Unawareness - Minicourse - Burkhard C. Schipper University of California, Davis Outline 1. 2. 3. 4. 5. 6. 7. 8. Informal introduction Epistemic models of unawareness Type spaces with unawareness Speculation Bayesian games with unawareness Revealed unawareness Dynamic games with unawareness …(???) 1. An informal introduction “Awareness” in Natural Language “I was aware of the red traffic light.” (Just knowledge?) “Be of aware of sexually transmitted diseases!" (“generally taking into account", “being present in mind", “paying attention to“) Etymology: “aware” ← “wary” ← “gewӕr” (old English) ← “gewahr” (German) Psychiatry: Lack of self-awareness means that a patient is oblivious to aspects of an illness that is obvious to his/her social contacts. (Failure of negative introspection.) “Reports that say that something hasn't happened are always interesting to me, because as we know, there are known knowns; there are things we know we know. We also know there are known unknowns; that is to say we know there are some things we do not know. But there are also unknown unknowns – the ones we don't know we don't know. And if one looks throughout the history of our country and other free countries, it is the latter category that tend to be the difficult ones.” (Former) United States Secretary of Defense, Donald Rumsfeld, February 12, 2002 Unawareness as Lack of Conception In most formal approaches: Unawareness means the lack of conception. (“not being present in the mind”) Lack of information versus lack of conception: We all know the homo oeconomicus. But how did he look as a baby? !1 !2 !3 !4 !5 !6 !7 !8 !9 !10 !11 !12 !13 !14 !15 !16 !17 !18 !19 !20 !21 !22 !23 !24 !25 !26 … !1 !2 !3 !4 !5 !6 !7 !8 !9 !10 !11 !12 !13 !14 !15 !16 !17 !18 !19 !20 !21 !22 !23 !24 !25 !26 … !1 !2 !3 !4 !5 !6 !7 !8 !9 !10 !11 !12 !13 !14 !15 !16 !17 !18 !19 !20 !21 !22 !23 !24 !25 !26 … ! Standard models allow for the lack of information but not for the lack of conception. In standard models, learning means shrinking the relevant state space but never discovering of new possibilities. An agent may have lack of conception of an event because: • never thought about it (i.e., novelties) • does not pay attention to it at the very moment we model (different from rational inattention) Relevance of unawareness • • • • • • • It is real phenomena Incomplete contracting, incomplete markets Speculation in financial markets Disclosure of information Strategic negotiations and bargaining Modelling discoveries and innovations Modeling games where the perception of the strategic context is not necessarily “common” among players • Exploring robustness of decision theory to small changes in assumptions on the primitives • … Non-robustness of Decision Theory In decision theory, the decision maker’s perception of the problem are captured in the primitives (state space, set of consequences, acts etc.) These primitives are assumed by the modeler and are not revealed. Preference are revealed given primitives. How do we know that the decision maker views the problem the same as the modeler? Example: Non-robustness of the Ellsberg Paradox 1 2 3 Bets Exp. Val. Red Green Blue A 33.33 $100 $0 $0 B 33.33 $0 $100 $0 C D 66.67 $100 $0 $100 66.67 $0 $100 $100 Balls # 30 60 30 30 30 Example: Non-robustness of the Ellsberg Paradox 1 Bets A B C D 2 3 3 4 Red 5 6 Green 7 8 Blue 9 10 11 12 13 14 15 16 Bets 1Exp.2 Val. Exp. Val. Red Green Blue A $100 $0 33.33 $100 33.33 $0 $0 $100 $0 $0 $0 $0 $100 $0$0 $100 $100 $0 $100 $100 $100 33.33 $0 $100 $0 $0 $0 $100 $0 $0 $100 $100 $0 $100 $100 $0 $100 $100 B 33.33 $0 $100 $0 66.67 $100 $0 $100 $0 66.67 $0 $100 $100 $0 Balls # 30 60 30 30 30 0 C D $0 $0 $0 $100 $0 $0 $0 $100 $0 $100 $0 $100 $100 $100 $0 $100 $0 $0 $100 $0 $100 $100 $100 $100 66.67 $100 $0 0 $100 0 0 0 0 0 66.67 $0 $100 $100 Balls # 30 60 30 30 30 0 0 0 0 0 0 Example: Non-robustness of the Ellsberg Paradox 1 2 3 4 5 6 Bets Exp. Val. Red Green Blue A 34.07 $100 $0 $0 $0 $100 $0 B 32.97 $0 $100 $0 $0 $0 $100 C D 65.93 $100 $0 $100 $0 67.03 $0 $100 $100 $0 Balls # 30 60 30 30 30 0 $0 $0 0 7 $0 $0 8 0 10 11 12 13 14 15 16 $0 $100 $0 $100 $100 $0 $100 $100 $100 $0 $100 $100 $0 $100 $100 $0 $100 $100 $0 $100 $0 $0 $0 $100 0 9 0 $0 $100 $0 $100 $100 $100 $0 $100 $0 $0 $100 $0 $100 $100 $100 $100 0 0 1 0 0 0 0 Rationalizes Ellsberg behavior with expected utility on a slightly different state-space. Unawareness models allow us to analyze decisions under varying primitives. 0 How to model unawareness? 2. Epistemic models of unawareness What’s the problem with modeling unawareness? Why not take a state-space model a la Aumann or a Kripke frame? What’s the problem with modeling unawareness? Digression: Necessitation of Belief Possibility correspondence: ¦ i : S ¡ ! 2S n f ; g K nowledge operat or de¯ned on event s E 2 2S : K i (E ) := f ! 2 S : ¦ i (! ) µ E g Sat is¯es Necessit at ion by de¯nit ion. Digression: Necessitation of Belief Type mapping t i : S ¡ ! ¢ (S; F S ) Probability-at -least -p-belief operat or de¯ned on event s E 2 F S : B ip (E ) := f ! 2 S : t i (! )(E ) ¸ pg Sat is¯es Necessit at ion by de¯nit ion of probability measures Digression: Necessitation of Belief \ Ambiguity" type mapping (mult iple probability measures model) t i : S ¡ ! F ¢ ( S) Ambiguous probability-at -least -p-belief operat or de¯ned on event s E 2 F S : B~ip (E ) := f ! 2 S : 9¹ 2 t i (! ); ¹ (E ) ¸ pg Sat is¯es Necessit at ion by de¯nit ion of probability measures What’s the problem with modeling unawareness? Modeling Unawareness Various approaches, interdisciplinary Computer science Economics • Modeling logical nonomniscience and limited reasoning • Inspired by Kripke structures • Analyst’s description of agents’ reasoning • Seminal work: Fagin and Halpern (AI 1988) • Focused on modeling lack of conception while keeping everything else standard • Inspired by Aumann structures and Harsanyi type spaces • Players’ descriptions of players’ reasoning Unawareness Structures Goals: 1. Define a structure consistent with non-trivial unawareness in the multi-agent case. 2. Prove all properties of awareness of Dekel, Lipman, Rustichini (1998), Modica and Rustichini (1999), Halpern (2001) 3. Prove unawareness is consistent with strong notions of knowledge (like S4 or stronger). 4. Clear separation between syntax and semantics to facilitate applications. hS; ¹ i nonempty complete lattice of nonempty disjoint spaces Digression: Lattices Let X is a set and ¹ be a binary relat ion de¯ned on X . ¹ is partial order if it is re° exive: x ¹ x for all x 2 X ant isymmet ric: for any x; y 2 X , x ¹ y and y ¹ x implies x = y t ransit ive: for any x; y; z 2 X , x ¹ y and y ¹ z implies x ¹ z Digression: Lattices Let Y µ X . u is an upper bound of Y if x ¹ u for all x 2 Y ` is a lower bound of Y if ` ¹ x for all x 2 Y u is a least upper bound, join, or surpremum of Y if u ¹ x for all upper bounds x of Y ` is a greatest lower bound, meet, or in¯mum of Y if x ¹ ` for all lower bounds x of Y Digression: Lattices X is a lattice if for any x; y 2 X has a join and meet . X is a complete lattice if any Y µ X has a join and a meet . Every nonempty ¯nit e lat t ice is complet e. For any set , t he set of all subset s is a complet e lat t ice ordered by set inclusion. hS; ¹ i nonempty complet e lat t ice of nonempty disjoint spaces For S; S0 2 S, S0 º S st ands for \ S0 is more expressive t han S" pqr ● pq¬r ● ¬pqr ● ¬pq¬r ● p¬qr ● p¬q¬r ● ¬p¬qr ● ¬p¬q¬r ● pq ● ¬pq ● p¬q ¬p¬q ● ● pqr ● pq¬r ● ¬pqr ● ¬pq¬r ● p¬qr ● p¬q¬r ● ¬p¬qr ● ¬p¬q¬r ● pq ● pqr ● pq¬r ● ¬pqr ● ¬pq¬r ● p¬qr ● p¬q¬r ● ¬p¬qr ● ¬p¬q¬r ● ¬pq ● pr ● ¬pr ● qr ● ¬qr ● p¬q ¬p¬q ● ● p¬r ● ¬p¬r ● q¬r ● ¬q¬r ● pq ● pqr ● pq¬r ● ¬pqr ● ¬pq¬r ● p¬qr ● p¬q¬r ● ¬p¬qr ● ¬p¬q¬r ● ¬pq ● pr ● ¬pr ● qr ● ¬qr ● p¬q ¬p¬q ● ● p¬r ● ¬p¬r ● q¬r ● ¬q¬r ● ● q ● ¬q ● p ● ¬p ● r ● ¬r pq ● pqr ● pq¬r ● ¬pqr ● ¬pq¬r ● p¬qr ● p¬q¬r ● ¬p¬qr ● ¬p¬q¬r ● ¬pq ● pr ● ¬pr ● qr ● ¬qr ● p¬q ¬p¬q ● ● p¬r ● ¬p¬r ● q¬r ● ¬q¬r ● ● q ● ¬q ● p ● ¬p ● Ø ● r ● ¬r hS; ¹ i nonempty complet e lat t ice of nonempty disjoint spaces For S; S0 2 S, S0 º S st ands for \ S0 is more expressive t han S" - := S S2 S S hS; ¹ i nonempty complet e lat t ice of nonempty disjoint spaces For S; S0 2 S, S0 º S st ands for \ S0 is more expressive t han S" - := S S2 S S 0 0 For S; S 2 S wit h S º S, S0 rS : S0 ¡ ! S surject ive project ion. For any S 2 S, r SS = i dS . 0 00 00 0 For any S; S ; S 2 S, S º S º S, S 00 rS = S0 rS S 00 ± r S0 . Digression: Surjection A funct ion f : X ¡ ! Y is surject ive or ont o if for every y 2 Y t here exist s an x 2 X such t hat f (x) = y. Student 1 Student 2 Student 3 Student 4 Thomas Anna 京 hS; ¹ i nonempty complet e lat t ice of nonempty disjoint spaces For S; S0 2 S, S0 º S st ands for \ S0 is more expressive t han S" - := S S2 S S 0 0 For S; S 2 S wit h S º S, S0 rS : S0 ¡ ! S surject ive project ion. For any S 2 S, r SS = i dS . 0 00 00 0 For any S; S ; S 2 S, S º S º S, S 00 rS = S0 rS S 00 ± r S0 . pq ● pqr ● pq¬r ● ¬pqr ● ¬pq¬r ● p¬qr ● p¬q¬r ● ¬p¬qr ● ¬p¬q¬r ● ¬pq ● pr ● ¬pr ● qr ● ¬qr ● p¬q ¬p¬q ● ● p¬r ● ¬p¬r ● q¬r ● ¬q¬r ● ● q ● ¬q ● p ● ¬p ● Ø ● r ● ¬r pq ● pqr ● pq¬r ● ¬pqr ● ¬pq¬r ● p¬qr ● p¬q¬r ● ¬p¬qr ● ¬p¬q¬r ● ¬pq ● pr ● ¬pr ● qr ● ¬qr ● p¬q ¬p¬q ● ● p¬r ● ¬p¬r ● q¬r ● ¬q¬r ● ● q ● ¬q ● p ● ¬p ● Ø ● r ● ¬r hS; ¹ i nonempty complet e lat t ice of nonempty disjoint spaces For S; S0 2 S, S0 º S st ands for \ S0 is more expressive t han S" - := S S2 S S 0 0 For S; S 2 S wit h S º S, S0 rS : S0 ¡ ! S surject ive project ion. For any S 2 S, r SS = i dS . 0 00 00 0 For any S; S ; S 2 S, S º S º S, 0 For ! 2 S , ! S = S0 r S (! S 00 rS = S0 rS ). For D ½ S0, D S = f ! S 00 ± r S0 . S : ! 2 D g. " For D µ S, D := ³ S S 02 S :S 0º S r SS 0 ´¡ 1 (D ). E µ - is an event if E = D " for some base D µ S in some base space S 2 S. (S(E )) pq ● pqr ● pq¬r ● ¬pqr ● ¬pq¬r ● p¬qr ● p¬q¬r ● ¬p¬qr ● ¬p¬q¬r ● ¬pq ● pr ● ¬pr ● qr ● ¬qr ● p¬q ¬p¬q ● ● p¬r ● ¬p¬r ● q¬r ● ¬q¬r ● ● q ● ¬q ● p ● ¬p ● Ø ● r ● ¬r " For D µ S, D := ³ S S 02 S :S 0º S r SS 0 ´¡ 1 (D ). E µ - is an event if E = D " for some base D µ S in some base space S 2 S. (S(E )) We writ e ; S for t he vacuous event wit h base space S. Not every subset of - is an event . pq ● pqr ● pq¬r ● ¬pqr ● ¬pq¬r ● p¬qr ● p¬q¬r ● ¬p¬qr ● ¬p¬q¬r ● ¬pq ● pr ● ¬pr ● qr ● ¬qr ● p¬q ¬p¬q ● ● p¬r ● ¬p¬r ● q¬r ● ¬q¬r ● ● q ● ¬q ● p ● ¬p ● Ø ● r ● ¬r " For D µ S, D := ³ S S 02 S :S 0º S r SS 0 ´¡ 1 (D ). E µ - is an event if E = D " for some base D µ S in some base space S 2 S. (S(E )) We writ e ; S for t he vacuous event wit h base space S. Not every subset of - is an event . Negat ion: For D " an event , ³ 0´ ¡ 1 S : D " := S 02 S :S 0º S r SS (S n D ). pq ● pqr ● pq¬r ● ¬pqr ● ¬pq¬r ● p¬qr ● p¬q¬r ● ¬p¬qr ● ¬p¬q¬r ● ¬pq ● pr ● ¬pr ● qr ● ¬qr ● p¬q ¬p¬q ● ● p¬r ● ¬p¬r ● q¬r ● ¬q¬r ● ● q ● ¬q ● p ● ¬p ● Ø ● r ● ¬r " For D µ S, D := ³ S S 02 S :S 0º S r SS 0 ´¡ 1 (D ). E µ - is an event if E = D " for some base D µ S in some base space S 2 S. (S(E )) We writ e ; S for t he vacuous event wit h base space S. Not every subset of - is an event . Negat ion: For D " an event , ³ 0´ ¡ 1 S : D " := S 02 S :S 0º S r SS (S n D ). " For D µ S, D := ³ S S 02 S :S 0º S r SS 0 ´¡ 1 (D ). E µ - is an event if E = D " for some base D µ S in some base space S 2 S. (S(E )) We writ e ; S for t he vacuous event wit h base space S. Not every subset of - is an event . Negat ion: For D " an event , ³ 0´ ¡ 1 S : D " := S 02 S :S 0º S r SS (S n D ). Typcially : E $ - n E . pq ● pqr ● pq¬r ● ¬pqr ● ¬pq¬r ● p¬qr ● p¬q¬r ● ¬p¬qr ● ¬p¬q¬r ● ¬pq ● pr ● ¬pr ● qr ● ¬qr ● p¬q ¬p¬q ● ● p¬r ● ¬p¬r ● q¬r ● ¬q¬r ● ● q ● ¬q ● p ● ¬p ● Ø ● r ● ¬r f E j g collect ion of event s Conjunct ion: V j E j := T j Ej pq ● pqr ● pq¬r ● ¬pqr ● ¬pq¬r ● p¬qr ● p¬q¬r ● ¬p¬qr ● ¬p¬q¬r ● ¬pq ● pr ● ¬pr ● qr ● ¬qr ● p¬q ¬p¬q ● ● p¬r ● ¬p¬r ● q¬r ● ¬q¬r ● ● q ● ¬q ● p ● ¬p ● Ø ● r ● ¬r f E j g collect ion of event s Conjunct ion: Disjunct ion: Typically W j V j W j E j := T E j := : Ej $ S j Ej j Ej ³V ´ j : Ej pq ● pqr ● pq¬r ● ¬pqr ● ¬pq¬r ● p¬qr ● p¬q¬r ● ¬p¬qr ● ¬p¬q¬r ● ¬pq ● pr ● ¬pr ● qr ● ¬qr ● p¬q ¬p¬q ● ● p¬r ● ¬p¬r ● q¬r ● ¬q¬r ● ● q ● ¬q ● p ● ¬p ● Ø ● r ● ¬r f E j g collect ion of event s Conjunct ion: Disjunct ion: Typically W j V j W j E j := T E j := : Ej $ S j j Ej ³V ´ j : Ej Ej E µ F if and olny if E µ F and S(E ) º S(F ). Set of all event s is not necessarily an algebra (many vacuous event s). For each i 2 I , t here is a possibility correspondence ¦ sat isfying t he following propert ies: i : - ¡ ! 2- n f ; g 0. Con¯nedment : If ! 2 S t hen ¦ i (! ) µ S0 for some S0 ¹ S. ! S ¦i(!) S’ ! ¦i(!‘) ¦i(!) !’ !’’ S S ¦i(!) ! S’ S“ ¦i(!‘‘) S’ S’’’ For each i 2 I , t here is a possibility correspondence ¦ sat isfying t he following propert ies: i : - ¡ ! 2- n f ; g 0. Con¯nedment : If ! 2 S t hen ¦ i (! ) µ S0 for some S0 ¹ S. 1. Generalized Re° exivity: ! 2 ¦ "i (! ) for every ! 2 - . 2. St at ionarity: ! 0 2 ¦ i (! ) implies ¦ i (! 0) = ¦ i (! ). 3. Project ions Preserve Awareness: If ! 2 S0, ! 2 ¦ i (! ) and S ¹ S0 t hen ! S 2 ¦ i (! S ). 4. Project ions Preserve Ignorance: If ! 2 S0 and S ¹ S0 t hen ¦ "i (! ) µ ¦ "i (! S ). 5. Project ions Preserve K nowledge: If S ¹ S0 ¹ S00, ! 2 S00 and ¦ i (! ) µ S0 t hen (¦ i (! )) S = ¦ i (! S ). ¡ ¢ S ¡ 1 r S0 (¦ i (! ! )) S ¦i(!) S’ ¡ ¢ S ¡ 1 r S0 (¦ i (! ! )) S ¦i(!) ¡ ¢ S ¡ 1 r S0 (¦ i (! )) S ¦i(!) S’ S’ For each i 2 I , t here is a possibility correspondence ¦ sat isfying t he following propert ies: i : - ¡ ! 2- n f ; g 0. Con¯nedment : If ! 2 S t hen ¦ i (! ) µ S0 for some S0 ¹ S. 1. Generalized Re° exivity: ! 2 ¦ "i (! ) for every ! 2 - . 2. St at ionarity: ! 0 2 ¦ i (! ) implies ¦ i (! 0) = ¦ i (! ). ¦i(!) = ¦i(!‘) ! !’ S ¦i(!) ¦i(!‘) ! !’ !’’ ¦i(!) = ¦i(!‘) ! !’ S S ¦i(!‘‘) S’ For each i 2 I , t here is a possibility correspondence ¦ sat isfying t he following propert ies: i : - ¡ ! 2- n f ; g 0. Con¯nedment : If ! 2 S t hen ¦ i (! ) µ S0 for some S0 ¹ S. 1. Generalized Re° exivity: ! 2 ¦ "i (! ) for every ! 2 - . 2. St at ionarity: ! 0 2 ¦ i (! ) implies ¦ i (! 0) = ¦ i (! ). 3. Project ions Preserve Awareness: If ! 2 S0, ! 2 ¦ i (! ) and S ¹ S0 t hen ! S 2 ¦ i (! S ). ! ¦i(!) S’ !S ¦i(!S) S ! ! ¦i(!) ¦i(!) S’ S’ !S S !S ¦i(!S) ¦i(!S) S S‘‘ For each i 2 I , t here is a possibility correspondence ¦ sat isfying t he following propert ies: i : - ¡ ! 2- n f ; g 0. Con¯nedment : If ! 2 S t hen ¦ i (! ) µ S0 for some S0 ¹ S. 1. Generalized Re° exivity: ! 2 ¦ "i (! ) for every ! 2 - . 2. St at ionarity: ! 0 2 ¦ i (! ) implies ¦ i (! 0) = ¦ i (! ). 3. Project ions Preserve Awareness: If ! 2 S0, ! 2 ¦ i (! ) and S ¹ S0 t hen ! S 2 ¦ i (! S ). 4. Project ions Preserve Ignorance: If ! 2 S0 and S ¹ S0 t hen ¦ "i (! ) µ ¦ "i (! S ). ! S’ ¦i(!) !S S ¦i(!S) ! ! S’ S’ ¦i(!) ¦i(!) !S !S S S ¦i(!S) ¦i(!S) For each i 2 I , t here is a possibility correspondence ¦ sat isfying t he following propert ies: i : - ¡ ! 2- n f ; g 0. Con¯nedment : If ! 2 S t hen ¦ i (! ) µ S0 for some S0 ¹ S. 1. Generalized Re° exivity: ! 2 ¦ "i (! ) for every ! 2 - . 2. St at ionarity: ! 0 2 ¦ i (! ) implies ¦ i (! 0) = ¦ i (! ). 3. Project ions Preserve Awareness: If ! 2 S0, ! 2 ¦ i (! ) and S ¹ S0 t hen ! S 2 ¦ i (! S ). 4. Project ions Preserve Ignorance: If ! 2 S0 and S ¹ S0 t hen ¦ "i (! ) µ ¦ "i (! S ). 5. Project ions Preserve K nowledge: If S ¹ S0 ¹ S00, ! 2 S00 and ¦ i (! ) µ S0 t hen (¦ i (! )) S = ¦ i (! S ). ! S“ ¦i(!) S’ !S ¦i(!S) = (¦i(!))S S ! ! S“ ¦i(!) S“ ¦i(!) S’ !S ¦i(!S) = (¦i(!))S S S’ !S ¦i(!S) ¾ (¦i(!))S S For each i 2 I , t here is a possibility correspondence ¦ sat isfying t he following propert ies: i : - ¡ ! 2- n f ; g 0. Con¯nedment : If ! 2 S t hen ¦ i (! ) µ S0 for some S0 ¹ S. 1. Generalized Re° exivity: ! 2 ¦ "i (! ) for every ! 2 - . 2. St at ionarity: ! 0 2 ¦ i (! ) implies ¦ i (! 0) = ¦ i (! ). 3. Project ions Preserve Awareness: If ! 2 S0, ! 2 ¦ i (! ) and S ¹ S0 t hen ! S 2 ¦ i (! S ). 4. Project ions Preserve Ignorance: If ! 2 S0 and S ¹ S0 t hen ¦ "i (! ) µ ¦ "i (! S ). 5. Project ions Preserve K nowledge: If S ¹ S0 ¹ S00, ! 2 S00 and ¦ i (! ) µ S0 t hen (¦ i (! )) S = ¦ i (! S ). R em ar k Generalized Re° exivity implies t hat if S0 ¹ S, ! 2 S and ¦ i (! ) µ S0, t hen r SS0 (! ) 2 ¦ i (! ). In part icular, we have ¦ i (! ) 6 = ; , for all ! 2 - . R em ar k Property 5 and Con¯nement (Property 0) imply Property 3. R em ar k Generalized Re° exivity implies t hat if S0 ¹ S, ! 2 S and ¦ i (! ) µ S0, t hen r SS 0 (! ) 2 ¦ i (! ). In part icular, we have ¦ i (! ) 6 = ; , for all ! 2 - . R em ar k Property 5 and Con¯nement (Property 0) imply Property 3. D S0 hS; ¹ i ; (r S ) S¹ E S 0 ; (¦ i ) i 2 I is an unawareness structure. T he knowledge operator of individual i on event s E is de¯ned, as usual, by K i (E ) := f ! 2 - : ¦ i (! ) µ E g ; if t here is a st at e ! such t hat ¦ i (! ) µ E , and by K i (E ) := ; S( E ) ot herwise. T he knowledge operator of individual i on event s E is de¯ned, as usual, by K i (E ) := f ! 2 - : ¦ i (! ) µ E g ; if t here is a st at e ! such t hat ¦ i (! ) µ E , and by K i (E ) := ; S( E ) ot herwise. P r op osit ion If E is an event , t hen K i (E ) is an S(E )-based event . P r op osit ion T he knowledge operat or K i has t he following propert ies: (i) Necessit at ion: K i (- ) = - , ³T ´ T (ii) Conjunct ion: K i = j K i (E j ), j Ej (iii) Trut h: K i (E ) µ E , (iv) Posit ive Int rospect ion: K i (E ) µ K i K i (E ), (v) Monot onicity: E µ F implies K i (E ) µ K i (F ), (vi) : K i (E ) \ : K i : K i (E ) µ : K i : K i : K i (E ). T he awareness operator of individual i is de¯ned on event s E by A i (E ) = f ! 2 - : ¦ i (! ) µ S(E )g; if t here is a st at e ! 2 - such t hat ¦ i (! ) µ S(E ), and by A i (E ) = ; S( E ) ot herwise. T he awareness operator of individual i is de¯ned on event s E by © ª " A i (E ) = ! 2 - : ¦ i (! ) µ S(E ) ; if t here is a st at e ! 2 - such t hat ¦ i (! ) µ S(E ), and by A i (E ) = ; S( E ) ot herwise. T he unawareness operator is t hen nat urally de¯ned by Ui (E ) = : A i (E ): P r op osit i on T he following propert ies obt ain: 1. K U Int rospect ion: K i Ui (E ) = ; S( E ) , 2. AU Int rospect ion: Ui (E ) = Ui Ui (E ), 3. Plausibility: Ui (E ) = : K i (E ) \ : K i : K i (E ), T1 n 4. St rong Plausibility: Ui (E ) = n = 1 (: K i ) (E ), ³ ´ " 5. Weak Necessit at ion: A i (E ) = K i S (E ) , 6. Weak Negat ive Int rospect ion: : K i (E ) \ A i : K i (E ) = K i : K i (E ), 7. Symmet ry: A i (E ) = A i (: E ), ¡T ¢ T 8. A-Conjunct ion: ¸ 2 L A i (E ¸ ) = A i ¸ 2 L E¸ , 9. AK - Re° ect ion: A i (E ) = A i K i (E ), 10. AA- Re° ect ion: A i (E ) = A i A i (E ), 11. A-Int rospect ion: A i (E ) = K i A i (E ). Illustration E = {!2} !2 !3 !1 Ab(E)={!2} Ub(E) = {!3} :KaUb(E) = {!2, !3} :KaAb(E) = {!2, !3} Kb:KaUb(E) = {!2} AaKb:KaUb(E) = {!2, !3} … T he mut ual knowledge operat or on event s is de¯ned by \ K (E ) = K i (E ): i2I T he mut ual knowledge operat or on event s is de¯ned by \ K (E ) = K i (E ): i2I T he common knowledge operat or is de¯ned by \1 CK (E ) = n= 1 K n (E ): T he mut ual knowledge operat or on event s is de¯ned by \ K (E ) = K i (E ): i2I T he common knowledge operat or is de¯ned by \1 K n (E ): CK (E ) = n= 1 T he mut ual awareness operat or on event s is de¯ned by \ A(E ) = A i (E ); i2I and t he common awareness operat or by \1 CA(E ) = n (A) (E ): n= 1 P r op osit i on T he following mult i-agent propert ies obt ain: 1. A i (E ) = A i A j (E ), 2. A i (E ) = A i K j (E ), 3. K i (E ) µ A i K j (E ), 4. A(E ) = K (S(E ) " ), 5. A(E ) = CA(E ), 6. K (E ) µ A(E ), 7. CK (E ) µ CA(E ), 8. CK (S(E ) " ) µ CA(E ). Logic of unawareness • Syntax versus semantics: What’s the internal structure of states? What’s the interpretation of the lattice? • How comprehensive are unawareness structures? Can the model itself be subject to agents’ uncertainties? Can any minute detail of awareness, beliefs, mutual beliefs, etc. of all individuals be described in some state of the model? • Soundness: Is any theorem valid in all states? • Completeness: Is every formula that is valid in all states also provable? Given a nonempty set of agent s i 2 I , a nonempty set of at omic formulae p 2 At as well as t he special formula > , t he formulae ' of t he language L kI ;a (At ) are de¯ned by t he grammar ' ::= p j : ' j ' ^ à j ki ' j ai ' : at omic formula: \ penicillium rubens has ant ibiot ic propert ies" Given a nonempty set of agent s i 2 I , a nonempty set of at omic formulae p 2 At as well as t he special formula > , t he formulae ' of t he language L kI ;a (At ) are de¯ned by t he grammar ' ::= p j : ' j ' ^ à j ki ' j ai ' : at omic formula: \ penicillium rubens has ant ibiot ic propert ies" ' _ à := : (: ' ^ : Ã) (' ) Ã) := (: ' _ Ã) (' , Ã) := (' ) Ã) ^ (à ) ' ) De¯ne induct ively t he set of primit ive proposit ions At (' ) t hat appear in ' ² At (> ) := ; , ² At (p) := p, for p 2 At , ² At (: ' ) := At (' ), ² At (' ^ Ã) := At (' ) [ At (Ã), ² At (ki ' ) := At (' ) = : At (ai ' ). De¯ne induct ively t he set of primit ive proposit ions At (' ) t hat appear in ' ² At (> ) := ; , ² At (p) := p, for p 2 At , ² At (: ' ) := At (' ), ² At (' ^ Ã) := At (' ) [ At (Ã), ² At (ki ' ) := At (' ) = : At (ai ' ). Modica-Rust ichini de¯nit ion of awareness: ai ' := ki ' _ ki : ki ' . An axiom is a formula assumed. An inference rule infers a formula (i.e., a conclusion) from a collect ion of formulae (i.e., t he hypot hesis). An axiom system consist s of a collect ion of axioms and inferences rules. Axiom syst em S5kI ;a : Prop. All subst it ut ions inst ances of t aut ologies of proposit ional logic, including t he formula > . AS. ai : ' , ai ' (Symmet ry) AC. ai (' ^ Ã) , A i K j R. ai ' , ai ' ^ ai à (Awareness Conjunct ion) ai kj ' , for all j 2 I (Awareness K nowledge Re° ect ion) T . ki ' ) ' (Axiom of Trut h) 4. ki ' ) ki ki ' (Posit ive Int rospect ion Axiom) MP. From ' and ' ) à infer à (modus ponens) RK . For all nat uralSnumbers n ¸ 1, if ' 1 ; ' 2 ; :::; ' n and ' are such t hat At (' ) µ n`= 1 At (' ` ), t hen ' 1 ^ ' 2 ^ ¢¢¢^ ' n ) ' implies ki ' 1 ^ ki ' 2 ^ ¢¢¢^ ki ' n ) ki ' . (RK -Inference) A proof in an axiom syst em consist s of a sequence of formulae, where each formula is eit her an axiom in t he axiom syst em or follows by an applicat ion of an inference rule. A proof is a proof of a formula ' if t he last formula in t he proof is ' . A formula ' is provable in an axiom syst em if t here is a proof of ' in t he axiom syst em. T he set of theorems of an axiom syst em is t he smallest set of formulae t hat cont ain all axioms and t hat is closed under inference rules of t he axiom syst em. De¯ne ui ' := : ai ' . R em ar k T he Modica and Rust ichini de¯nit ion of awareness and axiom syst em S5kI ;a implies: K . ki ' ^ ki (' ) Ã) ) ki ' ki ' ^ ki à ) ki (' ^ Ã) NNI. ui ' ) : ki : ki : ki ' AI. ai ' ) ki ai ' V AGPP. ai ' , p2 A t ( ' ) ai p GenA . If ' is a t heorem, t hen ai ' ) ki ' is a t heorem. Given a language L (At ), a set of formulae ¡ is consistent wit h respect t o an axiom syst em if and only if t here is no formula ' such t hat bot h ' and : ' are provable from ¡ . ! is maximally consistent of formulae if it is consist ent and for any formula ' 2 L (At ) n ! , t he set ! [ f ' g is not consist ent . Every consist ent subset of L (At ) can be ext ended t o a maximally consist ent subset ! of L (At ). Moreover, ¡ µ L (At ) is a maximally consist ent subset of L (At ) if and only if ¡ is consist ent and for every ' 2 L(At), ' 2 ¡ or : ' 2 ¡ . Canonical const r uct ion: For every At 0 µ At, let SA t 0 be t he set of maximally consist ent set s ! A t 0 of formulae in t he sublanguage L kI ;a (At 0). C anonical const r uct ion: For every At 0 µ At, let SA t 0 be t he set of maximally consist ent set s ! A t 0 of formulae in t he sublanguage L kI ;a (At 0). hf SA t 0 gA t 0µ At ; ¹ i is a complet e lat t ice of disjoint spaces wit h t he order de¯ned by SA t 00 º SAt 0 if and only if At 00 ¶ At 0. - := S At 0µ At SAt 0 . C anonical const r uct ion: For every At 0 µ At, let SA t 0 be t he set of maximally consist ent set s ! A t 0 of formulae in t he sublanguage L kI ;a (At 0). hf SA t 0 gA t 0µ At ; ¹ i is a complet e lat t ice of disjoint spaces wit h t he order de¯ned by SA t 00 º SAt 0 if and only if At 00 ¶ At 0. - := S At 0µ At SAt 0 . 00 For any SA t 00 º SA t 0 , surject ive project ions r AA tt 0 : SA t 00 ¡ ! A t 00 are de¯ned by r A t 0 (! ) := ! \ L kI ;a (At 0). SA t 0 T heor em For every ! and i 2 I , t he possibility correspondence de¯ned by ¦ i (! ) ½ ¾ 0 (i) ki ' implies ' 2 ! ; and := ! 0 2 - : For every formula ' ; (ii) ai ' 2 ! i® ' 2 ! 0 or : ' 2 ! 0 sat is¯es Con¯nement , Generalized Re° exivity, Project ions Preserve Ignorance, and Project ions Preserve K nowledge. Moreover, for every formula ' , t he set of st at es [' ] := f ! 2 - : ' 2 ! g is a SA t ( ' ) -based event , and [: ' ] = : [' ], [' ^ Ã] = [' ] \ [Ã], [ki ' ] = K i [' ], [ai ' ] = A i [' ], and [ui ' ] = Ui [' ]. Set of event s in unawareness st ruct ures § Valuat ion V : At ¡ ! § Set of event s in unawareness st ruct ures § Valuat ion V : At ¡ ! § 0 Denot e M = hhS; ¹ i ; (r SS ) S 0¹ S ; (¦ i ) i 2 I ; V i . Set of event s in unawareness st ruct ures § Valuat ion V : At ¡ ! § 0 Denot e M = hhS; ¹ i ; (r SS ) S 0¹ S ; (¦ i ) i 2 I ; V i . De¯ne induct ively t he sat isfact ion relat ion on t he st ruct ure of formulae in L kI ;a (At ) M ; ! j= > , for all ! 2 - , M ; ! j= p if and only if ! 2 V (p), M ; ! j= ' ^ à if and only if ! 2 [' ] \ [Ã], M ; ! j= : ' if and only if ! 2 [: ' ], M ; ! j= ki ' if and only if ! 2 K i [' ], where [' ] := f ! 0 2 - : M ; ! 0 j= ' g, for every formula ' . In a Kripke st ruct ure, a formula is valid if it is t rue in every st at e. In an unawareness st ruct ure, a formula may not be de¯ned in every st at e! In a K ripke st ruct ure, a formula is valid if it is t rue in every st at e. In an unawareness st ruct ure, a formula may not be de¯ned in every st at e! ' is de¯ned in state ! in M if A formula T ! 2 p2 At ( ' ) (V (p) [ : V (p)). A formula ' is valid in M if M ; ! j= ' for all ! in which ' is de¯ned. A formula ' is valid if it is valid in all M . An axiom syst em is sound for a language L wit h respect t o a class of st ruct ures if every formula in L t hat is provable in t he axiom syst em is valid wit h respect t o every st ruct ure M . An axiom syst em is complete for a language L wit h respect t o a class of st ruct ures if every formula in L t hat is valid in every st ruct ure M is provable in t he axiom syst em. An axiom syst em is sound for a language L wit h respect t o a class of st ruct ures if every formula in L t hat is provable in t he axiom syst em is valid wit h respect t o every st ruct ure M . An axiom syst em is complete for a language L wit h respect t o a class of st ruct ures if every formula in L t hat is valid in every st ruct ure M is provable in t he axiom syst em. T heor em For t he language L kI ;a (At ), t he axiom syst em S5kI ;a is a sound and complet e axiomat izat ion wit h respect t o unawareness st ruct ures. An Example: Speculative Trade How to model the following example? Two agents: An owner o of a firm and a potential buyer b. Status quo value of the firm is $100. The owner is aware of a potential lawsuit l that may cost the firm $20. The buyer is unaware of it. The owner knows that the buyer is unaware of it. The buyer is aware of a potential innovation n that may enhance the value of the firm by $20. The owner is unaware of it. The buyer knows that the owner is unaware of it. Suppose the buyer is offering to buy the firm for $100. Is the owner going to sell to her? An Example: Speculative Trade ● n, l ● ● n, :l :n, l ● :n,:l Sn, l ● n ● ● :n l ● :l Sl Sn ● > S; The First Approach: Awareness Structures (Fagin and Halpern, Artificial Intelligence 1988) L(n) ● L(l) ● ● L(l) n, :l n, l L(n) L(n) L(l) :n, l L(n) L(l) ● :n,:l L(n) ● L(l) ● L(l) n, :l n, l L(n) L(n) L(l) ● :n, l L(n) Fagin and Halpern (1988), Halpern (2001), Halpern and Rego (2008) provide sound and complete axiomatizations of awareness structures under various assumptions on accessibility relations and awareness correspondences. (details) L(l) ● :n,:l The example models our story. Buyer: L(n) ● L(l) ● L(l) n, :l n, l L(n) L(n) L(l) ● :n, l L(n) L(l) ● :n,:l “I (implicitly) know that the owner is aware of the lawsuit but unfortunately I am unaware of the lawsuit.” It models reasoning of an outside observer about the knowledge and awareness of agents but not the agents’ subjective reasoning that economists, decision theorists, and game theorists are interested in. Semantics is not syntax-free. What would be the analogue to a Kripke frame? Awareness structures are very flexible. For instance, Should be very useful to model various forms of framing. The Second Approach: Generalized Standard Models (Modica and Rustichini, GEB 1999) ● n, l ● n, :l ● :n, l ● Single-agent structure :n,:l Sn, l ● n Sn ● :n Modica and Rustichini (1999) prove a sound and complete axiomatization. Use “objective” validity. Models reasoning of an outside observer about knowledge and awareness of a single agent. A Fourth Approach: Product Models (Li, 2008, JET 2009) n ● l (1n,1l) n ● l (0n,1l) * n ● l (1n,0l) n ● l (0n,0l) A Fourth Approach: Product Models (Li, 2008, JET 2009) n ● l n ● l (1n,1l) (1n,0l) n ● n l (0n,1l) ● l (0n,0l) * ● (1n) ● ● (0n) (1n) b(*) o(*) ● o (b(*)) = b (o(*)) ● (0n) A Fourth Approach: Product Models (Li, 2008, JET 2009) n ● n l ● n l (1n,1l) (1n,0l) ● n l (0n,1l) l ● (0n,0l) * n ● ; (1n) n ● ; ; (0n) ● l (1n) b(*) o(*) ; ● ; o (b(*)) = b (o(*)) ; ● l (0n) A Fourth Approach: Product Models (Li, 2008, JET 2009) n ● n l ● n l (1n,1l) (1n,0l) ● n l (0n,1l) Example models our story l ● (0n,0l) Possibility correspondence models implicit knowledge. * n ● ; (1n) n ● ; ; (0n) ● l (1n) b(*) o(*) ; ● ; ● l (0n) Sublattices represent subjective perceptions of the situation, while the objective state space represents the outside modeler’s view. ; o (b(*)) = b (o(*)) Li (2009) proves properties of unawareness and knowledge Further Epistemic Approaches Awareness of Unawareness: • Awareness structures with propositional quantifiers: Halpern and Rego (MSS 2013), Halpern and Rego (GEB 2009) • First-order modal logic with unawareness of objects: Board and Chung (2011) • First-order modal logic with unawareness of objects and properties: Quantified awareness neighborhood structures: Sillari (RSL 2008) • Awareness of unawareness without quantifiers: Agotnes and Alechina (2007), Walker (MSS 2014) Dynamic awareness: … “Evolution” of the literature on epistemic models of unawareness Survey: Schipper, B.C. “Awareness”, in: Handbook of Epistemic Logic, Chapter 3, H. van Ditmarsch, J.Y. Halpern, W. van der Hoek and B. Kooi (Eds.), College Publications, London, 2015, 77–146. Li (2009) Prod. models Heinsalu (2012) Halpern (2001) Single-agent aw. struc. Halpern (2001) Modica Rustichini (1999) Gen. stand. models Li (2008) Multiagent prod. m. Single-agent Multi-agent HMS (2006, 2008) Unawareness struct. Board Chung Schipper (2011) Ewerhart (2001) Pires (1994) Halpern Rego (2008) Board Chung (2011b) Obj.-based unaw. FH (1988) Prop. gen. awareness structures van Ditmarsch et al. (2013) Feinberg (2004, 2005, 2012) Galanis (2011, 2013) Wansing (1990) Fagin Halpern (1988) Awarness struct. Agotnes Alechina (2007) Walker (2013) Quantification Sillari (2008b) Sillari (2008a) Aw. neighb. Sillari (2008a) Imp. worlds neighb. Halpern Rego (2009) Prop. quant. aw. struct. Halpern Rego (2013) Prop. quant. aw. struct. Board Chung (2011a) FO Obj.-based unaw. Rantala (1982) Impossible worlds Sillari (2008b) Sillari (2008a) FO Aw. neighb. Sillari (2008a) FO Imposs. w. neighb. Returning to the speculative trade example: Say that at a state s an agent is willing to trade at the price $x if either she strictly prefers to trade at $x or she is indifferent between trading or not at $x. • At $100, both agents are willing to trade (in every state). • This is common knowledge among the agents at all states. • Yet, each agent has a strict preference to trade in all in all states except the lowest space. Both are indifferent between trading and not trading in the lowest space. The states in the lowest space are the “states of mind” of an agent as viewed by the other agent. Returning to the speculative trade example: Say that at a state s an agent is willing to trade at the price $x if either she strictly prefers to trade at $x or she is indifferent between trading or not at $x. • At $100, both agents are willing to trade (in every state). • This is common knowledge among the agents at all states. • Yet, each agent has a strict preference to trade in all in all states except the lowest space. Both are indifferent between trading and not trading in the lowest space. The states in the lowest space are the “states of mind” of an agent as viewed by the other agent. This is in contrast to the “Nospeculative-trade-theorems” of structures without unawareness (e.g., Milgrom and Stokey, 1982): If there is a common prior and common knowledge of willingness to trade, then both must be indifferent to trade. Need to talk about probabilities. Outline 1. 2. 3. 4. 5. 6. 7. 8. Informal introduction Epistemic models of unawareness Type spaces with unawareness Speculation Bayesian games with unawareness Revealed unawareness Dynamic games with unawareness …(???) 3. Type spaces with unawareness Type Spaces with Unawareness • Economists frequently make use of probabilistic notions of belief • Quantified notions of belief are often useful for applications (optimization under uncertainty) • How to model unawareness and probabilistic beliefs? Each S 2 S is now a measurable space wit h sigma-¯eld F S . If S0 º S, we require a measurable surject ive project ion S0 r S : S0 ! S. § denot es now t he set of measurable event s in t he unawareness st ruct ure. Denot e by 4 (S) is a set of probability measures on (S; F S ) endowed wit h t he sigma-¯eld F 4 ( S) generat ed by f ¹ 2 4 (S) : ¹ (D ) ¸ pg, D 2 F S , p 2 [0; 1]. For ¹ 2 4 (S0), t he marginal ¹ j S of ¹ on S ¹ S0 is de¯ned by µ³ ¶ ´ ¡ 1 S0 ¹ j S (D ) := ¹ rS (D ) ; D 2 F S : Denot e by S¹ t he space on which ¹ is a probability measure. Whenever S¹ º S(E ), we abuse not at ion ¹ (E ) = ¹ (E \ S¹ ). If S¹ 6 º S(E ), t hen ¹ (E ) is unde¯ned. D e¯nit ion S For each individual i 2 I t here is a type mapping ti : - ! ®2 A ¢ (S® ), which is measurable in t he sense t hat for every S 2 S and Q 2 F ¢ ( S) we have t ¡i 1 (Q) \ S 2 F S , for all S 2 S. We require t he type mapping t i t o sat isfy t he following propert ies: (0) Con¯nement: If ! 2 S0 t hen t i (! ) 2 ¢ (S) for some S ¹ S0. S’ ti() S ti() ’ S’ S’ ti() S S ti(’) S“ D e¯nit ion S For each individual i 2 I t here is a type mapping ti : - ! ®2 A ¢ (S® ), which is measurable in t he sense t hat for every S 2 S and Q 2 F ¢ ( S) we have t ¡i 1 (Q) \ S 2 F S , for all S 2 S. We require t he type mapping t i t o sat isfy t he following propert ies: (0) Con¯nement: If ! 2 S0 t hen t i (! ) 2 ¢ (S) for some S ¹ S0. (1) If S00 º S0 º S, ! 2 S00, and t i (! ) 2 4 (S) t hen t i (! S 0 ) = t i (! ). S’’ S’ S’ ti() = ti(S’) S S“ S’’ S’ S’ S’ S’ ti() ti() = ti(S’) S ti(S') S ti(S’) S* D e¯nit ion S For each individual i 2 I t here is a type mapping ti : - ! ®2 A ¢ (S® ), which is measurable in t he sense t hat for every S 2 S and Q 2 F ¢ ( S) we have t ¡i 1 (Q) \ S 2 F S , for all S 2 S. We require t he type mapping t i t o sat isfy t he following propert ies: (0) Con¯nement: If ! 2 S0 t hen t i (! ) 2 ¢ (S) for some S ¹ S0. (1) If S00 º S0 º S, ! 2 S00, and t i (! ) 2 4 (S) t hen t i (! S 0 ) = t i (! ). (2) If S00 º S0 º S, ! 2 S00, and t i (! ) 2 4 (S0) t hen t i (! S ) = t i (! ) j S . S’’ ti() S’ ti(S) = ti()|S S S’’ S’’ ti() ti() S’ S’ ti(S) = ti()|S S ti(S) ti()|S S D e¯nit ion S For each individual i 2 I t here is a type mapping ti : - ! ®2 A ¢ (S® ), which is measurable in t he sense t hat for every S 2 S and Q 2 F ¢ ( S) we have t ¡i 1 (Q) \ S 2 F S , for all S 2 S. We require t he type mapping t i t o sat isfy t he following propert ies: (0) Con¯nement: If ! 2 S0 t hen t i (! ) 2 ¢ (S) for some S ¹ S0. (1) If S00 º S0 º S, ! 2 S00, and t i (! ) 2 4 (S) t hen t i (! S 0 ) = t i (! ). (2) If S00 º S0 º S, ! 2 S00, and t i (! ) 2 4 (S0) t hen t i (! S ) = t i (! ) j S . (3) If S00 º S0 º S, ! 2 S00, and t i (! S 0) 2 4 (S) t hen St i ( ! ) º S. S’’ ti() S’ S’ St () i ti(S’) S S’’ S’’ ti() S’ S’ St () i S’ ti(S’) S S’ ti() ti(S’) S St () i ti() D e¯nit ion S For each individual i 2 I t here is a type mapping ti : - ! ®2 A ¢ (S® ), which is measurable in t he sense t hat for every S 2 S and Q 2 F ¢ ( S) we have t ¡i 1 (Q) \ S 2 F S , for all S 2 S. We require t he type mapping t i t o sat isfy t he following propert ies: (0) Con¯nement: If ! 2 S0 t hen t i (! ) 2 ¢ (S) for some S ¹ S0. (1) If S00 º S0 º S, ! 2 S00, and t i (! ) 2 4 (S) t hen t i (! S 0 ) = t i (! ). (2) If S00 º S0 º S, ! 2 S00, and t i (! ) 2 4 (S0) t hen t i (! S ) = t i (! ) j S . (3) If S00 º S0 º S, ! 2 S00, and t i (! S 0) 2 4 (S) t hen St i ( ! ) º S. R em ar k Property 1 is implied by t he ot her propert ies. A n ssum pt ion ( I nt r osp ect ion) o If ! 0 2 - : t i (! 0) j St i ( ! ) = t i (! ) µ E , E an event , t hen t i (! )(E ) = 1. D e¯nit i on For i 2 I and an event E , de¯ne t he awareness operator A i (E ) := f ! 2 - : t i (! ) 2 ¢ (S) ; S º S (E )g if t here is a st at e ! such t hat t i (! ) 2 ¢ (S) wit h S º S(E ), and by A i (E ) := ; S( E ) ot herwise. T he unawareness operator of individual i 2 I on event s is now de¯ned by Ui (E ) = : A i (E ): L em m a If E is a (not necessarily measurable) event , t hen A i (E ) (and t hus Ui (E )) is an S (E )-based event . D e¯nit i on For i 2 I , p 2 [0; 1] and an event E , t he p-belief operator is de¯ned, as usual, by B ip (E ) := f ! 2 - : t i (! )(E ) ¸ pg; if t here is a st at e ! such t hat t i (! )(E ) ¸ p, and by B ip (E ) := ; S( E ) ot herwise. P r op osit i on If E is an event , t hen B ip (E ) is an S (E )-based event . P r op osit i on ( St andar d P r op er t ies) Let E and F be event s, f E l gl = 1;2;::: be an at most count able collect ion of event s, and p; q 2 [0; 1]. T he following propert ies of belief obt ain: (o) B ip (E ) µ B iq (E ), for q · p, (i) Necessit at ion: B i1 (- ) = - , (ii) Addit ivity: B ip (E ) µ : B iq (: E ), for p + q > 1, T1 p T1 (iiia) B i ( l = 1 E l ) µ l = 1 B ip (E l ), 1 (iiib) for any decreasing sequence of event s f E g l l = 1, T T B ip ( 1l= 1 E l ) = 1l= 1 B ip (E l ), T1 T1 1 (iiic) B i ( l = 1 E l ) = l = 1 B i1 (E l ), (iv) Monot onicity: E µ F implies B ip (E ) µ B ip (F ), (v) Int rospect ion: B ip (E ) µ B i1 B ip (E ). P r op osit ion Let E be an event and p; q 2 [0; 1]. T he following propert ies of awareness and belief obt ain: 1. Plausibility: Ui (E ) µ : B ip (E ) \ : B ip : B ip (E ), T1 n 2. St rong Plausibility: Ui (E ) µ n = 1 (: B ip ) (E ), 3. B p U Int rospect ion: B ip Ui (E ) = ; S( E ) for p 2 (0; 1], B i0 Ui (E ) = A i (E ), 4. AU Int rospect ion: Ui (E ) = Ui Ui (E ), ¡ ¢ 1 " 5. Weak Necessit at ion: A i (E ) = B i S(E ) , 6. B ip (E ) µ A i (E ), B i0 (E ) = A i (E ), 7. B ip (E ) µ A i B iq (E ), 8. Symmet ry: A i (E ) = A i (: E ), ¡T ¢ T 9. A Conjunct ion: ¸ 2 L A i (E ¸ ) = A i ¸ 2 L E¸ , 10. AB p Self Re° ect ion: A i B ip (E ) = A i (E ), 11. AA Self Re° ect ion: A i A i (E ) = A i (E ), 12. B ip A i (E ) = A i (E ). B elief A war eness mut ualT belief B p (E ) := i 2 I B ip (E ) mut ual T awareness A(E ) := i 2 I A i (E ) commonTcert ainty 1 CB 1 (E ) := n = 1 (B 1 ) n (E ) commonT awareness 1 n CA(E ) := n = 1 (A) (E ) P r op osit ion Let E be an event and p; q 2 [0; 1]. T he following mult i-person propert ies obt ain: 1. A i (E ) = A i A j (E ), 2. A i (E ) = A i B jp (E ), 3. B ip (E ) µ A i B jq (E ), 4. B ip (E ) µ A i A j (E ), 5. CA(E ) = A(E ), 6. CB 1 (E ) µ CA(E ), 7. B p (E ) µ A(E ), B 0 (E ) = A(E ), 8. B p (E ) µ CA(E ), B 0 (E ) = CA(E ), 9. A(E ) = B 1 (S(E ) " ), 10. CA(E ) = B 1 (S(E ) " ), 11. CB 1 (S(E ) " ) µ A(E ), 12. CB 1 (S(E ) " ) µ CA(E ). 4. Speculation Revisiting to the speculative trade example • Status quo value of the firm depends on high ($100) or low ($80) sales, which is equiprobable. • Both whether or not there is a lawsuit and whether or not there is a novelty are equiprobably too. • Moreover, all events are independent. nls n¬ls nl¬s n¬l¬s ¬nls ¬n¬ls ¬nl¬s ¬n¬l¬s ● ● ● ● ● ● ● ● S{nls} ns n¬s ¬ns ¬n¬s ls l¬s ¬ls ¬l¬s ● ● ● ● ● ● ● ● S{ns} S{ls} s ¬s ● ● S{s} nls n¬ls nl¬s n¬l¬s ¬nls ¬n¬ls ¬nl¬s ¬n¬l¬s ● ● ● ● ● ● ● ● S{nls} ns n¬s ¬ns ¬n¬s ls l¬s ¬ls ¬l¬s ● ● ● ● ● ● ● ● ¼ ¼ ¼ ¼ ¼ ¼ ¼ ¼ S{ns} S{ls} s ¬s ● ● ½ ½ S{s} nls n¬ls nl¬s n¬l¬s ¬nls ¬n¬ls ¬nl¬s ¬n¬l¬s ● ● ● ● ● ● ● ● ⅛ ⅛ ⅛ ⅛ ⅛ ⅛ ⅛ ⅛ S{nls} ns n¬s ¬ns ¬n¬s ls l¬s ¬ls ¬l¬s ● ● ● ● ● ● ● ● ¼ ¼ ¼ ¼ ¼ ¼ ¼ ¼ S{ns} S{ls} s ¬s ● ● ½ ½ S{s} Revisiting to the speculative trade example • There is a common prior (i.e., a projective system of probability measures with which agents’ types are consistent) and common certainty of willingness to trade but each agent has a strict preference to trade. • Counterexample to Milgrom and Stokey (1982). • Speculative trade is possible under unawareness. • Knife-edge case??? Prior in a st andard type space S (Samet , 1998): For every event E 2 F S , PiS (E ) = R S t (¢ ) (E ) dP i i (¢). S ² convex combinat ion of post eriors (types) ² a consist ency condit ion on types inst ead of a belief at a \ prior st age" D e¯nit i on ( P r ior ) A prior ¡ Sfor ¢ playerQi is a syst em of probability measures Pi = Pi S2 S 2 S2 S ¢ (S) such t hat 1. T he syst em is project ive: If S0 ¹ S t hen t he marginal S 0 S0 of Pi on S is Pi . (T hat is, if E 2 § is an event whose base-space S (E ) is lower or equal t o S0, t hen S S0 Pi (E ) = Pi (E ).) 2. Each probability measure PiS is a convex combinat ion of i 's beliefs in S: For every event E 2 § such t hat S(E ) ¹ S, Z PiS (E \ S \ A i (E )) = t i (¢) (E ) dPiS (¢) : ¡ S ¢ S\ A i ( E ) Q P = P S2 S 2 S2 S ¢ (S) is a common prior if P is a prior for every player i 2 I . 3 1/9 1 1/18 4 2/9 2 2/18 5 1/18 7 1/9 6 2/18 8 2/9 S’ odd even 1/3 2/3 S [t i (! )] := f ! 0 2 - : t i (! 0) = t i (! )g ¡ S ¢ Q D e¯nit ion ( P r ior ) A common prior P = P S2 S 2 S2 S ¢ (S) is positive if and only if for all i³ 2 I and ! 2 - : If ´t i (! ) 2 4 (S0), " t hen [t i (! )] \ S0 2 F S 0 and P S ([t i (! )] \ S0) \ S > 0 for all S º S0. Let x 1 and x 2 be real numbers and v a random variable on - .o n R · x1 De¯ne t he set s E 1 := ! 2 - : St ( ! ) v (¢) d (t 1 (! )) (¢) · x 1 1 n o R and E 2¸ x 2 := ! 2 - : St ( ! ) v (¢) d (t 2 (! )) (¢) ¸ x 2 . 2 We say t hat at ! , condit ional on his informat ion, player 1 (resp. player 2) believes t hat t he expect at ion of v is weakly below x 1 (resp. weakly above x 2 ) if and only if ! 2 E 1· x 1 (resp. ! 2 E 2¸ x 2 ). belief st ruct ure wit h T heor em Consider a ¯nit e unawareness ¡ S¢ Q a posit ive common prior P = P S2 S 2 S2 S ¢ (S). T hen t here is no st at e !~ 2 - such t hat t here are a random variable v : - ¡ ! R and x 1 ; x 2 2 R, x 1 < x 2 , wit h t he following property: at !~ it is common cert ainty t hat condit ional on her informat ion, player 1 believes t hat t he expect at ion of v is weakly below x 1 and, condit ional on his informat ion, player 2 believes t hat t he expect at ion of v is weakly above x 2 . Arbit rary small t ransact ion cost s (like a Tobin t ax) rule out speculat ive t rade under unawareness. Converse t o t he t heorem is false. 5. Bayesian games with unawareness Bayesian games with unawareness • Unawareness of (payoff-)relevant events, actions, and players. • Replace type space with unawareness type space. • Digression: How do we model uncertainty over action sets in standard games? D e¯nit ion A Bayesian game wit h unawareness ¿ À ³ ´ ¡ (S) = hS; ¹ i ; r SS¯® ; (t i ) i 2 I ; (M i ) i 2 I ; (M i ) i 2 I ; (ui ) i 2 I S¯ ¹ S® consist s of a ¯nit e unawareness ¿ À type space ³ ´ hS; ¹ i ; r SS¯® ; (t i ) i 2 I and S¯ ¹ S® (i) a nonempty ¯nit e set of act ions M i , for i 2 I , and a correspondence M i : - ¡ ! 2M i n f ; g, for i 2 I , such t hat for any nonempty subset of act ions1 M i0 µ M i , [M i0] := f ! 2 - : M i0 µ M i (! )g is an event (in t he unawareness type space), and ! 0; ! 00 2 [t i (! )] \ St i ( ! ) implies M i (! 0) = M i (! 00), for all ! 2 - , (ii) for every i ³ 2³ I , a ut ility funct ion ´ ´ S Q ui : ! 2 j 2 I M j (! ) £ f ! g ¡ ! R. A strategy of player i in a Bayesian game wit h unawareness is a funct ion ¾i : - ¡ ! ¢ (M i ) such t hat for all ! 2 - , ³ ´ (i) ¾i (! ) 2 ¢ M i (! St i ( ! ) ) , and (ii) t i (! 0) = t i (! ) implies ¾i (! 0) = ¾i (! ). Example (Feinberg 2005) Unique Nash equilibrium (a2, b1) !1 !2 S !3 S’ An equilibrium !1 !2 S !3 S’ An equilibrium ³ Denot e ¾St i ( ! := ) ´ 0 (¾j (! )) j 2 I . T he expected utility of player-type ! 02 S t i ( ! ) (i ; t i (! )) from t he st rat egy pro¯le ¾St i ( ! ) U( i ;t i ( ! ) ) (¾S t i ( ! ) ) := X ! 02 S t i 0 X (! ) m2 µ Q j 2I M j ¶ ! 0 St 0 j (! ) is given by 1 Y @ ¾j (! 0) (f m j g) A ¢ui ((m j ) j 2 I ; ! 0) t i (! )(f ! 0g): j 2I D e¯nit i on Given a Bayesian game wit h unawareness ¡ (S), de¯ne t he associat ed st rat egic game by (i) f (i ; t i (! )) : ! 2 - and i 2 I g is t he set of players, and for each player (i ; t i (! )), (ii) t he set of mixed st rat egies is ¢ (M i (! S t i ( ! ) ), and (iii) t he ut ility funct ion is given above. A pro¯le (¾i ) i 2 I is an equilibrium of t he Bayesian game wit h unawareness if and only if t he following is an equilibrium of t he associat ed st rat egic game: (i ; t i (! )) plays ¾i (! ), for all i 2 I and ! 2 - . P r op osit ion ( Ex ist ence) Every ¯nit e Bayesian game wit h unawareness has an equilibrium. Sublat t ice wit h least upper bound S is l (S) := f S0 2 S : S0 ¹ Sg Given ¡ (S), t he S-part ial game is ¡ (l(S)). At ! 2 - , player i views t he game as given by ¡ (l(St i ( ! ) )). P r op osit i on Given a Bayesian game wit h unawareness ¡ (S), consider for S0; S00 2 S wit h S0 ¹ S00 t he S0-part ial (resp. S00 -part ial) Bayesian game wit h unawareness. If I , - , and (M i ) i 2 I are ¯nit e, t hen for every equilibrium of t he S0-part ial Bayesian game, t here is an equilibrium of t he S00-part ial Bayesian 0 game in which equilibrium st rat egies of player-types in f (i ; t (! )) : ! 2 = i S 0 S2 l ( S 0) S and i 2 I g are ident ical wit h t he equilibrium st rat egies in t he S part ial Bayesian game. R em ar k Consider for S0; S00 2 S wit h S0 ¹ S00 t he S0-part ial (resp. S00part ial) Bayesian game wit h unawareness of given game ¡ (S). T hen for every equilibrium of t he S00-part ial Bayesian game t here is a unique equilibrium of t he S0-part ial Bayesian game in which t he equilibrium st rat egies of player-types S in f (i ; t i (! )) : ! 2 - 0 = S2 l ( S 0) S and i 2 I g are ident ical t o t he equilibrium st rat egies of t he S00-part ial Bayesian game. (Peleg and T ijs, 1996, Peleg, Pot t ers, and T ijs, 1996) Unawareness perfection Unawareness perfection Unawareness perfection Unawareness perfection Unawareness perfection Unawareness perfection Unawareness perfection Unawareness perfection Unawareness perfection • Opponents could have any awareness level • Full support belief over types of opponent • Consider limit belief over opponent’s types close to him being fully aware. • Limit Bayesian Nash equilibrium selects (U, L), the undominated Nash equilibrium. For each strategic game, construct a Bayesian game with unawareness in which each player has a full support belief over opponents’ having any awareness of action sets. Each such Bayesian game with unawareness has a Bayesian Nash equilibrium. Definition An unawareness perfect equilibrium of a strategic game is a Nash equilibrium for which there exists a sequence Bayesian games with certainty of awareness at the limit and a corresponding sequence of Bayesian Nash equilibria such that the limit of the sequence at the true state converges to the Nash equilibrium. Theorem For every finite strategic game, an unawareness perfect equilibrium exist. Theorem A Nash equilibrium is an unawareness perfect equilibrium if and only if undominated (i.e., not weakly dominated). Interpretation Undominated Nash equilibrium: No opponents’ action may be excluded from consideration. Unawareness perfect equilibrium: Slight chance that any opponents’ subset of action profiles may be excluded from consideration. (Increases the probability that other not excluded actions are played.) Comparison to Trembling Hand Perfection: • Independence of opponents’ mistakes. • Mutual belief in opponents’ mistakes. • No assumption of irrational behavior / mistakes under unawareness perfection. Instead beliefs are formed over opponents’ perception of the game. 6. Revealed Unawareness Revealed Unawareness • What’s the difference between a zeroprobability event and unawareness? • Can we reveal unawareness? Savage confined subjective expected utility theory (SEU) to the decision maker’s small world. The decision maker chooses among acts, i.e., mappings from states to outcomes. Can the decision maker choose among acts without being made aware of events by the description of acts? Yes, in reality we do it all the times. No, in standard SEU models. Proposal for resolution: • Replace the state space in Savage by lattice of spaces. • Define acts on the union of spaces. • Let preferences depend on the space (i.e., the awareness level). • The decision maker chooses among actions that are “names” for acts that are not necessarily understood by the decision maker. His understanding depends on her awareness level. l 80 :l 100 ; l :l 100 100 ~ ; l :l 100 80 ~ ; 100 100 100 Contract 1 Contract 2 Contract 3 Choice behavior is inconsistent with either “lawsuit” or “not lawsuit” being a Savage null event. But it is consistent with unawareness of “lawsuit”. Outline 1. 2. 3. 4. 5. 6. 7. 8. Informal introduction Epistemic models of unawareness Type spaces with unawareness Speculation Bayesian games with unawareness Revealed unawareness Dynamic games with unawareness …(???) 7. Dynamic games with unawareness • How to model dynamic interactions between players with asymmetric awareness? What are the problems: o Players may be aware of different subsets players, moves of nature, or actions (i.e., different “representations” of the game) o Players may become aware of further players, moves of nature or actions during the play of the game (i.e., endogenous changes of their “representations” of the game) • What is a sensible solution concept? What are the problems: o Players couldn’t learn equilibrium through repeated play (because of “novel” situations) o Subgame perfection, sequential equilibrium etc. ignore surprises but with unawareness players could be surprised frequently o Players may make others strategically aware. Thus players should be able to reason carefully when being surprised by others rather than discarding surprising actions of others as a mistake. Introductory Example • A glimpse of how we model unawareness in dynamic games • what solution concept we suggest to these models • Relevance: Show that outcomes under unawareness of an action may differ from outcomes under the unavailability of an action Example: Battle of the Sexes II B S B 3, 1 0, 0 S 0, 0 1, 3 I Example: Battle of the Sexes B II S M B 3, 1 0, 0 0, 4 I S 0, 0 1, 3 0, 4 M 0, 0 0, 0 2, 6 Example: A kind of “Battle of the Sexes” I not give car to player II give car to player II II II I B S B 3, 1 0, 0 S 0, 0 1, 3 M 0, 0 0, 0 I B S M B 3, 1 0, 0 0, 4 S 0, 0 1, 3 0, 4 M 0, 0 0, 0 2, 6 S1I = {any strategy except ones with “M” after not giving the car} S1II = {(B, M), (S, M)} S2I = {(not give, B, M), (give, B, M)} S2II = {(B, M), (S, M)} S3I = {not give, B, M), (give, B, M)} S3II = {(B, M)} S4I = {not give, B, M)} S4II = {(B, M)} Unique extensive-form rationalizable outcome Example: A kind of “Battle of the Sexes” I not give car to player II give car to player II II II I B S B 3, 1 0, 0 S 0, 0 1, 3 M 0, 0 0, 0 I B S M B 3, 1 0, 0 0, 4 S 0, 0 1, 3 0, 4 M 0, 0 0, 0 2, 6 Example: A kind of “Battle of the Sexes” I not tell player II about the Mozart concert tell player II about the Mozart concert II II I B S B 3, 1 0, 0 S 0, 0 1, 3 M 0, 0 0, 0 II I B S B 3, 1 0, 0 S 0, 0 1, 3 I B S M B 3, 1 0, 0 0, 4 S 0, 0 1, 3 0, 4 M 0, 0 0, 0 2, 6 Two novel features: - Forest of trees, partial order - Information set at a history of a tree may be located in a less expressive tree Example: A kind of “Battle of the Sexes” I not tell player II about the Mozart concert tell player II about the Mozart concert II II I B S B 3, 1 0, 0 S 0, 0 1, 3 M 0, 0 0, 0 II I I B S M B 3, 1 0, 0 0, 4 S 0, 0 1, 3 0, 4 M 0, 0 0, 0 2, 6 Notion of strategy B S B 3, 1 0, 0 S 0, 0 1, 3 Example: A kind of “Battle of the Sexes” I not tell player II about the Mozart concert tell player II about the Mozart concert II II I B S B 3, 1 0, 0 S 0, 0 1, 3 M 0, 0 0, 0 II I I B S M B 3, 1 0, 0 0, 4 S 0, 0 1, 3 0, 4 M 0, 0 0, 0 2, 6 Notion of strategy B S B 3, 1 0, 0 S 0, 0 1, 3 Player I Example: A kind of “Battle of the Sexes” I not tell player II about the Mozart concert tell player II about the Mozart concert II II I B S B 3, 1 0, 0 S 0, 0 1, 3 M 0, 0 0, 0 II I I B S M B 3, 1 0, 0 0, 4 S 0, 0 1, 3 0, 4 M 0, 0 0, 0 2, 6 Notion of strategy B S B 3, 1 0, 0 S 0, 0 1, 3 Player I Player II Example: A kind of “Battle of the Sexes” S1I = {any strategy except ones with “M” after not tell} S1II = {(M, B), (M, S)} S2I = {don’t tell, B, M, B), (don’t tell, B, M, S), (tell, B, M, B), (tell, B, M, S)} S2II = {(M, B), (M, S)} S3I = {don’t tell, B, M, B), (don’t tell, B, M, S), (tell, B, M, B), (tell, B, M, S)} S3II = {(M, B), (M, S)} Different extensive-form rationalizable outcomes Extensive Form Games with Unawareness Generalized Game Partially Ordered Set of Trees Partially Ordered Set of Trees Partially Ordered Set of Trees Partially Ordered Set of Trees Generalized Game T ● ●n ● ● ● ● T’ n’ Generalized Game ● i ● n’ i ●n a ● b c ● a ● ● b ● c ● ● ● i ● n’ i ●n a ● b c ● a ● ● b ● i ● n’ i ●n a c ● ● b c ● a ● ● b ● c ● i ● n’ i ●n a ● b c ● a ● ● ● ● b ● i ● n’ i ●n a c ● ● b c ● d a ● ● e b ● Information sets in a generalized game Standard Standard Generalized Standard Generalized New ● T ●n ● ● ● ● T’ n’ ● ● ● ● T ●n ● ● ● ● ● T’ ● ● n’ ● ● ● ● ● ● ● ● T ●n ● ● ● ● ● ● T ●n ● ● T’ Information set across subtrees ● ● n’ ● T’ ● ● ● ● ● n’ ● ● ● ●n ● ●n ● ● ● ● ● ● ● ● ● ● ● n’ ● ●n ● ● ● ● ● ●n Nested information sets ● n’ ●n ● ● ● ● n’ ● ● ● ● ● ● ● ● n’ ● n’ ●n ● ● ●n ● ● ● ● ● ● ● n’’ ● ● ● i ●n T ● ● ● i ● ● ● T’ ● ● i ● n’ ● ● ● ● ● i ● n” ● ● ● i ●n T ● ● ● i ● ● ● ● ● ● ● ● i ● n” ● i ● ● ● ● ● ● i ● n’ ● ● ● ● ● T’ ● ● ● ● i ● n’ T’ ● ● i ●n T i ● n” ● ● ● ●n T ● a ● T’ ● b ● n’ a b ● c ● ● a b ● T’ ● T ●n T ● n’ a b ● c ● ● ●n a ● n’ T’ ● b ● a b ● c ● ● ●n a ● ● n’ b a b ● ● ● ● ● ●n a ● ●n ● n’ b a b ● ● ● a ● ● n’ b a b ● ● ● ● ● n1 ai ● ● ● ● ● ● ● ● ● ●n1’ ai ● ● ● nl’ ● ● ● ● nk ● ● ● ● ● ● ● ● ● ● ● ● ● ● ● ● ● ● n’ i ● ● n’’ ● Generalized Extensive-Form Games Extensive-form Rationalizability Strategies Belief Systems Generalizing Extensive-form Rationalizability (Pearce 1984, Battigalli 1997) to Dynamic Unawareness Generalizing Extensive-form Rationalizability (Pearce 1984, Battigalli 1997) to Dynamic Unawareness Prudent Rationalizability Prudent Rationalizability Prudent rationalizability is not a refinement of extensive-form rationalizability in terms of strategies. Prudence vs. Rationalizability: Divining the opponent's past behavior I Prudent rationalizability Extensive-form rationalizability b a c II 6, 6 d 3, 4 e 4, 3 f 10, 0 d 5, 5 e 6, 6 f 0, 0 Application to Verifiable Information 1. With Full Awareness: a la Milgrom and Roberts (1986) • One seller, one buyer • One merchandise with quality L or H • For each quality, the seller is better off from selling a larger quantity. • The buyer’s utility is strictly concave in quantity with single peak ¯(¢) and ¯(L) < ¯(H). • Before a sale takes place, the seller can provide a certified signal about the quality: can be imprecise but must be truthful • The buyer’s unique prudent rationalizable strategy is to buy ¯(L) if presented with {L} or {L, H} and ¯(H) if presented with {H}, while the seller’s unique prudent rationalizable strategy is to certify {L, H} when his quality is L and {H} when is quality is H. Full unraveling. Application to Verifiable Information 2. With Unawareness of a Dimension of Quality • One merchandise with quality q 2 {L, H} £ {0, *} • For instance, available certificates in state (L,0): {L, H} £ {0, *}, {L} £ {0, *}, {L, H} £ {0}, and {L} £ {0} • ¯(L,*) < ¯(L,0) < ¯(H,0) < ¯(H,*). • If the buyer is fully aware of both dimensions of quality, we still obtain full unraveling by previous arguments. • Assume now that the buyer is aware only of dimension {L, H} while being unaware of dimension {0, *}. Assume ¯(L) = ¯(L,0) and ¯(H) = ¯(H,0). c L* L0 Seller Seller Seller {L,H}£{0, {L,H}£{0, *} ● ● {L,H}£{0} … ● {H}£{0} ● ● … ● {L,H}£{*} ● {H} … {H}£{0, *} … {L, H} … … {L,H}£{0, *} {H}£{0, *} {L, H} {L} *} {L,H}£{0} {L}£{0, *} ● … ● {L}£{*} {L, H} … *} {L,H}£{*} ● {L}£{0} Seller {L,H}£{0, ● … {L}£{0, *} {L} H* H0 … … {H} … c H Seller Seller {L} … {L,H} {L,H} ● ● … … … … L ● {L, H} … … {H}£{*} {H} … Application to Verifiable Information 2. With Unawareness of a Dimension of Quality • One merchandise with quality q 2 {L, H} £ {0, *} • For instance, available certificates in state (L,0): {L, H} £ {0, *}, {L} £ {0, *}, {L, H} £ {0}, and {L} £ {0} • ¯(L,*) < ¯(L,0) < ¯(H,0) < ¯(H,*). • If the buyer is fully aware of both dimensions of quality, we still obtain full unraveling by previous arguments. • Assume now that the buyer is aware only of dimension {L, H} while being unaware of dimension {0, *}. Assume ¯(L) = ¯(L,0) and ¯(H,0) = ¯(H). • In the verifiable information model in which the buyer is unaware of some dimension of the the good's quality, the seller does not fully reveal the quality in any prudent rationalizable outcome. E.g., (L, *). Conditional Dominance Can we capture these solution concepts in “normal-form“ games with unawareness? How crucial is the “time-structure” for the analysis of strategic interaction under unawareness? For standard extensive-form games, Shimoji and Watson (JET 1998) show that extensive-form rationalizability is characterized by iterated elimination of conditionally strictly dominated strategies. Chen and Micali (TE 2012) show orderindependence of iterated elimination of conditionally strictly dominated strategies. How about dynamic games with unawareness? Example: A kind of “Battle of the Sexes” I n t II II I B S B 3, 1 0, 0 S 0, 0 1, 3 M 0, 0 0, 0 II I B S B 3, 1 0, 0 S 0, 0 1, 3 I B S M B 3, 1 0, 0 0, 4 S 0, 0 1, 3 0, 4 M 0, 0 0, 0 2, 6 Example: A kind of “Battle of the Sexes” I T n t II II I B S B 3, 1 0, 0 S 0, 1 1, 0 M 4, 0 2, 3 II I T’ B S B 3, 1 0, 0 S 0, 1 1, 0 I B S M B 3, 1 0, 0 0, 4 S 0, 1 1, 0 0, 4 M 4, 0 2, 3 2, 6 I T n t II II I B S B 3, 1 0, 0 S 0, 1 1, 0 M 4, 0 2, 3 II I I B S M B 3, 1 0, 0 0, 4 S 0, 1 1, 0 0, 4 M 4, 0 2, 3 2, 6 What is the associated normal-form game? T’ B S B 3, 1 0, 0 S 0, 1 1, 0 II I T BB BS SB SS MB MS nBBB 3, 1 0, 0 3, 1 0, 0 3, 1 0, 0 nSBB 0, 1 1, 0 0, 1 1, 0 0, 1 1, 0 nMBB 4, 0 2, 3 4, 0 2, 3 4, 0 2, 3 nBSB 3, 1 0, 0 3, 1 0, 0 3, 1 0, 0 nSSB 0, 1 1, 0 0, 1 1, 0 0, 1 1, 0 nMSB 4, 0 2, 3 4, 0 2, 3 4, 0 2, 3 nBMB 3, 1 0, 0 3, 1 0, 0 3, 1 0, 0 nSMB 0, 1 1, 0 0, 1 1, 0 0, 1 1, 0 nMMB 4, 0 2, 3 4, 0 2, 3 4, 0 2, 3 nBBS 3, 1 0, 0 3, 1 0, 0 3, 1 0, 0 nSBS 0, 1 1, 0 0, 1 1, 0 0, 1 1, 0 nMBS 4, 0 2, 3 4, 0 2, 3 4, 0 2, 3 nBSS 3, 1 0, 0 3, 1 0, 0 3, 1 0, 0 nSSS 0, 1 1, 0 0, 1 1, 0 0, 1 1, 0 nMSS 4, 0 2, 3 4, 0 2, 3 4, 0 2, 3 nBMS 3, 1 0, 0 3, 1 0, 0 3, 1 0, 0 nSMS 0, 1 1, 0 0, 1 1, 0 0, 1 1, 0 nMMS 4, 0 2, 3 4, 0 2, 3 4, 0 2, 3 tBBB 3, 1 3, 1 0, 0 0, 0 0, 4 0, 4 tSBB 3, 1 3, 1 0, 0 0, 0 0, 4 0, 4 tMBB 3, 1 3, 1 0, 0 0, 0 0, 4 0, 4 tBSB 0, 1 0, 1 1, 0 1, 0 0, 4 0, 4 tSSB 0, 1 0, 1 1, 0 1, 0 0, 4 0, 4 tMSB 0, 1 0, 1 1, 0 1, 0 0, 4 0, 4 tBMB 4, 0 4, 0 2, 3 2, 3 2, 6 2, 6 tSMB 4, 0 4, 0 2, 3 2, 3 2, 6 2, 6 tMMB 4, 0 4, 0 2, 3 2, 3 2, 6 2, 6 tBBS 3, 1 3, 1 0, 0 0, 0 0, 4 0, 4 tSBS 3, 1 3, 1 0, 0 0, 0 0, 4 0, 4 tMBS 3, 1 3, 1 0, 0 0, 0 0, 4 0, 4 tBSS 0, 1 0, 1 1, 0 1, 0 0, 4 0, 4 tSSS 0, 1 0, 1 1, 0 1, 0 0, 4 0, 4 tMSS 0, 1 0, 1 1, 0 1, 0 0, 4 0, 4 tBMS 4, 0 4, 0 2, 3 2, 3 2, 6 2, 6 tSMS 4, 0 4, 0 2, 3 2, 3 2, 6 2, 6 tMMS 4, 0 4, 0 2, 3 2, 3 2, 6 2, 6 T’ I II B S B 3, 1 0, 0 S 0, 1 1, 0 T I II BB BS SB SS MB MS nB** 3, 1 0, 0 3, 1 0, 0 3, 1 0, 0 nS** 0, 1 1, 0 0, 1 1, 0 0, 1 1, 0 nM** 4, 0 2, 3 4, 0 2, 3 4, 0 2, 3 t*B* 3, 1 3, 1 0, 0 0, 0 0, 4 0, 4 t*S* 0, 1 0, 1 1, 0 1, 0 0, 4 0, 4 t*M* 4, 0 4, 0 2, 3 2, 3 2, 6 2, 6 1. 1. 2. 1. 1. II I T’ B S B 3, 1 0, 0 S 0, 1 1, 0 2. 1. Iterated conditional dominance coincides with extensive-form rationalizability. Iterated conditional dominance requires normal-form information sets and thus structure from the extensive-form. Can we dispense with any extensive-form structure entirely and obtain forward-induction outcomes in the associated normal-form game? => Iterated admissibility? Iterated admissibility: T I II BB BS SB SS MB MS nB** 3, 1 0, 0 3, 1 0, 0 3, 1 0, 0 nS** 0, 1 1, 0 0, 1 1, 0 0, 1 1, 0 nM** 4, 0 2, 3 4, 0 2, 3 4, 0 2, 3 t*B* 3, 1 3, 1 0, 0 0, 0 0, 4 0, 4 t*S* 0, 1 0, 1 1, 0 1, 0 0, 4 0, 4 t*M* 4, 0 4, 0 2, 3 2, 3 2, 6 2, 6 1. II I T’ B S B 3, 1 0, 0 S 0, 1 1, 0 1. 1. 1. A naïve approach would delete MB in the second step, which is the only extensive-form rationalizable strategy (i.e., the only strategy capturing forward induction)! How about iterated admissibility? T I II BB BS SB SS MB MS nB** 3, 1 0, 0 3, 1 0, 0 3, 1 0, 0 nS** 0, 1 1, 0 0, 1 1, 0 0, 1 1, 0 nM** 4, 0 2, 3 4, 0 2, 3 4, 0 2, 3 t*B* 3, 1 3, 1 0, 0 0, 0 0, 4 0, 4 t*S* 0, 1 0, 1 1, 0 1, 0 0, 4 0, 4 t*M* 4, 0 4, 0 2, 3 2, 3 2, 6 2, 6 1. II I T’ B S B 3, 1 0, 0 S 0, 1 1, 0 1. 1. A naïve approach would delete MB in the second step, which is the only extensive-form rationalizable strategy (i.e., the only strategy capturing forward induction)! 1. Iterated admissibility must rely on information sets (i.e., extensive-form structures). How about iterated admissibility? T I II BB BS SB SS MB MS nB** 3, 1 0, 0 3, 1 0, 0 3, 1 0, 0 nS** 0, 1 1, 0 0, 1 1, 0 0, 1 1, 0 nM** 4, 0 2, 3 4, 0 2, 3 4, 0 2, 3 t*B* 3, 1 3, 1 0, 0 0, 0 0, 4 0, 4 t*S* 0, 1 0, 1 1, 0 1, 0 0, 4 0, 4 t*M* 4, 0 4, 0 2, 3 2, 3 2, 6 2, 6 1. II I T’ B S B 3, 1 0, 0 S 0, 1 1, 0 1. 1. 2. A naïve1. approach would delete MB in the second step, which is the only extensive-form rationalizable strategy (i.e., the only strategy capturing forward induction)! 2. 1. Iterated admissibility must rely on information sets (i.e., extensive-form structures). We defined the normal form associated to dynamic games with unawareness. We characterize extensive-form rationalizability by iterative conditional strict dominance and prudent rationalizability by iterative conditional weak dominance. We show that iterative admissibility in the associated normal form must depend on information sets. We show that iterative conditional weak dominance coincides with iterated admissibility in dynamic games with unawareness. Other approaches to extensive-form games with unawareness An Example: Unforeseen Roadwork (Feinberg 2012) Alice (baker), Bob (coffee-shop owner), Carol (Alice’s worker) Alice has to deliver pastries to Bob on Monday or with penalties on Tuesdays or Wednesdays unless unforeseen contingencies occur Bob notices unforeseen roadwork on Monday morning that is likely to delay delivery; Bob thinks that Alice is unaware of roadwork Bob can decide to call Alice and renegotiate later delivery Carol notices upcoming roadwork on Sunday and emails Alice; Bob is unaware of Carol ¡; = ¡Road Work noticed by Carol, e-mail, Not Call = ¡Road Work Notice by Carol, e-mail, Call Alice =… Nature Feinberg (2012) Carol Bob Alice M T M W Bob Alice T W M T W Alice M T W Alice M T W Alice M T W Alice M Nature ¡ Road Work = ¡ Road Work noticed by Carol, No e-mail, = ¡ Road Work noticed by Carol, E-mail = ¡ Road Work, Call Alice = ¡ Road Work noticed by Carol, No e-mail, Call Alice =… Bob Alice M T W M Alice T W M T W Alice M T W ¡ No Road Work = ¡ Road Work, Not Call = ¡ Road Work noticed by Carol, No e-mail, Not Call =… T W Halpern and Rego (MSS 2014) ¡ Nature Carol Bob Alice M T W M Bob Alice T W M Nature T W Alice Alice M T W M T W Alice M T F ¡1 Bob Alice M T W M Alice T W M T W W Alice M T W ¡2 Alice M T W Grant and Quiggin (ET 2013) ¡ Nature Carol Bob Alice M T W M Bob Alice T W M Nature T W Alice Alice M T W M T W Alice M T e Z ¡1 Bob Alice M T W M Alice T W M T W W Alice M T W ¡2 Alice M T W Heifetz, Meier, Schipper (GEB 2013) ¡ Nature Carol Bob Alice M Bob Alice T W M T Alice W M Nature T W Bob M T W Alice Alice Alice M T W M T ¡1 Bob Alice Alice M T W M T W M T W Alice M T W ¡2 W Alice M T W In a Nutshell: Similarity: Every approach uses a forest of game trees. Main differences: How is dynamic awareness represented in the forest of game trees: • Feinberg: infinite sequences of views • Halpern-Rego: awareness correspondence • Grant-Quggin: perception correspondence • Heifetz, Meier, and Schipper: information sets Solution concepts: • Feinberg, Halpern-Rego, Grant-Quiggin: Sequential equilibrium • Heifetz, Meier, and Schipper: Extensive-form rationalizability Self-confirming games Self-confirming games Questions: • How do we arrive at our perceptions of strategic contexts? • How to model the process of discovering novel features of “repeated” strategic contexts? • Is there something like a “steady-state” of perceptions and if there is do they necessarily involve a common perception among players? • Is there a notion of equilibrium that makes sense in dynamic strategic interaction under unawareness? Equilibrium under unawareness? Problems: • Although mathematical definitions of standard equilibrium concepts can be extended to games with unawareness (Halpern and Rego, 2014, Rego and Halpern, 2012, Feinberg, 2012, Li 2008, Grant and Quiggin, 2013, Ozbay, 2007, Meier and Schipper, 2013), they cannot be interpreted as steadystates of behavior. • Players could not learn equilibrium through repeated play because they become aware of novel features. The perception of the game may “change” between “repetitions” and even along the supposed equilibrium path of a given game with unawareness. • How to reconcile equilibrium notions and non-equilibrium solutions (i.e., extensive-form rationalizability) in games with unawareness? Main ideas • Formal model of rationalizable discoveries in games with unawareness • Explain endogenously how players perceive strategic contexts. • Existence of equilibrium of perceptions and behavior: Show that for every game with unawareness there exists a discovered version that can be viewed as a steady-state of player’s perceptions and possess an equilibrium that can be interpreted as a steady-state of behavior. Examples 1 T l1 r1 2 l2 10,5 m2 0,10 1, 7 r2 5, 6 1 T l1 r1 2 l2 10,5 m2 0,10 T 1, 7 r2 5, 6 1 T l1 r1 2 l2 10,5 1, 7 r2 m2 0,10 5, 6 1 T l1 r1 2 l2 10,5 1, 7 r2 5, 6 1 T l1 r1 2 l2 10,5 1, 7 r2 m2 0,10 5, 6 1 T l1 r1 2 l2 10,5 1, 7 r2 5, 6 1 T l1 r1 2 l2 10,5 1, 7 r2 m2 0,10 5, 6 1 T l1 r1 2 l2 10,5 1, 7 r2 5, 6 1 T l1 r1 2 l2 10,5 1, 7 r2 m2 0,10 5, 6 1 T l1 r1 2 l2 10,5 1, 7 r2 5, 6 1 T l1 r1 2 l2 10,5 1, 7 r2 m2 0,10 5, 6 1 T l1 r1 2 l2 10,5 1, 7 r2 5, 6 1 T l1 r1 2 l2 10,5 1, 7 r2 m2 0,10 5, 6 1 T l1 r1 2 l2 10,5 1, 7 r2 5, 6 1 T l1 r1 2 l2 10,5 1, 7 r2 m2 0,10 5, 6 1 T l1 r1 2 l2 10,5 1, 7 r2 5, 6 1 T l1 ??? 2 l2 10,5 r1 1, 7 r2 m2 0,10 5, 6 1 T l1 r1 2 l2 10,5 1, 7 r2 5, 6 1 T l1 r1 2 l2 10,5 1, 7 r2 m2 0,10 5, 6 1 T l1 r1 2 l2 10,5 1, 7 r2 5, 6 • Does discovery always lead to common awareness? • Rationalizable discoveries versus nonrationalizable discoveries: Does rational play select among discoveries and thus representations of the strategic context? 1 l1 T * -1, 8 r1 2 l2 m2 10,5 1, 7 r2 0,10 5, 6 1 T 0 1 l1 T r1 00 2 l2 10, 5 m2 0,10 l1 * r1 -1,8 2 1, 7 r2 l2 5, 6 10,5 5, 6 1 T l1 r1 2 l2 10,5 1, 7 r2 5, 6 1, 7 r2 1 l1 T * -1, 8 r1 2 l2 m2 10,5 1, 7 r2 0,10 5, 6 1 T 0 1 l1 T r1 00 2 l2 10, 5 m2 0,10 l1 * r1 -1,8 2 1, 7 r2 l2 5, 6 10,5 5, 6 1 T l1 r1 2 l2 10,5 1, 7 r2 5, 6 1, 7 r2 1 l1 T * -1, 8 r1 2 l2 m2 10,5 1, 7 r2 0,10 5, 6 1 T 0 1 l1 T r1 00 2 l2 10, 5 m2 0,10 l1 * r1 -1,8 2 1, 7 r2 l2 5, 6 10,5 5, 6 1 T l1 r1 2 l2 10,5 1, 7 r2 5, 6 1, 7 r2 1 l1 T * -1,8 r1 2 l2 m2 10,5 1, 7 r2 0,10 5, 6 1 T 0 1 l1 T r1 00 2 l2 10, 5 m2 0,10 l1 * r1 -1,8 2 1, 7 r2 l2 5, 6 10,5 5, 6 1 T l1 r1 2 l2 10,5 1, 7 r2 5, 6 1, 7 r2 1 l1 T * -1,8 r1 2 l2 m2 10,5 1, 7 r2 0,10 5, 6 1 T 0 1 l1 T r1 00 2 l2 10, 5 m2 0,10 l1 * r1 -1,8 2 1, 7 r2 l2 5, 6 10,5 5, 6 1 T l1 r1 2 l2 10,5 1, 7 r2 5, 6 1, 7 r2 1 l1 T * -1, 8 r1 2 l2 m2 10,5 1, 7 r2 0,10 5, 6 1 T 0 1 l1 T r1 00 2 l2 10, 5 m2 0,10 l1 * r1 -1,8 2 1, 7 r2 l2 5, 6 10,5 5, 6 1 T l1 r1 2 l2 10,5 1, 7 r2 5, 6 1, 7 r2 1 l1 T * -1, 8 r1 2 l2 m2 10, 5 1, 7 r2 0,10 5, 6 1 T 0 1 l1 T r1 00 2 l2 10, 5 m2 0,10 l1 * r1 -1,8 2 1, 7 r2 l2 5, 6 10,5 5, 6 1 T l1 r1 2 l2 10,5 1, 7 r2 5, 6 1, 7 r2 1 l1 T * -1, 8 r1 2 l2 m2 10, 5 1, 7 r2 0,10 5, 6 1 T 0 1 l1 T r1 00 2 l2 10, 5 m2 0,10 l1 * r1 -1,8 2 1, 7 r2 l2 5, 6 10,5 5, 6 1 T l1 r1 2 l2 10,5 1, 7 r2 5, 6 1, 7 r2 1 l1 T * -1, 8 r1 2 l2 m2 10,5 1, 7 r2 0,10 5, 6 1 T 0 1 l1 T r1 00 2 l2 10,5 m2 0,10 l1 * r1 -1, 8 2 1, 7 r2 l2 5, 6 10,5 5, 6 1 T l1 r1 2 l2 10,5 1, 7 r2 5, 6 1, 7 r2 1 l1 T * -1, 8 r1 2 l2 m2 10,5 1, 7 r2 0,10 5, 6 1 T 0 1 l1 T r1 00 2 l2 10,5 m2 0,10 l1 * r1 -1, 8 2 1, 7 r2 l2 5, 6 10,5 5, 6 1 T l1 r1 2 l2 10,5 1, 7 r2 5, 6 1, 7 r2 • Consider extensive-form games with unawarenes a la Heifetz, Meier, Schipper (2013) with the stronger properties of unawareness. • Require additionally that the set of trees is a lattice. • Devise information sets also at terminal nodes. Self-confirming equilibrium Profile of behavioral strategies satisfying: For each player (0) awareness is self-confirming (i.e. constant) along the path(s) (i) is rational along the path(s) (ii) beliefs are self-confirming (constant and correct) along the path(s) Mutual knowledge of no changes of awareness? Lemma: No change of awareness for each player implies “mutual knowledge” of no change of awareness. Proof: Follows from complete lattice of trees and conditions on info. sets. Existence of self-confirming equilibrium • exists in standard games • often fails in games with unawareness (because of changes of awareness implied by rational play) A game is a self-confirming game if it possesses a selfconfirming equilibrium. Remark: Every game with common constant awareness is a self-confirming game. Converse is false. Discovered version Given an extensive-form game with unawareness and a strategy profile, the discovered version is defined by • the same set of players, same lattice of trees, the same player function, same payoffs • “updated” information sets: T5 : : T4 : : T3 : : T2 : T1 : T5 : : T4 : : T3 : : T2 : T1 : T5 : : T5 : : T4 : : T4 : : T3 : : T3 : : T2 : T2 : T2 : T1 : Discovered version Discovered versions are well-defined: Lemma: For any extensive-form game with unawareness and strategy profile, the discovered version is an extensive-form game with unawareness. Lemma: Given an extensive-form game with unawareness, any two strategy profiles that generate the same path have identical discovered versions. Discovery process Finite state machine: • Set of states: set of extensive-form games with unawareness (with identical upmost tree) • Initial state/game • Output function assigns strategy profile to each game • Transition function assigns the discovered version to each game and strategy profile • Final states/games (absorbing) Discovery process Proposition: For every discovery process, the final state exists and is unique. Remark: Final states may not have common constant awareness. Proposition: For every extensive-form game with unawareness, there exists a discovery process that leads to a self-confirming game. Remark: Typically extensive-form games with unawareness have several self-confirming versions. Extensive-form rationalizability Inductive definition Level 0 • All belief systems • Any strategy for which there exists a belief system such that the strategy is optimal at every non-terminal info. set. Level k • All belief systems concentrated on k-1 level rationalizable strategies of opponents if possible. • Any strategy for which there exists a level-k belief system such that the strategy is optimal at every non-terminal info. set. Extensive-form rationalizable strategies: intersection of every level-k rationalizable strategy sets. Rationalizable discoveries A discovery process is rationalizable if the output function assigns to each game an extensive-form rationalizable strategy. Proposition: For every extensive-form game with unawareness, there exists a rationalizable discovery process whose final state is a selfconfirming version. This refines the set of selfconfirming versions. Rationalizable self-confirming equilibrium A self-confirming equilibrium is rationalizable if non-rationalizable paths of play have zero probability. (???) Conjecture: For every extensive-form game with unawareness, there exists a rationalizable discovery process whose final state is a game with a rationalizable self-confirming equilibrium. Applications of unawareness • • • • • • • • • • Dynamic games: Halpern and Rego (MSS 2014), Rego and Halpern (IJGT 2012), Heifetz, Meier, and Schipper (GEB 2013), Feinberg (2004, 2005, 2012), Grant and Quiggin (ET 2013), Li (2006), Ozbay (2008), Nielsen and Sebald (2013) Bayesian games with unawareness: Meier and Schipper (ET 2014), Sadzik (2006) Value of information, value of awareness: Galanis (2013), Quiggin (2013) Disclosure of information: Heifetz, Meier, and Schipper (2012), Li, Peitz, and Zhao (MSS 2014), Schipper and Woo (2015) Contract theory: Auster (GEB 2013), Filiz-Ozbay (GEB 2012), Grant, Kline, and Quiggin (JEBO 2012), Lee (2008), Zhao and van Thadden (RES 2013) Decision theory: Karni and Viero (AER 2013), Schipper (IJGT 2013), Li (2006) Electoral Campaigning: Schipper and Woo (2015) General equilibrium: Exchange economies: Modica, Rustichini, and Thallon (ET 1998), Production economies: Kawamura (JET 2005) Finance: Siddiqi (2014) … (need more) I am looking forward to receiving your paper on unawareness.