Sharon Zheng | LAW 108C | Spring 2012| Donald Galloway CASE FACTS DECISION Athey v. Appellant suffered BUT FOR TEST Leonati back injuries in 2 A factor is a cause of a result of the result would successive motor SCC 1996 not have happened but for that factor vehicle accidents, o AKA that factor is a cause if it is a necessary went to the gym after, and then pre-condition Tortious acts: car accidents – caused back injury experienced disc (causation established) herniation o But for can still be used for multiple wrongdoers Non-tortious act: stretching exercises – worsened back injury BOTH contribute to the harm HELD: but for the tortious acts, there wouldn’t be the harm. Causation found, liability BUT there can be more than one cause – the negligence doesn’t have to be the SOLE cause of the injury! As long as the D is part of the cause, then the D is liable, even though his act alone was not enough to create the injury Although held contributorily ISSUE: the BUT FOR TEST is sometimes unworkable (Athey) WHAT DOES “NOT WORKABLE MEAN? o 1) a test that points in the wrong direction (ie we know the right answer but the test doesn’t provide it – and therefore there’s a way to get to the right answer) OR o 2) a test that doesn’t provide an answer OR o 3) a test that provides an unfair answer (not that the answer is wrong – but we don’t like it because it’s unfair)? SITUATIONS IN WHICH CAUSATION IS TRICKY o Ordinarily we attribute causality in circumstances where the event would still have happened. Examples: 1) Three people independently pull ropes that open a floodgate. Only two Sharon Zheng | LAW 108C | Spring 2012| Donald Galloway were needed 2) Two people shoot a victim through the heart at the same time 3) I dig a hole that you fall into; if I hadn’t dug it someone else would have dug it and you would still have fallen in (pre-emption) o 1) and 2) are examples of “over-determination” where >1 factor contributes Belt + suspenders In the first case, the extra person eases the effort of the other people, but is otherwise redundant o 3) is one where the defendant’s act pre-empts the operation of another element If no belt, then suspenders PROBLEM 1 OF THE BFT: it can extend to an indeterminate number of things! o It’s excessively inclusive: the gunman who shot the victim is a cause, the person who sold the gunman the gun, the person who made the gun, the parents of the person who made the gun … (at the end of Athey) o SOLUTION: 1. When we use the but for test, we don’t use it in the ordinary sense of the words We distinguish between background factors (taken as given) and causes Causes are unusual interventions that operate against the background, that help to explain the occurrence of an event or the non-occurrence of an event that should have happened 2. In tort we differentiate between factual cause and proximate cause (in crim, legal cause) FIRST we look at factual cause: is there a causation? THEN we look at proximate cause. Proximate cause is more normative and value laden … given the factual cause, is it fair to hold proximate cause? PROBLEM 2 OF THE BFT: there may be several chains of causation! o Courts have been seduced by the metaphor of a “chain” of causation o Each link is a necessary precondition - if you remove a link you break the chain o If you reject the metaphor, you reject the reason for the BFT o ISSUES: what if your chain is not linear? What if you have several chains feeding into the main one – if you break one chain, it would still happen Sharon Zheng | LAW 108C | Spring 2012| Donald Galloway PROBLEM 3 OF THE BFT: (the first major problem) o It is a test of INCLUSION Yes - if the BFT is met, the factor is a cause o It is NOT a test of EXCLUSION Just because a factor FAILS the BFT doesn’t mean it isn’t a cause! o That is to say: it does not allow us to determine when the factor is not a cause (it can give rise to false negatives) o For THIS REASON, it is sometimes not workable! Note on MATERIAL CONTRIBUTION o Law saying we need to supplement the inclusive part of the BFT with the MC test o Supplementing the BFT with a MC test does address cases where we would commonly identify causality, but it doesn’t address the pre-emption case unless we say that in that case the factor is MATERIALLY CONTRIBUTING Just because if I didn’t do it someone else would – does that attribute material contribution? o But if that is the case why don’t we just dispense with the BFT? ISSUE: o Material contribution SOUNDS like a great supplemental test because we use it in ordinary life o We use the word CONTRIBUTE rather than CAUSE to indicate that many factors were operational o But what stops the MC test from SUPPLANTING the BFT? Then we’re just supplementing a problematic test with another problematic test. According to Athey there are always multiple factors (the fire is caused by the match, O2, waste paper) so every case is a case of contribution o The BUT FOR TEST tells us that a cause is a necessary precondition (a synonym), AS WELL AS a method for defining when something contributes o The MATERIALLY CONTRIBUTION test provides a synonym, BUT does not show us when something is contributing or not o The idea of material contribution fits best where we take background conditions as given and have two interventions that combine to bring about a result: Ex: where 10 drops of poison kill, A gives one drop and B independently gives 9 drops. A has materially contributed to the death Same where A gives a drop to someone who has already taken 10 drops but is not yet dead (they’re gonna die anyways, but you give one more Sharon Zheng | LAW 108C | Spring 2012| Donald Galloway for luck – adding to the mess) Is A responsible? Factually, we accept they’ve contributed (requirement 1) Once we introduce material contribution as a test, it threatens to supplant the BFT rather than supplement it o So why does the SCC hold onto the BUT FOR test at the primary test? o Every BF factor is a contributing factor, some contributing factors that will count as causes are not BF factors o If all count as causes then we have a contribution test of causality rather than a BFT In fact, BFT is a factor which we can use to help us determine if something is MC o But once we use the MC test to supplement the BFT, then the BFT is no longer the test, the MC test is o What we really want is a valuation of the extent of something’s cause It’s a FAIRNESS test then, not a factual test Snell v. Respondent INFERENCE OF CAUSATION Farrell consented to have Tortious act: Dr a cataract Non-tortious act: stroke? Diabetes? surgically removed. Causation was not proven – do not know that but for SCC 1990 Surgery was performed negligently (Dr should have the Dr’s negligence the plaintiff would not be blind P: we should move away from the but for test! o McGhee realized bleeding and stopped) – shower lead to blindness in right eye due Brick kiln worker, had to cycle home to Contracts dermatitis, argues Coal Board responsible for not providing showers Coal Board: showers don’t remove every to atrophied optic grain of dust – you even if we had nerve but unsure supplied a shower we don’t know if you whether it was would’ve gotten dermatitis anyways! the surgery, a stroke (due to diabetes) or glaucoma SOLUTION 1 – reverse the onus (Wilberforce) SOLUTION 2 – material contribution is material increase (Lord Reid) – P just has to show material increase! ISSUE: material increase in risk and Sharon Zheng | LAW 108C | Spring 2012| Donald Galloway material contribution are collapsed into one here and they’re not the same! Only the later changes the state of the world! SOLUTION 3 – cook v. lewis: both plaintiffs equally liable, onus reversed In this case, one neg and one non neg cause! There P hasn’t established they’re a victim of tort! Cannot reverse onus Spokina does not accept any of these – if we did insurance for Drs would go through the roof SOLUTION: All the knowledge is with the defendant (Dr) therefore inf of causation If you’ve established there’s a tortious and nontortious cause but don’t know which one caused the harm – assume Dr is liable, and Dr can show evidence to rebut Note: “not shifting the burden”, and keeping the “robust and pragmatic approach” to causation using the but for test Galloway: this “non shift” is problematic – what if D doesn’t have extra info? Does this only apply to Drs? Why are we focussing on the integrity of evid? Cook v. Lewis ALTERNATIVE LIABILITY THEORY (SUBSET OF MATERIAL CONTRIBUTION) Two tortious act SCC 1951 Only one act causes the harm (two bullets, one bullet hole) but it’s not know which one caused the harm Since they’re both tortious, they should sort it out among themselves: presumption that both are liable, onus of proof shifts to wrongdoer to show each is not the sole wrongdoer Sharon Zheng | LAW 108C | Spring 2012| Donald Galloway HELD: Liability was split! Liability BM v. RCMP at Prince MATERIALLY CONTRIBUTION TEST BCAG George failed to DISS (Donald) – it’s time for change! investigate o Found duty, breach and causation BCCA complaint of o This case is like McGhee 2004 domestic violence o Just and fairness: RCMP should’ve investigated (reoccurring and didn’t (policy reasons – right to police incidents in which protection high) RCMP were o P: if I am unable to show causation and am not involved, F was compensated, there’s something wrong with the forgiving of M) – legal system! Donald agrees 7 weeks later he o If material contribution above de minimis range, shot his. M shoots friend and then it’s a cause o 4 part Haag formulation re: when we should daughter, kills apply a relaxed notion of causation: friend. M suing 1. Where a breach of duty has occurred, RCMP 2. The damage has arisen within the area of risk which brought the duty into being 3. The breach of duty materially increased the risk that damage of that type would occur (contentious) 4. It’s impossible, in a practical sense, for either party to lead evidence which would establish either that the breach of duty caused the loss or that it did not o All we know here is that police intervention = effective deterrent, and that there was a breach of a duty in this case (tortious cause) MAJ o HELD: No causation – no evidence that RCMP intervention would have lead to a different outcome, there were already disincentives in place Walker HIV + man, not asked HIV screening question ISSUE (Major): o Breach of duty – did the RC ask enough Qs in screening people? Sharon Zheng | LAW 108C | Spring 2012| Donald Galloway (Canadian Red o Causation – if the individual had been given the Cross Society proper warning would he have gone ahead and failed its duty to donated? implement Finds BFT unworkable (seems to have adequate donor overdetermination in mind) because multiple screening measures independent factors are contributing – but (Athey) ex. pamphlets), there are ALWAYS multiple causes! Multiple causes donates tainted creating independent series of events adding together blood. is what overdetermination is really about So this us a fairness issue! 3rd type of unworkability! The question is – was the failure a sufficient condition. Is this the right Q?! o Galloway: NO! Sufficiency is the wrong notion to introduce – you really don’t know what the donor would’ve done Major finds: we use MC when but for doesn’t work – but for doesn’t work in situations like this where you can’t be sure – and yet Major concludes the but for test works!! Claims to adopt Snell reasoning?! Nonsensical … HELD: CRCS/ hospital liable Resurfice Hanke placed v. Hanke water hose into for test (even for multiple wrongdoers), material gasoline tank of ice contribution is only for cases when it’s impossible for SCC resurfacing machine the P to prove that the D’s negligence cause the 2007 rather than water injury using but for tank. Hot water overfilled gas tank, vaporize gas, Whatever Donald J said, prima facie we use the but Causation is showing breach of duty exposed plaintiff to suffer that form of injury The SCC ends up saying the same thing as Donald J released into air, (the 4 factors as being a situation when MC is ignited by appropriate) –they characterize it broadly but then overhead heater, read it as leading to a NARROW number of cases causing explosion that apply! and fire. Breach of duty due to mislabelling of the 2 situations in which MC is appropriate: o Cook v. Lewis type = MC instead of causality ISSUE – this is actually an onus reversal, Sharon Zheng | LAW 108C | Spring 2012| Donald Galloway tank – caused a burn. not MC at all! o Impossible to prove what a person in the causal chain would have done had the D not committed the negligent act (Walker type) ISSUE – Walker is incoherent! (Galloway) And just because you fail at but for doesn’t mean you can move onto MC! But for causation is appropriate in this case HELD: no but for causation, no liability Clements Joan severely v. injured while riding Clements as passenger on motorcycle driven Issue; would the accident still have happened if the D had been careful about weight and speed? Mr. Clement liable for all 5 factors except #3 (tire puncture) BCCA201 by husband – 1) 0 overloaded, 2) determining factual causation – rather it provides a pulled out to pass basis for finding legal causation when there’s a another vehicle possibility that the D’s negligence could have been the (speeding), 3) hit factual cause a sharp object and Material contribution test is not a test for Therefore use of MC is not a test of causation – it’s punctured rear a policy-driven rule of law to allow P to recover in tire, 4) unevenly cases despite their failure to prove causation loaded 5) excess BCCA: no – if MC applies every time but for fails, speed considering then but for isn’t even a rule! If you fail but for it weather (pouring means you fail causation – not than you can move rain). Mr. onto MC Clements Felt it 2 situations in which MC is appropriate: weave, unable to o Circular causation: Cook v. Lewis regain control, o Dependency causation: Walker flipped over This is just a case where we don’t know and it’s not causing serious unfair to left the D off the hook – BFT should injury. operate! Are we convinced? Are we just turning causation into a fairness test? HELD: applies but for causation - no causation, no liability o Hypothetically: o P: but for the overloading/speeding in the rain Sharon Zheng | LAW 108C | Spring 2012| Donald Galloway etc. (4 factors that were Joe’s fault) the accident would not have happened, therefore Joe’s at fault o D: no – we don’t know that but for those things the accident would know have happened because there’s still the issue of the rock! Even without those things the rock could still have caused it – so we can’t prove that Joe caused it o P: FINE, MC, so Joe’s at fault Just because but for doesn’t produce the wanted result (you fail on it) doesn’t mean you can ditch it - it means you've failed causation! Can’t move onto MC! o Need to decide whether or not to apply but for FIRST and THEN apply if. If it shows no causation, then that’s the end! Tort is only where lack of care causes harm – there must be FAULT and we don’t ascribed fault unless we can prove causation on but for What should the decision of Clements say? FIRST PRINCIPLE If plaintiff can show that the BFT is met on the balance of probabilities, then P has proved causation Therefore the BFT is a strategic device that P can use to meet the burden of proof but there are other ways to meet it as well But if P cannot, P can turn to other strategies! Failing to meet BFT doesn’t necessarily show that the P fails. SECOND PRINCIPLE: Cook v. Lewis If P can show that he was the victim of a negligent act but there were more than one negligent actors that might have done it, P can rely on a reverse onus. Each of the negligent actors is deemed the cause unless they can show on the balance of probabilities that they were not Ex. Each defendant trying to find THEIR bullet is somewhere else, to prove their actions are uninvolved ISSUE: does this apply to more than 2 wrongdoers? We don’t know. Sharon Zheng | LAW 108C | Spring 2012| Donald Galloway This is about FAIRNESS of BURDEN OF PROOF, not causality THIRD PRINCIPLE: overdetermination Two independent series of events may combine or come together 2 independent shots hit the mark Although redundant, a factor may sometimes be cited as a cause A full explanation would note the combine operation of two independent factors ISSUE: can this also be applied to reasons? 1. If you give someone an incentive to do something that they probably would have done anyways you still contribute to their decision (you “seal the deal”) o Although some things count as incentive, though, and others don’t 2. Likewise if you fail to provide a disincentive, you contribute to the decision (reversing the first point) o This move would allow us to explain Donald J in B.M. and maybe even Walker o Donald (BM) and Major (Walker): in B.M. – if the police are under a duty to change the assailant’s reasoning, it doesn’t matter what the assailant would have done! The negligence is so big that by doing nothing, they’ve contributed to that person’s decision EVEN IF the assailant has made their mind up o BM Majority judge: the assailant had his mind made up! He already had disincentives in place! And they didn’t stop him, so the police couldn’t have stopped him! Galloway’s hypothesis: PART ONE Plaintiff must provide an explanation of how we got from past to present The plaintiff will cite factors and must show that there are serious reasons for believing these factors played a role o Galloway: We usually talk about proof and a bop – but really we have a flexible notion of proof operation here o Plaintiff, we will allow you to succeed if there are serious reasons for believing any of the elements they played a role in the result o Therefore in the case of causation, we’re asking for less than a balance of probabilities. We’re asking for a serious belief Ex. If you failed an exam but there was an ear splitting whistle in the exam room at the time Sharon Zheng | LAW 108C | Spring 2012| Donald Galloway o Would I have to prove that this jeopardized my performance on a bop? o Or would you say that I was a terrible student and would’ve failed anyways? o Despite the fact that I may have failed anyways, we’re not going to ask if I had done better without the whistle. We ask if there’s a serious reason for believing the whistle would affect my exam results If the plaintiff will succeed unless the defendant can show (on a bop) that the factor didn’t play a role o If there are serious reasons for believing the factor played a role, then the plaintiff will succeed o The defendant’s job is to say that their behavior didn’t play a role! Merely showing that it probably would still have happened is not enough for the D to succeed o Saying “on a balance of probabilities it would have happened anyways” is not sufficient Summary What we have done is reduce the plaintiff’s onus: if P can show that there are serious reasons for believing that a factor played a role then it is a cause unless D can show otherwise Saying “I have a serious reason for believing the Dr’s negligence did it” will be enough for the plaintiff. So the Doctor in Snell would be liable unless he can show that negligence was unrelated or trivially related to physical deterioration. Plaintiff met the burden of proof in this case! The police are liable in B.M. unless they can show that their failure played a trivial role Clements: P has a responsibility to show there are serious reasons the factors played a role P cites factors: overloading and speed P now has a good explanation for what happened – there are serious reasons to believe that these elements has a bearing on the outcome because these factors tent to produce accidents like this one Now to the D Evidence from the defendant that there is no bearing of the overloading and speed on the crash, that they played no role That they did not in the circumstances make it more difficult to control the Sharon Zheng | LAW 108C | Spring 2012| Donald Galloway bike Because they had an effect on the chain of events leading to the difficulty in controlling the bike Evidence from the D that the accident would have happened anyway is not enough to defeat the claim! Therefore, we’re dealing with FAIRNESS, RISK ALLOCATION, and using language that meets our intuition. It’s not about reversing the onus or proof or using 2 tests. It’s just about REDUCING the burden of proof and seeing what happens … Material contribution test is only really at home in the over determination cases Instead of asking “would dermatitis have happened even if they had the shower?” under material contribution, ask “is there a serious reason for believing that not having a shower is related to dermatitis?” and then the defendant’s responsibility to prove otherwise, under the reduced onus version of the causality test USUALLY: subjective test DRs: standards are much higher, personalized, therefore policy reasons to use modified objective MANUFACTURER OF MEDICAL GOODS: information imbalance, Reibl v. Underwent serious Hughes surgery, suffered a massive stroke, SCC 1980 Duty of Drs: to warn of all material risks (via BC Health Care Consent Act) 1. Severity – found that the o Objective ex. death and plaintiff did not o Subjective standard ex. scarring (ex. Videto), if have informed the Dr is made aware consent because he 2. Likelihood wasn’t warned. After Dr found to have breached failure to warn of a Suing for damages procedure, issue is whether, if informed of all of the in battery and risks, if they would have gone through with the negligence. Pension treatment anyways would vest in 1.5 years. Instead of normal causation: modified objective based on all the circumstances (reasonable person in all the circumstances of the accused), including gender, age, beliefs etc. – a reasonable patient in that decision, of but for test No one in hind sight would say they would have had a Sharon Zheng | LAW 108C | Spring 2012| Donald Galloway procedure that went so badly 10% chance poor outcome HELD: reasonable person would’ve opted against the surgery, liability Note: if there’s no causation of harm, there’s no negligence – so if nothing bad happened to you but your Dr failed in his duty to warn, still no neg The court is telling us there’s an objective test of causation for medical cases and that this is coherent with the current test of causation. HOW DO RE RECONCILE THIS? o SOLUTION 1: the but for test itself is bad – because the objective test is NOT even a test of causation! It’s actually an argument about fairness. Because it’s not fair to hold a Dr liable in certain situations Ex. if the reasonable person would have gone through the operation This isn’t about the world anymore, it’s about what’s fair etc. o This allows us to distinguish this case from Hollis, in which case you aren’t dealing with Drs! When the manufacturer of a product fails to warn the consumer, we use the normal subjective test – would this person have taken the product if she had been warned? Therefore, this is not an issue of causality between what happens, it’s actually about a favouritism towards Drs that doesn’t apply to manufacturers ISSUE: In this case, there are situations in which plaintiff can show causality, and yet the plaintiff is losing. Is this saying that the but for test isn’t working for plaintiffs anymore? o SOLUTION 2: The test is good! We are really using the subjective test in both! The problem with the but for test in Reibl v. Hughes though is not the BFT itself – it’s that the subjective test is not the way to go Relying on the plaintiffs evidence of what would have happened had they been given the information is unreliable The best we can rely on is what the reasonable person would have done, to replace what you would have done This means we don’t have to change the test of causation or have two different test (one in the manufacturing cases, one in the doctor’s cases) We have ONE SUBJECTIVE TEST – what would this person have done? It’s just supplemented by a rule of evidence – can’t reply on plaintiff’s Sharon Zheng | LAW 108C | Spring 2012| Donald Galloway words so go to what a reasonable person would’ve done Therefore Laskin: maintaining the subjective test, but just changing rules of evidence ISSUE: the concerns of a plaintiff must be reasonable based Galloway: you don’t want the objective test because of bitterness and hindsight – that’s the only evidence you want to exclude. This has nothing to do with the reasonableness of a plaintiff’s concerns. The idea of autonomy means you can decide the weight of your fears yourself. Therefore Laskin overstepped and went too far. Galloway: if you were really consistent though, you should be avoiding the bitter hindsight evidence in Hollis as well Hollis v. Plaintiff isn’t Dow informed of the Hollis would’ve elected otherwise, 2 – whether Dr. Corning risk of breast Birch would’ve warned Hollis had they known) is found implants. Implant to be irrelevant SCC 1995 rupture, causing harm The fact that there are two factors (1 – whether Poor policy to allows manufacturers who breach their duty to escape causation by questioning what the Dr would have done The ultimate duty of manufacture is to warn the plaintiff adequately – for practical reasons the law permits it to acquit itself that duty by warning an informed intermediary. Having failed to warn the intermediary, the manufacturer has failed in its duty to warn the plaintiff who ultimately suffered injury Perhaps: learned intermediary is already the courts going halfway, so really unforgiving when the manufacturers fail to come back the other half! HELD: causation found on the but for test, manufacturer liable for failing to disclose the dangers to the P ISSUE 1: Arndt v. Smith (2 years later in 1997) o Dissent (CJMac) – you can’t have different tests for doctors and manufacturers! The subjective test should be used in all cases o This shows how unsure this area of law is Sharon Zheng | LAW 108C | Spring 2012| Donald Galloway ISSUE 2: the causation test in the learned intermediary rule o Court abandons any notion of causality in this issue o An argument by the manufacturer (when it fails to inform doctors) that even if they had passed onto the information onto a Dr the Dr wouldn’t have passed it on will not stand Court: if manufacturers are going to make it easier for themselves by using a learned intermediary, then they cannot rely on the normal rules of causation! “The ultimate duty of the manufacturer is to warn the plaintiff adequately … having failed to warn the intermediary, the manufacturer has failed in its duty to warn the plaintiff who ultimately suffers …” Brito v. Plaintiff vaginally Professional women, (therefore had respect for other Woolley delivers twins, professionals?), had 2 children vaginally previously with second twin’s cord no complications BCJ prolapses causing 2003 severe mental advice and the lower likelihood of risk, rather disability to the than the emotional response she claims after child. Plaintiff claims that the doctors failed to present her with the material risk o Suggests that she would have followed the Dr’s o Received medical advice from more than one Dr who concurred <1% poor outcome (although dire consequence, so material risk) HELD: no causation – would have opted for a vaginal of prolapse and delivery even if she had been informed of the risk, and present her with a reasonable Fr would have recommended vaginal the option of delivery, no liability having a caesarean section ISSUE: just because a doctor recommends something doesn’t mean it would be unreasonable to not follow those directions: Laskin is very wary of this Sharon Zheng | LAW 108C | Spring 2012| Donald Galloway Donald in this case though, holds to the idea that if a doctor recommends something the plaintiff (and a reasonable person, a “loving mother”) would have always followed the doctor’s recommendation regardless of what kinds of warnings/ information was given o This is exactly of the antithesis of Laskin’s judgement! o Laskin wanted to allow patients to reject doctors and make up their own minds! o Galloway: goodbye autonomy? Can only win legal action if you follow doctor’s recommendations? This is the issue with the objective test! o Laskin’s method of using the subjective test but excluding certain information is much better Martin Martin needed surgery, but not Duty of Drs: to inform of all material risks in a manner that the patient would understand ABQC immediately. Dr Dr knew that Martin was looking forward 2007 warned of bleeding In this case, high risk of harm, disclosed, but not in the brain, but disclosed adequately – used language that was too not sufficiently medical (‘bleeding in the brain’ not ‘stroke’) using the proper language. He made it clear to the Dr P: you owe me damages for the rest of my life for this surgery: care, remodelling of the home etc o The surgery would have occurred later, and at he was looking the later surgery date, there would still be the forward to his same chance of the harm occurring! retirement and dancing with his daughter at her o Causation test is the mixed subjective/ objective but for o Therefore if something’s going to happen wedding. P claims anyway, you’re only responsible for the amount if he had been you sped it up (crumbling skull) warned, he would’ve had the surgery after his daughter’s D: no – we only owe the addition costs in between the two dates COURT: because we don’t know what would have happened at the surgery on the later date (unwilling Sharon Zheng | LAW 108C | Spring 2012| Donald Galloway wedding. to predict), they awarded the entire period (whole life!). Rejects the crumbling skull type analysis HELD: but for causation, liability ISSUE: how can you hold THIS Dr liable if the next Dr would have done the exact same thing?! Chester v. Woman goes to Deprivation of choice held sufficient for liability! Afsher (H doctor for medical Although not followed in Canada (Galloway – this case of L) treatment. Not explained by doctor the possibility of nerve is shocking) But for test is met by plaintiff, but still not going to find causality! HELD: the but for test is easily satisfied … but the damage, and she doctor isn’t going to be liable because the doctor’s suffers nerve duty to warn didn’t cause the injury. The risk was damage. Plaintiff the same irrespective of when or at whose hands she is a witness who is had the operation absolutely honest, Galloway: this is revolutionary! It’s not who caused and says she the injury – it’s whether the doctor’s breach of duty doesn’t know if INCREASED the risk of injury! We should only hold she would have the Dr liable when we say yes. Since the plaintiff had the operation could have had the operation later and would have – BUT she says been subject to the same risk then, we shouldn’t hold she knows that the Dr liable for ANYTHING she wouldn’t have US and UK trying to put less weight on causality and at the operation willing to recognize lost opportunity/ chances, since then the traditional tort rules don’t always lead to fair results Canada is really resistant to this! o In personal injury the question is who caused the injury, NOT who increased the risks! In Canada, can you sue the doctor who took the opportunity to decrease the risk of cancer? No! That’s not enough! There has to be harm! Sharon Zheng | LAW 108C | Spring 2012| Donald Galloway Sindell v. Generic drug on Abbott the market, for US pregnant women Normal solution would say that plaintiffs would not meet their case Issue is vast majority of plaintiffs unable to identify to prevent 12 years later the specific company which morning sicknesses. manufactured the pills 12 years later, Solution: should hold each company liable for the finds that the proportion of the injury that reflects their market drug causes share (how much of the drug they marketed during a increase in risk to particular period) cancer to o This means we don’t expect the plaintiff to tie daughters the harm they’ve suffered to a specific wrongdoing – we treat the companies as risk creators o Instead of joint and several liability for the whole harm, we divide the harm and allocate responsibility by market share This is a rethinking of the tort law of negligence! It’s all about holding people liable for losses suffered UK: References the Barker v. Fairchild case: Corus Suffering from House of Lords: Both should be liable. In reaching this decision, there are 6 factors (pg 126) o Doesn’t say why these 6 factors count (court asbestos related hasn’t figured it out) disease o When you satisfy all these factors, there will be Working at two workplaces over the time where it could be contracted – and evidence suggests no other source. Two negligent activities, happening one after the other (not liability Sharon Zheng | LAW 108C | Spring 2012| Donald Galloway contemporaneously ) but either one or both brought it about even though we don’t know which Hypotheticals o 1st employer has asbestos, but there’s no reason at that time for the employer to worry about asbestos because there’s no evidence of its harm o Employee might’ve contracted disease from first employer, but they weren’t negligent o Would the negligent party have to pay for anything?? House of Lords rethinking Fairchild case in Barker v. Corus It’s not just a Cook v. Lewis issue with 2 negligent parties – going back to McGee o Pg. 128: HOL – materially increasing the risk is not the same as materially contributing!! Unlike the SCC who made this mistake, we are avoiding it! o The employers have materially increased the risk of contracting mesothelioma so we should hold each liable to the degree they contributed to the illness – therefore liability is not for the harm but for the increasing of the risk o What if the plaintiff also worked with asbestos at home? HOL recognizing it’s still possible to apportion the risk based on the increase of risk by other parties Therefore severally liable only UK leg didn’t like this solution so wrote a statute o Worried about the impact on the economy, since lots of mesothelioma cases o Compensation Act (2006) – returning to the familiar situation If you’re pointing the finger, it must be done in relation to causing the harm, not increasing the risk So you have to go after each If there’s more than one, defendants can be jointly and severally liable Contributory negligence won’t necessarily deny liability, but just decreases the amount that will be paid Sharon Zheng | LAW 108C | Spring 2012| Donald Galloway In BC, Workers Compensation schemes would deal with this o Is this the best way to deal with this? o Only 40% make workers comp claims – therefore something is preventing people from seeking insurance redress. Why? Knowledge isn’t filtering to individuals This still raises causality problems - what’s the fairest way to solve a causality problem? Don’t know. REMOTENESS There’s been a breach of duty, a causal link, but D is saying “I shouldn’t be liable for THIS” Wagon Another ship in Mound 1 the harbour releasing bunker oil in the water – Re Polemis o 2 stevedores working on a boat unloading planks of wood o Drop a plank into hold of the ship, hits bottom this was negligent of boat, spark is caused, burned down ship because it’s mucky o Defendant: okay – we caused the loss of the to clean (but no boat but we shouldn’t be held liable because it’s one recognized it so bizarre and unforeseeable was flammable). In o Court: you’re liable! For all the consequences Vaughan v. that directly fall from your negligence – Menlove – whether or not they’re reasonably foreseeable haystacks are recognizably easy to light on fire, Initially we saw battery to be direct and negligence to be indirect Yet here, they want to say you’re but not bunker negligent for everything you directly oil. On docks, cause! people are welding. Molten metal gets on wood, a piece For it to be indirect, there has to be some element of intervention Cameron v. Hamilton Auction Mart (Scotland) of cotton on top o Excited cow that went up the stairs into a of that, bunk oil house, fell through floor, in its struggles, reaches this and a turned on a water tap, flooding the unit, cow Sharon Zheng | LAW 108C | Spring 2012| Donald Galloway fire’s created, and thrashing lost property the dock burns o Issue: too remote? Yes! down o Court: you can’t hold people liable for unforeseeable consequences just because they’re direct! Court: over-ruled Polemis. HELD: you should be liable for consequences that you should have foreseen as a reasonable man! Following Cameron v. Hamilton o Responsible only for the reasonably foreseeable consequences of one’s acts, and it was not reasonably foreseeable that dumping durance oil on water would cause conflagration This case is less bizarre, but the same conclusion being released PC: we use reasonable foreseeability – we hold you liable for only the probable consequences of your acts o ISSUE - Duty of care: you owe a duty to someone if it’s reasonably foreseeable you’ll harm them o For what harms are you liable? You’re only liable for reasonably foreseeable harms, in terms of probability o So we’re using the same standard for duty of care and remoteness! o Hughes v. Post office Modified Wagon Mound Lord employees left COURT: You’ve created an allurement – we don’t Adcovate manhole open, so expect children to listen to their parents, we expect put lamps and a them to explore what you’ve created! tent around the hole. Kids find it alluring and explore Def: this is like wagonmound! Too improbable to foresee that explosion would result! HOL: no – this is within proximity, not too remote it. Kids climb o Relaxing the standard down, climb back o Burns were reasonably foreseeable, these kids up, knock lamp suffered burns. They’re worse burns than into hole, there’s would’ve been foreseeable due to this strange Sharon Zheng | LAW 108C | Spring 2012| Donald Galloway a gas leak unfolding – but that’s not relevant! (unbeknown to o Why not? Being able to foresee the precise way anyone) and it the world unfolds is too hard – BUT if the explodes causing eventual consequence (last chain) is generally injury foreseeable, then we should hold the defendant liable Lord Reid p143: I agree that we shouldn’t be too sensitive about how things unfold, BUT there could be a case where the intrusion of a new and unexpected factor could be considered the cause of the accident instead of the act of the defendant o But that’s not the case here. The fact that there were kids is not a new factor – it’s a normal concatenation of circumstances o OKAY so what would count as a new factor? Lord Reid is thinking about the excited cow case! The damage caused is the same sort of damage as if the cow just barged into a place. But in that case the circumstances got so bizarre that liability wouldn’t apply What’s the difference between this situation and the cow story? It’s the difference between tragedy and farce – that some things are so strange that they are out of the world of drama and into the world of comedy Galloway: a reluctance to use foreseeability to describe the actual chain of events, and looking more towards the foreseeability of result! In the ensuing years, the compatibility of Hughes and Wagon Mound I has been questioned. Assibinoin Dad rigs up Held: not too remote! e snowmobile for kid Dickson J: Polemis, Wagon Mound I, Hughes, Wagon to be able to start, but it can’t Mound II (not the cow case) o Claims the force of WMI has been dissipated by Sharon Zheng | LAW 108C | Spring 2012| Donald Galloway stop. Kid loses Hughes (which is more plaintiff friendly) – control of the minor modification changing the emphasis snowmobile, it hits (although not overruling) the gas pipe of a o WMI says that if the unusual happens, then school, which that’s a categorical difference v. Hughes in floats up into an which we don’t recognize a categorical difference intake vent and o Don’t need to foresee the precise concatenation lights the school o Foreseeability doesn’t go to probabilities, it goes on fire to possibilities Wagon Mound II (1966) o Plaintiff was another ship that burned down o What happened between 1961 (WMI) and 1966? 1961: if plaintiff was contributorily negligence, def would get off the hook completely In 1961 (WMI), that plaintiff argued Polemis – you’re liable for direct responses, plaintiff trying to underplay their own contributory negligence and trying to downplay the negligence of the bunker oil release In 1966, this plaintiff was innocent, so claiming it’s negligent to release bunker oil! Evidence was therefore very different o Lord Reid: replay of Bolton and Stone! Very different than WMI! The reasonable person would concede that discharging the oil is a bad idea primarily because it adheres to the dock, but secondarily because it would go on fire Therefore even if it isn’t probable or foreseeable, it’s a possibility that a reasonable person would cite it as a reason for not discharging the oil Sharon Zheng | LAW 108C | Spring 2012| Donald Galloway Therefore it counts as a reason not to do it! In the cow case, a reasonable person wouldn’t cite the flooding as a reason for not caring for the cows o Plaintiff friendly! Pltf only needs a reasonable possibility to win a case This is the test accepted by Hoffer: it is enough to fix liability if one could foresee in a general way the sort of thing that happened o WMII is the high water mark SCC: action can be successful if this is not impossible to expect. You lose liability only with the bizarre and far fetched Conclusion: recovery may be available provided the event giving rise to the damage is not regarded as “impossible” o When you rig up a snowmobile like this, this result is NOT bizarre and far-fetched! o It is enough to fix liability if one could foresee in a general way the sort of thing that happened The idea seems to be that if a reasonable person with his/her understanding of the circumstances would cite the consequence as a reason for not doing the act the defendant can be held liable But is the consequence to be understood as the type of harm, the way in which the harm occurred, or the story of the events? Lauritzen Two Albertans Held: not too remote – held liable driving from pub Although the wife’s departure is seen as too remote. to pub, getting This reveals that remoteness can be raised at two severely drunk, one junctures interferes with o First, at the stage of determining liability and the driver, driver o Second, at the stage of assessing damages objects, causing car Lauritzen hypothetical Sharon Zheng | LAW 108C | Spring 2012| Donald Galloway to go off road, o Lets say driver walks out in the blizzard, walks lands in ditch in into refrigeration truck, truck driver locks up middle of nowhere drives off and driver gets frostbite! in winter. Driver o Because frostbite is in the realm of possible gets out to try circumstances (the final event is foreseeable), it and go for help, seems that the SCC would say that it doesn’t gets frostbite, matter how it happened wife leaves him. o Galloway: but that’s not the law Maybe the final event is foreseeable but the concatenation of events is so bizarre that you’re not in the world of reasonableness So what are we applying foreseeability to? 1. The eventual consequence; AND 2. The concatenation of events!! Pulling it all together 1. In some cases, the courts regard the defendant as acting against a set of stable circumstances. Where the defendant’s act produces a highly unusual type of harm because one of the pre-existing circumstances was unusual, the courts may see it as too remote and deny liability. (Dropping a plank - ship explodes) (Re Polemis) 2. On the other hand, if the harm is of the same type as could be reasonably expected, the court will be disinclined to deny liability. (Hughes: explosion and burns) 3. Where the defendant’s act modifies the pre-existing circumstances in a highly unusual way, the courts will be disinclined to deny liability. (You don’t have to foresee the precise concatenation of events) (Assiniboine, Lauritzen) 4. Only if the final result is farfetched or bizarre will the court find remoteness (Assiniboine, Lauritze ) Since 1961, courts trying to use the reasonably foreseeable standard for remoteness o But do you apply it to the result or chain of events? The former. THE THIN SKULL RULE • Where you have breached a duty to someone and caused physical harm, you take your victim as you find them • Where the victim’s unusual pre-existing condition produces results that are more serious than you would ordinarily expect, you are still liable for the full extent of the Sharon Zheng | LAW 108C | Spring 2012| Donald Galloway injury • This goes beyond Hughes, since it suggests that an injury of a different type would also be covered! Questions • Why do we have this rule? • The general rule is not that you take pre-existing circumstances as you find them. • Does it have something to do with the idea that it is your duty to treat all individuals as unique? • It’s problematic to think that you hold someone accountable only for harms a reasonable person would suffer • Treating people as autonomous agents means treating them as people – we’re all special! The law does not want to work to deny the uniqueness of individuals and individuals’ bodies • Bodies are unlike houses • It’s something that defines us • The normal rule might create an incentive to treat others as means rather than ends • Does it apply beyond the body to the mind? • • Does it apply to the “thin personality” rule? • Not really. Because fortitude is something you’re responsible for • If your body defines you, surely your personality defines you! Consider a person with a pre-disposition to anxiety or depression who may become severely anxious or depressed after being exposed to danger (return to this) • Consider also the person who for religious reasons does not treat an injury negligently caused by D and it becomes worse (see interventions) • • If your personality defines you, surely your religious beliefs define you! Would it also apply in a case where a person committed suicide? What if you’re negligent to someone, they suffer harm and they commit suicide – are you liable? (see interventions). Bishop Man is expecting Thin skull applies resistance from One would in most circumstances expect (at most) a opening door, there is none, he falls through. Sues for negligent failure to warn simple fracture and an uneventful recovery Here “the congenital condition becomes grossly exaggerated by trauma of any sort” o This isn’t a more serious injury of the same sort, it’s the bringing of distinct consequences Sharon Zheng | LAW 108C | Spring 2012| Donald Galloway against the door. that fall within the realm of liability! Serious injury Athey v. Appellant suffered Crumbling skull doctrine: although D is held liable for Leonati back injuries in 2 the injury that is precipitated by the pre-existing successive motor condition, the level of compensation should discount vehicle accidents, any losses that would be suffered without D’s went to the gym intervention after, and then experienced disc herniation INTERVENING ACT Stansbie Painter in the v. Troman house, doesn’t lock it. Burglar goes in and robs it. Offers one clear situation: if you undertake to protect a person from a third party intervention but are negligent you may be liable for the result o The issue at tort is not the intervention of the third party o It’s that the relationship that gives rise to any tort liability at all is the undertaking to prevent certain results from happening Held: liable Ex. why do you have locks in the house? To keep burglars out, vandals out o What about the person who goes into the house and burns it down? This is strange - you could’ve set the fire outside o Is the defendant liable for that? Unsure o There are some crimes are so bizarre that even the person who has undertaken to look after your interests is not held liable Therefore just because a third party has intervened, doesn’t mean the original wrongdoer won’t be held liable The negligent body guard, the negligent tradesman Bradford Restaurant – v. grease fire because Kenellos the grill is poorly The Supreme Court is divided on where to draw the line. If we expect that a certain kind of intervention will Sharon Zheng | LAW 108C | Spring 2012| Donald Galloway cleaned. Causes occur through the ordinary course of events, then the state of the art original wrongdoer is not absolved of liability sprinkler system The majority regard the intervention as “freakish”. to put it out but The link between D’s negligence and the result is someone at the broken by “hysterical” conduct that is not within the restaurant sees risk created by D’s negligence the fire, hears a o You’re not liable for the strange conduct of a hiss and thinks third party there’s a gas leak o Is it so far fetched that it’s unfair to hold the and there’s going original wrongdoer responsible for the to be an explosion. consequences? Cause everyone to In dissent Spence (citing Fleming), says that what panic, someone happened was “part of the ordinary course” of things gets trmpled. o There’s no intervention of a third party! The court sees it as critical that the hissing sounds leading to harm is based on a remedial action trying to resolve the harm, as opposed to the harm itself o This seems to really ignore the fact that their negligence did cause the fire in the first place! MANUFACTURERS, DISTRIBUTORS, CONTRACTORS AND REMOTENESS Smith v. Everyone in a Held: liable Inglis Nova Scotian The manufacturer of the fridge should have foreseen society cuts off that someone would cut off the third prong of the the third prong of plug (Everyone in the business knew or should have a plug for the known that this happens). Again the ordinary course refrigerator. The of events refrigerator manufacturer uses a cheap circuit, that is not safe to cut off the o The intentional decision to cut off the third prong is within the ordinary course of events Can you rely on the argument that people weren’t supposed to cut off the third prong? No. It’s not an intervention – you can trace it to third prong. the malfunctioning of a fridge. Anything anyone Someone gets regularly does is not an intervention, it’s part of the shocked. ordinary realm o You have a duty to look out for the interests Sharon Zheng | LAW 108C | Spring 2012| Donald Galloway of other parties o You have to look out for how they’ll actually behave Good- Good-Wear sold Q1 Did Good-wear breach a duty to roadusers? Q2 If wear retreaded tires to Treaders Pash that were o Pash’s decision to use the tires is not regarded not dangerous in as an intervention. The matter is resolved at themselves but the duty/breach stage. A result like this is the knew that Pash very reason behind the duty so, did the breach cause the death? was going to use There’s a duty to road users to make them in a sure they’re not subjected to this kind of dangerous way. harm Pash is warned not to use them in someone will be hurt (at the duty that way. Pash uses them and 3 stage), then you have a duty to not sell a tire that you know will be used in a rd party is killed through the use Court: because it’s foreseeable that dangerous way! Remoteness isn’t an issue. The facts are described in para 17 as rare. Is this true? o Court claims that this issue will only come up in rare situations Rarely would the seller know that the buyer would be using their products in a dangerous manner Good-wear has an obligation to road users – so we hold them to normal negligence standards (normal tort principles) … in terms of “who do I have to think about” includes road users o Is this actually rare? This is a subjective standard – but is there a way of stopping from moving to an objective standard? Pash’s negligence doesn’t “block or isolate” any prior negligence Galloway: this is very intriguing! And much broader implications than what the court would suggest Sharon Zheng | LAW 108C | Spring 2012| Donald Galloway SUBSEQUENT MEDICAL ERRORS Def 1 hurts plaintiff Dr (Def 2) is negligent and makes it worse Is Def 1 responsible for the Dr’s negligence as well? 1970s: if a wrongdoer puts a person in the hospital, theyre responsible for the plaintiff having to be in the hospital, but not for Dr’s negligence o Dr negligence is so unusual and strange that it breaks the causal link o This is different than negligence by someone else (non Dr) because negligence by others can be expected Galloway and modern law: this is likely wrong (Katzman) o Dr’s negligence is fairly common now, we don’t se it as being so unusual that it’s freakish o At some stage, the Dr’s negligence may be seen as bizarre so at some stage we’re in the realm of the unexpected BUT this is not the usual case DEFENCES? There are some defences to negligence actions, but they’re limited o 1. Voluntary assumption of risk We will only impose this in situations where it’s absolutely clear that the plaintiff knows there are risks, and are also aware of the legal risks (waiving legal rights) And these factors must be clearly articulated to the plaintiff If it’s unclear, then this defence will be limited o 2. Illegality (ex turpi causa) Limited – if you’re a bank robber you can’t sue your fellow bank robber for not having shot the cop BUT this is narrow – just because you’re doing something illegal doesn’t mean you can’t have an action in negligence o 3. Contributory negligence (partial defence) o 4. Inevitable accident? No – this really isn’t a defence! It’s a historical anachronism that hasn’t gone away yet – a car accident looks a lot like a battery and originally to defend against battery, had to argue inevitable accident (non intentional or negligent) Later, car accidents were treated as two cars hitting each other (not just one party hitting the other), and may be non battery and non negligent Sharon Zheng | LAW 108C | Spring 2012| Donald Galloway as well PURE PSYCHIATRIC HARM A HISTORY (discussed in Devji) Emotional disturbance itself will not be allowed as a tort action. Why not? o It’s more subjective than physical injury – it affects being vastly differently o We are responsible for our own wellbeing? o Compensating for the harm is very challenging, and there are perhaps evidentiary issues? What about the possibility of junk science? o Is creating an emotional disturbance really a wrong? Is it actually harmful? o Floodgate! We’ll have many claims and also, we won’t be able to distinguish between those that are worthwhile and those that aren’t – where would we draw the line? Courts: there is such thing as psychiatric harm BUT we must be dealing with recognized illnesses. Just general emotional distress won’t be enough o Seriously, likely long lasting would be more convincing Two questions re: the nature of this tort action: o 1) DUTY: when do you have a duty to look after someone else’s mental wellbeing? And to take measures to prevent a person from suffering psychiatric harm? Do you have the same duty to peoples’ mental wellbeing as their physical well-being? Dorset Yacht: YEAH – there’s a different set of circumstances where you’d recognize a duty to physical harm as you would to psychological harm Post Cooper: when will you be in a close enough relationship that you owe a duty to not harm someone? When are you in a sufficiently close relationship that is reasonable and just to hold someone to such a duty? Is proximity for psychiatric harm issues the same as for physical harm? o 2) REMOTENESS: If you breach a duty to a person and create the risk that they will suffer physical injury, should you be liable if they instead suffer psychiatric harm? Pre Cooper, duty is used in remoteness language as well WARNING! The courts of OFTEN confused the two questions o In Mustapha, the issues is REMOTENESS. SCC emphasizes the need to keep them Sharon Zheng | LAW 108C | Spring 2012| Donald Galloway apart o Plaintiff has shown a negligent breach of duty – issue is whether the defendant should be liable Another question: o What if you breach your duty and cause physical harm, and then as part of that also cause psychiatric harm (ex. depression?) If you’re liable for a breach of duty, causing harm, including psychiatric harm, then courts have little problem holding individuals responsible for the psychiatric harm (psychiatric harm caused by or concomitant with the physical harm) o Courts will talk often about pure vs. impure (resulting from physical harm) psychiatric harm There are 3 general types of cases we see commonly: 1. Duty case – when do I have a duty to pure psychiatric harms? To look after someone else’s mental health? 2. Remoteness case – I have breached my duty, but instead of causing physical harms it only caused psychiatric harms 3. Impure case – I have breached my duty, caused physical harms, and also psychiatric harms 1. When do you owe a duty to look after someone else’s mental health? o Pre-Cooper: part 2 Anns test says that reasonable foreseeability to decide liability, but we need control mechanisms There are some cases that are deserving, and some that are not o Courts seem to think that the suddenness of shock is more likely to lead to mental illness than a prolonged experience Therefore the difference between a deserving and undeserving person is whether is someone’s been subject to a sudden impact on the mind (deserving) Devji v. Devji v. Burnaby Burnaby Victorian Rlwy Comrs. (para 18) P171: 1888 – negligence causing near collision, leading to shock but no physical harm Yasmin Breach of duty, but the only thing suffered is nervous shock Devji is Court: will not recognize the harms killed in a IF she had also suffered physical injury, then we’d consider your nervous car shock Sharon Zheng | LAW 108C | Spring 2012| Donald Galloway accident, the family (father, Court: concerns due to 1) floodgates and 2) wide field for imaginary claims mother, Dulieu (miscarriage case) two Pregnant woman frightened when a carriage is negligently driven through the window of the pub in which she is sisters) o HELD: there cannot be recovery for nervous shock without are told immediate fear of personal injury to plaintiff o This means that a defendant can be liable for psychiatric harms IF by a police there’s an immediate fear of bodily harm officer at Remoteness case: duty was breached their No physical injury, but found liability for nervous shock! home and Hambrook asked to Looks like a duty analysis go to the Mother suffers shock at the sight of an accident in which one of her hospital children is injured due to defendant’s negligence to o Court: If you expose children to the dangers of the road, you identify don’t owe a duty to all witnesses, but you do owe a duty to the the MOTHER in addition to the other road users deceased. o This is true even if the mothers are not exposed to physical They go almost danger immediate Hay ly to the Motor cyclist driving too fast, hits a vehicle. Hay looks at the carnage, and while she wasn’t in immediate danger herself, suffers from shock hospital, Miscarriage like Duliu view the Court: Loses on the ground of reasonable foreseeability body, and Court’s Duty refinement: the test of liability for shock is reasonable foreseeability of injury by shock! then claim they suffered nervous Held: no duty owed here – woman’s decision to look at the accident was her own Chadwick shock Rescuer, rescuing people during a train wreck injury Traumatized by role, sues the train Held: there’s a duty to rescuers, extends to post traumatic stress even if they aren’t exposed to original risk and haven’t suffered physical harms o There’s a duty to not only those who use trains, but also those who help save the train situation Sharon Zheng | LAW 108C | Spring 2012| Donald Galloway McLoughlin v. O’Brian (Lord Wilberforce, HL) Starting to use proximity to define the ambit of duty – introduces language of proximity when defining the ambit of the duty FACTS: car accident, victims raced to hospital with serious injuries. Mother told about the accident, raced to the hospital, sees the kids in the aftermath of the accident. o This is a parasitical claim: injury is caused to kids, but extends to problems suffered by parents etc. HELD: where physical injury has been caused negligently to someone else, a duty will be owed to a limited class of people in regards to their mental health o 1. Closeness of family tie (mother, not just witness) Your connection doesn’t have to be mother: could be father, friend perhaps o 2. Proximity to accident (witnessing the accident or its immediate aftermath vs. hearing it on the telephone) Time and Space o 3. Means by which the shock is caused Is there a difference between actually witnessing something first hand vs. through a medium (TV etc.) In the UK: yes – there’s a dominant line between real and virtual experiences o But the less the relationship, then the close you’ll have to be to the accident 2 BCCAs that buy into McLoughlin 1) Beecham v. Hughes Husband and wife in a car accident Husband suffers no injury, wife suffers severe physical injury, husband has to take care of wife constantly, husband sinks into darkness and psychiatric care Husband sues defendant and loses o Held: psychiatric harm is a result of sorrow as opposed to as a result of the accident 2) Rhodes Plaintiff heard about the accident on the radio, and thinks the son is on the train Sharon Zheng | LAW 108C | Spring 2012| Donald Galloway Starts driving from Vancouver Island to the train wreck in Alberta She’s not allowed to get close to the train, she’s diverted, she’s given false information, and eventually learns that son was killed on the train Mother was sent the body parts by mail (although railway company was not responsible for that) Held: she can’t recover because (unanimously) she didn’t experience fright, terror or horror at the scene at the time of the accident o She head a long time to get to the train and get control of her emotions o You must trace your psychiatric harm to fright/ terror/ horror to have a successful action There lacks the immediacy of the horror What is this immediacy all about? It’s about limiting claims (see below) JUDGMENT The law expects people to be of ordinary fortitude We don’t all have the same resilience But we want and expect people to take responsibility for their own mental health – if they’re overly sensitive, we expect them to take measures to protect themselves (get a thicker skin) The talk of ordinary fortitude suggests that we will recognize a duty to those people from whom you have taken away the opportunity to brace themselves against psychiatric impact This arises from the shock, immediacy, close ties with the person getting injured These tend to be easy cases There seems to be a sense about the impact of love on your mental health We don’t expect you to brace yourself in a loving relationship – since it’s an unconditional relationship, we expect to throw yourself in We do expect you to brace yourself for harms that you Sharon Zheng | LAW 108C | Spring 2012| Donald Galloway might see against a stranger though, for ex. The more gruesome the case, the more we are willing to hear your claim though – is the familial and loving relationship required? o Unsure – but we have in the past been sympathetic to rescuers Where, however, a person has the opportunity to brace themselves, they will be held to be the single author of the psychiatric harm HELD: no liability Mustapha Remoteness case v. Culligan Everyone expected that this would answer all our questions re: the differences between deserving and undeserving cases Mustapha is a Two issues emerging in this case: o 1) It seems that the court is saying that the thin skull rule does customer not apply when we are dealing with questions of liability – that it of Culligan only applies when we are dealing with damages water. o 2) Would the situation be different if Mustapha had consumed the Sees flies fly, suffered gastroenteritis, and then suffered some psychiatric in an damage? AKA if some physical harm was suffered unopened delivered bottle of water, Common law countries are in complete disagreement re: how we deal with these kinds of cases o In UK, the courts adopted an idea of primary vs. secondary victims and Mustapha Primary victim = Mustapha, a duty of care is owed to them and breached against them. He has suffered harm The position of primary victims is very different than the suffers position of secondary victims – ex. the mother seeing the psychiatric dead son harm If the primary victim suffers harm, we should apply the “take from the your victim as you find them”, regardless if it’s psychiatric disgust he illnesses or physical illnesses alone experience s It’s only with secondary victims that we expect victims to be able to brace themselves, have ordinary fortitude etc. o SCC: we’re not going to draw this line. We’re going to draw the normal principles of negligence liability and see where that gets us In Mustapha, they don’t even go into the Cooper analysis – they just Sharon Zheng | LAW 108C | Spring 2012| Donald Galloway state that duty of manufacturer to customer is just a duty o This is quite radical! o SCC could have said that up until now, the manufacturer has had a duty only to guard against PHYSICAL harm! Not PSYCHIATRIC harm! o SCC accepts that physical and psychiatric harms are the same thing (any harm) The SCC also states (easily) that Culligan has a duty to prevent foreign objects from falling into the water o Galloway: this is a bit too quick – we’re worried about animals, body parts, feces, falling into the water but we’re less worried about food colouring etc. SCC states that, given there’s a breach and the suffering of recognized illness, the issue in this case is remoteness o The SCC could have dealt with this under the thin skull rule BUT they don’t want to go in that direction Don’t think it’s fair for Mustapha to succeed o SCC finds that this is not the type of injury that Culligan risked by letting flies fall in the water AKA defendant is not responsible for every consequence, just ones that occur in the ordinary course of events This is not the ordinary course of events because we expect people to have an ordinary fortitude Thin skill doesn’t get off the ground because the breach of duty has only caused one sort of injury, and that sort is one that we don’t think should be ordinarily compensable! This isn’t the kind of harm you risk by breaching your duty This case deals with psychiatric injury – and Mustapha passes that o The law does not recognize upset disgust or anxiety as injury Para 16: Tort imposes an obligation to compensate for harm done on a basis of reasonable foresight, not as insurance (Galloway: this is the turning point of the case) o Just like in Wagon Mound where you don’t associate bunker oil with large fire o Reading paragraph 16, do you get the idea that the thin skull rule is being rejected? Sharon Zheng | LAW 108C | Spring 2012| Donald Galloway We ask whether a person of ordinary fortitude would suffer the psychiatric harm o Is it significant that Mustapha had not suffered any harm? Had he swallowed the fly, suffered gastro-enteritis and then depression, would he be able to recover? (Compare the person who swallows the fly suffers gastro-enteritis and then has kidney failure because of a weak kidney) In the “duty cases” we require people to brace themselves In the remoteness cases we expect the same - the failure of Mustapha to brace himself is seen as an intervening factor! We’re adopting the secondary claim analysis – and we’re treating Mustapha like a secondary victim! We expect you to brace yourself, and you can’t blame those who have wronged you for your failure to brace yourself! o We’re telling Mustapha that he has a sensitivity, and that his opportunity to brace himself has not been taken away just by a fly o We identify Mustapha as the author of his problem We’re essentially saying that some claims are meritorious and some are not to restrict what will get through – but it’s not really fair to draw it this way SCC also says though that if the defendant knew the plaintiff had specific weaknesses (ex. if Culligan knew that Mustapha was sensitive to flies) then the ordinary fortitude requirement need not be applied strictly o = in situations where there’s knowledge o Galloway: how does that knowledge have an impact on the explanation?! If we’re telling Mustapha that his weakness is something that he alone is responsible for (ie he is the intervener), then how does the knowledge mater?? Thin skull only gets off the ground when we find that the defendant is liable for something – not in determining whether there was a tort PURE ECONOMIC LOSS DUTY issue Economic loss that is not derivative of any physical harm (personal injury or damages to one’s property) In Dorset Yacht we saw that Lord Reid note that if we based tort liability on the reasonable foreseeability of financial losses, competitive markets would cease to function Sharon Zheng | LAW 108C | Spring 2012| Donald Galloway o In the market, when someone wins, someone loses As with psychiatric harm, we can identify 2 questions: o 1. When do you owe a duty to take steps to prevent others from suffering economic loss? o 2. If you’ve breached a duty in relation to property damage but have only caused economic losses, when should you be liable? Recognized categories 1. D makes a negligent misstatement (= negligent misrepresentation). P relies on it and suffers loss; When do you owe a duty not to make a negligent mis-statement? Ex. Hedley Byrne. Someone trusts another for information, relies on it to their economic detriment In these cases, courts may recognize liability for economic losses under tort liability Hedley Byrne, Hercules 2. D provides that service for P’s benefit but does so negligently do that P does not benefit; When do you owe a duty In these cases, there may be liability even if the plaintiff has not relied on it to their detriment! Ex. if a lawyer is working for someone drafting their will, if the lawyer negligently drafts the will so that their void, and the person who loses is the beneficiary under the will (not the testator) Can the beneficiary sue the lawyer? Yes. And there need not be reliance in this situation until after the fact (after discovering the will is void) Since the lawyer has undertaken to provide a service Overlaps with the first, but this category is very slim 3. D markets a dangerous good. P must spend money in order to render it safe; This is a remoteness case If you have marketed a dangerous good but before the danger manifests itself the consumer discovers it and has to spend money to render the danger safe, there’s been no personal injury/ property damage But given you’ve breached your duty, can you be liable for those expenses to render it safe? 4. D harms 3P’s prop. Relies on that property in order to make a profit. P Sharon Zheng | LAW 108C | Spring 2012| Donald Galloway alleges relational economic loss; You don’t have a property interest, but you use someone else’s property This is not normally a situation that gives rise to tort liability for your economic losses (this is quite clear now) Ex. driver negligently hits hydro pole, knocks electricity out of homeowner’s house, and unable to carry on their business and make money. Can they sue the person who damaged the hydro pole? Probably not. NEGLIGENT MISREPRESENTATION Hedley Held: the bank is not liable – they covered themselves with a disclaimer Byrne v. However, it’s not problematic that D didn’t know who would be using the Heller info Lord Reid rejects out of hand the argument that the D is not liable because it did not know the ID of the P Easipower wants to buy advertisin g from P (on credit), but P wants to o D bank knew there was a client out there who would be relying on the information, and for contractual purposes o Therefore Lord Reid treat it as a case of info directly given to the P Dismisses the bank as agent as an important element o Therefore leaves open the Q of “the degree of proximity” to focus on the issue of economic loss due to negligent misrepresentation 1. P’s first argument: rely on Donague (p188) o Lord Reid rejects the Donaghue and Stevenson ruing in this case ensure a. There is a difference between words and actions Ex. on social occasions people give opinions even when that they see that others are likely to rely on their Easipower statements is good for its on a business occasion obligations . P’s bank They don’t take the same level of care that they would Therefore no duty of care on these occasions b. A negligently made article will only cause on accident: the approache level of proximity is easy to determine. On the other hand, d D bank words can be broadcast without consent. K can’t cover all to get these third parties credit rating reference o Therefore there’s good sense behind the generality that there’s no liability for economic losses caused by negligent misstatements 2. For liability something more is needed: the D must have undertaken Sharon Zheng | LAW 108C | Spring 2012| Donald Galloway for some responsibility (p. 189) or performed a gratuitous service (some Easipower. authority that there can be liability there) D gave references that were o The basic requirement is that a person, through their words in the context, is taking on responsibility 3. Lord Reid goes further to develop this legal principle: on its surface, not Derry v. Peek seems to suggest that there can be liability only for justified fraudulent mistakes. and P o However, the later cases indicate that courts have recognized relied to innocent or negligent misrepresentation in cases of special relationships their that give rise to liability for economic losses (p.190) detriment o What are these special relationships? All those relationship where the party seeking information was relying on the other where 1) one party trusts/ relies on the other to exercise due case 2) it’s reasonable to do so because of the circumstances 3) where the party giving the information knew or ought to have known the other’s reliance When all these elements are present, we conclude that the person has undertaken a responsibility! Applying this to a professional setting: where D provides information to another who is relying and the circumstances make it reasonable to rely, D will be liable How well does the undertaking analysis work? o If someone comes into your office for advice (and you know you’re being trusted in your advice) you could: 1. Keep silent 2. Give an answer but make a statement that no responsibility is accepted 3. Answer without qualification Therefore the choice is up to the person giving the information, but if you choose step three then you’ve accepted responsibility! o Therefore this doesn’t cover a social situation! o Would it cover a situation where P2 passes on the information to P2? If the test is just reasonable foreseeability, then this might be covered (where you get a professional opinion it is foreseeable Sharon Zheng | LAW 108C | Spring 2012| Donald Galloway that you will pass it on) If you say the test is reasonable foreseeability plus reasonable reliance, then it may still be covered BUT if the basis of the rule is that you have undertaken responsibility (“you may trust me on this”) then you have made no such statement to a 3P o So maybe there are 2: reasonable reliance + special relationship and undertaking Lord Morris o Voluntary undertaking can give rise to the duty to exercise reasonable care where another person relies o Where possessor of special skills undertakes to exercise those skills for the assistance of another who relies on them, a duty of care will arise (irrespective of contract) o Where it is reasonable for others to rely on skills of a person and that person takes it upon himself to give information or allow it to be passed on to a person who, as he should know, will rely, then there is a duty of care. What is the critical issue? o Is it the reliance and the reasonableness of reliance? Or is it the assumption of responsibility? o In Hedley Burne it doesn’t matter since either will decide the case o But in later cases, we find assumption of responsibility without reliance Remember: there was on K between the banks BG Checo Can sue in both tort and K v. BC In Hedley there is no K – but what if there is a K? Hydro o Central Trust – like Hedley Byrne. Professional relationship, defined by K. Can party due in tort and K? Yes Tender o Checo for a K Tort liability and contractual liability can run concurrently to erect Where they do, P may select the action that is more transmissi on towers and to string advantageous, or sue in both Where D is under a tort duty to P, they may include that duty as part of a K Three situations: Sharon Zheng | LAW 108C | Spring 2012| Donald Galloway transmissi on lines. o Iacobucci’s dissent BC Hydro claims duty, P can only sue in K that land will first be cleared Tort liability will only apply if the K does not address the required behaviour o LaForest/ McLachlin (majority) by a third party. If parties specify a duty in L then whether or not it’s a tort No that’s too narrow – we should allow concurrency to allow the plaintiff to recover 1) Where a contract stipulates that a party will live up to his Checo bids tort responsibilities, then the other party may sue either in and wins tort or contract. the K – 2) Where the contract requires a person to go further than then he would have to in tort, the tort duty remains open but it discovers is likely that the party will sue in contract. the clearing hasn’t 3) Where the contract allows a party to reduce or nullify liability in tort. Must be in clear terms. An interesting twist in Checo! The last line: a contractual limitation that been done limits tort liability (even clearly) may not apply where the tort is or has independent of the K been done poorly, and that they’ll o Therefore there’s a field that the K covers, but anything outside that field is fair tort game o A mysterious provision! On the same day the court decides Cognos: FACTS: P is an IT specialist, who is hired to the operation in lose Ottawa (made to feel very wanted by Cognos). P agrees to money by move from Calgary to Ottawa, and signs an employment K completin that can terminate him without cause g the K. P is brought to Ottawa on the basis of negligent BC Checo representations about the nature of the work he will be wants to doing. Turns out that the project P is hired for is just a pipe sue in dream (there’s no financing behind it), he is terminated and tort and loses his job K, even though K stipulates HELD: The contract allowed him to be terminated without cause – this relates to the doing of the project to something independent of the employment K what the standard The representations made to make P leave Calgary relate La Forest and Iacobucci see the tort to be independent Sharon Zheng | LAW 108C | Spring 2012| Donald Galloway will be of the contract! Iacobucci: the representations relate to the nature and the reality of the project not to the amount of involvement. Galloway: this is ridiculous, and a much too narrow way to construe the K! Hercules Pre-Cooper case. During this time, McLachlin and (Laforest) REALLY Mgmt v. disagreed about the meaning of tort law, and what proximity in tort law Ernst and meant Young o LaForest: instrumentalist view of tort – it’s meant to achieve certain social ends. Therefore we need to exercise controls to SCC 1997 prevent it leaking to areas where it doesn’t serve a social purpose o McLachlin: tort is about private relationships between parties, the Is an auditor notion of proximity is first and foremost to negligence LaForest’s decision (Maj) liable to o Adopts 2 part Anns Test investors (sharehold Prima facie duty of care at first stage o But claims that in cases of negligent misrep, most of the work will ers) in a be done at the second stage company who relied Social/ policy reasons for limiting/ recognizing tort liability o Acknowledges there’s some argument that the Anns test doesn’t on its apply to negligent misrep cases, but he doesn’t accept this negligently Analysis: prepared The concept of proximity is seen to be key audits of Para 23 and first part of para 24 is consistent with but not as well the company developed as the later statement in Cooper But they key to understanding proximity is identified in para 24 as reliance that were o The reliance in these circumstances is reasonable! prepared o The D ought to reasonably foresee that P will rely on the for all representation; the plaintiff’s reliance is in the particular shareholde circumstances reasonable rs? Some shareholde o Therefore, since these two elements are met, there’s a special relationship When is reliance reasonable? Para 43: 5 indicia rs are o 1) Def has direct financial interest claiming o 2) Def was a professional or someone possessed of special skill that they o 3) Advice provided in course of business Sharon Zheng | LAW 108C | Spring 2012| Donald Galloway relied on the negligently prepared document o 4) Given deliberately and not on a social occasion (old Hedley Byrne notion) o 5) Given in response to a specific enquiry or request (fact situation in Hedley Byrne) o LaForest: Don’t need to meet all five (here only first four are met) in order because it’s not a test of reasonableness, it’s just indicating where to make negligence is reasonable vs. where it is not further investmen ts and that if Ernst and Emphasizing not the relationship of the parties, but the professionalness of the services How is this different from Hedley Byrne? o In Hedley: if you’re a professional – you have 3 choices as to what you can do Young had Don’t give info done their Qualify the info job Make unqualified statement properly, o Galloway: Hedley suggests that it’s easy for a person putting info the into the public to avoid tort liability just by adding a disclaimer shareholde (“this info can only be used for limited purposes” ex. just for one rs would client) have withdrawn their money, BUT it’s up to the person providing the information to make the choice on what to do!! o But there is nothing in the analysis about Ernst and Young undertaking or assuming responsibility for the individuals’ losses! preventing the personal Usually when we think undertaking, we thing about someone asking “can I trust you” and you saying “yes” o LaForest: no! The burden shouldn’t be on the information provider! losses To meet Pt 1 of the Ann’s Test, just have to be in a situation they’ve where economic loss is reasonably forseeable and the other party is suffered. reasonably relying Therefore Primary basis on reasonable reliance given But now leaving it open for individuals to be liable for general there’s a statements they release into the public, so then creating the duty to control mechanisms shareholde Therefore saying that there’s a limited amount of rs people who can rely on Ernst and Young. Court must generally, create the limitations, via proximity Sharon Zheng | LAW 108C | Spring 2012| Donald Galloway can individuals Lord Reid would say different: he’d say that Ernst and Young could limit their own liability with a disclaimer sue when o So we move onto Pt 2 of the Anns Test they There are potentially enormous social costs – the number of experience tort actions will explode. So we introduce 2 control personal mechanisms: losses 1) Only owe duty of care to individuals for whom you made the statements o You know their identity or the class to which they belong 2) Only owe duty of care if the information is used for the very purpose for which it was created o For LaForest, this is the easy way to deal with the solution! But by emphasizing reasonable reliance as the key to the index of when there’s a duty of care, he may be causing problems for himself later on In this case, the audit wasn’t created for individuals to make investments although it’s reasonable for people to use it that way. It was created so that shareholders as a group can make decisions re: the management of the company. HELD: therefore no liability in this case Galloway: o This is a convoluted way of looking at a problem! That could’ve been dealt with easily under the Lord Reid method! o Instead adopts this: 1) broad notion of proximity, take reasonable reliance loosely 2) limit liability for social reasons o This might end up being a good answer but it creates TWO PROBLEMS: ISSUE 1 WITH HERCULES: if the basis of liability is the reasonable reliance of the plaintiffs, than can you ever (in a neg misrep case) have contributory negligence? o You should be able to determine that the defendant is still liable, but only so for a percentage or proportion of the losses If we base it on the reasonable reliance of the plaintiff, though, this becomes no longer available o If the reliance was unreasonable then there would be no tort. The court in Avco tries to resolve the issue – says that contributory negligence should still be Sharon Zheng | LAW 108C | Spring 2012| Donald Galloway available There can be reasonable reliance, and also responsibility for own downfall to some extent Ex. Business owner, gets a reference letter giving a great reference to a worker, but the writer gives the reference negligently (ex. they think they’re writing about someone else) and business owner hires them, who turns out to be an embezeller 1) I was reasonable to rely on the reference writer 2) But I might be contributorily negligent for not protecting my business against embezellers o This isn’t too troubling Avco Contributory negligence is still available! Financial v. Norman NEGLIGENT PROVISION OF A SERVICE ISSUE 2 WITH HERCULES: what if the person harmed is not the person who relied (the person to who the statement is made) but the person about whom the statement is made?? Haskett Creditor wants to Hercules decision based on reliance can’t deal with know the person’s this case! Because plaintiff hasn’t relied but there creditworthiness. should still be liability nonetheless! Bank says they aren’t creditworthy when they actually are, have to pay a lot Court suggests that reliance is not necessary Use the Cooper analysis instead: 1) is this case analogous to an established category of case where we recognize liability? 2) if this isn’t a recognized level, the relationship more to borrow, here is sufficiently proximate to fairly create a new and experience category hold there’s liability (recognizing negligent losses, due to the misrepresentation not based on reliance) negligence misstatement even though they’re not relying upon it o They’re saying reliance is not necessary – that this is analogous even without reliance o Monumental! Note the equivocation – the situation is analogous to the causes of action Sharon Zheng | LAW 108C | Spring 2012| Donald Galloway where liability for negligent misrepresentation has been recognized. o Court relies on Feldthusen in Cognos (who LaForest in Hercules relied on): Reliance not necessary – para 33 of Haskett o The key is a special relationship (not reliance) o Para 34 the representor has effectively assumed responsibility because of the potential harm. Where assumed or imposed liability exists (para 39) = ignore later precedent of the SCC and using a prior precedent 3) are there any social/ policy reasons to not recognize this new category in 2)? No – not in this case o Indeterminacy not a problem here. Knowledge and Control (para 45) o Are other legal remedies available, such that we don’t have to extend tort law into an area where it’s not necessary? Can’t this be treated under the law of defamation? Court: no – the law of defamation is insufficient (para 50), it’s too broad and has developed in a way that doesn’t sufficiently protect plaintiffs Allows defences: politicians and judges have “qualified privilege” against defamation, doctrine of qualified privilege also allows employers to give references without being subject to tort liability for negligence o Para 55 recognition that it may be problematic to recognize a tort duty in commercial negotiations involving sophisticated parties. Sharon Zheng | LAW 108C | Spring 2012| Donald Galloway This seems to be the basis of 2008 decision in Design Services (materials p 261) Court: this is not a situation in which the parties are in complex negotiations This is different Galloways conclusion re: negligent provision of a service o Where a person has assumed responsibility for another person’s economic wellbeing, they are responsible when they exercise that responsibility negligently. o The fact that the subject of a credit report is totally vulnerable and that “fairness is a clear legislative imperative” allow the court to hold that responsibility is assumed. o Same logic as in Cf. Childs! Implied responsibilities of those involved in a commercial or public venture. If you’re engaged in a commercial/public activity on which other people are completely dependent, then you owe them a duty We’re dealing with a situation in which one party has all the power and the other all the vulnerability = assumption of responsibility o The lawyer cases also back this up! This seems to apply in the case of the lawyer and the disappointed beneficiary The lawyer when undertaking to draft a will is assuming responsibility over the economic interests of the beneficiary Even though it is not a negligent misrep case, the same principle should apply to the negligent provision of a service due not to reliance, but due to dependence As in Hedley Byrne an analogy is drawn with fiduciary relationships Plus the beneficiary is “wholly dependent” on the solicitor (para 39) = extraordinary counter strategy, against the LaForest decision in the SCC! o Negligent misrep vs. negligent provision of a service are competing now – perhaps two forms of tort law are emerging? o How are these treated in the future? How does BDC adopt it? Wilhelm v. Hickson HELD: lawyers owe a duty of care to beneficiaries named in a will when drawing and executing a will, breach of which may render him/her liable to pay damages suffered by the beneficiaries as a result of Sharon Zheng | LAW 108C | Spring 2012| Donald Galloway the breach Even though the beneficiary did not rely BDC v. Government takes Hofstrand charge of a Farms document, has Government assures to take charge and offers to deliver the document o BDC takes responsibility to deliver the nothing to lose if document from the government, but don’t the document is know why it’s being delivered and why it has to late but if the be on time plaintiff has it HELD: no liability delivered late, o 1) BDC has no knowledge or constructive then the knowledge that the party exists. Unless its plaintiff’s being told about a third party or has contracting constructive knowledge, can’t owe them a duty partner can back lawyer cases (Wilhelm) out of the contract Distinguished this from Haskett and the o 2) There is no reliance. The person allowing the Plaintiff needs the government to go to the courier company isn’t contract relying itself on the courier company Galloway: this is weak And adds to the idea that these kinds of cases are not about reliance at all NEGLIGENT SUPPLY OF A SHODDY PRODUCT Where a manufacturer sells a shoddy good that doesn’t work, the consumer is out of pocket (must buy another or must get a repair). Tort law will not usually compensate leaving it to the law of contract. However where the product is dangerous (risk of personal injury/ property damage), and the consumer pays money to render it safe, Winnipeg Condo suggests that tort law may step in. o Galloway: we don’t know how broad a precedent Winnipeg Condo stands for though o This is the most general message that could come from Winnipeg Condo o Why? By producing/ marketing a dangerous product, you’ve breached a duty to your consumer. Will you be held liable if the damages are purely economic losses (different in kind than the losses you would have expected)? o Galloway: this may be a case about the construction industry and who should Sharon Zheng | LAW 108C | Spring 2012| Donald Galloway bear the risks in a construction industry – so is it about negligently built buildings or dangerous products? The judgment doesn’t say. Galloway: this is super problematic – an even deeper hole for us to fall into Laforest is attempting to deal with liability for economic losses by looking at torts from the instrumentalist point of view o This view should be doubted – and this is the prime example!! Winnipeg Condo 1) There is some question whether the damage suffered is pure economic loss v. property damage (para 14-15) (Negligently installed ties caused damage to cladding) Company o Addressed via the complex structure argument builds o The argument put forward is that the damages in this case is actual condo so negligently property damage, and not pure economic losses that it becomes Ex. cladding falls off the building because of the negligently manufactured metal ties dangerous If it can be held that a latent defect of a specific part of the building, that problematic piece is a property damage issue, not pure economic loss AKA dividing the building into its constituent harms o Laforest No – this is one building, all part of the same thing that is one entity and has an identity What makes the ties and cladding part of the building is that they’re interdependent – one is fully dependent on another and it forms one thing A furnace, though, can be taken out – it’s new property. If a building burns down due to the furnace, then that’s property damage Therefore economic losses HELD: the individual can turn to the original builder and sue them for the economic losses incurred to negate the danger o Laforet seems to say often that there’s good reason to not extend liability to economic losses – try to box off and limit this area as much as possible o AND YET for reasons of social policy, more than willing to recognize economic losses in the Winnipeg condo case, and this does not open Sharon Zheng | LAW 108C | Spring 2012| Donald Galloway the door to indeterminacy RATIO - LaForest: Assuming the losses are economic, para 21 suggests that a person participating in the construction of a large and permanent structure that has the capacity to cause serious damage to other persons should be held to a reasonable standard of care Galloway: he does so for social/ policy reasons, hasn’t really thought through what the consequences are 1) The first argument seems to be based on social responsibility (undertaking to build a permanent building) that gives rise to liability to the public, rather than on any relationship with the future owners. o Buildings have a long life: duty not only to original inhabitant but to future inhabitants (there are the members of the public likely to be affected) too (para 35) This is who bears the risk Galloway: but I thought the duty was actually to the owners! What if the owners of the building are not the inhabitants? The owners are not at risk of being hurt … If the building falls apart, the owners are only suffering economic loss Are the builders are liable for that?? Laforest isn’t super helpful here 2) Rivtow Marine Argument (follows dissent – it’s efficient to allow people to sue original contractor) o FACTS: Crane is faulty (has a crack), manufacturer informs charter, costs money to repair o Dissent: there should be liability for repair “It follows that the contractor should also be held liable where the damage is discovered and the owner wishes to mitigate the damages” (para 36) Does it? o ISSUE WITH ANALOGIZING RIVTOW MARINE: there’s a difference between the owner (responsible for losses) and the inhabitants (liable to suffer the physical damage if we let it unfold Therefore there’s a difference between allowing certain people to be hurt, and therefore owing a duty to an owner to Sharon Zheng | LAW 108C | Spring 2012| Donald Galloway compensate them This doesn’t follow if these aren’t the same people Consider: the owner is informed of the potential danger. The owner is now responsible for preventing harms to third people (ex. those living there). If the owner does nothing, the third party people could go after (joint and severably) either the owner or the manufacturer of the building Laforet: it follows as a matter of course that we should hold the contractor liable to the owner. If we didn’t, then the owner would have no incentive to fix the damages and prevent harm to third parties. We want that – the deterrence of disaster BUT Galloway: if the owner can be jointly and severably liable to third party harms, then they do have greater incentive to repair, regardless of whether they get money back form the contractors Laforet: consider a second owner (contractors build it, first owner, sell it to second owner). If second owner finds that the building will collapse and we won’t impose liability on the contractor, there will be no incentive to prevent danger occurring BUT Galloway: there is incentive to repair! They could be liable! o Therefore there’s something weird going on UK courts: People who buy products/ buildings that are defective, they have just lost out – they made a poor investment If you’ve bought a dangerous product and you know it can cause harm, it’s your responsible for discarding it Laforet: housing is different than this, because it would be terribly inefficient to require people to discard houses. We shouldn’t regard a dangerous building as a broken pen Laforet: when people are in the largest investment of their life and it’s not a sophisticated commercial transaction, we should offer them protection from losses, through tort law ANNS TEST PART 2 Sharon Zheng | LAW 108C | Spring 2012| Donald Galloway o Laforet claims that there is no issue of indeterminancy, because we limit claims to those of “real and substantial danger” for the “useful life of a building” What is a reason and substantial danger? Cladding falling off if clearly dangerous. But what about building leaks, mould, bad smells, poor air circulation … Inhabitability is not just a lack of danger though, it involves a level of pleasant and healthy life!! What is the “useful life of a building”? This is actually an onus of proof issue Liability on owner to show that at the time the building was being constructed, it was foreseeable the danger would occur o The longer the building exists, the harder it is to show that the defect is caused by design flaw, not wear and tear Laforet is not treating this as a time span issue (ex. 30 years) necessarily Problems with this judgment: o Laforet does equivocate between homeowners and building owners! The reasons behind Laforet’s decision is protecting vulnerable people Is the duty owed to a non-inhabiting investor though? o Is this a case about buildings or is it a case about dangerous products? o He creates a 2 tier system: original owner who buys it from builder may not be able to sue because there might be a limited liability clause in their contract But, if this individual sells to someone else, then that second party may be able to sue! o This actually discourages people form making fast repairs! Something may not be a real and substantial danger yet – but the contractors won’t be liable under it becomes a real and substantial danger Therefore instead of fixing mould (at own cost), may wait until the mould takes over, when it becomes dangerous, to Sharon Zheng | LAW 108C | Spring 2012| Donald Galloway charge the contractor Galloway: pure economic losses in Canada have been shaped primarily by LaForet, but his view of tort liability and the purpose of tort is very different than McLachlin (who shaped the Cooper analysis) o We adopt the McLachlin template generally o So there seems to be a fight to get Laforet model into the law There in the negligent misrepresentation case, liability for repairs of dangerous problems, LaForet’s voice is very strong Hasegawa v. Pepsi HELD: o There was not enough evidence here that the product was dangerous o If the product was dangerous and not just impure (ex. if there was Pepsi bottles water for Aqua P buys water poison in it) then Hasegawa might have an action against Pepsi o But in this case, action not available RATIO: for a manufacturer to be responsible for a product, it must be dangerous, not just shoddy Rejects Junior Books as an authority in BC law o Galloway: this it unfortunate and very sad because the analysis in from junior books is very much like Mclachlin’s take on tort in Cooper, Aqua for and worth looking at sale in Japan, but because of impurity o RATIO: for a manufacturer to be responsible, there doesn’t have to be a contract, a close relationship will suffice o FACTS: JB enters into K with contractor to building factor Contractor gets into touch with Veitchi, the floor specialist, because JB suggests they do so it is Therefore flooring is subcontracted to Veitchi unsellable Veitchi and JB are in contact during the building by the (Pepsi has contractor allowed o There is no K between JB and Veitchi, but there mould in is a close relationship developing between the commercial actors water, o Not negotiating rights/ obligations, but discussing and and trying to resolve problems Japanese health o Not done so in contractual terms though Flooring turned out to be substandard – not dangerous Sharon Zheng | LAW 108C | Spring 2012| Donald Galloway authority but didn’t meet JB’s needs (defective) refuse to o No contract, but had been in a close relationship allow it) When floor needs repairing, contractor is out of business o Argues that relationship between JB and Veitchi was not contractual, it was close enough to give rise to a duty of care Accepted by House of Lords! And J. Wilson in Kamloops. Rivtow Martine o FACTS: M – D – Charter (Rivtow Marine) o Crane hired for the logging industry o Rivtow Marine in K with distributor, and they are contacting the manufacturer all the time for advice about use of the crane Therefore there’s a very close non contractual business relationship between the M and Rivtow Marine Therefor through conversations get to know a lot about the seasonal aspect of logging, of the nature of Rivtow Marine’s business o At the low season, manufacturer finds out that another one of their cranes has cracked causing great danger Low season is a good time to warn However, M is worried about liability so doesn’t warn By the time M warns, it’s high season o Rivtow marine suffers great losses taking the crane out of service in the high season o Rivtow argues that they should recover the economic losses that they incurred due to losses in high season versus low season o HELD: YES – manufacturer is held liable for the losses Manufacturers in a very close relationship with the user of the product – you can be held liable for the economic losses This relationship is independent of K and it’s close enough that it can be acted on! Therefore business people can take on obligations in tort just by establishing a tort obligation! = duty to other individuals in business where a close relationship has been undertaken! Sharon Zheng | LAW 108C | Spring 2012| Donald Galloway In Hasegawa though, the BCCA is saying that business is a hardline between having contractual rights or not – a relationship between business people will not lead to tort liability. Have to go back on relying on K o Galloway: it’s sad that we can’t rely on talking about our needs and products and communication between parties any more. Now, we do have to rely on negotiation and contracts. RELATIONAL ECONOMIC LOSS The economic losses that third parties suffer when a second party has been injured (physically or property damage by defendant) but economic consequences borne by third party o UK: absolutely not!! o Canada: maybe CNR v. Norsk ISSUE: can railway sue barge? The economic losses are suffered by a different party than the property losses are suffered by. If we recognize the economic losses, where will we stop in the future? We’re hoping to SCC 1992 see a judgment that will clear up the extend of liability for economic losses – instead we get 3+3+1 and no majority. Bridge, Note: if bridge and railway were owned by the same company, then barge, and property harm and the economic loss tied to the property harm would be railway no issue – tort liability would be found company. K between Laforest (+2): NO! Proximity is a hopeless concept with no meaning. Pragmatically, we need to look at social policy reasons o We need a clear and certain rule! We can’t allow property owners/ bridge and those who use another’s property to go about business not knowing railway whether they should insure themselves company. o Certainty would be provided by a dominant exclusionary rule (not Barge recognizing parasitic/ relationship economic losses) with precise steerer is exceptions drunk, hits the bridge, o We already have precise islands where economic loss to 3rd parties have been recognized in the past – they’re technical, well defined: bridge is damaged. Ex. 1) where P has a possessory interest, Issue: who is a stakeholder? 2) Where there’s a joint venture (individuals coming together Sharon Zheng | LAW 108C | Spring 2012| Donald Galloway Railway and sharing the same objectives, out to achieve the same ends loses a but rely on property owned by 1 party), lot of money law because it can’t go over the This is complicated, but it has gained traction in the If damage done to property of one, done to both parties bridge, General averaging cases (Galloway – this is really arcane, from maritime law): but it Ship owners and cargo owners own different property, doesn’t but enter into commercial arrangements in which if own the there’s damage done to the boat, the cost of getting bridge the boat (and cargo) would be split proportionally company between boat owner and cargo owners = proportionality of sharing losses, to get the result of safety If one boat owners crashed into another causing damage, the damaging boat owner owes the damaged boat owner the money to be split among ship owner and cargo owners, even if no cargo is harmed Transferred loss cases Prior to ownership passing, non-owners are responsible for damage to the property, ex. construction steel And that’s it! Certainty is our prime interest. McLachlin (+2): Yes. Outlines the prototype for Cooper. First let’s look at the relationship between the parties and deal with it using proximity. A flexible solution is needed (to avoid arbitrary delineations) o Let’s look into the notion of a joint venture, and take a realistic look at what a property interest means There’s little difference between a user with property interest and an investor in the bridge So let’s actually look at how merged the economic interests are Liability for econ. Loss has been recognized in a joint venture situation. It is fair to extend that class of cases to cover this one: CN supplied materials, inspection, consulting services and Sharon Zheng | LAW 108C | Spring 2012| Donald Galloway was recognized in the periodic negotiations surrounding the closure of the bridge Bridge integral to railway system For practical purposes, P’s position is indistinguishable from the P owner’s! The pragmatic arguments: insurance cots, loss spreading and K allocation of risks – rests on questionable assumptions Stevens: yes, there is liability because the barge should have known about the train Laforest – we need to meet an amicable arrangement!! And wins the day through Bow Valley. Then loses the war through Cooper. Caltex oil case (Australia) o Similar to Norsk o Boat hits the pipeline, damaging it (property damage to the pipeline), oil going into the water o The company that owned the pipeline was not the company that used it to transport oil o Can the oil company sue the pipeline? Bow Bow Valley and Valley Husky Oil get together and set up a 3 rd company offshore (BV Bermuda) in order Allows LaForest and McLachlin the opportunity to form a compromise o It seems that McLachlin has turned her back on the idea of a flexible “just” solution – looks like a political compromise She may have been persuaded that her to get a govt hope for a role for tort law in grant (a tax sophisticated business relations is dodge). BVB hires problematic J to build an oil There may have been a tradeoff – keeping rig. On oil rig, the proximity approach in exchange for there’s a heat finding no liability transferer, with a lot of manufacturer’s Galloway: the situation became worse. At the end though, it seems that LaForest has won the day ISSUE: does manufacturer of heat transferer owe a defects (J in K duty to J to own a duty of fire? YES. Do they owe with heat transfer a duty to the rig (BVB) to warn it may go on fire? builder). Rig goes YES. Do they have a duty to warn those that only Sharon Zheng | LAW 108C | Spring 2012| Donald Galloway on fire – property have an economic interest in the rig (BV and HO) damage. In K, that it may go on fire? Majority: no agreement that even if BVB goes McLachlin o Because it is foreseeable that people will suffer out of commission, financially as a result of any fire, you owe them BV and HO will a duty to warn about that danger still pay the expenses Proximity (looking at the relationship) is out the door – collapsing foreseeability and proximity into Anns test Part 1 (met) o However, this would lead to an indeterminate solution and floodgates issue under Anns test Part 2 o Accepts LaForest’s general rule of exclusion for economic losses, to stop indeterminate liability at Anns Part 2 o Why did we get here? When you are dealing with multi-billion dollar transactions and sophisticated parties setting up large corporate shells, you don’t need tort law as a back up for K law The parties want certainty Parties want K values to operate, and tort values to not interfere Given that there’s no vulnerable parties here and only people who should know what they’re doing, we don’t need tort law here o If we’re building a building and one party is homeowners, we may need tort law to protect homeowners BUT once you’ve tied your economic interests to someone else’s property, you’re not longer a vulnerable person that tort wants to protect o True McLachlin (doesn’t come out here): we Sharon Zheng | LAW 108C | Spring 2012| Donald Galloway should recognize that there can be a source of obligation not tied to vulnerability but instead tied to honourable interactions and dealings and the relationships we form – that’s a very different decision than here NEW CATEGORIES! Design services case o FACTS: a building is about to be built by government At tendering stage, party puts in a bid for themselves, even though it would involves lots of subcontractors Awards contract to a party not entitled to be selected Suit by all the subcontractors that were economically dependent on the bid being accepted Claiming the government has not just wronged the bidder, has harmed the subcontracting individuals o HELD: no Instead of being a dependent company, could have become a joint venture with a bidder, in a contractual relationship Court says that in declining to create K rights – if you’re interested, you should have been formal about it o Court seems to be saying that we don’t want to make tort liability available to those who are in sophisticated commercial transactions – they can protect themselves through K o If a party in an economic relationship has the opportunity to become a contractual party in the cases, then they should do so because the consequences of not doing so would be unknown WHEN SHOULD THE GOVERNMENT BE SUBJECT TO TORT LAW? 1) We have a regime of controlling government (the public law regime) which requires public officials to stay within the bounds of their legal authority o Where govt fails to respect an individual’s rights, dignity, humanity etc., can seek an order from the courts based upon a public wrong Need not rely on the same notion of fault, if they move out of their public law power (have done something they have no legal authority to do) o = TORT LAW NOT NECESSARY – PUBLIC LAW MODEL OF WRONGDOING Sharon Zheng | LAW 108C | Spring 2012| Donald Galloway 2) However, government may provide goods and services like private actors, which may expose people/ their property to danger Seems acceptable to ask whether there is a relationship of proximity in these situations o = TORT LAW NECESSARY – TORT MODEL OF WRONGDOING In Cooper, even though McLachlin opens the notion of duty of care as being based on proximity, the court recognized this tension o Even at the first stage of the Anns test there is a tension between private and public duties If the issue is a mix of 1) and 2), which model of wrongdoing should be used?! THE TORT OF GOVERNMENT LIABILITY Just Arguments: o Arg Driver: breach of duty of care giving rise to this injury, govt Governme nt has taken should be liable o Govt: we own no liability here because the decision is a political one about how we should inspect the cliffs that abut the road charge of We act in a political capacity when we send people to inspect inspecting cliffs – as long as they stay within the boundaries of their highway legal powers, their decisions must be unassailable 99 and trying to negate Do we apply private or public law model? o Cory borrows concept from public law: we can distinguish between good faith decisions and bad faith decisions by government actors the HELD: case sent back to determine standard of care danger of Not focusing on proximity re: the government issue. Instead: rock falls on the o 1) Is the standard of care we expect from government the same as it would be for private actors road. Rock fall occurs, o 2) Whether there are policy reasons not to recognize a duty (Anns 2) hit a car, kill one person and No – the standard is different! Government status can be a reason to immunize a party from tort liability Therefore less of a focus on duty, and greater on standard and policy reasons Sharon Zheng | LAW 108C | Spring 2012| Donald Galloway injures the other Cites Barrat: roads inspected for potholes once every two weeks – day after checking, someone hits a pothole and has an accident. Court draws distinction between negligent inspection (grounds for liability) and a negligent regime of inspection (immune from liability – political decision). Not for the court to tell legislature how much the roads should be inspected o Cory: this is problematic! Surely a decision to inspect every 5 years would be subject to liability … o Tie this in with what he says later about bad faith – because a decision to inspect every 5 years would be a bad faith decision! Bad faith is not about dishonesty, malice (what we usually think of) – it’s the idea that govt have acted for reasons that are way beyond the reasons it’s entitled to act for If you set up a municipality and say the municipality has the right to inspect roads (taking it on and preventing private actors from coming in), you can’t say that there’s a duty only to inspect certain roads, or to inspect every 5 years – because then you’re not really taking on the power! Kind of like the positive duty argument where you have no duty to rescue, but if you do decide to rescue, you have to follow through because you’ve deprived the person of help from other rescuers Cory: governments should be able to make policy decisions free from judicial interference o 1) BUT must be good faith decisions (can’t exercise policy or fail to exercise policy – Kamloops), o 3) AND not every government decision is a policy decision – some are operational – these are held to liability but lower standard Challenge is distinguishing between policy and operational decisions From Heyman: no duty of care in relation to decisions which involve or are dictacted by financial, economic, social or political factors or constraints (P. 273 at the bottom) Trying to articulate where we want govt to be held responsible to the electorate vs. the courts? But it may be otherwise where the crt is assessing Sharon Zheng | LAW 108C | Spring 2012| Donald Galloway action/inaction that is the product of administrative directive o Lighthouse example: economic decision that money formerly spent on lighthouse inspection should now be diverted elsewhere is political and unassailable This would be a bona fide exercise of discretion If the decision was not bona fide (abusing discretion, not based on appropriate reasons), the implication is that it can be subject to tort scrutiny Galloway: Two issues: o 1) Notion of bona fide is hard to define How to you know when and administration is stepping out of its bounds? o 2) The introduction of a new policy may require some public announcement because of reliance issues Galloway: giving far too much power to govt decision making We may see governments making valid political decisions But if govt hasn’t treated members of society well enough by informing them of political decisions, isn’t there a tort? Ex. what if you’re in a boat when the government decides to cut the lighthouse, and you were relying on it? However, in Cooper and later in Hill, using proximity to address these tensions Kamloops Bad faith policy