Value/Criteron Consequentialism Consequentialism key to examining real world social problems. Robert Goodin a philosopher for ANDU, fellow in philosophy at Australian National Defense University, 1990 “The Utilitarian Response” Consequentialism is the idea that what matters most is the consequences of our actions. This de-emphasizes the direct content of an action by replacing such emphasis with the actual outcome of an action. There are many variations on this theme the most promising of which, I think, are the ones that take into count the actual consequences of an agent throughout their entire life as opposed to just immediate consequences and deceptions. ac This view looks at the overall success of protracted struggles above and beyond simply immediate victories that might eventually lead to the success of the overall struggle. Also, emphasis is placed on actual consequences instead of perceived consequences in which an agent might be deceived. The consequences of an action are many times influenced by a great number of outside forces or variables such as other agents in the world. Also, desired consequences may involve the conditions of others. In this way there is a social element implicit to Consequentialism. “It is because Consequentialism attaches value ultimately to states Upholding life is the ultimate moral standard. Uyl and Douglas Rasmussen, Professors of Philosophy at Bellarmine and St. John's, 1981, Reading Nozick, p.244 Rand has spoken of the ultimate end as the standard by which all other ends are evaluated. When the ends to be evaluated are chosen ones the ultimate end is the standard for moral evaluation . Life as the sort of thing a living entity is, then, is the ultimate standard of value, and since only human beings are capable of choosing their ends, it is the life as a human being-man's life qua man-that is the standard for moral evaluation. Douglas Den Utilitarianism is real world and non-utopian Joseph Nye, prof. of IR at Harvard University, 1986 ( “Nuclear Ethics”, p. 24) Whether one accepts the broad consequentialist approach or chooses some other, more eclectic way to include and reconcile the three dimensions of complex moral issues, there will often be a sense of uneasiness about the answers, not just because of the complexity of the problems “but simply that there is no satisfactory solution to these issues – at least none that appears to avoid in practice what most men would still regard as an intolerable sacrifice of value.” When value is sacrificed, there is often the problem of “dirty hands.” Not all ethical decisions are pure ones. The absolutist may avoid the problem of dirty hands, but often at the cost of having no hands at all. Moral theory cannot be “rounded off and made complete and tidy.” That is part of the modern human condition. But that does not exempt us from making difficult moral choices. Must Prevent Extinction No natural good can come out of extinction of the human race. It is the ultimate impact. You should prefer stopping it over all else. Nick Bostrum 11 (Professor, Faculty of Philosophy & Oxford Martin School EXISTENTIAL RISK PREVENTION AS THE MOST IMPORTANT TASK FOR HUMANITY “ 2011 , Faculty of Philosophy & Oxford Martin School http://www.existential-risk.org/concept.pdf ,DW) But even this reflection fails to bring out the seriousness of existential risk. What makes existential catastrophes especially bad is not that they would show up robustly on a plot like the one in figure 3, causing a precipitous drop in world population or average quality of life. Instead, their significance lies primarily in the fact that they would destroy the future. The philosopher Derek Parfit made a similar point with the following thought experiment: ¶ I believe that if we destroy [humankind] mankind, as we now can, this outcome will be much worse than most people think. Compare three outcomes: ¶ (1) Peace. ¶ (2) A nuclear war that kills 99% of the world’s existing population. ¶ (3) A nuclear war that kills 100%. (2) would be worse than (1), and (3) would be worse than (2). Which is the greater of these two differences? Most people believe that the greater difference is between (1) and (2). I believe that the difference between (2) and (3) is very much greater. … The Earth will remain habitable for at least another billion year s. Civilization began only a few thousand years ago. If we do not destroy [humankind] mankind, these few thousand years may be only a tiny fraction of the whole of civilized human history. The difference between (2) and (3) may thus be the difference between this tiny fraction and all of the rest of this history. If we compare this possible history to a day, what has occurred so far is only a fraction of a second. (10: 453-454) ¶ To calculate the loss associated with an existential catastrophe, we must consider how much value would come to exist in its absence. It turns out that the ultimate potential for Earth-originating intelligent life is literally astronomical. ¶ One gets a large number even if one confines one’s consideration to the potential for biological human beings living on Earth. If we suppose with Parfit that our planet will remain habitable for at least another billion years, and we assume that at least one billion people could live on it sustainably, then the potential exist for at least 1018 human lives. These lives could also be considerably better than the average contemporary human life, which is so often marred by disease, poverty, injustice, and various biological limitations that could be partly overcome through continuing technological and moral progress. Our strongest moral impulse ought to be prevention of human extinction. Nick Bostrum ‘11 (Professor, Faculty of Philosophy & Oxford Martin School EXISTENTIAL RISK PREVENTION AS THE MOST IMPORTANT TASK FOR HUMANITY “ 2011 , Faculty of Philosophy & Oxford Martin School http://www.existential-risk.org/concept.pdf ,DW) We might also consider the issue from a less theoretical standpoint and try to form an evaluation instead by considering analogous cases about which we have definite moral intuitions. Thus, for example, if we feel confident that committing a small genocide is wrong, and that committing a large genocide is no less wrong, we might conjecture that committing omnicide is also wrong.25 And if we believe we have some moral reason to prevent natural catastrophes that would kill a small number of people, and a stronger moral reason to prevent natural catastrophes that would kill a larger number of people, we might conjecture that we have an even stronger moral reason to prevent catastrophes that would kill the entire human population. Deontology Using people as a means goes against morality Manuel Velasquez, Moral Philosopher, Mar. 6, 2007. Philosophy: A Text with Readings, pg. 460 “Ethics”. Kant’s second version of the categorical imperative implies that we should not use people as objects, as things whose only function is to satisfy our desires. Instead, he claims, morality requires that we always give others the opportunity to decide for themselves whether or not they will join us in our actions. This rules out all forms of deception, force, coercion, and manipulation. It also rules out all the ways we have of exploiting other people to satisfy our own desires without their free consent. Moreover, the second version implies that we should promote people’s capacity to choose for themselves. It also implies that we should strive to develop this capacity in ourselves and in those around us (for example, through education). Again, some examples may clarify what Kant has in mind in this second version. For Kant, to respect a person as an end is to respect her capacity to freely and knowingly choose for herself what she will do. To treat a person as a means is to use the person to achieve my personal interests. In effect, this second version says that we should treat people only as they freely and knowingly consent to be treated, not merely as a means to my own goal. Kant would say that it is wrong to force or to manipulate a person into doing something because in manipulating or forcing a person I am failing to treat the person as she has freely and knowingly consented to be treated. Morality precedes all decision making Zygmunt Bauman, Professor Emeritus of Sociology, 1993. Postmodern Ethics pgs. 246-250. http://docs.exdat.com/docs/index-149754.html?page=82 accessed 7/19/12 But the moral crisis of the postmodern habitat requires first and foremost that politics - whether the politics of the politicians or the policentric, scattered politics which matters all the more for being so elusive and beyond control _ be an extension and institutionalization of moral responsibility. Genuine moral issues of the high-tech world are by and large beyond the reach of individuals (who, at best, may singly or severally purchase the right not to worry about them, or buy a temporary reprieve from suffering the effects of neglect). The effects of technology are long-distance, and so must be the preventive and remedial action. Hans Jonas's 'long-range ethics' makes sense, if at all, only as a political programme - though given the nature of the postmodern habitat, there is little hope that any political party competing for state power would be willing, suicidally, to endorse this truth and act upon it. Commenting on Edgar Allan Poe's story of three fishermen caught in the maelstrom, of whom two died paralysed with fear and doing nothing, but the third survived, having noticed that round objects are sucked into the abyss less quickly, and promptly jumping into a barrel - Norbert Elias sketched the way in which the exit from a nonexit situation may be plotted. The survivor, Elias suggests, “began to think more coolly; and by standing back, by controlling his own fear, by seeing himself as it were from a distance, like a chessman forming a pattern with others -on a board, he managed to turn his thoughts away from himself to the situation in which he found himself... Symbolically representing in his mind the structure and direction of the flow of events, he discovered a way of escape. In that situation, the level of self-control and the level of processcontrol were ... interdependent and complemen tary.'s” Let us note that Poe's cool and clever fisherman escaped alone. We do not know how many barrels there were left in the boat. And barrels, after all, have been known since Diogenes to be the ultimate individual retreats. The question is - and to this question private cunning offers no answer -- to what extent the techniques of individual survival (techniques by the way, amply provided for all present and future, genuine and putative maelstroms, by eagertooblige-and-profit merchants of goods and counsels) can be stretched to-embrace the-collective survival.--The-maelstrom-of the kind we are in - all of us together, and most of us individually - is so frightening because of its tendency to break down the issue of common survival into a sackful of individual survival issues, and then to take the issue so pulverized off the political agenda. Can the process be retraced? Can that which has been broken be made whole again? And where to find an adhesive strong enough to keep it whole? If the successive chapters of this book suggest anything, it is that moral issues cannot be 'resolved', nor the moral life of humanity guaranteed, by the calculating and legislative efforts of reason. Morality is not safe in the hands of reason, though this is exactly what spokesmen of reason promise. Reason cannot help the moral self without depriving the self of what makes the self moral: that unfounded, non-rational, un-arguable, no-excuses-given and noncalculable urge to stretch towards the other, to caress, to be for, to live for, happen what may. Reason is about making correct decisions, while moral responsibility precedes all thinking about decisions as it does not, and cannot care about any logic which would allow the approval of an action as correct. Thus, morality can be `rationalized' only at the cost of self-denial and self attrition. Compassion/Ethic of Care Compassion is the basis of all morality. Schopenhauer, Arthur. On the Basis of Morality. Indianapolis: Bobbs-Merrill, 1965. Print. But if what I do is to take place solely on account of some one else ; then it follows that his weal and woe must directly constitute my motive ; just as, ordinarily, my own weal and woe form it. This narrows the limits of our problem, which may now be stated as follows : How is it possible that another's weal and woe should influence my will directly, that is, exactly in the same way as otherwise my own move it ? How can that which affects another for good or bad become my immediate motive, and actually sometimes assume such importance that it more or less supplants my own interests, which are, as a rule, the single source of the incentives that appeal to me ? Obviously, only because that other person becomes the ultimate object of my will, precisely as usually I myself am that object ; in other words, because I directly desire weal, and not woe, for him, just as habitually I do for myself. This, however, necessarily implies that I suffer with him, and feel his woe, exactly as in most cases I feel only mine, and therefore desire his weal as immediately as at other times I desire only my own. But, for this to be possible, I must in some way or other be identified with him ; that is, the difference between myself and him, which is the precise raison d'etre of my Egoism, must be removed, at least to a since I do not live in his skin, there remains only the knowledge, that is, the mental picture, I have of him, as the possible means where- by I can so far identify myself with him, that my action declares the difference to be practically effaced. The process here analyzed is not a dream, a fancy floating in the air ; it is perfectly real, and by no means infrequent. It is, what we see every day, the phenomenon of Compassion ; in other words, the direct participation, independent of all ulterior considerations, in the sufferings of another, leading to sympathetic assistance in the effort to prevent or remove them ; whereon in the last resort all satisfaction and all well-being and happiness depend. It is this Compassion alone which is the real basis of all voluntary justice and all genuine loving-kindness. Only so far as an action springs therefrom, has it moral value ; and all conduct that proceeds from any other motive whatever has none. When once certain extent. Now, compassion is stirred within me, by another's pain, then his weal and woe go straight to my heart, exactly in the same way, if not always to the same degree, as otherwise I feel only my own. Consequently the difference between myself and him is no longer an absolute one. No doubt this operation is astonishing, indeed hardly comprehensible. It is, in fact, the great mystery of Ethics, its original phaenomenon, and the boundary stone, past which only transcendental speculation may dare to take a step. Herein we see the wall of partition, which, according to the light of nature (as reason is called by old theologians), entirely separates being from being, broken down, and the non-ego to a certain extent identified with the ego. I wish for the moment to leave the metaphysical explanation of this enigma untouched, and first to inquire whether all acts of voluntary justice and true loving- kindness really arise we shall have found the ultimate basis of morality, and shown that it lies in human nature itself. This foundation, however, in its turn cannot form a problem of Ethics, but rather, like from it. If so, our problem will be solved, for every other ultimate fact as such, of Metaphysics. Only the solution, that the latter offers of the primary ethical phaenomenon, lies outside the limits of the question put by the Danish Royal Society, which is concerned solely with the basis ; so that the transcendental explanation can be given merely as a voluntary and unessential appendix. States have a responsibility to practice compassion towards those in need; this responsibility can be provoked by civic debate. Elisabeth Porter, PhD, professor of social sciences at the University of South Australia, 2006, Hypatia, “Can Politics Practice Compassion?”, pp. 97-12, http://www.jstor.org/stable/4640024, Access date: 7/17/12 Yet, as intimated earlier, in order to move beyond empathy, we must also address claims for justice and equality. Again, I suggest that without the compassionate drive that is prompted by visualizing the pain of injustice, we will not feel peoples' anguish, or bother to consider what they need. As individuals, we have responsibilities beyond our personal connections to assist whenever it is within our capacities and resources to do so. I do not want to give the impression that our entire lives should be devoted to attending to others' needs. To do so would return women to exclusive nurturance at the expense of self-development and public citizenship. It is, rather, a matter of acting with compassion when it is possible to do so, and the possibility of course is debatable and requires priorities, which differ with us all. Politically, this means that politicians, nations, and international organizations have a similar responsibility to alleviate the suffering that results when peoples' basic needs are not met. There is a heavy responsibility on wealthy nations where the extent of poverty and misery is not as conspicuous as elsewhere to assist less wealthy nations.16 State responsibility is acute when suffering is caused by harsh economic policies, careless sales of arms and military weapons, severe immigration rules, and obscene responses to terrorism by further acts of violence. With the majority of these massive global issues, most of us can only demonstrate the first stage of cosuffering, and perhaps move to the second and debate the merit of options that might meet peoples' needs, and alleviate suffering. This vocal civic debate can provoke the third process of political responses that actually lead to political compassion. Given nations' moral failures of compassion and such conspicuous evidence of oppression, exploitation, brutality, and indifference, we need to be observant, and understand the implications of a failure to practice compassion. The responsibility of the state to those in need includes providing welfare programs. Elisabeth Porter, PhD, professor of social sciences at the University of South Australia, 2006, Hypatia, “Can Politics Practice Compassion?”, pp. 97-12, http://www.jstor.org/stable/4640024, Access date: 7/17/12 I am defending the position that it is possible to be politically compassionate and just and that such a claim should be disentangled from notions of gender. I dispute the essentialist claim that women are naturally compassionate. However, because of women's traditional association with caring and their role as primary parent, many women are experienced in caring and tend to respond readily with compassion. As others also argue (Philips 1993, 70; Sevenhuijsen 1998, 13), I am emphasizing the interplay between the particularity of compassion and the universality of justice. Undoubtedly, the dichotomy of public justice associated with masculinity and private care associated with femininity narrowed moral parameters, harmfully cementing restrictive gendered stereotypes. Rather, the relationship between compassion and justice is rich. Compassion "helps us recognize our justice obligations to those distant from us" (Clement 1996, 85). Examples of justice obligations include welfare programs; foreign aid; famine and disaster relief; humane immigration policies; and relieving the suffering of families who are affected by terrorism in Bali, Iraq, Israel, London, Morocco, Northern Ireland, Palestine, Saudi Arabia, Spain, Sri Lanka, Sudan, the United States, and elsewhere. A choice between justice and compassion is false; considerations of justice "arise in and about the practice of care" (Bubeck 1995a, 189). Thus, a defense of the need for compassion is as much a defense for the rights of justice. The obligation to care for others is delegated to whoever is best suited to provide that care. Rosemarie Tong, professor of health care ethics and women’s studies at the University of North Carolina, 2002, Hypatia, “Love's Labor in the Health Care System: Working toward Gender Equity”, pg. 200-213, http://www.jstor.org/stable/info/3810802, Date accessed: 7/18/12 Kittay's justification for the dependency worker's obligations to the dependent resembles the one Robert Goodin offers in his book, "the moral basis of special relations between individuals arises from the vulnerability of one party to the actions of another" (55). For example, a mother has an obligation to care for her infant because she is "the individual best situated, or exclusively situated to meet the needs of the dependent" (55). The source of a mother's moral obligation to her infant is not in the rights of the dependent as a person, but rather in the relationship that exists between one in need and one who is situated to meet the need. The defining characteristic of this largely socially constructed relationship is that it is not Protecting the Vulnerable (Goodin 1985). According to Kittay's interpretation of Goodin, usually chosen but already given in the ties of family, the dynamics of friendship, or the obligations of employment. The fact that a relationship is "given" to the dependency worker, however, does not mean that it is necessarily wrong for the dependency worker to break the relationship. Kittay disagrees with Goodin when he refuses to absolve a slave from his "obligations" to a master who becomes so ill that he cannot survive without the slave's help. The master's fragile condition is the slave's one chance for freedom. Is the slave obligated to stay and take care of his master who will most likely die if left unattended? Goodin argues yes. As he sees it, if vulnerability arises in a relationship, the moral worth of that relationship is not relevant to the existence of the obligation (Kittay 1999, 59). Kittay argues no. As she sees it, the relationship that was given to the slave was a "relationship" that society should not have constructed. Its coerciveness cancels out the obligations that human vulnerability ordinarily creates. Here Kittay is supported by many feminist ethicists, particularly Sarah Lucia Hoagland (1991). According to Hoagland, if a relationship is coercive, abusive, or destructive, the aggrieved party has no obligation to remain in it. She comments: "I must be able to assess any relationship for abuse/oppression and withdraw if I find it to be so. I feel no guilt, I have grown, I have learned something. I understand my part in the relationship. I separate. I will not be there again. Far from diminishing my ethical self, I am enhancing it" (256). Interestingly Kittay believes that others' obligations to dependency workers are no less weighty than dependency workers' obligations to their dependents. In fact, she implies they are more weighty. Even though Kittay believes, as we have just seen, that there are some dependency relationships that dependency workers may rightfully break, she does not also believe that society may break its obligations to dependency workers. AT Ethics of Care Ethics of care subjugates womyn. Further oppresses womyn by seeing them as the “care takers.” and reinforces patriarchal binary. Staudt, 2011 Maureen Sander-Staudt, Ph.D , feminist author, Peer reviewed philosophical data-base, March 18 2011 th “Care Ethics” http://www.iep.utm.edu/care-eth/#SH1a DW) One of the earliest objections was that care ethics is a kind of slave morality valorizing the oppression of women (Puka, 1990; Card, 1990; Davion, 1993). The concept of slave morality comes from the philosopher Frederick Nietzsche, who held that oppressed peoples tend to develop moral theories that reaffirm subservient traits as virtues. Following this tradition, the charge that care ethics is a slave morality interprets the different voice of care as emerging from patriarchal traditions characterized by rigidly enforced sexual divisions of labor. This critique issues caution against uncritically valorizing caring practices and inclinations because women who predominantly perform the work of care often do so to their own economic and political disadvantage. To the extent that care ethics encourages care without further inquiring as to who is caring for whom, and whether these relationships are just, it provides an unsatisfactory base for a fully libratory ethic. This objection further implies that the voice of care may not be an authentic or empowering expression, but a product of false consciousness that equates moral maturity with self-sacrifice and self-effacement. Care Ethics are Empirically Flawed Staudt 2011 (Maureen Sander-Staudt, Ph.D , feminist author, Peer reviewed philosophical data-base, March 18 th 2011 “Care Ethics” http://www.iep.utm.edu/care-eth/#SH1a DW) Critics also question the empirical accuracy and validity of Gilligan’s studies. Gilligan has been faulted for basing her conclusions on too narrow a sample, and for drawing from overly homogenous groups such as students at elite colleges and women considering abortion (thereby excluding women who would not view abortion as morally permissible). It is argued that wider samples yield more diverse results and complicate the picture of dual and gendered moral perspectives (Haan, 1976; Brabeck, 1983). For instance, Vanessa Siddle Walker and John Snarey surmise that resolution of the Heinz dilemma shifts if Heinz is identified as Black, because in the United States African-American males are disproportionately likely to be arrested for crime, and less likely to have their cases dismissed without stringent penalties (Walker and Snarey, 2004). Sandra Harding observes certain similarities between care ethics and African moralities, noting that care ethics has affinities with many other moral traditions (Harding, 1987). Sarah Lucia Hoagland identifies care as the heart of lesbian connection, but also cautions against the dangers of assuming that all care relations are ideally maternalistic (Hoagland, 1988). Thus, even if some women identify with care ethics, it is unclear whether this is a general quality of women, whether moral development is distinctly and dualistically gendered, and whether the voice of care is the only alternative moral voice. Narratives The only way to access the true moral and ethical questions of the resolution is through a narrative that humanizes the “other” Kapust Antje, Prof. of Philosophy at Ruhr-Universität Bochum. 2005: Addressing Levinas Ed. Eric Sean Nelson, Antje Kapust, and Kent Still. Northwestern University Press. Pgs. 236-257 From antiquity to modern times-it was always the other as barbarian, as horrid animal, and as uncivilized being, who was all too often decreed to be a legitimated target for extinction. This “labeling” coincided with an ambivalent refusal of situating him or her in the reign of “ethical speech." Passing from the late concept of polemos to the holy doctrine of sacred war, from conquest of civilizations to ideological legitimations of persecutions of others, rationally developed many ways of interrupting Levinas advances -that of preferring to talk to the so-called barbarian instead of killing him. Even the calling into memory of this orientation does not take place; violence is enacted in the sphere of mute acts of brutality such as took place in the mass execution the orientation that of Jews, a mass murder which was set forth in the final solution of National Socialism: "We have drunk a lot of alcohol during this time in order to stimulate our verve and Victims are deprived of any possibility of speech, since any request for deliverance, rescue, or survival has to be immediately denied and repressed: “The Jews who were still living exhilaration for work." after mass execution as well as those who were only shot and still wounded in the lower layers were suffocated by the upper layers or were drowned by the blood of the upper layers." The force of violence replaces the creative function that Hannah Arendt attributed to the political word. An agonistic productivity of political speech shifts all too quickly to a dysfunctional and destructive force. Ricoeur describes the logic of this collision in a metaphor which dismisses Levinas’s ethical point, since violence is described as the mechanical action and reaction of two forces-an image that applied to illustrate the phenomena of battle and combat from modern philosophy to the military discourses of the the ontological dilemma of this violence: it consists in the dominance of the blind spot in which “two powers of command confront each other at the same point of pretension where they cannot sustain both at the same time." In this blind spot of collision, speech gets destroyed and is replaced by a myth that imposes a stigma upon the target of extinction. nineteenth and twentieth centuries. But it is important that he links this collision of forces with a degradation of language. Ricoeur describes precisely Storytelling is necessary for the development of moral agency. Tirrell, Lynne, Prof. Philosophy at U. Mass Boston, Storytelling and Moral agency, The Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism, Vol. 48, No. 2 (Spring, 1990), pp. 115-126 It is through the articulation of events, motives and characters that we become moral agents. This is the sense in which storytelling is necessary for moral agency. In telling stories one develops a sense of self, a sense of self in relation to others, and a capacity to justify one's decisions. These features are necessary for being a moral agent in the categorical sense. Telling stories may also increase our sophistication as agents. We may begin with rudimentary stories that show a basic grasp of the moral, and sometimes we may eventually develop the thickened judgment that enables one to take control of oneself, one's place in one's community and to have a directed impact on that community. Levinas We must always interrupt the political with the ethical. Exposition to the suffering of the other is necessary for all ethical evaluations. Jordaan, Eduard. Professor of Political Science at Stellenbosch, 2006, “Responsibility, Indifference, and Global Poverty: A Levinasian Perspective” For Levinas, it is imperative that the political be forever interrupted by the ethical; the question is how? Awakening us to our responsibility for the other is the second function of the proposed strategy, which is intended to describe and emphasize human complexity to the greatest extent possible. Throughout this study, authors in the cosmopolitan-communitarian debate have been criticized for suppressing various aspects of the ethical relation with the other, which has resulted in us being left in good conscience, despite having failed the global other. At the start of this chapter it was argued that the cosmopolitan strategy to convince us of our guilt and responsibility for the global poor is counterproductive given that its emphasis on human equality numbs that which incites us to responsibility for the other, namely glimpses of him as inexpressibly different from everyone else, unique. So, it seems as though our task is to confront the world with the ‘face’ of the other, to accuse the world of having left the other to quite literally ‘die alone’. It is imperative that we “expose” the ‘skins’ of complacent selves to “wounds and outrage,” that we elicit a “suffering for the suffering of the other” (CPP 146). In order to bring the world into proximity to the other, to expose third parties to his ‘face,’ it is claimed that actions aimed at conveying the other in as great a complexity as possible can help us do this. Human complexity/difference/dissimilarity is therefore not important for its own sake (and therefore to be maintained at all costs), but insofar as it insinuates the uniqueness of the other. Of course, this ‘strategy’ immediately has to confront the objection that all representations of the other betray his alterity and suppress his otherness (see Broody, 2001). Granting this, the claim made here is that there are representations (and positionings) of the other and articulations of his situation that are more suggestive of his otherness and therefore of my ethical responsibility for him. That this is so is suggested by the opposite, namely an extreme form of negating the other’s alterity, his de-humanisation through racist and stereotyped representations whereby the way is paved for social and political disregard, maltreatment, or ‘disciplining’. Though one cannot be sure of the direction of causality, there seems to be a direct correlation between the fullness with which people are viewed and the extent of the concern we have for them. Is it not generally the case that the people we are most indifferent towards are also those most absent from our imaginations, those persons/groups we know least about? Returning to the group of people I am most concerned with in this study, the global poor, is it not the case that we generally know very little about tem, compared to say, Americans? And, for example, is this not part of the reason that while the world reacted with great sympathy for the victims of the September 11th attacks in which approximately three thousand people died, we do not pay much attention to the fact that every day approximately 30,000 children die from preventable illnesses, which translates into more than 10 million deaths per year (UNDP 2003: 5; World Bank, 2004)? It is my contention that there is a relationship between the fullness with which we view people and the concern we have for them, and a large part of the reason is that a fuller conception of the other person is a stronger suggestion of his altery and the ethical command that issues from the fact of his otherness. The State is the beginning of all violence-not helping those who aren’t “its own” ignores responsibility for the other and is the root cause of all violence. ¶ Aronowicz, prof Judaism Franklin and Marshall, 2006¶ Annette Aronowicz, professor of Judaic studies at Franklin and Marshall College, Summer 2006, “Levinas and Politics” http://66.102.1.104/scholar?q=cache:5L5lnjhcUSgJ:scholar.google.com/+levinas%2Bholocaust%2Bpolitics&hl=en ¶ ¶ What remains after so much bloodshed and tears shed in the name of immortal principles is individual sacrifice, which, amidst the dialectical rebounds of justice and all its contradictory aboutfaces, without any hesitation finds a straight and sure way (1990: 29). Once again, we have a very violent reality, “the cruelty inherent in rational order (and¶ perhaps simply in Order)” says Levinas (1990: 29). Countering this is the act of protection and mercy extended from one to the other. This is not to suggest that Levinas’ solution to the problem of violence lies simply in the individual’s act of responsibility. It is neither that simple nor that simplistic. In ‘Judaism and revolution’, a very complex commentary dealing with the relationship of the Jewish tradition and the State, Levinas makes clear that the State itself is responsible for guaranteeing conditions that permit for the fulfillment of the human (Levinas 1990: 99). Yet the State claims a universalism that is deceptive, for while it attempts to protect the individual person, it limits that protection to its own and thus divides the world into an ‘us and them’, quelling the responsibility of one to the other, beyond any distinctions whatsoever. The Jewish tradition’s universalism, on the other hand, does not recognize limits to responsibility for the other person. It thus introduces a wedge between the Jewish people and the State, for the latter cannot limit the responsibility of the former. As such, the Jewish tradition always signals a loyalty beyond the State, and propels political activity in two directions. The first is in the direction of care for the most vulnerable members within it, setting the standard by which the State offers guarantees against dehumanization (Levinas 1990: 99-100). The second is in refusing to identify the good with a particular State, thus preventing the State from turning into an object of idolatry. Levinas warns, however, that even a¶ revolutionary movement whose aim is to overthrow a hopelessly corrupt government can turn into a mirror image of the violence it contests, dividing the world into us and them just as much. A revolution always risks the very thing it is opposing. This does not mean that revolution is never justified but once again, we are left, as our only recourse, vigilance against abuses, rather than a once and for all transformation: Revolutionary action is first of all the action of the isolated man who plans revolution not only in danger but also in the agony of conscience. In the agony of conscience that risks making revolution impossible: for it is not only a question of seizing the evil-doer but also of not making the innocent suffer (Levinas 1990:¶ 110). We should reject the state-rather that it’s in a permanent revolution to always become more ethical. We must help by taking individual responsibility to check its instituions -without ethics we all face unlimited violence.¶ Simmons, associate prof social sciences ASU, 2003¶ William Paul Simmons, associate professor of social sciences at Arizona State University, 2003, “An-Archy and Justice: An Introduction to Emmanuel Levinas’s Political Thought” ¶ According to Levinas, the move from the Other to the Third is the beginning of all violence. In the realm of the said, the ego must necessarily weigh others in the name of justice, but this process reduces the Other to a cipher. Strangely enough, justice is un-ethical. When justice is universalized into laws and institutions it moves yet another step away from the anarchical responsibility for the Other. The necessary universalization of ethical responsibility into the state is inherently un-ethical and violent. In the state, the ego is unable to respond directly to the face of the Other. Further, the institutions of the state treat the Other as an interchangeable cog in its machinery, thereby denying the transcendent element in man. Even when the state functions perfectly it is, by its very nature, opposed to ethics. "For me, the negative element, the element of violence in the state, in the hierarchy, appears even when the hierarchy functions perfectly, when everyone submits to universal ideas. There are cruelties which are terrible because they proceed from the necessity of the reasonable order. There are, if you like, the tears that a civil servant cannot see: the tears of the Other.'45¶ Vigilance against violence in the state is essential. Institutions need to be constantly checked by the ethical relationship with the Other. "In order for things to work and in order for things to develop an equilibrium, it is absolutely necessary to affirm the infinite responsibility of each, for each, before each . .. . As I see it, subjective protest is not received favorably on the pretext that its egoism is sacred, but because the 1 alone can perceive the 'secret tears' of the Other which are caused by the functioning-albeit reasonable-of the hierarchy."4'¶ The state must be constantly reminded of its inherent violence. Levinas finds just such a self-critical state in the modem liberal state. The liberal state "always asks itself whether its own justice really is justice. "17¶ What qualities does the liberal state possess that makes it self-critical? First, there is the freedom of the press, the freedom to criticize the government, to speak out against injustice. "You know the prophets of the bible, they come and say to the king that his method of dispensing justice is wrong. The prophet doesn't do this in a clandestine way: he comes before the king and he tells him. In the liberal state, it's the press, the poets, the writers who fulfill this role."48 ¶ Second, in the liberal state, the leader is not above the people, but is chosen from among the people. A ruler who is in an ethical relationship sees humanity through the Other's eyes. Against the Platonic formulation that the best ruler is the one who is best in control of himself, Levinas argues that the best ruler is the one who is in an ethical relationship with the Other. "The State, in accordance with its pure essence, is possible only if the divine word enters into it; the prince¶ is educated in this knowledge."9¶ However, for Levinas, the most important component of the liberal state is its call for a "permanent revolution."50 The Levinasian liberal state is always trying to improve itself, trying to be more just. It is "a rebellion that begins where the other society is satisfied to leave off, a rebellion against injustice that begins once order begins."5' Although no state can be purely ethical, the liberal state at least strives for ethics. Such a state is the desideratum if politics cannot be ethical. There is no politics for accomplishing the moral, but there are certainly some politics which are further from it or closer to it. For example, I've mentioned Stalinism to you. I've told you that justice is always a justice which desires a better justice. This is the way that I will characterize the liberal state. The liberal state is a state which holds justice as the absolutely desirable end and hence as a perfection. Concretely, the liberal state has always admitted ¶ alongside the written law-human rights as a parallel institution. It continues to preach that within its justice there are always improvements to be made in human rights. Human rights are the reminder that there is no justice yet. And consequently, I believe that it is absolutely obvious that the liberal state is more moral than the fascist state, and closer to the morally ideal state.32¶ The ethical and the political are not separated-politics is the ethical relationship between more than one Other. Infusing Levinasian ethics into politics will create a more ethical, less violent state. Simmons, associate prof social sciences ASU, 2003 William Paul Simmons, associate professor of social sciences at Arizona State University, 2003, “An-Archy and Justice: An Introduction to Emmanuel Levinas’s Political Thought” Therefore, Levinas distinguishes the ethical relationship with the Other from justice which involves three or more people.2° The an-archical relationship with the Other is the pre-linguistic world of the saying. Language is unnecessary to respond to the Other. The Third, however, demands an explanation. "In its frankness it [language] refuses the clandestinity of love, where it loses its frankness and meaning and turns into laughter or cooing. The third party looks at me in the eyes of the Other-.language is justice."2' In order to judge between Others, they must be co-present, or synchronous. Thus, the Third also opens up the world of knowledge and consciousness. "Here is the hour and birthplace of the question: a demand for justice! Here is the obligation to compare unique and incomparable others; here is the hour of knowledge and, then, of the objectivity beyond or on the hither side of the nudity of the face; here is the hour of consciousness and intentionality."22¶ Finally, the Third introduces the realm of politics. The ego's infinite respon-¶ sibility must be extended to all humanity, no matter how far off. Ethics must be universalized and institutionalized to affect the others. "To the extent that someone else's Face brings us in relation with a third party, My metaphysical relation to the Other is transformed into a We, and works toward a State, institutions and laws which form the source of universality."¶ Before delving into the relationship between ethics and politics, several implications of Levinas's move from the Other to the Third need to be addressed. First, does the ego still have an infinite responsibility for the Other? In Otherwise than Being, Levinas defines justice as "the limit of responsibility and the birth of the question?'24 However, in the same work, he also claims that "in no way is justice a degradation of obsession, a degeneration of the for-the-other, a diminution, a limitation of anarchic responsibility.us How can these conflicting statements be resolved? Either justice limits the responsibility for the Other or it does not. The contradiction is resolved by considering, once again, Levinas's theoretical emphasis on the separation between the saying and the said. Ethics is found in the an-archical realm of the saying, while justice is a part of the totalizing realm of the said. Ethics and justice exist in both relation and separation. Neither can be reduced to the other. Thus, justice cannot diminish the infinite responsibility for the Other the ego remains infinitely, asymmetrically, and concretely responsible for the Other. This responsibility always maintains its potency. However, the ego is also invariably transported by the Third into the realm of the said. The ego must weigh its obligations. It is not possible to respond infinitely to all Others. The original demand for an infinite responsibility remains, but it cannot be fulfilled. Ethics must be universalized, but in attempting to do so, the ego has already reneged on its responsibility for the Other. Thus, Levinas's peculiar formulation; justice is un-ethical and violent "Only justice can wipe it [ethical responsibility] away by bringing this givingoneself to my neighbor under measure, or moderating it by thinking in relation to the third and the fourth, who are also my 'others,' but justice is already the first violence."¶ The State is the beginning of all violence-not helping those who aren’t “its own” ignores responsibility for the other and is the root cause of all violence. ¶ Aronowicz, prof Judaism Franklin and Marshall, 2006¶ Annette Aronowicz, professor of Judaic studies at Franklin and Marshall College, Summer 2006, “Levinas and Politics” http://66.102.1.104/scholar?q=cache:5L5lnjhcUSgJ:scholar.google.com/+levinas%2Bholocaust%2Bpolitics&hl=en ¶ ¶ What remains after so much bloodshed and tears shed in the name of immortal principles is individual sacrifice, which, amidst the dialectical rebounds of justice and all its contradictory aboutfaces, without any hesitation finds a straight and sure way (1990: 29). Once again, we have a very violent reality, “the cruelty inherent in rational order (and¶ perhaps simply in Order)” says Levinas (1990: 29). Countering this is the act of protection and mercy extended from one to the other. This is not to suggest that Levinas’ solution to the problem of violence lies simply in the individual’s act of responsibility. It is neither that simple nor that simplistic. In ‘Judaism and revolution’, a very complex commentary dealing with the relationship of the Jewish tradition and the State, Levinas makes clear that the State itself is responsible for guaranteeing conditions that permit for the fulfillment of the human (Levinas 1990: 99). Yet the State claims a universalism that is deceptive, for while it attempts to protect the individual person, it limits that protection to its own and thus divides the world into an ‘us and them’, quelling the responsibility of one to the other, beyond any distinctions whatsoever. The Jewish tradition’s universalism, on the other hand, does not recognize limits to responsibility for the other person. It thus introduces a wedge between the Jewish people and the State, for the latter cannot limit the responsibility of the former. As such, the Jewish tradition always signals a loyalty beyond the State, and propels political activity in two directions. The first is in the direction of care for the most vulnerable members within it, setting the standard by which the State offers guarantees against dehumanization (Levinas 1990: 99-100). The second is in refusing to identify the good with a particular State, thus preventing the State from turning into an object of idolatry. Levinas warns, however, that even a¶ revolutionary movement whose aim is to overthrow a hopelessly corrupt government can turn into a mirror image of the violence it contests, dividing the world into us and them just as much. A revolution always risks the very thing it is opposing. This does not mean that revolution is never justified but once again, we are left, as our only recourse, vigilance against abuses, rather than a once and for all transformation: Revolutionary action is first of all the action of the isolated man who plans revolution not only in danger but also in the agony of conscience. In the agony of conscience that risks making revolution impossible: for it is not only a question of seizing the evil-doer but also of not making the innocent suffer (Levinas 1990:¶ 110). This isn’t to say we should reject the state-rather that it’s in a permanent revolution to always become more ethical. We must help by taking individual responsibility to check its instituions -without ethics we all face unlimited violence.¶ Simmons, associate prof social sciences ASU, 2003¶ William Paul Simmons, associate professor of social sciences at Arizona State University, 2003, “An-Archy and Justice: An Introduction to Emmanuel Levinas’s Political Thought”¶ According to Levinas, the move from the Other to the Third is the beginning of all violence. In the realm of the said, the ego must necessarily weigh others in the name of justice, but this process reduces the Other to a cipher. Strangely enough, justice is un-ethical. When justice is universalized into laws and institutions it moves yet another step away from the anarchical responsibility for the Other. The necessary universalization of ethical responsibility into the state is inherently un-ethical and violent. In the state, the ego is unable to respond directly to the face of the Other. Further, the institutions of the state treat the Other as an interchangeable cog in its machinery, thereby denying the transcendent element in man. Even when the state functions perfectly it is, by its very nature, opposed to ethics. "For me, the negative element, the element of violence in the state, in the hierarchy, appears even when the hierarchy functions perfectly, when everyone submits to universal ideas. There are cruelties which are terrible because they proceed from the necessity of the reasonable order. There are, if you like, the tears that a civil servant cannot see: the tears of the Other.'45¶ Vigilance against violence in the state is essential. Institutions need to be constantly checked by the ethical relationship with the Other. "In order for things to work and in order for things to develop an equilibrium, it is absolutely necessary to affirm the infinite responsibility of each, for each, before each . .. . As I see it, subjective protest is not received favorably on the pretext that its egoism is sacred, but because the 1 alone can perceive the 'secret tears' of the Other which are caused by the functioning-albeit reasonable-of the hierarchy."4'¶ The state must be constantly reminded of its inherent violence. Levinas finds just such a self-critical state in the modem liberal state. The liberal state "always asks itself whether its own justice really is justice. "17¶ What qualities does the liberal state possess that makes it self-critical? First, there is the freedom of the press, the freedom to criticize the government, to speak out against injustice. "You know the prophets of the bible, they come and say to the king that his method of dispensing justice is wrong. The prophet doesn't do this in a clandestine way: he comes before the king and he tells him. In the liberal state, it's the press, the poets, the writers who fulfill this role."48 ¶ Second, in the liberal state, the leader is not above the people, but is chosen from among the people. A ruler who is in an ethical relationship sees humanity through the Other's eyes. Against the Platonic formulation that the best ruler is the one who is best in control of himself, Levinas argues that the best ruler is the one who is in an ethical relationship with the Other. "The State, in accordance with its pure essence, is possible only if the divine word enters into it; the prince¶ is educated in this knowledge."9¶ However, for Levinas, the most important component of the liberal state is its call for a "permanent revolution."50 The Levinasian liberal state is always trying to improve itself, trying to be more just. It is "a rebellion that begins where the other society is satisfied to leave off, a rebellion against injustice that begins once order begins."5' Although no state can be purely ethical, the liberal state at least strives for ethics. Such a state is the desideratum if politics cannot be ethical. There is no politics for accomplishing the moral, but there are certainly some politics which are further from it or closer to it. For example, I've mentioned Stalinism to you. I've told you that justice is always a justice which desires a better justice. This is the way that I will characterize the liberal state. The liberal state is a state which holds justice as the absolutely desirable end and hence as a perfection. Concretely, the liberal state has always admitted ¶ alongside the written law-human rights as a parallel institution. It continues to preach that within its justice there are always improvements to be made in human rights. Human rights are the reminder that there is no justice yet. And consequently, I believe that it is absolutely obvious that the liberal state is more moral than the fascist state, and closer to the morally ideal state.32¶ The ethical and the political are not separated-politics is the ethical relationship between more than one Other. Infusing Levinasian ethics into politics will create a more ethical, less violent state. Simmons, associate prof social sciences ASU, 2003 William Paul Simmons, associate professor of social sciences at Arizona State University, 2003, “An-Archy and Justice: An Introduction to Emmanuel Levinas’s Political Thought” Therefore, Levinas distinguishes the ethical relationship with the Other from justice which involves three or more people.2° The an-archical relationship with the Other is the pre-linguistic world of the saying. Language is unnecessary to respond to the Other. The Third, however, demands an explanation. "In its frankness it [language] refuses the clandestinity of love, where it loses its frankness and meaning and turns into laughter or cooing. The third party looks at me in the eyes of the Other-.language is justice."2' In order to judge between Others, they must be co-present, or synchronous. Thus, the Third also opens up the world of knowledge and consciousness. "Here is the hour and birthplace of the question: a demand for justice! Here is the obligation to compare unique and incomparable others; here is the hour of knowledge and, then, of the objectivity beyond or on the hither side of the nudity of the face; here is the hour of consciousness and intentionality."22¶ Finally, the Third introduces the realm of politics. The ego's infinite respon-¶ sibility must be extended to all humanity, no matter how far off. Ethics must be universalized and institutionalized to affect the others. "To the extent that someone else's Face brings us in relation with a third party, My metaphysical relation to the Other is transformed into a We, and works toward a State, institutions and laws which form the source of universality."¶ Before delving into the relationship between ethics and politics, several implications of Levinas's move from the Other to the Third need to be addressed. First, does the ego still have an infinite responsibility for the Other? In Otherwise than Being, Levinas defines justice as "the limit of responsibility and the birth of the question?'24 However, in the same work, he also claims that "in no way is justice a degradation of obsession, a degeneration of the for-the-other, a diminution, a limitation of anarchic responsibility.us How can these conflicting statements be resolved? Either justice limits the responsibility for the Other or it does not. The contradiction is resolved by considering, once again, Levinas's theoretical emphasis on the separation between the saying and the said. Ethics is found in the an-archical realm of the saying, while justice is a part of the totalizing realm of the said. Ethics and justice exist in both relation and separation. Neither can be reduced to the other. Thus, justice cannot diminish the infinite responsibility for the Other the ego remains infinitely, asymmetrically, and concretely responsible for the Other. This responsibility always maintains its potency. However, the ego is also invariably transported by the Third into the realm of the said. The ego must weigh its obligations. It is not possible to respond infinitely to all Others. The original demand for an infinite responsibility remains, but it cannot be fulfilled. Ethics must be universalized, but in attempting to do so, the ego has already reneged on its responsibility for the Other. Thus, Levinas's peculiar formulation; justice is un-ethical and violent "Only justice can wipe it [ethical responsibility] away by bringing this giving- oneself to my neighbor under measure, or moderating it by thinking in relation to the third and the fourth, who are also my 'others,' but justice is already the first violence."¶ Responsibility towards the other is the basis for all ethical relations .¶ Peter Jowers Senior Lecturer in Politics at the University of the West of England. 2005 Trust, Risk, and Uncertainty. “Risk, Sensibility, Ethics and Justice in the Later Levinas” Pgs. 47-73¶¶ \ The psyche senses a 'call' from outside, stemming from the proximate expressivity of the Other. The psyche as incarnation senses another body in proximity; the Other as expressive subjectivity. She, neighbour, makes demands on me, or in Levinasian terms - derived and profoundly reordered from Heidegger -'calls' me, placing me under an injunction or command. The Other 'solicits", 'institutes', 'accuses' or 'elects' me to cite some of the terms Levinas uses in this connection. I am incarnate, I feel and, above all, am both an enjoying and suffering sensate creature who involuntarily responds to and for the Other who suffers and, at this very root or on this ground, can do no other but passively place myself at their service, in their 'hour of need'. There is no choice. I am not a slave. In this involuntary response to the Other, I found my human self in responsibility. Levinas repeatedly cites the phrase 'Yes, I am here' as the psyche's response to the Other prior to any cognition as the founding moment of sociality which is always laced within the said!¶ The psyche, as being-for-the-other, needs incarnation and proximity. The self involuntarily responds to the Other's vulnerability via sensibility, prior to any conscious sense of compassion, sympathy or empathy. I do not place myself consciously in another's 'shoes' by first imagining my way into their suffering. I respond affectively. The Other takes me hostage in the sense that I, as minimal sensate self, cannot bear them suffering. I involuntarily respond to suffering because pain has happened to me and their worse pain must be alleviated. My capacity for pain meets the vulnerability 1 being for the other. Such affective truth' underpins our capacity for compassion. Otherwise we would remain coldly distance, dispassionate and uninvolved in the late of the Other. Levinas writes:¶ It is through the condition of being hostage that there can be in the world, pity, compassion, pardon, proximity ... Being hostage is ... the condition for all solidarity. (OR. 117)¶ Taking responsibility for the outrages suffered by the Other 'is the source of all compassion' (OR: 116).¶ The psyche is the point at which the minimal sensate self and Other interlink to the point of substitution, and the sense of being taken hostage occurs. Responsibility is placed on us. It informs our consciousness. Its flickering traces haunt us as guilt, conscience, remorse, expiation) atonement. Is this capacity for guilt universal or merely linked to the sacrificial structures of Abrahamic lineage (Derrida, 1992; 199S: 108-15)? Levinas writes:¶ The animation, the very pneuma of the psyche, alterity in identity, is the identity of the body exposed to the other, becoming 'for the other', the possibility of giving. (0B: 69)¶ This pneuma, or breath, is literally and spiritually inspiration. It is a different type of 'breathing in', as involuntary as the air the the approach of the other gives the self ethical meaning, makes us human, takes us from the pure fatality and meaningless of a merely material universe where the conscious ego locked up in its self-absorption merely finds monotony, the horror of the monochrome materiality that Levinas always characterised as the 'there is' or 'it y lungs take in. Just as air facilitates life prior to any intentionality, so too a' and which always emerges from ontology and is assuaged by ethics. The Other in proximity as node brings out this new identity, but is one at the service of the other'. Strangely, the Other brings a certain type of contradictory stabilisation to the self always in danger of slipping back towards mere responsiveness to stimuli signaling either enjoyment or danger. responsibility. Response becomes Rejection of Racism Racism is the ultimate moral evil and must be rejected at all costs Albert Memmi, Essayist qualified to write about the colonizer and the colonized, 2000. RACISM, pg. 165. http://books.google.com/books?id=lP8kKUKmOwAC&printsec=frontcover#v=onepage&q&f=fals e accessed 7/20/12 Of course, this is debatable. There are those who think that if one is strong enough, the assault on and oppression of others is permissible. But no one is ever sure of remaining the strongest. One day, per-haps, the roles will be reversed. All unjust society contains within itself the seeds of its own death. It is probably smarter to treat others with respect so that they treat you with respect. "Recall," says the Bible, "that you were once a stranger in Egypt," which means both that you ought to respect the stranger because you were a stranger yourself and that you risk becoming one again someday. It is an ethical and a practical appeal—indeed, it is a contract, however implicit it might be. In short, the refusal of racism is the condition for all theoretical and practical morality. Because, in the end, the ethical choice commands the political choice, a just society must be a society accepted by all. If this contractual principle is not accepted, then only conflict, violence, and destruction will be our lot. If it is accepted, we can hope someday to live in peace. True, it is a wager, but the stakes are irresistible. Rejecting racism is a pre-requisite to founding a moral order. Utilitarian considerations are irrelevant when racism runs rampant. Albert Memmi, Essayist qualified to write about the colonizer and the colonized, 2000. RACISM, pg. 165. However, it remains true that one's moral conduct only emerges from a choice; one has to want it. It is a choice among other choices, and always debatable in its foundations and its consequences. Let us say, broadly speaking, that the choice to conduct one-self morally is the condition for the establishment of a human order, for which racism is the very negation. This is almost a redundancy. One cannot found a moral order, let alone a legislative order, on racism, because racism signifies the exclusion of the other, and his or her subjection to violence and domination. From an ethical point of view, if one can deploy a lit-tle religious language, racism is "the truly capital sin."22 It is not an accident that almost all of humani-ty's spiritual traditions counsel respect for the weak, for orphans, widows, or strangers. It is not just a question of theoretical morality and disinterested commandments. Such unanimity in the safeguarding of the other suggests the real utility of such sentiments. All things considered, we have an interest in banishing injustice, because injustice engenders violence and death. Of course, this is debatable. There are those who think that if one is strong enough, the assault on and oppression of others is permissible. But no one is ever sure of remaining the strongest. One day, per-haps, the roles will be reversed. All unjust society Human worth and morality cannot exist with racism. Albert Memmi, Essayist qualified to write about the colonizer and the colonized, 2000. RACISM, pg. 165. The struggle against racism will be long, difficult, without intermission, without remission, probably never achieved, yet for this very reason, it is a struggle to be undertaken without surcease and without concessions. One cannot be indulgent toward racism. One cannot even let the monster in the house, especially not in a mask. To give it merely a foothold means to augment the bestial part in us and in other people which is to diminish what is human. To accept the racist universe to the slightest degree is to endorse fear, injustice, and violence. It is to accept the persistence of the dark history in which we still largely live. It is to agree that the outsider will always be a possible victim (and which [person] man is not [themself] himself an outsider relative to someone else?).Racism illustrates in sum, the inevitable negativity of the condition of the dominated; that is it illuminates in a certain sense the entire human condition. The anti-racist struggle, difficult though it is, and always in question, is nevertheless one of the prologues to the ultimate passage from animality to humanity. In that sense, we cannot fail to rise to the racist challenge. We have a moral obligation to reject racism even if we do not succeed, the less racist choice is always the most moral choice. The Aff does not have to solve all racism to garner offense. Michael K. Brown et al, Department of Politics at the University of California. 2003 Whitewashing Race: the myth of a color-blind society, “Conclusion: Facing up to Race” pg. 229. http://www.jonescollegeprep.org/ourpages/auto/2007/11/26/1196104740124/Facing%20Up% 20To%20Race.pdf accessed 7/20/12 Even if Derrick Bell is correct in his prognosis that durable racial inequality is permanent, it must be challenged. It cannot be ignored. And while we celebrate diversity and applaud cultural pluralism, we do not think that changing identities will eliminate or minimize the harsh reali-ties of the durable racial inequality we have described in this book. Nor do we think that remedies for class inequality by themselves will over-come persistent racial stratification. In fact, if our analysis of U.S. social policies since the New Deal reveals anything, it is the folly of assuming class-specific policies will benefit all racial groups equally. Objectivism Humans are not entitled to rewards, only actions. LEONARD PEIKOFF 09, Professor of Philosophy at Hunter College, Long Island University, and New York University, Health Care is Not a Right, http://www.aynrand.org/site/DocServer/ARC_Health_Care_Is_Not_A_Right_2009.pdf?docID=2161, July 17, 2012 Now our only rights, the American viewpoint continues, are the rights to life, liberty, property, and the pursuit of happiness. That’s all. According to the Founding Fathers, we are not born with a right to a trip to Disneyland, or a meal at McDonald’s, or a kidney dialysis (nor with the 18th-century equivalent of these things). We have certain specific rights—and only these. Why only these? Observe that all legitimate rights have one thing in common: they are rights to action, not rewards from other people. The American rights impose no obligations on other people, merely the negative obligation to leave you alone. The system guarantees you the chance to work for what you want—not to be given it without effort by somebody else. The right to life, e.g., does not mean that your neighbors have to feed and clothe you; it means you have the right to earn your food and clothes yourself, if necessary by a hard struggle, and that no one can forcibly stop your you have the right to act, and to keep the results of your actions, the products you make, to keep them or to trade them with others, if you struggle for these things or steal them from you if and when you have achieved them. In other words: wish. But you have no right to the actions or products of others, except on terms to which they voluntarily agree. Egoism allows you to help people – It is just done out of self interest Michael J. Hurd, psychotherapist, life coach and author of Effective Therapy, 1999, “What's So Bad About Being Selfish?, Capitalism Magazine”, http://capmag.com/article.asp?ID=145 Selfishness means acting in one’s rational self-interest. Contrary to popular opinion, all healthy individuals are selfish. Choosing to pursue the career of your choice is selfish. Choosing to have children–or not to have children–is selfish. Insisting on freedom and individual rights, rather than living under a dictatorship, is selfish. Indeed, even ordinary behaviors such as breathing, eating and avoiding an oncoming car when crossing the street are selfish acts. Without selfishness, none of us would survive the day–much less a lifetime. Individual Autonomy is Paramount. David Kelley, Ph. D and Professor of Philosophy, 1993, Is There A Right to Health Care?, http://www.atlassociety.org/is_health_care_a_right_obamacare, July 17, 2012 The rights of liberty are paramount because individuals are ends in themselves. We are not instruments of society, or possessions of society. And if we are ends in ourselves, we have the right to be ends for ourselves: to hold our own lives and happiness as our highest values, not to be sacrificed for anything else. I think many people are afraid to assert their rights and interests as individuals, afraid to assert these rights and interests as moral absolutes, because they are afraid of being labeled selfish. So it is vital that we draw certain distinctions. What I am advocating is not selfishness in the conventional sense: the vain, selfcentered, grasping pursuit of pleasure, riches, prestige, or power. Genuine happiness results from a life of productive achievement, of stable relationships with friends and family, of peaceful exchange with others. The pursuit of our self-interest in this sense requires that we act in accordance with moral standards of rationality, responsibility, honesty, and fairness. If we understand the self and its interests in terms of these values, then I am happy to acknowledge that I am advocating selfishness. Citizens do not have a right to Healthcare; ergo the government is not obligated to guarantee it. John David Lewis, PhD, Visiting Associate Professor of Philosophy, Politics and Economics at Duke University, wrote in his Aug. 12, 2009 Huffington Post article "Health Care, Why Call It a 'Right'? http://healthcare.procon.org/view.answers.php?questionID=001602, July 17, 2012 "[T]he very idea that health care -- or any good provided by others -- is a 'right' is a contradiction. The rights enshrined in the Declaration of Independence were to life, liberty, and the pursuit of happiness. Each of these is a right to act, not a right to things... To reform our health care industry we should challenge the premises that invited government intervention in the first place. The moral premise is that medical care is a right. It is not. There was no 'right' to such care before doctors, hospitals, and pharmaceutical companies produced it. There is no 'right' to anything that others must produce, because no one may claim a 'right' to force others to provide it. Health care is a service, and we all depend upon thinking professionals for it. To place doctors under hamstringing bureaucratic control is to invite poor results." The Affordable Care Act is Coercive Peter Lindsay. June 2005. Polity Volume 37, Number 3. “Exposing the Invisible Hand: The Roots of Laissez-Faire's Hidden Influence.” Pages 299-300. 7/18/12. Economic liberalism regards market competition as superior not only because it is in most circumstances the most efficient method known but even more because it is the only method by which our activities can be adjusted to each other without coercive or arbitrary intervention of authority. Indeed, one of the main arguments in favor of competition is that it dispenses with the need for “conscious social control” and that it gives the individuals a chance to decide whether the prospects of a particular occupation are sufficient to compensate for the disadvantages and risks connected with it. This use of coercion is shown in various ways in the Affordable Care Act (ACA), by penalizing employers for not providing healthcare insurance so that employer provided healthcare is no longer “voluntary,” by penalizing individuals who do not obtain healthcare insurance, and by requiring the expansion by the states of the State Medicaid programs to cover a larger portion of the population.¶ Coercion is not new to the healthcare field. The federal government has long used its power of coercion to compel individuals and employers to pay the Medicare tax, and while Medicare Part B is voluntary, higher income individuals who select Part B are required to pay a higher premium than the vast majority of individuals participating in Part B. The Medicare and Medicaid programs, while “voluntary” for physicians but not for hospitals in New Jersey, sets the rates they pay. What is missing so far in the discussion of ACOs and in the Massachusetts debate, is a general obligation on the part of the beneficiaries as to their compliance with medical instructions, as well as their election to live a healthy lifestyle. The government has exercised some coercion in this area, for instance, with significantly higher taxes on cigarettes as well as the numerous bans on smoking in various places. Society’s experience with Prohibition has made it clear that that is not the approach to take again, in the area of cigarettes, or quite frankly, in any other area. It should be noted that we are seeing calls for the legalization of marijuana and the taxation of marijuana rather than continuation of the current prohibition against the use of marijuana. A similar approach is being taken in the area of alcohol with higher taxes on alcohol.¶ Whether or not this coercive tool, taxation or in the case of smoking, prohibition in certain areas, will be extended to other activities or circumstances, such as obesity, which result in additional healthcare costs is yet to be seen. Citizens do not have a right to Healthcare; ergo the government is not obligated to guarantee it. John David Lewis, PhD, Visiting Associate Professor of Philosophy, Politics and Economics at Duke University, wrote in his Aug. 12, 2009 Huffington Post article "Health Care, Why Call It a 'Right'? http://healthcare.procon.org/view.answers.php?questionID=001602, July 17, 2012 "[T]he very idea that health care -- or any good provided by others -- is a 'right' is a contradiction. The rights enshrined in the Declaration of Independence were to life, liberty, and the pursuit of happiness. Each of these is a right to act, not a right to things... To reform our health care industry we should challenge the premises that invited government intervention in the first place. The moral premise is that medical care is a right. It is not. There was no 'right' to such care before doctors, hospitals, and pharmaceutical companies produced it. There is no 'right' to anything that others must produce, because no one may claim a 'right' to force others to provide it. Health care is a service, and we all depend upon thinking professionals for it. To place doctors under hamstringing bureaucratic control is to invite poor results." Nozick A government’s role is only that of a minimalist state. Robert Nozick, Former Professor of Philosophy at Harvard University, 1974, Anarchy, State and Utopia, Preface, pg ix, http://books.google.com/books?id=hAi3CdjXlQsC&printsec=frontcover&dq=anarchy,+state+and+utopia& hl=en&src=bmrr&sa=X&ei=a8wFULCLLIWHrgG_9IneCA&ved=0CDcQ6AEwAA#v=onepage&q=anarc hy%2C%20state%20and%20utopia&f=false, Date accessed: 7/17/2012 Individuals have rights, and there are things no person or group may do to them (without violating their rights). So strong and far-reaching are these rights that they raise the question of what, if anything, the state and its officials may do. How much room do individual rights leave for the state? The nature of the state, its legitimate functions and its justifications, if any, is the central concern of this book; a wide and diverse variety of topics intertwine in the course of our investigation. Our main conclusions about the state are a minimal state, limited to the narrow functions of protection against force, theft, fraud, enforcement of contracts, and so on, is justified; that any more extensive state will violate persons’ rights no to be forced to do certain things, and is unjustified; and that the minimal state is inspiring as well as right. Two noteworthy implications are that the state may not use its coercive apparatus for the purpose of getting some citizens to aid others, or in order to prohibit activities to people for their own good or protection. Despite the fact that is only coercive routes toward these goals that are excluded, while voluntary ones that remain, many persons will reject our conclusions instantly, knowing they don’t want to believe anything so apparently callous toward the needs and sufferings of others. Dehum Bad Dehumanization is the root of all evil. Katheryn D. Katz, Professor of Law at Albany Law School, 1997, Albany Law Journal It is undeniable that throughout human history dominant and oppressive groups have committed unspeakable wrongs against those viewed as inferior. Once a person (or a people) has been characterized as sub-human, there appears to be no limit to the cruelty that was or will be visited upon him. For example, in almost all wars, hatred towards the enemy was inspired to justify the killing and wounding by separating the enemy from the human race, by casting them as unworthy of human status. This same rationalization has supported: genocide, chattel slavery, racial segregation, economic exploitation, caste and class systems, coerced sterilization of social misfits and undesirables, unprincipled medical experimentation, the subjugation of women, and the social Darwinists' theory justifying indifference to the poverty and misery of others. have en Human Dignity Respecting Human Dignity Alison Barnes and Michael McChrystal Professors at Marquette University Law School JSTOR The Various Human Rights in Healthcare Human Rights , Vol. 25, No. 4 (Fall 1998), pp. 12-14 http://www.jstor.org/stable/27880119 July 18 2012 One of the most important issues at stake in the contemporary health care debate is the claim that the intrinsic value of persons requires a right to a basic level of health care. The argument is simple but powerful. Respect for the incalculably great value of each person creates a duty not only to refrain from destroying health a negative right but also a duty to take reasonable steps to preserve and restore health by ensuring access to basic health care. Failing to act on this duty, by allowing lives to be shortened or diminished in quality because of lack of access to basic health care, expresses callous disregard for the dignity of human life. DA Econ DA Shell A. Uniqueness United States Hiring On The Rise Dennis Cauchon USA today reporter and Correspondent. 6/27/12 Hiring rebounds for state, local governments. http://www.usatoday.com/news/nation/story/2012-06-27/state-local-hiring/55868796/1 Access date- 7/21/12 a rare bright sign for the job market, state and local governments are hiring at the fastest pace in four years.States, cities, counties and school districts hired 828,000 workers in the first four months of the year, up 20% from a year earlier, and the most since 2008, according to a USA TODAY analysis of the government's Job Openings and Labor Turnover Survey. The number of job openings at state and local governments also hit a four-year high. This lift in government hiring shows how state budget problems have eased in recent months as tax collections have improved. Total revenue is flat because extra federal aid is drying up. But tax money revenue generally is spent on workers, especially at the local level, while federal aid is often dedicated to outside vendors, such as health care providers in the Medicaid program and highway contractors. "We're hiring as many as we can," says Tucson police recruitment officer Liz Skeenes. "In the last few years, we haven't hired as many officers as we needed because of financial problems. Now we're going back to full force, and we're happy about that." Tucson — like other state and local governments — still expects to live with a smaller workforce than the 2008 peak. What's happening: Governments are filling jobs that had been left vacant to save money. State and local governments employ 19.6 million, down 3% from the peak. The recent jump in hiring is an early signal that job growth may be on the way, at least in government. It In takes six months to a year for a boost in hiring to create a bigger workforce. Reason for the lag: Government workers are quitting for new jobs and retiring in greater numbers. Voluntary departures are another sign of an improving job market. When times are tough, workers hang on to their jobs. The "don't-leave" phenomenon — not more hiring — is what caused government payrolls to swell to record numbers during the recession while private employment collapsed. Private companies are hiring a little more, too, up 4% in the first four months of 2012 from a year earlier. That's a weak rebound when measured against hiring declines every year from 2006 to 2009, including a 20% hiring drop in 2009. The hiring turnaround has been most dramatic, starting last August, in the nation's state and local governments. These 89,500 cities, park districts, sewer systems and other governments are a backbone of working-class America, employing millions of low-profile truck drivers, health care aides and motor vehicle clerks with decent pay, good benefits and exceptional job security B. Link: Economy Doing Well According to Fed Reuters News 7/18/12 U.S. Economy Expanding Modestly, Fed Says. http://www.foxbusiness.com/economy/2012/07/18/us-economy-expanding-modestly-fed-says/ Access date- 7/20/12 and hiring grew at a tepid pace in much of the country, the Federal Reserve said on Wednesday. "Reports from most of the twelve Federal Reserve districts indicated that overall economic activity continued to expand at a modest to moderate pace in June and early July," the central bank said in its latest "Beige Book" summary of Economic growth in the United States cooled in June and early July national activity. The Fed's previous Beige Book assessment of the economy, released on June 6, had painted growth in slightly more upbeat light, describing it as "moderate." The Beige Book, prepared this time by the Atlanta Fed based on information collected through July 9, has market interest because it is based on anecdotal reports from business people from coast to coast and will be "Employment levels improved at a tepid pace for most districts," the Fed said. In its previous assessment, the Fed said hiring was steady or increasing moderately. Many economists now think economic growth slowed in the second quarter, perhaps sharply. The used by Fed policymakers at their next meeting on July 31-Aug. 1. pace of hiring in the United States slowed sharply during the period, as did growth in factory output. Retail sales have also flagged in The Fed found businesses were still optimistic about the economy, but some companies "Overall, districts reported that their contacts remained cautiously optimistic," the Fed said. The central bank said inflation pressures appeared to be modest, in part because of modest wage pressures. recent months. were holding back on hiring because they were unsure about the future of government policies on taxes and spending. Pharmaceutical DA 1NC Link UHC Free health care kills pharmacy innovation through a loss of profit. Brown ‘04, Staff Writer, 04 (John Brown, Staff Writer, The Daily Beacon, Senior in Political Science, 9/28/04, http://www.freerepublic.com/focus/fnews/1229567/posts,dw) Let's pretend, for a moment, that the left gets its way, and the United States adopts a universal health care system. This profit motive will effectively be removed. Doctors will then be government employees, and, as such, have far less accountability, as well as lower pay. Could we still expect the best and brightest to strive to be doctors? Probably not. More than likely, they will pursue other careers where they can make more money. Some love to bemoan the fact that the United States is one of the few industrialized nations without a government health care system. Yet they rarely note that the United States produces disproportional amounts of the new, life-saving drugs, largely because of the profits drug companies make. Will we continue to produce these drugs if we abolish the profit motive? Not likely. Chances are, they will not be produced at all, and more people will needlessly suffer and die as a result. When we examine countries that have embraced socialized medicine, we find long waiting lists, expansive red tape and little concern for the individual. Do you really want to be told which doctor to go to? Do you want to wait years to have necessary medical procedures performed? If so, then socialized medicine is for you. But if you believe in individual rights, competent healthcare and sound economic policies, we must get the government out of the doctor's office. Free health care kills because it creates long waiting lists for life saving surgeries Schwartz ‘08 (Brian Schwartz, Staff analyst for ppn,““Universal” Health Care Kills”,2008 March 25,http://www.patientpowernow.org/2008/03/universal-health-care-kills/) ¶ What good is having medical insurance if you cannot get medical care? Peddlers of “universal health care” — from Hillary, Obama, to Colorado congressional candidate Jared Polis — don’t get this.¶ ¶ “Universal health care” is false advertising for politically-controlled medicine, with government as the “single-payer” monopolistic insurer. But having coverage does not guarantee getting medical care.¶ ¶ Since patients prepay through taxes, medical care appears “free.” Hence, they have strong incentive to over-consume and providers need not compete on price. To contain costs, governments restrict your access to life-saving treatment. In countries with such “universal coverage,” patients die waiting for treatment.¶ ¶ The Canadian Medical Association Journal reports that in one year, 71 Ontario patients died while waiting for coronary bypass surgery and over one hundred more became “medically unfit for surgery.” The Canadian Broadcasting Corporation reports that “109 people had a heart attack or suffered heart failure while on the waiting list. Fifty of those patients died.”¶ ¶ This week the Globe and Mail reported that¶ ¶ Inside Sylvia de Vries lurked an enormous tumour and fluid totalling 18 kilograms. But not even that massive weight gain and a diagnosis of ovarian cancer could assure her timely treatment in Canada.¶ ¶ She sought treatment in the United States, as do Canadians in need of intensive care and emergency cardiac care.¶ ¶ “Physicians across Canada are in an advanced stage of burnout due to work conditions” which “causes them to retire early…or simply leave,” a former Canadian Medical Association president told the New York Times. He “attributed much of the problem to technological shortages and the powerlessness doctors feel when patients complain about long waits for treatment.”¶ ¶ “Access to a waiting list is not access to healthcare ,” wrote Canadian Chief Justice McLachlin when striking down legislation banning private insurance in 2005. Last year a New York Times headline read: “As Canada’s SlowMotion Public Health System Falters, Private Medical Care Is Surging.”¶ ¶ And England? The BBC reports that “up to 500 heart patients die each year while they wait for potentially life-saving surgery.” The Times reports that a British woman “will be denied free National Health Service treatment for breast cancer if she seeks to improve her chances by paying privately for an additional drug.” A Daily Telegraph headline reads: “Sufferers pull out teeth due to lack of dentists.” “Doctors are calling for NHS treatment to be withheld from patients who are too old or who lead unhealthy lives,” reports another article.¶ ¶ Consider politically-controlled health care in America: Medicaid and Medicare. Doctors are five times more likely to refuse seeing new Medicaid patients than privately-insured patients. Increasing reimbursement rates won’t help much; more than two-thirds of doctors reported being overwhelmed by Medicaid’s billing requirements, paperwork, and delays in payment.¶ ¶ ABC News reports that “Medicare rules bar cancer drugs for patients,” including the privately-insured. As the population ages and Medicare costs continue to increase, Medicare may further restrict patients and doctors.¶ ¶ “Single payer” advocates cite international comparisons of life expectancy to support their cause. But life expectancy depends on factors unrelated to healthcare, such as unintentional injury and homicide. Health economist Robert Ohsfeldt found that when accounting for these two factors, life expectancy in America is comparable to that of Canada and England.¶ ¶ What really matters is your chance of surviving a serious illness. The American Cancer Society reported that “U.S. patients have better survival rates than European patients for most types of cancer.” Last August the Telegraph reported that the “UK cancer survival rate lowest in Europe,” and that it’s highest in the United States.¶ ¶ So if politically-controlled medicine isn’t the solution, what is?¶ ¶ Not a Massachusetts-style “individual mandate,” which forces everyone to buy insurance. This is essentially single-payer in disguise. Insurance regulations severely limit competition, so insurance companies are effectively government contractors for politically-defined insurance.¶ ¶ The Boston Globe reports that to contain costs, Massachusetts authorities will “probably cut payments to doctors and hospitals” and “reduce choices for patients.” Sound familiar?¶ ¶ Instead, we must recognize how government policies have crippled free markets.¶ ¶ Because the tax code deeply discounts employer-provided insurance, you’re essentially stuck with your employer’s non-portable plans. Hence, insurance companies can afford to be stingy and deny you care; they know that losing you as a customer requires that you change jobs. With government as “single-payer” it’s even worse: to change insurance providers you must move to a different state or country.¶ ¶ Our current system also encourages thoughtless overconsumption and skyrocketing costs. The tax code punishes paying for medical care out-of-pocket and rewards buying insurance. So “insurance” has become prepaid medicine, and patients over-consume like business travelers dining on their company’s expense account.¶ ¶ Further, legislation mandating minimum benefits makes insurance unaffordable for many. Consider: Colorado law compels widowed wives to pay higher premiums for prostate screening, maternity, and marital therapy. Sponsors of Colorado House Bill 08-1327 recognize this injustice. Just as businesses incorporated in other states can operate in Colorado, Coloradans should be able to buy affordable policies from insurance companies that meet less damaging regulations of another state.¶ ¶ So remember, the uninsured aren’t the problem, but a symptom of political meddling in our most important personal choices. Heg Heg Stable Hegemony High – General US primacy unmatched Flourney, Co-Founder Center for a New American Security, and Davidson, Professor Public Policy George Mason, ’12 (Michele- Former US Undersecretary of Defense for Policy and JanineFormer US Deputy Assistant Secretary of Defense for Plans, July/August, “Obama’s New Global Posture” Foreign Affairs, Vol 91 Issue 4, EbscoHost) TOUGH ECONOMIC times have often been met in the United States by calls for a more modest foreign policy. But despite the global economic downturn, in today's interdependent world, retrenchment would be misguided. The United States' ability to lead the international community is still invaluable and unmatched. Its economy is still by far the largest, most developed, and most dynamic in the world. Its military remains much more capable than any other. The United States' network of alliances and partnerships ensures that the country rarely has to act alone. And its soft power reflects the sustained appeal of American values. The United States should not reduce its overseas engagement when it is in a position to actively shape the global environment to secure its interests. US primacy unmatched – military and relative economic clout Dorfman, Editor of Ethics and International Affairs, 5-22-’12 (Zach, “What We Talk About When We Talk About Isolationism” Dissent Magazine, http://www.carnegiecouncil.org/resources/articles_papers_reports/0127.html) The rise of China notwithstanding, the United States remains the world's sole superpower. Its military (and to a considerable extent, political) hegemony extends not just over North America or even the Western hemisphere, but also Europe, large swaths of Asia, and Africa. Its interests are global; nothing is outside its potential sphere of influence. There are an estimated 660 to 900 American military bases in roughly 40 countries worldwide, although figures on the matter are notoriously difficult to ascertain, largely because of subterfuge on the part of the military. According to official data there are active-duty U.S. military personnel in 75 percent of the world's states. The United States checks Russian power in Europe and Chinese power in South Korea and Japan and Iranian power in Iraq, Afghanistan, and Turkey. In order to maintain a frigid peace between Israel and Egypt, the American government hands the former $2.7 148 countries, or over billion in military aid every year, and the latter $1.3 billion. It also gives Pakistan more than $400 million dollars in military aid annually (not including counterinsurgency operations, which would drive the total far higher), Jordan roughly $200 million, and Colombia over $55 million. U.S. long-term military commitments are also manifold. It is one of the five permanent members of the UN Security Council, the only institution legally permitted to sanction the use of force to combat "threats to international peace and security." In 1949, the United States helped found NATO, the first peacetime military alliance extending beyond North and South America in U.S. history, which now has 28 member states. The United States also has a trilateral defense treaty with Australia and New Zealand, and bilateral mutual defense treaties with Japan, Taiwan, the Philippines, and South Korea. It is this Madeleine Albright to sort of reach that led call the United States the sole "indispensable power" on the world stage. Hegemony High – Military US military primacy unmatched Kagan, Foreign Policy at Carnegie, 1-17-’12 (Robert, “Not Fade Away: Against the Myth of American Decline” http://www.brookings.edu/opinions/2012/0117_us_power_kagan.aspx) Military capacity matters, too, as early nineteenth-century China learned and Chinese leaders know today. As Yan Xuetong recently noted, “military strength underpins hegemony.” Here the United States remains unmatched. It is far and away the most powerful nation the world has ever known, and there has been no decline in America’s relative military capacity—at least not yet. Americans currently spend less than $600 billion a year on defense, more than the rest of the other great powers combined. (This figure does not include the deployment in Iraq, which is ending, or the combat forces in Afghanistan, which are likely to diminish steadily over the next couple of years.) They do so, moreover, while consuming a little less than 4 percent of GDP annually—a higher percentage than the other great powers, but in historical terms lower than the 10 percent of GDP that the United States spent on defense in the mid-1950s and the 7 percent it spent in the late 1980s. The superior expenditures underestimate America’s actual superiority in military capability. American land and air forces are equipped with the most advanced weaponry, and are the most experienced in actual combat. They would defeat any competitor in a head-to-head battle. American naval power remains predominant in every region of the world. Rising powers don’t reduce US power projection capabilities Kagan, Foreign Policy at Carnegie, 1-17-’12 (Robert, “Not Fade Away: Against the Myth of American Decline” http://www.brookings.edu/opinions/2012/0117_us_power_kagan.aspx) But what about the “rise of the rest”—the increasing economic clout of nations like China, India, Brazil, and Turkey? Doesn’t that cut into American power and influence? The answer is, it depends. The fact that other nations in the world are enjoying periods of high growth does not mean that America’s position as the predominant power is declining, or even that “the rest” are catching up in terms of overall power and influence. Brazil’s share of global GDP was a little over 2 percent in 1990 and remains a little over 2 percent today. Turkey’s share was under 1 percent in 1990 and is still under 1 percent today. People, and especially businesspeople, are naturally excited about these emerging markets, but just because a nation is an attractive investment opportunity does not mean it is a rising great power. Wealth matters in international politics, but there is no simple correlation between economic growth and international influence. It is not clear that a richer India today wields greater influence on the global stage than a poorer India did in the 1950s under Nehru, when it was the leader of the Non-Aligned Movement, or that Turkey, for all the independence and flash of Prime Minister Recep Tayyip Erdoğan, really wields more influence than it did a decade ago. As for the effect of these growing economies on the position of the United States, it all depends on who is doing the growing. The problem for the British Empire at the beginning of the twentieth century was not its substantial decline relative to the United States, a generally friendly power whose interests did not fundamentally conflict with Britain’s. Even in the Western hemisphere, British trade increased as it ceded dominance to the United States. The problem was Britain’s decline relative to Germany, which aimed for supremacy on the European continent, and sought to compete with Britain on the high seas, and in both respects posed a threat to Britain’s core security. In the case of the United States, the dramatic and rapid rise of the German and Japanese economies during the Cold War reduced American primacy in the world much more than the more recent “rise of the rest.” America’s share of the world’s GDP, nearly 50 percent after World War II, fell to roughly 25 percent by the early 1970s, where it has remained ever since. But that “rise of the rest” did not weaken the United States. If anything, it strengthened it. Germany and Japan were and are close democratic allies, key pillars of the American world order. The growth of their economies actually shifted the balance irretrievably against the Soviet bloc and helped bring about its demise. When gauging the impact of the growing economies of other countries today, one has to make the same kinds of Does the growth of the Brazilian economy, or of the Indian economy, diminish American global power? Both nations are friendly, and India is increasingly a strategic partner of the United States. If America’s future competitor in the world is likely to be China, then a richer and more powerful India will be an asset, not a liability, to the United States. Overall, the fact that Brazil, India, Turkey, and South Africa are calculations. enjoying a period of economic growth—which may or may not last indefinitely—is either irrelevant to America’s strategic position or of benefit to it. At present, only the growth of China’s economy can be said to have implications for American power in the future, and only insofar as the Chinese translate enough of their growing economic strength into military strength. No Challengers US primacy unmatched – no nation is a real threat Friedman, Defense Fellow at Cato, and Logan, Director of Foreign Policy at Cato, ’12 (Benjamin- PhD Candidate PolSci at MIT, and Justin; Spring, “Why the U.S. Military Budget is ‘Foolish and Sustainable’” Orbis) The dirty little secret of U.S. defense politics is that the United States is safe—probably the most secure great power in modern history. Weak neighbors, vast ocean barriers, nuclear weapons and the wealth to build up forces make almost nonexistent the threats that militaries traditionally existed to thwart. Americans cannot seriously fear territorial conquest, civil war, annexation of peripheral territories, or blockade. What passes for enemies here are small potatoes compared with what worried most states at most times. 4 Most U.S. military interventions affect U.S. security at best marginally. We have hopes and sometimes interests in the places where we send troops, but no matter how much we repeat it to honor the troops, it is untrue that they are fighting to protect our freedom. No challengers to US primacy Blumenthal, Fellow at AEI, 3-22-’11 (Dan, “Why it’s Still a Unipolar Era” http://www.american.com/archive/2011/march/why-its-still-a-unipolar-era/article_print) Sometimes it takes a crisis to dispense with intellectual fads. The world’s response to Libya has made clear that currently fashionable arguments about the “rise of the Rest” and the world’s new “nonpolarity” are simply untrue. Charles Krauthammer was wrong about one thing in his description of the “unipolar moment” at the end of the Cold War: We are not living in a unipolar moment, we are witnessing a unipolar era. Why? Because the “rest”—China and India—are unable and unwilling to lead. The current fashion in foreign policy argumentation is to explain that America is in decline, particularly relative to Asia. The new declinists usually line up an impressive array of statistics that tell a story of India and China’s high rates of economic growth, military spending, energy consumption, and so on. The new declinists have a point—the raw numbers are impressive. But power is about much more than raw numbers. It is the most elusive concept in politics. It usually cannot be measured accurately until it is used. The recent example of the West’s decision to use force against Libyan leader Muammar Qaddafi is a case in point. The United States was supposed to be entering a new era of constraints, perhaps even decline, bound by a severe financial debt crisis and an unwillingness to properly fund our military forces. Moreover, we have a president as ambivalent about exercising American power as we have seen in a generation. President Obama did all he could to dither and procrastinate while Qaddafi Obama understood two things: the world order Washington needs demands that Qaddafi be stopped, and only America could stop him. Obama’s rhetoric about the United States not butchered his people. After all the hand-wringing, President being in the lead against Qaddafi is just that: rhetoric meant to further a bizarre public relations agenda (Does anyone in the Middle East really believe we are not leading the effort in Libya? What purpose does pretending to take a back seat serve except to satisfy the Western left-wing intelligentsia?). Until President Obama directed his staff to secure a UN Security Council resolution and commit the U.S. military to stopping Qaddafi, the “international community” was paralyzed by inaction. The United Kingdom and France admirably made a strong moral and strategic case for intervention, but could not act without U.S. leadership. What about China and India, countries that the new declinists identify as the future guardians of world order? The best that could be said is they did not get in the way. Of the two, India is the greater disappointment. Washington applauds the potential of the relationship based in part on India’s impressive democracy. India’s democratic character is supposed to bind it with the West to keep strong the liberal order that characterizes international politics. But with its decision to abstain from a resolution that would end Qaddafi’s treachery, Delhi demonstrated that shared values do not extend to preventing a dictator from butchering his people. Delhi’s multicultural democracy is impressive and there may be great potential for cooperation with Washington. But until Delhi sheds the vestiges of its self-indulgent and sentimental non-alignment policies, the chances that it will exercise power on the world stage in a positive and meaningful way remain low. For the foreseeable future, Washington and Delhi are fated to cooperate on a narrow set of issues much closer to India’s borders. Then the idea that China will rise to world leadership presupposes that Beijing has some vision of world order beyond protecting its material interests. But so long as a committee of nine dictators rule China, this idea is a fantasy. In a country there is China. Who knows why China decided to abstain rather than threaten a veto. Perhaps Beijing did not want another confrontation with Washington. But in which citizens are blocked from Internet searches of the words “Arab” and “democracy,” it is farfetched to expect any help in felling extremists. Even closer to China’s borders, in Afghanistan—a country whose failure can have serious deleterious consequences for China—Beijing has not seen fit to shed a drop of its blood or spend a yuan of its treasure. Instead, while NATO and the United States fight and die for stability in South Asia, China has been building a military that can challenge the United States in the Pacific. The net effect is a less peaceful world. Instead of contributing to the stability from which it benefits, China has made it more costly for the United States to provide the public while measures of power such as gross domestic product growth, numbers of scientists and engineers, and shares of decision-making in international bodies may tell us something about a country’s power, they do not tell us enough. These crude calculations of power miss the intangibles of leadership: political culture, values, and purpose. The West has a set of ideas about how the world should run. This vision includes the sometime necessity of goods upon which Asia’s prosperity depends. In turns out that deposing a brutal dictator. India and China do not see a purpose for international politics beyond advancing narrow self-interest. The fact that India is democratic means that it may one day decide to join the ideological West and exercise international power for grander purposes. China is run by dictators. Until that changes, the most Washington should expect is for Beijing not to make problems worse. Forget about China becoming a responsible stakeholder in the international system. Our diplomacy should encourage China to become a less irresponsible power. What the new declinists miss is while the United States is not as far ahead of India and China in material strength as it used to be, the vision of world order it shares with its NATO allies provides it with a moral strength and legitimacy impossible to measure. The new declinists point to the ways in which the “Rest” can make life marginally more difficult for the West. But while the “Rest” may carp from the sidelines and gum up the works on international trade and financial agreements, when it comes to upholding international order, Delhi and Beijing will take a pass. We may be tiring of it, but the Unipolar Era is alive and well. that An economic crisis would collapse heg Joshua Zoffer July 7, 2012 3:11 PM Harvard International Review The United States’ Undoing? http://hir.harvard.edu/crafting-the-city/future-of-dollar-hegemony?page=0,2 Page 3 Access Date: 7/18/12 Despite the dollar’s long history as the international reserve currency, the past few years have seen a growing number of calls for the end of dollar hegemony. Countries as diverse as France, Russia, and China have decried the dollar’s monopoly in foreign exchange markets, while in 2009 reports of a shift away from dollar-based oil trading surfaced in the Middle East. Reported plans to move away from the dollar reflected international frustration at a system fueling the United States’ “exorbitant privilege,” as the French have called it, one that rests its stability on the financial conditions of a country mired in debt and facing a financial meltdown. The implications of a true end to dollar hegemony, a shift away from the dollar as a reserve currency and pricing standard for oil transactions, could be catastrophic for the United States. In the worst case scenario, a drastic drop in demand for dollar-denominated assets would cause the interest rates on Treasury Securities to skyrocket, sending ripples through the US economy as the value of the dollar plummets. What is certain, however, is that whatever decrease in demand for US debt occurs will constrain the federal government’s ability to spend and the ability of the United States to defend itself. The United States has built its foreign policy around its vast military capability; a sudden budgetary shock and drop in military spending would leave the United States vulnerable as it scrambles to regroup in a new security environment. The ability of the United States to respond to threats across the globe would be diminished, and enemies would be incentivized to take aggressive action to take advantage of this new weakness. In particular, a rapidly militarizing China might be emboldened by its partial decoupling from US economic fortunes to adopt a bolder stance in the South China Sea, threatening US allies and heightening tensions with the United States. While war with China is all but off the table in the status quo, an international system devoid of both US military might and Chinese dependence on US debt as a place to park excess liquidity might lead to the conflict feared on both sides of the Pacific Heg Good-Stability US hegemony key to maintain world stability and check back major wars Thayer 2007 (Bradley. A is an Associate Professor in the Dept. of Defense and Strategic Studies at Missouri State University, “American Empire: A Debate”, Taylor and Francis Group, 2007, MJB) Stability – Peace, like good health, is not often noticed, but certainly is missed when absent. Throughout history, peace and stability have been a major benefit of empires. In fact, pax Romana in Latin means the Roman peace, or the stability brought about by the Roman Empire. Rome’s power was so overwhelming that no one could challenge it successfully for hundreds of years. The result was stability within the Roman Empire. Where Rome conquered, peace, law, order, education, a common language, and much else followed. That was true of the British Empire (pax Britannica) too. So it is with the United States today. Peace and stability are major benefits of the American Empire. The fact that America is so powerful actually reduces the likelihood of major war. Scholars of international politics have found that the presence of a dominant state in international politics actually reduces the likelihood of war because weaker states, including even great powers, know that it is unlikely that they could challenge the dominant state and win. They may resort to other mechanisms or tactics to challenge the dominant country, but are unlikely to do so directly. This means that there will be no wars between great powers. At least, not until a challenger (certainly China) thinks it can overthrow the dominant state (the United States). But there will be intense security competition—both China and the United States will watch each other closely, with their intelligence communities increasingly focused on each other, their diplomats striving to ensure that countries around the world do not align with the other, and their militaries seeing the other as their principal threat. his is not unusual in international politics but, in fact, is its “normal” condition. Americans may not pay much attention to it until a crisis occurs. But right now states are competing with one another. This is because international politics does not sleep; it never takes a rest. US hegemony prevents war. Robert Kagan 2007: (Senior Associate at the Carnegie Endowment for International Peace [Robert “End of Dreams, Return of History” Policy Review (http://www.hoover.org/publications/policyreview/8552512.html#n10)] ) Finally, there is the United States itself. … as it maintains its position as the predominant global power, it is also engaged in hegemonic competitions in these regions with China in East and Central Asia, with Iran in the Middle East and Central Asia, and with Russia…. American predominance prevents these rivalries from intensifying — its regional as well as its global predominance. Were the United States to diminish its influence in the regions where it is currently the strongest power, the other nations would settle disputes as great and lesser powers have done in the past: sometimes through diplomacy and accommodation but often through confrontation and wars of varying scope, intensity, and destructiveness. One novel aspect of such a multipolar world is that most of these powers would possess nuclear weapons. That could make wars between them less likely, or it could simply make them more catastrophic…. Such conflicts may be unavoidable no matter what policies the United States pursues. But they are more likely to erupt if the United States weakens or withdraws from its positions of regional dominance. This is especially true in East Asia, where most nations agree that a reliable American power has a stabilizing and pacific effect on the region. That is certainly the view of most of China’s neighbors. But even China, which seeks gradually to supplant the United States as the dominant power in the region, faces the dilemma that an American withdrawal could unleash an ambitious, independent, nationalist Japan…... It is also optimistic to imagine that a retrenchment of the American position in the Middle East and the assumption of a more passive, “offshore” role would lead to greater stability there…. The subtraction of American power from any region would not end conflict but would simply change the equation. In the Middle East, competition for influence among powers both inside and outside the region has raged for at least two centuries. The rise of Islamic fundamentalism doesn’t change this. It only adds a new and more threatening dimension to the competition , which neither a sudden end to the conflict between Israel and the Palestinians nor an immediate American withdrawal from Iraq would change. The alternative to American predominance in the region is not balance and peace. It is further competition. The region and the states within it remain relatively weak. A diminution of American influence would not be followed by a diminution of other external influences. .American withdrawal from Iraq will not return things to “normal” or to a new kind of stability in the region. It will produce a new instability, one likely to draw the United States back in again. The alternative to American regional predominance in the Middle East and elsewhere is not a new regional stability. In an era of burgeoning nationalism, the future is likely to be one of intensified competition among nations and nationalist movements. Difficult as it may be to extend American predominance into the future, no one should imagine that a reduction of American power or a retraction of American influence and global involvement will provide an easier path. UHC Protects us UHC insures common defense David R. Remer, July 24, 2009, poliwatch.org, Constitution And Universal Health Insurance pg 1http://poliwatch.org/2009/07/24/constitution_and_univeral_heal.php July 19, 2012 That leaves one ideal outlined in the Constitution's preamble left, the common defense; or, what we often refer to today as national security. A healthy population is clearly in the national security interest. It doesn't take any intellectual prowess to ask if our nation would be safer with an unfit and unhealthy population and grasp the correct answer? The Swine Flu threatens Americans this Fall along with the seasonal flu variants of different strains. Would it be in the national security interest of this nation to have a quarter or third of its population culled over the course of several years by a multi-strained flu pandemic? Of course not. The economic consequences alone would undermine our national defense and security. Heg Bad Uniqueness Hegemony Low – Military Tech US no longer has dominant lead in military technology Krepinevich, President of Center for Strategic and Budgetary Assessments, ’11 (Andrew, September/October, “Get Ready for the Democratization of Destruction” Foreign Policy, http://www.foreignpolicy.com/articles/2011/08/15/get_ready_for_the_democratization_of_de struction) As Niels Bohr famously observed, "Prediction is very difficult, especially if it's about the future." But we need not be caught entirely unaware by future events. The rapid pace of technological progression, as well as its ongoing diffusion, offer clues as to some of the likely next big things in warfare. Indeed, important military shifts have already been set in motion that will be difficult if not impossible to reverse. Sadly, these developments, combined with others in the economic, geopolitical, and demographic realms, seem likely to make the world a less stable and more dangerous place. Consider, to start, the U.S. military's loss of its near monopoly in precision-guided munitions warfare, which it has enjoyed since the Gulf War two decades ago. Today China is fielding precision-guided ballistic and cruise missiles, as well as other "smart" munitions, in ever greater numbers. They can be used to threaten the few major U.S. bases remaining in the Western Pacific and, increasingly, to target American warships. Like Beijing, Iran is buying into the precision-guided weapons revolution, but at the low end, producing a poor man's version of China's capabilities, to include anti-ship cruise missiles and smart anti-ship mines. As these trends play out we could find that by the beginning of the next decade, major parts of the Western Pacific, as well as the Persian Gulf, become no-go zones for the U.S. military: areas where the risks of operating are prohibitively high. Even nonstate groups are getting into the game. During its war with Israel in 2006, Hezbollah fired more than 4,000 relatively inaccurate RAMM projectiles -- rockets, artillery, mortars, and missiles -- into Israel, leading to the evacuation of at least 300,000 Israelis from their homes and causing significant disruption to that country's economy. Out of these thousands of munitions, only a few drones and anti-ship cruise missiles were guided. But as the proliferation of guided munitions -- G-RAMM weapons -- continues, irregular warfare will be transformed to the point that the roadside bomb threats that the United States has spent tens of billions of dollars defending against in Iraq and Afghanistan may seem trivial by comparison. The spread of nuclear weapons to the developing world is equally alarming. If Iran becomes a nuclear power, the pressure on the leading Arab states as well as Turkey to follow suit is likely to prove irresistible. With ballistic-missile flight times between states in the region measured in singledigit minutes, the stability of the global economy's energy core would be exceedingly fragile. But the greatest danger of a catastrophic attack on the U.S. homeland will likely come not from nuclear-armed missiles, but from cyberattacks conducted at the speed of light. The United States, which has an advanced civilian cyberinfrastructure but prohibits its military from defending it, will prove a highly attractive target, particularly given that the processes for attributing attacks to their perpetrators are neither swift nor foolproof. Foreign powers may already have prepositioned "logic bombs" -- computer code inserted surreptitiously to trigger a future malicious effect -- in the U.S. power grid, potentially enabling them to trigger a prolonged and massive future blackout. As in the cyber realm, the very advances in biotechnology that appear to offer such promise for improving the human condition have the potential to inflict incalculable suffering. For example, "designer" pathogens targeting specific human subgroups or designed to overcome conventional antibiotics and antiviral countermeasures now appear increasingly plausible, giving scientists a power once thought to be the province of science fiction. As in the cyber realm, such advances will rapidly increase the potential destructive power of small groups, a phenomenon that might be characterized as the "democratization of destruction." International stability is also increasingly at risk owing to structural weaknesses in the global economic system. Commercial man-made satellites, for instance, offer little, if any, protection against the growing threat of anti-satellite systems, whether ground-based lasers or directascent kinetic-kill vehicles. The Internet was similarly constructed with a benign environment in mind, and the progression toward potential sources of single-point system failure, in the forms of both common software and data repositories like the "cloud," cannot be discounted. Then there is the undersea economic infrastructure, primarily located on the world's continental shelves. It provides a substantial portion of the world's oil and natural gas, while also hosting a web of cables connecting the global fiber-optic grid. The value of the capital assets on the U.S. continental shelves alone runs into the trillions of dollars. These assets -- wellheads, pumping stations, cables, floating platforms -- are effectively undefended. As challenges to the global order increase in scale and shift in form, the means for addressing them are actually declining. The age of austerity is upon us, and it seems likely if not certain that the U.S. military will confront these growing challenges with relatively diminished resources. The Pentagon's budget is scheduled for $400 billion or more in cuts over the next decade. Europe certainly cannot be counted on to pick up the slack. Nor is it clear whether rising great powers such as Brazil and India will try to fill the void. With technology advancing so rapidly, might the United States attempt to preserve its military dominance, and international stability, by developing new sources of military advantage? Recently, there have been dramatic innovations in directed energy -- lasers and particle beams -that could enable major advances in key mission areas. But there are indications that competitors, China in particular, are keeping pace and may even enjoy an advantage. The United States has the lead in robotics -- for now. While many are aware of the Predator drones used in the war against radical Islamist groups, robots are also appearing in the form of undersea craft and terrestrial mechanical "mules" used to move equipment. But the Pentagon will need to prove better than its rivals at exploiting advances in artificial intelligence to enhance the performance of its unmanned systems. The U.S. military will also need to make its robot crafts stealthier, reduce their vulnerability to more sophisticated rivals than the Taliban, and make their data links more robust in order to fend off efforts to disable them. The bottom line is that the United States and its allies risk losing their military edge, and new threats to global security are arising faster than they can counter them. Think the current world order is fragile? In the words of the great Al Jolson, "You ain't seen nothin' yet." Unsustainable – General Decline now—rising challengers and erosion in political, military and economic cred Layne ’12 Christopher Layne, Robert M. Gates Chair in Intelligence and National Security at the George Bush School of Government and Public Service at Texas A&M University, noted neorealist, “This Time It’s Real: The End of Unipolarity and the Pax Americana,” International Studies Quarterly (2012) 56, 203-213 Some twenty years after the Cold War’s end, it now is evident that both the 1980s declinists and the unipolar pessimists were right after all. The Unipolar Era has ended and the Unipolar Exit has begun. The Great Recession has underscored the reality of US decline, and only ‘‘denialists’’ can now bury their heads in the sand and maintain otherwise. To be sure, the Great Recession itself is not the cause either of American decline or the shift in global power, both of which are the culmination of decades-long processes driven by the big, impersonal forces of history. However, it is fair to say the Great Recession has both accelerated the causal forces driving these trends and magnified their impact. There are two drivers of American decline, one external and one domestic. The external driver of US decline is the emergence of new great powers in world politics and the unprecedented shift in the center of global economic power from the EuroAtlantic area to Asia. In this respect, the relative decline of the United States and the end of unipolarity are linked inextricably: the rise of new great powers—especially China—is in itself the most tangible evidence of the erosion of the United States’ power. China’s rise signals unipolarity’s end. Domestically, the driver of change is the relative—and in some ways absolute—decline in America’s economic power, the looming fiscal crisis confronting the United States, and increasing doubts about the dollar’s long-term hold on reserve currency status. Unipolarity’s demise marks the end of era of the post-World War II Pax Americana. When World War II ended, the United States, by virtue of its overwhelming military and economic supremacy, was incontestably the most powerful actor in the international system. Indeed, 1945 was the United States’ first unipolar moment. The United States used its commanding, hegemonic position to construct the postwar international order—the Pax Americana— which endured for more than six decades. During the Cold War, the Pax Americana reflected the fact that outside the Soviet sphere, the United States was the preponderant power in the three regions of the world it cared most about: Western Europe, East Asia, and the Persian Gulf. The Pax Americana rested on the foundational pillars of US military dominance and economic leadership and was buttressed by two supporting pillars: America’s ideological appeal (‘‘soft power’’) and the framework of international institutions that the United States built after 1945. Following the Cold War’s end, the United States used its second unipolar moment to consolidate the Pax Americana by expanding both its geopolitical and ideological ambitions. In the Great Recession’s aftermath, however, the economic foundation of the Pax Americana has crumbled, and its ideational and institutional pillars have been weakened. Although the United States remains preeminent militarily, the rise of new great powers like China, coupled with US fiscal and economic constraints, means that over the next decade or two the United States’ military dominance will be challenged. The decline of American power means the end of US dominance in world politics and a transition to a new constellation of world power. Without the ‘‘hard’’ power (military and economic) upon which it was built, the Pax Americana is doomed to wither in the early twenty-first century. Indeed, because of China’s great-power emergence, and the United States’ own domestic economic weaknesses, it already is withering. Unsustainable – Economics Structural economic weaknesses make heg collapse inevitable Layne ’12 Christopher Layne, Robert M. Gates Chair in Intelligence and National Security at the George Bush School of Government and Public Service at Texas A&M University, noted neorealist, “This Time It’s Real: The End of Unipolarity and the Pax Americana,” International Studies Quarterly (2012) 56, 203-213 Contrary to the way their argument was portrayed by many of their critics, the 1980s declinists did not claim either that the United States already had declined steeply, or that it soon would undergo a rapid, catastrophic decline. Rather, they pointed to domestic and economic drivers that were in play and which, over time, would cause American economic power to decline relatively and produce a shift in global distribution of power. The declinists contended that the United States was afflicted by a slow—’’termite’’—decline caused by fundamental structural weaknesses in the American economy.7 Kennedy himself was explicitly looking ahead to the effects this termite decline would have on United States’ world role in the early twenty-first century. As he wrote, ‘‘The task facing American statesman over the next decades. .. is to recognize that broad trends are under way, and that there is a need to ‘manage’ affairs so that the relative erosion of the United States’ position takes place slowly and smoothly, and is not accelerated by policies which bring merely short-term advantage but longer-term disadvantage’’ (Kennedy 1987:534; my emphasis). When one goes back and re-reads what the 1980s declinists pinpointed as the drivers of American decline, their analyses look farsighted because the same drivers of economic decline are at the center of debate today: too much consumption and not enough savings; persistent trade and current account deficits; chronic federal budget deficits and a mounting national debt; and de-industrialization. Over time, 1980s declinists said, the United States’ goals of geopolitical dominance and economic prosperity would collide. Today, their warnings seem eerily prescient. Robert Gilpin’s 1987 description of America’s economic and grand strategic plight could just as easily describe the United States after the Great Recession: With a decreased rate of economic growth and a low rate of national savings, the United States was living and defending commitments far beyond its means. In order to bring its commitments and power back into balance once again, the United States would one day have to cut back further on its overseas commitments, reduce the American standard of living, or decrease domestic productive investment even more than it already had. In the meantime, American hegemony was threatened by a potentially devastating fiscal crisis. (Gilpin 1987:347–348) In the Great Recession’s wake— doubly so since it is far from clear that either the United States or global economies are out of the woods—the United States now is facing the dilemmas that Gilpin and the other declinists warned about. Impact Unipolarity undermines cooperation over issues like terrorism Gvosdev 7-6-‘12 ( Nikolas Gvosdev, former editor of the National Interest, and a frequent foreign policy commentator in both the print and broadcast media. He is currently on the faculty of the U.S. Naval War College. “The Realist Prism: U.S. Power and Its Discontents” http://www.worldpoliticsreview.com/articles/12133/the-realist-prism-u-s-power-and-itsdiscontents) There are two simultaneous and contradictory trends occurring right now in the international system. The first is the diffusion of power, as reflected by the displacement of the old Group of Seven, which at its founding in the 1970s comprised the bulk of the world’s productive capacity, by the Group of 20, where there is no longer one dominant power capable of driving the global agenda. The second is the reality that the United States still far outstrips any other one state or group of states in terms of capabilities, ranging from the power of its currency to its ability to project military force to any corner of the globe. The result has been a growing “trust deficit” between the United States and several of the rising and resurgent powers, such as Russia and China, which in turn has had an impact on the latter states’ willingness to work with Washington to address major international challenges, such as in Syria and Iran. The recent jeremiads about American decline notwithstanding, the United States still holds the bulk of the world’s political, economic and military power. As a result, other countries remain focused on finding ways to limit how Washington deploys that power. In a recent monograph on arms control, Paul Saunders of the Center for the National Interest notes how “the asymmetries between America’s global capabilities and ambitions and Russia’s more limited options and aims” produce continued uneasiness in Moscow, something that was quite evident to me during the recent sessions of the Dartmouth Dialogue on U.S.-Russia relations, held in Valdai, Russia. These concerns are shared by other rising powers, including China, who seek reassurances and formal treaty limitations that would constrain America’s ability to use its power in the international system. Whether arguing against U.S. plans for theater ballistic missile defense, seeking a binding international agreement on cybercapabilities or pushing for a very limited and stringent definition of the conditions under which the “right to protect” can be invoked, these governments, cognizant of their own weaknesses and capabilities deficits, are expressing their concern over their vulnerability. This sense of exposure is heightened by what appears to them to be the unpredictable way in which the U.S. exercises its power. In other words, the question they all must consider is, what will “set Washington off”? How and why the U.S. intervened in Libya when Washington routinely ignores humanitarian crises elsewhere raises the unpleasant notion that the United States does not operate according to any fixed set of criteria. Governments in Moscow and Beijing are left to wonder whether, given the right set of circumstances, the United States would push for regime change in Russia or China, too. Hence the growing trend of these powers seeking to limit the exercise of U.S. power whenever possible. These fears also limit their enthusiasm for wanting to help Washington solve some of the current intractable issues it faces. None of the world’s great powers want Iran, for instance, to pursue a nuclear “breakout” and become an atomic-weapons state. But, as Russian interlocutors have sometimes privately indicated, they see no rush in solving this problem either. Assuming that the United States might be inclined to turn its attentions to thwarting some of Russia’s geopolitical objectives once the problem of Iran’s nuclear program is settled, what incentive does Moscow have to help get the Iran portfolio quickly off America’s agenda?9 Considered in this light, the course that Russia and China and other rising powers have adopted makes sense: some sanctions on Tehran, notably for its sins of omission and nondisclosure, but otherwise not bringing their full force to bear on Iran to help force a settlement. Washington, for its part, is unwilling to give the types of commitments that the rising powers want to reassure them of U.S. intentions. In a dangerous and unpredictable world, the United States does not want to foreclose on its options or voluntarily sign away any tool that might become acutely necessary. Missile defense is a good example. With the continuing spread of both missile and nuclear technology around the world, who can say with any certainty whether the current status quo will endure? Within a few years, a whole host of unsavory regimes, not to mention even less accountable nonstate actors, might have access to dangerous technologies that could threaten the American homeland. America’s position is that it seeks limited but effective defenses against such threats and that the established nuclear powers need to trust that whatever capabilities Washington deploys are not designed to upset the pre-existing global strategic balances. At best, the United States is willing to accept only unilateral and, if necessary, easily reversible limits on its capabilities, rather than locking in such barriers in terms of longer-term and more-binding compacts. The United States also sees no reason to voluntarily limit the exercise of its own power and to trust that other countries will “do the right thing” to help protect America’s own security. The continuing leakage of sensitive technologies from countries such as Russia -- sometimes in defiance of government efforts to stop such export, sometimes with officials turning a blind eye to the trafficking -- raises questions in Washington as to whether other powers would really exert themselves to take action to stop threats aimed at America. As the 2011 raid that killed Osama bin Laden showed, Washington is perfectly willing to ignore international rules to “get the job done.” Whether it concerns utilizing drones or deploying sophisticated cybertools to cripple an opponent’s infrastructure or research programs, the United States is not going to forego any of the tools it has in its arsenal that could neutralize emerging threats. Washington’s first preference will always be to work through international institutions, as demonstrated by its approach to both Iran and Syria. In its efforts to bring pressure to bear on both Tehran and Damascus, the United States has worked through the United Nations Security Council -- where both Moscow and Beijing have a veto and emerging powers such as India, Brazil and South Africa often have a vote -- and taken part in international conferences, such as the P5+1 negotiations with Iran and the recent conclave in Geneva that produced the agreement for a possible transition of power in Syria. But if these efforts fail, the United States will find a way to act, even over the objections of Moscow or Beijing. If that happens, however, finding a way to assuage the insecurities of the rising powers will become an absolute necessity. Right now, despite some opposition to U.S. policies, there is no sustained anti-American bloc in the world interested in consistently and uniformly contesting Washington’s power around the world. U.S. policymakers must therefore focus on finding the right mix of incentives to keep such a bloc from emerging. Being more sensitive to how the U.S. exercises its power is an important first step. The United States’ Military and Economic Power Threatens Other Countries Ivo H. Daalder, U.S. Permanent Representative on the NATO Council, and James M. Lindsay, Senior Gice President, Director of Studies, and Maurice R. Greenberg Chair at the Council on Foreign Relations, Brookings Review, “The Globalization of Politics” 2003 pg 12-17 Which brings us to the issue of how to transform this unquestioned power into influence. Unless employed deftly, America's military and economic superiority can breed resentment, even among its friends. A growing perception that Washington cares only about its own interests and is willing to use its muscle to get its way has fueled a worrisome gap between U.S. and European attitudes. European elites increasingly criticize the United States as being morally, socially, and culturally retrograde--especially in its perceived embrace of the death penalty, predatory capitalism, and fast food and mass entertainment. Europe has also begun to exercise diplomatic muscle in international institutions and other arenas, seeking to create new international regimes designed to limit America's recourse to its hard power. Kritiks Geopolitics Using words such as “the” creates an “us”-“them” dichotomy, which is inherently aggressive Nigel Thrifter,Professor of Geography at the University of Bristol, 2000. Geopolitical Traditions: A Century of Geopolitical Thought, “The Little Things” pgs. 383-385. http://frenndw.files.wordpress.com/2011/03/geopolitical-traditions-a-century-of-geopoliticalthought-edited-by-klaus-dodds-and-david-atkinson_copy.pdf accessed 7/19/12 Let us finally come to one more arena: the arena of words. After all, here we¶ might be thought to have the clearest example of representation at work, the word.¶ Yet, what we do not get from critical geopolitics is a clear enough sense of ¶ words function to bring about geopolitical change and it is not possible to do so as long as geopolitical forces continue to be framed as ‘big’ and ‘commanding’ (with¶ all the masculine overtones). Some of the most potent geopolitical forces are, I¶ suspect, lurking in the ‘little’ ‘details’ of people’s lives, what is ‘“carried” in the¶ specific variabilities of their activities’ (Shotter and Billig 1998:23), in the context¶ of utterances. And these variabilities have immediate consequences. Thus,¶ As Bakhtin notes , and as is confirmed by the work in conversational¶ analysis, ‘we sensitively catch the smallest shift in intonation, the slightest¶ interruption of voices in anything of importance to us in another person’s¶ practical every day discourse. All those verbal sideward glances ,¶ reservations, loopholes, hints, thrusts do not slip past our ear, are not¶ foreign to our own lips’ (Bakhtin 1984:201). And we in turn show our¶ stance to what they do or say also in fleeting bodily reactions , facial¶ expressions, sounds of approval or disapproval, etc. Indeed, even in the¶ continuously responsive unfolding of non-linguistic activities between¶ ourselves and others—in a dance, in a handshake, or even a mere chance¶ collision on the street—we are actively aware of whether the other’s¶ motives are, so to speak, ‘in tune’ or ‘at odds’ with ours. And in our¶ sense of their attunement or lack of it, we can sense their attitude to us as¶ intimate or distant, friendly or hostile, deferential or arrogant, and so on.¶ (Shotter and Billig 1998:23)¶ Thus, very effective work has been done in disciplines like anthropology and¶ discursive psychology (Billig 1995, 1997) which attempts to provide a sense of how¶ national identity and an accompanying geopolitical stance are inscribed through the¶ smallest of details. Thus, for example, national identity is not accomplished in grand¶ displays which incite the citizen to wave the flag in a fit of patriotic fervou r.¶ Instead, it goes on in more mundane citations: it is done unobtrusively on the margins of conscious awareness by little¶ words such as ‘the’ and ‘we’. Each day we read or hear phrases such as¶ ‘the prime minister’, ‘the nation’, or the ‘weather’. The definite article¶ assumes deictically the national borders. It points to the homeland: but¶ while we, the readers or listeners, understand the pointing, we do not¶ follow it with our consciousness—it is a ‘seen but unnoticed’ feature of¶ our everyday discourse.¶ 6¶ (Shotter and Billig 1998:20)¶ Such work goes some way towards understanding the deep, often unconscious¶ aggressions which lurk behind so much geopolitical ‘reasoning’, which through small details build a sense of ‘us’ as not like ‘them’, and from which political¶ programmes then flow as infractions are identified and made legible.¶ 7¶ In these few brief comments, I hoped to have outlined a parallel agenda for¶ critical geopolitics, one still based on discourse, but on discourse understood in a¶ broader way, and one which is less taken in by representation and more attuned to¶ actual practices In turn , such an agenda leads us away from interpretation of¶ hyperbolic written and drawn rhetorics (which, I suspect, are often read by only a¶ few and taken in by even fewer) towards the (I hesitate to say ‘real’) work of¶ discourse, the constant hum of practices and their attendant which geopower ferments and sometimes boils over.l territorializations within¶ Geopolitical borders breed racism and must be rejected Mustafa Dikec, PhD candidate in the Department of Urban Planning at the University of California, 2002. Pera Peras Poros: Longings for Spaces of Hospitality, “Openings: On not being Home” pgs. 243-244. http://tcs.sagepub.com/content/19/1-2/227.full.pdf+html accessed 7/19/12 California’s Proposition 187 was an attempt to build ‘safe homes’ for Californians, not for all of them of course. The political abuse of the image of¶ home as a sheltered and safe place drew upon an ‘exclusionary, territorializing, xenophobic, premodern and patriarchal cult of home’ (Antonopoulos,¶ 1994: 57). It was an elaborate fixing of boundaries, making California a safe¶ home for its ‘legal’ residents based on the exclusionary politics of home.¶ Boundaries, evidently, not only evoke the idea of hospitality, but of hostility and racism as well.¶ 12¶ It is important to remember, however, that it is not only the situation¶ of the guest but also the host that needs to be reconsidered since, in the¶ case of immigration, for example, it is ‘both receiving populations and immigrants [that] . . . risk mutual transformation, [that] . . . engage and attenuate their home-yearning for each other’s sakes and for the sake of their¶ political life together’ (Honig, 1999: 203). The point, therefore, is about¶ openings, about ‘keeping open the question of who “the people” (the demos)¶ is’, since the question of democracy ‘always arises at the limit of the demos¶ . . . wherein native, subject, citizen, or people receives its designation as¶ such from the way the human encounter with the stranger and the strange¶ is assumed’ (Dillon, 1999: 120 and 96). There is a need to reconsider the¶ boundary, not only as a separator but as a connector as well, where hospitality comes into play pointing beyond the boundaries. There is a need,¶ perhaps, to reflect on what the title words, in Greek, of this text suggest:¶ Pera – peras – poros: the other side/beyond – limit – passage; ‘beyond the¶ limits that interdict passage’ (Baptist, 1999: 102). There is a need, more¶ importantly, if a cosmopolitan approach is to be assumed, to think about¶ hospitality ‘that would be more than cosmopolitical, that would go beyond¶ strictly cosmopolitical conditions’, that would go beyond the interests, authority, and legislation of the state (Derrida, 1999a: 43).¶ To conclude, there is no way, I would argue, to escape the advent of¶ the stranger, to avoid questions and questionings that tremble, if not stir,¶ the socio-political order that once appeared, perhaps, as a safe home. Nor¶ is there a way to avoid the production of others. What is more important,¶ instead of reflecting on the ways by which no other would be produced, isto be able to resist processes that produce and reproduce others; processes¶ that stabilize themselves, that close spaces, and that derive their sustainability from the very process of othering itself. Again, what is more important, rather than reflecting on the ways by to be able to provide for the social, cultural, institutional,¶ ethical and political spaces where we could learn to engage with and learn¶ from each other, while being able to constitute our subjectivities free from¶ subordination, in democratic ways. The point, which to avoid the ‘disturbance’¶ of the stranger, is then, is to open spaces,¶ spaces where recognition as well as contestation and conflict can take place.¶ Furthermore, the point is not merely to open spaces; more importantly, it is¶ to keep them open. Hospitality is aimed at such a concern. Single Payer Good Universal Health Care improves the quality of life. Kathy Lavidge, Yale school of management, April 2008, yale.edeu Does universal healthcare make everyone's life better? Pg.1 http://qn.som.yale.edu/content/does-universal-healthcaremake-everyones-life-better July 20, 2012 I have lived in England, which has universal healthcare, for 14 years, and I have become a firm believer in the benefits universal access to healthcare brings to all -- even those who do not need or intend to use it. In the UK, healthcare is a universal right: You will be treated the same way whether you are working for a corporation or are a selfemployed dance teacher; whether you are retired, or have just been made redundant. In England, if you need healthcare, you get it - at no cost. There are no forms to fill out and no insurance claims to file or fight over. If the ambulance is called, no one is going to ask to see your health insurance card before they put you in the vehicle, nor will they detour away from the closest hospital to find the one that takes “charity” cases.¶ In a nutshell, the primary benefit of universal healthcare is that it improves the quality of life for everyone. ¶ • No one in England remains in a job they absolutely hate because they are afraid of losing healthcare insurance for themselves or a family member. • No one stays in a job because they have a “pre-existing” condition and know they will never be covered again. • No one has to worry about having to mortgage their house to pay the hospital, doctor, or pharmacy while they are waiting for repayment from the insurance company, which may never come. • No one has to worry because they have a significant illness and their insurance company has told them they have reached the maximum payout under their policy. • No one has to become frantic when an uninsured relative gets into an accident, and assets saved for a well-planned retirement are put at risk in order to assure care for the injured individual. • No one has to fear a true accident occurring on their property and finding out that the lawyers plan to file a big lawsuit because the injured party does not have health insurance. • No one worries that the last six months of their life will deplete their family’s savings, forcing them to choose whether or not to pay for treatments. • No one worries that parents too young to qualify for Medicare will become a financial burden if they become ill. • No one has to decide that that lump can wait to be checked or that blood in their stool is not really “too serious” -- only to have it truly become too serious. • No one is frantic when a child is born with a serious, but treatable, defect because there is no insurance to cover the hospitals and doctors. Single Payer Good-Economy Abortion is paid for from individuals pocket Dana Cody, Et. Al, Attorney at Law, President and Executive Director of the Life Legal Defense Foundation, February 14, 2012, Life Legal Defense Foundation, U.S. Supreme Court Brief Highlights Unconstitutionality of Obamacare, http://www.lldf.org, Access Date: July 19th 2012. Tuesday, February 14, 2012: Today, Life Legal Defense Foundation and four other pro-life law firms filed a friend of the court brief in the United States Supreme Court challenging the constitutionality of the Patient Protection and Affordable Care Act (ACT) on Free Exercise and First Amendment grounds. The brief, written by attorneys with the Bioethics Defense Fund, was filed on behalf of several religious and pro-life medical associations, such as the Christian Medical and Dental Association and Physicians for Life. Some of the primary arguments in today’s filing with the Supreme Court are as follow: The ACT contains a hidden “Abortion Premium Mandate” that compels enrollees in certain health plans to pay a separate abortion premium from their own pocket, while denying enrollees the ability to decline abortion coverage based on moral objection. The ACT and its individual mandate violate the Free Exercise Clause by imposing this“Abortion Premium Mandate” without regard to religious objection. Our nation has a long and deeply-rooted history of respecting and protecting the conscience rights of individuals to not be forced into the practice or funding of elective abortions. Our founders’ protection of individual liberty, including religious liberty, is directly undermined by the ACT’s transgression of the constitutional limits on congressional power. “This ACT and President Obama want citizens to have their choices impermissibly limited by being forced to choose between their conscience and a health insurance plan that requires an abortion premium,” said Cody. “How could Congress allow for this ACT to make pro-life individuals pay for a pro-abortion agenda?” Arguments on the constitutionality of the Act will be heard at the Supreme Court in March.