Aristotle’s Nicomachean Ethics we desire), and if we do not choose everything for the sake of something else (which means the process of desiring would go on to infinity, rendering our desires empty and vain)—if this is the case, then clearly this end or purpose must be the good and the chief good. Will not the knowledge of it, then, have a great influence on life? Shall we not, like archers who have a mark to aim at, be more likely to hit upon what is right? If so, we must try, in a general outline at least, to determine what this most precious purpose is. And we must determine which of the sciences or branches of knowledge are concerned with this final end, or final purpose (for which everything else is desired). It would seem to belong to the most authoritative art, the most comprehensive art, and that which is most truly the master art. And politics appears to be of this nature; for it politics this that ordains which of the sciences (and arts) should be studied in a state, and it politics which determines what each class of citizens should learn and do and what they should not learn and not do. And we see even the most highly esteemed capacities—the most honorable pursuits—fall under the political: e.g. military strategy, economics, rhetoric (that is, legal speech or Law) BOOK I Ch. 1 The Good as the aim of every action For every art and every inquiry, for every science and investigation, and similarly for every action and pursuit and choice, there seems to be some good which is aimed at; and for this reason the good has rightly been declared to be that at which all things aim. But it is clear that there is a certain difference to be found among the various ends, or purposes, at which we aim; some ends, or purposes, are activities. Others are products apart from the activities that produce them. Where there are ends apart from the actions, it is the nature of the products to be better than the activities. Now, as there are many actions, arts, and sciences, their are also many ends (or purposes); the end of the medical art is health, that of shipbuilding a vessel, that of military strategy victory, that of economics wealth. But where such arts fall under a single capacity—as bridle-making and the other arts concerned with the horse equipment fall under the art of riding or as every military action under the capacity of military strategy or in the same way other arts fall under more general capacities—in all of these the ends of the master arts, the more general arts, are to be preferred to all of those different subordinate ends. For it is for the sake of the former that the latter are pursued. It makes no difference whether the activities themselves are the ends of the actions, or something else apart from the activities, as in the case of the sciences just mentioned. Now, since politics uses the rest of the sciences, and since, again, it legislates as to what we are to do and what we are to abstain from, the end of this science must include those of the others, so that this end must be the good for man. For even if the end is the same for a single man and for a state, that of the state seems at all events something greater and more complete whether to attain or to preserve; though it is worthwhile to attain the end merely for one man, it is finer and more godlike to attain it for a nation or for citystates. These, then, are the ends at which our inquiry aims, since it is political science, in one sense of that term. Ch. 2 Politics as the master science of the good Ch. 4 Happiness is the Good but many views are held about it If, then, there is some end or purpose, in the realm of action, which we desire for its own sake (and which determines everything else Let us resume our inquiry and state, in view of the fact that all 1 For the “fact”—what is known without argumentation—is the starting-point, and if these “starting facts” are sufficiently plain to him, he will not at the start need the reason or agruemnts for these facts. So the man who has been well brought up can easily get the starting points. knowledge and every pursuit aims at some good, what it is that we say political science aims at and what is the highest of all goods achievable by action. Verbally there is very general agreement; for both the general run of men and people of superior refinement say that it is happiness, and identify living well and doing well with being happy; but with regard to what happiness is they differ, and the “many” do not give the same account as the wise. For the many think happiness is some plain and obvious thing, like pleasure, wealth, or honour; they differ, however, from one another- and often even the same man identifies it with different things, with health when he is ill, with wealth when he is poor; but, conscious of their ignorance, they admire those who proclaim some great ideal that is above their comprehension. And as for him who neither has nor can get the starting points—the known facts—let him hear the words of Hesiod: Far best is he who knows all things himself; Good, he that is attentive when the wise men counsel right; But he who neither knows, nor desires to hear Another's wisdom: he is as useless a weight. Now some thought that apart from these many goods there is another which is self-subsistent and causes the goodness of all these as well. To examine all the opinions that have been held would be somewhat fruitless; it is enough to examine those that are most prevalent or that seem to be plausible. Ch. 5 Various views on the highest good Let us, however, resume our discussion from the point at which we digressed. To judge from the sort of lives that men in this world actually lead—most men, and men of the most vulgar type, seem (not without some basis) to identify the Good, or happiness, with pleasure. This is the reason why they love the life of enjoyment. For there are, we may say, three prominent types of life, three prominent “ways-of-being”: the “vulgar life of pleasure,” which we just mentioned, and the “political life,” and, thirdly, the “contemplative life.” Let us not fail to notice, however, that there is a difference between arguments from fundamental principles and arguments leading to fundamental principles. Plato was right in raising this question and asking, as he used to do, “are we on the way from or to the first principles?” There is a difference, as there is in a race-course, between running from the judges to the far end of the track, and running back again. For, we must begin with what is “known,” But this term has two connotations: what is known to use and what is known “pure and simple.” Presumably, then, we must begin with things known to us. Now the masses of mankind are evidently quite slavish and vulgar in their tastes, preferring a life suitable to beasts. But they get some justification for their view of life from the fact that many of those in very high places share these sorts of tastes—the tastes of Sardanapallus [He, apparently, was a sex-crazed King of Assyria]. A consideration of these prominent types of life shows that people of superior cultivation and an active disposition identify happiness with honour; for this is, roughly speaking, the end of the political life. Hence anyone who listens intelligently to lectures about what is noble and just, and generally, about the subjects of political science must have been brought up in good habits. 2 Ch. 7 The Good is the final and self-sufficient; happiness is defined But an “honorable life” seems too superficial an answer, since it is dependent on those who bestow honour rather than on he who receives it; but the good that we are after—it must be something that belongs properly to to a man and not easily taken from him (or given to him). Let us again return to the good that we have been seeking, and ask what it can be. It seems to be different in different actions and arts; it is one thing in medicine, another in military strategy, and so on with the other arts. Further, men seem to pursue honour in order that they may be assured of their goodness; at any rate, they seek to be honored by sensible men, by men of practical wisdom. And they seek to be honred based on their own worth and virtue. Clearly, then, virtue is better than honor (even according to the men who seek honor). What then is the good of each? Surely, it must be that for whose sake everything else is done. In medicine this is health, in military strategy it is victory, in building it would be the production of a house—and in any other sphere, or art, it would be something else. But it is always, and in every art, the end (the purpose) for the sake of which all actions are performed. Therefore, if there is some one end, some purpose, for all that we do—well then this end or purpose will be The Good achievable by action, and if there are more than one, then these many ends will make up the goods achievable by action. Perhaps one might even suppose excellence (or virtue) to be the end of the political life, instead of honor. But even this appears somewhat incomplete; for possession of virtue seems actually compatible with being asleep, or with lifelong inactivity, and, further, with the greatest sufferings and misfortunes; but a man who was virtuous, yet also miserable—no one would call this man happy, unless just for argument’s sake. But enough of this. There was the vulgar pleasure seeking life, the life of honor, and third comes the contemplative life, but we shall only consider this later. So, the argument has proceeded such that we have reached the same point where we began in Ch. 2: namely, that there at least appears to be some end, in the realm of action, that is desired for its own sake, and which determines all other desires. But we must try to clarify this even further. Since there are, obviously, several ends, and since we choose some of these ends (for example, wealth, flutes, all instruments) for the sake of something else, clearly not all ends are final ends; but the chief good is evidently something final. Now, the life of money-making is one undertaken under compulsion. And wealth is evidently not the good we are seeking; for it is merely useful and for the sake of something else. And so one might rather regard the before mentioned objects—pleasure, honor, contemplation—to be end, or purpose, of the good life. for they are loved and desired for themselves. Therefore, if there is only one final end—one final purpose—this will be what we are seeking, and if there are more than one, the most final of these will be what we are seeking. But it is evident that not even these are really ends; yet many arguments have been thrown away in support of them. Let us leave this subject, then. Now we call that which is in itself worthy of pursuit more final than that which is worthy of pursuit for the sake of something else. And we call that which is never desirable for the sake of something else more final than the things that are desirable both in themselves and 3 for the sake of that other thing. Therefore, what is always chosen as an end in itself (which is never chosen as means to something else) we call final, in an unqualied sense. It is that which is always desirable in itself and never for the sake of something else. of as simply one good thing among others, then adding more goods to it (in even the small goods) would improve it—because the addition would produce an extra amount of good. And a greater amount of good is always more desirable than a lesser amount. We seen then that happiness [eudaimonia] is something final and selfsufficient. It is the end, or final purpose, of all our actions. Presumably, however, to say that happiness is the chief good seems a little trite, a mere platitude. A clearer account of what happiness is, is still desired. Now, it appears that we are describing that which we call “happiness” [eudaimonia]. Happiness, above all else, is held to be this final end, that is desired for itself and nothing else. On the other hand, consider honour, pleasure, beauty, intelligence, and every virtue we choose indeed for themselves. We choose these virtues for themselves, because if nothing else resulted from them we, would still choose them. But we choose them also for the sake of happiness, judging that by means of them we shall be happy. Perhaps, this clearer account of happiness could be given, if we could first ascertain the function [ergon] of man. For just as it is for a flute-player, or a sculptor, or an artist—and in general, for anyone who fulfills some function or performs some action—the good, in all those cases, the good and the “well” seems to reside in the proper function, if that thing has a function. Happiness, eudaimonia, on the other hand—no one chooses for the sake of these previous virtues. No, in general, happiness is never chosen for anything other than itself. Does the carpenter, then, and the tanner have certain functions or activities, and yet man in general has none? Is man born without a function? Or as eye, hand, foot, and in general each of the parts of the body evidently has a function, may one lay it down also that man, similarly, has a function apart from all these? What then can this function be? From the point of view of self-sufficiency the same result seems to follow; for the final good is thought to be self-sufficient. Now, by “self-sufficient” we do not mean the man who lives in isolation, as self-sufficient. We mean a man who lives with, and for, his parents, his children, his wife, and in general who lives with and for his friends and fellow citizens. This is because man is born for citizenship—man is a political being. Life seems to be common even to plants, but we are seeking what is peculiar to man. Let us exclude, therefore, the life of nutrition and growth. Next there would be a life of perception, but it also seems to be common even to the horse, the ox, and every animal. There remains, then, an active life of the element that has a rational principle. The rational element of man has two parts: one part is rational in the sense that it is obedient to reason and the other part is rational in the sense that it possesses and conceives of rational rules (it possesses and exercises thought) But some limit must be set to this; for if we extend our requirement to ancestors and descendants and friends of friends, then we are in for an infinite series. Let us examine this question, however, on another occasion. The self-sufficiency we now have in mind is: that which taken by itself makes life something desirable, and deficient in nothing. And as such, we think happiness to be exactly this. Further, we think It the most desirable of all things, without being counted as one simply “one good thing among others.” If happiness were thought Because the “life of the rational element” has two meanings, we must make it clear that we mean—when we’re getting after the 4 … The life of men who are active in this sense—men whose happiness is an activity, a doing—is also in itself pleasant life in itself. For pleasure is a state of the soul, and each man is said to derive pleasure from that which he is said to love: a lover of horses, from horses; a lover of theater, from plays; and in the same way, a lover of justice, from just acts; and a lover of virtue in general, from virtuous acts. Now for most men, their pleasures are in conflict with one another because these pleasures are no pleasant by nature. But the lovers of what is noble find pleasant the things that are by nature pleasant. And virtuous actions are such things. Actions which conform to virtue are naturally pleasant, and as a result, such actions are not only pleasant for those who love the noble, but they are also pleasant in themselves. The life of such men, therefore, has no further need of pleasure as added attraction, but that life contains pleasure within itself. function of man—a life that is determined by the activity (as opposed to the mere possession) of the rational element of man. For the activity, it seems, has a greater claim to be the function of man. The proper function of man, then, is an activity of the soul which follows or implies a rational principle or standard. And if we say “so-and-so has a good function,”we mean that he sets a high standard for himself. He is a “serious man” [spoudaios]. For example the proper function of a harpist is same thing as the function of a harpist who has set high standards for himself. The same applies to any and every group of individuals. Of course, the attainment of excellence must be added to the mere function. In other worlds, the function of the harpist is to play the harp. The function of the harpist who sets high standards for himself is to play the harp well. On these assumptions, if we take the proper function of man to be a certain kind of life, and if this kind of life is an activity of the soul and consists of actions performed in conjunction with the rational element, and if a man of high standards is he who performs the actions well and properly, and if a function is well performed when it is performed in accordance with the excellence appropriate to it— then based on all this, we reach the conclusion: that the good of man is an activity of the soul in conformity with excellence or virtue, and if there are several virtues, then in conformity with the best and most complete. We may even go so far as to state that the man who does not enjoy performing noble actions is not a good man at all. Nobody would call a man call a man just who did not enjoy acting justly, nor any man generous who did not enjoy generous actions; and similarly in all other cases. If this is true actions performed in conformity with virtue are in themselves pleasant. Of course, it goes without saying that that such actions are good as well as noble, and they are both in the highest degree—if, that is, the man of high moral standards [spoudaios] displays any right judgment about them at all. And his judgment corresponds to our description. SO we see that happiness is at once the best, noblest, and most pleasant thing, and these qualities are not separate, just as the inscription at Delos makes out: But we must add to this: “in a complete life.” For one swallow does not make a spring, nor does one sunny day. Similarly, one day, or a short time, does not make a man blessed and happy. The most just is most noble, but health is best, and to win what one loves in pleasantness Ch. 8 Popular views about happiness confirm our position 5 For the best activities encompass all these activities encompass all these attributes, and it is in these, or in the best of one of them, that we identify with happiness. Yet evidently, as we said, it needs the external goods as well; for it is impossible, or not easy, to do noble acts without the proper equipment. In many actions we use friends and riches and political power as instruments; and there are some things the lack of which spoils happiness,--such things as good birth, goodly children, beauty and so on. For the man who is very ugly in appearance or ill-born or solitary and childless is not very likely to be happy, and perhaps a man would be still less likely if he had thoroughly bad children or friends or had lost good children or friends by death. As we said, then, happiness seems to need this sort of prosperity in addition; for these reasons some identify happiness with good fortune, though others identify it with virtue. 6