and language yet is anchored to external reality. The realist answer is the causal theory of reference. According to the causal theory the meaning of terms is determined by a two-stage process.35 First there is a "baptism/' in which some new referent in the environment (say, a previously unknown animal) is given a name; then this connection of thing-to-term is handed down a chain of speakers to contemporary speakers. Both stages are causal, the first because the referent impressed itself upon someone's senses in such a way that they were induced to give it a name, the second because the handing down of meanings is a causal process of imitation and social learning. Both stages allow discourse to affect meaning, and as such do not preclude a role for "difference" as posited by the relational theory. Theory is underdetermined by reality, and as such the causal theory is not a picture theory of reference. However, conceding these points does not mean that meaning is entirely socially or mentally constructed. In the realist view beliefs are determined by discourse and nature.36 This solves the key problems of the description and relational theories: our ability to refer to the same object even if our descriptions are different or change, and the resistance of the world to certain representations. Mind and language help determine meaning, but meaning is also regulated by a mind-independent, extra-linguistic world. Terrorism studies are epistemologically and methodologically valid---our authors are self-reflexive Michael J. Boyle '8, School of International Relations, University of St. Andrews, and John Horgan, International Center for the Study of Terrorism, Department of Psychology, Pennsylvania State University, April 2008, “A Case Against Critical Terrorism Studies,” Critical Studies On Terrorism, Vol. 1, No. 1, p. 51-64 Jackson (2007c) calls for the development of an explicitly CTS on the basis of what he argues preceded it, dubbed ‘Orthodox Terrorism Studies’. The latter, he suggests, is characterized by: (1) its poor methods and theories, (2) its state centricity, (3) its problemsolving orientation, and (4) its institutional and intellectual links to state security projects. Jackson argues that the major defining characteristic of CTS, on the other hand, should be ‘a skeptical attitude towards accepted terrorism “knowledge”’. An implicit presumption from this is that terrorism scholars have laboured for all of these years without being aware that their area of study has an implicit bias, as well as definitional and methodological problems. In fact, terrorism scholars are not only well aware of these problems, but also have provided their own searching critiques of the field at various points during the last few decades (e.g. Silke 1996, Crenshaw 1998, Gordon 1999, Horgan 2005, esp. ch. 2, ‘Understanding Terrorism’). Some of those scholars most associated with the critique of empiricism implied in ‘Orthodox Terrorism Studies’ have also engaged in deeply critical examinations of the nature of sources, methods, and data in the study of terrorism. For example, Jackson (2007a) regularly cites the handbook produced by Schmid and Jongman (1988) to support his claims that theoretical progress has been limited. But this fact was well recognized by the authors; indeed, in the introduction of the second edition they point out that they have not revised their chapter on theories of terrorism from the first edition, because the failure to address persistent conceptual and data problems has undermined progress in the field. The point of their handbook was to sharpen and make more comprehensive the result of research on terrorism, not to glide over its methodological and definitional failings (Schmid and Jongman 1988, p. xiv). Similarly, Silke’s (2004) volume on the state of the field of terrorism research performed a similar function, highlighting the shortcomings of the field, in particular the lack of rigorous primary data collection. A non-reflective community of scholars does not produce such scathing indictments of its own work. Preventing extinction needs to come first Paul Wapner, associate professor and director of the Global Environmental Policy Program at American University, Winter 2003, Dissent, online: http://www.dissentmagazine.org/menutest/archives/2003/wi03/wapner.htm All attempts to listen to nature are social constructions-except one. Even the most radical postmodernist must acknowledge the distinction between physical existence and non-existence. As I have said, postmodernists accept that there is a physical substratum to the phenomenal world even if they argue about the different meanings we ascribe to it. This acknowledgment of physical existence is crucial. We can't ascribe meaning to that which doesn't appear. What doesn't exist can manifest no character. Put differently, yes, the postmodernist should rightly worry about interpreting nature's expressions. And all of us should be wary of those who claim to speak on nature's behalf (including environmentalists who do that). But we need not doubt the simple idea that a prerequisite of expression is existence. This in turn suggests that preserving the nonhuman world-in all its diverse embodiments-must be seen by eco-critics as a fundamental good. Eco-critics must be supporters, in some fashion, of environmental preservation. Postmodernists reject the idea of a universal good. They rightly acknowledge the difficulty of identifying a common value given the multiple contexts of our value-producing activity. In fact, if there is one thing they vehemently scorn, it is the idea that there can be a value that stands above the individual contexts of human experience. Such a value would present itself as a metanarrative and, as Jean-François Lyotard has explained, postmodernism is characterized fundamentally by its "incredulity toward meta-narratives." Nonetheless, I can't see how postmodern critics can do otherwise than accept the value of preserving the nonhuman world. The nonhuman is the extreme "other"; it stands in contradistinction to humans as a species. In understanding the constructed quality of human experience and the dangers of reification, postmodernism inherently advances an ethic of respecting the "other." At the very least, respect must involve ensuring that the "other" actually continues to exist. In our day and age, this requires us to take responsibility for protecting the actuality of the nonhuman. Instead, however, we are running roughshod over the earth's diversity of plants, animals, and ecosystems. Postmodern critics should find this particularly disturbing. If they don't, they deny their own intellectual insights and compromise their fundamental moral commitment. Quality of life is skyrocketing worldwide by all measures Ridley, visiting professor at Cold Spring Harbor Laboratory, former science editor of The Economist, and award-winning science writer, 2010 (Matt, The Rational Optimist, pg. 13-15) If my fictional family is not to your taste, perhaps you prefer statistics. Since 1800, the population of the world has multiplied six times, yet average life expectancy has more than doubled and real income has risen more than nine times. Taking a shorter perspective, in 2005, compared with 1955, the average human being on Planet Earth earned nearly three times as much money (corrected for inflation), ate one-third more calories of food, buried one-third as many of her children and could expect to live one-third longer. She was less likely to die as a result of war, murder, childbirth, accidents, tornadoes, flooding, famine, whooping cough, tuberculosis, malaria, diphtheria, typhus, typhoid, measles, smallpox, scurvy or polio. She was less likely, at any given age, to get cancer, heart disease or stroke. She was more likely to be literate and to have finished school. She was more likely to own a telephone, a flush toilet, a refrigerator and a bicycle. All this during a half-century when the world population has more than doubled, so that far from being rationed by population pressure, the goods and services available to the people of the world have expanded. It is, by any standard, an astonishing human achievement. Averages conceal a lot. But even if you break down the world into bits, it is hard to find any region that was worse off in 2005 than it was in 1955. Over that half-century, real income per head ended a little lower in only six countries (Afghanistan, Haiti, Congo, Liberia, Sierra Leone and Somalia), life expectancy in three (Russia, Swaziland and Zimbabwe), and infant survival in none. In the rest they have rocketed upward. Africa’s rate of improvement has been distressingly slow and patchy compared with the rest of the world, and many southern African countries saw life expectancy plunge in the 1990s as the AIDS epidemic took hold (before recovering in recent years). There were also moments in the half-century when you could have caught countries in episodes of dreadful deterioration of living standards or life chances – China in the 1960s, Cambodia in the 1970s, Ethiopia in the 1980s, Rwanda in the 1990s, Congo in the 2000s, North Korea throughout. Argentina had a disappointingly stagnant twentieth century. But overall, after fifty years, the outcome for the world is remarkably, astonishingly, dramatically positive. The average South Korean lives twenty-six more years and earns fifteen times as much income each year as he did in 1955 (and earns fifteen times as much as his North Korean counter part). The average Mexican lives longer now than the average Briton did in 1955. The average Botswanan earns more than the average Finn did in 1955. Infant mortality is lower today in Nepal than it was in Italy in 1951. The proportion of Vietnamese living on less than $2 a day has dropped from 90 per cent to 30 per cent in twenty years. The rich have got richer, but the poor have done even better. The poor in the developing world grew their consumption twice as fast as the world as a whole between 1980 and 2000. The Chinese are ten times as rich, one-third as fecund and twenty-eight years longer-lived than they were fifty years ago. Even Nigerians are twice as rich, 25 per cent less fecund and nine years longer-lived than they were in 1955. Despite a doubling of the world population, even the raw number of people living in absolute poverty (defined as less than a 1985 dollar a day) has fallen since the 1950s. The percentage living in such absolute poverty has dropped by more than half – to less than 18 per cent. That number is, of course, still all too horribly high, but the trend is hardly a cause for despair: at the current rate of decline, it would hit zero around 2035 – though it probably won’t. The United Nations estimates that poverty was reduced more in the last fifty years than in the previous 500. No root cause – war causes their impacts Goldstein 01 [Professor of International Relations at American University, 2001 (Joshua S., War and Gender: How Gender Shapes the War System and Vice Versa, pp.411-412) ] First, peace activists face a dilemma in thinking about causes of war and working for peace. Many peace scholars and activists support the approach, “if you want peace, work for justice”. Then if one believes that sexism contributes to war, one can work for gender justice specifically (perhaps among others) in order to pursue peace. This approach brings strategic allies to the peace movement (women, labor, minorities), but rests on the assumption that injustices cause war. The evidence in this book suggests that causality runs at least as strongly the other way. War is not a product of capitalism, imperialism, gender, innate aggression, or any other single cause, although all of these influences wars’ outbreaks and outcomes. Rather, war has in part fueled and sustained these and other injustices. So, “if you want peace, work for peace.” Indeed, if you want justice (gener and others), work for peace. Causality does not run just upward through the levels of analysis from types of individuals, societies, and governments up to war. It runs downward too. Enloe suggests that changes in attitudes toward war and the military may be the most important way to “reverse women’s oppression/” The dilemma is that peace work focused on justice brings to the peace movement energy, allies and moral grounding, yet, in light of this book’s evidence, the emphasis on injustice as the main cause of war seems to be empirically inadequate. Can’t solve – Nommo only speaks to those who already agree on the terms and doesn’t allow for the inclusion of other perspectives Clarke 4 [Lynn, professor of communication at Vanderbilt, “Talk About Talk: Promises, Risks, and a Proposition Out of Nommo”, The Journal of Speculative Philosophy 18.4, pp. 317-325] Returning to the question of creative power's compass—Yancy's account of Nommo raises problems here as well. In the account, recall, the word's generative function funds "an oppositional way of speaking" (Yancy 2004, 289). Among other products, the speech acts of resistance manifest themselves in a black identity and reality based on a presumption of shared interests among African American selves.4 At the same time, however, Nommo's creative force is conceptually detached from the word's power to constitute intersubjective relations between selves and others within the African American community. Thus, Yancy's concept of Nommo only admits a generative power to create identification among blacks who already agree to the presence and terms of shared interest . The power of this Nommo fails to reach those African Americans who disagree with black majoritarian terms. This relatively minimal compass of power suggests that Nommo's potential to define black community and reality may need to be reconceptualized beyond the presumptions of shared experience and common values to consider Nommo's potential to forge relations between African Americans who are divided on the terms of their present and future. Yancy’s conceptualization of Nommo precludes the possibility intersubjective dialogue and debate – constrains the power of Nommo to effectively resist oppressive structures Clarke 4 [Lynn, professor of communication at Vanderbilt, “Talk About Talk: Promises, Risks, and a Proposition Out of Nommo”, The Journal of Speculative Philosophy 18.4, pp. 317-325] The question of Nommo's compass of power is also significant for relations between African American selves and European American others. Though it may not appear to be of immediate relevance to the task of theorizing a language spoken among African Americans, the question may still be worth raising for at least two reasons: Yancy's linguistic theory of AAL is offered in the name of black Americans, and a cursory look at political discourse within the African American community reveals a centuries-old controversy over whether (or in what contexts) blacks should integrate with or separate from whites. Given the unresolved status of this controversy, African Americans may benefit from renewed discussion and debate on the terms of integration and separation and the attitude that distinguish and relate them. If so, AAL may have a role to play in the important talk ahead. Either way, the presence of these two concepts in black public discourse suggests that relations between black and white Americans is not a settled issue for the community in whose name AAL has been defined and thought. The question of Nommo's power to constitute relations between blacks and whites may therefore be relevant to thinking and defining AAL. If black and white racial division is a cause for concern in the U.S., the concept of Nommo as instrumental power butts upon a problem of relation much like the one we encountered with dissent among African Americans. Specifically, Yancy's and others' accounts of Nommo do not address the word's power to forge relations between African Americans and the white benefactors of racial [End Page 321] and racist thinking in America. Cast in relation to the production of "hidden transcripts" (Scott 1990), the power of Nommo in the aforementioned accounts is constrained to a resistance that risks foreclosing the capacity of humans to collectively define their selves and world(s). Recalling Fanon, the risk speaks to the question of whether, upon self-consciousness, an oppressed group may "choose action (or passivity) with respect to the real source of the conflict—that is, toward the social structures" (Fanon 1967, 100). The choice to act would require a concept of Nommo that works to mend division and invite intersubjective dialogue and debate about racial and racist thinking and their pernicious affects on black and white Americans, and others. Together, the question of Nommo's creative compass of power, along with the problem of holding creative power accountable to intersubjective reason, point to the risk of conceptualizing language in such a way that the word's instrumental force is disconnected from the argumentative form of communication. To leave this connection unnamed and unthought in an account of AAL is to proceed according to at least two questionable presuppositions about contemporary speech situations in which Nommo is uttered: the speaker of AAL is of good moral character; and the speaker and audience are united on their preferred form of life and the terms of their identification. While these presuppositions may have been appropriate in the past times and spaces to which African "tradition(s)" refer, today both premises are untenable in the U.S. and elsewhere in the African diaspora. Speakers regularly express a will to power and, increasingly, communities are an admixture of identities, cultural traditions, and forms of life. Present contingencies warrant an account of Nommo that invites reflection upon the products of invention attributed to AAL.5 Nommo falls short – focusing on the self forecloses creating relations between communities and does not allow the power of the word to connect to resistance efforts Clarke 4 [Lynn, professor of communication at Vanderbilt, “Talk About Talk: Promises, Risks, and a Proposition Out of Nommo”, The Journal of Speculative Philosophy 18.4, pp. 317-325] So far, informed by a rhetorical philosophical approach to language, I have discussed certain promises and risks of framing a linguistic theory of AAL in Nommo as creative power. Regarding the promises, the architectonic force of Nommo is the possibility of expressing social trauma, and of defining the self and her experience of the world. In facilitating these acts of speech and definition, Nommo fosters subjectivity and a vital sense of human agency. Moreover, self-identity, the representation of private experience, and the practiced capacity to define one's sense of self and world, are all necessary to the work of struggle. Finally, a concept of the productive force of the word acknowledges the mutual interdependence of personhood and community and the role of creativity in fashioning the terms of social existence and, potentially, common life. Framing AAL in a theory of Nommo offers philosophers of language an opportunity to appreciate and think the potential of AAL to contribute to thriving black community. Important, these promises of invention do not come without risks. A sole focus on Nommo's power to define the self and his sense of the world forecloses the potential of speech to create relations between self and other. Similarly, the potential of Nommo to move between and relate particular [End Page 322] interests, to connect creative power to the force of communicative reason without collapsing one into the other, is squandered before it appears. The linguistic resistance attributed to AAL transforms the terms of identity and reality, but leaves unaccounted-for those members of the African American community who do not see their selves, their experiences, their values, or their interests in the newly created terms. Too, in this particular linguistic theory of AAL, the important question of affecting resistance towards collective transgression of racialized norms is at worse overlooked, and at best deferred until a time yet to be named. Turn – ontological expansiveness: exposing Nommo to whites allows them to insert their ontology into it, perpetuating white supremacy and short-circuiting resistance to it Sullivan 4 [Shannon, professor of philosophy, women’s studies, and African American studies @ Penn State, “White WorldTraveling”, Journal of Speculative Philosophy, 18.4, pp. 300-04] Letting white people into the code also risks reinforcing a particular habit of white privilege, that of ontological expansiveness (Sullivan 2001). As ontologically expansive, white people often manifest a way of being in the world (often nonconscious) in which they presume the right to occupy any and all geographical, moral, psychological, linguistic, and other spaces. From the point of view of white ontological expansiveness, the existence of a linguistic space off-limits to white people is an “unjust” violation of the “natural” order of the world that must be rectified. From an antiracist perspective, however, white ontological expansiveness not only presumes a “right” grounded in white supremacy, but also tends to damage and destroy spaces of resistance to white domination. White people’s knowledge of the code of African American Language thus can strengthen their sense that it is appropriate for them to inhabit any space they choose to enter. Treating Nommo as a interruption of whiteness flattens different cultural and racial projects within both whiteness and blackness. John McClendon 4, Associate Professor of African American and American Cultural Studies at Bates College (Ji "Philosophy of Language and the African American Experience: Are There Metaphilosophical Implications?" The Journal of Speculative Philosophy 18.4 (2004) 305-310 MUSE Philosophy, Yancy clearly shows, is not removed from the institutional practice of racism. Besides, the road to recovering a more humane sense about the doing of philosophy is to go beyond the constraining boundaries imposed by the dominant conception of African American language and its underlying racism. This racist conception offers up a view of African American language that ultimately renders it as substandard and pathological. This pathology, Yancy and Smitherman contend, in turn neglects the rich heritage of culture semiotics and nuanced meanings, which are intrinsically intertwined with the African American experience (Yancy 2004,283-84). Yancy's overriding thesis is not only the claim that there are philosophical gems locked away in the African American locutional experience: in addition, he argues that this language that so brightly radiates from African American culture is not only a site of investigation fan object of inquiry") but also a viable means as a mode for philosophical inquiry. This is all possible since in terms of a general principle, Yancy holds that modes of philosophical inquiry are at root cultural undertakings (Karp and Masoio 2000). In this manner of thinking about metaphilosophy, Yancy reiterates and extends the tradition within African American philosophy toward which Alain Locke, the first Black Rhodes Scholar and gadfly of the Harlem Renaissance, [End Page 307] dedicated so much of his intellectual efforts. Yancy, who is steeped with a substantive comprehension of the history of African American philosophy, brings into bold relief how the very definition, tasks, substance, and scope of philosophy—or, in a word, metaphilosophy—cannot expect to develop in a progressive manner without due attention to the collective lives and language practices of African Americans (Locke 1983). Here I do want to give a cautionary suggestion. Yancy must stay alert to the fact that a common culture, or shared experiences and even the enduring heritage of having the same language, is not a sufficient condition for claiming there exists, among African Americans, some kind of spontaneously arrived at common ontology, where ontology is taken as philosophical in substance. Furthermore, it seems this very premise—about the actual existence of a common African American ontology— subsequently grounds Yancy's notion about how African American language is foundational to the construction of a new conception of metaphilosophy. Now when we take into account the fact that theory is always distinct from experience, we must accordingly recognize the differentia specifica is none other than the matter of the distinction between the inquiries into experience vis-a-vis the lived experience. The determinate theoretical responses to common experience (and I take philosophy to be the most abstract form of theory) are always critical reflections adjoined to an inquiry about collective existence; thus, theory remains mediated and distanced from the immediacy of experience. The mediated relationship of the theoretical (ontology) to the empirical (lived experience) means there is room for a conceptual space, which allows for the description, definition, and interpretation of experience. This necessary space between the theoretical and the empirical is why common experiences are not a sufficient condition for sharing a common ontology. Additionally, the function of various forms of social stratification—especially the impact of class contradictions—harbors the real possibility for different ideological responses to commonly experienced conditions of life. In the manner of the Marxist conception of ideology, as found in The German Ideology, I presume that philosophy (ontology) is a form of ideology (Marx and Engels 1976). Hence, only on the presupposition that the African American community is socially homogeneous can it plausibly he argued that African Americans all share the same ontology. Given it is not the case that the African American community is homogeneous, then there is no plausible warranting for the belief that all African Americans share a common ontology. This leads directly to point three and my charge of Yancy's (and Smitherman's) vindicationism, where he argues that resistance to white supremacy is the defining characteristic of African American culture and hence language. When African American vindicationism is bereft of dialectical theory and method, as a determinate philosophical approach to African American culture, it neglects a very important aspect of the historical dialectic of African American [End Page 308] culture, viz, that African American culture is not in any way a monolithically formed culture where there are only manifestations of resistance. There is more to African American history and culture than a continuous line of resistance to oppression, for, by way of example, not all African Americans sang the spirituals with an eve to Joining the Underground Railroad (Fisher 1990). Some believed that freedom was wearing a robe in "heahen" and that washing in the blood of Jesus would make one "as white as the snow," Or that lovaitv to Massa was the highest virtue and resistance and revolt were of the greatest follv. The modem dav connotation for "Uncle Tom" did not enter the lexicon of African American language without the historical presence of real, existing "Toms." It is no accident that there is the current exercise in African American locution of playing on this word (Tom) whenever Supreme Court Justice, Clarence "Tom-to-us" is mentioned among African American political speakers. After all, the historical record indicates that the failure of Gabriel Prosser's. Denmark Vesev's. and Nat Turner's slave insurrections were due in part to other slaves that were more loval to Massa than their own liberation . Mind you that those who ratted out the slave revolts shared in the same language, ate the same food, lived the same experiences, but also had a different worldview (conception of reality) and set of values. The idea that social ontology and identity among African Americans, past and present, are preeminently the same for all is the sort of reductionism that flattens out the cultural, social, nolitical. and ideological landscape called African American culture. Albeit, resistance is cardinal and crucial to any description, definition, and interpretation of African American culture, nonetheless, it is not exhaustive of its actualities and even of its future possibilities. African American culture in its full substance and scope is more complex than a singular thrust in the monodirection of resistance. Rather, African American culture historically constitutes an ensemble of traditions in which we are able, for analytical purposes, to locate what are two primary and yet contradictory forms, viz. one of resistance and another of accommodation. This internal dialectic is undermined when a scenario of resistance sans accommodation gains support via vindicationism. In conclusion, the Yancy/Smitherman thesis about the importance of African American language is a needed corrective to the hegemonic perspective that relegates African American language to a form of substandard speech and African American culture to the dismal state of pathology. In providing this service, they present to us what are new avenues for the philosophy of language to creatively explore. Alternatively, Yancy's accent on the African American collective lived experience as the source for a common ontology affixed with the vindicationist conception of African American culture, where resistance becomes the only viable cultural/political tradition, is problematic. Moreover, I think it is precisely the common ontology and vindicationist theses that function as the twin pillars on which Yancy builds his case for not only viewing African American language [End Page 309] as a viable object of philosophical inquiry but also making the stronger claim that African American language can act as the basis for the construction of metaphilosophy. Here, I would only say that given my aforesaid arguments concerning the lack of evidential and logical support for a distinctive African American ontology and along my charges about the inherent weaknesses with vindicationism, the matter and manner of how African American language would serve in the reconceptualization of metaphilosophy remain open questions. 1 Culture, not language, constitutes reality and thought Faccone 2K Claudia Faccone, Robert Kearns, Ashley Kopp, Elizabeth Watson April 19, 2000, The Effects of Language on Thought http://www.unc.edu/~jdumas/projects/languagethought.htm The issue of whether or not language influences thought is tricky since more than one factor affects thought patterns. Many researchers have used differing languages to study the relationship between language and thought, and they have come up with many different hypotheses. We propose that although specific languages would affect the part of the brain that one uses, it is not language alone that produces "linguistically" differentiated thought patterns. Rather it is one’s culture. Though different linguistic cultures have specific language for certain ideas and concepts, the culture they are raised in most likely produce their differentiated ways of thinking. In the United States of America, where English is the predominate language, school systems have a specific method of teaching their curriculum to students. Though not all students are able to grasp this teaching process, most are; this method, taught to them by their teachers, becomes a large part of their thought processes. If one takes into account the idea of society and its impact on thought processes, then both the linguistic universalism and linguistic relativity theories are applicable. Humans are biologically capable of learning any language, but once an individual has passed a certain age, he/she is less likely to develop new language skills. At that point, culture will use the knowledge of words from education to teach a specific way of analyzing the world. It is the culture, not purely language, which facilitates a different way of thinking. Consequently, this is the extra piece of the puzzle that so many scholars have left out in their research endeavors concerning the relationship between thought and language. debating the law teaches us how to make it better – rejection is worse Hedrick 12 Todd Hedrick, Assistant Professor of Philosophy at Michigan State University, Sept 2012, Democratic Constitutionalism as Mediation: The Decline and Recovery of an Idea in Critical Social Theory, Constellations Volume 19, Issue 3, pages 382–400 Habermas’ alleged abandonment of immanent critique, however, is belied by the role that the democratic legal system comes to play in his theory. While in some sense just one system among others, it has a special capacity to shape the environments of other systems by regulating their interaction. Of course, the legal system is not the only one capable of affecting the environments of other systems, but law is uniquely open to inputs from ordinary language and thus potentially more pliant and responsive to democratic will formation: “Normatively substantive messages can circulate throughout society only in the language of law … . Law thus functions as the ‘transformer’ that guarantees that the socially integrating network of communication stretched across society as a whole holds together.”55 This allows for the possibility of consensual social regulation of domains ranging from the economy to the family, where actors are presumed to be motivated by their private interests instead of respect for the law, while allowing persons directed toward such interests to be cognizant that their privately oriented behavior is compatible with respect for generally valid laws. While we should be cautious about automatically viewing the constitution as the fulcrum of the legal order, its status as basic law is significant in this respect. For, recalling Hegel's broader conception of constitutionalism, political constitutions not only define the structure of government and “the relationship between citizens and the state” (as in Hegel's narrower “political” constitution); they also “implicitly prefigure a comprehensive legal order,” that is, “the totality comprised of an administrative state, capitalist economy, and civil society.”56 So, subsystems, their while these social spheres can be conceived of as autonomous functional boundaries are legally defined in a way that affects the manner and degree of their interaction: “The political constitution is geared to shaping each of these systems by means of the medium of law and to harmonizing them so that they can fulfill their functions as measured by a presumed ‘common good’.”57 Thus, constitutional discourses should be seen less as interpretations of a positive legal text, and more as attempts to articulate legal norms that could shift the balance between these spheres in a manner more reflective of generalizable interests, occurring amidst class stratification and cultural pluralism.¶ A constitution's status as positive law is also of importance for fundamentally Hegelian reasons relating to his narrower sense of political constitutionalism: its norms must be public and concrete, such that differently positioned citizens have at least an initial sense of what the shared hermeneutic starting points for constitutional discourse might be. But these concrete formulations must also be understood to embody principles in the interest of all citizens, so that constitutional discourse can be the site of effective democratic will formation concerning the basic norms that mediate between particular individuals and the general interests of free and equal citizens. This recalls Hegel's point that constitutions fulfill their mediational function by being sufficiently positive so as to be publicly recognizable, yet are not exhausted by this positivity – the content of the constitution is instead filled in over time through ongoing legislation. In order to avoid Hegel's foreshortened conception of public participation in this process and his consequent authoritarian tendencies, Habermas and, later, Benhabib highlight the importance of being able to conceive of basic constitutional norms as themselves being the products of public contestation and discourse. In order to articulate this idea, they draw on legal theorists like Robert Cover and Frank Michelman who characterize this process of l egal rearticulation as “jurisgenesis”58: a community's production of legal meaning by way of continuous rearticulation, through reflection and contestation, of its constitutional project.¶ Habermas explicitly conceives of the democratic legal order in this way when, in the context of considering the question of how a constitution that confers legitimacy on ordinary legislation could itself be thought to be democratically legitimate, he writes:¶ I propose that we understand the regress itself as the understandable expression of the future-oriented character, or openness, of the democratic constitution: in my view, a constitution that is democratic – not just in its content but also according to its source of legitimation – is a tradition-building project with a clearly marked beginning in time. All the later generations have the task of actualizing the still-untapped normative substance of the system of rights.59¶ A constitutional order and its interpretive history represent a community's attempt to render the terms under which they can give themselves the law that shapes their society's basic structure and secure the law's integrity through assigning basic liberties. Although philosophical reflection can give us some grasp of the presuppositions of a practice of legitimate lawmaking, this framework of presuppositions (“the system of rights”) is “unsaturated.”60 In Hegelian fashion, it must, to be meaningful, be concretized through discourse, and not in an one-off way during a founding moment that fixes the terms of political association once and for all, but continuously, as new persons enter the community and as new circumstances, problems, and perspectives emerge. ¶ The stakes involved in sustaining a broad and inclusive constitutional discourse turn out to be significant. Habermas has rec ently invoked the concept of dignity in this regard, linking it to the process through which society politically constitutes itself as a reciprocal order of free and equal citizens. As a status rather than an inherent property, “dignity that accrues to all persons equally preserves the connotation of a self-respect that depends on social recognition.”61 Rather than being understood as a quality possessed by some persons by virtue of their proximity to something like the divine, the modern universalistic conception of dignity is a social status dependent upon ongoing practices of mutual recognition. Such practices, Habermas posits, are most fully instantiated in the role of citizens as legislators of the order to which they are subject.¶ [Dignity] can be established only within the framework of a constitutional state, something that never emerges of its own accord. Rather, this framework must be created by the citizens themselves using the means of positive law and must be protected and developed under historically changing conditions. As a modern legal concept, human dignity is associated with the status that citizens assume in the self-created political order.62¶ Although the implications of invoking dignity (as opposed to, say, autonomy) as the normative core of democratic constitutionalism are unclear,63 plainly Habermas remains committed to strongly intersubjective conceptions of democratic constitutionalism, to an intersubjectivity that What all of this suggests is a constitutional politics in which citizens are empowered to take part and meaningfully impact the terms of their cultural, economic, and political relations to each other. Such politics would need to be considerably less legalistic and precedent bound, less focused on the democracy-constraining aspects of constitutionalism emphasized in most liberal rule of law models. The sense of incompleteness and revisability that marks this critical theory approach to constitutionalism represents a point where critical theories of democracy may claim to be more radical and revisionary than most liberal and deliberative counterparts. It implies a sharp critique of more familiar models of bourgeois constitutionalism: whether they conceive of constitutional order as having a foundation in moral rights or natural law, or in an originary founding moment, such models a) tend to be backward-looking in their justifications, seeing the legal order as founded on some exogenously determined vision of moral order; b) tend to represent the law as an already-determined container within which legitimate ordinary politics takes place; and c) find the content of law to be ascertainable through the specialized reasoning of legal professionals. On the critical theory conception of constitutionalism, this presumption of completeness and technicity amounts to the continues to be legally and politically mediated (a dimension largely absent from Honneth's successor theory of intersubectivity).¶ reification of a constitutional project, where a dynamic social relation is misperceived as something fixed and objective.64 We can see why this would be immensely problematic for someone like Habermas, for whom constitutional norms are supposed to concern the generalizable interests of free and equal citizens. If it is overall the case for him that generalizable interests are at least partially constituted through discourse and are therefore not given in any pre-political, pre-discursive sense,65 this is especially so in a society like ours with an unreconciled class structure sustained by pseudo-compromises. Therefore, discursive rearticulation of basic norms is necessary for the very emergence of generalizable interests.¶ Despite offering an admirably systematic synthesis of radical democracy and the constitutional rule of law, Habermas’ theory is hobbled by the hesitant way he embraces these ideas. Given his strong commitment to proceduralism, the view that actual discourses among those affected must take place during the production of legitimate law if constitutionalism is to perform its mediational function, as well as his opposition to foundational or backward-looking models of political justification, we might expect Habermas to advocate the continuous circulation in civil society of constitutional discourses that consistently have appreciable impact on the way constitutional projects develop through ongoing legislation such that citizens can see the links between their political constitution (narrowly construed), the effects that democratic discourse has on the shape that it takes, and the role of the political constitution in regulating and transforming the broader institutional backbone of society in accordance with the common good. And indeed, at least in the abstract, this is what the “two track” conception of democracy in Between Facts and Norms, with its model of discourses circulating between the informal public sphere and more formal legislative institutions, seeks to capture.66 As such, Habermas’ version of constitutionalism seems a natural ally of theories of “popular constitutionalism”67 emerging from the American legal academy or of those who, like Jeremy Waldron,68 are skeptical of the merits of legalistic constitutionalism and press for democratic participation in the ongoing rearticulation of constitutional norms. Indeed, I would submit that the preceding pages demonstrate that the Left Hegelian social theoretic backdrop of Habermas’ theory supplies a deeper normative justification for more democratic conceptions of constitutionalism than have heretofore been supplied by their proponents (who are, to be fair, primarily legal theorists seeking to uncover the basic commitments of American constitutionalism, a project more interpretive than normative.69) Given that such theories have very revisionary views on the appropriate method and scope of judicial review and the role of the constitution in public life, it is surprising that Habermas evinces at most a mild critique of the constitutional practices and institutions of actually existing democracies, never really confronting the possibility that institutions of constitutional review administered by legal elites could be paternalistic or extinguish the public impetus for discourse he so prizes.70 In fact, institutional questions concerning where constitutional discourse ought to take place and how the power to make authoritative determinations of constitutional meaning should be shared among civil society, legislative, and judiciary are mostly abstracted away in Habermas’ post-Between Facts and Norms writings, while that work is mostly content with the professional of administration of constitutional issues as it exists in the United States and Germany.¶ This is evident in Habermas’ embrace of figures from liberal constitutional theory. He does not present an independent theory of judicial decision-making, but warmly receives Dworkin's well-known model of “law as integrity.” To a certain extent, this allegiance makes sense, given Dworkin's sensitivity to the hermeneutic dimension of interpretation and the fact that his concept of integrity mirrors discourse theory in holding that legal decisions must be justifiable to those affected in terms of publicly recognizable principles. Habermas does, however, follow Michelman in criticizing the “monological” form of reasoning that Dworkin's exemplary Judge Hercules employs,71 replacing it with the interpretive activities of a specialized legal public sphere, presumably more responsive to the public than Hercules. But this substitution does nothing to alleviate other aspects of Dworkin's theory that make a match between him and Habermas quite awkward: Dworkin's standard of integrity compels judges to regard the law as a complete, coherent whole that rests on a foundation of moral rights.72 Because Dworkin regards deontic rights in a strongly realistic manner and as an unwritten part of the law, there is a finished, retrospective, “already there” quality to his picture of it. Thinking of moral rights as existing independently of their social articulation is what moves Dworkin to conceive of them as, at least in principle, accessible to the right reason of individual moral subjects.73 Legal correctness can be achieved when lawyers and judges combine their specialized knowledge of precedent with their potentially objective insights into deontic rights. Fashioning the law in accordance with the demands of integrity thereby becomes the province of legal elites, rendering public discourse and the construction of generalizable interests in principle unnecessary. This helps explain Dworkin's highly un-participatory conception of democracy and his comfort with placing vast decision-making powers in the hands of the judiciary.7¶ There is more than a little here that should make Habermas uncomfortable. Firstly, on his account, legitimate law is the product of ac tual discourses, which include the full spate of discourse types (pragmatic, ethical-political, and moral). If the task of judicial decision-making is to reconstruct the types of discourse that went into the production of law, Dworkin's vision of filling in the gaps between legal rules exclusively with considerations of individual moral rights (other considerations are collected under the heading of “policy”75) makes little sense.76 While Habermas distances himself from Dworkin's moral realism, calling it “hard to defend,”77 he appears not to appreciate the extent to which Dworkin links his account of legal correctness to this very possibility of individual insight into the objective moral order. If Habermas wishes to maintain his long held position that constitutional projects involve the ongoing construction of generalizable interests through the democratic process – which in my view is really the heart of his program – he needs an account of legal correctness that puts some distance between this vision and Dworkin's picture of legal elites discovering the content of law through technical interpretation and rational intuition into a fixed moral order.¶ Also puzzling is the degree of influence exercised by civil society in the development of constitutional projects that Habermas appears willing to countenance. While we might expect professional adjudicative institutions to play a sort of yeoman's role vis-à-vis the public, Habermas actually puts forth something akin to Bruce Ackerman's picture of infrequent constitutional revoluti ons, where the basic meaning of a constitutional project is transformed during swelling periods of national ferment, only to resettle for decades at a time, during which it is administered by legal professionals.78 According to this position, American civil society has not generated new understandings of constitutional order that overcome group divisions since the New Deal, or possibly the Civil Rights era. Now, this may actually be the case, and perhaps Habermas’ apparent acquiescence to this view of once-every-few-generations national conversations is a nod to realism, i.e., a realistic conception of how much broad based, ongoing constitutional discourse it is reasonable to expect the public to conduct. But while a theory with a Left Hegelian pedigree should avoid “the impotence of the ought” and utopian speculation, and therefore ought not develop critical conceptions of legal practice utterly divorced from present ones, such concessions to realism are unnecessary. After all, critical theory conceptions of constitutionalism will aim to be appreciably different from the more authoritarian ones currently in circulation, which more often than not fail to stimulate and sustain public discourse on the basic constitution of society. Instead, their point would be to suggest how a more dynamic, expansive, and mediational conception of constitutionalism could unlock greater democratic freedom and rationally integrated social identities. ¶ Given these problems in Habermas’ theory, the innovations that Benhabib makes to his conception of constitutionalism are most welcome. While operating within a discourse theoretic framework, her recent work more unabashedly recalls Hegel's broader conception of the constitution as the basic norms through which a community understands and relates to itself (of which a founding legal document is but a part): a constitution is a way of life through which individuals seek to connect themselves to each other, and in which the very identity and membership of a community is constantly at stake.79 Benhabib's concept of “democratic iterations,” which draws on meaning-as-use theories, emphasizes how meaning is inevitably transformed through repetition: ¶ In the process of repeating a term or a concept, we never simply produce a replica of the original usage and its intended meaning: rather, very repetition is a form of variation. Every iteration transforms meaning, adds to it, enriches it in ever-so-subtle ways. In fact, there is really no ‘originary’ source of meaning, or an ‘original’ to which all subsequent forms must conform … . Every iteration involves making sense of an authoritative original in a new and different context … . Iteration is the reappropriation of the ‘origin’; it is at the same time its dissolution as the original and its preservation through its continuous deployment.80 ¶ Recalling the reciprocal relationship that Hegel hints at between the narrow “political” constitution and the broader constitution of society's backbone of interrelated institutions, Benhabib here seems to envision a circular process whereby groups take up the conceptions of social relations instantiated in the legal order and transform them in their more everyday attempts to live with others in accordance with these norms. Like Cover and Michelman, she stresses that the transformation of legal meaning takes place primarily in informal settings, where different groups try (and sometimes fail) to live together and to understand themselves in their relation to others according to the terms they inherit from the constitutional tradition they find themselves subject to.81 Her main example of such democratic iteration is the challenge Muslim girls in France raised against the head scarf prohibition in public schools (“L’Affaire du Foulard”), which, while undoubtedly antagonistic, she contends has the potential to felicitously transform the meaning of secularity and inclusion in the French state and to create new forms of togetherness and understanding. But although Benhabib It is telling, however, that Benhabib's examples of democratic iterations are exclusively centered on what Habermas would call ethical-political discourses.83 While illustrates the concept of democratic iterations through an exemplary episode, this iterative process is a constant and pervasive one, which is punctuated by events and has the tendency to have a destabilizing effect on authority.82 ¶ otherwise not guilty of the charge,84 Benhabib, in her constitutional theory, runs afoul of Nancy Fraser's critical diagnosis of the trend in current political philosophy to subordinate class and distributional conflicts to struggles for cultural inclusion and recognition.85 Perhaps this is due to the fact that “hot” constitutional issues are so often ones with cultural dimensions in the foreground, rarely touching visibly on distributional conflicts between groups. This nonetheless is problematic since much court business clearly affects – often subtly and invisibly – the outcomes of these conflicts, frequently with bad results.86 For another reason why centering constitutional discourse on inclusion and cultural issues is problematic, it is useful to remind ourselves of Habermas’ critique of civic republicanism, according to which the main deficit in republican models of democracy is its “ethical overburdening” of the political process.87 To some extent, republicanism's emphasis on ethical discourse is understandable: given the level of cooperativeness and public spirit that republicans view as the font of legitimate law, political discourses need to engage the motivations and identities of citizens. Arguably, issues of ethical self-understanding do this better than more abstract or arid forms of politics. But it is not clear that this is intrinsically so, and it can have distorting effects on politics. In the American media, for example, this amplification of the cultural facets of issues is very common; conflicts over everything from guns to taxes are often reduced to conflicts over who is a good, real American and who is not. It is hard to say that this proves edifying; substantive issues of rights and social justice are elided, politics becomes more fraudulent and conflictual. None of this is to deny a legitimate place for ethical-political discourse. However, we do see something of a two-steps-forward-one-step-back movement in Benhabib's advancement of Habermas’ discourse theory of law: although her concept of democratic iterations takes center stage, she develops the notion solely along an ethical-political track. Going forward, critical theorists developing conceptions of constitutional discourse should work to see it as a way of integrating questions of distributional justice with questions of moral rights and collective identities without subordinating or conflating them.¶ 4. Conclusion¶ Some readers may find the general notion of reinvigorating a politics of constitutionalism quixotic. Certainly, it has not been not my intention to overstate the importance or positive contributions of constitutions in actually existing democracies, where they can serve to entrench political systems experiencing paralysis in the face of long term fiscal and environmental problems, and where public appeals to them more often than not invoke visions of society that are more nostalgic, ethno-nationalistic, authoritarian, and reactionary than what Habermas and Benhabib presumably have in mind. Instead, I take the basic Hegelian point I started this paper with to be this: modern persons ought to be able to comprehend their social order as the work of reason; the spine of institutions through which their relations to differently abled and positioned others are mediated ought to be responsive to their interests as fully-rounded persons; and comprehending this system of mediation ought to be able to reconcile them to the partiality of their roles within the universal state. Though modern life is differentiated, it can be understood, when seen through the lens of the constitutional order, as a result of citizens’ jointly exercised rationality as long as certain conditions are met. These conditions are, however, more stringent than Hegel realized. In light of this point, that so many issues deeply impacting citizens’ social and economic relations to one another are rendered marginal – and even invisible – in terms of the airing they receive in the public sphere, that they are treated as mostly settled or non-questions in the legal system consitutues a strikingly deficient aspect of modern politics. Examples include the intrusion of market logic and technology into everyday life, the commodification of public goods, the legal standing of consumers and residents, the role of shareholders and public interests in corporate governance, and the status of collective bargaining arrangements. Surely a contributing factor here is the absence of a shared sense of possibility that the basic terms of our social union could be responsive to the force that discursive reason can exert. Such a sense is what I am contending jurisgenerative theories ought to aim at recapturing while critiquing more legalistic and authoritarian models of law.¶ This is not to deny the possibility that democratic iterations themselves may be regressive or authoritarian, populist in the pejorative sense. But the denial of their legitimacy or possibility moves us in the direction of authoritarian conceptions of law and political power and the isolation of individuals and social groups wrought by a political order of machine-like administration that Horkheimer and Adorno describe as a main feature of modern political domination. Recapturing some sense of how human activity makes reason actual in the ongoing organization of society need not amount to the claim that reason culminates in some centralized form, as in the Hegelian state, or in some end state, as in Marx. It can, however, move us to envision the possibility of an ongoing practice of communication, lawmaking, and revision that seeks to reconcile and overcome positivity and division, without the triumphalist pretension of ever being able to fully do so. Racial progress has occurred through legal change and shifts in civil society---reversals don’t justify pessimism because specific reforms have achieved lasting reductions in racial inequality Michael Omi and Howard Winant 13, Resistance is futile?: a response to Feagin and Elias, Ethnic and Racial Studies Volume 36, Issue 6, p. 961-973, 2013 Special Issue: Symposium - Rethinking Racial Formation Theory In Feagin and Elias's account, white racist rule in the USA appears unalterable and permanent. There is little sense that the ‘white racial frame’ evoked by systemic racism theory changes in significant ways over historical time. They dismiss important rearrangements and reforms as merely ‘a distraction from more ingrained structural oppressions and deep lying inequalities that continue to define US society’ (Feagin and Elias 2012, p. 21). Feagin and Elias use a concept they call ‘surface flexibility’ to argue that white elites frame racial realities in ways that suggest change, but are merely engineered to reinforce the underlying structure of racial oppression. Feagin and Elias say the phrase ‘racial democracy’ is an oxymoron – a word defined in the dictionary as a figure of speech that combines contradictory terms. If they mean the USA is a contradictory and incomplete democracy in respect to race and racism issues, we agree. If they mean that people of colour have no democratic rights or political power in the USA, we disagree . The USA is a racially despotic country in many ways, but in our view it is also in many respects a racial democracy, capable of being influenced towards more or less inclusive and redistributive economic policies , social policies, or for that matter, imperial policies. What is distinctive about our own epoch in the USA (post-Second World War to the present) with respect to race and racism? ¶ Over the past decades there has been a steady drumbeat of efforts to contain and neutralize civil rights, to restrict racial democracy, and to maintain or even increase racial inequality. Racial disparities in different institutional sites – employment, health, education – persist and in many cases have increased. Indeed, the post-2008 period has seen a dramatic increase in racial inequality. The subprime home mortgage crisis, for example, was a major racial event. Black and brown people were disproportionately affected by predatory lending practices; many lost their homes as a result; race-based wealth disparities widened tremendously. It would be easy to conclude, as Feagin and Elias do, that white racial dominance has been continuous and unchanging throughout US history . But such a perspective misses the dramatic twists and turns in racial politics that have occurred since the Second World War and the civil rights era.¶ Feagin and Elias claim that we overly inflate the significance of the changes wrought by the civil rights movement, and that we ‘overlook the serious reversals of racial justice and persistence of huge racial inequalities’ (Feagin and Elias 2012, p. 21) that followed in its wake. We do not . In Racial Formation we wrote about ‘racial reaction’ in a chapter of that name, and elsewhere in the book as well. Feagin and Elias devote little attention to our arguments there; perhaps because they are in substantial agreement with us. While we argue that the right wing was able to ‘rearticulate’ race and racism issues to roll back some of the gains of the civil rights movement, we also believe that there are limits to what the right could achieve in the post-civil rights political landscape.¶ So we agree that the present prospects for racial justice are demoralizing at best. But we do not think that is the whole story. US racial conditions have changed over the post-Second World War period, in ways that Feagin and Elias tend to downplay or neglect. Some of the major reforms of the 1960s have proved irreversible; they have set powerful democratic forces in motion . These racial (trans)formations were the results of unprecedented political mobilizations, led by the black movement, but not confined to blacks alone. Consider the desegregation of the armed forces, as well as key civil rights movement victories of the 1960s: the Voting Rights Act, the Immigration and Naturalization Act (Hart- Celler), as well as important court decisions like Loving v. Virginia that declared antimiscegenation laws unconstitutional. While we have the greatest respect for the late Derrick Bell, we do not believe that his ‘interest convergence hypothesis’ effectively explains all these developments. How does Lyndon Johnson's famous (and possibly apocryphal) lament upon signing the Civil Rights Act on 2 July 1964 – ‘We have lost the South for a generation’ – count as ‘convergence’?¶ The US racial regime has been transformed in significant ways . As Antonio Gramsci argues, hegemony proceeds through the incorporation of opposition (Gramsci 1971, p. 182). The civil rights reforms can be seen as a classic example of this process; here the US racial regime – under movement pressure – was exercising its hegemony. But Gramsci insists that such reforms – which he calls ‘passive revolutions’ – cannot be merely symbolic if they are to be effective: oppositions must win real gains in the process. Once again, we are in the realm of politics, not absolute rule. ¶ So yes, we think there were important if partial victories that shifted the racial state and transformed the significance of race in everyday life. And yes, we think that further victories can take place both on the broad terrain of the state and on the more immediate level of social across civil society . Indeed we have argued that in many ways the most important accomplishment of the anti-racist movement of the 1960s in the USA was the politicization of the social. In the USA and indeed around the globe, race-based movements demanded not only the inclusion of racially defined ‘others’ and the democratization of structurally racist societies, but also the recognition and validation by both interaction: in daily interaction, in the human psyche and the state and civil society of racially-defined experience and identity. These demands broadened and deepened democracy itself. They facilitated not only the democratic gains made in the USA by the black movement and its allies, but also the political advances towards equality, social justice and inclusion accomplished by other ‘new social movements’: secondwave feminism, gay liberation, and the environmentalist and anti-war movements among others.¶ By no means do we think that the postwar movement upsurge was an unmitigated success. Far from it: all the new social movements were subject to the same ‘rearticulation’ (Laclau and Mouffe 2001, p. xii) that produced the racial ideology of ‘colourblindness’ and its variants; indeed all these movements confronted their mirror images in the mobilizations that arose from the political right to counter them. Yet even their incorporation and containment, even their confrontations with the various ‘backlash’ phenomena of the past few decades, even the need to develop the highly contradictory ideology of ‘colourblindness’, reveal the transformative character of the ‘politicization of the social’. While it is not possible here to explore so extensive a subject, it is worth noting that it was the long-delayed eruption of racial subjectivity and self-awareness into the mainstream political arena that set off this transformation, shaping both the democratic and anti-democratic social movements that are evident in US politics today. ¶ What are the political implications of contemporary racial trends?¶ Feagin and Elias's use of racial categories can be imprecise. This is not their problem alone; anyone writing about race and racism needs to frame terms with care and precision, and we undoubtedly get fuzzy too from time to time. The absence of a careful approach leads to ‘ racial lumping’ and essentialisms of various kinds. This imprecision is heightened in polemic. In the Feagin and Elias essay the term ‘whites’ at times refers to all whites, white elites, ‘dominant white actors’ and very exceptionally, anti-racist whites, a category in which we presume they would place themselves. Although the terms ‘black’, ‘African American’ and ‘Latino’ appear, the term ‘people of colour’ is emphasized, often in direct substitution for black reference points. ¶ In the USA today it is important not to frame race in a bipolar manner. The black/white paradigm made more sense in the past than it does in the twenty-first century. The racial make-up of the nation has now changed dramatically. Since the passage of the Immigration Reform Act of 1965, the USA has become more ‘coloured’. A ‘majority–minority’ national demographic shift is well underway. Predicted to arrive by the mid-twenty-first century, the numerical eclipse of the white population is already in evidence locally and regionally. In California, for example, non-Hispanic whites constitute only 39.7 per cent of the state's population. While the decline in the white population cannot be correlated with any decline of white racial dominance, the dawning and deepening of racial multipolarity calls into question a sometimes implicit and sometimes explicit black/white racial framework that is evident in Feagin and Elias's essay. Shifting racial demographics and identities also raise general questions of race and racism in new ways that the ‘systemic racism’ approach is not prepared to explain.3¶ Class questions and issues of panethnicizing trends, for example, call into question what we mean by race, racial identity and race consciousness. No racially defined group is even remotely uniform; groups that we so glibly refer to as Asian American or Latino are particularly heterogeneous. Some have achieved or exceeded socio-economic parity with whites, while others are subject to what we might call ‘engineered poverty’ in sweatshops, dirty and dangerous labour settings, or prisons. Tensions within panethnicized racial groups are notably present, and conflicts between racially defined groups (‘black/brown’ conflict, for example) are evident in both urban and rural settings. A substantial current of social scientific analysis now argues that Asians and Latinos are the ‘new white ethnics’, able to ‘work toward whiteness’4 at least in part, and that the black/white bipolarity retains its distinct and foundational qualities as the mainstay of US racism (Alba and Nee 2005; Perlmann 2005; Portes and Rumbaut 2006; Waters, Ueda and Marrow 2007).¶ We question that argument in light of the massive demographic shifts taking place in the USA. Globalization, climate change and above all neoliberalism on a global scale, all drive migration. The country's economic capacity to absorb enormous numbers of immigrants, low-wage workers and their families (including a new, globally based and very female, servant class) without generating the sort of established subaltern groups we associate with the terms race and racism, may be more limited than it was when the ‘whitening’ of Europeans took place in the nineteenth and twentieth centuries. In other words this argument's key precedent, the absorption of white immigrants ‘of a different color’ (Jacobson 1998), may no longer apply. Indeed, we might think of the assimilationist model itself as a general theory of immigrant incorporation that was based on a historically specific case study – one that might not hold for, or be replicated by, subsequent big waves of immigration. Feagin and Elias's systemic racism model, while offering numerous important insights, does not inform concrete analysis of these issues. ¶ It is important going forward to understand how groups are differentially racialized and relatively positioned in the US racial hierarchy: once again racism must be seen as a shifting racial project. This has important consequences, not only with respect to emerging patterns of inequality, but also in regard to the degree of power available to different racial actors to define, shape or contest the existing racial landscape. Attention to such matters is largely absent in Feagin and Elias's account. In their view racially identified groups are located in strict reference to the dominant ‘white racial frame’, hammered into place, so to speak. As a consequence, they fail to examine how racially subordinate groups interact and influence each others’ boundaries, conditions and practices. Because they offer so little specific analysis of Asian American, Latino or Native American racial issues, the reader finds her/himself once again in the land (real or imaginary, depending on your racial politics) of bipolar US racial dynamics, in which whites and blacks play the leading roles, and other racially identified groups – as well as those ambiguously identified, such as Middle Eastern and South Asian Americans (MEASA) – play at best supporting roles, and are sometimes cast as extras or left out of the picture entirely. ¶ We still want to acknowledge that blacks have been catching hell and have borne the brunt of the racist reaction of the past several decades. For example, we agree with Feagin and Elias's critique of the reactionary politics of incarceration in the USA. The ‘new Jim Crow’ (Alexander 2012) or even the ‘new slavery’ that the present system practises is something that was just in its beginning stages when we were writing Racial Formation. It is now recognized as a national and indeed global scandal. How is it to be understood? Of course there are substantial debates on this topic, notably about the nature of the ‘prison-industrial complex’ (Davis 2003, p. 3) and the social and cultural effects of mass incarceration along racial lines. But beyond Feagin and Elias's denunciation of the ferocious white racism that is operating here, deeper political implications are worth considering. As Alexander (2012), Mauer (2006), Manza and Uggen (2008) and movement groups like Critical Resistance and the Ella Baker Center argue, the upsurge over recent decades in incarceration rates for black (and brown) men expresses the fear-based, law-and-order appeals that have shaped US racial politics since the rise of Nixonland (Perlstein 2008) and the ‘Southern strategy’. Perhaps even more central, racial repression aims at restricting the increasing impact of voters of colour in a demographically shifting electorate.¶ There is a lot more to say about this, but for the present two key points stand out: first, it is not an area where Feagin and Elias and we have any sharp disagreement, and second, for all the horrors and injustices that the ‘new Jim Crow’ represents, incarceration, profiling and similar practices remain political issues. These practices and policies are not ineluctable and unalterable dimensions of the US racial regime. There have been previous waves of reform in these areas. They can be transformed again by mass mobilization, electoral shifts and so on. In other words, resistance is not futile.¶ Speaking of electoral shifts and the formal political arena, how should President Barack Obama be politically situated in this discussion? How do Feagin and Elias explain Obama? Quite amazingly, his name does not appear in their essay. Is he a mere token, an ‘oreo’, a shill for Wall Street? Or does Obama represent a new development in US politics, a black leader of a mass, multiracial party that for sheer demographic reasons alone might eventually triumph over the white people's party, the Republicans? If the President is neither the white man's token nor Neo, the One,5 then once again we are in the world of politics: neither the near-total white despotism depicted by Feagin and Elias, nor a racially inclusive democracy. ¶ President Obama continues to enjoy widespread black support, although it is clear that he has not protected blacks against their greatest cumulative loss of wealth in history. He has not explicitly criticized the glaring racial bias in the US carceral system. He has not intervened in conflicts over workers’ rights – particularly in the public sector where many blacks and other people of colour are concentrated. He has not intervened to halt or slow foreclosures, except in ways that were largely symbolic. Workers and lower-middle-class people were the hardest hit by the great recession and the subprime home mortgage crisis, with black families faring worst, and Latinos close behind (Rugh and Massey 2010); Obama has not defended them. Many writers have explained Obama's centrism and unwillingness to raise the issue of race as functions of white racism (Sugrue 2010). ¶ The black community – and other communities of colour as well – remains politically divided. While black folk have taken the hardest blows from the reactionary and racist regime that has mostly dominated US politics since Reagan (if not since Nixon), no united black movement has succeeded the deaths of Malcolm and Martin. Although there is always important political activity underway, a relatively large and fairly conservative black middle class, a ‘black bourgeoisie’ in Frazier's (1957) terms, has generally maintained its position since the end of the civil rights era. Largely based in the public sector, and including a generally centrist business class as well, this stratum has continued to play the role that Frazier – and before him, Charles S. Johnson. William Lloyd Warner, Alison Davis and other scholars – identified: vacillation between the white elite and the black masses. Roughly similar patterns operate in Latino communities as well, where the ‘working towards whiteness’ framework coexists with a substantial amount of exclusion and super-exploitation.¶ Alongside class issues in communities of colour, there are significant gender issues. The disappearance of blue-collar work, combined with the assault by the criminal justice system – chiefly profiling by the police (‘stop and frisk’) and imprisonment, have both unduly targeted and victimized black and brown men, especially youth. Women of colour are also targeted, especially by violence, discrimination and assaults on their reproductive rights (Harris-Perry 2011); profiling is everywhere (Glover 2009).¶ Here again we are in the realm of racial politics. Debate proceeds in the black community on Obama's credibilty, with Cornel West and Tavis Smiley leading the critics. But it seems safe to say that in North Philly, Inglewood or Atlanta's Lakewood section, the president remains highly popular. Latino support for Obama remains high as well. Feagin and Elias need to clarify their views on black and brown political judgement. Is it attuned to political realities or has it been captured by the white racial frame? Is Obama's election of no importance? ¶ ***¶ In conclusion, do Feagin and Elias really believe that white power is so complete, so extensive, so ‘sutured’ (as Laclau and Mouffe might say) as they suggest here? Do they mean to suggest, in Borg-fashion, that ‘resistance is futile?’ This seems to be the underlying political logic of the ‘systemic racism’ approach, perhaps unintentionally so. Is white racism so ubiquitous that no meaningful political challenge can be mounted against it? Are black and brown folk (yellow and red people, and also others unclassifiable under the always- absurd colour categories) utterly supine, duped, abject, unable to exert any political pressure? Is such a view of race and racism even recognizable in the USA of 2012? And is that a responsible political position to be advocating? Is this what we want to teach our students of colour? Or our white students for that matter? ¶ We suspect that if pressed, Feagin and Elias would concur with our judgement that racial conflict, both within (and against) the state and in everyday life, is a fundamentally political process. We think that they would also accept our claim that the ongoing political realities of race provide extensive evidence that people of colour in the USA are not so powerless, and that whites are not so omnipotent, as Feagin and Elias's analysis suggests them to be.¶ Racial formation theory allows us to see that there are contradictions in racial oppression. The racial formation approach reveals that white racism is unstable and constantly challenged, from the national and indeed global level down to the personal and intra-psychic conflicts that we all experience, no matter what our racial identity might be. While racism – largely white – continues to flourish, it is not monolithic. Yes, there have been enormous increases in racial inequality in recent years. But movement-based anti-racist opposition continues, and sometimes scores victories. Challenges to white racism continue both within the state and in civil society . Although largely and properly led by people of colour, anti-racist movements also incorporate whites such as Feagin and Elias themselves. Movements may experience setbacks, the reforms for which they fought may be revealed as inadequate, and indeed their leaders may be co-opted or even eliminated, but racial subjectivity and self-awareness, unresolved and conflictual both within the individual psyche and the body politic, abides. Resistance is not futile. Legal change has resulted in racial advancement and more is still possible---reject pessimism because it results in subversive alternatives Randall Kennedy 12, Harvard Law Professor, Race, Crime, and the Law, Knopf Doubleday Publishing Group, pp. 388-389 True, it is sometimes genuinely difficult to determine an appropriate remedial response. The proper way to address that difficulty, however, is to acknowledge and grapple with it, not bury it beneath unbelievable assertions that, in fact, no real problem exists. Whitewashing racial wrongs (especially while simultaneously proclaiming that courts are doing everything reasonably possible to combat racially invidious government action) corrupts officials and jades onlookers, nourishing simplistic, despairing, and defeatist critiques of the law that are profoundly destructive .¶ The second impression that I want to leave with readers should serve as an antidote to these overwrought, defeatist critiques by acknowledging that the administration of criminal law has changed substantially for the better over the past half century and that there is reason to believe that, properly guided, it can be improved even more. Today there are more formal and informal protections against racial bias than ever before, both in terms of the protections accorded to blacks against criminality and the treatment accorded to black suspects , defendants, and convicts. That deficiencies, large deficiencies, remain is clear. But comparing racial policies today to those that prevailed in 1940 or 1960 or even 1980 should expose the fallacy of asserting that nothing substantial has been changed for the better .¶ This point is worth stressing because of the prevalence and prominence of pessimistic thinking about the race question in American life. Some commentators maintain, in all seriousness, that there has been no significant improvement in the overall fortunes of black Americans during the past half century, that advances that appear to have been made are merely cosmetic, and that the U nited States is doomed to remain a pigmentocracy. This pessimistic strain often turns paranoid and apocalyptic in commentary about the administration of criminal law.¶ It is profoundly misleading , however, to focus exclusively on the ugliest aspects of the American legal order. Doing so conceals real achievements: the Reconstruction Constitutional Amendments, the Reconstruction civil rights laws, Strauder v. Alabama, Dempsey v. Moore, Brown v. Mississippi, Powell v. Alabama, Norris v. Alabama, Batson v. Kentucky, the resuscitation of Reconstruction by the civil rights movement, the changing demographics of the bench, bar, and police departments—in sum, the stigmatization (albeit incomplete) of invidious racial bias. Neglecting these achievements robs them of support . Recent sharp attacks upon basic guarantees bequeathed by the New Deal ought to put everyone on notice of the perils of permitting social accomplishments to lose their rightful stature in the public's estimation. Moreover, one-dimensional condemnations of the racial situation in America renders attractive certain subversive proposals that are, given actual conditions, foolish, counterproductive, and immoral. I think here in particular of the call for racially selective jury nullification. Such proposals should be openly challenged on the grounds that they fundamentally misperceive the racial realities of American life.