“What publicity can do: the benefits of corporate environmental audits” [REMOVED BY EDITOR] Word count (excluding footnotes): 10,663 12 December 2013 2 ABSTRACT This paper advances the argument that corporate governance law should include public and independent environmental audits in order to improve corporate treatment of the environment. Part I posits that since the norm of shareholder value maximization is undermined by the business judgment rule, the rule for enforcing shareholder claims against the corporation, similar norms requiring corporations to improve their treatment of the environment will suffer from similar weaknesses. Rather, shareholder value maximization is enforced through non-legal forces. Consequently, corporate governance should leverage non-legal forces to improve corporate treatment of the environment on the principle that ‘sunlight is the best disinfectant.’ Part II proposes a system of public and independent environmental audits. It first surveys current methods of environmental information production and proposes a way of thinking about a more robust system mandated by law. 3 What publicity can do: the benefits of corporate environmental audits Table of Contents INTRODUCTION 4 PART I 5 1. PROBLEMS WITH ENFORCING A FIDUCIARY DUTY TO MAXIMIZE PROFITS 5 1.1 SHAREHOLDER PRIMACY 6 1.2 WHY THE BUSINESS JUDGMENT RULE MAKES THE DUTY IMPOSSIBLE TO PERFECTLY ENFORCE. 8 1.3 OTHER REJECTIONS OF SHAREHOLDER PRIMACY 12 1.4 ECONOMIC SANCTIONS: ENFORCING SHAREHOLDER PRIMACY. 15 1.5 CONCLUSION 17 2. PROBLEMS WITH ENFORCING A FIDUCIARY TO DUTY MINIMIZE ONE’S IMPACT ON THE ENVIRONMENT 18 2.1 WHY A FIDUCIARY DUTY IS DIFFICULT TO ENFORCE 18 2.2 WHY A FIDUCIARY DUTY IS UNDESIRABLE 22 3. WHY WE SHOULD FOCUS ON ENVIRONMENTAL AUDITS 24 3.1 WHY SOCIAL AND MORAL SANCTIONS ARE REQUIRED 25 3.2 WHY ENVIRONMENTAL AUDITS CAN EXPOSE CORPORATE ACTORS TO SOCIAL AND MORAL SANCTIONS 30 4. CONCLUSION 31 PART II 32 1. THE CURRENT SYSTEM 1.1 LEGISLATED DISCLOSURES – SECURITIES REGULATION 1.2 INDUSTRY ASSOCIATIONS AND VOLUNTARY DISCLOSURE 1.3 ISO ENVIRONMENTAL STANDARDS 1.4 ENVIRONMENTAL CONSULTING 1.5 BRINGING THE CURRENT SYSTEM TOGETHER 2. REFORM: AN ANALOGY WITH FINANCIAL AUDITS 2.1 WHY AN ANALOGY TO FINANCIAL AUDITS? 2.2 THE FIVE QUESTIONS: WHO? WHAT? WHEN? WHERE? HOW? 3. FURTHER CONSIDERATIONS 33 33 36 38 39 41 41 41 44 47 CONCLUSION 48 BIBLIOGRAPHY 50 4 INTRODUCTION Through this paper, I hope to contribute to a conversation about how best to incentivize, convince, or compel (as the case may be) corporate actors to treat the environment better. My argument is based on the assumption that better treatment of the environment is desirable. The question is therefore about instrument, not objective. To focus my inquiry, I will respond to Professor Gail Henderson’s proposal to expand legal obligations for corporate actors to consider the environment.1 She proposes to subject corporate directors to a fiduciary duty to minimize one’s impact on the environment. I will argue for a different instrument: audits. My thesis is that that mandating independent and public environmental audits will significantly improve corporate actors’ treatment of the environment. I have built my argument by investigating the norms and other incentives that influence the behavior of corporate actors. I have applied Professor Einer Elhauge’s landmark analysis2 to the question of how we can incentivize corporate actors to be more careful of their environmental impact. Throughout this paper, the reader should be mindful of Elhauge’s categories of norms: legal, economic, and social and moral. While a fiduciary duty to minimize one’s impact on the environment is exclusively legal, I will demonstrate that mandating environmental audits is justified by legal, economic, and social and moral considerations. My argument is structured in two parts. In the first part, I will demonstrate why a legal fiduciary duty is neither necessary nor sufficient to compel environmentally See Gail Henderson, “A Fiduciary Duty to Minimize the Corporation’s Environmental Impacts” (2013) 9:3 Intl Comp Corp LJ 67. 2 Einer Elhauge, “Sacrificing Corporate Profits in the Public Interest” (2005) 80:3 NYU LR 733. 1 5 responsible corporate behavior, and why a legally mandated regime of environmental audits is preferable. First, I will demonstrate that shareholder primacy is often legally unenforceable, but that this duty is enforced through economic forces. Second, I will outline the problems with enforcing a fiduciary duty to minimize one’s impact on the environment. Third, I will argue that environmental audits are more suitable for shaping how corporations treat the environment. In the second part, I will propose a regime of environmental audits. In the first section, I will survey different ways in which environmental information is currently produced. In the second section, I will propose that we think of environmental audits in the same way as we think of financial audits. Throughout the paper I will illustrate my argument with a scenario borrowed from Elhauge’s paper: clear-cutting.3 I will suggest how a clear-cutting company, Timber Co, would find itself situated at the various stages of the argument. Timber Co’s is not particularly environmentally motivated, both in the sense that the board is not overly aggressive in externalizing its costs onto the environment, but it also does not take extraordinary measures to ensure to minimize its environmental impact. I will further assume that this company’s shares are widely held. In other words, the company has a few large institutional shareholders and several dissipated individual shareholders. PART I 1. Problems with enforcing a fiduciary duty to maximize profits I must first establish that the traditionally dominant doctrine in corporate law, that of shareholder primacy, is not legally enforceable in many cases. In other words, shareholders are weak in legally enforcing their primacy. I will first briefly explain 3 Ibid at 735-736. 6 shareholder primacy. I will then argue that the business judgment rule, the test for enforcing shareholder primacy, as articulated in Delaware4 makes the doctrine impossible to perfectly enforce. Third, I will demonstrate how the doctrine of shareholder primacy has been largely abandoned by Canadian legislation and case law, further neutering a legal norm of profit maximization in Canada. Finally, the above argument does not attempt to prove that corporations do not maximize profits. Rather, it seeks to establish that law is not the prime enforcer of the doctrine of shareholder primacy. Economic sanctions, rather than legal sanctions, explain why corporate directors and managers continue to seek profits. 1.1 Shareholder primacy The doctrine of shareholder primacy has long been the established doctrine in corporate law.5 The doctrine holds that corporate directors and managers have a fiduciary duty to maximize shareholder value while complying with other laws and regulations.6 The Dodge v Ford Motor Co7 court famously articulated the doctrine thus: 4 Delaware is important because it is perhaps the most influential jurisdiction for common law corporate case law. See Elhauge, supra note 2 at 738. Professor Elhauge describes Delaware as “the eight-hundred-pound gorilla of corporate law”. 5 Elhauge, supra note 2 at 736, calls this the “canonical law and economics account”. 6 See e.g. Elhauge, supra note 2 at 736; see also Leonard Ian Rotman, Fiduciary Law (Toronto: Thomson Carswell, 2005) at 420-25 for a discussion of the debate in the 1930’s between Adolf A Berle Jr, a contractarian, and E Merrick Dodd Jr, an anti-contractarian, and the subsequent emergence of the shareholder primacy doctrine. For the debate itself, see AA Berle, Jr, “Corporate Powers as Powers in Trust” (1931) 44 Harv L Rev 1049; and E Merrick Dodd, Jr, “For Whom are Corporate Managers Trustees?” (1932) 45 Harv L Rev 1145. For a 1970s articulation of the shareholder primacy argument, see also Milton Friedman, “The Social Responsibility of Business Is to Increase its Profits”, The New York Times (13 September 1970) 32; Jonathan R Macey & Geoffrey Miller, “Corporate Stakeholders: A Contractual Perspective” (1993) 43 UTLJ 402-403. See also Henderson, supra note 1 at 77-82 for a review of the arguments in favor of shareholder primacy. 7 Dodge v Ford Motor Co 170 NW 668 (Mich 1919) [Dodge]. 7 “A business corporation is organized and carried on primarily for the profit of the stockholders. The powers of the directors are to be employed for that end. The discretion of directors is to be exercised in the choice of means to attain that end, and does not extend to a change in the end itself, to the reduction of profits, or to the nondistribution of profits among stockholders in order to devote them to other purposes.”8 Arguments in favor of shareholder primacy usually come from contractarian scholars. Contractarians view the corporation as a ‘nexus of contracts’. As Professor Jonathan R Macey puts it: “Every facet from beginning to end is organized around contracts”.9 Shareholders are the owners of corporations, such as Timber Co, and contractually nominate directors and managers as their agents. These agents then go about managing the shareholder’s assets: hiring employees, negotiating supply contracts, sale contracts, real estate transactions, machinery leases, or whatever else Timber Co may require. All activity must be for the benefit of the owners of the corporation, the shareholders. In his oft-cited 1970 New York Times piece, “The Social Responsibility of Business is to Increase its Profits,” Milton Friedman argued that to pursue goals other than profit maximization would be to infringe on shareholder rights. If the Timber Co board decided to undertake some non-profit activity with the corporation’s money, such as building a school in its community, then it “would be spending someone else’s money for a general social interest.”10 Since the board members are the shareholders’ agents, they have no right to use corporation resources without some sort of mandate from shareholders. 8 Dodge, supra note 7 at 684. Jonathan R Macey, Corporate Governance (Princeton University Press, 2008) at 18. 10 Friedman, supra note 6 at 33. 9 8 That is the shareholder primacy doctrine in a nutshell. If the directors and managers lower Timber Co’s potential profits by replanting areas of the forest or declining to clear-cut in certain areas, then Timber Co’s shareholders would be entitled to a legal remedy. Shareholders are the corporation’s raison d’être and all activity should further their interests; maximizing the company’s value. 1.2 Why the business judgment rule makes the duty impossible to perfectly enforce. However, shareholder primacy is not easy to enforce through legal action.11 The test that shareholders must satisfy, the ‘business judgment rule,’ provides corporate directors and managers with wide discretion to sacrifice profits and escape legal sanctions. Moreover, this discretion does not result from some statutory or jurisprudential relaxation of the rule. The rule has been weak since its birth. Two cases demonstrate just how weak the rule has been in the past: Dodge and Shlensky v Wrigley12. Dodge was one of the earliest shareholder primacy cases. Henry Ford founded the Ford Motor Company in 1903 together with some business associates, among whom were the Dodge brothers, John and Horace.13 FMC saw sales explode in the early 20th century, resulting in very large profits. Mr. Ford, as the company’s president, stopped 11 I will leave aside any discussion of other objections to the shareholder primacy rule. Normative arguments could be made regarding the desirability of directors’ and managers’ duty to maximize profits, but I will stick to a discussion of whether such a duty is even enforceable in the first place. See also D Gordon Smith, “The Shareholder Primacy Norm” (1998) 23:2 J of Corp Law 277 at 280: “The assumption that the shareholder primacy norm is a major factor in the ordinary business decisions of boards of directors of modern, publicly traded corporations is pervasive in modern corporate law scholarship. The influence of the shareholder primacy norm seems so obvious that arguments among corporate law scholars typically leapfrog over descriptive aspects of the debate and rush straight to the normative question: should corporate law require profit maximization?” 12 Shlensky v Wrigley, 237 NE (2d) 776 (Ill. 1968) [Wrigley]. 13 Dodge, supra note 7 at 668. 9 paying special dividends to shareholders because he wanted to finance an expansion of operations, including the acquisition of an iron ore mine and a smelter, and an increase in employment in the area.14 The court ordered Mr. Ford to announce dividends, holding that Ford Motor Co had more money than it needed to finance its business expansion.15 Mr. Ford was required to announce dividends for the excess amount between what Ford Motor Co had and what he claimed it needed for the business expansion. However, Dodge demonstrates the duty of loyalty as it relates to conflict of interest, not as it relates to shareholder primacy. Elhauge suggests that Ford likely suspended dividends to depress stock prices so that he could squeeze out the Dodge brothers at a favorable price (which eventually happened).16 The court held that this move was a violation of Mr. Ford’s duty of loyalty not to use his corporate control to benefit himself financially at the expense of other shareholders.17 Not mentioned in the case is that the Dodge brothers had recently set up their own firm to compete with Ford.18 Additionally, the decision never stated that directors’ exclusive duty is to maximize shareholder profits.19 Instead, the corporation must “primarily” have shareholder profits in mind, meaning that directors cannot “conduct the affairs of a corporation for the merely incidental benefit of shareholders and for the primary purpose of benefitting others … .”20 That is a far cry from using the case as evidence for shareholder primacy. 14 Ibid at 683-685. Ibid at 685. 16 Elhauge, supra note 2 at 774. 17 Ibid. 18 M Todd Henderson, “The Story of Dodge v Ford Motor Company: Everything Old is New Again” in J Mark Ramseyer eds, Corporate Law Stories (Foundation Press 2009) at 37. 19 Elhauge, supra note 2 at 772-773. 20 Dodge, supra note 7 at 684. 15 10 Wrigley grants even more deference to corporate directors. Mr. Wrigley, 80% owner and director of the Chicago Clubs baseball team, refused to install lights on Wrigley field. Mr. Wrigley refused to do so on the basis of his opinion that baseball is a daytime sport and that the installation of lights would have a deteriorating effect upon the surrounding neighborhood.21 Every other baseball team had installed lights for the purpose of increasing attendance and revenue but Mr. Wrigley still refused, even admitting that he “is not interested in whether the Cubs would benefit financially” from lights.22 In short, Wrigley contained the perfect facts to make the claim that the corporate director (Mr. Wrigley) was not maximizing shareholder value. But the court refused to grant relief to the minority shareholders, instead holding that profit-sacrificing motives other than fraud, illegality or conflict of interest (such as in Dodge) were irrelevant.23 Wrigley, too, suggests that shareholders are not able to effectively enforce the primacy granted to them by the canon of corporate law. The courts’ deference to directors is known as the business judgment rule. In its recent iterations, Delaware case law has upheld that deference. For example, in 2008 the Delaware Court of Chancery held in Postorivo v AG Paintball Holdings Inc Chancery that: “[c]ourts generally will not substitute the judgment of a judge for that of a board. Rather, a judge ensures that the board made the business judgment with a disinterested and independent mindset. Therefore, the courts avoid questioning the merits of a director’s decision, but examine instead the allegations questioning the motivation fueling the decision”.24 21 Wrigley, supra note 12 at 778. Ibid at 777-778. 23 Ibid at 780. 24 Postorivo v AG Paintball Holdings Inc, 29 Del Ch Lexis (2008) at 13, 2008 WL 553205 at 4 (Del Ch Feb 29 2008) [Postorivo]; see also Beam v Stewart, 845 A.2d 1040, 22 11 Pursuant to Postorivo plaintiff shareholders will face obstacles similar to those faces by the plaintiff shareholders in Wrigley: they must prove that directors had some improper motive. Recent Delaware case law thus continues to give shareholders a hard time enforcing any duty directors might have to maximize profits for their advantage. The exception is change of control situations. In Unocal Corp. v. Mesa Petroleum Co.25 and Revlon Inc. v. MacAndrews & Forbes Holdings26 the Delaware courts held that decisions of a board should be subject to “enhanced scrutiny” when the company is in a change of control situation, such as a hostile takeover. Directors in these situations are under a duty to maximize shareholder value; to sell the company to the highest bidder. The reason is that in anti-takeover situations there is the “the omnipresent specter that a board may be acting primarily in its own interests, rather than those of the corporation and its shareholders . . ."27 At this point the board must demonstrate that it had “reasonable grounds for believing there was a danger to corporate policy and effectiveness, a burden satisfied by a showing of good faith and reasonable 1048 (Del. 2004): the business judgment rule is “a presumption that directors were faithful to their fiduciary duties”; In re Walt Disney Co Derivative Litig, 906 A.2d 27, 52 (Del. 2006), Am Soc’y for Testing & Materials v Corrpro Cos, 487 F.3d 557, 572, (3d Cir. 2007): the business judgment rule is “a rule of law that ‘insulates an officer or director of a corporation from liability for a business decision made in good faith if he is not interested in the subject of the business judgment, is informed with respect to the subject of the business judgment to the extent he reasonably believes to be appropriate under the circumstances, and rationally believes that the business judgment is in the best interests of the corporation.”; In re infoUSA Inc S’holders Litig, 953 A.2d 963, 984 (Del Ch 2007): Courts do “not safeguard shareholders by substituting the opinion of a judge for that of a business person merely because a plaintiff shows up at the courthouse asking for relief.” 25 493 A.2d 946 (Del. Sup. Ct. 1985) [Unocal]. 26 506 A.2d 173 (Del. Sup. Ct. 1986) [Revlon]. 27 Unocal, supra note 25 at 954. 12 investigation.”28 While under the business judgment rule boards are presumed to have acted in good faith, boards are subject to a reasonableness review when a change of control situation activates their Revlon duties. Consequently, the business judgment rule weakens the doctrine of shareholder primacy considerably. As Elhauge puts it: “Because just about any decision to sacrifice profits has a conceivable link to long-term profits, this suffices to give managers substantial de facto discretion to sacrifice profits in the public interest.”29 In other words, while a doctrine of shareholder primacy may exist, the business judgment rule undermines its enforcement. We can thus conclude that the doctrine of shareholder primacy is legally unenforceable to the extent that corporate directors and managers have discretion in spending the corporation’s profits. 1.3 Other rejections of shareholder primacy While the traditional rule elaborated in Dodge, Wrigley, and the Delaware case law already weakens the enforceability of shareholder primacy, Canadian law goes even further in permitting corporate directors and managers to consider non-shareholder interests. Canadian legislation pegs corporate directors’ allegiance to the corporation, rather than shareholders as individuals. Canadian case law must then answer the question: what are the best interests of the corporation? The short answer is: 1) the best interests of the corporations are much wider than simply the pecuniary interests of individual shareholders; and 2) the board must determine the best interests on an ongoing basis. Canadian corporate directors and managers find the source of their fiduciary obligations in section 122(1)(a) of the Canada Business Corporations Act, which reads: 28 29 Revlon, supra note 26 at 180; see also Unocal, supra note 25 at 955. Elhauge, supra note 2 at 771. 13 “[e]very director and officer of a corporation in exercising their powers and discharging their duties shall [...] act honestly and in good faith with a view to the best interests of the corporation.”30 Canadian law has therefore not explicitly incorporated shareholder primacy into its corporate law; rather, the matter hinges on the interpretation of ‘best interests of the corporation’. While shareholder primacy informed Canadian corporate law in the past,31 the Supreme Court of Canada’s decision in Peoples Department Stores Inc (Trustee of) v Wise32 in 2004 and BCE Inc v 1976 Debentureholders33 in 2008 signaled a marked divergence from shareholder primacy in Canadian corporate law. While the Court in Peoples noted that “[t]his appeal does not relate to the non-statutory duty directors owe to shareholders”, it did clarify that “the phrase the ‘best interests of the corporation’ should be read not simply as ‘the best interests of the shareholders.’”34 The Court in Peoples summarized its decision as follows: “We accept as an accurate statement of law that in determining whether they are acting with a view to the best interests of the corporation it may be legitimate, given all the circumstances of a given case, for the board of directors to consider, inter alia, the interests of shareholders, employees, suppliers, creditors, consumers, governments and the environment.”35 30 Canada Business Corporations Act, RSC 1985, c C-44, s 122(1)(a) [CBCA]. See Sarah P Bradley, “BCE Inc v 1976 Debentureholders: The New Fiduciary Duties of Fair Treatment, Statutory Compliance and Good Corporate Citizenship?” (2010) 41:2 Ottawa L Rev 325 at para 10: “It is uncontroversial to observe that the shareholder primacy model informed much of the early development of our system of corporate laws, or that, perhaps until recently, it was clearly understood to be the law in Canada.” See also J Anthony VanDuzer, The Law of Partnerships and Corporations, 2d ed (Toronto: Irwin Law, 2003) at 271-72. 32 Peoples Department Stores Inc (Trustee of) v Wise, 2004 SCC 68, [2004] 3 SCR 461 [Peoples]. 33 BCE Inc v 1976 Debentureholders, 2008 SCC 69, [2008] 3 SCR 560 [BCE]. 34 Peoples, supra note 32 at para 42. 35 Ibid. 31 14 The Court’s decision in Peoples thus marked a divergence from the doctrine of shareholder primacy and gives much hope for environmental causes in particular. However, the decision left many questions unresolved. For example, under which circumstances could a board consider stakeholders? The Court took the opportunity to clarify some of these questions when it heard BCE in 2008. The decision in BCE involved a leveraged buy-out that would lower the long-term value of the company’s debentures. The debenture holders argued that the directors did not consider their interests in a fair and balanced way.36 The Court held that while directors owe a fiduciary obligation only to the corporation, a director must act in the “best interests of the corporation viewed as a good corporate citizen.”37 Additionally, the Court held that the phrase ‘best interests of the corporation’ means that: “Directors, acting in the best interests of the corporation, may be obliged to consider the impact of their decisions on corporate stakeholders, such as the debenture-holders in these appeals.”38 This dictum suffers from ambiguities, such as what is meant by ‘may be obliged.’39 Additionally, the Court adds a qualifier to the ‘best interests of the corporation’ in the very same paragraph, holding that “This is what we mean when we speak of a director being required to act in the best interests of the corporation viewed as a good corporate citizen.”40 The introduction of ‘good corporate citizen’ could provide a basis on which directors could act in the interests of stakeholders. Whatever ‘good 36 BCE, supra note 33 at para 32. Ibid at para 66. 38 Ibid. 39 Edward Iacobucci, “Indeterminacy and the Canadian Supreme Court's Approach to Corporate Fiduciary Duties" (2009) 48 Canadian Business Law Journal 232 at 244-245. See also Bradley, supra note 30 at para 45. 40 BCE, supra note 33 at para 66. 37 15 corporate citizen’ means, the point is clear: shareholder primacy is not longer the guiding principle in Canadian corporate law. In addition to the license granted by the case law to consider stakeholders, directors also benefit from a statutory defense. Section 123(5) of the CBCA grants directors a defense of good faith. Given the ambiguities left in BCE as to when directors ‘may be obliged’ to consider stakeholders41, directors can now adopt many courses of action ‘in good faith’ to the best interests of the corporation. The good faith defense thus further dilutes the doctrine of shareholder primacy in Canada. Canada therefore cannot be said to have a robustly enforceable legal duty to maximize shareholder value. The combination of the business judgment rule, the definition of ‘the best interests of the corporation’ in Peoples and BCE, and the good faith defense in section 123(5) of the CBCA ensure that directors can consider stakeholders in their business decisions. 1.4 Economic sanctions: enforcing shareholder primacy. If corporate directors and managers do not have an enforceable legal obligation to maximize profits, then why do they continue to do so? Why do the directors of Timber Co continue to seek the profits even though they could likely escape legal sanctions? Part of the answer might be the possibility of legal sanctions. But that is unlikely in Canada, for the reasons explained above. Instead, the bulk of the answer lies in economic sanctions. As Einer Elhauge puts it: “The discretion to sacrifice profits is instead powerfully limited by managerial profit-sharing or stock options, product market See also Jeffrey Bone, “Corporate Environmental Responsibility in the Wake of the Supreme Court Decision of BCE Inc and Bell Canada” (2009) 27 Windsor Rev Legal Soc Issues 5 at 30: after BCE, Bone argues that directors can pursue objectives that include “long-term sustainability as an entrenched value”. 41 16 competition, the labor market for corporate officials, the need to raise capital, the threat of takeovers, and the prospect of being ousted by shareholder vote.42 I will elaborate on three factors: voting rights, the market for corporate control, and corporate finance. Shareholders are still dominant where it matters most: voting rights.43 The directors of Timber Co still answer to its shareholders. The directors and managers of Timber Co derive their powers from a continued renewal of them by shareholders. The threat to a directors’ corporate survival comes from the labor market for corporate officials. If Timber Co’s profits begin to slack, then its shareholders will start questioning whether it would not be preferable to replace the CEO with the former CEO of Lumber Co, who is conveniently out of work and has a great track record of delivering profits. The corporate board and officers thus have some skin in the game. They must pursue profits or the shareholders will send them packing. Second, publicly traded companies must constantly concern themselves with the market for corporate control.44 Suppose that in quarter 4 of 2013 Timber Co’s board decides not to clear-cut a piece of forest because the environmental damage would be unpalatable. Lumber Co may decide to clear-cut that land instead. For quarter-4 of 2013 Timber Co’s profits will be lower than Lumber Co’s. Analysts will say nasty things in an earnings call and Timber Co’s share price will fall. With Timber Co’s price depressed, it becomes vulnerable to a takeover bid. Lumber Co may offer Timber Co’s shareholders a premium on its current price since it believes much more money could be made with 42 Elhauge, supra note 2 at 840. While shareholder passivity and collective action problems diminish the influence of certain shareholders, I will deal with those problems below. 44 See generally, Henry G. Manne, “Mergers and the Market for Corporate Control” (1965) 73:2 J of Pol Econ 110. 43 17 Timber Co’s assets. The company has all of the equipment to clear-cut, it simply refrains from doing so in certain situations. Consequently, publicly traded companies face market pressure to either engage in profit-maximizing activity or be taken over by a company that will maximize profits. Third, companies need financing. The facts in Peoples are a good example. When the Wise brothers bought Peoples Department Stores (“Peoples”) from Marks & Spencer Canada Inc. (“M&S”), M&S took Peoples’ assets “as security and negotiated strict covenants concerning the financial management and operation of the company.”45 One of those covenants was that the Wise brothers could not amalgamate the two companies until the purchase price had been paid.46 Consequently, Wise was pushed to maximize profits as much as possible to escape the burdens of financing its acquisition. Enforceable legal sanctions are therefore not necessary to enforce profit maximization. Economic sanctions act as a sufficient substitute, subject to any intervening market inefficiencies or failures, by placing market pressures on the corporate actors to maximize profits. 1.5 Conclusion The doctrine of shareholder primacy is not a robustly enforceable legal duty to maximize profits, but this duty may be economically enforceable. The business judgment rule first dilutes the duty by allowing broad discretion to directors and a presumption of good faith. Furthermore, Canadian law has given explicit support for directors to consider stakeholders and has even provided an opening to argue that there are situations in which they are obligated to consider stakeholders. However, economic sanctions are much more 45 46 Peoples, supra note 32 at para 11. Ibid. 18 effective in enforcing profit maximization. The result is that companies continue to maximize profits notwithstanding the absence of a robust legal obligation to do so. 2. Problems with enforcing a fiduciary to duty minimize one’s impact on the environment Having proven the weakness of enforcing a legal duty to maximize shareholder profits, I will now demonstrate the difficulties in enforcing a fiduciary duty to minimize one’s impact on the environment. I will begin by discussing the problems in enforcing such a fiduciary duty. Second, I will address the duty’s purported benefits. 2.1 Why a fiduciary duty is difficult to enforce A fiduciary duty to minimize one’s impact on the environment will be just as difficult to enforce, if not more difficult, than the duty to maximize shareholder profits. Professor Henderson acknowledges that fiduciary duties for corporate directors are difficult to enforce.47 However, she argues that this difficulty is not fatal because: 1) environmentally-minded shareholders might bring derivative suits; and 2) socially responsible institutional investors will play an important role in monitoring compliance. However, I argue that a fiduciary duty will be confusing, will create conflicts of interest, that even well-financed environmentally-minded shareholders will have difficulties bringing successful derivative actions, and that the participation of institutional investors is not sufficient to enforce the duty. A fiduciary duty to minimize one’s impact on the environment will be confusing because the term “minimize” is always relative to some sort of baseline. From which basis would directors have to minimize their corporation’s environmental footprint? One 47 Henderson, supra note 1 at 92. 19 interpretation could be that a director will have discharged her duty if she successfully reduces her corporation’s environmental footprint to a minimum, where minimum is defined as the footprint her particular industry requires to continue operations. A second interpretation could be that each prospective decision must minimize its environmental impact. A third interpretation still could be that a director must continuously reduce her corporation’s environmental impact. Each interpretation has dramatically different implications. On the first interpretation, Timber Co can continue to pollute the environment as long as it and the rest of the timber industry demonstrate that they cannot otherwise continue operations. On the second, Timber Co might have to factor the environment into future business decisions, but its underlying environmental footprint remains. On the third, Timber Co may be forced to cease clear-cutting operations altogether and forced to move into some other industry, since moving into a different industry would continue to reduce its environmental impact. Since companies operate in industries with varying environmental implications, each will be held to a different standard. The duty is confusing because it fails to clarify these questions. Second, even if we could provide a definition for “minimize”, the duty creates conflicts of interest. In its discussion of when directors may consider stakeholders in BCE, the Court noted that “conflicts may arise between the interests of stakeholders inter se and between stakeholders and the corporation”.48 Professor Iacobucci has argued that this cannot make sense: the ‘corporation’ is a legal construct and stakeholders feature in its definition. A stakeholder can never be in conflict with the corporation; properly 48 BCE, supra 33 at para 81. 20 speaking, stakeholders can only be in conflict with each other.49 If we are to consider future generations and the environment as stakeholders50, then we must have some way of adjudicating between stakeholders. As Professor Iacobucci puts it, “for the fiduciary duty to offer a meaningful guide to behaviour, it must offer some indication of what to do in the presence of a true conflict.”51 Professor Iacobucci already laments how indeterminate the Court rendered directors’ duties in BCE.52 Telling directors that they simultaneously owe a fiduciary duty to the ‘corporation’ (all stakeholders) and toward the environment (one stakeholder) would exacerbate the confusion and would make corporate law matters even more difficult to adjudicate. Moreover, the duty would require directors to serve two masters whose interests constantly conflict. Third, even if we assume that well-financed, environmentally-minded, and legally-activist shareholders exist in corporations, derivative actions will not successfully enforce the duty. Professor Henderson herself notes Fischel and Bradley’s empirical conclusion that “the very generality of fiduciary duties...limits their application to relatively egregious cases.”53 The problems associated with enforcing the duty to maximize shareholder profits persist in the environmental context. The confusion caused with regards to its content and the confusion cause with regards to conflict of interests, discussed above, will only serve to enhance the difficulties of enforcing the duty. If the doctrine of shareholder primacy is difficult to enforce legally because it is difficult to 49 Iacobucci, supra note 39 at 236. See generally Henderson, supra note 1. 51 Iacobucci, supra note 39 at 236. 52 Ibid at 237. 53 Daniel R Fischel & Michael Bradley, “The Role of Liability Rules and the Derivative Suit in Corporate Law: A Theoretical and Empirical Analysis” 71 Cornell L Rev 261 at 283. 50 21 determine when the directors have inappropriately balanced long-term profit and shortterm profit; and if the ‘best interests of the corporation’ is difficult to determine because of the competing interests that make up the ‘corporation’; then adding a fiduciary duty to the environment will only serve to compound those difficulties. The result will be a duty that not even a highly motivated, well-financed, environmentally-minded shareholder could enforce. Finally, Professor Henderson argues that environmentally-minded, activist investors will monitor conduct. By this she does not mean that they will bring derivative actions; rather, she hypothesizes that they will impose market pressures upon directors to act in an environmentally responsible way.54 However, as Professor Richardson points out, only two of the forty shareholder proposals filed in Canada in 2001 dealt with ethical concerns, namely labor standards.55 While investor activism could be encouraged and supported with some reform,56 activist investors cannot enforce a fiduciary duty to minimize one’s impact on the environment on a systemic scale. Doing so would require that environmentally minded investors take sufficient equity in every corporation that may have negative impacts on the environment. First, the requisite investing power would be astronomical. Second, private corporations would be immune from such controls. Consider Glencore Xstrata plc, for example, a natural resources company founded in 1974.57 Glencore International plc, a privately held corporation until 2011, merged with Xstrata plc in 2012. Glencore was a big company: it had revenues of $70 54 Henderson, supra note 1 at 93-94. Benjamin Richardson, “Financing Environmental Change: A New Role for Canadian Environmental Law” (2004) 49:1 McGill LJ 145 at para 71. 56 See Richardson, supra note 55 at para 68-76. 57 Glencore Xstrata, History, online: Glencore Xstrata <http://www.glencorexstrata.com/about-us/history/. 55 22 billion in the first half of 2010, prior to its IPO.58 An environmentally-activist pension fund would not have been able to influence Glencore Xstrata’s corporate behavior prior to 2011. Even now, any activist investor would need a lot of capital to influence the company’s treatment of the environment. 2.2 Why a fiduciary duty is undesirable Professor Henderson further argues that a fiduciary duty will improve corporate environmental performance: 1) by instilling a norm of environmental protection among directors; 2) by improving compliance with existing environmental regulation; and 3) by integrating environmental factors into boards’ decision-making processes.59 I will now address these benefits. Professor Henderson argues that directors will internalize a norm to protect the environment and that this norm will influence them to make more environmentallyfriendly decisions.60 She does so by drawing an analogy with the duty to maximize shareholder profits: “the fact is that the existing corporate governance structure relies on directors’ internalized senses of honour, responsibility and obligation to act in the corporation’s best interests, given the weak sanctions for breach of their fiduciary duty.”61 However, as demonstrated above, economic sanctions (otherwise termed ‘market pressures’) do a lot of the work to enforce profit-maximization. Therefore, drawing an Glencore International plc, Interim Report, “Release of Interim Report for 2011” (25 August 2011) online: HKEx News <http://www.hkexnews.hk/listedco/listconews/sehk/2011/0825/LTN20110825243.pdf> at 8. 59 Henderson, supra note 1 at 71. 60 Henderson, supra note 1 at 82-83. 61 Henderson, supra note 1 at 84. 58 23 analogy to profit-maximization is not sufficient to argue that directors will internalize a fiduciary duty to minimize one’s impact on the environment. Second, Professor Henderson argues that the duty will improve compliance with existing regulations.62 She argues that directors view environmental regulations as a price that should be incurred if the profits warrant it. However, it is not clear that directors’ duty of care cannot work to protect against such behavior. In BCE, the Supreme Court of Canada held that directors’ duty of care63 “is not owed solely to the corporation, and may thus be the basis for liability to other stakeholders in accordance with principles governing the law of tort and extracontractual liability”.64 A duty to take reasonable care involves instituting internal controls for environmental impact. Not only does that involve complying with current laws to their fullest, but it also serves to establish environmental protection in the minds of those who create business processes. The same arguments apply for Professor Henderson’s third noted benefit: that a fiduciary duty will better integrate the environment into corporate practice. Professor Henderson makes two arguments. First, she argues that while voluntary standards could have the effect of integrating environmental considerations into corporate practices, a fiduciary duty will necessarily do that because it is mandatory.65 As argued above, the duty to minimize one’s impact on the environment would be unenforceable in practice, and the duty of care in section 122(1)(b) of the CBCA achieves the same (or a similar) imperative. Second, she argues that a fiduciary duty will compel a director to inform 62 Henderson, supra note 1 at 87. CBCA, supra note 31, s 122(1)(b). 64 BCE, supra note 33 at para 44. 65 Henderson, supra note 1 at 89. 63 24 herself of her corporation’s environmental impacts.66 Again, if the duty of care requires a director to institute adequate due diligence controls, then it also necessarily requires her to inform herself of her corporation’s environmental impacts. Additionally, a system of environmental audits would contribute more to public knowledge about corporate environmental impacts that would a fiduciary duty, as directors would not be required to reveal that information. Consequently, a fiduciary duty to minimize one’s impact on the environment is not the best way to influence corporations to treat the environment better. First, the duty will be difficult to enforce because its content is confusing, because it creates conflicts of interest for directors, because it suffers from the same difficulties as the duty to maximize shareholder profits, and because market forces will not compel its enforcement. Second, even the purported benefits of the duty can be achieved using other means: either the duty of care in section 122(1)(b) of the CBCA or through the system of environmental audits, which I will describe now. 3. Why we should focus on environmental audits I will now argue that a comprehensive system of environmental audits is a productive way to advance the cause of environmental protection in corporate law. First I will argue why social and moral sanctions are required to compel corporations to treat the environment better. Second I will argue why environmental audits can effectively expose corporate actors to social and moral sanctions. 66 Ibid. 25 3.1 Why social and moral sanctions are required As discussed above, legal sanctions are not enough. In the profit-maximizing context, economic sanctions must supplement legal sanctions in order to effectively enforce the duty. If, with regards to the environment, we are having a difficult time a) enforcing legal sanctions, and b) requiring corporations to internalize their environmental costs, then investigating the possibility of supplementing legal sanctions with social and moral sanctions is in order. I will argue that there is a lot of room for improvement in this regard. The corporate structure insulates corporate and social actors from social and moral sanctions. However, social and moral sanctions can be just as effective as hard law in shaping corporate behavior. Exposing corporate actors to social and moral sanctions will have two principal benefits: first, they will expose corporate behavior, thereby increasing corporate actors’ accountability to society; second, they will create a large body of environmental data that can be used to better enforce existing environmental laws and understand environmental challenges. First, the corporation insulates its actors from social and moral sanctions. One of the great fears when corporate personality became entrenched into law was that the corporation would become soulless. Professor Lawrence Friedman writes: “The word “soulless” constantly recurs in the debates on corporations. Everyone knew that corporations were really run by human beings. Yet the metaphor was not entirely pointless. Corporations did not die, and had no ultimate size. There were no natural limits to their life or to their greed. Corporations, it was feared, could concentrate the worst urges of whole groups of men; the economic power of a corporation would not be tempered by the mentality of any one man, or by considerations of family or morality”.67 Lawrence Friedman, “A History of American Law” 2d ed (Simon & Schuster 1985) at 171-172. 67 26 What Professor Friedman means by ‘soulless’ is that each actors family and moral considerations are divorced from their corporate considerations. Each corporate actor is insulated in different ways. For example, shareholders are insulated from corporate conduct in at least two ways: lack of information and a collective action problem.68 First, shareholders suffer from a lack of information about corporate operations. Consequently, shareholders do not have “detailed and vivid” information about corporate activity.69 Adam Smith observes that a person would not sleep all night if they lost their little finger; but upon learning about an earthquake in China, would simply express sorrow and get on with their day.70 The division between owner-shareholders and managers means that shareholders “do not participate in the sort of social and moral processes that give ordinary business owners [sole proprietors] affirmative desires to behave in socially desirable ways when the law 68 See Elhauge, supra note 2 at 798-800. Ibid at 798. 70 Adam Smith, Theory of Moral Sentiments (Oxford University Press, 1976) at III.iii.3.4: “Let us suppose that the great empire of China, with all its myriads of inhabitants, was suddenly swallowed up by an earthquake, and let us consider how a man of humanity in Europe, who had no sort of connexion with that part of the world, would be affected upon receiving intelligence of this dreadful calamity. He would, I imagine, first of all, express very strongly his sorrow for the misfortune of that unhappy people, he would make many melancholy reflections upon the precariousness of human life, and the vanity of all the labours of man, which could thus be annihilated in a moment. He would too, perhaps, if he was a man of speculation, enter into many reasonings concerning the effects which this disaster might produce upon the commerce of Europe, and the trade and business of the world in general. And when all this fine philosophy was over, when all these humane sentiments had been once fairly expressed, he would pursue his business or his pleasure, take his repose or his diversion, with the same ease and tranquillity, as if no such accident had happened. The most frivolous disaster which could befall himself would occasion a more real disturbance. If he was to lose his little finger to-morrow, he would not sleep tonight; but, provided he never saw them, he will snore with the most profound security over the ruin of a hundred millions of his brethren, and the destruction of that immense multitude seems plainly an object less interesting to him, than this paltry misfortune of his own.” 69 27 and profit motives are insufficient to do so.”71 Suppose that you own $500 worth of shares in Timber Co. If allegations emerged in the newspapers that Timber Co was engaging in excessive-but-legal clear cutting, you might shrug and move on with your day since they are only allegations. Maybe you do not want to be associated with a firm that even has allegations of environmental misconduct, so you sell your shares. But you will never feel complicit in the environmental damage. It remains abstract to you. As Elhauge puts it, a shareholder will feel morally divorced from “her corporation’s clear cutting if she isn’t sure whether it is really doing it, how bad its environmental effects are, or whether they are offset by favorable employment effects.”72 In other words, the corporation is structured to morally isolate shareholders from the consequences of their agents. Shareholders also have a collective action problem. If, upon learning of allegations of environmental misconduct at Timber Co, you decide to deploy your $500 stake to moral ends, you will run into an insurmountable obstacle: your say matters very little. Given such low probability of impact, you would not have an incentive to read past a newspaper article and check the facts of various reports against other sources of information.73 Since institutional investors (as discussed above) cannot (or, more properly speaking, do not) lend their considerable weight to solving these collective action problems, shareholders still do not feel morally culpable for their corporation’s actions. Corporate directors and managers, collectively known as ‘management’, are less insulated from their actions; nonetheless, they should be even less so. Given that 71 Elhauge, supra note 2 at 798. Ibid at 799. 73 Ibid at 800. 72 28 management is so close to the corporation’s processes and decisions, it feels more connected to them. In other words, management does not suffer from informational bias74 or from the collective action problem faced by shareholders.75 But management is largely insulated from outside sanctions. This is important because social and moral sanctions only work when there is someone to sanction you or when you sanction yourself. So either we must simply rely on the inherent goodness of people or we must expose those people to the social and moral judgment of others. If we simply relied on the inherent goodness of the people managing corporations, the corporate form would be a modern manifestation of the Ring of Gyges.76 Indeed, the empirical evidence suggests that when left unchecked, corporate management can do some pretty nasty things.77 One needs only to think of the Enron scandal: Kenneth Lay is forever solidified in the corporate imagination as someone very bad, indeed.78 Social and moral sanctions are therefore necessary to moderate the behavior of corporate management. One criticism might be that we cannot control the enforcement of social and moral sanctions in the way that we can control the enforcement of hard law. However, 74 Ibid at 800. Arguably, management suffers from an economic collective action problem. See the above discussion about economic sanctions. If Timber Co does not engage certain activity, then it will fall behind Lumber Co. In this sense, competitiveness could present a collective action problem with regards to the environment. 76 See Plato, The Republic of Plato, translated by Allan Bloom (New York: Basic Books, 1991) at 359a–2.360d. Glaucon, one of Socrates’ interlocutors, presents the Myth of Gyges, in which a shepherd finds a ring that conferred upon the him the power of invisibility. Given “license to do whatever he wants,” (at 359c1-2) the shepherd commits adultery with the king’s wife and kills the king. Glaucon’s point is that people will be unjust given the opportunity to do so without being punished. 77 See also Ian B Lee, “Is There a Cure for Corporate ‘‘Psychopathy’’?” 42 Am Bus LJ 65. 78 Macey, supra note 9 at 79: “By now Enron has become a metaphor for corporate failure.” 75 29 Professor Iacobucci surveys the literature on non-legal sanctions and notes that they “may deter behavior just as, or more, effectively than formal legal sanctions”.79 For example, social and moral sanctions likely explain why “there is widespread compliance with the US tax laws even though odds that tax evasion will be detected and prosecuted are extremely small”.80 And when, in 2012, reports of widespread aggressive tax planning among multinational corporations became public, social and moral sanctions turned up in full force. Several multinationals, including Apple and Google, were dragged in front of US Congress and British Parliament to explain their actions.81 Other social and moral sanctions include active negatives: “embarrassment of publicity, the reproach of family and friends, the pain of enduring insults and protests, or being disdained or shunned by acquaintances and strangers.”82 Recent history is rife with examples of the exercise of social and moral sanctions.83 Social and moral sanctions may not be precise, but the threat of them certainly has an impact. Iacobucci, “On the Interaction between Legal and Reputational Sanctions” (2011) [unpublished, archived at SSRN], referencing: Stewart Macaulay, “Non-Contractual Relations in Business: A Preliminary Study” (1963) 28:1 American Sociological Review 55 and Lisa Bernstein, “Opting Out of the Legal System: Extralegal Contractual Relations in the Diamond Industry” (1992) 21 J Legal Stud 115. See also: Robert Cooter, “Three Effects of Social Norms on Law: Expression, Deterrence, and Internalization” (2000b) 79:1 Oregon Law Review 1 and Melvin Eisenburg, “Corporate Law and Social Norms” (1999) 99:5 Columbia Law Review 1253. 80 Elhauge, supra note 2 at 753. 81 Schumpeter Blog, “Apple’s tax arrangements: Biting criticism” (21 May 2013), online: The Economist <http://www.economist.com/blogs/schumpeter/2013/05/apples-taxarrangements>. 82 Elhauge, supra note 2 at 752 83 For example Graeme Wearden, “Oil spill: Protesters disrupt BP speech as Tony Hayward pulls out” (22 June 2010), online: The Guardian <http://www.theguardian.com/business/2010/jun/22/oil-spill-bp-hayward-cancelsspeech>:Tony Hayward (CEO of British Petroleum during the Deepwater Horizon crisis) often endures protests in public. Another example is Dick Fuld (CEO of Lehman 79 30 3.2 Why environmental audits can expose corporate actors to social and moral sanctions Environmental audits can effectively expose corporate actors to social and moral sanctions. The reason for focusing on environmental audits is not revolutionary. As early as 1913, Justice Louis Brandeis advocated for transparency in the financial sector: the way to deal with excessive bankers’ commissions was publicity, since “publicity is justly commended as a remedy for social and industrial diseases.”84 The maxim that emerged from Justice Brandeis’ piece is: sunlight is the best disinfectant.85 Transparency has certainly become an immutable part of the financial sector.86 For example, corporate law requires corporations to disclose certain information, to have their finances independently audited;87 securities law requires financial market participants to disclose their dealings;88 and, increasingly, we create disclosure requirements for the environment.89 If Brothers when it went bankrupt in 2008). See Joshua Green, “Where Is Dick Fuld Now? Finding Lehman Brothers' Last CEO” (12 September 2013), online: Businessweek <http://www.businessweek.com/articles/2013-09-12/where-is-dick-fuld-now-findinglehman-brothers-last-ceo>: “‘Hi, I’m Dick Fuld, the most hated man in America.’ It was just after the crisis, and Fuld was making a rare social appearance at a party in the Sun Valley, Idaho, mansion of Jim Johnson, the former head of Fannie Mae. The selfmocking introduction, described by a guest, was Fuld’s armor—his way of broaching, and deflecting, the first thought that leaps to mind whenever someone hears his name: Dick Fuld was the chief executive officer who, on Sept. 15, 2008, led Lehman Brothers into the largest bankruptcy in U.S. history, setting a torch to the global financial system.” 84 Louis Brandeis, “Chapter V: What publicity can do” in On other people’s money (Harper’s Weekly: 1913). 85 Ibid. Originally, the quote appears as: “Sunlight is said to be the best of disinfectants; electric light the most efficient policeman”. 86 IOSCO, Objectives and Principles of Securities Regulation, (June, 2010) at 3. 87 CBCA, supra note 31, s 155(1)(a). 88 IOSCO, supra note 86 at 8. 89 See, for example, Continuous Disclosure Obligations, NI 51-102, (2004) 27 OSCB 3439. 31 environmental fraud is just as morally reprehensible as financial fraud, then we should apply the same level of transparency to the former as we do to the latter. Two benefits (in addition to exposure to social and moral sanctions) immediately jump to mind: compliance and informational asymmetry. First, compliance: recall Professor Henderson’s claim, discussed above, that a fiduciary duty would improve compliance with the law because it will require a director to inform herself about her corporation’s environmental impact. I argued that the duty of care in section 122(1)(b) could do the same work. Once corporations (and, incidentally, also potential tort plaintiffs) have access to an environmental auditors’ report, directors will be forced to institute processes that adequately deal with most, if not all, environmental issues. Otherwise, directors will violate the duty of care. Second, information: Professor Henderson notes that “the information asymmetry between regulators and regulated entities” one of the fundamental shortcomings of traditional forms of environmental regulation.90 With a system of independent environmental audits, regulators (and, incidentally, also the scientific community) will have a large amount of data being produced every year. The quality of regulations and of scientific knowledge would be greatly improved. 4. Conclusion I have argued in this part that we should focus our energy on creating a system of independent and public environmental audits. I started by arguing that the doctrine of shareholder primacy is not robustly enforceable in reality. I extended that argument to claim that a fiduciary duty to minimize one’s impact on the environment will suffer from 90 Henderson, supra note 1 at 73. 32 an equal, if not greater, unenforceability. I also presented additional reasons for which such a fiduciary duty is undesirable. Instead, I suggested that we should be seeking exposure to social and moral sanctions, and that a system of independent environmental audits could achieve that objective. PART II In this Part II, I will propose a way to start thinking about environmental audits. I will propose an analogy to financial audits. My goal is not to set forth a comprehensive regime. Rather, I will introduce the idea that we should think of environmental accountability in the same way as we think of financial accountability and discuss some of the implications that arise from thinking of environmental audits in this way. Consequently, I must proceed in two steps. In the first section, I will discuss the myriad of assessments and legal mechanisms that exist to produce environmental information. I will discuss four types of assessments or legal mechanisms that exist: legislated disclosures, industry associations, ISO environmental standards, and environmental consulting. While such an overview does not reflect all of the assessments or mechanisms in use, they serve to illustrate the point that significant environmental analysis ability exists in society. In the second step, I will argue that a system that subjects most corporations to a baseline audit and that standardizes a level of environmental transparency is preferable to a hodgepodge of industry association requirements or voluntary adherence to ISO standards. The analogy is to financial audits. Corporations should be just as accountable for their environmental activity as they are for their financial activity. While we create additional financial disclosures for corporations, we also subject all corporations to a 33 baseline level of transparency. We require independent parties to carry out this baseline so that we can be sufficiently confident in the veracity of the results. We do this so that we can be confident that corporate actors do not engage in fraud or some other commercial shenanigans. The same should apply to environmental affairs: given the alleged propensity of corporations to externalize their costs onto the environment, we should require verification of their activities so that environmentally-minded social actors (government agencies, academia, environmental watchdogs, environmentally-minded investors) can be sufficiently informed about the true environmental impacts of corporations. As with financial matters, the hope is that such sunlight will also disinfect environmental misbehavior. 1. The current system It would be very difficult to enumerate and discuss every way in which legal, economic, or social pressures require the production of information about corporate environmental impact. However, I do not need to give a comprehensive overview in order to achieve my objectives. Instead, I only seek to establish that there are, in fact, a variety of ways in which corporate environmental information is produced. From that conclusion, I hope to further argue that a standardized system of public and independent audits would be a desirable reform. Consequently, I will restrict my discussion to four topics: legislated disclosures, industry associations, ISO environmental standards, and environmental consulting. Additionally, I will limit my discussion to the Canadian context. 1.1 Legislated disclosures – securities regulation An example of legislature-mandated disclosure of environmental information is in Canadian securities law. National Instrument 51-102 sets out ongoing disclosure 34 requirements for companies that are reporting issuers – in other words, companies that have participated in the public money markets.91 Companies are required to disclose environmental information pursuant to their ongoing disclosure requirements in two ways: through a filing of 1) an MD&A form; and 2) an AIF form.92 MD&A stands for “Management Discussion & Analysis” and requires an issuer to report a narrative on its performance. Specifically, the Canadian Securities Association interprets the obligation as pertaining to the “extent [that] trends and uncertainties regarding environmental matters materially impact its financial performance and future prospects.”93 Consequently, an MD&A filing should only discuss environment matters if they have an impact on the issuing company’s financial performance. AIF stands for “Annual Information Form” and requires issuers to report on the material information relating to its business. Item 5 of the AIF form requires the issuer to describe the business.94 In particular, Item 5.1(1)(k) requires an issuer to report what impact the costs of environmental protection will have on its financial performance and Item 5.1(2) requires reporting of environmental or social policies.95 Item 5.2 requires issuers to disclose risk factors, including environmental or health risks.96 However, as Form 51-102F2 makes clear, issuers should only report information that may have an impact on financial performance: “If there is a risk that securityholders of your company 91 Continuous Disclosure Obligations, supra note 89, s 4.1. Ibid, s 5.1 and 6.1 93 Canadian Securities Administrators, Notice 51-333 “Environmental Reporting Guidance” (27 October 2010) at 11, interpreting Form 51-102F1, Item 1.4(g). 94 Form 51-102F2 95 Form 51-102F2, Item 5.1(1)(k) and 5.1(2). 96 Form 51-102F2, Item 5.2. 92 35 may become liable to make an additional contribution beyond the price of the security, disclose that risk.”97 Crucially, issuers are only required to report on “material” matters. Issuers are told to: “Focus your MD&A on material information. You do not need to disclose information that is not material. Exercise your judgment when determining whether information is material.”98 The test for materiality is objective and focuses on whether the “a reasonable investor’s decision whether or not to buy, sell or hold securities of the issuer would likely be influenced or changed if the information was omitted or misstated.”99 Again, the focus of the disclosure rules is on the financial importance of environmental impacts. The focus of the rules is insufficient because it frames what information is included or excluded in disclosures along lines of financial impact. Assume that Timber Co is listed on the TSX and therefore subject to NI 51-102. Assume also that Timber Co causes significant environmental damage that does not run afoul of any environmental protection legislation or other type of liability. In other words, the company can externalize their cost without financial consequences due to, for example, a lawsuit. Timber Co’s directors would not be required to report this environmental impact under NI 51-102. Mandatory disclosure is also insufficient because there is no verification. Directors are told to use their judgment. Not only are we not assured that directors have 97 Form 51-102F2, Item 5.2 Form 51-102F1, Part 1(e); Form 51-102F2, Part 1(d). 99 CSA, supra note 93 at 5. 98 36 told us everything they are supposed to tell us, we are also not assured that what they are properly characterizing their disclosure. 1.2 Industry associations and voluntary disclosure Industry associations and voluntary disclosure are also a significant source of information about corporate environmental impact. I will discuss the Chemistry Industry Association of Canada (CIAC) and its Responsible Care program, in particular, to illustrate how industry associations can produce environmental information and encourage compliance. With regards to other types of voluntary disclosure, I will point to Ceres’ Global Reporting Initiative and its reporting standards. CIAC is an association of chemical manufacturers in Canada that have decided to set standards of environmental conduct and adhere to them.100 They call these standards “Responsible Care®” (Responsible Care).101 Borrowing from Lord Chief Justice Hewart’s dictum in R v Sussex Justices, ex parte McCarthy102, the Responsible Care motto is “Do the right thing, and be seen to do the right thing.”103 What is the right thing? CIAC has developed three Responsible Care Codes to which member companies must adhere: an Operations Code, a Stewardship Code, and an Accountability Code.104 The Operations Code sets standards for facilities and equipment.105 The Stewardship 100 Chemical Industry Association of Canada, Members and Partners, online: CIAC <http://canadianchemistry.nmd.cc/index.php/en/members-partners>. 101 Chemical Industry Association of Canada, Responsible Care, online: CIAC <http://canadianchemistry.nmd.cc/responsible_care/index.php/en/index>. 102 R v Sussex Justices, ex parte McCarthy [1924] 1 KB 256, [1923] All ER Rep 233. 103 Chemical Industry Association of Canada, Our Commitment, online: CIAC <http://canadianchemistry.nmd.cc/responsible_care/index.php/en/our-commitment>. 104 Chemical Industry Association of Canada, Responsible Care Codes, online: CIAC <http://canadianchemistry.nmd.cc/responsible_care/index.php/en/responsible-carecodes>. 105 Ibid. 37 Code sets standards for the impact and safety of CIAC members’ products throughout their entire life cycle.106 The Accountability Code requires member companies to communicate the risks and benefits of their operations to the communities in which they operate.107 In order to ensure compliance, CIAC requires members to undergo verification. The verification process is robust: “Every three years, a team of industry experts, public advocates and representatives chosen by local communities, visits each CIAC member- and partner-company and interviews its senior managers. The verification team looks for answers to three key questions: . . . Is the company meeting the expectations outlined in the Responsible Care® Codes? Is an effective management system in place that supports Responsible Care, and drives continuous improvement, in all areas? Is the company’s commitment to the Responsible Care® Ethic and Principles for Sustainability tangible, and does it guide the company’s judgment, decisions and actions, internally and externally?”108 The resulting verification reports are posted on the Responsible Care website and are available for anyone to consult.109 Consequently, CIAC imposes upon its members not only standards of conduct, but also a public and independent verification process to ensure that its members comply with those standards. 106 Ibid. Ibid. 108 Chemical Industry Association of Canada, Responsible Care Verification, online: CIAC <http://canadianchemistry.nmd.cc/responsible_care/index.php/en/responsible-careverification>. 109 Chemical Industry Association of Canada, Responsible Care Verification Reports, online: CIAC <http://canadianchemistry.nmd.cc/responsible_care/index.php/en/responsible-careverification-reports>. 107 38 The Global Reporting Initiative (GRI), on the other hand, is international and spans across industries. The GRI is an organization that promotes the use of “sustainability reporting as a way for companies to become more sustainable and contribute to sustainable development.”110 Sustainability reports focus on the environmental, economic and social impacts of a business in their operations. To guide reporting, the GRI has therefore come up with reporting standards. The current iteration of those standards is “4G”, to indicate that the standards are in their fourth generation. Environmental reporting includes extensive reporting of the company’s impact on: materials, energy, water, biodiversity, and effluents and waste.111 The GRI thus provides a comprehensive framework to assess a company’s environmental impacts. The Responsible Care program and the Global reporting initiative are good example of the effect that transparency can have on corporate environmental performance. The CIAC example is particular because its members have set standards of conduct that will be verified. What I want to draw from the example is that verification systems exist for environmental performance. 1.3 ISO environmental standards The International Organization for Standardization (ISO) is a network of national standards bodies that develops international standards for good practice, products, technologies, and services.112 Each standard is a document that provides “requirements, specifications, guidelines or characteristics that can be used consistently to ensure that 110 Global Reporting Initiative, About GRI, online: GRO <https://www.globalreporting.org/information/about-gri/Pages/default.aspx>. 111 Global Reporting Intiaitive, Reporting Standards and Disclosures, online: GRI <https://www.globalreporting.org/reporting/g4/Pages/default.aspx> at 9. 112 International Organization for Standardization, Home, online: ISO <http://www.iso.org/iso/home/about.htm>. 39 materials, products, processes and services are fit for their purpose.”113 A salient example of an ISO standard is with regards to water. ISO committee ISO/TC 224 is “working on best-practice guidelines specifically for the management of assets within the municipal water sector.”114 The ISO 14000 family addresses environmental management.115 Specific standards within the family may address environmental systems management, product lifecycles, and, most importantly, audits.116 ISO thus contributes to a knowledge base about what information is relevant in conducting environmental audits. 1.4 Environmental consulting Environmental consulting also contributes to our collective knowledge about how to think of corporations’ environmental impacts. For example, we have general consulting firms like KPMG or McKinsey, and specific environmental consulting firms like Eco Canada. General consulting firms like KPMG and McKinsey offer environmental consulting services. McKinsey advertises that it has recently worked to make land use and ocean fisheries sustainable. Specifically, it mentions: “Recent examples of our work include helping a global fertilizer company design a climate-compatible growth strategy; working with a national government to launch an international partnership to reduce greenhouse gas emissions through forestry initiatives; and helping a pulp and paper 113 International Organization for Standardization, Standards, online: ISO <http://www.iso.org/iso/home/standards.htm>. 114 International Organization for Standardization, Managing water assets - Tackling the infrastructure gap, online: ISO <http://www.iso.org/iso/home/news_index/news_archive/news.htm?Refid=Ref1762>. 115 International Organization for Standardization, ISO 14000, online: ISO <http://www.iso.org/iso/home/standards/management-standards/iso14000.htm>. 116 Ibid. 40 company analyze its supply chain to reduce fiber sourcing costs and increase sustainability.”117 Similar firms such as KPMG offer similar services. KPMG has an entire sustainability practice that seeks to help companies “enhance processes, grow revenue, manage risk, strengthen reporting, optimize costs, and spur innovation.”118 Notwithstanding any corporate buzzwords and green-washing of studies that may exist, these practices reveal two important facts: 1) that corporate services provides are using language of sustainability; and 2) that they are engaging with environmental questions and situations. Consequently, there exists within the general consulting firms at least some useful and important knowledge about how to assess the environmental impacts of corporations. Environmental consulting firms, like Eco Canada, help professionalize the knowledge that I discussed above. Eco Canada provides certifications for environmental auditing, among other environmental functions.119 Aspiring environmental auditors come in two brands: Compliance Auditors and Environmental Management Systems Lead Auditor. The latter is further divided into two specializations: Environmental Management Systems and Sustainable Forestry Management. Certified auditors are trained to use ISO standards, among others.120 117 McKinsey & Company, Sustainability & Resource Productivity, online: McKinsey <http://www.mckinsey.com/client_service/sustainability/expertise/biosystems>. 118 KPMG International, Climate Change and Sustainability Services, online: KPMG <http://www.kpmg.com/global/en/topics/climate-change-sustainabilityservices/pages/default.aspx?utm_medium=mdd&utm_campaign=mddglobal&utm_source=link>. 119 Eco Canada, Environmental Auditor, online: Eco Canada <http://www.eco.ca/certification/environmental-auditor/>. 120 Ibid. 41 1.5 Bringing the current system together The point of the above discussion is to demonstrate that we have significant abilities to evaluate corporate environmental impact. However, each is not sufficient by itself. For example, mandatory disclosures in securities regulation do not produce the right type of information because disclosures focus on financial impact and because they are not verified. Industry associations like CIAC that produce independent and public audits are desirable, but they are not comprehensive: not every industry has an association, and not all members are or seek to be part of their industry association. Other mechanisms like GRI and ISO standards are equally desirable but require the voluntary compliance of companies. I think that we could, and should, pull these environmental evaluation capabilities together into one standardized public and independent audit. This will be the subject of the next section. 2. Reform: an analogy with financial audits 2.1 Why an analogy to financial audits? I am proposing that the law should apply the same level of scrutiny to a corporation’s environmental performance as it does to a corporation’s financial performance. In other words, we should starting thinking of environmental audits in the same way as we think of financial audits. I discussed some reasons for this in Part I, particularly in reference to how environmental audits can expose corporate actors to social and moral sanctions. But this argument can go even a step further: it would be legally incoherent not to require corporations to undergo environmental audits. We require financial audits in corporate law, and financial disclosure in securities law, to protect investors. Think of Louis Brandeis’ argument that “sunlight is the best of 42 disinfectants.”121 Corporations use other people’s money and we need to ensure that they do not misuse that money. Indeed, the business judgment rule cases above reveal the same concern: we do not want corporate actors to use their corporate control to benefit themselves financially, like in Dodge. Instead, all we ask is that corporate actors be personally disinterested in the decision, be informed about the decision, and have some reason to believe that the decision is in the best interests of the corporation. Financial disclosure aids compliance with the business judgment rule. In other words, we require financial audits to prevent fraud. Another way of looking at fraud is as a cost of doing business. Assuming that they could do so with impunity, corporate actors would have an incentive to defraud the corporation. All other things (legal, economic, social and moral sanctions) being equal, fraud means cash in corporate directors’ and officers’ pockets. But we both think of that as theft, and do not think that corporate directors and managers should personally benefit from their positions beyond remuneration. Consequently, we institute a compliance mechanism, “the audit,” to ensure that corporate directors and managers are not stealing from their shareholders. Another way of looking at corporate mistreatment of the environment is as a cost of doing business. It is commonly accepted that companies have a tendency to ‘externalize their environmental costs’ onto other actors in society.122 All other things equal, a factory would have an incentive to dump its waste into a river. Simply put, it would be a cost of cleanup not incurred. The law provides for various mechanisms to pursue the factory in that case, including environmental legislation or the tort of nuisance. 121 122 See supra, at Part I, section 3.2. See, for example, Henderson, supra note 1 at 70, 78-79. 43 I do not mean to go so far as claim that corporations are defrauding society when externalizing their environmental costs. But as a matter of policy, it is incoherent to require compliance for financial honesty and not for environmental matters. The incoherence becomes apparent when we think of the environment as capital. E.F. Schumacher writes: “The illusion of unlimited powers, nourished by astonishing scientific and technological achievements, has produced the concurrent illusion of having solved the problem of production. The latter illusion is based on the failure to distinguish between income and capital where this distinction matters most. Every economist and businessman is familiar with the distinction, and applies it conscientiously and with considerable subtlety to all economic affairs – except where it really matters: namely, the irreplaceable capital which man has not made, but simply found, and without which he can do nothing.”123 If the environment is society’s capital and money is an investor’s capital, then why should we not apply the same scrutiny to the use or misuse of one as we do to the other? We would argue that a corporate director or manager squandering the capital of a corporation without accountability to the investor is unlawful. How then can we allow a corporation to squander the capital of society without being accountable to it? The result is that we must apply the thinking on investor money to the environment and require corporations to disclose environmental information in an analogous same way to the disclosure financial information. In other words, we should think of environment audits as equally important as financial audits. 123 EF Schumacher, Small Is Beautiful: Economics as if People Mattered (London, Blond & Briggs Ltd, 1973) at 14. 44 2.2 The five questions: Who? What? When? Where? How? Having answered the question, “why environmental audits,” five questions remain to illustrate what type of reform I am proposing. First: who should conduct the audits? In keeping with a financial audit analogy, professionally accredited environmental auditors should conduct these audits. A professional association would need to be created. The first objection could be that we do not have enough consensus to develop proper professional standards. However, the above discussion about the current system reveals that sufficient knowledge exists about how to assess environmental standards. Organizations like Eco Canada already accredit environmental auditors. Just as the professional best practices of accountants and lawyers evolve, so will the best practices of environmental auditors. The current problem is a market one: environmental auditors do not have a big enough market. Accountants and lawyers both have the monopoly over their respective work, and work is always assured. Companies need financial audits and legal advice. If companies would be compelled to produce environmental audits, demand for environmental auditors would increase and remain constant to the point that a robust professional association would be able to develop. A second objection could be that different industries have different needs. This may be true, but that does not mean that we should abandon a project of setting a baseline standard for environmental auditing. Perhaps the best example would be to compare environmental auditing to the legal profession. There are many different types of legal services: criminal, civil litigation, tax advice, securities regulation, etc. And while in reality lawyers often specialize in one over the other, all lawyers are members of the same bar. Similarly, while the specific requirements of Timber Co versus a CIAC 45 member versus an oil refiner might be different, we can still subject each to the same standard of auditing. Second: of what should the audits consist? As discussed above, there currently exist many standards from which to draw. ISO, GRI, and Responsible Care would be a good place to start. But lawyers ultimately lack the institutional expertise to make these arguments. This should be left to the professional association and scientific discourse. More scientific information is therefore also needed before we can answer the third question: how often should audits occur? One answer could be that environmental audits should be produced every three years, like CIAC audits. However, this question should therefore also be left to the professional association and scientific consensus. Fourth: how should this reform be implemented into the law? This is the work of lawyers. The most logical solution is to place the reform somewhere in the existing financial audit framework. Directors are required to submit comparative financial statements to shareholders pursuant to section 155(1)(a) of the CBCA.124 Section 155(1)(b) states that directors may choose to submit an auditor’s report.125 In the case of large corporations directors will often do so because they have a statutory duty to approve financial statements pursuant to section 158.126 Auditor reports help directors to discharge their duty of diligence in accordance with their statutory duties. Environmental audits would logically fit well in this part of the legislation. There should also be exceptions. In recognition of the burden that audits place on corporate resources, section 163(1) permits corporations that are not “distributing 124 CBCA, supra note 31, s 155(1)(a). CBCA, ibid, s 155(1)(b). 126 CBCA, ibid, s 158. 125 46 corporations” to dispense with an auditor.127 The CBCA Regulations define “distributing corporation” as a “reporting issuer” under any legislation, a corporation that has filed a prospectus or registration statement pursuant to provincial legislation, a corporation that has listed securities on any exchange, or one that is sufficiently connected to one of the aforementioned corporations.128 The ‘not a distributing corporation’ exception has the effect of exempting ‘mom and pop stores’ from the burdens of a full-scale audit. Similarly, a reform could require companies to present an environmental auditor’s report alongside that of a financial auditor. The same exceptions could easily apply in the environmental context. We are concerned with the environmental footprint of Timber Co, the chemicals manufacturer, and the oil refiner, not of the dépanneur down the street. Fifth, and finally: where should the audits be available? As discussed above, environmental audits should be public in order to achieve the objective of exposing corporate actors to social and moral sanctions. Additionally, audits must be public in order to gain the benefits of increased scientific understanding gained from having systematically collected environmental information available. Some wretched and unfortunate research assistant cannot tabulate the results of the environmental audits into his or her professor’s environmental model unless those audits are available. Nor can the watchdog agencies call out bad behavior unless the audits are public. One solution would be to require companies to make the audit reports public on their websites. This is the way they make annual reports public. However, the better solution would be to aggregate the reports in some audit repository on Environment Canada’s website. Placing all of the audit reports in one place dispenses with the need to collect reports from each individual 127 128 CBCA, ibid, s 163(1). Canada Business Corporations Regulations, SOR/2001-512, s 2(1) [CBCA Regs]. 47 company’s website, a process that would almost certainly result in some companies being overlooked. Given the stated objectives for the reform, locating all of the audit reports in one location is the preferred choice. 3. Further considerations Some further considerations are of a scientific nature and have already been flagged: What should be the standards for admission to the professional environmental auditing association? What should be the content on the audits? How often should audits occur? Some other questions arise of a legal nature. For example, I have suggested that a new professional association would be created. Should we be concerned about the possibility of the accounting profession controlling this new profession, or would that give it the legitimacy it needs? Perhaps it would be better to subsume environmental auditors within the accounting profession altogether. Will the knowledge required of accountants become unwieldy? Similarly, I have suggested a way to implement this reform into the law. I have proposed to simply create an environmental auditing obligation similar to the financial auditing obligation and borrowed an exception that the financial audit rules afford to smaller companies. Perhaps we should consider other exceptions or methods of enforcement. Finally, we should consider the ways in which such a reform could benefit corporations. One argument could be that environmental audits will increase social confidence in the corporate form. In other words, environmental audits will increase a corporation’s ‘social license to operate’. This benefit, and other benefits, should be considered in future papers. 48 CONCLUSION In this paper, I have argued that a system of independent and public environmental audits of corporations is desirable. In the first part, I argued that creating a legal duty to minimize one’s impact on the environment is neither enforceable nor desirable. To prove that statement, I demonstrated that the traditional doctrine of shareholder primacy with its duty to maximize profits was not enforceable due to the business judgment rule. Any duty to minimize one’s impact on the environment would have to incorporate a rule that offers some similar deference to corporate decisions. Additionally, legislation and case law in Canada has already given directors of Canadian corporations large discretion to consider stakeholders, including the environment. Consequently, we should not be looking to pressure directors with legal sanctions. Instead, I argued, we should be pressing directors on social and moral sanctions. I argued that the structure of information and incentives in the corporate largely insulates corporate management from the effects of their decisions. If we want corporations to treat the environment better, then we should expose the people who run them to social and moral sanctions. I have proposed that the way to do that is through a system of independent and public environmental audits. In the second part, I argued that society’s collective environmental analysis capabilities are extensive enough to develop the infrastructure needed to create such a system. I do not suggest that this should be a cumbersome state program. Rather, by simply creating the obligation (with a few exceptions) to produce environmental audits, the private market will develop its own environmental auditing industry analogous to the 49 financial auditing industry. My hope has been to contribute to the ways of thinking about corporate accountability and the environment. 50 BIBLIOGRAPHY Legislation, Regulations, Bills & Treaties Canada Business Corporations Act, RSC 1985, c C-44, s 122(1)(a). Canada Business Corporations Regulations, SOR/2001-512. Continuous Disclosure Obligations, NI 51-102, (2004) 27 OSCB 3439. Form 51-102F2. Form 51-102F1. Jurisprudence Am Soc’y for Testing & Materials v Corrpro Cos, 487 F.3d 557, 572, (3d Cir. 2007). Beam v Stewart, 845 A.2d 1040, 1048 (Del. 2004). BCE Inc v 1976 Debentureholders, 2008 SCC 69, [2008] 3 SCR 560. Dodge v Ford Motor Co 170 NW 668 (Mich 1919). In re Walt Disney Co Derivative Litig, 906 A.2d 27, 52 (Del. 2006). In re infoUSA Inc S’holders Litig, 953 A.2d 963, 984 (Del Ch 2007). Peoples Department Stores Inc (Trustee of) v Wise, 2004 SCC 68, [2004] 3 SCR 461. Postorivo v AG Paintball Holdings Inc, 29 Del Ch Lexis (2008) at 13, 2008 WL 553205 at 4 (Del Ch Feb 29 2008) R v Sussex Justices, ex parte McCarthy [1924] 1 KB 256, [1923] All ER Rep 233. Revlon Inc v MacAndrews & Forbes Holdings 506 A.2d 173 (Del. Sup. Ct. 1986). Unocal Corp v Mesa Petroleum Co, 493 A.2d 946 (Del. Sup. Ct. 1985). Secondary sources: monographs Brandeis, Louis. “Chapter V: What publicity can do” in On other people’s money (Harper’s Weekly: 1913). 51 Friedman, Lawrence. “A History of American Law” 2d ed (Simon & Schuster 1985). Henderson, M Todd. “The Story of Dodge v Ford Motor Company: Everything Old is New Again” in J Mark Ramseyer eds, Corporate Law Stories (Foundation Press 2009). Macey, Jonathan R. Corporate Governance (Princeton University Press, 2008). Plato, The Republic of Plato, translated by Allan Bloom (New York: Basic Books, 1991). Rotman, Leonard Ian. Fiduciary Law (Toronto: Thomson Carswell, 2005). Schumacher, EF. Small Is Beautiful: Economics as if People Mattered (London, Blond & Briggs Ltd, 1973). Smith, Adam. Theory of Moral Sentiments, as published by (Oxford University Press, 1976). VanDuzer, J Anthony. The Law of Partnerships and Corporations, 2d ed (Toronto: Irwin Law, 2003). Secondary sources: articles Berle, AA Jr. “Corporate Powers as Powers in Trust” (1931) 44 Harv L Rev 1049. Bernstein, Lisa. “Opting Out of the Legal System: Extralegal Contractual Relations in the Diamond Industry” (1992) 21 J Legal Stud 115. Bone, Jeffrey. “Corporate Environmental Responsibility in the Wake of the Supreme Court Decision of BCE Inc and Bell Canada” (2009) 27 Windsor Rev Legal Soc Issues 5. Bradley, Sarah P. “BCE Inc v 1976 Debentureholders: The New Fiduciary Duties of Fair Treatment, Statutory Compliance and Good Corporate Citizenship?” (2010) 41:2 Ottawa L Rev 325. Cooter, Robert. “Three Effects of Social Norms on Law: Expression, Deterrence, and Internalization” (2000b) 79:1 Oregon Law Review 1. Dodd, E Merrick Jr. “For Whom are Corporate Managers Trustees?” (1932) 45 Harv L Rev 1145. Elhauge, Einer. “Sacrificing Corporate Profits in the Public Interest” (2005) 80:3 NYU LR 733. Eisenburg, Melvin. “Corporate Law and Social Norms” (1999) 99:5 Columbia Law Review 1253. 52 Fischel, Daniel R & Bradley, Michael. “The Role of Liability Rules and the Derivative Suit in Corporate Law: A Theoretical and Empirical Analysis” 71 Cornell L Rev 261 Henderson, Gail. “A Fiduciary Duty to Minimize the Corporation’s Environmental Impacts” (2013) 9:3 Intl Comp Corp LJ 67. Iacobucci, Edward. “Indeterminacy and the Canadian Supreme Court's Approach to Corporate Fiduciary Duties" (2009) 48 Canadian Business Law Journal 232. ––––. “On the Interaction between Legal and Reputational Sanctions” (2011) [unpublished, archived at SSRN]. Lee, Ian B. “Is There a Cure for Corporate ‘‘Psychopathy’’?” 42 Am Bus LJ 65. Macaulay, Stewart. “Non-Contractual Relations in Business: A Preliminary Study” (1963) 28:1 American Sociological Review 55. Macey, Jonathan R & Miller, Geoffrey. “Corporate Stakeholders: A Contractual Perspective” (1993) 43 UTLJ 402-403. Manne, Henry G. “Mergers and the Market for Corporate Control” (1965) 73:2 J of Pol Econ 110. Richardson, Benjamin. “Financing Environmental Change: A New Role for Canadian Environmental Law” (2004) 49:1 McGill LJ 145. Smith, D Gordon. “The Shareholder Primacy Norm” (1998) 23:2 J of Corp Law 277. Secondary sources: news, opinion & informational media Friedman, Milton. “The Social Responsibility of Business Is to Increase its Profits”, The New York Times (13 September 1970) 32. Green, Joshua. “Where Is Dick Fuld Now? Finding Lehman Brothers' Last CEO” (12 September 2013), online: http://www.businessweek.com/articles/2013-09-12/where-isdick-fuld-now-finding-lehman-brothers-last-ceo. Schumpeter Blog, “Apple’s tax arrangements: Biting criticism” (21 May 2013), online: http://www.economist.com/blogs/schumpeter/2013/05/apples-tax-arrangements. Wearden, Graeme. “Oil spill: Protesters disrupt BP speech as Tony Hayward pulls out” (22 June 2010), online: http://www.theguardian.com/business/2010/jun/22/oil-spill-bphayward-cancels-speech. 53 Secondary sources: other Canadian Securities Administrators, Notice 51-333 “Environmental Reporting Guidance” (27 October 2010) at 11, interpreting Form 51-102F1, Item 1.4(g). Chemical Industry Association of Canada (CIAC), online: http://canadianchemistry.nmd.cc/index.php. Eco Canada, online: http://www.eco.ca. Glencore International plc, Interim Report, “Release of Interim Report for 2011” (25 August 2011) online: http://www.hkexnews.hk/listedco/listconews/sehk/2011/0825/LTN20110825243.pdf. Glencore Xstrata, History, online: http://www.glencorexstrata.com/about-us/history/. Global Reporting Initiative, online: https://www.globalreporting.org. IOSCO, Objectives and Principles of Securities Regulation, (June, 2010). International Organization for Standardization, online: http://www.iso.org. KPMG International, online: http://www.kpmg.com. McKinsey & Company, online: http://www.mckinsey.com.