BIOLAW I. theories: bioethics and biolaw II. problems: beginning and of life issues III. case analysis bioethics Van Rensselaer Potter, Bioethics: bridge to the future, 1970 - the fact that the rapid advances in science had proceeded without due attention being paid to values - field of medicine, biology, environmental issues bioethics, as a ‘bridge’ between ‘facts’ and ‘values’. Potter said that he coined the word bioethics using two Greek words, bíos, life, representing the facts of life and life sciences, and éthos, morals, referring to values and duties bioethics • not all that is technically possible is morally right, • some control of our intervention in nature and the environment, on animals and on human beings, is needed • the future of life and of humankind is at stake BIOETHICS • scientific and technological advance in the biomedical field opens new possibilities of intervention on life (human and nonhuman) and raises new moral questions • anything that can be done, must be done anyway? are there limits/which? ethics ethical pluralism: which ethics for bioethics? • libertarian theory • utilitarian theory • personalism • concept of person liberal-libertarian theory • non-existence and the impossibility to know a common objective truth (non cognitivism) • ‘strong’ pluralism of values: no unification of the plurality of values is possible and desirable 1. principle of autonomy: self-determination 2. principle of tolerance: every subjective ethical view must be accepted, passively tolerated and indifferently legitimated in an equivalent way to any other utilitarianism • an empirical/consequentialist moral theory • priority to the sensation: ability to feel pleasure and pain, the ability to prefer pleasure to pain 1. principle of utility: welfare (or happiness) = the best optimal balance of benefits over costs, of satisfactions over frustrations, of preferences/interests (in terms of pleasure/joy) over damage (pain/suffering) 2. principle of the maximisation of the interests of all the individuals involved considered as a whole personalism • possibility to know the common/objective truth: recognition of the intrinsic dignity of the person in every human being, irrespective of the phase of physical-psychic development, the condition of existence (health or illness) or of the properties that they possess or the abilities that they are able to show • principle of physical integrity, therapeutic principle, liberty/responsability, justice/solidarity the concept of person • most frequently used philosophical concept • evocative nature of the word “person” = a subject worthy of some respect and protection philosophical ambiguities • what is a person? (conceptual definition) • who is a person? (factual identification) • how should we treat a person? (definition of rules of conduct) pluralism (different answers to the questions) two trends: • “personism”: separation of the concept of person from the human being (not all human beings are persons/some nonhuman beings may be considered persons) • “personalism”: an intrinsic identity between person and human being “personism” (separation person/humans) - the human being is not a person from the moment of fertilization, but “becomes” a person at some subsequent moment - the person may end “before” the natural biological death of the human being boundaries of personal status: 1. personhood = relationship person begins with the implantation of the embryo in the uterus person dies when the human being is no more capable of relationship objection: relationship does not constitute “being” in ontological terms, but it “presupposes” his/her existence boundaries of personal status: 2. personhood = individuality person begins at the 14th day of conception (end of totipotentiality: possibility of twinning) objections: recent studies support the hypothesis that twinning is not a separation (one individual becomes two individuals) but a “duplication” (one individual gives birth to another individual) boundaries of personal status: 3. personhood = sensibility (perception of pleasure and pain) person begins with the formation of the central nervous system/with the capacity of maximizing pleasure (human beings and animals) person ends in condition of maximization of pain objection: experience of pleasure or pain is structurally subjective, cannot be quantified or calculated boundaries of personal status 4. personhood = rationality (possibility to exercise rationality) person begins with the formation of the cerebral cortex (parallelism between “brain death” and “brain life”; emergentism) objection: no mirror-correspondence between life and death (death is the negation of life)/ emergentism does not explain how conscience “emerges” from matter boundaries of personal status: 5. personhood = rationality (actual exercise), selfconsciousness, selfdetermination person begins with the capability of understanding, reasoning evaluating (human beings and robots) person ends with the incapability of understanding, reasoning and evaluating objection: the performance of a function is inseparable from the ontological subject who is the condition of its existence consequences: the ambiguous use of the concept of person in bioethics opens the way to new forms of discriminations in terms of the degree of physical, psychological and social development of the human being/existential conditions the concept of person does it make sense any longer to use the concept of person in bioethics and biolaw? - the recognition of the dignity and rights of the human being may, in principle, rule out the discussion of the concept of person (human rights) - the notion of person was actually devised in western philosophy for the precise purpose of characterizing the human being person = human being the identification of the human being as a person specifies the characteristics and the constituent property of the human being (explaining the basis of the person’s values and rights) personalism justification of the identity between human being and person the definition of person was originally devised to characterize the real human being definition, originally formulated by Boethius “rationalis naturae individua substantia” personalism • substance = distinct subject who exists in himeself/herself, not inherent to anything else, or who belongs only to himeself/herself the functions which the human being exercises do not exist in themselves, but exist only as functions and activities “of” a substantial human individual, who is their singular and permanent reference-point (real ontological condition) personalism • rational nature: “nature” means what the person “is” by virtue of birth “rational” does not merely indicate intelligence and rationality but it indicates reason and thought, word, language, communication, freedom and intention ontological personalism the human being “is” a person by virtue of his/her rational nature the human being doesn’t “become” a person by virtue of the effective exercise of certain functions (such as relationship, sensibility and rationality) the functions are “of” a person (in that they inhere to his/her substantial nature), they are not “the” person ontological personalism the presence of a substantial principle makes it possible to recognize the actual status of the person in the human being even in conditions of “potentiality” or “privation” the zygote, the embryo, and the fetus (and also the newly born or the minor) are “already” persons the moribund, the handicapped, people in comas, are “still” persons ontological personalism • the ontological concept of person could relate to the doctrine of human rights, which is universally agreed and recognized • recognition of our duty to respect all human beings and the fundamental rights to life and integrity of every human being at every stage of physical, psychological and social development • human being must always be recognized as an end, and never just a means BIOLAW “biolaw”: the search for rules to discipline human behaviour at a social level, in the context of progress in scientific knowledge and technological applications in biology and medicine biothics/biolaw bioethics and biolaw do not overlap • bioethics: good/bad; duty (non binding) • biolaw: rules of behaviour in a binding way (also foreseeing administrative or penal sanctions for unlawful behaviour) so as to guarantee social life biolaw • on the one hand, we perceive a urgent need for biojuridical rules that make social life possible and resolve disagreements (which appear to be more and more difficult to resolve because of ethical pluralism); • on the other hand a juridical answer, or systematic reflection, is delayed at a legislative, doctrinal and jurisprudential level biolaw • reasons for the delay in biolaw: - the asynchrony between the rapidity and dynamism of the biomedical technical-scientific progress and the slowness of the law (in the political debate, the production of laws, the jurisprudential interpretation, the elaboration of doctrines) the risk of obsolescence (biolaw tends to arrive too late when the problem is no longer felt, substantially transformed or perceived differently), the risk of hurried interventionism (with problems giving rise to particular social alarm) biolaw - the interdisciplinary structure of bioethics requires the continuous updating of the operators and the opportunity for debate with the experts of different disciplines, with heterogeneous languages and methodologies - the need of juridical categories to define and classify phenomena that depart from the usual context of analysis - prudence (or precaution) of the legislator, in the fear that certain techno-scientific intervention on life may cause unforeseeable and irreversible effects models of biolaw biojuridical pluralism - model of abstension - model of intervention procedural, ‘soft’ substantive, ‘hard’ abstension the libertarian model, in the name of the affirmation of individual freedom, considers the absence of law/regulation preferable in bioethics intervention of law, perceived as an instrument of oppression a “space free from law/regulation”, supposing that all that is neither prescribed nor forbidden by laws is/may be considered allowed . abstension movement of thought known as “Hil”, or “highly inappropriate legislation”, which considers that legislation in bioethics, in whatever way it may be formulated, can only be ‘highly inadequate a preference for regulations of deontological codes, codes of professional practice codes of conduct, or the opinions of ethical committees, as indirect and flexible rules and regulations, self-control of a community or the self-discipline of single researchers intervention ‘soft’ • intervention of the law in bioethics with the function of guaranteeing freedom, understood as individual self-determination • biolaw should protect the external and formal conditions allowing freedom to be concretely manifested and should abolish the impediments, ensuring the means for the translation of intention into behaviour • biolaw should strengthen subjective freedom, broadening it with the multiplication of the possibilities of choice (technologically possible) intervention ‘soft’ • biolaw recognises ethical pluralism, seeking to elaborate “neutral” rules, without taking sides in favour or against any moral perspective, so that each single person is free to express his/her individual option, with the only limit to avoid damages to others (free individuals) • “minimal legislation”, procedural rules to negotiate controversies or flexible intervention of jurisprudence • only if there is a justified fear of possible severe and irreversible risks of society, temporary rules, to deal with social emergencies, which may be reviewed and eliminated if not necessary intervention ‘hard’ • detailed, specific legislation, with specific moral contents • substantive intervention: specific moral prespective • deduction of law from morals • limits of jurisprudence, protection of certainty biolaw • the law can find ethics in it, inside it: it is not a question of making a choice between the ethics in the context of the plurality characterising the present debate (such a choice would inevitably determine the privilege of one set of ethics and the delegitimisation of another) • the law is called upon to account for the internal meaning of the law itself, as an instrument for the defence of human coexistence and the dignity of each human being, as a presupposition and condition of structural possibility of the existence and human coexistence biolaw • fragmentation: phenomenon of “bioethical tourism”, the displacement of individuals claiming rights being prohibited in their country to go to the country that allows the implementation of those rights • search for harmonization International committees Unesco: - International Committee for Bioethics - Intergovernmental Committee fro Bioethics World Commission on the Ethics of Scientific Knowledge and Technology (Comest) WHO, Department of ethics and health WHO, Global Summit EU, International dialogue on bioethics European committees - European Group of Ethics in Science in New Technologies EGE (European Commission) - Bioethics Committee (Council of Europe) DH-BIO European Commission, Nec Forum National organism Italian Committee for Bioethics http://www.governo.it/BIOETICA/ born in 1990 35 members: interdisciplinar ans pluralistic structure advice to Parliament and Government; information to society opinions, motions bioethics and culture bioethical issues are strictly connected to cultural belonging - diverse level of development of scientific knowledge and technological applications in biomedicine - different theoretical and practical contexts bio-ethno-ethics • the coexistence of different ethnic groups in the same territory • solutions to bioethical problems within a culture often have implications outside • health cooperation between advanced countries and developing countries to ensure equity in health ethno-centric bioethics • one’s own culture is superior to all others in a hierarchical view (imposition of one culture over other cultures, considered inferior) • bioethical colonialism/imperialism/paternalism ethno-centric bioethics • “model of assimilation”: those belonging to other cultures adapt and adjust to the bioethics of the “mainstream” culture • “model of subordination”: possible exploitation objection • an arbitrary imposition of one culture as superior (it is neither the bioethical place of origin nor possession of advanced technology that confers superior ranking to bioethics) • an attitude of unjustified intolerant “arrogance” multicultural bioethics • relativist prospective: bioethics of each culture is and must be placed on the same level with regard to the bioethics of any culture, all cultures being equivalent • tolerance: passive and indulgent acceptance of every culture/bioethics, without making any ethical judgement multicultural bioethics • juxtaposition of multiple and diverse bioethics: the search for common values is futile and undesirable, considering plurality better than unity as an expression of richness and originality multicultural bioethics • “model of separation”: each culture is a “closed” world (which internally affirms its own values and preserves its own traditions) and externally tolerates any other bioethical culture objections • the principle of equivalence as neutral and uncritical acceptance of every culture is unable to avoid cultural conflict among cultures which are opposing and incompatible (allowing the stronger culture to prevail over the weaker one) • equivalence can lead to self-closure of each culture in itself, resulting in incommunicability intercultural bioethics • against hierarchy among cultures and against equivalence • all bioethics in every culture is judgeable: it is a duty to express judgement on the bioethics of different cultures: not a judgement of superiority or inferiority, but a judgement of truth in reference to human dignity, considered as the minimum common value intercultural bioethics • equality must ensure that all men, regardless of cultural belonging, have the possibility of knowing each other as human beings (before realisation of their belonging to a specific cultural group) • affirming equality means assuming the differences: equality is the precondition for “recognition” of the “differences” as significant interaction between human beings bioethics • the role of bioethics is not to impose a vision as superior (negating and annulling the others) nor is it to legitimise every request from each cultural group (uncritically), thereby creating a series of ‘separate islands’ that risk conflict • the structural reference to human rights acquires priority in ethnoethics: human rights are the “units of meaning” bioethics: communication • negative paths: - egalitarianisation (assimilation: all men of diverse cultures should conform to the dominant culture) - differentiation (separation: the individuals of different ethnic groups should be guaranteed by the broadest possible conservation of what makes them different) bioethics: communication • intercultural bioethics - critical search for continuous mediation and integration of human rights and the specific needs of diverse cultures - affirming the relational logic of diversity in equality documents • Convention for the Protection of Human Rights and Biomedicine of the Council of Europe (1997) • Charter of Fundamental Rights of the European Union (Nice, 2000) • Universal Declaration on Bioethics and Human Rights by Unesco (2005) problems 1. 2. 3. 4. 5. 6. 7. 8. 9. reproductive technologies genetic tests cloning ascertainment of death organ transplants therapeutic obstinacy euthanasia living will, advance care directives allocation of health care resources reproductive technologies • the increase in new technological possibilities with regard to reproduction and the rise of sterility and/or infertility of the individual and the couple (despite the persistence of the desire to have a child that is biologically one’s own), • constitute the facts behind the emergence over the last few decades of an increasingly pressing social demand for access to medically assisted procreation reproductive technologies • is the desire to have a child with the use of technologies always and anyhow licit? • what must the limits to the request for access be? • does the desire to have a child represent the claiming of a “right”? • do “reproduction rights” exist, choosing not only if and when, but also how to reproduce oneself? reproductive technologies • assisted/artifical insemination/fertilization: intracorporeal insemination (in vivo) = taking of the male gamete, its treatment and insertion into the woman’s body extracorporeal insemination (in vitro) = taking both gametes, treating them, fertilising them, transferring the embryo into the woman’s body • homologous/heterologous • surrogate motherhood (ectogenesis; hibridation) ethical issue: sexuality/generation • the question of the separation between sexuality and generation, mediated by the technical intervention of the doctor - libertarians and utilitarians consider the access to reproduction technologies legitimate, even if they require an invasive and substitutive intervention by the doctor with respect to the unifying act of the couple, appealing to procreative freedom and the satisfaction of a widespread social desire (individual and collective) sexuality/generation - the personalist standpoint considers that the excessive technicalisation and medicalisation increasingly tends to reduce procreation to being an impersonal artificial procedure: the depersonalisation, the impoverishment of the personal significance of the generation sexuality/generation with intracorporeal artificial insemination: the technical intervention is a concomitant cause, insofar as it accompanies the semen into the uterus; the doctor intervenes in an auxiliary way with respect to natural conception, limiting his action to facilitating the meeting of the gametes, overcoming the obstacle impeding natural conception, which anyway takes place inside the woman’s body sexuality/generation with extracorporeal artificial insemination, greater manipulation is involved: the doctor’s intervention substitutes the sexual act: in this case it is not a facilitation but a substitution conscientious objection given the possible ethical reserves towards artificial extracorporeal insemination, biolaw should, when legislating over such practices, foresee the possibility for conscientious objection by medical staff biolaw should offer the doctor and medical staff the possibility not to take part in the use of certain techniques when they go against their ethical conscience main problems for biolaw - status of the embryo: manipulation (overproduction, crioconservation, reduction, selection) - value of the family libertarian theory • procreative freedom: positive reproductive rights no personal status of the embryo family: product of society, or decision of the individuals (relativistic conception) libertarian theory - lecit to access even in condition of fertility - lecit the manipulation of embryos: priority of the desires of individuals over the value of the embryos - lecit homologous/heterologous fertilization (anonymity of the donors) - lecit: acces of single, homosexuals, postmortem, personalist perspective • procreative responsability: personal status of the embryo value of the (natural) family personalist perspective - lecit to access only in condition of infertility - illecit the manipulation of embryos: priority of the dignity of the embryos over the desires of adults (limitation of the number of production, no reduction, no selection) - lecit homologous; problems of heterologous fertilization - illecit: acces of single, homosexuals, postmortem, personalist perspective problems of heterologous fertilization: - the right of the embryo to know his/her origin - asymmetry of the couple (possibile refusal of fatherhood) Summary • • • • Historical background Motives/aims of the Convention Leading principles Possible restrictions of the rights accorded by the Convention • Violations of the Convention • Further developments • Questions and discussion Historical background Council of Europe • Council of Europe established in 1949 during the Cold War • Its main aim: to defend western values against Soviet Union • 1989 : fall of the Berlin Wall • New central and eastern European states join the Council of Europe • Second breath for the Council: bioethics The Convention for Biomedicine • Prepared between 1991 and 1996 by the Comité Directeur de Bioéthique (CDBI) • Adopted by the Committee of Ministers of the CoE on 19 November 1996 • Opened for signature in Oviedo, Spain on 4 April 1997 • It entered into force on 1 December 1999, after the fifth ratification (Spain) Italy and the Convention • Italy signed the Convention already in 1997 • On 28 March 2001 the Act N° 145 ratifying the Convention was approved by the Italian Parliament with a majority of 386 votes for, 3 against and 13 abstentions although the Parliament was already dissolved because of the forthcoming elections • However, the deposit of the instrument of Ratifications • 28 (of 47) member states have ratified the Convention • Mostly central/ eastern European countries • No ratification by Belgium, France, Germany, Netherlands, UK…. Motives/aims of the Convention • a need to make a greater effort to harmonise existing standards (EM, §4). To prevent so called ‘bioethics’ paradises • The Convention as a whole will provide a common framework for the protection of human rights and human dignity. Member states may provide a higher level of protection (article 27 Convention) Motives/aims of the Convention • Parties to this Convention shall see to it that the fundamental questions raised by the developments of biology and medicine are the subject of appropriate public discussion in the light, in particular, of relevant medical, social, economic, ethical and legal implications, and that their possible application is made the subject of appropriate consultation (article 28 Convention) Leading principle A A. The protection of the human being and of everyone • CONVENTION FOR THE PROTECTION OF HUMAN RIGHTS AND DIGNITY OF THE HUMAN BEING WITH REGARD TO THE APPLICATION OF BIOLOGY AND MEDICINE • Parties to this Convention shall protect the dignity and identity of all human beings and guarantee everyone, without discrimination, respect for their integrity and other rights and Human Being and Everyone • The Convention does not define the term ‘everyone’ nor (‘human being’. In the absence of a unanimous agreement on the definition of these terms among member States of the Council of Europe, it was decided to allow domestic law to define them for the purposes of the application of the present Convention (EM § 18) Protection of prenatal life • Article 18 – Research on embryos in vitro 1 Where the law allows research on embryos in vitro, it shall ensure adequate protection of the embryo. 2 The creation of human embryos for research purposes is prohibited. Leading principle B B. The protection of the human dignity and the identity of the human being Parties to this Convention shall protect the dignity and identity of all human beings (article 1) Leading principle B The protection of human dignity is further elaborated by the following articles: • The interests and welfare of the human being shall prevail over the sole interest of society or science (article 2) • The use of techniques of medically assisted procreation shall not be allowed for the purpose of choosing a future child's sex, except where serious hereditary sexrelated disease is to be avoided (article 14) Leading principle B • The creation of human embryos for research purposes is prohibited (article 18.2) • The human body and its parts shall not, as such, give rise to financial gain (article 21) Leading principle B • The protection of the identity of the human being is of importance in light of the growing possibilities to intervene in the human genome. An intervention seeking to modify the human genome may only be undertaken for preventive, diagnostic or therapeutic purposes and only if its aim is not to introduce any modification in the genome of any descendants (article 13) Leading principle C C. The protection of the integrity of everyone ‘Parties to this Convention shall (...) guarantee everyone, without discrimination, respect for their integrity (...) with regard to the application of biology and medicine’ (article 1) Leading principle C The protection of the integrity is further elaborated in article 5: ‘An intervention in the health field may only be carried out after the person concerned has given free and informed consent to it. This person shall beforehand be given appropriate information as to the purpose and nature of the intervention as well as on its consequences and risks. The person concerned may freely withdraw Leading principle C ‘The term "intervention" must be understood here in a broad sense; it covers all medical acts, in particular interventions performed for the purpose of preventive care, diagnosis, treatment or rehabilitation or in a research context’ (EM §29) Article 16 (medical research), 19 (removal of organs for transplantation) and 22 (use of human material) repeat the requirement of consent for these particular interventions Leading principle C • Article 9 deals with the so called positive and negative Advance declarations of will: ‘The previously expressed wishes relating to a medical intervention by a patient who is not, at the time of the intervention, in a state to express his or her wishes shall be taken into account’. Leading principle D D. Protection of other rights and fundamental freedoms Parties to this Convention (...) shall guarantee everyone, without discrimination, respect for their integrity and other rights and fundamental freedoms with regard to the application of biology and medicine (article 1) Leading principle D The Convention explicitly refers to some of these rights and fundamental freedoms: - Article 10 – Private life and right to information 1 Everyone has the right to respect for private life in relation to information about his or her health. 2 Everyone is entitled to know any information collected about his or her health. However, the wishes of individuals not to be so informed shall be observed. Leading principle D • Article 11 – Non-discrimination Any form of discrimination against a person on grounds of his or her genetic heritage is prohibited. • Article 24 – damage Compensation for undue The person who has suffered undue damage resulting from an intervention is entitled to fair compensation according to the conditions and procedures prescribed by law. Leading principle D • ‘The term "Human Rights" refers to the principles laid down in the Convention for the Protection of Human Rights and Fundamental Freedoms of 4 November 1950, which guarantee protection of such rights. The two Conventions share not only the same underlying approach but also many ethical principles and legal concepts. Indeed, this Convention elaborates some of the principles enshrined in the European Convention for the Protection of Human Rights. The concept of the human being has been used because of its general character. The concept of human dignity, which is also highlighted, constitutes the essential value to be upheld. It is at the basis of most of the values emphasised in the Convention’. • The close link with the ‘mother Convention’ is also of imprtance with regard of the enforcement of the Biomedicine Convention Leading principle E • The protection of incompetent persons The Convention contains 3 articles that protect incompetent persons subjected to a medical intervention : articles 6, 17 and 20 Leading principle E • Article 6 – Protection of persons not able to consent 1 Subject to Articles 17 and 20 below, an intervention may only be carried out on a person who does not have the capacity to consent, for his or her direct benefit. 2 Where, according to law, a minor does not have the capacity to consent to an intervention, the intervention may only be carried out with the authorisation of his or her representative or an authority or a person or body provided for by law. The opinion of the minor shall be taken into consideration as an increasingly determining factor in proportion to his or her age and degree of maturity. Leading principle E • Article 6 – Protection of persons not able to consent 3 Where, according to law, an adult does not have the capacity to consent to an intervention because of a mental disability, a disease or for similar reasons, the intervention may only be carried out with the authorisation of his or her representative or an authority or a person or body provided for by law. The individual concerned shall as far as possible take part in the authorisation procedure. 4 The representative, the authority, the person or the body mentioned in paragraphs 2 and 3 above shall be given, under the same conditions, the information referred to in Article 5. 5 The authorisation referred to in paragraphs 2 and 3 above may be withdrawn at any time in the best interests of the person concerned. Leading principle E • Article 17 – Protection of persons not able to consent to research 1 Research on a person without the capacity to consent as stipulated in Article 5 may be undertaken only if all the following conditions are met: i to iv, are fulfilled; the conditions laid down in Article 16, sub-paragraphs i ii the results of the research have the potential to produce real and direct benefit to his or her health; iii research of comparable effectiveness cannot be carried out on individuals capable of giving consent; iv the necessary authorisation provided for under Article 6 has been given specifically and in writing; and v the person concerned does not object. Leading principle E • Article 20 – Protection of persons not able to consent to organ removal 1 No organ or tissue removal may be carried out on a person who does not have the capacity to consent under Article 5. Leading principle F • Article 3 – Equitable access to health care ‘Parties, taking into account health needs and available resources, shall take appropriate measures with a view to providing, within their jurisdiction, equitable access to health care of appropriate quality’. ‘The purpose of this provision is not to create an individual right on which each person may rely in legal proceedings against the State, but rather to prompt the latter to adopt the requisite Leading principle G • Respect for professional obligations and standards ‘Any intervention in the health field, including research, must be carried out in accordance with relevant professional obligations and standards’ (article 4) ‘The Article covers both written and unwritten rules’ (EM § 30) ‘The content of professional standards, obligations and rules of conduct is not identical in all countries. The same medical duties may vary slightly from one society to another. However, the fundamental principles of the practice of medicine apply in all countries. Doctors and, in general, all professionals who participate in a medical act are subject to legal and ethical imperatives. They must act with care and Leading principle H • Freedom of scientific research ‘Scientific research in the field of biology and medicine shall be carried out freely, subject to the provisions of this Convention and the other legal provisions ensuring the protection of the human being’ (article 15) ‘Freedom of scientific research in the field of biology and medicine is justified not only by humanity's right to knowledge, but also by the considerable progress its results may bring in terms of the health and well-being of patients’ Possible restrictions and exceptions General restrictions • Article 26 – Restrictions on the exercise of the rights 1 No restrictions shall be placed on the exercise of the rights and protective provisions contained in this Convention other than such as are prescribed by law and are necessary in a democratic society in the interest of public safety, for the prevention of crime, for the protection of public health or for the protection of the General restrictions Examples: • EM § 150. Compulsory isolation of a patient with a serious infectious disease, where necessary, is a typical example of an exception for reason of the protection of public health. • EM § 151. A person who may, due to his or her mental disorder, be a possible source of serious harm to others may, according to the law, be subjected to a measure of confinement or treatment without his or her consent. • EM § 152. Protection of the rights of others may also, for example, justify an order by a judicial authority for a test to be carried out to establish parentage. General restrictions • Article 16. 2 ‘The restrictions contemplated in the preceding paragraph may not be placed on Articles 11, 13, 14, 16, 17, 19, 20 and 21’. - Article 11 : - Article 13 : genome - Article 14 : Non-discrimination Interventions on the human Non-selection of sex General restrictions - Article 17 : Protection of persons not able to consent to research - Article 19: Removal of organs from a competent donor - Article 20: Protection of persons not able to consent to organ removal - Article 21 : Prohibition of financial gain Specific restrictions • Treatment without consent of a mental disorder ‘Subject to protective conditions prescribed by law, including supervisory, control and appeal procedures, a person who has a mental disorder of a serious nature may be subjected, without his or her consent, to an intervention aimed at treating his or her mental disorder only where, without such treatment, serious harm is likely to result to Specific restrictions • Treatment in urgent situations ‘When because of an emergency situation the appropriate consent cannot be obtained, any medically necessary intervention may be carried out immediately for the benefit of the health of the individual concerned’ (article 8) Specific restrictions • Restrictions to the right to know and not to know Article 10.2 ‘Everyone is entitled to know any information collected about his or her health. However, the wishes of individuals not to be so informed shall be observed’ Article 10.3 ‘In exceptional cases, restrictions may be placed by law on the exercise of the rights contained in paragraph 2 in the interests of the patient’. Specific restrictions • Non-therapeutic research with incompetent persons Article 17.2 ‘Exceptionally and under the protective conditions prescribed by law, where the research has not the potential to produce results of direct benefit to the health of the person concerned, such research may be authorised subject to the conditions laid down in paragraph 1, subparagraphs i, iii, iv and v above, and to the following additional conditions: i the research has the aim of contributing, through significant improvement in the scientific understanding of the individual's condition, disease or disorder, to the ultimate attainment of results capable of conferring benefit to the person concerned or to other persons in the same age category or afflicted with the same disease or disorder or having the same condition; ii the research entails only minimal risk and minimal burden for the individual concerned’. Specific restrictions • Removal of tissue from an incompetent person: Article 20.2 ‘Exceptionally and under the protective conditions prescribed by law, the removal of regenerative tissue from a person who does not have the capacity to consent may be authorised provided the following conditions are met: i consent; ii iii recipient; there is no compatible donor available who has the capacity to the recipient is a brother or sister of the donor; the donation must have the potential to be life-saving for the iv the authorisation provided for under paragraphs 2 and 3 of Article 6 has been given specifically and in writing, in accordance with the law and with the approval of the competent body; v the potential donor concerned does not object’. Specific restrictions ‘Any State and the European Community may, when signing this Convention or when depositing the instrument of ratification, acceptance, approval or accession, make a reservation in respect of any particular provision of the Convention to the extent that any law then in force in its territory is not in conformity with the provision. Reservations of a general character shall not be permitted Violations of the Conventions • The Parties shall provide appropriate judicial protection to prevent or to put a stop to an unlawful infringement of the rights and principles set forth in this Convention at short notice(article 23) • Parties shall provide for appropriate sanctions to be applied in the event of infringement of the provisions contained in this Convention (article 25) Violation of the Convention • Cases of infringement of the provisions of the so called ‘mother convention’ may ultimatey be taken to the European Court of Human Rights (Strasbourg). This is however not the case for the Biomedicine Convention. • The European Court may only give advisory opinions on legal questions concerning the Convention, at the request of a Member State and the Steering Violation of the Convention • In case the infringement also concerns a provision of the ‘mother Convention’ (article 8 – protection of private and family life), an individual has the right to institute proceedings at the European Court Violation of the Convention • Increasingly, the European Court is referring to the Convention itself • Glass v. UK (9 March 2004), requirement to seek the intervention of a court in the event of parental objection is in any way consistent with the standards laid down in the Convention. UK did not sign nor ratify the Convention Violation of the Convention • Vo v France, (ECtHR, 8 July 2004). The Court made reference to the “Oviedo” Convention with regard to the interpretation of “everyone” and “human being”. France has signed but not ratified the Convention • Evans v.UK, (ECtHR, 10 April 2007) : reference to article 5 of the Convention ( Informed Consent) • Özalp v.UK, (ECtHR, 11 October 2007). Violation of the Convention • Ada Rossi v. Italy, ( ECtHR, 16 December 2008; inadmissibilily decision – Eluana Englaro – in which the Court indicated it would take into account the Oviedo Convention. • The European Court imposes the provisions of the Convention “through the backdoor” Further developments • In order to monitor scientific developments, the present Convention shall be examined within the Committee no later than five years from its entry into force and thereafter at such intervals as the Committee may determine (article 32.4) • Protocols may be concluded in pursuance of Article 32, with a view to developing, in specific fields, the principles contained in this Convention (article 31) Further developments • Protocol on the prohibition of cloning human beings (1998) • Protocol concerning transplantation of organs and tissues of human origine (2002) • Protocol concerning biomedical research (2005) Questions and discussion Embryo research in Italy: the bioethical and biojuridical debate Laura Palazzani the debate on the embryo before the law • the negation of rights to the human embryo: human embryo is considered a mere set or material aggregate of cells belonging to the human species (conventional rights) • the recognition of the rights of the embryo from the very moment of conception: the embryo is ‘already’ human (absolute rights of respect) the so-called embryonic stem cells • libertarians/utilitarians: licit (value of freedom of reseach) • intermediate position: licit only the use of frozen non-implantable embryos • personalism: illicit (absolute value of human life) the regulation in Italy • embryo research is explicitly legally regulated in the sense of prohibition • Act 40 of 2004 (Rules on medically assisted procreation) art. 1: the conceptus has rights analogous to all the subjects involved in assisted fertilisation; art. 13: any experimentation on the human embryo is prohibited; the clinical and experimental research on the human embryo is allowed on condition that exclusively therapeutic and diagnostic purposes are pursued and linked to the protection of the health and development of the embryo itself and should alternative methods not be available. the regulation in Italy art. 3 prohibits: a) the production of human embryos for research or experimental aims or for ends different from those foreseen by the law; b) every type of selection of embryos and gametes for eugenic purposes or interventions; c) cloning by means of the transfer of the nucleus or early scission of the embryo or ectogenesis both for procreation purposes and research; referenda On June 2005 four referenda were put to the vote for the partial repeal of Act 40 of 2004: one of the questions concerned embryo research. The referendum turnout did not reach the necessary quorum to be valid. jurisprudence jurisprudence tends to distinguish the protection of the embryo when related to scientific research from the protection of the embryo when related to the mother. When the relationship between the life expectancy of the embryo and the mother is highlighted, the rules do not foresee absolute protection for the embryo. the use of imported embryonic stem cells to date, it is not clear whether this is allowed or prohibited at a juridical level One point of view: the law does not express any prohibition with regard to the import of embryonic stem cells (so it is licit) Opposed point of view: as embryonic stem cells are embryos, the law expresses a prohibition (so it is illicit) arguments in favor • a) it is not a question of research on embryos but on stem cells of embryonic origin which had been extracted outside Italy; b) this kind of research does not alter the genetic patrimony • according to criminal law ‘implicit criminal prohibitions’ cannot exist as they would breach the constitutional principle of legality and certainty of the punishment • the Italian Constitution recognises the freedom of research arguments against: • as the totipotent stem cells are susceptible to embryonic development if implanted in the womb, they are to be considered embryos • since such cells or embryos are obtained by the destruction of a human embryo, their use is to be considered illicit and criminally sanctionable • the Italian Constitution protects human dignity an open problem: the use of frozen and non-implantable embryos The National Bioethics Committee Opinion on the destiny of embryos resulting from medically assisted procreation and not complying with the conditions for implantation (2007) different positions • the intention to donate embryos to research can be justified, with the informed consent of the biological parents, providing that the embryos have not been abandoned, even if this results in their destruction • any exploitative use of the embryos with destructive outcomes is never ethically acceptable because it is against their intrinsic dignity different positions • an analogy with organ donation ex-mortuo: the removal of live blastomeres from a non transferrable embryo can be compared to the removal of organs and tissues from an individual who has been declared dead. In this sense it could be licit to use the donated embryonic blastomeres in research. objections a) it must be specified that we can strictly speak of ‘unsuitability for implantation’ only when referring to embryos that are characterised by intrinsic conditions and that this concept cannot properly include extrinsic conditions b) ‘not implanted’ is different from ‘not implantable’ c) there might be indications of ‘probability’ but not ‘certainties’ The debate in Italy now • The philosophical issue of the debate concerns the balance between freedom of research and human dignity. • Some consider that freedom is inscribed in dignity and others, on the contrary, consider that dignity has priority over freedom.