Stephen Davies

advertisement
Geneva conference paper
Music-to-Listener Emotional Contagion
Stephen Davies
Abstract
I have argued that some emotional responses to music's expressiveness involve emotional
contagion. In this paper I outline the challenge this view poses to the cognitive theory of the
emotions, because, in the cases in question, the listener does not believe of the music what would
make it an appropriate object of her response. And I use the response to music to question some
models of emotional human-to-human contagion developed by psychologists.
It was in 1980 and 1983 that I first published on the relation between music's
expressiveness and the listener's response. I do not subscribe to the so-called
arousal theory, according to which "the music is sad" is true if and only if the
music disposes a suitably qualified and interested listener to feel sad. I regard
music's expressive properties as possessed independently of their effects.1
Nevertheless, I do think that music's expressiveness can induce an emotional
reaction and that, in the interesting case, the listener is moved to feel the
emotion that the music expresses.2 I call this a "mirroring" response and
describe the communication of emotion from music to listener as emotional
"contagion" or "infection." I am not wedded to the medical metaphor, however; I
also describe the connection as involving transmission, communication, or
osmosis.
Here is a more formal characterization of emotional contagion (from
Davies forthcoming): one emotional state, appearance, or condition is
transmitted to a person (or creature) who comes to feel the same way; the
display of the first emotional state plays a causal role in the process of
transmission and the first emotional state must be perceived, either attentionally
or non-attentionally, by the emotion's recipient; the first emotional state is not
the emotional object of the response, however, because the responder does not
hold about the first emotional state beliefs that make it an appropriate
intentional object for the response in question.
Some psychologists, including Patrik Juslin and Daniel Västfjäll (2008a),
identify emotions as involving appraisals and objects that are appraised, even
where contagion is involved.3 Let me make clearer what I mean by saying that
music is not the emotional object of the listener's mirroring response. Though it
is true that background music of which the hearer is not consciously aware
might affect her feelings by way of contagion, that is not the relevant case. And
though the intentional object of one's response can drift apart from its
perceptual object under conditions of error, as when one fears the presence of a
lion when one mistakes the shadow of a mop for the shadow of a lion, that again
is not the relevant case. Rather, the important point is that even where the
mirroring response of sadness targets and tracks the music, one is not sad for or
about the music. The emotional object of the emotion, as this notion is applied by
philosophers of emotion, is the object that is perceived with belief as falling
1
2
3
For details, see Davies 1994, 2006.
Psychologists have recorded the effect; see Evans & Schubert 2008.
By the way, I agree with Robinson (2008) that Juslin and Västfjäll frequently
depart from their definition in the paper (of 2008a) in which they give it.
under the emotion-relevant description; for instance, where the emotion is envy
of another, its emotional object is the person who I believe to possess something
that I do not have and desire. While the listener's contagious response of sadness
is reflected back to the sad music and in that sense takes the music as its object,
the music is not the emotional object of the response because the listener does
not believe of the music what would make it the emotional object of a sad
response, namely, that the music is unfortunate, suffering, or regrettable. The
music is not brought under the characterization that picks out the emotional
object of sadness. And provided that nothing else is brought under that
characterization, the response lacks an emotional object though the music
remains its perceptual object.
Emotional contagion should be distinguished from cases that are
outwardly similar in that two people come to experience the same emotion
(Davies forthcoming). The following are not instances of emotional contagion as
I have characterized that notion: We both feel the same emotion because our
emotions have a common intentional object about which we both hold the same
emotion-relevant beliefs. (We both laugh at the same joke.) I react to your
emotion by feeling the same, because I believe the basis of your reaction will also
provide me with a reason to react similarly. (Seeing you flee in terror, I do the
same without waiting to discover what you are terrified of.) Your emotion is the
emotional object of my response and our emotions are the same. (You are angry
that we are delayed, and I am angry that you are angry because you promised
you would keep your cool.) I try to work out what you are feeling by
imaginatively simulating your situation, or I use knowledge of your character
and circumstances, and thereby empathically share your state. Also to be
distinguished from emotional contagion are certain social influences on our
reactions, for example, that people laugh more with others who laugh out loud,
that they may feel a sense of community through shared emotion, or that they
may become self-conscious and embarrassed to react as others do.
I
There are many mechanisms by which an emotional response to music might be
induced. Juslin and Västfjäll (2008a) identify six of which emotional contagion is
only one, the others being brain stem reflexes, evaluative conditioning, visual
imagery, episodic memory, and musical expectancy. Some of these – for example,
increased tension when a prediction about the course of the music is defeated or
the reflex induction of a startle response by an unexpected loud chord – perhaps
should not count as emotions, and others – for example, happiness when music
triggers memories of a happy occasion – reveal more about the experiences of
the listener than the nature of the music. One reason for focusing on the
mirroring response, then, is that it is usually identified as a fully-fledged emotion
that is directly connected to and is revealing of the music's expressive character.
More important for the philosopher, perhaps, is that the mirroring response is
intriguingly problematic in two respects.
First, this type of response violates the cognitive theory of the emotions,
which is a theory put forward by Anthony Kenny (1969) and Robert C. Solomon
(1976) among others. Not everyone went so far as Solomon, who declares that
emotions are no more than judgments, but the cognitive theory maintains that
emotions are to be characterized in terms of the kinds of beliefs one holds about
their objects. It cannot be fear for myself I feel unless I believe of something that
it poses a threat to me; I cannot envy you unless I believe you possess something
that I do not have and desire. The cognitive theory stresses the cognitive
dimension of emotions, their intentionality or object-directedness, and the public
aspect of the expressive behaviors that are in part constitutive of them, and
contrasts with a physiological, often pneumatic, view that sees emotions as inner
stirrings that are distinguished one from the other by their distinctive
phenomenological profiles.
Now, the mirroring response to music does not align with the cognitive
theory because, as I observed earlier, the listener does not believe of sad music
what would make it an appropriate emotional object of the sad response she
experiences, namely, that there is something about the music that is unfortunate
or regrettable. She does not believe the music is sentient, and hence does not
believe that it suffers the sadness it expresses, so there is nothing here for her to
get sad about, yet she does become sad. Not all her sad responses are of this
kind; she might be saddened by the music's banality and execrable execution.
Such responses match the cognitive theory and are otherwise unproblematic.4
But the mirroring response of sadness does not rely on her beliefs about the
music, and where she thinks the music is good – is indeed better for its
expressiveness – such beliefs as she has are at odds with the sad response she
feels.
The second respect in which the mirroring response is problematic is
this: it appears to be non-rational, yet notwithstanding this we often would
acknowledge such a response as evidence that the listener follows the music
with understanding. Typically, we justify our emotions by showing that their
emotional objects have the emotion-relevant qualities that we believe them to
have. I justify my fear for myself by pointing to the dangerous qualities of the
apparently hungry lion that shares the room with me, for instance. But in the
case of the mirroring response, the listener does not hold beliefs about the music
appropriate for her response to its expressiveness. She cannot justify her
response of sadness in the usual way, by indicating what is unfortunate and
regrettable about the music or its expressiveness.5
II
There are several ways one might try to address the first worry. One possibility
is that the emotion takes something other than the music as its emotional object.
Perhaps the listener believes the composer must have experienced loss and
suffering to compose such sad music, and her sadness is directed to him. It seems
implausible to suggest that all mirroring responses could be explained away in
this fashion, however; after all, composers often were happy to be commissioned
4
5
Peter Kivy (1987) is one philosopher who argues that all emotional
responses to music are of this kind and that the mirroring response never
occurs.
There is a third issue, specifically about the sad (rather than the happy)
mirroring response, that I will not consider here, namely, why we enjoy and
return to music that makes us feel sad. For discussion, see Davies 1994.
to write sad requiems. A second, more promising approach is to argue that
make-believe can substitute for belief in securing an emotion to its object. And it
is quite plausible to suggest that our responses to fictional novels, dramas,
paintings, and movies involve making believe that one is seeing (or hearing
about) actual events, and that this grounds the response, whether we call it a
genuine emotion or not.6 Moreover, such a move answers the second concern as
well as the first; we can justify the rationality of the response by reference to
what is true in the fiction, that is, to the truths that the audience make-believedly
entertains under the artist's direction (Davies 1983). But what is one supposed
to make-believe on hearing an "abstract" musical work without a sung text,
program story, or literary title? Several philosophers have suggested that the
listener make-believes that the music provides a narrative about the experiences
of a hypothetical persona.7 The listener feels sad because she hears the music as
a direct expression of that fictional persona's suffering, just as she feels sad on
reading Anna Karenina or weeps at the end of La Bohème though she knows that
Anna and Mimi are no more real than is the persona imagined as being in the
music.
I agree that the cognitive theory should be modified to include makebelieve as well as belief (and perhaps other modes of mental representation as
well) and that this allows us to make sense of our responses to fictional
narratives and depictions. Moreover, I allow that the hypothetical persona
account does capture an important aspect of our experience of music's
expressiveness, namely, that it is more like a direct encounter with someone who
feels an emotion and shows it than it is like being told about or reading a
description of such matters. Nevertheless, I am not convinced that the
hypothetical persona theory correctly characterizes music's expressiveness and
our mode of reacting to this.8 In brief, many listeners who recognize music's
expressiveness are not aware of the acts of make-believe posited by the theory,
and what might be imagined along such lines is too little controlled by the course
of the music to explain agreement about what music expresses.
III
My response to the first issue did not take the form of a defense of or friendly
amendment to the cognitive theory of the emotions. A number of problem cases
for that theory are widely recognized: phobias (which do not involve beliefs
appropriate to the emotion experienced) and moods (which are apparently not
targeted on any specific intentional objects and therefore do not involve
emotion-relevant object-directed beliefs). The musical case does not fit in either
of these camps, but is a new kind of counterexample that was not widely
recognized as such. This does not mean that the musical case is one peculiar to
the aesthetic context, however, which is a good thing because the application of
emotion terms under circumstances that bear no resemblance to the wider
context of their use, as in talk of sui generis artistic emotions or responses, is
6
7
8
Carroll (1990, 1997) and Lamarque (1981) count these as genuine emotions,
Walton (1990) does not.
For example, see Levinson 1996, 2006; Robinson 2005.
For details, see Davies 1983, 1997, 2006.
rightly regarded with suspicion by contemporary philosophers of art. In fact,
appealing to what I took to be commonplaces of folk psychology, I claimed that
emotional contagion is familiar as a response to our fellow humans. We often
catch or are affected by the mood of others. Moreover, the outcome is not
necessarily diminished when we move to modes of expression that do not
involve sentience. I speculate that a person would be more likely to be depressed
working on the production of masks of tragedy than on the production of masks
of comedy. And to move yet further from the human case, it is widely held that
the weather and colors can affect our emotions, and we predicate expressive
properties to both the weather and to colors. So my response to the first concern,
that the musical mirroring response is not consistent with the cognitive theory of
the emotions (even if amended to include make-believe alongside belief) can be
summarized this way: yes, the musical reaction is an exception to the cognitive
theory of the emotions, but there are other exceptions to the theory, including
ones that parallel the musical case.
As for the second problem – that the listener does not have the beliefs
that could justify her response – one should admit that it has some force. It is not
obvious that we should criticize someone who is not moved to sadness by sad
music, because it is not as if he thereby betrays callousness or lack of sympathy.
But we can also argue that, if the mirroring response does occur, it can be
justified, not by reference to emotion-relevant beliefs but rather in the sense that
no other equally non-cognitively directed response is equally apt. By comparison
with the person who is typically cheered by sad music and depressed by happy
music, but without believing or make-believing about it anything that makes it a
fit object for happiness or depression, the person who is cheered by happy music
or saddened by gloomy music seems normal and has the appropriate response.
Or to make the point differently, there seems to be a place prepared in our
natural history for the mirroring response in a way that is not true for
alternatives that are similar in also not being cognitively directed. It is for this
reason that the listener's response can be taken as indexing her sensitive
comprehension of the music's character.
We might draw a parallel here with emotional responses to what are
known to be fictions. Some philosophers regard these as paradoxical and
irrational. After all, why should I fear the movie monster that I know not to exist
and, hence, not to be able to harm me? Whatever one says in answer to this
paradox, it seems reasonable to suggest that it is more rational to fear the
monster than the cowering, little old lady that it is threatening in the film. In the
same way, it is more rational to be saddened by sad music and gladdened by
happy music, even if I think the music expresses no one's feelings in either case
and even if I hold no other emotion-relevant beliefs about the music, than it is to
feel the reverse.
IV
At the time I was developing these views, psychologists apparently had not
clearly isolated and studied the phenomenon of emotional contagion, though
there had been much work on empathy and sympathy. The pioneering Emotional
Contagion of Elaine Hatfield, John Cacioppo, and Richard Rapson came in 1994.
Of course, those earlier researchers are not interested in the musical case; they
study the human-to-human transmission of affect. And their primary interest,
unlike mine, is in the mechanism causally responsible for inducing in one person
what is felt by the other. In brief, they describe this mechanism as follows:
(i) in attending to person A, her interlocutor, person B tends
unconsciously to ape A's facial expressions, vocal tone,
etc.;
(ii) as part of working out what she feels, B monitors her
facial expression, vocal tone, etc.;
(iii) so, if A feels some emotion and betrays it in her
appearance, tone, and action, B is inclined to come to
feel the same emotion.
In a different work, Teresa Brennan (2004) surmises that the mechanism
involves the subconscious detection of pheromones. However, if there is
emotional contagion between music and humans, or between colors or the
weather and humans, it cannot be facial mimicry or pheromones that underpin it
because music, colors, and the weather do not present a human physiognomy or
give off pheromones. The error of these psychologists is to equate the
phenomenon with causal mechanisms that apply only in the cases of contagion
that interest them. We need a more careful characterization of the phenomenon,
such as I offered earlier.
When psychologists searched for an analogous role for music in the
induction of emotion, it was in the context of testing how background music
affects the mood and behavior of diners and shoppers and in the use of music as
therapy.9 Neither kind of study specifically targets music-to-listener emotional
contagion, as opposed to more general interactive effects between music and
mood, and in many cases the concern is with effects that do not involve the
hearer's attention to the music as such. As a result, these studies do not provide
useful paradigms for the study of emotional contagion where this results from
the listener's close attention to the music's expressive character in a context of
trying to follow the music with understanding.
Psychologists concerned with music-to-listener emotional contagion of
the attentional variety tend to return to the human-to-human model. Emotional
contagion "refers to a process whereby an emotion is induced by a piece of music
because the listener perceives the emotional expression of the music, and then
'mimics' this expression internally, which by means of either peripheral feedback
from muscles, or a more direct activation of the relevant emotional
representations in the brain, leads to an induction of the same emotion … Recent
research has suggested that the process of emotional contagion may occur
through the mediation of so-called mirror neurons discovered in studies of the
monkey premotor cortex in the 1990s" (Juslin & Västfjäll 2008a, 565). The
problem with this is that it appears to turn what is supposed to be literal for
human-to-human contagion into something metaphorical. It is not as if the music
has muscles the movements of which can be mimicked, or a premotor cortex
with neuronal activity that can be mirrored in the brains of listeners. Because of
their apparently metaphorical character, the explanatory power of such
characterizations of the relevant mechanisms is questionable.
9
On shopping, see Bruner 1990; North & Milliman 1982, 1986; Hargreaves
1997; on therapy, see Bunt & Pavlicevic 2001.
Yet talk of emotional contagion seems perfectly apt in such cases. In part
this is because talk of musical movement, pattern, tension, and expressive
appearances is literal, or so I would maintain. Such attributions are secondary, in
that the meanings of the relevant terms are not first taught by reference to such
examples, but once the secondary extensions of these meanings are acquired, the
terms have the kind of shared interpersonal use that live metaphors lack (Davies
1994). If this is so, talk of listeners mimicking the music is not merely poetic;
even if there are no musical muscles or neuronal patterns to be imitated or
mirrored, there can be musical movement and process, patterns of tension and
release, and the like.
How then does emotional contagion operate in the musical case? That is
for scientists to discover, but it is possible to offer some speculative suggestions.
I favor the view that music is expressive because we experience it as presenting
the kind of carriage, gait, or demeanor that can be symptomatic of states such as
happiness, sadness, anger, sassy sexuality, and so on.10 If contagion operates
through mimicry, we might expect the listener to adopt bodily postures and
attitudes (or posturally relevant muscular proprioceptions) like those apparent
in the music's progress.11 Vocal mimicry, in the form of subtle tensing or flexing
of vocal muscles, would also be a predictable response to vocal music or to acts
of subvocal singing along with instrumental music.12 And where the flux of music
is felt as an articulated pattern of tensing and relaxing, this is likely to be imaged
and mimed within the body, perhaps in ways that are neither subpostural nor
subvocal. Finally, there is the possibility that music works on the brain, not only
by eliciting physical-cum-physiological changes that nudge the subject as she
becomes aware of them toward affective appraisals and responses, but also more
immediately, by directly stimulating cortical regions linked with emotional
recognitions and responses. Many and diverse routes of emotional transmission
might be involved, perhaps simultaneously.
Stephen Davies
Department of Philosophy,
University of Auckland.
10
11
12
For details see Davies 1980, 1994, 2006.
For relevant empirical data, see Janata & Grafton 2003.
For relevant empirical data, see Koelsch, Fritz, Crammon, Müller, & Frederici
2006. Juslin & Laukka (2003) and Juslin & Västfjäll (2008a), who postulate
that the response to music can be explained as involving emotional
contagion, make the comparison not with facial mimicry but with the
communication of affect through vocal cues. See Patel 2008 on how this
hypothesis might be tested via brain imaging; Simpson, Oliver, & Fragaszy
2008 suggest brain-imaging results count against the thesis. (Juslin &
Västfjäll reject this criticism in 2008b.) Simpson, Oliver, & Fragaszy suggest
their results – that instrumental music is not processed by parts of the brain
concerned with the voice – show that contagion is not a mechanism for the
arousal of emotion by music, but that conclusion is unwarranted because
they do not consider alternatives to the suggestion by Juslin and his fellow
researchers that music is experiences as a super-expressive voice.
References
Brennan, Teresa. 2004. The Transmission of Affect, (Ithaca: Cornell University
Press).
Bruner, G. C. 1990. "Music, Mood, and Marketing," Journal of Marketing, 54 (4),
94-104.
Bunt, Leslie & Pavlicevic, Mercédès. 2001. "Music and Emotion: Perspectives
from Music Therapy," in P. N. Juslin & J. A. Sloboda (eds), Music and
Emotion: Theory and Research, (Oxford: Oxford University Press), 181201
Carroll, Noël. 1990. The Philosophy of Horror or Paradoxes of the Heart, (New
York: Routledge).
— 1997. "Art, Narrative, and Emotion," in M. Hjort & S. Laver (eds.) Emotion and
the Arts, (Oxford: Oxford University Press), 190-211.
Davies, Stephen. 1980. "The Expression of Emotion in Music," Mind, 89, 67-86.
— 1983. "The Rationality of Aesthetic Responses," British Journal of Aesthetics,
23, 38-47.
— 1994. Musical Meaning and Expression, (Ithaca: Cornell University Press).
— 1997. "Contra the Hypothetical Persona in Music," in M. Hjort & S. Laver (eds.)
Emotion and the Arts, (Oxford: Oxford University Press), 95-109.
— 2006. "Artistic Expression and the Hard Case of Pure Music," in M. Kieran
(ed.), Contemporary Debates in Aesthetics and the Philosophy of Art,
(Oxford: Blackwell), 179-191.
— forthcoming. "Infectious Music: Music-Listener Emotional Contagion," in Peter
Goldie & Amy Coplan (eds.) Empathy: Philosophical and Psychological
Perspectives, (Oxford: Oxford University Press).
Evans, P. & Schubert, E. 2008. "Relationships between express and felt emotions
in music," Musicae Scientiae, 12, 75 – 99.
Hatfield, E., Cacioppo, J. T., & Rapson, R. L. 1994. Emotional Contagion, (New
York: Cambridge University Press).
Janata, P. & Grafton, S. T. 2003. "Swinging in the Brain: Shared Neural Substrates
for Behaviors Related to Sequencing and Music," Nature Neuroscience, 6,
682-7.
Juslin, Patrik N. & Laukka, Petri. 2003. "Communication of emotion in vocal
expression and music performance: Different channels, same code?"
Psychological Bulletin, 129/5, 770-814.
Juslin, Patrik N. & Västfjäll, Daniel. 2008a. "Emotional responses to music: The
need to consider underlying mechanisms," Behavioural and Brain
Sciences, 31, 559-75.
Juslin, Patrik N. & Västfjäll, Daniel. 2008b. "All emotions are not created equal:
Reaching beyond the traditional disputes," Behavioral and Brain Sciences,
31, 600-12.
Kenny, Anthony. 1963. Action, Emotion, and Will, (London: Routledge & Kegan
Paul).
Kivy, Peter. 1987. "How Music Moves," in P. Alperson (ed.), What Is Music?: An
Introduction to the Philosophy of Music, (New York: Haven), 149-163.
Koelsch, S., Fritz, T., Crammon, D. Y. von, Müller, K., & Frederici, A. D. 2006.
"Investigating Emotion with Music: an fMRI Study," Human Brain
Mapping, 27(3): 239-50.
Lamarque, Peter. 1981. "How Can We Fear and Pity Fictions?" British Journal of
Aesthetics, 21, 291-304.
Levinson, Jerrold. 1996. "Musical Expressiveness," in The Pleasures of Aesthetics,
(Ithaca: Cornell University Press), 90-125.
— 2006. "Musical Expressiveness as Hearability-as-expression," in M. Kieran
(ed.), Contemporary Debates in Aesthetics and the Philosophy of Art,
(Oxford: Blackwell), 192-204.
Milliman, R. E. 1982. "Using Background Music to Affect the Behavior of
Supermarket Shoppers," Journal of Marketing, 46 (3), 86-91.
— 1986. "The Influence of Background Music on the Behavior of Restaurant
Patrons," Journal of Consumer Research, 13 (2), 286-9.
North, A. C., & Hargreaves, D. J. 1997. "Music and Consumer Behaviour," in D. J.
Hargreaves and A. C. North (eds.), The Social Psychology of Music, (Oxford:
Oxford University Press), 268-89.
Patel, Aniruddh D. 2008. "A neurobiological strategy for exploring links between
emotion recognition in music and speech," Behavioral and Brain Sciences,
31, 589-90.
Robinson, Jenefer. 2005. Deeper than Reason: Emotion and Its Role in Literature,
Music, and Art, (Oxford: Clarendon Press).
Robinson, Jenefer. 2008. "Do all musical emotions have the music itself as their
intentional object?" Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 31, 592-3.
Simpson, Elisabeth A., Oliver, William T., & Fragaszy, Dorothy. 2008. "Superexpressive Voices: Music to my Ears?" Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 31,
596-7.
Solomon, Robert C. 1976. The Passions, (Garden City: Anchor).
Walton, Kendall L. 1990. Mimesis as Make-Believe: On the Foundations of the
Representational Arts, (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press).
Download