Ch2

advertisement

Chapter 2: Logic & Incidence Geometry

Back To the Very Basic Fundamentals

1

Copyright, 1996 © Dale Carnegie & Associates, Inc.

Theorems and Proofs

A mathematical theorem is a conditional statement of the form:

If H , then C . (In symbols: H

C)

A mathematical proof is a list o statements, along with a justification for each statement, ending with the conclusion expected.

2

Logic Rules (1)

Rule 1:The following are the six types of justifications allowed for statements in proofs:

1. By hypothesis. . .

2. By axiom . . .

3. By theorem . . .

4. By definition . . .

5. By (previous) step . . .

6. By rule . . . of logic

3

Logic Rules (2)

Rule 2: Indirect Proof [redutio ad absurdum (RAA)] :

To prove a statement H

C, assume the negation of statement C (RAA hypothesis and deduce an absurd statemtent, using H if needed.

To prove: H

C

1. Assume H

~C (Symbol for negation of C: ~C)

2. Use this idea to arrive at a contradiction to H or some other known theorem, definition or axiom. ( Symbol for contradiction:



)

4

Logic Rules

(Some of DeMorgan’s Laws)

(3)

Rule 3: The statement ~(~S) means S.

Rule 4: The statement ~[H

C] is the same statement as H & ~C. (& and

 mean “and”)

(Alternate symbols: H

~C)

Rule 5: The statement ~ [S same thing as [~ S

1

~S

2

1

S

2

] means the

]. (

 means “or”)

A contradiction (absurd statement) is a statement of the form S

~S. (



)

5

Logic Rules: Quantifiers (1) (4)

Quantifiers are of two types:

– Universal: For all x …, For any x …, For every x…, If x is any… (Symbol:  x)

(Note: For allx does NOT imply the existence of anything!)

– Existential: There exists an x…, For some x…, There are x…, There is an x… (Symbol:  x)

Statements involving quantifiers: If S is a statement that says something about x, written S(x), and it is quantified, we write for example:

 x S(x) or

 x S(x).

6

Logic Rules: Quantifiers (2) (5)

Rule 6: The statement ~[

 x S(x) ] means the same as

 x ~S(x).

Rule 7: The statement ~[

 x S(x)] means the same as

 x ~S(x).

7

Logic Rules: Implication (6)

Rule 8: If P

Q and P are several steps in a proof, the Q is a justifiable step.

Conditional Statement: P

Q (If P, then Q.)

– Its converse: Q

P

– Its inverse: P

~Q (negation)

– Its contrapositive : ~Q

~P

Logically equivalent: P

Q. “P if and only if Q”

P is logically equivalent to Q. (P and Q are the same thing!)

8

Logic Rules: Tautologies (6)

Rule 9: Statements that are true strictly because of their form and not what individual parts might “say”.

A) [ [P

Q ]

[Q

R] ]

[P

R]

(Transitive)

B) [P

Q]

P, or, [P

Q]

Q (Inclusive)

C) [~Q

~P]

[P

Q] (Contrapositive)

9

Logic Rules (7)

Rule 10: (The Excluded Middle) For every statement P, P

~P is a valid step in a proof.

Rule 11: (Proof by cases) Suppose the disjunction of statements S

1

S

2

 … 

S n already a valid step in a proof. Suppose that is the proofs of C are carried out from each of the case assumptions S

1

, S

2

… S n

. Then C can be concluded as a valid step in the proof.

1

0

Incidence Geometry (1)

Incidence Axioms

I-1: For every point P and for every point Q not equal to P there exists a unique line l incident with P and Q.

I-2: For every line l there exist at least two distinct points that are incident with l .

I-3: There exist three distince points with the property that no line is incident with all three of them.

1

1

Incidence Geometry (2)

Incidence Propositions

P-2.1: If l and m are distinct lines that are not parallel, then l and m have a unique point in common.

P-2.2: There exist three distinct lines that are not concurrent.

P-2.3: For every line there is at least one point not lying on it.

P-2.4: For every point there is at least one line not passing through it.

P-2.5

: For every point P there exist at least two lines through P.

1

2

Example 5: Isomorphism -- 1) one and only one element goes to each member of the other set. 2) All elements in the range are used up.

System 1: 3 points in the "universe" A, B, C

U = { A, B, C}

Points

A

Lines a = {A,C}

B

C b = {A,B} c = {B,C}

System 2: 3 lines in the "universe" a,b,c

U = {a,b,c}

Lines Points

a A = {a,b}

b

c

B = {b,c}

C = {a,c}

1

3

Projective and Affine Planes

A projective plane is a model of the incidence axioms having the elliptical property (any two lines meet) and such that every line has a t least three distinct points lying on it.

An affine plane is a model of incidence geometry having the Euclidean parallel property

1

4

Equivalence Relations

• An equivalence relationship ”~” between two objects “a and b” is a relationship with these three properties:

1. a ~ a, i.e. a is equivalent to itself. (reflexive)

2. a ~ b

 b ~ a. (symmetric)

3. [a ~ b

 b ~ c]

[a ~ c]. (transitive).

Examples of equivalence relations: a = b (equality) x

 y (similar) l || m (parallel) p

 q (perpendicular)

• Example of relations not equivalence classes.

G < H (less than) C

D (proper subset)

1

5

Equivalence Classes

• An equivalence class C is the set of all objects y equivalent to some object x.

C ={ y : y~x}

Example: Given the affine plane A and a line l in A

(l

A ) the set of all lines m parallel to l would be an equivalence class and represented by [ l ] = {x : x || l, l

A } m

[ l

] (m is one of the x’s. We write m ~ l and also [m] ~ [ l ].

1

6

Points at Infinity

Points at infinity, by definition, are these equivalence classes defined in the above example.

The line at infinity l

 is the set of all the points at infinity!

l

= {[t] : [t] ~ [ l ], l any line in A }, i.e. l

= {[ l ], [k],[r] . . . where l, k, r

A but none are parallel to each other}.

1

7

Download