Mathematical Structures for Computer Science Chapter 1.2 Copyright © 2006 W.H. Freeman & Co. MSCS Slides Formal Propositions or statements are sentences that are either true or false. In logic, propositions are represented by the letters A, B, C, … Propositions can be combined into more complicated expressions known as wellformed formulas, or wffs. ◦ The connectives: and (), or (), implies (), and negation () Wffs are represented by the letters P, Q, R, … Propositional Logic Section 1.2 1 o o A system for determining whether or not a particular logical argument is valid, using rules of inference (also known as propositional calculus.) Definition of Argument: o A sequence of statements in which the conjunction of the initial statements (called the premises, or hypotheses) is said to imply the final statement (called the conclusion). o Presented symbolically as (P1 Λ P2 Λ ... Λ Pn) Q where P1, P2, ..., Pn represent the hypotheses and Q represents the conclusion. Propositional Logic Section 1.2 2 What is a valid argument? When does Q logically follow from P1, P2, ..., Pn? Informal answer: When the truth of the hypotheses guarantees the truth of the conclusion. Note: We need to be sure the hypotheses are related to the conclusion; not just any knowledge we might have about the conclusion Q. Example: ◦ P1: Neil Armstrong was the first human to step on the moon. ◦ P2 : Mars is a red planet And the conclusion ◦ Q: No human has ever been to Mars. ◦ P1, P2 , and Q are all true, but Q isn’t a logical consequence Propositional Logic Section 1.2 3 Definition of valid argument: In a formal logical system an argument is valid if, whenever the hypotheses are all true, the conclusion must also be true. i.e. (P1 Λ P2 Λ ... Λ Pn) Q is a tautology. ◦ You must be able to logically deduce Q from the hypotheses How to arrive at a valid argument? ◦ Using a proof sequence Propositional Logic Section 1.2 4 Definition of Proof Sequence: A proof sequence is a sequence of wffs in which each wff is either a hypothesis or the result of applying one of the formal system’s derivation rules to earlier wffs in the sequence. Derivation rules allow you to rewrite a hypothesis in a more useful form, based on the equivalence relations from section one, or to derive new wffs from the old ones. Propositional Logic Section 1.2 5 Derivation rules for propositional logic Equivalence Rules Inference Rules Allows individual wffs to be rewritten Allows new wffs to be derived Truth preserving rules Work only in one direction Propositional Logic Section 1.2 6 Certain pairs of wffs are equivalent, hence one can be substituted for the other with no change to truth values. The set of equivalence rules are summarized here: Let R and S be statement variables Expression Equivalent to Abbreviation for rule PVQ PΛ Q QVP QΛP Commutative (comm) (P V Q) V R (P Λ Q) Λ R P V (Q V R) P Λ (Q Λ R) Associative (assoc) (P V Q) (P Λ Q) P Λ Q P V Q De Morgan’s Laws PQ P V Q Implication (imp) P (P) Double Negation (dn) PQ (P Q) Λ (Q P) Equivalence (equ) Propositional Logic Section 1.2 7 Inference rules allow us to add a new wffs to aproof sequence. If one or more wffs match an existing part of the proof sequence (this is the “from” part) you can deduce the second part and add to the proof. From Can Derive Abbreviation for rule R, R S S Modus Ponens- mp R S, S R Modus Tollens- mt R, S RΛS Conjunction-con RΛS R, S Simplification- sim R RVS Addition- add Note: Inference rules do not work in both directions, unlike equivalence rules. ◦ E.g., if you know R V S you can’t deduce R (or S). Propositional Logic Section 1.2 8 Example for using Equivalence rule in a proof sequence: ◦ Simplify (A V B) V C 1. (A V B) V C 2. (A Λ B) V C 3. (A Λ B) C 1, De Morgan 2, imp Example of using Inference Rule ◦ If it is bright and sunny today, then I will wear my sunglasses. Modus Ponens (given P, P S, conclude S) It is bright and sunny today. Therefore, I will wear my sunglasses. Modus Tollens (given P S, S, conclude P) I will not wear my sunglasses. Therefore, it is not bright and sunny today. Propositional Logic Section 1.2 9 Prove the argument A Λ (B C) Λ [(A Λ B) (D V C)] Λ B D First, write down all the hypotheses. 1. A 2. B C 3. (A Λ B) (D V C) 4. B Use the inference and equivalence rules to get at the conclusion D. 5. C 2,4, mp 6. A Λ B 1,4, con 7. D V C 3,6, mp 8. C V D 7, comm 9. C D 8, imp and finally 10. D 5,9 imp The idea is to keep focused on the result and sometimes it is very easy to go down a longer path than necessary. ◦ Propositional Logic Section 1.2 10 Used to prove an argument of the form P1 Λ P2 Λ ... Λ Pn R Q Deduction method allows for the use of R as an additional hypothesis and thus prove P1 Λ P2 Λ ... Λ Pn Λ R Q Suppose you want to prove [(A B) Λ (B C)] (A C) Propositional Logic Section 1.2 11 Prove [(A B) Λ (B C)] (A C) Using deduction method, prove (A B) Λ (B C) Λ A C 1. A B hyp 2. B C hyp 3. A hyp 4. B 1,3 mp 5. C 2,4 mp The above is called the rule of Hypothetical Syllogism or hs for short. Many such other rules can be derived from existing rules which thus provide easier and faster proofs. Propositional Logic Section 1.2 12 These rules can be derived using the previous rules. They provide a faster way of proving arguments. From Can Derive Name / Abbreviation P Q, Q R PR Hypothetical syllogismhs P V Q, P Q Disjunctive syllogismds PQ Q P Contraposition- cont Q P PQ Contraposition- cont Propositional Logic Section 1.2 13 Additional inference rules yield shorter proofs, but more rules to remember. From Can Derive Name / Abbreviation P PΛ P Self-reference – self PVP P Self-reference – self (P Λ Q) R P (Q R) Exportation – exp P, P Q Inconsistency – inc P Λ (Q V R) (P Λ Q) V (P Λ R) Distributive - dist P V (Q Λ R) (P V Q) Λ (P V R) Distributive - dist Propositional Logic Section 1.2 14 Prove that (P Q) (Q P) is a valid argument (called Contraposition – con). ◦ ◦ Hence prove, (P Q) Λ Q P (using deduction method). The above is true using the modus tollens inference rule. Prove P Λ P Q 1. 2. 3. 4. 5. 6. 7. 8. P P PVQ QVP (Q) V P Q P (Q) Q (called Inconsistency) hyp hyp 1, add 3, comm 4, dn 5, imp: (A V B) (A B) 2, 6, mt: from (P S, S ) get P 7, dn Propositional Logic Section 1.2 15 1. 2. 3. 4. 5. 6. 7. 8. 9. 10. 11. 12. 13. (A Λ B) Λ (C Λ A) Λ (C Λ B) A is an argument (A Λ B) (C Λ A) (C Λ B) A V B B V A B A (C) V A C A C V (B) (B) V C B C B A (B A) Λ (B A) hyp hyp hyp 1, De Morgan 4, comm 5, imp 2, De Morgan 7, imp 3, De Morgan 9, comm 10, imp 8, 11, hs 6, 12, con Propositional Logic Section 1.2 16 At this point, we have now to prove that (B A) Λ (B A) A 1. 2. 3. 4. 5. 6. Proof sequence B A B A A B A A A V A A hyp hyp 1, cont 3, 2, hs 4, imp 6, self Propositional Logic Section 1.2 17 To convert a verbal argument to a symbolic form so it can be tested for validity: “Symbolize” the argument using propositional wff’s Use the derivation rules for propositional logic to prove the argument is valid Example: “If interest rates drop, the housing market will improve. Either the federal discount rate will drop or the housing market will not improve. Interest rates will drop. Therefore the federal discount rate will drop.” Let I represent Interest rates drop H represent The housing market will improve F represent The federal discount rate will drop Then (I H) (F H) I F Propositional Logic Section 1.2 18 1. 2. 3. 4. 5. 6. 7. A proof sequence for (I H) (F H) I F IH hyp F H hyp I hyp H F 2, comm HF 4, imp IF 1, 5, hs F 5, 3, mp Propositional Logic Section 1.2 19 Russia was a superior power, and either France was not strong or Napoleon made an error. Napoleon did not make an error, but if the army did not fail, then France was strong. Hence the army failed and Russia was a superior power. Converting it to a propositional form using letters A, B, C and D Combining, the statements using logic Combining them, the propositional form is A: Russia was a superior power B: France was strong B: France was not strong C: Napoleon made an error C: Napoleon did not make an error D: The army failed D: The army did not fail (A Λ (B V C)) C (D B) (D Λ A) hypothesis hypothesis hypothesis conclusion (A Λ (B V C)) Λ C Λ (D B) (D Λ A) Propositional Logic Section 1.2 20 Prove (A Λ (B V C)) Λ C Λ (D B) (D Λ A) Proof sequence 1. A Λ (B V C) 2. C 3. D B 4. A 5. B V C 6. C V B 7. B 8. B (D) 9. (D) 10. D 11. D Λ A hyp hyp hyp 1, sim 1, sim 5, comm 2, 6, ds 3, cont 7, 8, mp 9, dn 4, 10 , con Propositional Logic Section 1.2 21 Prove the following arguments ◦ (A´ B´) Λ (A C) (B C) ◦ (Y Z´) Λ (X´ Y) Λ [Y (X W)] Λ (Y Z) (Y W) If the program is efficient, it executes quickly. Either the program is efficient, or it has a bug. However, the program does not execute quickly. Therefore it has a bug. (use letters E, Q, B) The crop is good, but there is not enough water. If there is a lot of rain or not a lot of sun, then there is enough water. Therefore the crop is good and there is a lot of sun. (use letters C, W, R, S) Propositional Logic Section 1.2 22 Write down the propositional form of the following argument: If my client is guilty, then the knife was in the drawer. Either the knife was not in the drawer or Jason Pritchard saw the knife. If the knife was not there on October 10, it follows that Jason Pritchard didn’t see the knife. Furthermore, if the knife was there on October 10, then the knife was in the drawer and also the hammer was in the barn. But we all know that the hammer was not in the barn. Therefore, ladies and gentlemen of the jury, my client is innocent. Propositional Logic Section 1.2 23