Chapter5 Lefebvre Draft, please do not quote or circulate Co41@sussex.ac.uk In this chapter I examine the role of fetishism in Henri Lefebvre’s theory of social domination. I argue that Lefebvre’s conception of fetishism as an alien, abstract and autonomous ‘concrete abstraction’ that inverts to dominate but not entirely determine society runs through his work where it serves as a basis for a series of attempts to conceive how domination is socially embodied. I demonstrate this in what I designate as three phases of Lefebvre’s work. I show that: phase one consists in Lefebvre’s classic Marxist humanist formulation of the critique of everyday life. In this phase Lefebvre conceives of social domination in analogy with the concrete abstraction of commodity fetishism as the objective and subjective alienation of the human essence of total man. In phase 2 Lefebvre’s reformulation of the critique of everyday life moves away from his classic Marxist humanist conception of social domination. Lefebvre enumerates a typology of objective terroristic forms of domination that are parallel to the concrete abstraction of commodity fetishism and replaces the standpoint of total man with a typology of social alienation (3) Lefebvre’s writings on cities and space mark a third phase in the evolution of this strand. These writings use Lefebvre’s conception of concrete abstraction to theorize how domination is socially embedded in the production of social spaces while jettisoning the theory of alienation for its lack of explanatory power. I close by criticizing the methodological and theoretical coherence of Lefebvre’s theory of fetishism and its role in his theories of social domination. I Literature Review. My argument in this chapter puts me at odds with the leading commentary on Lefebvre, which interprets his theory as paradigmatic of the theory of alienation. However, it does put me alongside several recent analyses of particular aspects of Lefebvre’s Marxism. 1.1 Fetishism as Alienation The majority of Anglophone commentary on Lefebvre defines his Marxism in the context of the debate between Althusserian and humanist interpretations of Marx.1 In these interpretations, Lefebvre is portrayed as a seminal Marxist humanist theorist of alienation.2 This characterization faithfully account for Lefebvre’s early writings and describes several of the characteristics of Lefebvre’s later theory of social domination. Yet this commentary is not concerned with a sustained 1 See (Jay 1986) (Elden 2004), (Merrifield 2006) and (Shields 1999) Martin Jay is the most notable example.2 For Jay the ‘key concept of alienation’ was ‘the centerpiece of his widely influential reading of Marx.’ (Jay 1986) 293. See also Merrifield’s statement that ‘in the Anglophone world…Lefebvre reigns as a prophet of alienation and Marxist humanism.’ (Merrifield 2006) XXXII Recent studies on Lefebvre by (Elden 2004) and (Shields 1999) mirror Jay and address Lefebvre’s Marxist theorization of domination as equivalent to his early theory of alienation. 2 1 examination of the content of Lefebvre’s Marxism, nor with analyzing how Lefebvre’s theory of alienation fits into his theory of the constitution of social domination. This commentary consequently neglects that (a) Lefebvre’s earlier writings conceive of alienation in relation to the concrete abstraction of commodity fetishism in order to construct a theory of how domination is socially embedded3 and (b) that Lefebvre’s later theoretical accounts move away from his classic Marxist humanist theory of alienation to utilize other means of conceptualizing domination in relation to Lefebvre’s theory of the concrete abstraction of commodity fetishism. 1.2 Abstraction and social domination Several recent works that examine particular theoretical aspects of Lefebvre’s Marxism provide a solid basis from which to differentiate Lefebvre’s Marxism from this standard humanist interpretation4. Greig Charnock’s Challenging New State Spatialities: The Open Marxism of Henri Lefebvre5, provides a discussion of the importance of dialectical critique, alienation and fetishism in Lefebvre’s Marxism.6 Lukas Stanek’s Henri Lefebvre on Space7, provides an excellent examination of how Lefebvre’s concept of abstract space draws on Lefebvre’s Hegelian Marxist idea of concrete abstraction. By doing so Stanek provides an analysis of Lefebvre’s theory of social domination that does not simply treat it in terms of alienation. Yet, Stanek does not to show how Lefebvre’s concept of abstract space relates to Lefebvre’s earlier theories of concrete abstraction. Consequently, there is still room for a work that adequately focuses on the role Lefebvre’s concept of concrete abstraction plays in his theories of social domination, which I provide in this chapter in my study of Lefebvre’s conception of fetishism and social domination. In order to do so I begin by discussing the context, non-dogmatic and nonsystematic nature of Lefebvre’s Hegelian-Marxism. I then turn to explicating the basis of Lefebvre’s Hegelian Marxism by outlining his interpretation of Marx’s critical dialectical method and his theory of alienation. I close this section by expositing how Lefebvre’s conception of fetishism as a concrete abstraction fuses these HegelianMarxian elements in a manner that Lefebvre distinguishes from Lukacs and critical theory. I then move to demonstrate how Lefebvre’s interpretation of the concrete abstraction of fetishism fits into his theory of social domination. In part three I 3 See for example Jay’s treatment of Lefebvre which: (1) relies entirely on his earlier works, such as Dialectical Materialism. (2) Refrains from discussing how Lefebvre conceives of the social constitution of alienation in his early work: “The general argument of Dialectical Matena/tsm, whIch has since become common coin among Marxist Humanists, does not bear repeating.” 4 In addition (Goonewardena et al. 2008) include a number of essays that focus on particular aspects of Lefebvre’s thought in conjunction with his interpretation of Marx. (Roberts 2006) also provides an excellent discussion of Lefebvre in the context of theories of everyday life, while (Osborne 2011) touches upon Lefebvre’s theory in the Politics Of time. 5 6 (Charnock 2010) This is done by comparing the similarities Lefebvre’s thought has with the stream of thinkers in the school of ‘Open Marxism.’ 7 (Stanek 2011) 2 discuss how Lefebvre uses fetishism in his classic Marxist humanist conception of the critique of everyday life. In part four I show how Lefebvre’s revises this theory in tandem with his reformulation of the critique of everyday life. In part five I show how Lefebvre’s writings on cities and space represent a further attempt to socially embed domination in parallel with the idea of concrete abstraction. I close by considering how these theories construe social domination and provide some criticisms of Lefebvre’s methodology and conception of social domination. 2 Lefebvre’s Marxism Two important aspects of Lefebvre’s Marxism are generally not accounted for in works that interpret his theory of social domination as symptomatic of his classic Marxist humanist conception of alienation: the contexts in which Lefebvre’s work appeared and his non-systematic, non-dogmatic and shifting interpretation of Marx.8 2.1 The Contexts of Lefebvre’s Marxist Theory As Stefan Kipfer has argued, Lefebvre’s politics shifted in response to his historical context.9 The same can be said of the development of Lefebvre’s HegelianMarxian theory of social domination. Lefebvre first came into contact with Marx and Hegel through the surrealists in the 1930’s. In this decade Lefebvre and Norbert Guterman also published the first French translation of Marx’s Economic and Philosophical Manuscripts and the first French work of Hegelian Marxism: le Conscience Mystifee, which fused Marx’s idea of mystification with Hegel’s unhappy consciousness. During this time Lefebvre also wrote the unpublished fragment: Notes on Everyday Life. Following a period when Lefebvre served as the leading intellectual and polemicist of the French communist party, Lefebvre’s ties to the party were severed. This freed Lefebvre to re-engage with his earlier Hegelian interpretation of Marx and led Lefebvre to stress a non-dogmatic and non-systematic Hegelian-Marxism that focused on areas of social life that were anathema to party doctrine. Lefebvre’s project of the critique of everyday life and his utilization of the theory of alienation are the prime example of Lefebvre’s writings during this period. Lefebvre’s reformulation of the critique of everyday life occurred in the context of his engagement with the Situationists and the New Left in the 1960s. Lefebvre’s writings in this context incorporated the theoretical and political concerns of the 1960s such as consumer societies, the bureaucratic state and the emergence of new social movements. This is reflected in his reformulation of social domination and the fragmentation and jettisoning of the explanatory power of the theory of alienation. These influences are also evident in Lefebvre’s writings on Cities and Space, which lead Lefebvre to once again reformulate his Hegelian-Marxism and his concurrent conception of domination. 8 Authors such as Elden use to describe Lefebvre’s revision of The Critique of Everyday Life and his writings on Cities and Space. This is in spite of what I will show is Lefebvre revision and jettisoning of alienation. 9 Kipfer characterizes these contexts as (1) the critique of Stalinism in France and Eastern Europe before and after his expulsion from the PCF [French Communist Party] at the end of the 1950s; (2) a critical engagement with Situationist avant-gardism in the 1950s and 1960s; (3) a brief flirtation with the alternative Communism of Yugoslavia and China; and (4) his contribution to New Left politics in France both before and after 1968. In (Marx 2004) 232 3 2.2 Lefebvre’s non-dogmatic Marxism and non-systematic Marxism The shifting nature of Lefebvre’s theory is also mirrored in what can be characterized as Lefebvre’s non-dogmatic and non-systematic interpretation of Marx. Marxism ‘is not a system or dogma’ for Lefebvre, but a reference’10 and a ‘starting point’ that is indispensable for understanding the present-day world. This means that Marx’s “basic concepts have to be elaborated, refined, and complemented by other concepts where necessary.”11 As I will show the manner in which these basic concepts are conceived and refined and complimented through Lefebvre’s conception of fetishism and its role in his theory of social domination. Nevertheless there is enough of a unity in how Lefebvre conceives of Marxism as a starting point to elaborate the main characteristics of what can be termed Lefebvre’s critical Hegelian-Marxism Lefebvre’s interpretation of the relationship between Hegel and Marx forms the basis of this critical Hegelian-Marxism. Lefebvre designates this relationship-- in which Marx ‘continues’ and ‘breaks’, ‘extends’ and ‘transforms’ the Hegelian12 method (logic and dialectics)’ and ‘certain concepts (totality, negativity, alienation)’13‘dialectical.’ For while Hegel’s method is idealist and mystifies reality, Marx’s dialectical materialist method uses the Hegelian categories of totality, negativity and alienation in his ‘radical critique’ of social praxis14 demonstrating “how dialectical reason arises precisely from…practical social activity, by man as he is in everyday life.” Critique is therefore centrally important to Lefebvre’s interpretation of Marx, In his view ‘the fundamentals’ of Marx’s ‘thought means that 'critique' must be taken in its widest sense.”15 Marx’s radical critique is thus defined by Lefebvre as a method “to get to know economic phenomena . . . to study their objective and substantial process, while at the same time destroying and denying this absolute substantiality by determining it as a manifestation of man’s practical activity, seen as a whole (praxis).”16 As a result Lefebvre’s interpretation of Marx’s modification of Hegel’s theory of alienation—which describes this objective and substantial process—is integral to critique. This is due to Lefebvre’s interpretation of Marx’s theory of alienation as constitutive of all heretofore historical forms of social constitution. According to Lefebvre, Marx’s modification of Hegel’s theory of alienation consists in a theory of alienation that “is no longer the absolute foundation of contradiction. On the contrary: alienation is defined as an aspect of contradiction and of becoming in man.”17 Accordingly, in contrast to Hegel, contradiction is “not in Marxist thought itself. It is an internal contradiction in history itself.” This contradiction is “defined philosophically as this single yet dual movement of objectification and externalization—of realization and derealisation”. For while objectification is necessary-- “he [man i.e. humanity] must 10 (Lefebvre 1988:77). (Osborne 2011) 19 12 Relationship a dialectical one: i.e. one full of conflict. 25 11 13 14 15 16 (Lefebvre 2009) 17 (Lefebvre 1969) 4 (Lefebvre 2009)19 (Lefebvre 2009) 19 17 (Lefebvre 2008a) 69 4 objectify himself’18-- in capitalism it takes on an alienated form in which “social objects become things, fetishes, which turn upon him.”19 As a consequence, Lefebvre’s interpretation of fetishism, as a concrete abstraction, fuses his interpretation of Marx’s theory of critique and his theory of alienation. 2.3 Lefebvre’s conception of fetishism Lefebvre conception of fetishism entails this fusion because: (a) “The economic theory of Fetishism takes up again, raises to a higher level and makes explicit the philosophical theory of alienation and the 'reification' of the individual.’20 (b) is conceived as a concrete abstraction that is constituted by social praxis. The notion of concrete abstraction stems from Lefebvre’s interpretation of Marx’s relationship to Hegel in which the “starting point for abstraction is not the mind but practically activity.” 21 Thus Social praxis, broadly construed, 22 constitutes economic forms such as commodity which is “an abstraction.” yet it is also concrete.”23 As a result concrete abstraction is a ‘practical power”24 which is “the very basis of the objectivity of the economic, historical and social process which has led up to modern capitalism” in which “man's activity, capital, thus appears as an objective, alien and autonomous condition'. For Lefebvre Fetishism is therefore interpreted as a socially constituted concrete abstraction that possesses what Lefebvre terms “real appearances” 25 and functions as an alienated, quantified, autonomous and inverted form: 18 (Lefebvre 2008a) 71 (Lefebvre 2008a) 71 20 (Lefebvre 2009) 84 19 (Lefebvre 2009) 77 praxis is first and foremost act, dialectical relation between man and nature, consciousness and thing (which can never be legitimately separated in the manner of philosophers who make them two distinct substances). (Lefebvre 1969) 45. 23 Once launched on its existence the Commodity involves and envelops the social relations between living men. It develops, however, with its own laws and imposes its own consequences, and then men can enter into relations with one another only by way of products, through commodities and the market, through the currency and money. Human relations seem to be nothing more than relations between things. But this is far from being the case, or rather it is only partly true. In actual fact the living relations between individuals in the different groups and between these groups themselves are made manifest by these relations between things: in money relations and the exchange of products. Conversely, these relations between things and abstract quantities are only the appearance and expression of human relations in a determinate mode of production, in which individuals (competitors) and groups (classes) are in conflict or contradiction. The direct and immediate relations of human individuals are enveloped and supplanted by mediate and abstract relations which mask them. The objectivity of the commodity, of the market and of money is both an appearance and a reality. It tends to function as an objectivity independent of men. (Lefebvre 2009) 76 21 22 24 (Lefebvre 2009) 125 The categories are abstract, inasmuch as they are elements obtained by the analysis of the actual given content, and inasmuch as they are simple general relations involved in the complex reality. But there can be no pure abstraction. The abstract is also concrete, and the concrete, from a certain point of view, is also abstract. All that exists for us is the concrete abstract. There are two ways in which the economic categories have a concrete, objective reality: historically (as moments of the social reality) and actually (as elements of the social objectivity). And it is with this double reality that the categories are linked together and return dialectically into the total movement of the world. (Lefebvre 2009) 76 25 5 Fetishism properly so called only appeared when abstractions escaped the control of the thought and will of man. Thus commercial value and money are only in themselves quantitative abstractions: abstract expressions of social, human relations; but these abstractions materialize, intervene as entities in social life and in history, and end by dominating instead of being dominated.26 The Social domination constituted by fetishism is instantiated in both sides of the class relation: Capitalists are deprived' of everything except money while the ‘non-capitalist experiences a more brutal form of privation.” This social situation is also indicative of the subjective aspect of alienation, human estrangement-- where ‘the essence of man has been handed over to thing, to money, to the fetish.’27—and is reflected in everyone being alienated from human community because they are compelled to act as atomized individuals and treat each other as means or instruments of self-perpetuation. However, Lefebvre also posits limits to the extent of domination through which he distinguishes himself from Lukacs. These limits are premised on his nonsystematic interpretation of Marx and his dualistic opposition between quantitative form and qualitative content in which quantified fetishistic abstractions cannot entirely grasp or determine their qualitative content. This can be seen on a theoretical level where Lefebvre argues that Lukacs’ formulation of reification systemizes what is only an aspect of Marx’s theory.28 In Lefebvre’s view, Lukacs’ systematic theory of reification while recognizing the autonomous and abstract aspects of fetishism treats them as determinate and neglects the social relationships that constitute it:29 The thesis of reification misinterprets the essential meaning of the socio-economic theory expounded in Capital. The fetishes that take on a life of their own, become autonomous, and impose their laws on interhuman relationships, can function only as abstract things by reducing humans beings to the status of abstract things, by relegating them to the world of forms, reducing them to these forms to their structures and functions. There is logic immanent in commodities qua forms, a logic which tends to constitute a world of its own, the world of commodities.30 However this process of inversion and determination has a limit: The logic of commodities, however, for all its encroachments upon praxis and its complex interactions with other forms of society and consciousness does not succeed in forming a permanent, closed system. With its complex determinations 26 27 (Lefebvre and ? 2003)71 (Lefebvre 2009) 45 the “very important observations by Marx are not to be systematized as a single theory of reification, which according to some constitutes the essence of Capital and of Marxism generally.” (Lefebvre 1969) 48 29 (Lefebvre 1969) 49 28 30 (Lefebvre 1969) 48 6 human labor is not entirely taken over by this form, does not become an inherent element of its content.31 Therefore, according to Lefebvre, ‘the abstract thing, the form (commodity, money, capital) cannot carry the process of reification ("thingification") to Its conclusion.”32 This is because “It cannot free itself from the human relationships it tends to delineate, to distort, to change into relations between things. It cannot fully exist qua thing.” As a result, this process “Doesn’t impose an entirely closed system. Human labor is not entirely taken over by form.”33 This means that individuals are not transformed into things but what Lefebvre’s terms ‘animated abstractions.’ These theoretical differences have repercussions for theories of social domination: “the school of Lukacs has overestimated the theory of reification to the point of making it the foundation of a philosophy and sociology (the two are regarded as identical in this systematization).” Lukacs’ social theory is thus “a purely speculative construction on the part of a philosopher unacquainted with the working class” so that “the proletariat’s class consciousness replaces classical philosophy.”34 On the other hand Lefebvre’s social theory conceives of an internal opposition between forms that cannot entirely determine content at the heart of his theory of social domination Lefebvre’s non-dogmatic non-systematic interpretation of Marx thus conceives of Marxism as a dialectical social critique. In this radical critique Marx utilizes the concept of fetishism to articulate the social constitution of the concrete abstractions of commodities, money and capital, which are characteristic of the autonomous, inverted alienated and alienating social domination of capitalism. At the same time this critique also posits that qualitative content resists being entirely determined by these forms serving as the grounds for becoming and emancipation. As I will now show this interpretation of Marx’s basic categories serves as the starting point that Lefebvre refines and compliments in his attempts to conceive of how domination is socially embedded and resisted in the socially complex categories of everyday life, urban forms and social spaces. 3 The Critique of Everyday Life The critique of everyday life is perhaps Lefebvre’s most widely known theoretical endeavour, consisting in several volumes published over the course of 50 years. Since these volumes do not encapsulate one sustained critique, but consist in 31 (Lefebvre 1969) 48 (Lefebvre 1969) 47 33 (Lefebvre 1969) 47 32 3434 These criticisms can also be seen in Lefebvre’s criticism of what he referred to as the “watered down Marxism of critical theory.” As part of the school of Lukacs it is likewise totalizing and sociologically deficient and rests on the ‘long-obsolescent notion of ideology.’ (Lefebvre 1992) 7 several phases, I separate them into the early classic Marxist humanist phase of the critique and his later attempt to revise the critique in the 1960s.35 3.1 Notes for a Critique of Everyday Life Two passages in Mystification: Notes For A Critique of Everyday Life show the way fetishism will be utilized as a basis to articulate alienation in the initial formulation of the category of everyday life. This can be seen in Lefebvre’s remark that “The theory of fetishism contained in Marx’s work explains how” the phenomena of alienation and mystification are possible”36due to the specific way that capitalist production creates the alienated abstract and autonomous fetishistic form of commodities. These forms alienate humanity while granting the world they collectively create an ‘alien power.’37 Consequently, “this insane, indissoluble will of the fetish by which we are compelled to live”38 is used by Lefebvre to provide the basis for what he envisions as a study of the ways in which mystification and alienation are instantiated in the everyday life of capitalist society. Lefebvre’s notion of mystification is termed mystified consciousness, which draws on Hegel’s notion of the unhappy consciousness.39 While alienation in everyday life focuses on the way that human social praxis constitutes an alienated, fetishistic form that inverts and dominates humanity.40 Yet, crucially for Lefebvre, mystification and alienation are not a closed or totalized but represent the possibility through which unalienated ‘total man’ can be achieved. 3.2 The Critique of Everyday Life These themes are drawn out in the first volume of The Critique of Everyday Life, Lefebvre’s first extended attempt to theorize how domination is embodied in the I refrain from focusing on Lefebvre’s return to the theme of everyday life in the 80s for two reasons: (1) Lefebvre devotes more time to the critique of everyday life in the 40s and 60 (2) because his reformulation of the critique of everyday life in the 1980s focuses on Lefebvre’s idea of rhythmanalysis rather than alienation, fetishism and social domination. 35 36 (Elden, Lebas, and Kofman 2006) 82 Capitalism is a system for producing merchandise. When it turns into merchandise the object becomes detached from itself, so to speak, It enters a system of relationships that are expressed through it, so that in the end it seems to be the subject of these relationships, their causal agent. Relationships between men are masked by relationships between objects, human social existence is realized only by the abstract existence of their products. Objects seem to take on a life of their own. The market dominates human beings; they become the plaything of anything with which they are unfamiliar, and which sweeps them along. The market is already a machine and an inexorable destiny. People are now alienated, divided from themselves. Divisions of labour, labour itself, individual roles and functions, the distribution of work, culture and traditions, all impose themselves as constraints. Each person experiences the collective achievements of society as the work of an alien power. (Elden, Lebas, and Kofman 2006) 82-83 37 38 39 (Elden, Lebas, and Kofman 2006) 83 (Elden, Lebas, and Kofman 2006) 85 40 “To talk about the mechanization of man, to say that machines have turned against him, has become a commonplace that only conceals the true situation. It is not only machines that have become detached from man. All the immense machinery of capitalism – ideas, values, institutions, culture—all this civilization has taken on a sort of independent existence that weighs on man and wrenches them apart from themselves; the very expression ‘man’ is drenched in mystification, because man still has no real existence. Alienation, that real abstraction, that false life that exists only through him and feeds on man- the ‘human’ that has lost its way on the road towards his realization—inevitably is dispersal, and a mutual exteriority of the elements of culture. But in this very exteriority, the elements have a unity in the movement of alienation.” (Elden, Lebas, and Kofman 2006) 75 8 lived social and cultural forms of capitalist society. Lefevbre conceives of everyday in conjunction with critical Marxist method, everyday life is thus defined as a ‘residual category’41 embedded and dialectically related to the ‘socio-economic formation.’42 Everyday life is thus conceived as “profoundly related to all activities, and encompasses them with all their differences and their conflicts; it is their meeting place, their bond, their common ground.”43 Accordingly, everyday life is where “the sum total of relations which make the human - and every human being - a whole takes its shape and its form. In it are expressed and fulfilled those relations which bring into play the totality of the real.”44 This is due to Lefebvre’s critical method of ‘Marxist social criticism’ which is the ‘only’ method capable of uncovering the genesis of representations and feelings’ because ‘it can trace the interactions of the social milieu and in this way understand our composite and heterogeneous consciousness of life.’45 Everyday life is also the point where Lefebvre’s dualistic opposition between quantity and quality resides. In his early work this dualistic opposition is conceived to occur between the alienating forms that seek to dominate everyday life, which are paired with the quantifying and abstract aspects of the commodity, and the qualitatively humane ways in which this unsuccessful attempt at total domination is resisted. As a consequence Lefebvre’s conception of social domination in Critique of Everyday Life is centred on the relationship between Lefebvre’s interpretation of fetishism and his classical Marxist humanist conception of alienation.46 At this point, Lefebvre defines alienation as consisting in the notion that: (a) capitalist social praxis produces alien and abstract forms that invert to dominate society and (b) this process of alienation is mirrored in other types of social alienation (c) that these forms alienation constitute human subjectivity and cumulatively estrange humanity from its essence as total man. Lefebvre conceives of the constitution of (a) in relation to fetishism, with fetishism also acting as one type of (b). These kinds of alienation are thus premised on Lefebvre’s understanding of the relationship between fetishism and alienation and its role in social constitution. In the case of the former fetishism is what links the young and old Marx:47 “The theory of 41 Everyday life, in a sense residual, defined by “what is left over” after all distinct, superior, specialized, structured activities have been singled out for analysis, must be defined as a totality. Considered in their specialization and their technicality, superior activities leave a “technical vacuum” between one and another which is filled by everyday life. Everyday life is profoundly related to all activities, and encompasses them with all their differences and their conflicts; it is their meeting place, their bond, their common ground. And it is in everyday life that the sum total of relations which make the human—and every human being—a whole takes its shape and its form. In it are expressed and fulfilled those relations which bring into play the totality of the real, albeit in a certain manner which is always partial and incomplete: friendship, comradeship, love, the need to communicate, play, etc. (Lefebvre 2008a) 97 Lefebvre’s critcal Marxism thus bypasses the schematism of the basesuperstructure 43 (Lefebvre 2008a) 57 42 44 (Lefebvre 2008a) 91-92 45 Lefebvre 2008a) 194 This classical humanist Marxist conception of alienation is encapusulated in Lefebvre’s statement that alienation is destined to ‘become the central notion’ of philosophy and literature. (Lefebvre 2008a) 168 47 “where economy and philosophy meet lies the theory of fetishism.” (Lefebvre 2008a) 17847 46 9 alienation becomes transformed into the theory of fetishism (fetishism of commodities, money, capital).”48 For the later Fetishism, according to Lefebvre, discloses how social relations create alienated fetish forms that invert to dominate both sides of the class relation: Money, currency, commodities, capital are nothing more than relations between human beings (between ‘individual,’ qualitative human tasks). And yet these relations take on the appearance and the form of things external to human beings. The appearance becomes reality; because men believe that these ‘fetishes’ exist outside of themselves they really do function like objective things. Human activities are swept along and torn from their own reality and consciousness, and become subservient to these things. Humanly speaking, someone who thinks only of getting rich is living his life subjected to a thing, namely, money. But more then this, the proletarian, whose life is used as a means for the accumulation of capital, is thrown to the mercy of an external power.” 49 As a result, fetishism is fundamental to the constitution of alienation in everyday life, accounting for the social process that establishes alienation. According to Lefebvre, the “the theory of fetishism” therefore “demonstrates the economic, everyday basis of the philosophical theories of mystification and alienation”50 where everybody “moves within fetishism as a mode of existence and of consciousness.” Lefebvre proposes to study this mode of existence by outlining several types of alienation. Fetishism is conceived as one of these types of alienation-- economic alienation—and is placed alongside other types of social alienation.51These types of alienation disclose that “alienation is constant and everyday’ and articulate the “way a dehumanized, brutally objective power holds sway over all social life; according to its differing aspects, we have named it: money, fragmented division of labour, market, capital, mystification and deprivation etc.”52 These forms of alienated objectivity are mirrored in the constitution of human subjectivity. This notion of subjectivity is grounded on the way alienated and fetishistic labour inverts to dominate and compel individualistic behaviour.53 It consists in the dialectical counterparts to the objective forms of alienation54, culminating in a proto-existential situation where ‘man is torn from his self, from his (Lefebvre 2008a) 180 (Lefebvre 2008a) 179 50 (Lefebvre 2008a) 179 51 These other types consist in: individuality and private consciousness, mystifications and mystified consciousness, money fetishism and economic alienation, the critique of needs and psychological and moral alienation and work and the alienation of the worker and man. 52 (Lefebvre 2008a) 166 48 49 53 “for every individual, worker or expert, the division of labour is imposed from without, like an objective process, with the result that each man’s activity is turned back against him as a hostile force which subjugates him instead of being subjugated by him.” (Lefebvre 2008a) 160 The types of alienated subjectivity include mystified consciousness, false needs, private consciousness and psychological and moral alienation 54 10 own nature, from his consciousness dragged down and dehumanized by his own social products”55 so that ‘alienation appears in day-to-day life, the life of the proletarian and even of the petty bourgeois and the capitalist (the difference being the capitalists collaborate with alienation’s dehumanizing power.’56 As a consequence, humanity as a whole is alienated from its essence as total man.57 Opposed to these forms of alienation is qualitative side of Lefebvre’s dualistic opposition between quantity and quality. Lefebvre identifies a myriad of qualitative moments that are present in capitalist society that resist determination.58 These oppositions are premised on the wide-ranging capacities of total man, leading Lefebvre to designate different phenomena such as political and social institutions, human needs and creativity as qualitative forms of opposition. As a whole, the social state of alienation is construed as part of the necessary process of historical ‘becoming’ in which the criticism59 of alienation will lead to its overcoming and the development of total man.60 In sum, Lefebvre’s first formulation of the critique of everyday life is centred on how capitalist social praxis constitutes alien and abstract fetishistic social forms that dominate sociality and alienate humanity from its own essence. At the same time these abstract forms are not entirely determinant and are opposed by qualitative contents of human society. This classic Marxist humanist formulation of the critique of everyday is modified in Lefebvre’s second formulation of the critique of everyday life. 4 The Critique of Everyday Life in the 1960s Lefebvre re-envisioned his project of the critique of everyday life 15 years after the first volume was published. Critique of Everyday Life Volume II and Everyday life in the Modern World are indicative of a contextual and theoretical shift in Lefebvre’s project. These volumes consequently reflect the development of French consumer society and Lefebvre’s dialog with the Situationists and other members of the French Avant Garde. Both of these contextual influences are captured in Lefebvre adopting (Lefebvre 2008a) 166 (Lefebvre 2008a) 167 57 In every attitude which tears every man away from what he is and what he can do— in art, in the moral sphere, in religion—criticism will reveal alienation. (Lefebvre 2008a) 167 55 56 58 Some of these are stated dualistic manner by Lefebvre “as an opposition and ‘contrast’ between a certain number of terms: everyday life and festival—mass moments and exceptional moments— triviality and splendour—seriousness and play, reality and dreams, Etc. (Lefebvre 2008a) 251 59 Genuine criticism will then reveal the human reality beneath this general unreality, the human ‘world’ which takes shape within us and around us; in what we see, what we do, in humble objects and (appearently) humble and profound feelings. A human world which has been torn away from us, dissociated and dispersed by alienation, but which still constitutes the irreducible core of appearances. (Lefebvre 2008a) 168 60 The drama of alienation is dialectical. Through the manifold forms of his labour, man has made himself real by realizing a human world. He is inseperable from this ‘other self’, his creation, his mirror, his statue—more; his body. The totality of object and human products taken together form an integral part of human reality. On this level, objects are not simply means or implements; by producing them, men are working to create the human. (Lefebvre 2008a) 169 11 Guy Debord’s term to describe everyday life as ‘literally colonized.’61 4.1 Critique of Everyday Life Volume II These volumes also theoretically revise the classic Marxist humanism of the first volume. Volume two outlines the ‘foundations for a sociology of everyday life.’ intended to join the ‘meta-philosophical’62 Hegelian-Marxian themes of Lefebvre’s project with social complexity. This leads Lefebvre to modify the classic Marxist humanism of Volume 1 by: (1) amending Hegelian-Marxist categories and integrating them with theories taken from contemporary theoretical developments such as linguistics and structuralism. (2) Jettisoning the category of total man as the basis of his conception of subjective domination.63 Lefebvre’s revision of alienation is indicative of these modifications. Lefebvre argues that Marx’s theory of alienation focused on one specific type of alienation— fetishism—to the detriment of other types.64 Lefebvre proposes to supplement this objective sense of alienation—as socially constituted alienated and inverted social domination--by moving to elaborate a typology. This typology Lefebvre proposes also addresses his criticism of Lukacs’ sociological deficit. In contrast to reification -which Lefebvre argues disguises the many forms alienation adopts”65—Lefebvre argues that alienation is ‘infinitely complex.” He proposes that other forms of alienation should be taken into account without subsuming them.66 This leads Lefebvre to prose a typology of alienation in which alienation in the everyday would form one type, reification another, political alienation another and new alienations yet others.67 61 (Lefebvre 2008b) 11 Lefebvre’s concept of meta-philosophy is also developed during this time. The terms designates that Lefebvre is using philosophical concepts to investigate social phenemona. 63 However, A summary of the complex foundations Lefebvre elaborates to critique this level are beyond the confines of this thesis. Furthermore many of them are not even taken up by Lefebvre in Everyday Life in the Modern World. For these reasons I focus on how Lefebvre amends his Hegelian-Marxism in his these volumes of the critique of everyday life.63 62 64 Marx tended to push the many forms of alienation to one side so as to give one specific defininition in terms of the extreme case he chose to study: the transformation of man’s activities and relations into things by the action of economic fetishes….reduced to economic alienation within and by capitalism, alienation would disappear completely and in one blow. (Lefebvre 2008b) 207 65 (Lefebvre 2008b) 208 This typology differs with objective sociol typology of alienation Lefebvre proposes in volume 1by including NSM such as feminism, consumer society etc: 66 In contrast alienation within and by the state (political alienation) must not be confuses with economic alienation (by money and commodities), although there are links between them. The alienation of the worker differs from the alienation of women and children. The ruling class…is alienated by artificial desires and phoney needs, whereas the prolietariat is alienated by privations and frustrations. The alienatin of social groups, which stops them from fully ‘appropriating’ the conditions in which they exist and keeps them below their possibilities differs from the alienation of the individual within the group or by the group…which derealizes the individual by subjecting him to external rules and norms. There is a technologica alienation…and an alienation as a result of a low level of technology. There is an alienation through escapism and different one through non-escapism. We also need to be aware of alienation in respect of society as a whole…and alienation in respect of oneself…and so alienation is infinitely complex. (Lefebvre 2008b) 209 67 Lefebvre also proposes defining these types in terms of the distinctions Marx makes between enfremdung, entaussarung, verdinlichung etc. 12 As part of this revision of alienation Lefebvre also builds on his conviction that alienation can never be total. He outlines a dialectic of alienation-disalienation-new alienation which he contends exemplifies everyday life in capitalist society. In this way alienation is never conceived as total and never determines or entirely captures human social activity. This revision of alienation is embodied in Lefebvre’s new conception of everyday life, which is defined as a ‘something’ that exists as a ‘level’ in capitalism.68 On this level Lefebvre’s dualistic opposition is no longer considered in terms of alienated and non-alienated essence. It is now construed in the opposition between the category of the everyday (which consists in abstract quantifying forms of domination) and everydayness (which entails qualitative needs, desires and possibility.) This opposition is extended to a number new everyday phenomena Lefebvre introduces, through which society mediates individuals seeking to enclose them in abstract everydayness. 69 Lefebvre characterizes these amendments to the critique of everyday life in a Hegelian-Marxist vein by designating everyday life as the content of this variety of abstract forms. This opposition between form and content is also representative of the dialectic of alienation-dis-alienation that is reflective of the dual opposition between everyday and everydayness in which fetishistic concrete abstractions cannot fully determine the content of social activity: In the everyday, alienations, fetishisms and reifications (deriving from money and commodities all have their various effects. At the same time, when (up to a certain point) everyday needs become desires, they come across goods and appropriate them. Therefore critical study of everyday life will reveal the following conflict: maximum alienation and relative disalienation….The theory of alienation and reification must take this dialectic into account if it is not to lapse into that speculative form of reification known as dogmatism. There is a ‘world’ of objects, but it is also a human world, and area of desires and goods, an area of possibilities, and not simply a ‘world’ of inert things.70 4.2 Everyday Life in the Modern World These Hegelian-Marxian elements of Lefebvre’s reformulation of the critique of Everyday Life are drawn out in Everyday Life in the Modern World. In this work Lefebvre outlines a study of contemporary capitalism. His definition of which- as ‘forced bureaucratic consumption-- reflects the concerns with consumer society and bureaucracy outlined in volume II. Lefebvre proposes to study capitalism by conceiving of the different social phenomena he sees as indicative of what he terms ‘terroristic forms of domination.’ These forms are indicative of ‘terrorist society’ and exemplify ‘forced bureaucratic consumption.’ As a whole terrorist society consists in: (a) social production that is oriented for the ends of one class, impoverishing the other class. (b) Widespread biological, physiological, natural educational and developmental repression (c) Lefebvre’s fragmented and revised typology of In this reinvisioning Critique of Everyday Life Volume II’s ‘guideline will be a critical study of what can and ought to change in human reality. By emphazing one part (one level) of reality, and above all by referring to critique of this level of reality. (Lefebvre 2008b) 97 68 69 70 These include time, exploitation and appropriation etc. (Lefebvre 2008b) 66-67 13 alienation71 (d) the reproduction of (a)(b) and (c) through ideology and compulsion in everyday life. These factors lead to the diffuse of nature ‘terrorist society’ in which ‘pressure is exerted from all sides on its members’ and ‘comes from everywhere and from every specific thing; the system’… ‘submit[ing] every member to the whole.’72 Lefebvre’s study of terroristic forms aims to understand ‘the conditions from which terrorism arises.’73 He proposes to conduct this study by transforming the residual category of everyday life into ‘space.’ For Lefebvre everyday life is now the space where these terrorist forms of capitalism are embedded in what he terms the ‘lived.’ These terroristic forms of domination are conceived as fetishistic concrete abstractions analogous to Marx’s theorization of the constitution and constituent of the fetishism of the commodity form.74These forms and the space they ‘infiltrate’ thus also constitute Lefebvre’s dualistic opposition between the everyday and everydayness, quantity and quality.75 Abstract, quantative ‘pure formal space’ defines the world of terror”[istic]76 forms. Yet these terrorist forms cannot reduce the 71 The theory of alienation is reputed to be out of date; indeed, certain forms of alienation may perhaps have vanished….New types of alienation have joined ranks with the old, enriching the typology of alienation; political, ideological, technological, bureaucratic, urban etc. We would suggest that alienation is spreading and becoming so powerful that it obliterates all trace or consciousness of alienation….what is new is that the theory of alienation….has become a social practice, a class strategy whereby philosophy and history are set aside so as to confuse the issue and successfully inhibit any consciousness of the actual state of total alienation.(Lefebvre 1984) 94 72 (Lefebvre 1984) 147 73 (Lefebvre 1984) 150 74 Our inquiry into the manner in which forms exist has led to an investigation of social reality. Ought we to reconsider and modify our concept of 'reality'? The existence and the effects of forms are unlike those of sensorial objects, technical objects, meta physical substances or 'pure' abstractions; though they are abstract they are none the less intellectual and social objects, they require sensorial, material and practical foundations but cannot be identified with such vehicles. Thus trade value requires an object (a product) and a comparison between objects in order to appear and express its content which is productive collective labour and a comparison between labours. However, object and content without form have neither a specifically intellectual nor a specifically social reality. To a certain extent form defines a thing's significance ; yet it possesses something both more and less, some thing different from what is signified; it constitutes an object's significance but also appropriates it, allows itself to be signified and absorbs the signifier…. They are real but not in the terms of other types of reality; they are projected on the screen of everyday life without which they would have nothing to explore, define and organize. (Lefebvre 1984) 186 One of example of this can be seen in the following: ‘A summary analysis suffices to show that there are two distinct types of leisure ‘structurally’ opposes: a) leisure integrated with everyday life (the perusual of daily papers, television etc.) and conducive to profound discontent …b) the prospect of departure, the demand for evasion, the will to escape through worldliness, holidays, lsd, debauchery of madness.’ (Lefebvre 1984) 85 75 76 in edl in relation to terrorism and edl lays out theory that ‘pure formal space defines the world of terror….terror defines a pure formal sp, its own, the sp of its power and its powers; time has been evicted from this unified sp; the writing that fixes it has eliminated speech and desire, and in this literal sp, isolated from action, presence and speech, so called human actions and objects are catalogued, classed and tied away, together with writings that are lined up on written matter. * *thus terror is not 14 ‘irreducible’ qualitative aspects of the lived.77 For while these forms aspire to a concrete existence they are ultimately reliant on human social actions they cannot entirely determine. Furthermore, the interrelation between these forms is not total.78 In sum, Lefebvre’s re-envisions the critique of everyday life in the 1960s by moving away from his classic Marxist humanism. The theory of alienation is fragmented on an objective level and supplanted on a subjective level by the jettisoning of total man. Yet at the same time there are continuities in Lefebvre’s attempt to conceive of (1) a complex socially embedded theory of domination in analogy with the properties of the concrete abstraction of commodity fetishism and (2) an internal opposition between form and content and quantity and quality in everyday life demonstrating that the concrete abstractions are not entirely determinate. As I will now show Lefebvre’s work on Cities and space represent Lefebvre’s attempt to transpose these elements to the categories of the urban form and abstract space. 4 Fetishism and Social Domination in Cities and Space. 4.1 The Urban Form Lefebvre’s writing on urbanization and cities were undertaken shortly after the publication of Critique of Everyday Life Volume II and Everyday Life in the Modern World. In these works Lefebvre examines the historic and social process of what Lefebvre refers to as the ‘urban revolution.’ Lefebvre employs many of the same themes he brought to the critique of everyday life to do so. In particular he conceptualizes this historical and social process by adapting his interpretation of Marx’s theory of fetishism as a socially constituted concrete abstraction constitutive of society to characterize the urbanization of cities and opposes it to a qualitative idea of urban dwelling. This can be seen in Lefebvre designation of what he terms the ‘urban form’ as a the space of fc but of true consciousness or of the conscience of reality, isolated from possibility, virtuality and shaping activity; terror is not simply pathological, it becomes normal (Lefebvre 1984) 177. 77 Everyday life is part of the content, but ambiguous; on the one hand it derives from the efficiency of forms, is their result or resultant. Product and residue, such is the definition of everyday life; forms simultaneously organize it and are projected upon it, but their concerted efforts cannot reduce it; residual and irreducible, it eludes all attempts at institutionalization, it evades the grip of forms. Everyday life is, furthermore, the time of desire; extinction and rebirth. Repressive and terrorist society cannot leave everyday life well alone but pursue it, fence it in, imprision it in its own territory. But they would have to suppress it to have done with it, and that is impossible because they need it. (Lefebvre 1984) 189 78 (Lefebvre 1984) 188 There is no single absolute chosen system but only sub-systems separated by cracks, gaps and lacunae; forms do not converge, they have no grip on the content and cannot reduce it permanently; the irreducible crops up after each reduction…only a relative, temporary reduction can be achieved….urban life is the setting for this. (Lefebvre 1984) 190 15 concrete abstraction.79 For Lefebvre the ‘urban form’ is the result of the urban revolution of social space that has occurred in the contemporary phase of capitalism. This process has modified the relationship between town and country as well as the structure of cities and remodelled all of them in the image of ‘industrial urbanization.’ This process of industrial urbanization consists in the form of urbanization the Keynesian state capitalist mode of production imposes upon urban spaces. Urbanization homogenizes urban regions rendering previously distinct and localized areas into one undifferentiated abstract mass space that swallows up and obliterates city neighbourhoods and the historical difference between the town and country.80 This process is implemented by what Lefebvre refers to as Urbanism which he defines as the form of organizational capital….in other words, a bureaucratic society of controlled consumption…[that] supplements “the logic of commodities” because it “controls consumption of space and habitat”81 The Urban form is therefore a concrete abstraction because it is constituted in tandem with the neo-capitalist state, mirroring its characteristics, and consisting in the place where production becomes socialized and where social relationships occur. 82 For Lefebvre the abstract urban form thus inhabits several levels of social space. The first level is the level of the concrete abstractions of exchange, networks and urban phenomena. This is the level shaped by the logic of these abstractions, which as abstract alien forms, invert to try to dominate urban life. This level is thus the level of the form of organized capital consisting in the “totalizing repressive space of the logic of commodities present in every object that is bought, sold and consumed,” as well as the logic of urbanism and of the state planned bureaucratic society of controlled consumption. The second level consists in the social terrain these abstractions inhabit. Like the category of everyday life, what Lefebvre terms the ‘urban fabric,’ can be said to consist in how these abstractions are embedded in the constitutive structure and 79 The urban is, therefore, pure form: a place of encounter, assembly, simultaneity. This form has no specific content but is a centre of attraction and life. It is an abstraction, but unlike a metaphysical entity, the urban is a concrete abstraction, associated with practice. Living creatures, the products of industry, techonology of wealth, works of culture, ways of living, situations, the modulations and ruptures of the everyday- the urban accumulates all content. (Lefebvre 2003) 119 80 Lefebvre periodizes this historical development as follows “First period. Industry and the process of industrialization assault and ravage pre-existing urban reality, destroying it through practice and ideology, to the point of extirpating it from reality and consciousness. Led by a class strategy, mdustrialization acts as a negative force over urban reality: the urban social is denied by the industrial economic. Second period (in part juxtaposed to the first). Urbanization spreads and urban society becomes general. Urban reality, in and by its own destruction makes itself acknowledged as sociaeconomic reality. One discovers that the whole society is liable to fall apart if it lacks the city and centrality: an essential means for the planned organization of production and consumption has disappeared.” (Lefebvre 2003) 81 81 (Lefebvre 2003) 164 Space is no longer only an indifferent medium, the sum of places where surplus value is created, realized, and distributed. It becomes the product of social labor, the very general object of production, and consequently of the formation of surplus value. This is how production becomes social within the very framework of neocapitalism (Lefebvre 2003)155 However, the urban is not indifferent to all differences, 82 precisely because it unites them. In this sense, the city constructs, identifies and delivers the essence of social relationships. (Lefebvre 2003) 118 16 terrain of the city. The urban fabric is thus where the logic of level one is socially embodied in the fragmented, homogenous, alienated and opaque industrial urban form of the city. But it is also where these ‘logics’ clash with resistant qualitative elements of the urban fabric such as grass roots collective self-management. In Writings on Cities Lefebvre further develops this notion of studying how social forms are embedded in urban environments. He outlines a number of forms that possess a ‘double existence as mental and social.’83 These forms would presumably be situated at the level of the urban fabric further locating metaphilosophical Hegelian Marxist notions of social domination in everyday life. These forms are coupled with oppositions in the urban environment that the urban form cannot determine-- such as the right to city-- that contest the abstract logic of commodities and bureaucratic controlled consumption. Level three is where this embodiment is resisted by qualitative human capacities that cannot be entirely determined. Lefebvre holds that there are elements in the urban fabric that cannot be reduced to quantified abstractions, which resist these abstractions. These elements of the ‘non-reducible’ tie in with the strand of Lefebvre’s thought that conceives of creativity and expression as qualitative oppositions to abstraction We can then see how Lefebvre’s writings on urban form and cities develop and concretize the themes of the critique of everyday life. Rather than a residual category Lefebvre embodies the lived experience of everyday life in the social space of the urban form. Like everyday life the urban form is defined as a historically specific multi-level phenomenon that is analogous and supplementary to Lefebvre’s interpretation of Marx’s theory of fetishism. As a consequence, urban space is theorized as a concrete abstraction that functions as an abstract alien form that attempts to dominate the social environment of those who construct it. This attempted dominance cannot achieve complete closure because of types of resistance and potential inherent within the urban city. The idea of urban space would be drawn on in The Production of Space. 4.2 SPACE For Lefebvre the “theory of social space encompasses on the one hand the critical analysis of urban reality and on the other that of everyday life.” Both “everyday life and the urban, indissolubly linked, at one and the same time products and production, occupy a social space.”84 Lefebvre’s analysis of space is therefore “concerned with the whole of practico-social activities, as they are entangled in a complex space, urban and everyday, ensuring up to a point the reproduction of relations of production (that is, social relations). The global synthesis is realized through this actual space, its critique and its knowledge.”85 Lefebvre’s theory of social space thus represents another attempt to conceive of the constitution of socially embedded domination by locating his earlier projects in the production of social space.86 These forms include logic, mathematics, contracts, practico-material objects which are socially embodied quantitative forms equivalent to exchange and the urban form. 83 84 85 (Lefebvre 1996) 185 (Lefebvre 1996) 185 86 As with is other theories Lefebvre views his theory of social space as complimentary to Marx’s critical method. This by seen in his statement that a 17 The Production of Space also marks the point where Lefebvre integrates Nietzsche into his Hegelian Marxian social theory. Lefebvre formally aligns Nietzsche with aspects of Lefebvre’s thought that oppose rational calculation and celebrate artistic activity, creativity and desire. As I have implied this strand of Lefebvre’s thought was originally aligned with his theory of total man and became more pronounced in Lefebvre’s writings in the 60’s.87 Lefebvre conceptually aligns this Nietzschean strand with his Hegelian-Marxism by using it to articulate another facet of his dualistic opposition between abstracte/concrete, quantity and quality. Lefebvre formally integrates Nietzchean into his critical methodology by formulating what he terms the ‘metaphilosophical’ ‘triadic dialectic.” As in his earlier work, the triadic dialectic reads the Hegelian conception of the concrete universal through Marx’s concept of ‘social practice.’ In The Production of Space this Hegelian-Marxism is transformed into a triad by adding Nietzsche’s conception of ‘art, poetry, and drama.’ This Nietzschean aspect of the triadic dialectic is also used by Lefebvre to incorporate the linguistic field and signs as aspects of social praxis that function in space.88 This leads Lefebvre to conceive of social space as the place where these three interrelated types of social activity emerge as representational, represented and abstract space. In what follows I focus on the later. Lefebvre’s concept of abstract space is premised on his Hegelian-Marxian theory of social constitution. What Lefebvre terms social space designates that space is socially constituted. This leads Lefebvre to conceive of social space as the location of social and cultural life where social labour and social contradictions ‘emerge’ and ‘regulate life’ This is reflected in Lefebvre’s two conceptions of how abstraction emerges in space: (1) the abstraction of humanity from nature (2) the social forms that social interaction with nature manifests itself in.89 The abstraction of humanity from nature is exemplary of the Nietzschean aspect of Lefebvre’s thought90 which views rationality as a pernicious type of abstraction that separates humanity from nature. Rationality is abstract, according to Lefebvre, because it functions ‘by virtue of the forced introduction of abstraction ‘comparable approach’ to ‘Marx’s fundamental critique of capitalism’ is ‘called for today, an approach which would analyse not things in space but space itself, with a view to uncovering the social relationships embedded in it.’ (Lefebvre 1996) 89 87 This can be seen in third level of non-reducibility of the abstract urban form and the hedonistic opposition to terrositic forms 88 The way that this is integrated, in Lefebvre’s notion of the linguistic field, lie outside of the concerns of this thesis. 89 As it did not denote a particular ‘product’—a thing or an object—but a cluster of relationships, this concept required that the notions of production and product, and their relationships, be enlarged….space can no longer be conceived of as passive or empty, nor as having, like ‘products’ no other meaning then that of being exchanged and disappearing. As a product, interactively or retroactively, space intervenes in production itself: organization of productive work, transport, flow of raw materials and energy, product distrobution networks. In its productive role, and as producer, space (well or badly organized) becomes part of the relations of production and the forces of production. Thus the concept cannot be isolated or remain static. It becomes dialectical: productproducer, underpinning economic and social relations. Does it not also play a part in reproduction, reproduction of the productive apparatus, of enlarged reproduction, or relations which it realizes in practice, ‘on the ground?” (Lefebvre 1992) 208 90 This aspect also has parallels with the Nietzschean narratives in The Dialectic of Enlightenment which deserve to be looked at in greater detail. 18 into nature’ resulting in a type violence that is inherent to rationality.9192 This process of abstraction thus seperates and fragments human interaction with nature and emerges in social space. Lefebvre’s other conception of abstraction concerns how this process of human interaction with nature is contained in social space. In capitalism this occurs in abstract space, which is the space where capitalist social forms emerge.93 Like his previous work, abstract space is conceived analogously with Lefebvre’s interpretation of the concrete abstraction of commodity fetishism. Lefebvre thus characterizes the commodity as a ‘concrete abstraction.’ Abstract ‘on account of its status as a thing, divorced, during its existence, from its materiality, from the use to which it is put, from productive activity, and from the need that it satisfies.”94 Concrete “just as certainly, by virtue of its practical power.” The “enigma” that results from this concrete abstraction is “entirely social.”95 From this it follows that since the concrete abstraction of the commodity is an object produced by social labour it must necessarily function in space.96 There is therefore “ a language and a world of the commodity. Hence also a logic and a strategy of the commodity.”97 In Lefebvre’s view ‘the genesis and development of this world, this discourse and this logic were portrayed by Marx.’98 Yet at the present moment capitalism has been globalized99 so that “The actualization of the worldwide dimension, as a concrete abstraction, is under way.. 'Everything' - the totality - is bought and sold.” As a consequence, ‘the commodity world brings in its wake certain attitudes towards space, certain actions upon space, even a certain concept of space,’100 that Lefebvre terms abstract space. Abstract space thus possesses the same characteristics as the commodity: it is a concrete abstraction that possesses quantative, homogenous and equivalent properties. As a result abstract space is conceived as the space where abstract forms emerge and try to regulate life in social space. This process takes place in what Lefebvre terms contradictory space. Contradictory space is reflective of the dualistic opposition of the commodity form,101 wherein abstract space is opposed by a qualitative and differentiated type of space that exists within and in opposition to abstract space which Lefebvre terms 91 The violence involved does not stem from some force intervening aside from rationality, outside or beyond it. Rather, it manifests itself from the moment any action introduces the rational into the real, from the outside, by means of tools which strike, slice and cut — and keep doing so until the purpose of their aggression is achieved (Lefebvre 1992)288 92 (Lefebvre 1992)288 93 (Lefebvre 1992) 100 94 (Lefebvre 1992) 340 95 Lefebvre 1992)340 96 ‘The commodity is a thing: it is in space, and occupies a location’ so that “social relations, which are concrete abstractions, have no real existence save in and through space. Their underpinning is spatial. (Lefebvre 1992) 340 97 (Lefebvre 1992) 341 98 (Lefebvre 1992) 350 99 ‘Chains of commodities (networks of exchange) are constituted and articulated on a world scale.’ (Lefebvre 1992) 343 100 (Lefebvre 1992) 342 the “paradigmatic (or 'significant') opposition between exchange and use, between global networks and the determinate locations of production and consumption, is transformed here into a dialectical contradiction, and in the process it becomes spatial.” (Lefebvre 1992) 101 19 concrete space.102 Social space is therefore contradictory and marked by a number of dualistic oppositions that play out in a number of areas in Lefebvre’s analysis.103These areas reside at a number of levels. Abstract space structures these levels in the forms of what Lefebvre refers to as the ‘great fetishes’ of neo-capitalism. Lefebvre utilizes the Trinity Formula as the analogical basis for his theory of how these great fetishes of abstract space, abstract labour, bureaucracy and the state are interrelated. 104 These abstract social entities combine as a whole to structure social life: 102 1. has a part to play among the forces of production, a role originally played by nature, which it has displaced and supplanted; 2. appears as a product of singular character, in that it is sometimes simply consumed (in such forms as travel, tourism, or leisure activities) as a vast commodity, and sometimes, in metropolitan areas, productively consumed (just as machines are, for example), as a productive apparatus of grand scale; 3. shows itself to be politically instrumental in that it facilitates the control of society, while at the same time being a means of production by virtue of the way it is developed (already towns and metropolitan areas are no longer just works and products but also means of production, supplying housing, maintaining the labour force, etc.); 4. underpins the reproduction of production relations and property relations (i.e. ownership of land, of space; hierarchical ordering of locations; organization of networks as a function of capitalism; class structures; practical requirements); 5. is equivalent, practically speaking, to a set of institutional and ideological superstructures that are not presented for what they are (and in this capacity social space comes complete with symbolisms and systems of meaning sometimes an overload of meaning); alternatively, it assumes an outward appearance of neutrality, of insignificance, of semiological destitution, and of emptiness (or absence); 6. contains potentialities — of works and of reappropriation -existing to begin with in the artistic sphere but responding above all to the demands of a body 'transported' outside itself in space, a body which by putting up resistance inaugurates the project of a different space (either the space of a counterculture, or a counter-space in the sense of an initially Utopian alternative to actually existing 'real' space). (Lefebvre 1992) 330 104 This analogical basis stems from Lefebvre’s interpretation of the trinity formula as a triadic theory of value ‘according to which there were three, not two, elements in the capitalist mode of production and in bourgeois society. These three aspects or 'factors' were the Earth (Madame la Terre), capital (Monsieur le Capital), and labour (the Workers). In other words: rent, profit, wages — three factors whose interrelationships still needed to be identified and clearly set forth.12 And three, I repeat, rather than two: the earlier binary opposition (wages versus capital, bourgeoisie versus working class), had been adandoned.’ (Lefebvre 1992) 325 This is replicated in Lefebvre’s theory of the relationship between capital, space and the state: ‘the capitalist 'trinity' is established in space - that trinity of land—capital-labour which cannot remain abstract and which is assembled only within an equally tri-faceted institutional space: a space that is first of all global, and maintained as such - the space of sovereignty, where constraints are implemented, and hence a fetishized space, reductive of differences; a space, secondly, that is fragmented, separating, disjunctive, a space that locates specificities, places or localities, both in order 20 neo-capitalist space is a space of quantification and growing homogeneity, a commodified space where all the elements are exchangeable and thus interchangeable; a police space in which the state tolerates no resistance and no obstacles. Economic space and political space thus converge toward the elimination of all differences.105 These elements of abstract space are managed and used as instruments of repressive rule by bureaucratic political power, which while not a ‘substance or pure form” does “make use of realities and forms” by creating and controlling space.106 The abstract forms of neo-capitalism are embedded in what Lefebvre terms spatial practice--a wide-ranging category that “subsumes the problems of the urban sphere (the city and its extensions”) and “everyday life” which are in “thrall to abstract space.” Spatial practice is thus where abstract space transforms107 ‘lived experience’ and ‘bodies’ into ‘lived’ abstractions.108 So that ‘under the conditions of to control them and in order to make them negotiable; and a space, finally, that is hierarchical, ranging from the lowliest places to the noblest, from the tabooed to the sovereign.’ (Lefebvre 1992) 283 1(Lefebvre 1992) 92 Political power and the political action of that power's administrative apparatus cannot be conceived of either as 'substances' or as 'pure forms'. This power and this action do make use of realities and forms, however. The illusory clarity of space is in the last a n a l y s i s the illusory clarity of a power that may be glimpsed in the reality that it governs, but which at the same time uses that reality as a veil. Such is the action of political power, which creates fragmentation and so controls it which creates it, indeed, in order to control it. But fragmented reality (dispersion, segregation, separation, localization) may on occasion overwhelm political power, which for its part depends for sustenance on continual reinforcement. This vicious circle accounts for the ever more severe character of political authority, wherever exercised, for it gives rise to the sequence forcerepression-oppression. This is the form under which state-political power becomes omnipresent: it is everywhere, but its presence varies in intensity; in some places it is diffuse, in others concentrated. In this respect it resembles divine power in religions and theologies. Space is what makes it possible for the economic to be integrated into the political. 'Focused' zones exert influences in all directions, and these influences may be 'cultural', ideological, or of some other kind. It is not political power per se that produces space; it does reproduce space, however, inasmuch as it is the locus and context of the reproduction of social relationships - relationships for which it is responsible. 105 106 (Lefebvre 1992) 320-21 107 So what escape can there be from a space thus shattered into images, into signs, into connectedyet-disconnected data directed at a 'subject' itscll doomed lo abstraction? For space offers itself like a mirror to the thinking 'subject', but, after the manner of Lewis Carroll, the 'subject' passes through the looking-glass and becomes a lived abstraction. (Lefebvre 1992) 313-314 108 The error - or illusion — generated here consists in the fact that, when social space is placed beyond our range of vision in this way, its practical character vanishes and it is transformed in philosophical fashion into a kind of absolute. In face of this fetishized abstraction, 'users' spontaneously turn themselves, their presence, their 'lived experience' and THEÄ° R bodies into abstractions too. Fetishized abstract space thus gives rise to two practical abstractions: 'users' who cannot recognize themselves within it, and a thought which cannot conceive of adopting a critical stance towards it (Lefebvre 1992) 93 21 modern industry and city life, abstraction holds sway over the relationship to the body.”109 These levels of domination are interrelated and condition each other.110 As a consequence, this multi-level theory of domination leads Lefebvre to jettison the theory of alienation for lacking explanatory power: At this level it becomes apparent just how necessary — and at the same time how inadequate — the theory of alienation is. The limitations of the concept of alienation lie in this: it is so true that it is completely uncontested. The state of affairs we have been describing and analyzing validates the theory of alienation to the full — but it also makes it seem utterly trivial. Considering the weight of the threat and the level of terror hanging over us, pillorying either alienation in general or particular varieties of alienation appears pointless in the extreme. The 'status' of the concept, or of liberal (humanist) ideology, is simply not the real issue.111 Lefebvre uses the theory of concrete space to outline a number of types of opposition to abstract space. These qualitative, localized, differentiated aspects of concrete space persist through out the areas and levels of social space. They are also reflective of the different theoretical elements in his triadic dialectic. Lefebvre’s notion of re-appropriating space and workplace democracy are aligned with the Marxian elements of his theory. His espousal of difference over homogeneity draws on the Nietzschean aspects of Lefebvre’s thought. Lastly, other types of opposition such as the qualitative space of leisure, the consumption of exchange value, and libidinal release promote a type of opposition to abstraction through a politicization of desire. Lefebvre’s theory of abstract space thus draws on his interpretation of fetishism as a concrete abstraction. This formulation of abstract space is utilized to show where the abstract, quantitative and homogenous ‘great fetish’ forms of domination emerge and how they attempt to regulate life in contradictory social space. At the same time abstract space is opposed by the qualitative contents of concrete space. Lefebvre’s theory of space thus represents an attempt to ground and concretize his persistent concerns of articulating how abstract social forms are socially embedded. Conclusion In this chapter I examined the role of fetishism in Henri Lefebvre’s theory of social domination. I argued that Lefebvre’s conception of fetishism as an alien, abstract and autonomous concrete abstraction that inverts to dominate but not entirely determine sociality runs through his work where it serves as a basis for his attempts to conceive how domination is socially embedded. I demonstrated this in three phases. My examination of Lefebvre’s classic Marxist humanist work showed (Lefebvre 1992) 204/5 “everything (the 'whole') weighs down on the lower or 'micro' level, on the local and the localizable - in short, on the sphere of everyday life. Everything (the 'whole') also depends on this level: exploitation and domination, protection and — inseparably — repression.” (Lefebvre 1992) 368 109 110 111 (Lefebvre 1992) 371 22 how Lefebvre conceived of his theory of objective and subjective alienation in tandem with his interpretation of fetishism and total man. I then moved to Lefebvre’s writing in the 60s, which used fetishism as a basis for Lefebvre’s supplementary theory of terrorist social forms that were embodied in a myriad of typologies of alienation no longer based on human essence. I finished by showing how Lefebvre transposed these theoretical interests in his writings on cities and space, which jettisoned the theory of alienation as an explanation of domination, but still used the theorization of fetishism as a concrete abstraction as the basis of his theory that construed how social constitution of domination was embedded in cities and space. This demonstrates that Lefebvre’s theory of social domination is more complex than a theory of alienation, with his theory of fetishism as a concrete abstraction holding a previously unrecognized important to his work. However, there are also some problems with this theory of fetishism and social domination. These criticisms may not be fair due to Lefebvre’s emphasis on nonsystematicity but they are valid. For it is one thing to be non-systematic in the sense of being opposed to the systematic function of a social system. It is another thing to be opposed to systematicity as such, since systematicity can provide you with an understanding of how the society you are seeking to criticize and understand functions. Unfortunately, Lefebvre’s theory is often non-systematic in the second sense. This can be seen in a number of places and ultimately undermines his various formulations of a theory that endeavors to supplement Marx by conceiving of how domination is socially embedded. This can first be seen in Lefebvre’s interpretation of Marx. Lefebvre’s interpretation is certainly admirable in stressing a non-dogmatic treatment of Marx. It also forthright about how the gaps in Marx’s theory make it necessary to supplement Marx with other theories or other theorists. However, the nonsystematic manner in which Marx is interpreted and supplemented is problematic. In the first case Lefebvre’s non-systematic interpretation prevents him from accounting for how certain categories fit into Marx’s attempt to systematically portray how capital functions at its ideal average. Providing such an account could have lent coherence to his social analysis. Instead, much like Lukacs and Adorno, this social analysis focuses on extrapolating from certain categories such as the commodity or the trinity formula. This means that Lefebvre’s accounts of the genesis of the forms that underlie his analysis relies on vague and unsubstantiated terminology such as praxis, social labour or socio-economic form which are treated as constitutive of theories of social constitution. This is likewise the case for the supplementary types of concrete abstraction Lefebvre proposes or develops which are accounted for by analogy or by positing that they are interrelated particular Marxian categories. In the second case this non-systematic leads Lefebvre to supplement Marx with an eclectic array of theories in his various attempts to conceive of how domination is socially embedded with some degree of social complexity. However, rather than capturing social complexity or domination, it is often the case that this combination of theorists clash with each other. This is noticeably the case in the construction of his triadic dialectic where little justification is given for how or why dialectic should or could be triadic. Nor are theoretical incongruities between Hegel, Marx and Nietzsche discussed. The same is the case for an eclectic array of theories Lefebvre draws from structuralism, Heidegger and others. This means that Lefebvre’s attempt to capture social complexity is often undermined by this process of theoretical supplementation. 23 At the same time it can also be said that the fundamental categories of Lefebvre’s social theory are too simplistic. On one hand these categories are nondeterministic and open enough to capture social complexity. But on the other hand they are too open to explain any degree of determinacy. This is the case for the categories Lefebvre constructs, such as everyday life, the urban form and space that are often too vague and residual to articulate how or where domination is socially embedded. This also the case for Lefebvre’s simplistic dualistic opposition that treats any form of quantification or abstraction as dominating or dehumanizing and any type of qualitative behavior as resistant and humane. Such an opposition leads to Lefebvre bundling together disparate phenomena due to his reductive assessment of their essence. As a result rationality and types of homogeneity are treated as equivalent to abstractions that compel human behavior while phenomena as disparate as consumption, festivals, artistic creativity, grass roots democracy and urban living are characterized as qualitative and are thus seen as equivalent and inherently oppositional to social domination. As a result, despite some potentially interesting innovations that could potentially articulate how a theory of domination is socially embedded, Lefebvre’s theory of fetishism and social domination is problematic. In the first place his interpretation of fetishism is under theorized. In the second place this under theorized interpretation is used as the basis for a series of theories that are ultimately unable to provide an account of how the constitution of domination is socially embedded, and at points even failing to offer a plausible account of domination. 24 25