Review 1: Authority and community in classical and postfoundational theory Leila Dawney Abstract This review surveys classical sociological literature on authority and the production of community alongside more recent postfoundational approaches to set out the parameters for thinking about the concept of “immanent authority”, and in doing so attempts to reinvigorate both the thought and practice of community. This review also identifies and works through some of the important themes in the way in which social theorists have thought about authority, such as foundational myths (Arendt, Honig, Derrida,) augmentation (Arendt, Friedman), experience (Benjamin) and truth (Foucault). Introduction “With the loss of tradition we have lost the thread which safely guided us through the vast realms of the past, but this thread was also the chain fettering each successive generation to a predetermined aspect of the past. It could be that only now will the past open up to us with unexpected freshness and tell us things no-one has yet had ears to hear” (Arendt 1977:91) In this review, authority is considered as a specific type of power that is associated with the founding and formation of community, that is generated through strong community, and that assures people that community and connectivity are real. The philosopher and political theorist Hannah Arendt (1906-1975) argues that the wish for a community without authority is the wish for a despot, seeing to impose a total will on a community without opposition. Authority is considered here in terms of wider “practices”, and the understanding that central to these practices are shared beliefs in the idea of a community (Flathman 1980). In order to show this, the review surveys classical sociological literature on authority and the production of community alongside more recent postfoundational approaches to set out the parameters for thinking about the concept of “immanent authority”, and in doing so attempts to reinvigorate both the thought and practice of community. This review also identifies and works through some of the important themes in the way in which social theorists have thought about authority, such as foundational myths (Arendt, Honig, Derrida,) augmentation (Arendt, Friedman), experience (Benjamin) and truth (Foucault). Legitimacy Authority in social and political thought is commonly used to refer to a specific type of power that is identified through the concept of legitimacy: as a relation of obedience through an appeal to legitimacy (Weber 1964:325). This definition places the concept in opposition to power wielded through coercion 1 or violence. Indeed, the use of coercion or violence may preclude a relationship from being defined as authoritative and moreover may cause the subject of authority to lose that authority: in On Violence Arendt writes that in an authoritative relationship, “neither coercion nor persuasion is needed. (A father can lose his authority either by beating his child or by starting to argue with him, that is, wither by behaving to him like a tyrant or by treating him as an equal” (Arendt 1970:45). Authority is not only produced through social practice: it is also productive of social practice. Authority produces community by placing limits on contingency and thus produces a sort of becoming-together in the practice of producing something solid, something that exists beyond the present (Sennett 1980). As the experience of a power coming from an ‘outside’ (see below), a power beyond the capacities of individuals, authority affirms the possibility of society and transcendence beyond the boundaries of the individual, giving credulity to the promise of community and the escape from singularity. The philosopher Alasdair Macintyre, in the Riddell Memorial Lectures, claimed that “the notion of authority can only find application in a community, and in areas of life in which there is an agreed way of doing things according to accepted rules” (Macintyre 1967:53), arguing for community as a prerequisite for authority, in the sense that what produces community qua community is agreement or a sharing of that which is common, whether that is considered in terms of investment in something that is to come or belief in something that is held to exist. Authority and modernity Many writers have discussed the notion of the loss of authority through modernity – a theme identified in Bertrand de Jouvanal, Schaar, Arendt and Benjamin, for example (Friedman 1990). This is perhaps most famously argued by Hannah Arendt in “What is Authority?”, who claims that “ a constant, everwidening and deepening crisis of authority has accompanied the development of the modern world in our century” (Arendt 1977:91). The authority that Arendt refers to here is a historically specific form – a type of authority of Greco-Roman origin based on an external source understood as a transcendent foundation. In Christian times the idea of hell and eternal damnation was appealed to as this foundation; in Roman times the founding of the Empire. This form of authority gains its power through elders, whose connection to the foundation is testified to and ‘augmented’ through that testimony. Walter Benjamin’s essay “The work of art in the age of its technological reproducibility” focuses on the decline of what he calls the “aura” and the corresponding emergence of a culture based on the ephemeral (Benjamin 2002). Benjamin, a German Marxist and critical theorist writing in the early part of the twentieth century, was concerned with the way in which shifts in modes of production entail shifts of perceptive human apparatuses. Specifically, he explains how the technical reproducibility of the work of art is related to the decline of ‘authenticity’ as a criterion for the appreciation of a work of art. This is understood in terms of the decline of what he calls the “aura” in modernity, meaning that the meaning of the work of art is no longer given by the here and now of its production, nor by the cult value and correlated ideal of eternity that circumscribed the value attached to the work of art. Again, Benjamin associates the destruction of the aura with the rise of totalitarianism in the figure of German Fascism, but also with the possibility of new creative forms of the common. A turn to recent social theory can provide us with a conceptual framework through which to respond to these perceived changes in political formations and in the structure of experience. The changes discussed above suggest that there is an increasing recognition of the constructedness of foundational modes of social organisation, and that this in turn has led to what we might consider as a “politics of contingency” based on immanence. 2 Immanent authority: immanence as a starting point By immanence, we refer to a move in philosophy and social theory towards thinking about a totality that relates to itself, that does not position a transcendent or rely on it as an ahistorical truth. Philosophies of immanence include those by Spinoza, Nietzsche, Foucault, Deleuze and Derrida. Immanence, then is being “without outside”. Instead of a transcendent foundation, a politics of immanence positions a field of technical production that has only itself as a referent. A transcendent ‘outside’ is thus considered as a production of the immanent technologies of truth and knowledge. Deleuze and Guattari in What is Philosophy discuss a “plane of immanence that refuses the possibility of a transcendent. This ultimately has its roots in Spinoza’s notion of substance as an immanent totality, causa sui . (Spinoza 1996). Deleuze and Guattari write: “immanence is immanent only to itself and consequently captures everything, absorbs All-One, and leaves nothing remaining to which it could be immanent. In any case, whenever immanence is interpreted as immanent to Something, we can be sure that this Something reintroduces the transcendent”(Deleuze and Guattari 1994:45). Agamben’s discussion of Deleuze in “pure immanence” also reiterates the nature of immanence as that which does not refer to anything other than itself (Agamben 1999). An engagement with literature on biopolitics and vitalism can also inform thinking about ‘immanent authority’. Foucault’s genealogical work, for example, demonstrates that the problem of immanence preoccupied scholars in a wide variety of fields since as far back as the 1600s. In Discipline and Punish, he charts the emergence of forms of power that, rather than being imposed from outside, are exercised from within. In modernity, techniques for exercising power immanently rather than from a transcendent outside (e.g. a sovereign) proliferate. Indeed, in The Order of Things he had already argued that in modernity the very conditions of possibility of knowledge and experience in the human sciences were transformed by the emergence of three ‘quasi-transcendentals’: language, production, and life. Organic life came to be understood as self-forming, autonomous and, most importantly, effecting a continuous circulation between the inside and outside (i.e. the organism and its milieu) through breathing, eating and so on. Life, as something immanently self-producing, continually transcends its own state of being (1970: 273) Thus in modernity, life – and hence, the human – can only be thought from the perspective of immanence. This does not mean that the transcendent disappears (any more than the emergence of disciplinary power means that sovereign power disappears), but that the transcendent can no longer be opposed to the immanent. Life immanently produces its own outside. Thus, while this concept of life emerged in an attempt to define the human, its self-transcending nature means that it contains within it the possibility of transcending the human itself (1970: 387). The post-humanist turn associated with post-structuralism, then, is not a radical break from the thought of modernity because it is the modern concept of life of self-transcendence that makes post-humanism thinkable. A related perspective on immanence is explored in Simmel’s essay “The transcendent character of life (Simmel 1971). In Simmel, the concept of the transcendent emerges in the transcending of boundaries, and it is these boundaries that give form to social life. The very fact that we become aware of our bounded condition brings out our unbounded condition. Life, for Simmel, is a movement beyond itself. Life exists in both past and future and, as such, constitutes the content of temporality (we experience time precisely because there is life). Further, the nature of life is the perpetual production of and escape from form as a process of self-transcendence. Life has to produce forms and yet it always has to escape and break with forms. Life is as such both always more-life and more-than-life, transcendent in itself: a process of immanent transcendence. Thus Simmel develops a theory of life that, rather than opposing immanence to transcendence, argues that the outside is itself created immanently. ”To climb beyond oneself in growth and reproduction, to sink below oneself in old age and death – these are not additions 3 to life, but such rising up and spilling over the boundaries of the individual condition constitutes life itself. Perhaps the whole immortality of man simply signifies the accumulated feeling, heightened for once into a huge symbol, for this self-transcendence of life” (Simmel 1971:369). In figuring life as a stream proceeding through generations – flowing through, or as, individuals, the subject is once again displaced as the origin and focus on movement of power, and instead the concept of life becomes important. As for Foucault, and Bergson, too, the concept of life in Simmel is that which exceeds the individual, and exceeds that which can be encountered through the phenomenological subject. Life as object of power, then, transcends what can be captured and enables new regimes of capture. life is an ongoing battle against form – against the closing, “between continuity and individuality” (Simmel 1971:367). Jean-Luc Nancy , similarly, argues that a key problem faced in modernity is the response to immanence. He argues for a reading of totalitarianism, for example, as an ‘immanentism’ whose rationality forms ‘the general horizon of our time’ (Inoperative Community, p. 3). Immanentism is a mode of thought that is oriented towards a fusion of community – a creation of a single communal body or population – leading to a ‘goal of achieving a community of beings producing in essence their own essence as their work, and furthermore producing precisely this essence as community’ (p. 2). In his joint work with Philippe Lacoue-Labarthe in The Literary Absolute, he traces aspects of the genealogy of immanentism through a study of 18th and 19th century Romanticism, charting the emergence of an ideal of community as an organic artwork, a community that is wholly immanent to itself: self-producing, continually expanding, and reaching out towards the Absolute. In contrast to such logics of immanence, Nancy formulates a concept of ‘trans-immanence’ where existence cannot be thought in terms of immanence and transcendence (interiority and exteriority), but must be approached through more complex spatial vocabularies (e.g. position, distance, spacing touch, tact, contact) that can better express a thinking of ‘being-with’ as an excess or exposure of singularities, rather than as fusion of identities (The Sense of the World: page number?). Deconstructive thinking and a politics of immanence can lead to the exposure of that outside as something that has its origins in the politics of its own production, yet is projected as an idea of an outside. Indeed, in thinking in these terms we can perhaps begin to conceive of authoritative relations based on contingency rather than permanence, and which no longer rely on the position of God or an outside in order to function. What this means, then, is that the loss of authority in modernity may only simply be the loss of a chimera. Honig poses Arendt’s problem thus: “How can we establish lasting foundations without appealing to gods, a fundamentalist ground, or an absolute” (Honig 1991:88)? We wish to consider the technologies through which authority can be produced such that one can consider how authority can take place that does not rely on a foundation. Recent poststructural writing on authority has demonstrated that all forms of authority, when traced back, are based on an absence, or an aporia at the foundational moment. We have seen, through the writing of poststructuralist thinkers such as Foucault, Derrida and Deleuze, how the foundational basis for authority can be undone, and moreover, that a foundational basis for ethics and judgment becomes problematic. It is now for us to consider, then, where this leaves us in terms of building communities and providing technologies and practices of authority-production. An exploration in to recent social theory can inform us that the foundations upon which authority was seen to lie are always immanently produced as such: they are always products of various practices and technologies of authority production. However, this is not to say that foundational authority is no longer with us; indeed it is still one of the main ways in which authoritative relations take place. For example, where Arendt 4 considers the statements of the US constitution as purely performative, and as a result not based on a foundational outside, Honig, through a consideration of Derrida’s deconstruction of the US Declaration of Independence, points to fact that the Declaration still resorts to the logic of the foundation through the recourse to the idea of “nature’s god”, and through the use of the constative rather than the performative in order to appeal to the weightiness it seeks (Honig 1991). During modernity, we have become more aware of the immanent production of authority and the way in which foundations, outsides and the past are contingently produced in the present and in the contest of immanence, out of a community of practice rather than a foundation. This is not to uncritically celebrate a relativistic account of multiple narratives; rather, to recognize in the contemporary world a confluence of positive and affirmative movements towards self-transcendence, as well as tendencies towards fascistic, or saturated control. Arendt and Benjamin offer not so much a lamentation on the loss of authority, but rather a hope, a glimmer of possibility for new forms of authority to emerge from a transformation in structures of experience and technological grounds that draw on a politics of contingency. Benjamin suggests that this opens up a novel horizon for experience, based on the ephemeral instead of the eternal, and in which the reception of the work of art is open and contingent. While not specifically a text on political authority, what Benjamin charts the decline of is those very systems and modes of experience through which authority gains its power: the decline of tradition and permanence in favour of the ephemeral. However the possibilities that lie in the contingent politics of modernity also, for Arendt and Benjamin, can lead to dangers. For example, while Arendt positions the performative foundation of the US constitution as an idealisation of authority, she notes how authority can also be the context of totalitarianism, both in terms of Fascism and State socialism. Similarly, Benjamin celebrates the possibility of utopian communism that a politics of contingency could invite, while also citing it as the context of the rise of Fascism. For Benjamin, this promise and danger emerges from modernity’s increased sense of the ‘universal equality of things’ (Benjamin 2002) that harbours both revolutionary energy but also a growing ability to manipulate entire masses as calculable, statistical bodies. It is this emphasis on calculability that Foucault draws out in much more detail in his work on biopolitics (e.g. Security, Territory & Population). He observes how the advance of statistical techniques from the eighteenth century led to a growing body of knowledge concerning the nature of the human population, the normal distribution of disease, scarcity, crime, death etc, and how it could be governed as an organic totality without restricting the individual freedoms of any of its constituent members. Populations could be governed by proliferating contingency rather than eliminating it. Thus the immanence of a biological population could be controlled by altering its milieu or environment. The arrangement of space – most importantly, towns and cities – became one crucial means through which the immanence of a population could be controlled (Security, Territory and Population, Lecture One). Immanent life became a key object of power – but also an important site of resistance and practices of freedom. Biopolitical rationalities enable a thinking of life in terms of beauty, for example (in the Kantian sense of beauty as a free interplay of the faculties) that creates one resource from which to refuse the contemporary constitution of the individual and communal self (Foucault, The Use of Pleasure). This section has outlined what is meant by the terms “immanence” and a “politics of contingency” in order to prepare the ground for thinking about authority in the light of these theoretical moves. It has suggested that an ontology of immanence can help to expose the conditions of production of those ideas and forces positioned as transcendental, and also that the perceived decline in authority is actually related to a decline in belief in transcendentals. To begin with an ontology of contingency, then enables a review of theories of authority production that can shed light on the techniques and technologies through which authority is produced and what this means in terms of thinking about community production. 5 Theories of how authority is produced. Sennett, Friedman and the common As Macintyre suggests above, the notion of authority can be understood as presupposing a relationship with the idea of community or of the common (Macintyre 1967). Authority and community are seen to emerge from relations between people that produce some idea of the common. The sociologist Richard Sennett, a key writer on authority and author of Authority (1980) has a positive view of authority and its role in social cohesion, arguing that authority is both useful and important and acts as an emotional bond in modern society; as such it is necessary for society’s functioning (Sennett 1980). Sennett’s argument is that the study of authority ties together psychology and politics, since it is primarily concerned with an emotional and affective relation that is involved in the production of specific and political forms. He also argues for authority as a “way of expressing care for others”, and suggests that a need for authority is concerned with a need for someone to express care for us (Sennett 1980:15). Authority answers a desire for stability and order, for defiance in the face of time, in the same way that a monument can stand as a symbol that power will last “beyond the generation which now rules and the generation which now obeys” (Sennett 1980:18). Sennett argues that authority can be figured as something to strive towards – as a dream rather than something that exists objectively and as such is open to analysis. It is the dream of authority that is important for cohesive social life, as well as its living out: “Authority, however, is itself inherently an act of imagination. It is not a thing; it is a search for solidity and security in the strength of others which will seem to be like a thing. To believe the search can be consummated is truly an illusion, and a dangerous one. Only tyrants fit the bill. But to believe the search should not be conducted at all is also dangerous. Then, whatever is, is absolute” (Sennett 1980:197). In his study of the idea of authority in political philosophy, Richard B. Friedman identifies two approaches to the idea of the common in classical social theory that have an impact on how authority is conceptualised. Firstly, he argues that political institutions have authority if people believe they reflect their own beliefs or embody shared beliefs. In this view of the substance of the common, shared norms and values are central to the production of authority, and this is of course associated with consensus theories such as those of Durkheim and Parsons. The breakdown of consensus in society is then intrinsically linked to the loss of authority, and as such those who write on authority’s loss, such as Arendt, can be placed in this school (Friedman 1990). The second way of conceptualising the common does not assume shared beliefs, but instead focuses on the state regulation of conduct which becomes a social contract with members of society (e.g. Hobbes, Spinoza and Mill). Where someone is considered “an authority”, Friedman argues, there is a presupposed world of common beliefs and the recognition of inequality in the capacity of men to understand those beliefs” (Friedman 1990:84). Where there is a relation of “in authority” there is a presupposition of a “world of conflicting opinions and the recognition that all opinions are equally ‘private’, no one having a claim in its own right to organise society” (Friedman 1990:84-5). Here, a distinction is made between a personalised bestowal of authority onto another, and a form of authority based on the social contract and on a belief in the system through which the subject of authority acquires its authoritative status. Authority is thus understood as a means of exploring the substance of cohesion/unity in societies, and Friedman argues that the substance of the authoritative relation is inextricably tied to the way in which a sense of the common is formed, and hence its implicit relation to ideas of community. In the first definition, an a priori community of values is assumed, while in the second a community of interests emerges. 6 Judgment, legitimacy and community: structural accounts of authoritative relations. Weber, Friedman and Lukes offer to us a formal, structuralist account of the way in which authority works in social systems, of the emergence of specific relations through these claims to legitimacy. Weber also suggests that those subject to authority need to have an interest in the “continuation and the continual reactivation of the community” - in other words, there needs to be personal motives for the re-creation of community and authority which is part of the recognition of and listening to authority (Weber 1964:370). Max Weber’s (1864-1920) famous account of authority in Economy and Society focuses on what produces the authoritative figure and as such involves a descriptive breakdown of the authoritative relation into three ideal types: rational/legal, traditional and charismatic. The ideal types are distinguished in terms of the basis for their legitimation: the substance of claim made to legitimacy. In Weber, then, obedience to or acceptance of authority is a result of the belief in the legitimacy of an authoritative relation. Authority is not based on whether the contractual nature of the authoritative relation is voluntary or involuntary (here he makes reference to the relationship between the soldier and commanding officer), or to do with power wielded through economic might. Instead, legitimacy is measured by the probability that attitudes match conduct, and ensure conduct relates to command. “What is important is the fact that in a given case the particular claim to legitimacy is to a significant degree and according to its type treated as ‘valid’” (Weber 1964:327). In the case of rational/legal authority, the claims for legitimacy are made on rational grounds. Claims for legitimacy are based on an abstract set of rules or norms, and roles are placed in order to perform/enact this. These roles are considered as necessary for the functioning of the system. Figures of authority in this case occupy an “office” based on their position in the bureaucratic order rather than on their qualities or lineage. In rational/legal authority there is a separation of the personal and the official, and obedience to authority takes place by the subject as a member of a status group. Here, hierarchical systems of authority are in operation. Weber gives the example of a military structure or priesthood. Weber’s definition of legal-rational authority captures well the imagination of the law. Obedience is not to the figure of the leader, but to the impersonal order – the set of rules and a generalised agreement on the rationality of those rules. The authority of the law in this sense is legitimate (it is obeyed not enforced) authority in that it is grounded upon a belief in rationality and actualised in an administrative order. Traditional authority is grounded on belief in the sanctity of immemorial traditions, and as such involves a temporality that is quite distinct from the other forms. The sanctity of the order is handed down – central to this is the notion that these practices and relations “have always existed” (Weber 1964:341). Obedience here can be based on a more personal relation than in rational/legal authority – for example through bonds of loyalty. Rather than members of a group, subjects of authority are considered subjects or comrades, their allegiance based on “not the impersonal obligation of office, but personal loyalty to the chief” (Weber 1964:341). Legitimacy is maintained through a) traditions that determine the content of the command and b) the chief’s decisions – through personal loyalty. Authority can be granted to others by chiefs in a top down system of authority bestowal. For example, a knight may be granted authority over a particular fiefdom. The third ground for legitimacy is manifest in the concept of charismatic authority: based on a “sanctity, heroism or exemplary character” of a charismatic leader (Weber 1968:215). The leader is driven by a “call” rather than being appointed. There are no administrative organs in the pure form of this type of authority. The domain of the charismatic necessarily stands outside of the profane or everyday. It is not based on rational systems – indeed is foreign to all rules, lying in the relationship between leaders and 7 followers. Similarly, it eschews economic power and is described by Weber as an “anti-economic force” (Weber 1964:362). In modernity, according to Weber, democratisation and bureaucratisation go together through the separation of the person from the office held by that person characterised by the move from charismatic or traditional models of authority to rational-legal models. With the move to permanence from charismatic authority, Weber argues, the two other types of authority need to move in and fill the role, since charismatic authority is by definition new and always self-recreating. It “may be said to exist only in the process of originating” (Weber 1964:364). In Weber, then, belief in the grounds upon which the authoritative relation is built is central to an understanding and analysis of authority. In Weber’s account of authority, belief in the legitimacy of the authoritative structure is essential for authority and this is what makes it different from coercion. “Every system attempts to establish and to cultivate the belief in its own legitimacy” (Weber 1964:325). As a supplement to this broadly descriptive account, Friedman maintains that the distinction between belief and conduct is central to an analysis of authority, where the combination of belief and conduct rather than conduct alone is what distinguishes an authoritative relationship. (Friedman 1990:57). In this way, as in Weber, belief and conduct are necessary in the authoritative relation: conduct alone is not sufficient. Authority can thus be understood as taking place through the act of bestowing – through a listening which is not coerced, but rather emerges as a result of the subject positions produced in the authoritative relation. Authority is not imposed upon, rather it is given as those subject to authority accept the position of those in authority and listen to what they have to say. As such it has a direct relationship with knowledge and the production of truth, which is explored later in this review, particularly through the work of Foucault. Authority can be seen to inhabit the space between knowledge and truth, and as such is dependent on the assumption of unequal access to knowledge and truth. The emphasis on knowledge and inequality on writing on authority is also clear in Arendt, who understands authority as based on a relation of inequality of legitimate access to knowledge (Arendt 1970). In a similar fashion, the listening that is central to the authoritative relationship is discussed by Friedman in terms of a “special and distinctive kind of dependence on the will or judgment of another so well conveyed by the notion of ‘surrender of private judgment;” (Friedman 1990:68). This concept of the surrender of private judgment comes initially from Mill’s essay on Tocqueville. In this way, Friedman asserts that “to cite authority as a reason for doing an act (or believing an opinion) is to put a stop to the demand for reasons at the level of the act itself, and to transfer reason to an other person’s will or judgment” (Friedman 1990:67). In this way, then, the authoritative relationship is conceived from the point of view of those who give authority and accede to it: authority is produced through listening, surrender and the recognition of unequal access to knowledge and wisdom. Counter to this, however, Richard Flathman argues in The Practice of Political Authority that the notion of surrender of judgment is misleading (Flathman 1980:124) and suggests that bestowing authority involves evidence and reason and therefore judgment. In other words, the bestowal of authority involves not so much a surrender of judgment as a judgment of who to listen to and trust based on evidence and reason. Arendt and augmentation Arendt notes how the word authority, from the Latin auctoritas, shares its root with augere, to augment. Augmentation, through various techniques and figures, is what produces and maintains the authoritative relation. These techniques and practices might include discursive articulation and rearticulations, repetition through ritual practices, or sedimentation in the habits and common sense practices of everyday life. Such practices of authority establish future referents for collective life by reinterpreting the past. Authority carries something into the present – to “add to what existed before, 8 as a witness adds to the thing his testimony about the thing”. (Gladstone 1829 in Friedman 1990:75). Authority then becomes an intermediary between those subject to its power and a foundation upon which that power rests. This has focused our attention onto the practices and techniques of the authoritative relation as performative of itself, through this concept of augmentation. The etymological roots of authority are helpful in understanding Arendt’s account of the decline of the specific form of authority she follows through the Roman reinterpretation of Greek political authority with the forming of the city state as foundation of authority and her association of the political crisis of her contemporary world with a rise in totalitarianism. She argues that, in modernity, as the foundational reference points augmented through traditions become unstable, the social is divested of the capacity to give form to a being beyond individual being, or what we might consider to be community. Foundational authority, which as we have seen is intrinsically tied to the idea of community, becomes impossible under the conditions of modernity. For Arendt, the foundational moment is positioned in terms of a need to cope with finitude – as a way of dealing with mortality and as a way of addressing the problem of memory as a means of holding on to the past. The production of continuity through the idea of permanence and durability in her account of authority enables the continuity of life. As such, authority resides in the technologies of preserving time – such as the technologies of testimony, both written and oral, which link past and present through providing partial access to the excess of the foundational moment, as well as through tradition as preserved in institutions such as education systems. Testimony enables collective memory – a collective witness to the foundation and therefore a link to that foundation, in a similar way to Sennett’s figuring of the comfort of the monument in its ability to outlive present life (Sennett 1980:18-19). The authority of the foundation is augmented through the handing down of the testimony of the founders from generation to generation. Authority is thus conceived as a specific relation, reliant on an outside, on something transcendent that establishes that authority and upon which the authoritative relation ultimately depends: “The source of authority in authoritarian government is always a force external and superior to its own power; it is always this source, this external force which transcends the political realm, from which the authorities derive their “authority”, that is, their legitimacy, and against which their power can be checked” (Arendt 1977:97). This transcendent outside might take the form of a religious foundation, or laws of nature, or Platonic ideas. Authority is governed by and appeals to an outside. The authoritative relation, however, does not reside in the outside; nevertheless it relies on the outside for its legitimacy. Authoritative relations testify to the power of the outside - to the foundation - through the positioning of certain subjects and institutions as having a privileged access to the foundation, and it is this practice of testifying to that foundation through which authority is bestowed and also through which it is augmented. The authority of the foundation is thus positioned as an outside, as an exteriority which wields no power itself, yet enables power through reference to this outside. The externality is in excess of itself, it can never be reached in entirety, and is accessed only through the testimony of those who in some way witnessed the foundational moment. “Tradition preserved the past by handing down from one generation to the next the testimony of the ancestors, who first had witnessed and created the sacred founding and then augmented it by their authority throughout the centuries. As long as this tradition was uninterrupted, authority was inviolate; and to act without authority and tradition, without accepted, timehonoured standards and models, without the help of the wisdom of the founding fathers, was inconceivable” (Arendt 1977:124). To understand authority in terms of its augmentation is central to understanding it in terms of practice. To figure authority as techniques and technologies through which it emerges in an ongoing self9 production enables an analysis of the conditions and practices through which authority emerges and positions it as something that happens, rather than something that simply exists. Foucault, the subject and authority The writing of Foucault on the subject and power is also central to thinking about the way in which the authoritative relation has been theorised. The concepts of subjectivation and subject production, in particular, can help elucidate the conditions through which the authoritative relation is produced. In Foucault’s work, the mechanisms of historically specific regimes of truth become inseparable from the cultivation of particular disciplines and technologies of the self, which are mutually constitutive of the specificity and reach of power. Foucault enables thinking about the ‘conditions of possibility’ (Foucault 2001:xxiv, 183, 265) of a particular relation, and of the regimes, rationalities and truth games through which the possibility for the authoritative relation emerges. Foucault understands power not as violence, nor consent. Rather, it is a ‘total structure of actions brought to bear upon possible actions; it incites, induces, and seduces … and in the extreme constrains or forbids absolutely (Foucault 1982:790). In this definition, power is nevertheless always a way of “acting upon an acting subject or acting subjects by virtue of their acting or being capable of action” (Foucault 1982:790). Foucault employs the term ‘conduct’ to understand the specificity of power relations, which refers at one and the same time to the capacity to lead others (e.g. according to mechanisms of coercion), and way of behaving within a more or less open field of possibilities. Hence the exercise of power consists in guiding the possibility of conduct and putting in order the possible outcome: “this form of power applies itself to immediate everyday life which categorises the individual, marks him by his own individuality, attaches him to his own identity, imposes a law of truth on him which he must recognise and which others have to recognise in him. It is a form of power which makes individuals subjects” (Foucault 1982:781). In the particular form of political rationality which Foucault traces genealogically to an ensemble of procedures, tactics and instruments which emerged during the eighteenth century, “population” is constituted both as an object of government and as the collective bearer of certain rights, belonging to particular notions of collective well-being, or “life” (Foucault 1978). In this new form of power, “biopolitics”, subjects are simultaneously subjected to a law of truth which imposes certain relations and responsibilities in relation to social problems, and, by means of the same individualised selfrelations, invested with the capacity to “refuse what we are” and thereby produce new forms of subjectivity (Foucault 1982:782). From this point onwards, the structuring of the possible field of action is understood to be inseparable from the establishment of transversal links between institutions, political-economic rationalities, and modes of reflection directed towards the preservation of freedom and prosperity. Foucault’s concepts of subjectivation are useful for thinking about the production of subjects of and to authority, and the concept of biopower and population life for a thinking about a transpersonal and posthuman account of authority production. Through these analyses, Foucault displaces the authoritative relation by considering it as the effect of particular processes. For example, in positioning power as what produces bodies, Foucault critiques the idea of the subject and in doing so attempts to free the “history of thought from its subjection to transcendence” (Merquior 1985:17). The subject is destabilised and repositioned as an effect of processes of subjectification. In this way, subjectivation becomes the process through which productive power works: “it is not power but the subject which is the general theme of my research” (Foucault 1982:778). 10 To think with Foucault enables us to analyse relations between knowledge, values and social change in a manner sensitive to both the historical specificity sought by Weber and Arendt, and also the capacities of bodies for desire and the will to act. Foucault’s critique of the foundational subject and of a pure interior to the subject focuses on bodies not as originators of ways of being and acting but as nodes, or points of contact in networks of power relations: bodies as part of technologies of control that can be analysed accordingly, and whose pleasures too are produced in the service of power (Foucault 1978, 1988, 1992). As such, the subject is displaced from being origin of experience of authority and community to that which is produced through the regimes of truth and power that are the substance of authoritative relations. Foucault does away with depth in favour of an account of the social that is a constant production of surface effects, a play of surfaces over the movement of bodies, matter and knowledge. It is Deleuze who perhaps most clearly discusses this surfacing in Foucault’s work, when he writes that the outside is not a fixed limit but a moving matter animated by peristaltic movements, folds and foldings that together make up an inside: they are not something other than the outside, but precisely the inside of the outside (Deleuze 1988:80). This is perhaps clearest in his often cited discussion of the soul as subjectification in Discipline and Punish: the soul as effect of an apparatus that surveys, supervises, coerces and regulates, an effect of a “certain technology of power over the body” that is produced out of methods of punishment, supervision and restraint… [and that] inhabits [the subject] and brings him (sic) to existence, which is itself a factor in the mastery that power exercises over the body. The soul is the effect and instrument of a political anatomy; the soul is the prison of the body (Foucault 1979:29). Here, the ‘soul’ emerges as a surface effect that effaces the idea of the inside. Foucault moves towards a consideration of the body as materialising power in a way that disrupts the foundational subject of Western thought through analyses of the processes through which subjects are produced - the techniques and technologies of subjectivation (assujetissement) - and at the same time that does away with the possibility of positing an outside to the power/knowledge relations that are produced through and produce materialities. He finds a way to escape any attempt to “grasp the ineffable moment of origin, the primitive intention of authors” (Foucault 1972:138-40), instead positioning the subject as always already embedded in relations of power (Foucault 1982). In his discussion of Foucault and governmentality, Mitchell Dean writes of the ways in which subjectivation and objectivation are involved in the production of authority and how government occurs through the production of subjects who are able to produce and reproduce, through their conduct, the authoritative relationship. He notes how “the establishment of an interior domain is thus dependent on the enfolding of external authority” (Dean 1996:222). In particular, he refers to the governing substance as the material that is worked on in this enfolding, and the governing work, which relates to the “means, techniques, rationalities, forms of knowledge and expertise that are used to accomplish the enfolding of authority” (Dean 1996:222-3). In doing so, we can see that subjectivation is only part of the story. It is also necessary to consider “the relation between the forms of truth by which we have come to know ourselves and the forms of practice by which we seek to shape the conduct of ourselves and others” (Dean 1996:220). These observations open up the possibility to consider authority as no longer a relation between people alone, but instead as to do with knowledge production and those regimes of truth through which bodies and subjects are produced. Instead of beginning with people, or subject positions, we are able to begin with the conditions of possibility through which those people/subjects come to be produced as such, 11 and with the processes through which the authoritative relation becomes recognised. Authority can thus be considered in terms of the recognition of a gap between knowledge and truth: and an interrogation of how that gap is realised through differential access to knowledges which are considered nearer or further to truth. The analysis of authority, then, is reformulated and displaced through a focus not on the figures of authority themselves, but on the regimes through which some bodies come to be considered as figures of authority and through which some come to be produced as those who listen, recognise and respect that authority. Foucault also writes about looking at where power does not encompass all – where resistance to power emerges as being a way of shedding light on how it works in other situations. In looking at authoritative relations which have “broken down,”, then, we can consider more about the processes through which authority is figured. “rather than analysing power from the point of view of its internal rationality, it consists of analysing power relations through the antagonism of strategies” (Foucault 1982:780). Deleuze and Derrida: ethics, combat and deconstruction Finally, we move to the writing of Deleuze and Derrida in order to offer new ways of thinking authority after the negation of the foundation. In “Force of Law: the mystical foundation of authority”, Derrida writes on the problem of justice and deconstruction, asking whether it is indeed possible to think deconstructively about justice (Derrida 1990), and what is positioned as a foundation and a truth if we do away with thinking about truth. Derrida suggests in this text that deconstruction always implies the question of justice, even when it is approached obliquely: “Deconstruction, while seeming not to “address” the problem of justice, has done nothing but address it, if only obliquely, unable to do so directly” (Derrida 1990:935). This post-Nietzschean approach to ethics is also considered in Deleuze’s “To have done with judgment” as containing a way of considering the production of knowledge through what he refers to as “combat”. As we have seen above, Friedman conceptualises authority in terms of a surrender of judgment to another. Here Deleuze argues for the specificity of the consideration of justice and judgment together, arguing that justice does not necessitate judgment, and that in this recognition lies the possibility of opening up a space for justice through what he calls “combat”. Deleuze argues that there can be a justice that is opposed to all judgment – the justice of combat. This is a justice that is opposed to judgment: “a system of blood and life that is opposed to the writing of the book” (Deleuze 1997:128). Deleuze argues that judgment is a historical product of Christianity. Against judgement, combat is about the body, about experience, about the affective intensities that build in certain situations. The logic of combat involves a move towards the body without organs, “an affective, intensive, anarchist body that consists solely of poles, zones, thresholds, and gradients” (Deleuze 1997:131). Combat replaces judgment, the will to power, the “powerful, nonorganic vitality that supplements force with force, and enriches whatever it takes hold of” (Deleuze 1997:133). These two texts call into question the ethical foundations for authority and open up the possibility for discussion about what values, what ethical tenets can be set that provide a way in which to produce communities. Derrida writes that the authority of the law contains within it the spectre of force – there is no law without its possibility of enforcement – and, as a result, the concept of justice, upon which the law is based, contains within it always the possibility of force. This is particularly true of the English phrase, to enforce the law, which, as Derrida points out, loses its power in the French idiom “appliquer la loi”. This linguistic slippage, as Derrida points out in his discussion of Benjamin’s “Zur Kritik der 12 Gewalt”, also emerges in the German. The text is translated as “Critique of violence”, yet, as Derrida points out, gewalt also refers to legitimate power, public force and authority. In “Force of Law: the mystical foundation of authority”, Derrida also considers the aporia at the foundation of the law and of its authority through the recognition that at the moment of foundation there is nothing to appeal to. Referring to a term used by Montaigne’s and adopted by Pascal, Derrida discusses how the fondement mystique de l’autorite refers to this aporia: “custom is the sole basis for equity,for the simple reason that it is received; it is the mystical foundation for authority. Whoever traces it to its source annihilates it” (Derrida 1990:939). As he points out: “Justice, in the sense of droit (right or law) would not simply be put in the service of a social force or power, for example an economic, political, ideological power that would exist outside or before it and which it would have to accommodate or bend to when useful. Its very moment of foundation or institution (which in any case is never a moment inscribed in the homogeneous tissue of a history, since it is ripped apart with one decision), the operation that consists of founding, inaugurating, justifying law (droit), making law, would consist of a coup de force, of a performative and therefore interpretative violence that in itself is neither just nor unjust and that no justice and no previous law with its founding anterior moment could guarantee or contradict or invalidate” (Derrida 1990:941-3). Authority, then, becomes a “violence without a ground” (Derrida 1990:943). Deconstructing the grounds of authority thus reveals its nonfoundational nature and calls for attention to be paid not to the means through which it not only appears as foundational, but how those foundations are produced as such through technology and practice. It also draws attention to the power of the performative in the production of authority. Arendt argues that the performative nature of the formation of the US constitution is a positive example of authority production that does not rely on an outside. Derrida’s ‘Signature, Event, Context’ discusses the force of the performative, arguing that the performative has force precisely in its break from structure as a force de rupture (Derrida 1988) . Using the example of Rosa Parks, Butler writes how the sheer lack of iteration in her act of sitting in the front of the bus, without prior right provided a break that opened up new forms of authority: “in laying claim to the right for which she had no prior authorisation, she endowed a certain authority on the act, and began the insurrectionary process of overthrowing those established codes of legitimacy” (Butler 1997:147) . This is an interesting case in point, however, as we could also argue that her authority relied on the legitimacy bestowed upon the act by the political community of those who felt she should have a legitimate right to do what she did. In other words, the performative authority attached to the act was not in isolation, and did not come from nowhere. Nancy: spacing, community and technics Another thinker that administers to the issue of immanent authority is the French philosopher Jean-Luc Nancy. Nancy, like Deleuze in his effort to be done with judgment, sees the search for nonfoundational authority as an ethical project. His philosophy incorporates the aporias and indeterminacies of poststructuralism into a phenomenology that critiques the very ground of phenomenological thought. Nancy’s philosophy argues for an ontology of ‘singular–plural’ existence – an ontology that is based on being among others but implying no relation of gathering. Being cannot be thought of without beingwith, as the primary ontological condition: “Being cannot be anything but being-with-one-another, circulating in the with and as the with of this singular-plural existence” (Nancy 2000:3). Being-with, and the idea of being as singular-plural, raises the question of the possibility of thinking the body or the subject in isolation. Being can only be thought through being-with. Being-with for Nancy implies no sense of similarity between bodies, any recourse to identity politics or ethics: rather it is an ontological state of opening out onto the world, of the production of time and space through this 13 movement - what Nancy sees as the spacing of the world. Moreover it is only through being-with that we are capable of thinking about individuals and groups. Being-with occurs prior to the determination of space and time, prior to the individual. It operates as divisions and entanglements – intertwinings and dispersions. It is what makes space and time possible, and also the possibility of thinking about individuals and societies, which are understood as hypostatisations of the primary being-with. Being-with, the “co-”, the “mit-”, is a spacing, an opening out of the world. Being-with, however, can apply to one who is alone. Indeed, to be alone, for Nancy, is to be alone-with (Nancy 2005). Being-with is a condition for being-alone. The ontological separation implied by Nancy’s concept of spacing as opening out can bring about a move away from foundational identity politics and towards a new politics of singularity, since the gathering implied by identity politics and the logic of the nation and the political group can be displaced through this move. Nancy’s writing on community intends to refigure the concept of community such that it enables a posthuman, post-identity politics reading of the idea of the common. Taking the ontological being-with as a starting point, Nancy repositions community as that which occurs through a shared sense of finitude – a shared relation to death, rather than an identarian grounding in similar nationality or ethnic group. Nancy attempts to formulate an experience of community which does not retreat to the level of the individual, and which bypasses and challenges a metaphysics of the subject. In doing so, he critiques the idea of community as that which is lost – a prior mode of being that nostalgia is felt for – and instead positions community as that which stands in the realm of the to-come. “community is possible, in the first instance, and on a primordial level, only as a kind of rupturing or dispersion, which is itself constitutive of the sharing or communication proper to the being-in-common of the communal. The experience of rupture or dispersal, that is, the separation of those entities which are “in common” in community, would be, according to this account, precisely that which allows them to be exposed to each other, to communicate and to share an existence” (James 2006:176). Nancy’s critique of the idea of community is directed in particular towards the notion that community is something which has become lost in modernity and needs to be regained. Nostalgia for community is thus deconstructed as being based on an idea of community which itself is contingent, this deconstruction itself enables a rethinking of the concept of community and of the common. Nancy argues that one cannot subsume the singular in-common into a communal project or collective identity. Rather, community lies in the shared experience of finitude: “community reveals, or rather is, our exposure to the unmasterable limit of death, and thus our being together outside of all identity, or work of subjectivity” (James 2006:185). Community is the “fundamental “being-with” of those singularities, and not as a collection of individual subjects who bind themselves together on the basis of a shared identity” (James 2006:177). This has significant implications for the study of authority and community, insofar that a politics of the common, of the with, the co-, the mit- that is not based on identity but on shared spacing, can emerge from such thinking. Nancy’s work invites a consideration of foundationless ethics that are based on the refusal of the sovereign, or of identity politics in favour of a solidarity-based ethics: a being-together that dissolves the I or the you and replaces it with the we. However, Nancy's chapter “War, sovereignty, right, technē”, describes a world where the foundation has been replaced by technē, or ecotechnics, which can broadly be considered in terms of a political economy without a sovereign. The sovereign, as foundational authority, although it is displaced by technē, still reappears as a spectre filling the space where the sovereign lay. So for Nancy the problem lies in thinking without foundation, allowing for a new ethics, an ethics based on the ontology of spacing 14 and opening out of meaning. This ethics, then, as a utopian project, is perhaps more consonant with the world emerging through ecotechnics than the world working on the logic of the displaced sovereign. A move towards an ethics of spacing, a world where the empty space of the sovereign is allowed to remain empty, then, may lead to a less dissonant experience of the world and the possibility of a new ethics without foundation. The argument made by Nancy around the decline of Sovereign law is that sovereign authority is being undermined by ecotechnics. He argues that there is a gap in the efficacy of sovereign law in its grounding of claims for authority lying on foundational grounds (blood and soil, for example) which opens up the possibility of what he calls the spacing of the world. For Nancy, the field of experience provided by the link of techne and finitude – which implies a radical affirmation of our technicity – may provide the grounds for the spacing of the world as something that can fill the empty space of law and of justice. Conclusion This review has explored the work of various thinkers on the subject of authority through the lens of what might be considered an ontology of immanence. In doing so, it has attempted to show how the authoritative relation is produced through legitimacy, surrender of judgement, performative acts and the projection of foundations. In combining structural and poststructural accounts, the review intends to demarcate a specific field for thinking about authority and immanence that takes into account the work of social theorists such as Sennett, Weber and Arendt, yet supplements it through the thought of writers such as Derrida, Nancy and Deleuze. As such, the review prepares the ground for further thinking about the ethics and aesthetics of the authoritative relation, and also for thinking specifically about the experience of authority in the light of postfoundational thought. For example, one can investigate the substance and conditions of emergence of those beliefs and motives referred to by Weber in his account of types of authority. This would involve a consideration of the production of subjects and particular forms of life and how this can help to theorise the way in which authoritative relations and subject positions are produced. This involves a consideration of the conditions for their appearance, and specific rationalities through which these forms of authority are generated such that they appear as powerful motivations for action. Agamben, G. (1999). Absolute Immanence. Potentialities: Collected Essays in Philosophy. D. HellerRoazen. Stanford, CA, Stanford University Press: 220-235. Arendt, H. (1970). On Violence. New York, Harcourt Publishers. Arendt, H. (1977). What Is Authority? Between Past and Future: Eight Exercises in Political Thought. H. Arendt. Harmondsworth, Penguin: 91-142. Benjamin, W. (2002). The Work of Art in the Age of Its Technological Reproducability. Walter Benjamin: Selected Writings Vol 3, 1935-1938. H. Eiland and M. Jennings. Cambridge: Massachusetts, Harvard University Press: 101-133. Butler, J. (1997). Excitable Speech: Politics of the Performative. London, Routledge. Dean, M. (1996). Foucault, Government and the Enfolding of Authority. Foucault and Political Reason. A. Barry, T. Osborne and N. Rose. London, UCL Press. Deleuze, G. (1988). Foucault. Minneapolis and London, University of Minnesota Press. Deleuze, G. (1997). To Have Done with Judgment. Essays Critical and Clinical. Minneapolis, University of Minnesota Press: 125-135. Deleuze, G. and F. Guattari (1994). What Is Philosophy? London, Verso. Derrida, J. (1988). Limited Inc. Evanston, IL, Northwestern University Press. 15 Derrida, J. (1990). "Force of Law: The "Mystical Foundation of Authority"." Cardozo Law Review 11: 9201045. Flathman, R. E. (1980). The Practice of Political Authority. Chicago, University of Chicago press. Foucault, M. (1972). The Archæology of Knowledge. London, Routledge. Foucault, M. (1978). The History of Sexuality, Volume 1: An Introduction. New York, Pantheon Books. Foucault, M. (1979). Discipline and Punish. New York, Vintage. Foucault, M. (1982). "The Subject and Power." Critical Inquiry 8(4): 777-789. Foucault, M. (1988). The History of Sexuality Vol.3, the Care of the Self Harmondsworth, The Penguin Press. Foucault, M. (1992). The History of Sexuality Vol.2, the Use of Pleasure London, Penguin. Foucault, M. (2001). The Order of Things: An Archaeology of the Human Sciences. London, Routledge. Friedman, R. B. (1990). On the Concept of Authority in Political Philosophy. Authority. J. Raz. New York, New York University Press: 56-91. Honig, B. (1991). "Declarations of Independence: Arendt and Derrida on the Problem of Foundation a Republic." The American Political Science Review 85(1): 97-113. James, I. (2006). The Fragmentary Demand :An Introduction to the Philosophy of Jean-Luc Nancy. Stanford, CA, Stanford University Press. Macintyre, A. (1967). Secularization and Moral Change : The Riddell Memorial Lectures,N36th Series,Delivered at the University of Newcastle Upon Tyne on 11,2 and 1 November,1964. Oxford, Oxford University Press. Merquior, J. G. (1985). Foucault. London, Fontana. Nancy, J.-L. (2000). Being Singular Plural Stanford, CA, Stanford University Press. Nancy, J.-L. (2005). "The Insufficiency of 'Values' and the Necessity of 'Sense'." Journal for Cultural Research 9(4): 437-441. Sennett, R. (1980). Authority. New York, Alfred A. Knopf. Simmel, G. (1971). The Transcendent Character of Life. On Individuality and Social Forms. D. N. Levine. London and Chicago, University of Chicago Press: 353-374. Spinoza, B. d. (1996). Ethics London, Penguin. Weber, M. (1964). The Theory of Social and Economic Organization / Edited with an Introduction by Talcott Parsons. London, Collier-Macmillan. Weber, M. (1968). Economy and Society: An Outline of Interpretive Sociology. New York, Bedminster Press. 16