Stefan Bauschard Offensive PKOs release 1 Background .................................................................................................................................................................... 3 Offensive Operations .................................................................................................................................................. 4 Chapter VII ................................................................................................................................................................. 6 Mali Offensive ............................................................................................................................................................ 7 Peacekeepers Taking Sides ......................................................................................................................................... 8 Pro -- Offensive PKOs Good .......................................................................................................................................... 9 Offensive PKOs Stop Genocide ................................................................................................................................10 Force Negotiations.....................................................................................................................................................12 Necessary to Stop Rebels ..........................................................................................................................................15 Genocide/Failed States Impacts .................................................................................................................................16 Human Rights Impacts ..............................................................................................................................................21 A2: Offensive PKO Undermine Impartiality .............................................................................................................24 A2: Kritiks of Peacekeeping ......................................................................................................................................26 A2: Offensive Peacekeeping Fails .............................................................................................................................27 A2: No UN Authority for Offensive PKOs ...............................................................................................................28 No Turns are Unique .................................................................................................................................................29 Pro – Positive Peace Answers .......................................................................................................................................33 No Impact – Direct Violence OW’s ..........................................................................................................................34 A2: Structural Violence = Root Cause ......................................................................................................................35 A2: Structural Violence = Root Cause ......................................................................................................................37 Perm Solves – Generally ...........................................................................................................................................40 Perm Solves – Generally ...........................................................................................................................................42 Perm Solves – Exclusive Focus Bad .........................................................................................................................43 Perm Solves – Links ..................................................................................................................................................44 Perm Solves – A2: Co-optation .................................................................................................................................45 Perm Solves – Militarism ..........................................................................................................................................46 We’re a Prereq to the Alt ...........................................................................................................................................47 Pro – Imperialism Answers ...........................................................................................................................................48 Con -- Offensive Peacekeeping Bad ..............................................................................................................................54 Militarism/Colonialism..............................................................................................................................................55 Don’t Solve Violence ................................................................................................................................................56 Undermine Impartiality .............................................................................................................................................57 Impartiality Impact ....................................................................................................................................................59 Undermines Humanitarianism ...................................................................................................................................61 Nationalism ...............................................................................................................................................................62 Inconsistent With Peacekeeping Values ....................................................................................................................63 Undermines Support for Peacekeeping .....................................................................................................................64 Snowball ....................................................................................................................................................................66 Alternatives ...............................................................................................................................................................67 Bad to Support Congo Government ..........................................................................................................................69 A2: Offensive PKOs Necessary to Stop Rebel Groups .............................................................................................70 A2: Necessary to Defeat Rebels ................................................................................................................................71 Con – Militarized Approaches Fail............................................................................................................................72 Con – Solvency Answers ...........................................................................................................................................76 Con – Right to Protect (R2P) Bad .................................................................................................................................77 Right to Protect Bad Link ..........................................................................................................................................78 Right to Protect Undermines American Leadership ..................................................................................................79 R2P Bad: Sovereignty ...............................................................................................................................................87 A2: “R2P Expands Sovereignty” ...............................................................................................................................91 A2: “R2P Doesn’t kill Sovereignty - it’s Preventive” ..............................................................................................92 A2: “Safeguards Protect Sovereignty” ......................................................................................................................93 A2: “N/U – Sovereignty is Down Now” ...................................................................................................................94 Sovereignty Impact ....................................................................................................................................................96 R2O Increase War – Moral Hazard (Syria/Iran) ........................................................................................................97 R2P Increases War – Moral Hazard ..........................................................................................................................98 Stefan Bauschard Offensive PKOs release 2 Moral Hazard: Secessionism ...................................................................................................................................100 Secession: A2: Alternative Causality ......................................................................................................................101 Secession Spills Over ..............................................................................................................................................102 R2P Fails: A2 Good.................................................................................................................................................104 R2P Bad: Bias .........................................................................................................................................................110 R2P = Genocide (Sudan/Syria)................................................................................................................................113 R2p Bad: Drone Strikes ...........................................................................................................................................115 R2P = Imperialism ...................................................................................................................................................117 R2P = imperialism: Africa .......................................................................................................................................118 R2P =Imperialism – Kills International Law ...........................................................................................................121 R22 Hypocritical .....................................................................................................................................................125 R2P = White Supremacy .........................................................................................................................................127 R2P = Syria Intervention .........................................................................................................................................129 Ditching R2P Solves................................................................................................................................................130 Syria Crisis Impact: Middle East War .....................................................................................................................132 Right to Protect Causes War Escalation ..................................................................................................................134 Right to Protect Triggers Nuclear Proliferation .......................................................................................................139 Right to Protect Destroys US-Brazil Relations........................................................................................................142 Con – Positive Peace Kritik .........................................................................................................................................146 *** Links *** ..........................................................................................................................................................147 Link – War...............................................................................................................................................................148 Link – War...............................................................................................................................................................149 Link – War...............................................................................................................................................................150 Link – Hegemony ....................................................................................................................................................151 ***Impacts*** ........................................................................................................................................................153 Impact – No Solvency – War ..................................................................................................................................154 Impact – No Solvency – Poverty .............................................................................................................................155 Impact – War ...........................................................................................................................................................156 Impact – War ...........................................................................................................................................................157 Impact – Structural Violence Outweighs .................................................................................................................158 Impact – Structural Violence Outweighs .................................................................................................................160 Impact – Sexism ......................................................................................................................................................161 Impact – Environment .............................................................................................................................................162 Impact – Environment .............................................................................................................................................163 Impact – Genocide ...................................................................................................................................................164 Impact – Morality OW’s Extinction ........................................................................................................................165 ***Alternative*** ...................................................................................................................................................166 Alternative – Discourse ...........................................................................................................................................167 Alternative – Reject .................................................................................................................................................168 Alternative – Reject .................................................................................................................................................170 Alternative – Small Actions ....................................................................................................................................171 Alternative – Solves Politicians/Elites .....................................................................................................................172 A2: Positive Peace – Vagueness ..............................................................................................................................174 A2: Aff Alone Doesn’t Solve ..................................................................................................................................175 A2: Aff Alone Doesn’t Solve ..................................................................................................................................176 A2: Positive Peace = Violence/Revolt .....................................................................................................................177 A2: Positive Peace = Authoritarianism....................................................................................................................178 Positive Peace Good – Solves Root Cause (1/2) .....................................................................................................179 Positive Peace Good – Solves Militarism ................................................................................................................181 Con – Imperialism Bad ................................................................................................................................................182 Racism .....................................................................................................................................................................183 Ethics .......................................................................................................................................................................185 Indigenous Rights ....................................................................................................................................................186 Terrorism .................................................................................................................................................................188 Stefan Bauschard Offensive PKOs release 3 Background Stefan Bauschard Offensive PKOs release 4 Offensive Operations Courtney Brooks, March 28, 2013, Explainer: UN Move to Give Peacekeepers First Ever Combat Mandate, http://www.rferl.org/content/un-peacekeepers-combatresolution/24941095.html DOA: 12-5-14 This resolution would grant peacekeepers their greatest authority to engage in combat in the history of the United Nations. Peacekeepers currently cannot open fire unless they are attacked. The newly empowered "intervention brigade" -part of the 20,000-troop mission in DRC -- would be authorized to "search and destroy," as an anonymous diplomat told Reuters. The draft resolution explicitly states that the force would be authorized on an "exceptional basis and without creating a precedent or any prejudice to the agreed principles of peacekeeping." UN Peacekeeping Operations: New Trends (Concept Note) 2014, https://www.pminewyork.org/pdf/Concept%20Note%20Russian.pdf One of the milestones for UN peacekeeping along this path was the adoption of UNSC Resolution 2098 in March 2013, which extended the mandate of the UN Stabilization Mission in the DRC and established an Intervention Brigade in its structure empowered to use preemptive force and conduct targeted offensive operations. A short time later, the UN Security Council adopted Resolution 2100 establishing the peacekeeping operation in Mali. The UN Security Council, taking into consideration specific threats in that country, authorized MINUSMA to use all necessary means to fulfill its mandate, including to deter threats and take active steps to prevent the return of armed elements to key population centers. One should also bear in mind earlier and quite common mandates, which envisage the use of "all necessary means/actions". In some cases peacekeepers used force at a larger scale - UNOCI's posture under UNSC Resolution 1933 is a relevant example. Brett D. Schaefer, is the Jay Kingham Fellow in International Regulatory Affairs in the Margaret Thatch, April 10, 2013, Center for Freedom, a division of the Kathryn and Shelby Cullom Davis Institute for International Studies, at The Heritage Foundation and editor of ConUNdrum: The Limits of the United Nations and the Search for Alternatives (Rowman & Littlefield Publishers, 2009), U.S. Should Oppose a Return to U.N. Peace Enforcement, http://www.heritage.org/research/reports/2013/04/us-should-oppose-return-to-unpeace-enforcement DOA: 12-6-14 Traditional peacekeeping, as acknowledged in Resolution 2098, involves several basic principles, “including consent of the parties, impartiality, and non-use of force, except in self-defence and defence of the mandate.” However, recent Security Council action evidences enthusiasm for more aggressive missions that harken back to the 1990s, authorizing missions in the gray area between Stefan Bauschard Offensive PKOs release 5 traditional missions and peace enforcement. MONUSCO. Resolution 2098 established an offensive U.N. combat force within the authorized troop ceiling of 19,815 to neutralize and disarm armed groups in the eastern DRC. The “intervention brigade” was deemed necessary after current MONUSCO peacekeepers—already possessed of the most aggressive mandate among U.N. missions—failed to fulfill their charge to prioritize “protection of civilians” and instead retreated in the face of attacks by a rebel group late last year. The DRC government has little authority over eastern Congo, which is infested with armed groups with political and economic motives. This mandate removes entirely the fig leaf of U.N. neutrality by establishing MONUSCO as an armed participant in the conflict required to confront armed adversaries directly and forcefully. MINUSMA. Resolution 2100 instructs 12,600 peacekeepers to use “all necessary means” to stabilize “key population centres and support for the reestablishment of State authority throughout the country” and to protect “civilians and United Nations personnel” in Mali.[5] The Malian government has minimal authority in northern Mali, and there is no peace agreement between the provisional government and rebel groups in northern Mali. Radical Islamists continue to conduct terrorist attacks periodically. The U.N. has acknowledged the volatile environment in Mali. The “use all necessary means” phrase in U.N. parlance encompasses the use of force and, combined with instructions to reestablish state authority and protect civilians in northern Mali, virtually assures that peacekeepers will need to act aggressively to meet their mandate and will be a target. Thankfully, the Security Council did not repeat the DRC error by authorizing an offensive peacekeeping force as part of MINUSMA. Instead, the resolution prudently authorizes the continued presence of an independent French force to “use all necessary means…to intervene in support of elements of MINUSMA when under imminent and serious threat.” Stefan Bauschard Offensive PKOs release 6 Chapter VII Most scholars say the UN has the authority to conduct these type of operations under its Chapter VII mandate/authority. Fiona Blyth, April 10, 2013, IPI Global Observatory, “Too Risk-Averse, UN Peacekeepers in the DRC Get New Mandate and More Challenges,” Fiona Blyth is a former military intelligence officer with the British Army who is a Research Assistant in the Africa program at the International Peace Institute, http://theglobalobservatory.org/2013/04/too-risk-averse-un-peacekeepers-in-the-drc-get-new-mandate-and-morechallenges/ DOA: 12-5-14 Interpreted by some as the UN’s first authorization for the use of offensive force, UN Security Council Resolution 2098 passed on March 29 and called for the deployment of an “intervention brigade” to the Democratic Republic of the Congo (DRC) that can use offensive combat operations to “neutralize and disarm” Congolese rebel groups, in particular the M23 rebels responsible for taking over Goma in the eastern DRC last year. Despite the declaration by the UN that this breaks new ground, the UN Stabilization Mission in the Congo (MONUSCO) is already authorized to conduct offensive operations under its Chapter VII mandate, as are all other missions operating under Chapter VII. The Rules of Engagement (ROE) in these missions authorize the use of force beyond self-defense. As MONUSCO, and its predecessor MONUC, already have this authorization, the Security Council and DPKO should instead analyze how and why the mission has failed on notable occasions to fulfill its priority of protecting civilians before prescribing the solution in the form of an intervention brigade. Stefan Bauschard Offensive PKOs release 7 Mali Offensive Mali mission also offensive Dr. Jeni Whalan, 2014, Partial Peace: The Politics of Taking Sides in UN Peacekeeping, Paper prepared for International Studies Association Annual Convention, Toronto, 26-29, https://www.academia.edu/6474185/Partial_Peace_The_Politics_of_Taking_Sides_in_UN_Peacekeeping DOA: 12-6-14 Lecturer in International Security and Development BA (UNSW), M.Phil (Oxon), D.Phil (Oxon) What’s in Blue, June 2014, Open Debate on New Trends in UN Peacekeeping, http://www.whatsinblue.org/2014/06/open-debate-on-new-trends-in-unpeacekeeping.php The enhanced focus on these issues was sparked largely by developments in the Democratic Republic of the Congo (DRC) and Mali. In quick succession, the Council adopted resolutions in March and April 2013 to address unraveling security situations in both these countries. Responding to the threat posed by the March 23 Movement (M23)—a source of instability and massive displacement of civilians in the DRC—the Council unanimously adopted resolution 2098 on 28 March 2013. The resolution established an intervention brigade based in Goma for an initial period of one year that consisted of three infantry battalions and auxiliary forces under the command of the UN Organization Stabilization Mission in the DRC (MONUSCO). Its key task, renewed in resolution 2147, is to carry out offensive operations to neutralise armed groups that threaten state authority and civilian security. Less than a month later, on 25 April 2013, the Council adopted resolution 2100, establishing the UN Multidimensional Integrated Stabilisation Mission in Mali (MINUSMA) and authorising French troops to operate parallel to MINUSMA. The mission is authorised to use all necessary measures to stabilise “the key population centres, especially in the north of Mali and, in this context, to deter threats and take active steps to prevent the return of armed elements to those areas” Stefan Bauschard Offensive PKOs release 8 Peacekeepers Taking Sides Congo mission is unique because the peacekeepers are taking sides in the conflict Dr. Jeni Whalan, 2014, Partial Peace: The Politics of Taking Sides in UN Peacekeeping, Paper prepared for International Studies Association Annual Convention, Toronto, 26-29, https://www.academia.edu/6474185/Partial_Peace_The_Politics_of_Taking_Sides_in_UN_Peacekeeping DOA: 12-6-14 Lecturer in International Security and Development BA (UNSW), M.Phil (Oxon), D.Phil (Oxon) In a number of its recent decisions, the UN Security Council has asked peacekeepers essentially to take sides in conflict-affected societies, including by authorizing an intervention brigade to conduct offensive operations in order to 'neutralize' rebel forces in the eastern Democratic Republic of Congo. This particular decision is notable not so much for giving peacekeepers authority to use force, which they have regularly received in the past, but because it makes them a party to the conflict. In addition to raising potentially profound implications under international humanitarian law, this decision also appears to transgress the long-standing principle of impartiality in UN peacekeeping Stefan Bauschard Offensive PKOs release Pro -- Offensive PKOs Good 9 Stefan Bauschard Offensive PKOs release 10 Offensive PKOs Stop Genocide Offensive peacekeeping necessary to protect civilians in the Congo from genocide. There is a moral obligation to support offensive peacekeeping The East African, October 11, 2014 UN force in Congo appears poised to strike FDLR rebels, http://www.theeastafrican.co.ke/news/UN-force-in-Congo-appears-poised DOA: 12-414 The United Nations Mission in the Democratic Republic of Congo (Monusco) appears to be on the verge of a military offensive to eliminate a Rwandan rebel group based in the east of the country. Monusco Commander Lt-Gen Carlos Alberto dos Santos Cruz told the UN Security Council last week that Congolese civilians can be effectively protected only through "proactive" operations against armed groups. He asserted that offensive action on the part of Monusco's combat brigade is consistent with international law despite risks of "collateral damage." "I am absolutely convinced that the best way to protect civilians is being proactive rather than reactive," Lt-Gen Santos Cruz declared. "Civilian protection is far more than text in a mandate it is a moral duty." Carrying out genocide The FDLR, which is accused of slaughtering and raping civilians in eastern DRC, consists largely of Hutu militia who fled Rwanda after carrying out the 1994 Genocide against the Tutsi. The Brazilian general's October 9 remarks followed an October 3 UN Security Council call for the "swift neutralisation" of the FDLR, the French acronym for the Democratic Force for the Liberation of Rwanda. Noting that no progress has recently been made in the surrender and demobilisation of FDLR fighters, the Security Council urged Monusco and the Congolese armed forces to "undertake military action" against leaders and members of the group who do not comply with UN demands. In a statement issued three months prior to the UN deadline for FDLR disarmament, the Security Council ruled out any political dialogue with the rebel group. READ: UN could attack FDLR ahead of target date The Council said it was assessing FDLR's compliance in concrete terms, including the number of fighters and leaders surrendering and weapons handed over. Rwanda has been at the forefront of demands by some UN member states that Monusco launch military action against the FDLR following an offensive last year that eliminated another rebel group known as M23. READ: Kigali wants military action to neutralise FDLR in Congo That was the first time in the UN's 70-year history that its military deployment had initiated combat as part of a peacekeeping mandate. A 2013 UNSC resolution established a 3,000-member Force Intervention Brigade (FIB) within Monusco. The United States has echoed Rwanda's insistence that the FDLR must be destroyed. Samantha Power, the US ambassador to the UN, last week praised Lt-Gen Santos Cruz's proactive approach. Offensive PKOs designed to protect civilians Courtney Brooks, September 6, 2013, Al Jazeera America, “UN Tests Combat Brigade in Democratic Republic of Congo,” http://america.aljazeera.com/articles/2013/9/5/un-tests-combat- Stefan Bauschard Offensive PKOs release brigadeindemocraticrepublicofcongo.html 11 DOA: 12-6-14 The Aug. 28 offensive has been brewing since March, when the U.N Security Council authorized what it calls an "intervention brigade" in the DRC. The 3,000-person unit is part of the more than 19,000 troops in DRC attempting to fulfill the U.N.'s "stabilization mission," but it has a significantly different purpose. According to Al Jazeera correspondent Malcolm Webb, the intervention brigade is better equipped than either the local rebel groups or the Congolese military, with tanks, armored personnel carriers, artillery and night vision goggles. The brigade is comprised of three infantry battalions, one artillery unit and one special forces and reconnaissance company, and is authorized to shoot first – unlike any peacekeeping mission before it. The brigade, which the Security Council stressed did not set a "precedent" for peacekeeping in general, was authorized to use all necessary means to protect civilians and "neutralize armed groups" – referring specifically to the March 23 Movement, or M23, a rebel force made up of Congolese army deserters which has acted as a spoiler in the region since forming in 2009. Stefan Bauschard Offensive PKOs release 12 Force Negotiations Action in the DRC forced negotiations Courtney Brooks, September 6, 2013, Al Jazeera America, “UN Tests Combat Brigade in Democratic Republic of Congo,” http://america.aljazeera.com/articles/2013/9/5/un-tests-combatbrigadeindemocraticrepublicofcongo.html DOA: 12-6-14 While the world's attention has been fixed on Syria over the past few weeks, the landscape of diplomacy quietly but radically evolved amid the dense green hills of the Democratic Republic of the Congo (DRC). A flock of attack helicopters descended there on Aug. 28, in a town north of Goma, in the eastern region of the beleaguered Central African nation. The aircraft were filled with armed United Nations peacekeepers, along with Congolese military forces. The first-ever U.N. peacekeeping force with an offensive combat mandate – tasked with "neutralizing" and disarming rebel forces in one of the world's most intractable conflicts – was in action. Within two days, the peacekeepers and army had forced rebel militias threatening Goma to withdraw from the front lines. On Thursday, a rebel group known as M23 agreed to resume peace talks with the Congolese government. Rebels were committing human rights violations Courtney Brooks, September 6, 2013, Al Jazeera America, “UN Tests Combat Brigade in Democratic Republic of Congo,” http://america.aljazeera.com/articles/2013/9/5/un-tests-combatbrigadeindemocraticrepublicofcongo.html DOA: 12-6-14 About 800,000 people have reportedly fled their homes in eastern DRC since the M23 captured Goma in November 2012. The U.N. Stabilization Mission in the DRC, known by its French initials, MONUSCO, was criticized for standing by as the city was overrun. U.N. officials later said the troops lacked the authority to combat the rebel advance. M23 withdrew under international pressure after briefly holding the city. Since mid-July, de facto truces between the army and rebels have been repeatedly broken as fighting erupted, with human rights atrocities accompanying the violence. In July, Human Rights Watch reported that M23 rebels had summarily executed at least 44 people and raped at least 61 women and girls since March. UN militarism has forced parties to return to the negotiating table East African, April 26, 2014, intervention missions Partiality dilemma: The new model of UN Unlike typical peacekeepers, the brigade was not only sanctioned to engage in combat but it was also equipped for war with tanks, night vision goggles, artillery and armoured personnel carriers. The new combat style has been praised for resolving longstanding security stalemates and protecting civilians in conflicts. As Jeffrey Laurenti, a UN expert at the Century Foundation argues, it was the frustration with Monusco's failure to protect civilians and create a conducive environment for lasting peace after being on the ground for nearly two decades that led to the authorisation of the interventionist brigade by the Security Council. There is every reason to rejoice at the success of new UN militarism. In its aftermath, the UN combative mission has forced the M23 rebels to return to the negotiation table and resume the previously stalled peace talks with the DRC government in Stefan Bauschard Offensive PKOs release 13 Kampala. Predictably, within the UN corridors of power, interventionism is the new norm. Speaking in Goma on September 2 2013, Mary Robinson, Special Envoy of the UN to the Great Lakes Region, said, "The recent military engagement [in the DRC] did not at all complicate it, it was necessary." In the same vein, the United States ambassador to the UN, Samantha Power, said the brigade was invigorating both the Congolese National Army and the UN peacekeeping mission. And the US special envoy to the Great Lakes Region, Russ Feingold, echoed Powers' view, describing the brigade as "a stronger approach that can give peacekeeping operations more strength in the future and help resolve knotty problems." Offensive peacekeeping in the Congo forcing the rebels to the table Dr Robert Besseling, January 1, 2014, Besseling is a Senior Political Adviser to the IHS Country Risk and Forecasting Sub-Saharan Africa team, Jane’s Intelligence Review, Elusive riches - Continued threats to the DRC's minerals trade The Democratic Republic of Congo's (DRC) government is likely to sign a conclusive peace agreement with the defeated M23 rebel group before the end of 2014. Rwandan and Ugandan pressure on the M23 to disarm, as well as a stronger, United Nations-backed DRC military, will deter the M23 from launching a fresh insurgency. Despite the demise of the M23, the group's former combatants are likely to join new or existing rebel groups in 2014, posing increased risks to the region's valuable extractive sector. Rwanda's motivations for seeking an end to the M23's insurgency in eastern DRC lie in economics. Specifically, President Paul Kagame and senior members of the RDF are seeking the removal of restrictions on foreign budgetary support imposed by several states including the Netherlands and the United Kingdom, which were introduced in 2011 following UN accusations of Rwandan support for the M23. Moreover, Rwanda is likely to seek a renewed FARDC offensive against the ethnic Hutu armed group, the Democratic Forces for the Liberation of Rwanda (Forces démocratiques de libération du Rwanda: FDLR), which threatens Rwandan security. Offensive operations forced the rebels into peace talks Sudarsan Raghavan, November 2, 2013, Washington Post, Raghavan has been The Post's Kabul bureau chief since 2014. He was previously based in Nairobi and Baghdad for the Post, In Volatile Congo, A New UN Force with Teeth, http://www.washingtonpost.com/world/africa/in-volatile-congo-a-new-un-forcewith-teeth/2013/11/01/0cda650c-423f-11e3-b028-de922d7a3f47_story.html DOA: 12-514 The capture of Goma prompted the U.N. Security Council to approve the intervention brigade this year, giving it a mandate to “neutralize” all of Congo’s militias. The force, made up of troops from South Africa, Malawi and Tanzania, became operational this summer. In late August, the brigade went into action for the first time, backing Congolese government forces by firing artillery shells at M23 rebel positions a few miles north of Goma in the town of Kibati. The fighting drove the rebels back a few miles, preventing them from shelling Goma and convincing them to enter peace talks in the Ugandan capital, Kampala, in September. Stefan Bauschard Offensive PKOs release 14 Offensive operations forced rebels to the table Daniel Donovan, April 11, 2013, Foreign Policy Association, “UN Offensive Operation in DRC a long time coming,” http://foreignpolicyblogs.com/2013/04/11/un-offensive-operation-in-drc-a-longtime-coming/ The second and maybe most important facet this new force brings to the table is the threat of interference against the M23. While talks between the DRC government and M23 began in December, they stalled as of mid-February as divisions within the rebel ranks forced them to abandon the negotiation table until they could once again unify. Now talks have again resumed. The rebels have taken steps to give the impression that they would not back down from a UN force, such as labelling this move an act of war, as well as spreading anti-U.N. propaganda to the populace. The bottom line remains that this organized brigade represents a threat to the rebel position, and one that cannot be ignored. This may force the hand of M23 leadership to consent to a peace deal before facing the possibility of fighting enemies on multiple fronts. If this move brings about a peace deal, then it will have already been successful. Stefan Bauschard Offensive PKOs release 15 Necessary to Stop Rebels Sustained offensive peacekeeping critical to fend off the rebels Dr Robert Besseling, January 1, 2014, Besseling is a Senior Political Adviser to the IHS Country Risk and Forecasting Sub-Saharan Africa team, Jane’s Intelligence Review, Elusive riches - Continued threats to the DRC's minerals trade A stronger FARDC enjoying continued support from the FIB is likely to be a key deterrent against a renewed M23 insurgency from across the Ugandan border. MONUSCO is the UN's largest mission, with 21,485 uniformed personnel. On 3 December, it also became the first UN mission to deploy unmanned aerial vehicles (UAVs) to engage in surveillance of the DRC-Rwanda frontier to deter crossborder raids. It is therefore unlikely that a fresh M23 insurgency will erupt in eastern DRC over at least the coming year. With the demise of the M23, other armed groups are likely to recruit the group's former combatants and secure new agreements with arms and mineral smugglers to finance their operations. Mining and energy operations are therefore likely to face an ensuing risk of extortion and theft. Fighting between rival armed groups and the FARDC/FIB is also likely to raise collateral risks to mining operations. Potential fighting between former M23 combatants and other rebel groups and militia forces will also increase these risks. Although the primary targets for any cross-border raids over the coming months are likely to be FARDC and FIB forces, rebels are also likely to stage attacks on mining assets in the region to secure new revenue flows. However, the most significant risk of widespread disruption in the region would come from a potential Rwandan (and possibly Ugandan) military incursion against ethnic Hutu groups such as the FDLR, which will become likely if the FARDC and FIB fail to move against the FDLR. Stefan Bauschard Offensive PKOs release 16 Genocide/Failed States Impacts Genocide happens more frequently and is more destructive than traditional warfare Gutman, Journalist and Staff Writer, December 25th, 1999 [Roy, “Wars Without End,” Newsday, www.newsday.com] That it could happen in Rwanda underscores a terrifying trend that began with the end of the Cold War and is likely to persist for decades - that civilians have become the principal targets in conflicts throughout the world. Today, as the world puts behind it the bloodiest century in human history, a staggering 90 civilians die for every 10 combatants. In World War I, the opposite was true. While policy-makers remain vigilant about traditional conflicts between states that could erupt between India and Pakistan, China and Taiwan, or the two Koreas, for example, the growing focus is on the internal conflicts in states that fail and collapse. The 21st Century dawns with the grim reality that the greatest human toll will likely continue to be the innocents in places such as Burundi, Indonesia, Sierra Leone, Congo and Angola. Genocide and massive crimes against humanity have become the biggest threat to peace and stability. "If you look at the death toll in international war versus that in internal ethnic conflict, the vast preponderance of deaths is from the latter category," said one senior U.S. official familiar with the intelligence data on conflicts worldwide. What's more, conventional attempts like diplomacy to head off conflicts often don't work in these cases, because they may distract attention from the real aim of those who go to war-to conduct a mass pogrom against their racial, tribal or ethnic opponents. This not only causes hundreds of thousands of deaths, but it also prevents societies from rebuilding themselves after conflicts Newman, Academic Associate in the Peace and Governance Programme at the UN University, 2002 [Recovering from Civil Conflict, ed. Newman & Schnabel, p. 910] Many recent domestic conflicts are the direct result of the collapse of the Soviet system. In Eastern and Southeastern Europe and the former Soviet Union, the political and economic transitions experienced by most countries left many or most of them weak and vulnerable to internal and external political and economic pressures. As previous elites began to compete for power with newly emerging elites, many of these countries struggled through their first-ever experience with democracy and free political and economic competition. In addition, many of them were created after the Second World War and during the Soviet reign, their demographic make-up was reshuffled by forced population movements. After 1991, populations throughout the post-communist camp experienced a dramatic drop in wealth, personal security and living standards. A combination of economic collapse, political vacuum and demands for political strongmen caused the eruption of internal conflict and war. The former Yugoslavia, the Southern Caucasus and Central Asi a , have suffered most from this developlement. In the meanwhile, internal conflicts, often with significant involvement from neigbouring states, have continued to rage in Africa, Asia and Latin America. From Somalia to Rwanda, from Cambodia to East Timor, and from El Salvador to Haiti, internal conflicts have continued to destabilize their regions, causing immense human suffering. The most atrocious conflicts take place in Africa. Many African conflicts are rooted in governments' lack of respect for the rights of individuals, corruption, lack of efficient administration, poor infrastructure and weak national coherence - ills that are in turn rooted largely in the colonial legacy of randomly drawn borders, destruction of traditional communities and their governing and conflict management mechanisms, and economic exploitation. Democracy and political stability are still distant goals in many African countries. The combination of weak states and the struggle by elites for natural resources and wealth, the culture of looting, as is particularly obvious in the case of diamond mines in Angola, Congo, Liberia and Sierra Leone, has resulted in a dangerous structural Stefan Bauschard Offensive PKOs release 17 environment that fuels conflict. The patterns of conflict are often very similar: military hostilities between rebel groups and the incumbent government. Characteristic is the use of force to settle disputes and the fact that most conflicts in Africa take the form of ‘irregular warfare’ in which for strategic reasons civilians - instead of professional soldiers - are targeted. Finally, almost all conflicts in Africa have been commercialized. Huge amounts of arms have been-used to destabilize the continent. While most conflicts are fought for access and control over resources in the absence of responsible governments, many conflicts have a decisive external dimension - neighbouring countries that support either government or rebel groups. At least in theory these conflicts could be resolved or prevented rather easily - certainly easier than supposed primordial and ethnic intergroup conflicts. It is usually quite apparent what caused the conflict, and who the responsible parties are. The OAU and other subregional organizations are trying to prevent and manage conflicts, but they can do little without the necessary resources and lack of interest in regional cooperation among member states, who are either part of the conflict or do not care about its resolution. The North's indifference to inequality, injustice, humanitarian plight and war-lordism in many African countries, along with poorly designed development strategies over many decades, have done little to prevent violence on the African continent.' Internal, often intergroup conflicts carry a high price tag - for the populations involved in violence and for those willing to offer assistance in settling and resolving it. The example of Mozambique's 16-year civil war is illustrative of the tremendous costs of conflict: 490,000 children died from war-related causes; 200,000 children were orphaned or abandoned by adults; at least 10,000 children served as soldiers during the conflict; over 40 per cent of schools were destroyed or forced to close; over 40 percent of health centres were destroyed; economic losses totalled US$15 billion, equal to four times the country's 1988 GDP; and damage to industry was so heavy that postwar production equalled only 20-40 per cent of pre-war capacity. Intergroup conflicts affect the whole of society, irrespective of age, occupation and gender. Targeting civilians has become a deliberate strategy of warfare, with the result that an estimated 90 per cent of the casualties of today's civil wars are civilians, mostly women and children. T h is high rate of civilian casualties characterizes more than anything else today's internal wars, contributing to the deep sense of hatred and hostility that make it a difficult task to rebuild war-torn societies once a settlement has eventually been reached. And, every time we fail to stop a genocide, it emboldens would-be genocidaires to carry out more genocides, causing a vicious cycle of atrocities Ronyane, Professor at the University of Virginia and the Federal Executive Institute, 2001 [Peter, Never Again? The United States and the Prevention and Punishment of Genocide Since the Holocaust, p.207-208] Nonintervention also sends messages to other would-be genocidaires that they can pursue their atrocious agendas with impunity. Roger Winter, head of the State Department's Office of Refugee Resettlement during the Carter and Reagan administrations and head of the nonprofit U.S. Committee for Refugees, expressed his fear that at the end of the twentieth century "we actually have a greater possibility of genocide and ethnic cleansing than we did five or six years ago because all these despots feel they can get away with it." Such a message, however unintentional, sets a terrible precedent and ignores the moral interdependence of nations that mirrors growing economic interdependence. Genocide goes beyond physical death to destroy the very fabric of social existence that makes life worth living and death bearable—social death outweighs Card, Emma Goldman Professor 2003 [Claudia, “Genocide and muse] of Philosophy at the University of Wisconsin, Social Death,” Hypatia 18.1 (2003) 63-79, project Stefan Bauschard Offensive PKOs release 18 Genocide is not simply unjust (although it certainly is unjust); it is also evil. It characteristically includes the one-sided killing of defenseless civilians— babies, children, the elderly, the sick, the disabled, and the injured of both genders along with their usually female caretakers—simply on the basis of their national, religious, ethnic, or other political identity. It targets people on the basis of who they are rather than on the basis of what they have done, what they might do, even what they are capable of doing. (One commentator says genocide kills people on the basis of what they are, not even who they are). [End Page 72] Genocide is a paradigm of what Israeli philosopher Avishai Margalit (1996) calls "indecent" in that it not only destroys victims but first humiliates them by deliberately inflicting an "utter loss of freedom and control over one's vital interests" (115). Vital interests can be transgenerational and thus survive one's death. Before death, genocide victims are ordinarily deprived of control over vital transgenerational interests and more immediate vital interests. They may be literally stripped naked, robbed of their last possessions, lied to about the most vital matters, witness to the murder of family, friends, and neighbors, made to participate in their own murder, and if female, they are likely to be also violated sexually. 7 Victims of genocide are commonly killed with no regard for lingering suffering or exposure. They, and their corpses, are routinely treated with utter disrespect. These historical facts, not simply mass murder, account for much of the moral opprobrium attaching to the concept of genocide. Yet such atrocities, it may be argued, are already war crimes, if conducted during wartime, and they can otherwise or also be prosecuted as crimes against humanity. Why, then, add the specific crime of genocide? What, if anything, is not already captured by laws that prohibit such things as the rape, enslavement, torture, forced deportation, and the degradation of individuals? Is any ethically distinct harm done to members of the targeted group that would not have been done had they been targeted simply as individuals rather than because of their group membership? This is the question that I find central in arguing that genocide is not simply reducible to mass death, to any of the other war crimes, or to the crimes against humanity just enumerated. I believe the answer is affirmative: the harm is ethically distinct, although on the question of whether it is worse, I wish only to question the assumption that it is not. Specific to genocide is the harm inflicted on its victims' social vitality. It is not just that one's group membership is the occasion for harms that are definable independently of one's identity as a member of the group. When a group with its own cultural identity is destroyed, its survivors lose their cultural heritage and may even lose their intergenerational connections. To use Orlando Patterson's terminology, in that event, they may become "socially dead" and their descendants "natally alienated," no longer able to pass along and build upon the traditions, cultural developments (including languages), and projects of earlier generations (1982, 5-9). The harm of social death is not necessarily less extreme than that of physical death. Social death can even aggravate physical death by making it indecent, removing all respectful and caring ritual, social connections, and social contexts that are capable of making dying bearable and even of making one's death meaningful. In my view, the special evil of genocide lies in its infliction of not just physical death (when it does that) but social death, producing a consequent meaninglessness of one's life and even of its termination. This view, however, is controversial. Stopping genocide is an absolute imperative—there is no reason we can justify inaction O’Donnell, Staff Writer, 2003 [Michael J, “Genocide, the United Nations, and the Death of Absolute Rights.” Spring, 23 B.C. Third World L.J. 399, l/n] Genocide is the most heinous crime that can be committed against a human population. 39 In the famous words of the UN General Assembly, genocide "shocks the conscience of mankind." 40 A mandate for its prevention and punishment has been enshrined in a widely-ratified multilateral treaty. 41 Genocide's status as a jus cogen, or customary norm of international law from which no derogation is permitted under any circumstances, is broadly accepted. 42 Commentators have suggested that any list of absolute rights should be short and relatively abstract. 43 It nearly goes without saying that the right any such list. 44 Given wrong, genocide stands wrong, magnifying its of a people to be free from wholesale slaughter would top the near-universal consensus that the taking of innocent life is a moral alone as a wrong [*407] that actually multiplies a infamy. 45 The essence of genocide's power is that it denies the very right to exist to entire groups of people based solely upon their identity, making it at once Stefan Bauschard Offensive PKOs release 19 selective in practice and universal in scope. Genocide has killed more people in the twentieth century than all wars combined Heidenrich, Director of the Project on Genocide Prevention at the Institute for Defense & Disarmament Studies, 2001 [John G., How to Prevent Genocide: A Guide for Policymakers, Scholars, and the Concerned Citizen, p. 7-8] No one knows how many people in total died from genocide in the twentieth, century, but some estimates for the years between 1900 and 1988 were compiled by Rudolph Rummel, the professor who coined the word democide. Rummel’s chillingly comprehensive estimates, published in 1994 in a book entitled Death by Government, generally exclude -war-related deaths unless caused by methods now considered criminal under the Geneva Conventions; therefore his estimates include the Allies' aerial bombings of civilian populations in World War II, including the atomic bombings of Hiroshima and Nagasaki. He wrote: In total, during the first 88 years of this century, almost 170 000,000 men, women and children have been shot, beaten, tortured, knifed, burned, starved, frozen, crushed, or worked to death, buried alive, drowned, hanged, bombed, or killed in any other of the myriad ways regimes have inflicted death on unarmed, helpless citizens and foreigners. The number of dead could even conceivably be near a high of 360,000,000 people. This is as though our species has been devastated by a modern Black Plague. And indeed it has, but a plague of absolute power and not germs. genocide will create international instability that leads to nuclear extinction Campbell, Assistant Professor at the University of Delaware, 2001 [Kenneth J., Genocide and the Global Village, p. 10-11] The Cold War came to a sudden end a decade ago and the current post- Cold War era seems to have many decision makers, pol icy analysts, and scholars confused and uncertain. However, in this period of great turbulence and complexity, we should be clear about one large, simple, but critically important fact: this transition era is completely unique in the historical cycles of rising and falling international orders. In two critical respects this is so: first, this transition is occurring (so far) without the general catastrophe typically associated with such periods. Second, in no previous transition era did the prevailing powers charged with creating an improved international order possess the scientific and technical capacity—as the leading powers now do—to destroy the entire international system along with everyone in it. This is the first time in the cyclical creation of new international orders that the great powers possess the power to end the "great game" for all players, for all time! In no previous transition period from one international order to another has this been the case. In this sense, the present cycle is truly singular. These two critical peculiarities should give pause to the architects of our new emerging global order. For the above factors seem to indicate that our leaders maximize their efforts to break with this cycle of "learning-by-catastrophe" and make a leap in institutional learning without waiting for a breakdown of the international order and a systemic catastrophe from which none of us might recover. The unique characteristics of this critical transition period seem to place a premium on state cooperation at least regarding those core problems which , if not managed or mitigated, threaten to unravel the entire international order. The main task in this period of transition, in the midst of globalization, is to consolidate, reinforce, and extend the present , post-Cold War liberal international order. At the heart of this effort at global governance must be the prevention of genocide and crimes against humanity. Stefan Bauschard Offensive PKOs release 20 Genocide and the collapse of states threatens US security Sarah Sewall and Carly Kaysen, The United States and the International Criminal Court: National Security and International Law. Rowman & Littlefield, 2000 American skeptics may remain unconvinced that prosecuting foreign mass murderers or war criminals is related to U.S. national security. They will argue that U.S. interests are unaffected by most mass atrocities occurring abroad and that when atrocities do matter, The United States will address them directly. Only in the most superficial sense is this true. One does not have to believe Robert Kaplan’s prediction of a coming anarchy in order to recognize that the United States is affected in some measure by the dissolution of responsible government structures and the spread of violence worldwide. The effect can be multidimensional, affecting U.S. trade and investment, military security and access, or political objectives. Mass atrocities almost always have wider regional security repercussions, such as expanded armed conflict, massive refugee flows, and arms trafficking and organized criminal activity. Crises fueled by gross violations of international law will continue to occupy the attention of the United States. Furthermore the lines between security interests and normative interests are blurring. When mass atrocities dominate the media, or when tyrants push too far, democratic societies may choose to stop them partly or purely for moral reasons. Some NATO leaders called the Kosovo operation a human rights intervention; U.S. government officials deemed it a matter of national interest. Future campaigns may not bother to dress up normative goals. Stefan Bauschard Offensive PKOs release 21 Human Rights Impacts Global human rights violations create conditions where extinction is inevitable Human Rights Web, 94 (An Introduction to the Human Rights Movement Created on July 20, 1994 / Last edited on January 25, 1997, http://www.hrweb.org/intro.html) The United Nations Charter, Universal Declaration of Human Rights, and UN Human Rights convenants were written and implemented in the aftermath of the Holocaust, revelations coming from the Nuremberg war crimes trials, the Bataan Death March, the atomic bomb, and other horrors smaller in magnitude but not in impact on the individuals they affected. A whole lot of people in a number of countries had a crisis of conscience and found they could no longer look the other way while tyrants jailed, tortured, and killed their neighbors. In Germany, the Nazis first came for the communists, and I did not speak up, because I was not a Communist. Then they came for the Jews, and I did not speak up, because I was not a Jew. Then they came for the trade unionists, and I did not speak up, because I was not a trade unionist. Then they came for the Catholics, and I did not speak up, because I was not a Catholic. Then they came for me... and by that time, there was no one to speak up for anyone. -- Martin Niemoeller, Pastor, German Evangelical (Lutheran) Church Many also realized that advances in technology and changes in social structures had rendered war a threat to the continued existence of the human race. Large numbers of people in many countries lived under the control of tyrants, having no recourse but war to relieve often intolerable living conditions. Unless some way was found to relieve the lot of these people, they could revolt and become the catalyst for another wide-scale and possibly nuclear war. For perhaps the first time, representatives from the majority of governments in the world came to the conclusion that basic human rights must be protected, not only for the sake of the individuals and countries involved, but to preserve the human race. Stefan Bauschard Offensive PKOs release 22 Human rights key to stop global war Burke white 04 Burke-White 4 – William W., Lecturer in Public and International Affairs and Senior Special Assistant to the Dean at the Woodrow Wilson School of Public and International Affairs, Princeton University and Ph.D. at Cambridge, "Human Rights and National Security: The Strategic Correlation", The Harvard Human Rights Journal, Spring, 17 Harv. Hum. Rts. J. 249, Lexis For most of the past fifty years, U.S. foreign policymakers have largely viewed the promotion of human rights anti the protection of national security as in inherent tension. Almost without exception, each administration has treated the two goals as mutually exclusive: promote human rights at the expense of national security or protect national security while overlooking international human rights. While U.S. |*)licymakers have been motivated at times by human rights concerns, such concerns have generally been subordinate to national security. For example, President Bushs 2(X)2 U.S. National Security Strategy speaks of a “commitment to protecting basic human rights.” In the same document, President Bush makes it clear that “defending our Nation against its enemies is the first and fundamental commitment of the Federal Government.”1 This subordination of human rights to national security is both unnecessary and strategically questionable. A more effective U.S. foreign policy would view human rights and national security as correlated and complementary goals. Better protection of human rights around the world would make the United States safer and more secure. The United States needs to restructure its foreign policy accordingly. This Article presents a strategic—as opposed to ideological or normative—argument that the promotion of human rights should be given a more prominent place in U.S. foreign policy. It does so by suggesting a correlation between the domestic human rights practices of states and their propensity to engage in aggressive international conduct . Among the chief threats to U.S. national security arc acts of aggression by other states. Aggressive acts of war may directly endanger the United States, as did the Japanese bombing of Pearl Harbor in 19dl, or they may require U.S. military action overseas, as in Kuwait fifty years later. Evidence from the post-G)ld War period indicates that states that systematically abuse their own citizens’ human rights are also those most likely to engage in aggression. To the degree that improvements in various states’ human rights records decrease the likelihood of aggressive war, a foreign policy informed by human rights can significantly enhance U.S. and global security. Since 1990, a state’s domestic human ri ghts policy appears to be a telling indicator of that state’s propensity to engage in international aggression . A central element of U.S. foreign policy has long been the preservation of peace and the prevention of such acts of aggression. 2 If the correlation discussed herein is accurate, it provides U. S. policymakers with a powerful new tool to enhance national security through the promotion of human rights. A strategic linkage between national s ecurity and human rights would result in a number of important policy modiªcat ions. First, it cha nges the prioritization of those countries U.S. policymakers have identiªed as presenting the greatest concern. Second, it alters so me of the policy prescriptions for such states. Third, it offers states a mean s of signaling benign international intent through the improvement of their domestic human Stefan Bauschard Offensive PKOs release 23 rights records. Fourth, it provides a way for a current government to prevent future governments from aggressive international behavior th rough the institutionalization of human rights protections. Fifth, it addresses the particular threat of human rights abusing states obtaining weapons of mass destruction (WMD). Finally, it offers a mechanism for U.S.-U.N. cooperation on human rights issues. Stefan Bauschard Offensive PKOs release 24 A2: Offensive PKO Undermine Impartiality Impartiality won’t work in many environments Dr. Jeni Whalan, 2014, Partial Peace: The Politics of Taking Sides in UN Peacekeeping, Paper prepared for International Studies Association Annual Convention, Toronto, 26-29, https://www.academia.edu/6474185/Partial_Peace_The_Politics_of_Taking_Sides_in_UN_Peacekeeping DOA: 12-6-14 Lecturer in International Security and Development BA (UNSW), M.Phil (Oxon), D.Phil (Oxon) Regardless of intent, however, impartiality proved impossible in many of the conflict environments to which peacekeepers were deployed. The case of Bosnia is perhaps the clearest example of this challenge. A New York Times feature in 1995 put it this way: How could the "neutrality" or "impartiality" many of them believed to be essential to a peacekeeping mission be preserved in the face of an often barbarous Serbian assault on a Bosnia whose "sovereignty" was recognized by the very institution they served? Impartiality enables genocide Dr. Jeni Whalan, 2014, Partial Peace: The Politics of Taking Sides in UN Peacekeeping, Paper prepared for International Studies Association Annual Convention, Toronto, 26-29, https://www.academia.edu/6474185/Partial_Peace_The_Politics_of_Taking_Sides_in_UN_Peacekeeping DOA: 12-6-14 Lecturer in International Security and Development BA (UNSW), M.Phil (Oxon), D.Phil (Oxon) Indeed, the experiences of many conflict situations in which peacekeepers were deployed during this time—above all, those of Bosnia and Rwanda—created a profound crisis in the substantive legitimacy of the entire peacekeeping enterprise. Faced with belligerents intent on continuing the conflict, rather than building peace, peacekeepers found that, rather than giving them the power of procedural legitimacy, their impartiality left them powerless, lacking the credibility to deal with ‘spoilers’ of peace processes and, worse, standing idly by as mass atrocities were committed on their watch Impartiality should not be understood to mean neutrality amongst waring parties Dr. Jeni Whalan, 2014, Partial Peace: The Politics of Taking Sides in UN Peacekeeping, Paper prepared for International Studies Association Annual Convention, Toronto, 26-29, https://www.academia.edu/6474185/Partial_Peace_The_Politics_of_Taking_Sides_in_UN_Peacekeeping DOA: 12-6-14 Lecturer in International Security and Development BA (UNSW), M.Phil (Oxon), D.Phil (Oxon) Later that year, Annan continued: The world has recognized that diplomacy, whether in the Balkans or in Baghdad, has to be backed by firmness and by force. Peacekeeping today requires not only rethinking the means but also the method of implementing the mandates set out by the Security Council. We have learned that while impartiality is a vital condition for peacekeeping, it must be impartiality in the execution of the mandate—not just an unthinking neutrality between warring parties.52 Impartiality should not mean appeasement Stefan Bauschard Offensive PKOs release 25 Dr. Jeni Whalan, 2014, Partial Peace: The Politics of Taking Sides in UN Peacekeeping, Paper prepared for International Studies Association Annual Convention, Toronto, 26-29, https://www.academia.edu/6474185/Partial_Peace_The_Politics_of_Taking_Sides_in_UN_Peacekeeping DOA: 12-6-14 Lecturer in International Security and Development BA (UNSW), M.Phil (Oxon), D.Phil (Oxon) In 2000, this new understanding of impartiality was codified in the Report of the Panel on UN Peace Operations, known better as the Brahimi Report after its chair, the veteran UN envoy Lakhdar Brahimi. The influential report declared: Impartiality for such operations must therefore mean adherence to the principles of the Charter and to the objectives of a mandate that is rooted in those Charter principles. Such impartiality is not the same as neutrality or equal treatment of all parties in all cases for all time, which can amount to a policy of appeasement. “Impartial” intervention is a delusion Dr. Jeni Whalan, 2014, Partial Peace: The Politics of Taking Sides in UN Peacekeeping, Paper prepared for International Studies Association Annual Convention, Toronto, 26-29, https://www.academia.edu/6474185/Partial_Peace_The_Politics_of_Taking_Sides_in_UN_Peacekeeping DOA: 12-6-14 Lecturer in International Security and Development BA (UNSW), M.Phil (Oxon), D.Phil (Oxon) Others argued that peacekeeping needed more partiality and enforcement in order to face down the aggressors in what constituted ongoing conflicts. Writing in 1994, Richard Betts described impartial intervention as a ‘delusion’ abetting ‘slow-motion savagery’ in Bosnia, Somalia, Haiti and Rwanda. Impartiality, Betts wrote, sounds like common sense: that intervention should be both limited and impartial, because weighing in on one side of a local struggle undermines the legitimacy and effectiveness of outside involvement. This Olympian presumption resonates with respect for law and international cooperation. It has the ring of prudence, fairness, and restraint. In makes sense in oldfashioned UN peacekeeping operations, wh re the outsiders’ role is not to make peace, but to bless and monitor a cease-fire that all parties have decided to accept. But it becomes a destructive misconception when carried over to the messier realm of ‘peace enforcement’, where the belligerents have yet to decide that they have nothing more to gain by fighting.’42 Stefan Bauschard Offensive PKOs release 26 A2: Kritiks of Peacekeeping Peacekeeping is a necessary compromise Dr. Jeni Whalan, 2014, Partial Peace: The Politics of Taking Sides in UN Peacekeeping, Paper prepared for International Studies Association Annual Convention, Toronto, 26-29, https://www.academia.edu/6474185/Partial_Peace_The_Politics_of_Taking_Sides_in_UN_Peacekeeping DOA: 12-6-14 Lecturer in International Security and Development BA (UNSW), M.Phil (Oxon), D.Phil (Oxon) It is no wonder that peacekeeping practice is subject to intense debate about its goals, methods, means, and effects. Peacekeeping is an ad hoc, ever-evolving instrument of international security that finds no straightforward authority in the UN Charter, little consistency in the interests, norms and crises that prompt its deployment, and no clear objective against which its effectiveness can be assessed. Peacekeeping is in many cases the ‘least bad’ option between inaction and imperialism, an undesirable but necessary compromise that demands continued justification since it cannot rely on a simple expression of legal norms, political interests, or its record of success. Stefan Bauschard Offensive PKOs release 27 A2: Offensive Peacekeeping Fails Congo operation more successful than other PKOs Lionel Beehner, November 15, 2013, Is UN Offensive Intervention in Congo a New Model of Peacekeeping?http://politicalviolenceataglance.org/2013/11/15/is-unoffensive-intervention-in-congo-a-new-model-of-peacekeeping/ DOA: 12-6-14 Lionel Beehner is currently a PhD candidate at Yale University, a fellow at the Truman National Security Project, and a Term Member with the Council on Foreign Relations, where he is formerly a senior writer. He is a member of USA Today’s Board of Contributors and holds an M.A. in international affairs from Columbia University. Good news is a rare commodity in the Democratic Republic of Congo (DRC). So skepticism is in order but the initial reports about the progress made by the UN’s Force Intervention Brigade in pushing the M23 rebels to disarm sound promising. Earlier this year I blogged that the UN’s 3,000-strong intervention brigade, sent to “neutralize armed groups” in the DRC, could provide a template of sorts for future conflicts. The UN suggested that the brigade, which was accompanied by the use of drones over DRC airspace, was a one-off and not a plug-and-play template to be tried elsewhere. But compared to past peacekeeping missions, it has been remarkably successful in a short amount of time. The M23 rebels have, at least temporarily, laid down their arms. Sure, there are at least 10 other rebel groups still present in the eastern parts of the country. Sure, the rebels were riven with internal rivalries before the arrival of UN peacekeepers. And sure the US decision to squeeze the Rwandan government probably helped shift the momentum as much as the peacekeeper’s arrival. But, there is still room for cautious optimism. Stefan Bauschard Offensive PKOs release 28 A2: No UN Authority for Offensive PKOs UN has authority for offensive PKOs under Article VII Fiona Blyth, April 10, 2013, IPI Global Observatory, “Too Risk-Averse, UN Peacekeepers in the DRC Get New Mandate and More Challenges,” Fiona Blyth is a former military intelligence officer with the British Army who is a Research Assistant in the Africa program at the International Peace Institute, http://theglobalobservatory.org/2013/04/too-risk-averse-un-peacekeepers-in-the-drc-get-new-mandate-and-morechallenges/ DOA: 12-5-14 Interpreted by some as the UN’s first authorization for the use of offensive force, UN Security Council Resolution 2098 passed on March 29 and called for the deployment of an “intervention brigade” to the Democratic Republic of the Congo (DRC) that can use offensive combat operations to “neutralize and disarm” Congolese rebel groups, in particular the M23 rebels responsible for taking over Goma in the eastern DRC last year. Despite the declaration by the UN that this breaks new ground, the UN Stabilization Mission in the Congo (MONUSCO) is already authorized to conduct offensive operations under its Chapter VII mandate, as are all other missions operating under Chapter VII. The Rules of Engagement (ROE) in these missions authorize the use of force beyond self-defense. As MONUSCO, and its predecessor MONUC, already have this authorization, the Security Council and DPKO should instead analyze how and why the mission has failed on notable occasions to fulfill its priority of protecting civilians before prescribing the solution in the form of an intervention brigade. Chapter VII permits use of force beyond self-defense Fiona Blyth, April 10, 2013, IPI Global Observatory, “Too Risk-Averse, UN Peacekeepers in the DRC Get New Mandate and More Challenges,” Fiona Blyth is a former military intelligence officer with the British Army who is a Research Assistant in the Africa program at the International Peace Institute, http://theglobalobservatory.org/2013/04/too-risk-averse-un-peacekeepers-in-the-drc-get-new-mandate-and-morechallenges/ DOA: 12-5-14 The announcement of the intervention brigade in the DRC in Resolution 2098 was framed as the “first ever ‘offensive’ combat force;” however, offensive operations are already authorized under Chapter VII of the UN Charter. Chapter VII mandates typically permit the use of force beyond self-defense to ensure the freedom of movement of the mission, protect civilians, and for the protection of UN personnel and property. Previous field commanders have interpreted their mandates as such to allow UN forces to actively pursue rebel groups and to preempt and disrupt rebel movement ahead of time. Examples of this include the United Nations Mission in Sierra Leone (UNAMSIL), the United Nations Stabilization Mission in Haiti (UNSTAMIH) and the United Nations Mission in Somalia II (UNISOM II). Stefan Bauschard Offensive PKOs release 29 No Turns are Unique It was necessary in the Congo Daniel Donovan, April 11, 2013, Foreign Policy Association, “UN Offensive Operation in DRC a long time coming,” http://foreignpolicyblogs.com/2013/04/11/un-offensive-operation-in-drc-a-longtime-coming/ Also, despite the potential effectiveness of the mandate by this offensive force, they certainly have the faculty to be just as inept as their predecessors. Falling under the management of MONUSCO may water down their abilities due to political posturing. However, with the U.N. Security Council recognizing the need for results after all of the money that was spent in the past, the new brigades may yet avoid this fate. Ultimately this move was a necessity for all involved except the rebels. The pattern of the twenty year conflict in the Congo of the rebel leadership seemingly passing from one person to the next without hope for peace needs to end. Even when peace is signed it has been habitually cast aside in favor of further war and the ability to smuggle minerals from the lawless eastern provinces. A series of failures by previous missions have brought the DRC no closer to peace and sustainable development than they were 2 decades ago. The fact that the U.N. Security Council realized this and responded in kind bodes well for the future of the nation. Who knows, maybe the rebels will realize they have reached the end of the road and settle with the government? In the end, doing something different is preferable in this situation than continuing down the same fruitless path. Past UN PKOs not powerful enough to force negotiations Lionel Beehner, November 15, 2013, Is UN Offensive Intervention in Congo a New Model of Peacekeeping?http://politicalviolenceataglance.org/2013/11/15/is-unoffensive-intervention-in-congo-a-new-model-of-peacekeeping/ DOA: 12-6-14 Lionel Beehner is currently a PhD candidate at Yale University, a fellow at the Truman National Security Project, and a Term Member with the Council on Foreign Relations, where he is formerly a senior writer. He is a member of USA Today’s Board of Contributors and holds an M.A. in international affairs from Columbia University. I think the benefits of ending the violence promptly and with aggressive force far outweigh the risks (which are plenty). I also think that those who seek political solutions may be deluding themselves (nor are the two types of conflict resolution mutually exclusive, of course). Indeed, as readers of this blog know quite well, the trouble with UN peacekeeping to date has been its inability to shape the balance of power on the ground in any kind of meaningful way and provide the necessary security to bring about political reconciliation. Previous PKOs don’t have the resources Lionel Beehner, November 15, 2013, Is UN Offensive Intervention in Congo a New Model of Peacekeeping?http://politicalviolenceataglance.org/2013/11/15/is-unoffensive-intervention-in-congo-a-new-model-of-peacekeeping/ DOA: 12-6-14 Lionel Stefan Bauschard Offensive PKOs release 30 Beehner is currently a PhD candidate at Yale University, a fellow at the Truman National Security Project, and a Term Member with the Council on Foreign Relations, where he is formerly a senior writer. He is a member of USA Today’s Board of Contributors and holds an M.A. in international affairs from Columbia University. The lessons from the Intervention Brigade are twofold: First, sending in a peacekeeping force is not enough to change the balance of power and bring about peace. Without the US cutoff of support to Rwanda’s Kagame, it is likely the brigade would still be bogged down. Second, the leadership and makeup of such interventions matter. The skills of Santos Cruz have brought discipline to the brigade. The South Africans, Tanzanians, and Malawians who make up the bulk of the brigade have an obvious vested interest in seeing this area pacified. To be sure, nobody is suggesting this kind of peacekeeper is a neutral or honest broker. In that way, some might argue they violate the oath of “do no harm.” But too often such peacekeepers are poorly equipped, or simply lack the mandate, to have any effect on controlling the belligerents on the ground. This is not a lesson that “force works, and absolute force absolutely.” But we would be crazy not to try to replicate success. The disarming of the M23 rebels is a rare success story from a region starving for good news. Peacekeeping failed in the Congo until it was offensive Jacy Fortin, 3-29,13, International Business Times, UN Peacekeepers For Combat? In DR Congo, Blue Helmets To Get Serious About Intervention http://www.ibtimes.com/un-peacekeepers-combat-dr-congo-blue-helmets-getserious-about-intervention-1160971 The draft resolution, a copy of which was leaked to RFE/RL, would give a oneyear mandate to a UN peacekeeping brigade in the mineral-rich eastern Democratic Republic of the Congo (DRC) to use force against a group known as the M23 rebels. It says peacekeepers would have the "responsibility of neutralizing armed groups...and the objective of contributing to reducing the threats posed by armed groups to state authority and civilian security in eastern DRC." The resolution is the result of fatigue and frustration felt by diplomats in the UN Security Council over the fact that a peacekeeping force in the Central African country, which has suffered through decades of conflict, has thus far failed to have any significant impact on security. Richard Gowan, associate director at New York University's Center on International Cooperation, says the resolution is a "very controversial option" but one that Security Council members felt had to be put on the table. "It's a response to that fact that you've had peacekeepers in the eastern Congo for over a decade, and actually, the force has been pretty well-armed by UN peacekeeping standards," Gowan says. "[But] the force has been repeatedly unable to deal with militia offensives in the region." Previous efforts failed Africa Report, August 21, 2013, http://www.theafricareport.com/East-HornAfrica/world-bank-dollars-and-un-peacekeeping-on-the-offensive-in-greatlakes.html Stefan Bauschard Offensive PKOs release 31 The deadly conflict in the DRC, whose vast size covers an area about the size of western Europe, has long defied solution. For decades the country's litany of woes has confounded observers, caused untold suffering and death for millions of its citizens, and destroyed its infrastructure. Past peacekeeping operations failed to prevent genocide Citizens for Global Solutions, September 2013, “A Peacekeeping Mission with Teeth,” http://globalsolutions.org/blog/2013/09/Peacekeeping-MissionTeeth#.VILN1YcttmA A peacekeeping force that can actually go after rebels and guerrillas that attack civilians and destabilize regions is a very positive step forward for UN Peacekeeping. Past UN operations have been heavily criticized for be unable to stop events and groups that were killing innocent civilians. The most damning example of a UN Peacekeeping failure is the Rwandan Genocide. Peacekeepers were not allowed to combat machete wielding Hutus as they massacred Tutsis and even when several Peacekeepers were killed the force was withdrawn rather than being reinforced and allowed to counterattack. Being able to stop and combat the groups that led to a need for a UN mission will make for a more lasting peace than when the groups were ignored or government forces had to be relied on to stop them. Future instances of the brigade will depend on how well the one in the DRC performs, but being able to actually stop violence directed at civilians and peacekeepers alike will go a long way in ensuring that a tragedy like the Rwandan Genocide will not happen again just because peacekeeping forces' hands are tied by red tape. MONUSCO failures were killing its credibility Sudarsan Raghavan, November 2, 2013, Washington Post, Raghavan has been The Post's Kabul bureau chief since 2014. He was previously based in Nairobi and Baghdad for the Post, In Volatile Congo, A New UN Force with Teeth, http://www.washingtonpost.com/world/africa/in-volatile-congo-a-new-un-forcewith-teeth/2013/11/01/0cda650c-423f-11e3-b028-de922d7a3f47_story.html DOA: 12-514 The U.N. soldiers are in Congo with an ambitious goal: to reverse the trajectory of one of the world’s most horrific and complex conflicts, one that has killed more than 5 million people since 1998, the deadliest war since World War II. They are also here to rescue the image of the troubled U.N. peacekeeping mission in the Congo. “To be a peacekeeper doesn’t mean you need to be passive,” their top commander, Gen. Carlos Alberto dos Santos Cruz, said hours before the offensive began. “To be a peacekeeper, you need to take action. The way to protect the civilians is to take action. If you see the history of atrocities here, it justifies action.” naction is precisely what the U.N. mission here has been criticized for in the 14 years since the United Nations dispatched soldiers to Congo, the first members of what has become the largest peacekeeping force in U.N. history. Now, the U.N. Security Council has launched the Forward Intervention Brigade in a bold attempt to defeat the dozens of militias that pillage this mineral-rich central African country, which is roughly the size of Western Europe. The brigade, composed of 3,000 soldiers, is the United Nations’ first offensive combat force and is seen as a possible model for defusing crises in other chaotic parts of the world. Stefan Bauschard Offensive PKOs release 32 Previous peacekeeping forces failed in the Congo Daniel Donovan, April 11, 2013, Foreign Policy Association, “UN Offensive Operation in DRC a long time coming,” http://foreignpolicyblogs.com/2013/04/11/un-offensive-operation-in-drc-a-longtime-coming/ First, the UN Security Council has recognized the failure by the peacekeeping mission MONUSCO, originally called MONUC, which has been in operation for almost 15 years. Despite its mandate to “protect civilians under imminent threat of physical violence,” the inhabitants of the DRC, particularly within the eastern provinces, have dealt with a near constant state of conflict since the U.N. force put boots on the ground. The citizens have suffered from war crimes and crimes against humanity such as rape, pillage and murder occurring right under the noses of the U.N. forces madndated to protect them. Last year, the M23 rebels seized Goma, with little resistance from a U.N. force stationed nearby. It is no small feat for a body such as the Security Council to admit to past blunders. This new force is not expected to sit back and watch as the countryside is ravaged. With a mandate to carry out targeted offensive operations, they have the potential to bring peace to the region once and for all. This may help build an environment conducive to development. We can only hope. The reality remains that no semblance of developmental infrastructure can exist against the backdrop of a state in perpetual war, where the average citizen fears for their well being or has already fled their home. Stefan Bauschard Offensive PKOs release Pro – Positive Peace Answers 33 Stefan Bauschard Offensive PKOs release No Impact – Direct Violence OW’s Direct violence outweighs structural violence Maley 85 (William, The University of New South Wales at Duntroon, “Peace, Needs and Utopia”, Political Studies, XXXIIl, 578-591, Political Studies) The difficulties in Galtung's approach can be seen clearly when one recalls his view that it is probably a disservice to man to try to see either direct or structural violence as the more important. To this it can be replied that, particularly in its most recent formulations, Galtung's idea of structural violence embraces a number of forms which scarcely anyone would regard as seriously as the crushing, tearing, piercing, burning, poisoning, evaporation, strangulation, dehydration and starvation which constitute personal somatic violence,'^ To treat being deprived of 'cultural stimuli' as an evil commensurable with being torn to pieces is a step so audacious as to demand very specific moral justitication. This Galtung fails to supply, and as a result, his notion of peace is a very unsatisfactory ideal against which to evaluate a social order. 34 Stefan Bauschard Offensive PKOs release 35 A2: Structural Violence = Root Cause Discrete causes of war do exist – Structural violence isn’t the root cause Patomaki 2 (Heikki, U of Helsinki, The Challenge of Critical Theories: Peace Research at the Start of the New Century’, JPR 38(6), http://www.prio.no/misc/Download.aspx?file=%2Fcscw%2Frd%2FReplication+Data%2Ffile41602_wjprappendix1 .doc.) What Galtung fails to do is spell out more generally the essential ontological qualities of society. Social systems are open: neither the intrinsic nor the extrinsic condition of closure is, in general, applicable. Social entities – including socio-historically formed social actors and their understandings and relations – can and do change, and any social whole, specified in whatever manner, is susceptible to extrinsic influences, including influences from non-social layers of reality (physical, biological, ecological etc.). In a sense that every event has a real (structured and complex) cause, ubiquity determinism holds; but causality does not have anything to do with constant conjunctions. Causality is about the production of outcomes. Moreover, socio-historically formed human/social beings and their contextual reasons for action are also causally efficacious. The focus on structural violence instead of direct violence makes preventing war impossible. Thompson 3 (William, Professor of Political Science and Director of the Center for the Study of International Relations at Indiana University, “A Streetcar Named Sarajevo: Catalysts, Multiple Causation Chains, and Rivalry Structures,” International Studies Quarterly, 47(3), AD: 7-10-9) BL Richard Ned Lebow (2000–2001) has recently invoked what might be called a streetcar interpretation of systemic war and change. According to him, all our structural theories in world politics both overdetermine and underdetermine the explanation of the most important events such as World War I, World War II, or the end of the Cold War. Not only do structural theories tend to fixate on one cause or stream of causation, they are inherently incomplete because the influence of structural causes cannot be known without also identifying the necessary role of catalysts. As long as we ignore the precipitants that actually encourage actors to act, we cannot make accurate generalizations about the relationships between more remote causation and the outcomes that we are trying to explain. Nor can we test the accuracy of such generalizations without accompanying data on the presence or absence of catalysts. In the absence of an appropriate catalyst (or a ‘‘streetcar’’ that failed to arrive), wars might never have happened. Concrete information on their presence (‘‘streetcars’’ that did arrive) might alter our understanding of the explanatory significance of other variables. But since catalysts and contingencies are so difficult to handle theoretically and empirically, perhaps we should focus instead on probing the theoretical role of contingencies via the development of ‘‘what if ’’ scenarios. Stefan Bauschard Offensive PKOs release 36 Stefan Bauschard Offensive PKOs release 37 A2: Structural Violence = Root Cause There is no root cause of war Ahmed 8 (Jan, Bill, Asia Observer, Staff, http://www.asiaobserver.com/component/option,com_fireboard/Itemid,453/func,view/id,3803/catid,26/.)JR War arises because of the changing relations of numerous variables--technological, psychic, social, and intellectual. There is no single cause of war. Peace is equilibrium among many forces. Change in any particular force, trend, movement, or policy may at one time make for war, but under other conditions a similar change may make for peace. A state may at one time promote peace by armament, at another time by disarmament, at one time by insistence on its rights, at another time by spirit of conciliation. All empirical reality denies their claims – Reducing structural disparities has not reduced the tendency toward war and the causes of war are complex Rummel 79 (R.J., Understanding war, power, and peace, U of Hawaii, http://www.hawaii.edu/powerkills/NOTE13.HTM#CHAP) There have been about 350 wars of all kinds since the Battle of Waterloo in 1815, which once and for all defeated Napoleon's lust for power. If this number fairly well represents the frequency of war in history, there have been nearly 13,600 wars since 3,600 B.C.1 The toll of human misery measures around 30,000,000 direct battle deaths since Waterloo and 1,000,000,000 since 3,600 B.C.1a Then there are the uncountable deaths, the broken bodies and lives from the ravages and effects of these wars. Nor has war abated. Not with civilization. Not with education and literacy. Not with burgeoning international organizations and communications. Not with the swelling library of peace plans and antiwar literature. Not with the mushrooming antiwar movements and demonstrations. In the 25 years after World War II, for so many the war to create and insure peace for generations, some 97 internal and international wars occurred. Total deaths about equal those killed in World War II. On any single day during these 25 years slightly more than 10 internal or international wars were being fought somewhere.1b Nor is war increasing. Although there are ups and downs in the intensity and scope of warfare, the historical trend is level: a little more than six major international wars per decade and 2,000,000 battle deaths. Around this trend there are at least three cycles of warfare, showing different peaks around every 10, 25, and 50 years. Empirical analysis is effective and liberating Rummel 79 (R.J., Understanding war, power, and peace, U of Hawaii, http://www.hawaii.edu/powerkills/NOTE13.HTM#CHAP) After all, it is through an intimate, personal experience with our close friends and relatives, with all their virtues and vices, that enables us to see them as individuals and develop reliable expectations (predictions) of their behavior. But yet, we also find that for an understanding of those close to us we must push toward common elements. Certain common needs (hunger, sex), certain common interests (status, love), certain common psychological mechanisms (frustration, ego), certain social and cultural factors (peer-group pressure, cultural norms). Even in our closest relationships, understanding seems to presuppose a mixture of intimate personal knowledge and an insight into common causes, conditions, explanations, and so on. Similarly with war. To understand a war or a situation in which war is likely is partly to know the war or situation intimately, of course. As historians, journalists, and diplomats do. But to understand also requires knowing what this war or situation has in common with other such wars or situations. There is no root cause of violence American Psychological Association 7 (http://www.apahelpcenter.org/featuredtopics/feature.php?id=38&ch=2.) JR Violence is a learned behavior. Like all learned behaviors, it can be changed. This isn't easy, though. Since there is no single cause of violence, there is no one simple solution. The best you can do is learn to recognize the warning signs of violence and to get help when you see them in your friends or yourself. Stefan Bauschard Offensive PKOs release 38 Stefan Bauschard Offensive PKOs release 39 Stefan Bauschard Offensive PKOs release 40 Perm Solves – Generally We don’t need to exclude the aff Cuomo 96 (Chris J. Professor of Philosophy and Women's Studies, and Director of the Institute for Women's Studies at the University of Georgia, “War Is Not Just an Event: Reflections on the significance of Everyday Violence”, Published in Hypatia 11.4 nb, pp. 31-48) I propose that the constancy of militarism and its effects on social reality be reintroduced as a crucial locus of contemporary feminist attentions, and that feminists emphasize how wars are eruptions and manifestations of omnipresent militarism that is a product and tool of multiply oppressive, corporate, technocratic states.' Feminists should be particularly interested in making this shift because it better allows consideration of the effects of war and militarism on women, subjugated peoples, and environments. While giving attention to the constancy of militarism in contemporary life we need not neglect the importance of addressing the specific qualities of direct, large-scale, declared military conflicts. But the dramatic nature of declared, large-scale conflicts should not obfuscate the ways in which military violence pervades most societies in increasingly technologically sophisticated ways and the significance of military institutions and everyday practices in shaping reality. Philosophical discussions that focus only on the ethics of declaring and fighting wars miss these connections, and also miss the ways in which even declared military conflicts are often experienced as omnipresent horrors. These approaches also leave unquestioned tendencies to suspend or distort moral judgement in the face of what appears to be the inevitability of war and militarism. Treating structural and direct violence as a zero-sum game makes both worse – Should do both Maley 85 (William, The University of New South Wales at Duntroon, “Peace, Needs and Utopia”, Political Studies, XXXIIl, 578-591, http://web.ebscohost.com/ehost/pdf?vid=6&hid=7&sid=fbf7951e-fa9b-4ac2-ba3b2c07e8326bd2%40sessionmgr2) CH Given the cogency of the case against methodological essentialism, there is no desire to argue here that there are any logical grounds for preferring one usage of a term in political theory over another,''* However, there can be sound practical reasons for favouring a particular usage, A particular usage might provide distinctions of meaning which a different usage might obliterate,^Furthermore, it might be so well entrenched that any departure from it would be liable to cause confusion. Finally, a particular term, when used consistent to refer to one thing, may acquire irremediably favourable or unfavourable overtones, to the extent that to use it to mean anything else might give the new referent an unwarranted lustre or tarnish, A Russian anecdote reported by Vladimir Bukovsky illustrates this clearly: A Jew came to his Rabbi and asked: 'Rabbi, you are a very wise man. Tell me, is there going to be a war?' 'There will be no war,' replied the Rabbi, 'but there will be such a struggle for peace that no stone will be left standing,'-* The difficulties in Galtung's approach can be seen clearly when one recalls his view that it is probably a disservice to man to try to see either direct or structural violence as the more important. To this it can be replied that, particularly in its most recent formulations, Galtung's idea of structural violence embraces a number of forms which scarcely anyone would regard as seriously as the crushing, tearing, piercing, burning, poisoning, evaporation, strangulation, dehydration and starvation which constitute personal somatic violence,'^ To treat being deprived of 'cultural stimuli' as an evil commensurable with being torn to pieces is a step so audacious as to demand very specific moral justitication. This Galtung fails to supply, and as a result, his notion of peace is a very unsatisfactory ideal against which to evaluate a social order, Stefan Bauschard Offensive PKOs release 41 Stefan Bauschard Offensive PKOs release 42 Perm Solves – Generally Perm solves peace and violence are coexistent parts of life, making the maintenance of human rights and social services possible Kemp 3 (Graham, Associate Professor at Chalmers University of Technology, “Keeping the Peace: Conflict Resolution and Peaceful Studies around the World”, October 2003, p. 14-15, AD: 7-11-9) The thesis that violence coexists with peace can be illustrated in reference to Colombia, considered one of the most violent places on earth. Colombia has endured an armed conflict among the army, guerrillas, and paramilitaries for more than fifty tears, Statistics show that the rate of assassinations in Colombia has grown as high as 89.5 per 100,000 inhabitants per annum (Comision Interamericana de Derechos Humanos 1999:34). However, whereas about 250,000 men and women fighters engage in deadly confrontation, the remaining 40 million people go about their work peacefully, raising children, building a home, having a family, interacting with friends and neighbors, believing that a better future is yet to come. In effect, widespread direct violence and many forms of structural and cultural violence coexist with a very strong sense of family, community, and cooperative networks. In Colombia, interpersonal relations are easily established, and people are renowned for their friendliness and warmth. More impressively, in the face of conflict, entire communities have established themselves as "peace areas," where participants in conflict are not allowed to use the territory as part of the war scenario or involve members of the community in it. Additionally, there are many efforts involving peace building, campaigns for human rights, expanding participation in the public sector, and improving social services . Finally, many other informal forms of solidarity exist among ordinary people as they go about their daily lives. Ultimately, this observation explains why a war-torn society does not collapse. The existence of peace does not count on the partial or total abolition of violence or war. There is peace amidst great violence; there is violence associated with fighting for peace. In the same way, it is unrealistic to believe that the more likely peace, the less likely violence, and vice versa. In fact, both phenomena can increase or decrease simultaneously, or can be present at the same time and place. Viewing peace and violence as coexisting has practical consequences. Rather than opposing extremes of a continuum like different ends of the same cotton string peace and violence each make cotton strings of their own. And both peace and violence, together with many other social entities, wave the fabric of life. Stefan Bauschard Offensive PKOs release 43 Perm Solves – Exclusive Focus Bad Inclusive solutions for peace are preferable to exclusive notions – Do both solves Duncan 2 (Grace, Student of Peace and Conflict, School of Political Science and International Studies, UQ, Winter, “Peace, Action and Consequences”, http://web.ebscohost.com/ehost/pdf?vid=9&hid=7&sid=fbf7951e-fa9b-4ac2-ba3b2c07e8326bd2%40sessionmgr2) This theory is based on a few key ideas. First, it rests on the assumption that ‘global problems’ such as genocide, war and poverty are ultimately the result of human failings and imperfections. This is a psychological, rather than a political or structural understanding of the world. By that I mean that while institutions, economies, ideas and perceptions obviously play a central role in creating or destroying peace, they are understood to have been constructed by previous societies, by human beings with psychological motivations that are not dissimilar from our own. The power of economic forces, for example, could be seen as the power of greed and fear of poverty. The power of nationalism derives from the human desire to be accepted and protected within a group. Through this understanding of the world, it can be seen that people have a profound ability to determine their collective destiny. Just as the present condition of society was constructed by the past, so the future condition will be created by the present. Second, negative peace and positive peace will be considered as existing along a continuum. While negative peace is merely the absence of armed conflict, positive peace is much more. Drawing upon Johan Galtung’s (1969) definition, positive peace will be taken to mean a condition in which no human being is influenced so that their physical and mental realizations are below their potential realizations. While it may seem somewhat utopian, this definition is useful for describing the aim of an action. Thus, this discussion includes under its umbrella of ‘action for peace’ any act that could conceivably lead to such a condition and contribute to a more peaceful world. Exclusive focus on either form of violence is worse – Examining both solves their impacts Schnabel (Albrecht, Senior Research Fellow at Swiss peace and a Lecturer in International Organizations and Conflict Management at the University of Bern Institute of Political Science, “The human security approach to direct and structural violence” http://www.sipri.org/yearbook/2008/files/SIPRIYB0802C.pdf) Galtung’s differentiation between direct and structural violence is not an undisputed approach, but it makes sense in the context of human security analysis. If human security generally means ‘the security of people— their physical safety, their economic well-being, respect for their dignity and worth as human beings, and the protection of their human rights and fundamental freedoms’,9 then threats experienced by individuals and communities that are part of specific social, cultural, economic and political communities are not limited to direct armed violence. Such threats may be overt expressions of violence committed by specific and identifiable actors or covert expressions of violence inherent in the disadvantaged position of individuals and communities in a social, political or economic system that is upheld by power structures beyond their control. Without violence there is greater potential to provide and meet at least basic human needs, and to develop possibilities to satisfy needs that determine not only survival but also well-being and quality of life. Galtung seems to have sensed the need to give greater consideration to the structural aspects and sources of violence and to shift exclusive (or primary) focus, particularly by governments, from the prevention of direct violence to the prevention of structural violence. Whether done voluntarily due to a sense of national and international responsibility or forced by others promoting such norms, such a shift would lower violence and increase human security. Stefan Bauschard Offensive PKOs release 44 Perm Solves – Links Idealistic conceptions of peace do not need to exclude external manifestations of war and political changes to avert them Rinehart 95 (Milton, July, “Title: Understanding the concept of `peace'”, Peace & Change, 01490508, Vol. 20, Issue 3, ) The Numinar paradigm includes concepts of peace that are more idealistic, intra- and interpersonal, both internal and external. Peace is idealistic in that nonmaterial goals and processes are valued. Peace is not necessarily related to economic prosperity. In addition, peace is idealistic in that it is constructed and maintained through social processes that can be progressively revised. Peace is intra- and interpersonal in that the best level at which to begin peacemaking is internal. Peace must first exist within the individual in his or her relationship to others; peace is more the product of interactional patterns or subjective states than of social structures. Yet external concepts of peace are not excluded. Social systems must also be changed. The problem of peace is the problem of the internal, but shared, subjective states of people: the manner in which we interpret each other's actions and the value preferences that underlie our own actions. Cox comments, "To make peace with people, we need to understand them. To understand them, we need to engage in a holistic and participatory research which treats social reality as structured in purposive, value-laden, institutional and non-axiomizable ways."[19] We don’t preclude an interest in structural violence Rinehart 95 (Milton, July, “Title: Understanding the concept of `peace'”, Peace & Change, 01490508, Vol. 20, Issue 3, ) For example, Galtung and Gandhi represent the fuzzy area in between the peace paradigms. Galtung's social justice concept suggests the creation of intra- and interpersonal peace by changing the social structures that prohibit the possibility of such peace. Here the ends appear Numinar, but the means are clearly Popular. Further, I have argued in this article that the worldview hidden beneath this concept remains fear based while containing some degree of faith in human potential. Their alternative is additive – Doesn’t exclude our conception of war Rinehart 95 (Milton, July, “Title: Understanding the concept of `peace'”, Peace & Change, 01490508, Vol. 20, Issue 3, ) Even though I have used some opposing terms to contrast the Popular and the Numinar paradigms, they do not appear to be dialectically related as polar opposites. Rather, the Numinar appears to integrate yet go beyond the Popular in some key ways. First, although the emphasis on peacemaking in the Numinar view is on the intra- and interpersonal level, the need for structural change is accepted. Peace is found through the integration of both internal and external processes. Second, the idealistic peace of the Numinar is not the antithesis of the materialistic peace of the Popular. Rather, it subsumes the material aspects of social reality in the larger process of the reconstruction of that reality. Stefan Bauschard Offensive PKOs release 45 Perm Solves – A2: Co-optation Defense posture doesn’t preclude solutions to structural violence Groten and Jansen 81 (Hubert and Juergen, Doctorate in International Studies and Peace Lobbyist, “Interpreters and Lobbies for Positive Peace”, Journal of Peace Research, Vol. 18, No. 2, Special Issue on Theories of Peace 175-181, Sage Publications, http://www.jstor.org/stable/424209, A.D.: 7/9/09) In the absence of any even partly suc- cessful alternative procedure, there is nothing to lose if we suggest the following: Interpreters and go-betweens are needed to communicate the important message of critical peace research to the people. They must be women or men who can relate to both groups, or can be brought to do so. The group of people closest to the workers be- cause they are together on the job and have other things in common are what we might call 'skilled workers'. In the general way we suggest this term be used it applies to all oc- cupations. The 'skilled worker' would also be in a good position to collaborate with committed peace researchers towards the common goal. Thus the 'skilled worker' could be a medium and a contact for both sides involved. She or he would act as an interpreter and a link between the mass of democratic voters, the niches of democratic workers and the peace researchers. She or he would be the vital link in a network of people of good will united under the com- mon aim of communicating to the voters what peace research has to say about struc- tural violence and positive peace and about possible activities. There would be com- munication among all those involved but the main job would lie with the 'skilled workers', i. e., to pass on the information to the people at work. This network of people of good will would have to be loosely organized. Most emphatically it would not be a state organization. It would not engage in research as such. Rather, it would draw on the findings of critical peace research and transpose them to other levels of thinking and language use . 'Skilled workers' would be essential. Trade unions could help to prepare them. School teachers could be in it, though not qua school teachers. The local and regional press would be instrumental in communicat- ing information and raising consciousness. This may sound utopian but there is no harm in trying this road. Civic action groups have proved through their involvement in ecology that a group of dedicated people can influence politics. It is not the group itself, or in our case the network, that can influence high politics but they can form lobbies that are sure to find some politicians who are glad to bring their influence to bear on high politics once they receive support from their voters. Even small groups could produce results to begin with. And once there are results it is never difficult to find more dedicated people among all those whose main concern is positive peace. Peace researchers know there is structural violence and that we must work for positive peace. They only need people of good will to help them pass on this knowledge to those who can decide by using their democratic vote. Interpreters and lobbies ought to be used as links. Perhaps this will work. Eschewing security proposals won’t create positive peace and security plans aren’t coopted Jahn 83 (Egbert, Author of “Nationalism in Late and Post-Communist Europe: Nationalism in the Nation States” and Doctor of Relations, “Peace Research and Politics within the Field of Societal Demands”, Journal of Peace Research, Vol. 20, No. 3, Sage Publications, http://www.jstor.org/stable/423797, A.D.: 7/9/09) JH Peace cannot be the result of just one policy , but of different and opposing policies. Otherwise, an absolute world dictatorship would be the precondition which would merely make the will of others an object of a peace dictator. That is why the label 'German peace research' is as absurd as for example social- liberal peace research. The very day when peace research agrees with German foreign policy either total world peace will have come true, or - and this is more probable - the scientific death of peace research will have come. Peace research which corresponds completely to the policy of a national govern- ment, a party or a peace organization is no more than peace ideology. Peace research has to keep permanent distance to a policy with peace intentions and to question national, partisan and bureaucratic prejudices which blur scientific reasoning. This cannot be accomplished without distance to everyday politics. Without effective leisure, time and work no scientific reasoning is possible. Therefore, I would like to have at least one room in the ivory tower devoted to applied science within the turmoil of political expec- tations and attacks. Distance does not imply shunning contacts with parties, government departments and peace organizations. On the contrary, without an approach to and knowl- edge of political life in detail, one cannot observe at a suitable distance; at best one would reject politics out of prejudice. Value- oriented peace research is a science which draws its questions and problems from society and takes no refuge in the ivory tower. How- ever, peace research cannot let itself be directed by societal expectations. There must be an appreciation of the fact that peace research cannot formulate a scientifically well-founded analysis with regard to every violent incident on earth. Peace researchers may utter political statements concerning Afghanistan, El Salvador or the NATO decision on the moderniza- tion of missiles in Europe, but then they do not act as scientists, but as politicians with the borrowed reputation of their scientific institu- tion or their function. Stefan Bauschard Offensive PKOs release 46 Perm Solves – Militarism The permutation prevents a military-focus, prescribing nuanced solutions Schnabel 7 (Albrecht, Senior Research Fellow at Swiss peace and a Lecturer in International Organizations and Conflict Management at the University of Bern Institute of Political Science, “The human security approach to direct and structural violence” http://www.sipri.org/yearbook/2008/files/SIPRIYB0802C.pdf) As discussed in the previous section, the human security concept implies that the provision of human security requirements is largely the responsibility of states. Many states need to rethink and refocus their security policies and systems in order to provide effective human security for their population and—in cooperation with other states and coordinated by intergovernmental organizations—assist or encourage states that lack the necessary capacities to follow suit. The ‘responsibility to protect’ concept seems a suitable response to these calls for the provision of universal human security. Yet it is for this very reason that scepticism prevails about the legality of a new norm that considers human security as an innate right and the provision of human security as the responsibility of states. Such expectations seem to be at odds with states’ rights to sovereignty and non-intervention. Protagonists of the concept point out that their work—and the accompanying evolving global norm—applies only to direct violence and, in that context, the extreme action of military intervention under the responsibility to protect concept is concerned only with the most grievous crimes: mass atrocities and genocide. However, the basic assumptions of the concept justifying measures short of military intervention are applicable to direct violence in more general terms and to structural violence ‘committed’ by national and international cultural, social, economic and political structures—a major paradigm shift in international norms and values Focusing on both provides balanced solutions Schnabel 7 (Albrecht, Senior Research Fellow at Swiss peace and a Lecturer in International Organizations and Conflict Management at the University of Bern Institute of Political Science, “The human security approach to direct and structural violence” http://www.sipri.org/yearbook/2008/files/SIPRIYB0802C.pdf) Galtung argues that ‘there is no reason to believe that the future will not bring us richer concepts and more forms of social action that combine absence of personal violence with [the] fight against social injustice [i.e. negative and positive peace] once sufficient activity is put into research and practice’. This appendix suggests that human security may well be the concept that offers this opportunity. Focusing on the impact that both types of violence have on the human security of individuals and communities, without prejudicing one over the other in terms of strategic, political or economic significance, allows a more effective focus on the basic needs of individuals, compared to the security needs of states as expressed in more traditional national security thinking. This approach responds to one of the original components of the human security concept: that national and international political and security structures should consider human security equally important to national security. At this juncture, the human security concept is able to advance the distinctions between direct and structural violence and between negative and positive peace. In combination with a heightened sense of (or a moral and legal call for) responsibility by human security providers—those who govern individuals and communities, the referent objects of human security—both accountability and responsibility for the prevention of human insecurity might eventually enter the theory and practice of international law and custom. Stefan Bauschard Offensive PKOs release 47 We’re a Prereq to the Alt Events of war preclude solutions to structural violence – No alt without our action Rabie 94 (Mohamed, professor of International political economy, Georgetown University, Praeger, “Conflict Resolution and Ethnicity”, 1994, http://www.questiaschool.com/read/14788166?title=Conflict%20Resolution%20and%20E thnicity, AD; 7/11/9) TR In countries where democracy does not exist and where the control of authoritarian states over peoples' lives and fortunes is real, the nonviolent resolution and prosecution of political conflict is an impossibility because violence is the major tool of the oppressor rather than the oppressed. Democratization as the first order of concern, which the proponents of a limited definition of peace further advocate, cannot be effected without freedom and liberty, two conditions for access to cherished values. Therefore, a realistic definition of peace ought to take both arguments into consideration. This is particularly important since the proponents of positive peace tend to view it more as a process and less as a stationary state of political affairs, while the others see it generally in opposite terms. In fact, human experience seems to indicate that the absence of war and violence cannot be maintained without social justice, and social justice cannot be achieved under conditions of war and violence. Consequently, an operational definition of realistic peace would probably describe it as the absence of violence under conditions and relationships that provide for the nonviolent resolution of political conflict and the freedom to pursue legitimate individual and group goals without threat or coercion. Peace, to be real and human, must be understood and employed as a continuous process to lessen social tension, resolve political conflict, and create conditions to pursue freedom and justice through a gradual evolution of human perceptions and socio-political institutions. Thus, a strategy for universal peace must deal not only with war but also with the very forces and conditions that cause the eruption of war and induce the spread of violence in the first place. It must also strive to change a people's perceptions of the other in order to humanize the adversary, acknowledge his grievances, and legitimize his basic concerns. Above all, it must lay the foundation for transforming existing group relationships and state and civil society institutions, with a view to creating new more dynamic ones committed to promoting compatible visions and values with developing shared interests. War causes structural violence Schnabel 7 (Albrecht, Senior Research Fellow at Swiss peace and a Lecturer in International Organizations and Conflict Management at the University of Bern Institute of Political Science, “The human security approach to direct and structural violence” http://www.sipri.org/yearbook/2008/files/SIPRIYB0802C.pdf) Among the causes of insecurity, armed violence is a factor of unique significance because it: (a) causes human insecurity and prevents the adequate provision of human security through its debilitating direct and indirect effects; (b) acts as an accelerator of human insecurity, with knock-on effects that increase the negative impact of existing levels of violence and harm; and (c) is often the articulation of underlying, protracted and unresolved structural violence and thus an indicator of societal and political instability. Armed violence is a highly visible pointer to the long overdue necessity of addressing structural violence and its manifestations. Stefan Bauschard Offensive PKOs release Pro – Imperialism Answers 48 Stefan Bauschard Offensive PKOs release 49 Imperialism Good Imperialism does more good than bad Boot 03 (Max, Jeane J. Kirkpatrick Senior Fellow for National Security Studies, “U.S. Imperialism: A Force for Good” May 13, 2003, http://www.cfr.org/iraq/us-imperialism-force-good/p5959) While the formal empire mostly disappeared after the Second World War, the United States set out on another bout of imperialism in Germany and Japan. Oh, sorry -- that wasn't imperialism; it was "occupation." But when Americans are running foreign governments, it's a distinction without a difference. Likewise, recent "nation-building" experiments in Somalia, Haiti, Bosnia, Kosovo and Afghanistan are imperialism under another name. ¶ Mind you, this is not meant as a condemnation. The history of American imperialism is hardly one of unadorned good doing; there have been plenty of shameful episodes, such as the mistreatment of the Indians. But, on the whole, U.S. imperialism has been the greatest force for good in the world during the past century. It has defeated the monstrous evils of communism and Nazism and lesser evils such as the Taliban and Serbian ethnic cleansing. Along the way, it has helped spread liberal institutions to countries as diverse as South Korea and Panama.¶ Yet, while generally successful as imperialists, Americans have been loath to confirm that's what they were doing. That's OK. Given the historical baggage that "imperialism" carries, there's no need for the U.S. government to embrace the term. But it should definitely embrace the practice.¶ That doesn't mean looting Iraq of its natural resources; nothing could be more destructive of the goal of building a stable government in Baghdad. It means imposing the rule of law, property rights, free speech and other guarantees, at gunpoint if need be. This will require selecting a new ruler who is committed to pluralism and then backing him or her to the hilt. Iran and other neighbouring states won't hesitate to impose their despotic views on Iraq; we shouldn't hesitate to impose our democratic views. Imperialism is needed to maintain order FERGUSON 04 (NIALL, Professor of History at Harvard University, “A World Without Power” JULY 1, 2004, http://www.foreignpolicy.com/articles/2004/07/01/a_world_without_power?page=full) Critics of U.S. global dominance should pause and consider the alternative. If the United States retreats from its hegemonic role, who would supplant it? Not Europe, not China, not the Muslim world -- and certainly not the United Nations. Unfortunately, the alternative to a single superpower is not a multilateral utopia, but the anarchic nightmare of a new Dark Age. ¶ We tend to assume that power, like nature, abhors a vacuum. In the history of world politics, it seems, someone is always the hegemon, or bidding to become it. Today, it is the United States; a century ago, it was the United Kingdom. Before that, it was France, Spain, and so on. The famed 19thcentury German historian Leopold von Ranke, doyen of the study of statecraft, portrayed modern European history as an incessant struggle for mastery, in which a balance of power was possible only through recurrent conflict.¶ The influence of economics on the study of diplomacy only seems to confirm the notion that history is a competition between rival powers. In his bestselling 1987 work, The Rise and Fall of the Great Powers: Economic Change and Military Conflict from 1500 to 2000, Yale University historian Paul Kennedy concluded that, like all past empires, the U.S. and Russian superpowers would inevitably succumb to overstretch. But their place would soon be usurped, Kennedy argued, by the rising powers of China and Japan, both still unencumbered by the dead weight of imperial military commitments. ¶ In his 2001 book, The Tragedy of Great Power Politics, University of Chicago political scientist John J. Mearsheimer updates Kennedy's account. Having failed to succumb to overstretch, and after surviving the German and Japanese challenges, he argues, the United States must now brace for the ascent of new rivals. "[A] rising China is the most dangerous potential threat to the United States in the early twenty-first century," contends Mearsheimer. "[T]he United States has a profound interest in seeing Chinese economic growth slow considerably in the years ahead." China is not the only threat Mearsheimer foresees. The European Union (EU) too has the potential to become "a formidable rival." ¶ Power, in other words, is not a natural monopoly; the struggle for mastery is both perennial and universal. The "unipolarity" identified by some commentators following the Soviet collapse cannot last much longer, for the simple reason that history hates a hyperpower. Sooner or later, challengers will emerge, and back we must go to a multipolar, multipower world.¶ But what if these esteemed theorists are all wrong? What if the world is actually heading for a period when there is no hegemon? What if, instead of a balance of power, there is an absence of power?¶ Such a situation is not unknown in history. Although the chroniclers of the past have long been preoccupied with the achievements of great powers -whether civilizations, empires, or nation-states -- they have not wholly overlooked eras when power receded.¶ Unfortunately, the world's experience with power vacuums (eras of "apolarity," if you will) is hardly encouraging. Anyone who dislikes U.S. hegemony should bear in mind that, rather than a multipolar world of competing great powers, a world with no hegemon at all may be the real alternative to U.S. primacy. Apolarity could turn out to mean an anarchic new Dark Age: an era of waning empires and religious fanaticism; of endemic plunder and pillage in the world's forgotten regions; of economic stagnation and civilization's retreat into a few fortified enclaves. Stefan Bauschard Offensive PKOs release 50 American imperialism is awesome Miller 11 (Harrison, head writer and research for The Miller Monitor, “Justifying Imperialism” December 21, 2011, https://sites.google.com/a/ncps-k12.org/amhnews-h-miller-2011/intellectual/justifying-imperialism) United States imperialism began in the late 1800s and since its inception Americans have been debating the moral validity behind the idea. Through the tenacious leadership of American presidents, the United States has been influencing other countries in political, economic, and cultural ways. The effects of United States imperialism have been positive and justify the concept because the ideals of democracy have been spread to the nations of Panama and the Philippines, and Puerto Rico continue to be positively influenced by American politics, economy, and culture.¶ Since interaction began between America and Panama in the early twentieth century we have been able to see how both parties benefit from the United States intervention. America originally went into Panama because they wanted to build the Panama Canal. The Panama Canal would benefit the United States in trade because it was a good passageway between the Atlantic and Pacific oceans - it could save Americans time and money. However, Columbia owned Panama at the time, and would not let the United States build and use a canal in Panama; Panama, displeased with Columbia’s rule in their country, turned to the United States for help. Once independent, Panama granted America the canal and both nations walked away from the situation very pleased. America stayed in Panama to build and use the canal until 1977, when the Panamanians wanted to be fully independent. In 1989, however, the United States helped Panama overthrow the dictator Noriega and restored democracy to the Central American nation. The United States has stayed in Panama ever since, and the Panamanians are happy with their involvement because America has helped them maintain both liberty and democracy.¶ Panama is just one example; America has also maintained freedom and democracy in Puerto Rico. The United States originally became involved in Puerto Rico as a result of the Spanish American War. They gained Puerto Rico from the war, and helped Puerto Rico by guiding them and controlling the island's politics and economics for the first few years of independence. Times have changed, and, Puerto Rico has become a commonwealth; they have their own their own government, we support them economically. Politically, Puerto Rico’s government is democratic due to the exposure the island received in prior years from the United States. The democratic government ensures that all Puerto Ricans are free and equal and entitled to suffrage. Without America’s involvement, Puerto Rico might not have become the democracy that it is today; America spread democracy to them, and perhaps there is one less dictatorship because of that. ¶ Although America is no longer taking over other countries as much as they used to in the twentieth century, but a different kind of imperialism still exists – cultural imperialism. Cultural imperialism is the promotion of American beliefs in morals through the growth of our industry in other nations. While some say that cultural imperialism does not affect other countries positively, it is clear that there many benefits linked to cultural imperialism. Those who don't support imperialism believe that America needs to listen to Gandhi, who said that “I want the culture of all lands to be blown about my house as freely as possible. But I refuse to be blown off my feet by any”. While the quote has its truths, this is indeed and opinion that can easily be argued. Gandhi is saying that he is open to learning about other cultures, but doesn’t want to be forced to take part in one. However, America is not forcing anyone to take part in their culture and has not in the past; countries like France and China have limited American cultural programming through satellites and the Internet. With six billion people in the world, one culture taking over would be impossible. And even if it were possible, what constitutes American culture? It is my belief that our culture is just a homogenized cluster of all the cultures in the world, so in part, nations are scared to accepted a "tainted" version of their original culture? Cultural imperialism is spreading though American culture to those who want it, just as the most successful imperialism in the twentieth century resulted when countries were happy overall with American influence. The majorities of both Panama and Puerto Rico (based on a vote) are happy with the current involvement of the United States. The United States helped them economically and politically. They are both democratic, and cultural imperialism is just spreading other American beliefs through American movies goods, and brand names, to those who want them. ¶ After analyzing historical growth of the American empire, it is safe to say that there has been an overall positive affect of United States imperialism. Panama has been helped economically with the building of the canal, and the ideal of democracy made their government democratic. Puerto Rico also has a democratic government, and the United States economically supports them. Americans spread the ideal of democracy, and as a result these two countries are democratic. American cultural imperialism exists today for those countries who want to learn about American culture. Thus, the United States has positively affected other countries with the ideal of democracy, and continues to spread their culture to other countries today, justifying the validity of imperialism. Colonialism is key for democracy in underdeveloped nations Ishiyama ‘11 [John T. Ishiyama, “6. Democratization and the Global Environment”, Comparative Politics: Principles of Democracy and Democratization, April 20 2011, Wiley interscience] Stefan Bauschard Offensive PKOs release 51 An oft- cited additional “ international ” factor affecting democratic development, particularly in the developing world, is the legacy of colonialism. On the one hand, there is the extremely Eurocentric view that the spread of democracy is the political outcome of the spread of European values and traditions via colonialism (for a discussion, see Huntington, 1984 ). This is because, theoretically, the colonial power may have transmitted some of its culture and language to the colony, which in turn may have led to the emergence of a “ cooperative ” political culture, or may have left institutions that were conducive to democracy in place when the colonizing powers exited (Weiner, 1989 ). However, some scholars (Barro, 1999 ; Quainoo, 2000 ) have found no relationship between colonial heritage and democracy, while others (Lipset et al ., 1993; Clague et al. , 2001 ) fi nd that being a former British colony increases the probability that a country becomes democratic. In particular, several scholars have argued that the type of colonizer was important in explaining whether a country was able to develop into a democracy after the end of colonial rule. Myron Weiner (1989) , for instance, noted that by 1983 every country in the Third World that emerged from colonial rule since World War II with a population of at least one million (and almost all the smaller countries as well) with a continuous democratic experience was a former British colony. This would suggest that there was something about British colonial rule that made it different from the colonial administration of other European states, such as France and Belgium. Khapoya (1998) , for instance, distinguishes between two main types of colonial rule in Africa: indirect rule and direct rule. The British generally used a system of indirect rule, where the emphasis was not on the assimilation of Africans to become “ black Britishers, ” but rather to share skills, values, and culture, to “ empower ” the Africans with the ability to run their own communities. Thus, instead of assimilating the Africans as British citizens, society was segregated between the natives and the whites living in the colony. The British also employed an indirect system of administrative rule. Generally this meant that the colonial authorities would co - opt the local power structure (the kings, chiefs, or headman) and via invitations, coercion, or bribery, incorporate them into the colonial administrative structure. In return, these local elites were expected to enforce laws, collect taxes, and serve as the “ buffer ” between the natives and colonial authorities. A positive consequence of this system of indirect rule (a system used elsewhere in the British Empire, such as in India and Malaya) was that it provided native elites with important experiences in self - rule. Further, many British colonies adopted practices that mimicked British practices such as experience with electoral, legislative, and judicial institutions (Clague et al. , 2001 ). Given this level of preparedness, then following World War II, Britain was much more willing than other colonial powers to grant independence, which in turn made the newly independent states more willing to retain the institutions the British had put into place. Thus, from this perspective, Britain seems to have left its colonies in a better situation to develop democracy later than non - British colonies. Stefan Bauschard Offensive PKOs release 52 Imperialism Ethical Imperialism breeds democratic self rule Kurtz 03 (Stanley, Senior Fellow at the Ethics and Public Policy Center, A just empire? Democratic Imperialism: A Blueprint, April 1, 2003, http://www.hoover.org/publications/policy-review/article/6426) Our commitment to political autonomy sets up a moral paradox. Even the mildest imperialism will be experienced by many as a humiliation. Yet imperialism as the midwife of democratic self-rule is an undeniable good. Liberal imperialism is thus a moral and logical scandal, a simultaneous denial and affirmation of self-rule that is impossible either to fully accept or repudiate. The counterfactual offers a way out. If democracy did not depend on colonialism, we could confidently forswear empire. But in contrast to early modern colonial history, we do know the answer to the counterfactual in the case of Iraq. After many decades of independence, there is still no democracy in Iraq. Those who attribute this fact to American policy are not persuasive, since autocracy is pervasive in the Arab world, and since America has encouraged and accepted democracies in many other regions. So the reality of Iraqi dictatorship tilts an admittedly precarious moral balance in favor of liberal imperialism. American imperialism K2 world peace Elshtain 03 (Jean Bethke, Laura Spelman Rockefeller Professor of Social and Political Ethics at the University of Chicago Divinity School, “Just War Against Terrorism” pg. 169) The heavy burden being imposed on the United States does not require that the United States remain on hairtrigger alert at every moment. But it does oblige the United States to evaluate all claims and to make a determination as to whether it can intervene effectively and in a way that does more good than harm—with the primary objective of interdiction so that democratic civil society can be built or rebuilt. This approach is better by far than those strategies of evasion and denial of the sort visible in Rwanda, in Bosnia, or in the sort of "advice" given to Americans by some of our European critics. At this point in time the possibility of international peace and stability premised on equal regard for all rests largely, though not exclusively, on American power. Many persons and powers do not like this fact, but it is inescapable. As Michael Ignatieff puts it, the "most carefree and confident empire in history now grimly confronts the question of whether it can escape Rome's ultimate fate."9 Furthermore, America's fate is tied inextricably to the fates of states and societies around the world. If large pockets of the globe start to go bad—here, there, everywhere (the infamous "failed state" syndrome)—the drain on American power and treasure will reach a point where it can no longer be borne. Intervention protects basic human rights Nardin and Pritcharal 90 (Terry- professor and head of the Political Science Department at the National University of Singapore, Kathleen D- director of community impact product development for the United Way of America, “ETHICS AND INTERVENTION: THE UNITED STATES IN GRENADA, 1983” 1990, pg 9) A second major argument in favor of intervention is based on a concern for human rights. This argument rests on the idea that a country that values democracy and individual rights should be pre-pared to act when those values are threatened, not only at home but abroad. According to this view, it is simply intolerable for a free nation to stand on the sidelines while foreign tyrants like Idi Amin and Pal Pat enslave and massacre their own unfortunate subjects. At least in extreme cases like these. unilateral intervention should be permitted if other means fall. A nation that is not in a position to intervene Itself should support those governments (like Tanzania in the case of Idi Amin) that are able to act. Stefan Bauschard Offensive PKOs release 53 Imperialism Inevitable Imperialism can’t be blamed solely on the imperialist Said 94 (Edward W., was a professor of English and Comparative Literature at Columbia University, a literary theorist, and a public intellectual, “Culture and Imperialism” May 31, 1994, pg. 19) Domination and inequities of power and wealth are perennial facts of human society. But in today's global setting they are also interpretable as having something to do with imperialism, its history, its new forms. The nations of contemporary Asia, Latin America, and Africa are politically independent but in many ways are as dominated and dependent as they were 'when ruled directly by European powers. On the one hand, this is the consequence of self-inflicted wounds, critics like V. S. Naipaul are wont to say: they (everyone knows that "they" means coloreds, wogs, niggers) are to blame for what "they" are, and it's no use droning on about the legacy of imperialism. On the other hand, blaming the Europeans sweepingly for the misfortunes of the present is not much of an alternative. What we need to do is to look at these Matters as a network of interdependent histories that it would be inaccurate and senseless to repress, useful and interesting to understand.¶ The point here is not complicated. If while sitting in Oxford, Paris, or New York you tell Arabs or Africans that they belong to a basically sick or unregenerate culture, you are unlikely to convince them. Even if you prevail over them, they are not going to concede to you your essential superiority or your right to rule them despite your evident wealth and power. The history of this standoff is manifest throughout colonies where white masters were once unchallenged but finally driven out. Conversely, the triumphant natives soon enough found that they needed the West and that the idea of fatal independence was a nationalist fiction designed mainly for what Fanon calls the "nationalist bourgeoisie," who in turn often ran the new countries with a callous, exploitative tyranny reminiscent of the departed masters. Stefan Bauschard Offensive PKOs release Con -- Offensive Peacekeeping Bad 54 Stefan Bauschard Offensive PKOs release 55 Militarism/Colonialism Offensive peacekeeping embraces militarism and colonialism East African, April 26, 2014, intervention missions Partiality dilemma: The new model of UN Since then, the UN has swung like a pendulum in both theory and praxis from its traditional non-combative and "neutral" peacekeeping model to a new militaristic approach that has seen its forces embroiled in combat in African theatres of war. This follows a new tendency by major global powers at the helm of the United Nations Security Council to pursue a more militaristic approach, which is turning UN missions into "combative peacekeeping." This has fuelled scepticism about the neutrality of UN missions and the behind-the-scenes role of former European colonial powers in these missions. Stefan Bauschard Offensive PKOs release 56 Don’t Solve Violence Offensive peacekeeping can’t resolve the structural causes of violence East African, April 26, 2014, intervention missions Partiality dilemma: The new model of UN But the new UN interventionism has its fierce critics. Jean-Marie Guehenno, the United Nations peacekeeping chief from 2000 to 2008, has cautioned against the thinking that a combative mission will resolve conflicts in Africa, particularly Congo's quagmire. Offensive peacekeeping cannot be relied upon to resolve the structural causes of the conflicts in Somalia, South Sudan or eastern DRC, which often have regional dimensions and linkages in neighbouring countries. These pundits want the UN to pursue a solution that will involve willing heads of state from the region. They say that it is "not a SWAT team that's going to clean up a bad neighbourhood That requires politics." An offensive force could encourage the involvement of more groups News Record, July 30, 2013, “United Nations Authorizes Offensive Operations in the Democratic Republic of Congo,” http://www.newsrecord.co/united-nationsauthorizes-offensive-operations-in-the-democratic-republic-of-the-congo/ Pieter Vanholder, the DRC country director for the Life and Peace Institute, believes that attempting to accomplish these goals may result in unintended consequences. Speaking to Al-Jazeera, Vanholder explained, “The brigade may be seen as a kind of occupation force. As a consequence it could become a push factor for some to join armed groups, adding to local resistance.” Stefan Bauschard Offensive PKOs release 57 Undermine Impartiality Offensive peacekeeping kills the UN’s role as a mediator Africa Policy Brief, April 1, 2014, Partiality dilemma: The new model of UN intervention missions, http://www.africapi.org/wpcontent/uploads/2014/05/Combative-Peace-UN-Interventionism-CSP-brief-No-1-April2014.pdf DOA: 12-7-14 Also worrying experts is that the new militarism is radically changing the way the UN has been perceived in conflict situations. "The bigger danger is that when the UN becomes a combatant on the ground it loses what has been its unique role of having been a potential mediator of being the impartial outsider," said Mr Laurenti. Others feel that the shift to a combative style can compromise the image of the UN peacekeeping forces as neutral actors in conflicts. "It may compromise the neutrality and impartiality which we find essential to the organisation's peacekeeping. Its presence should be perceived by all parties as that of an honest broker, and not a potential party to the conflict," said Gert Rosenthal, the envoy of Guatemala, a non-permanent member of the UN Security Council. Lack of impartiality has undermined peacekeeping in the Sudan Africa Policy Brief, April 1, 2014, Partiality dilemma: The new model of UN intervention missions, http://www.africapi.org/wpcontent/uploads/2014/05/Combative-Peace-UN-Interventionism-CSP-brief-No-1-April2014.pdf DOA: 12-7-14 The impartiality dilemma Beyond Congo, UN interventionism is facing an "impartiality" dilemma. The role of the UN mission in South Sudan (UNMISS) has caused friction with the leaders in Juba, who are trying to quell an insurgency led by the former vice-president Riek Machar. Following the outbreak of violence in December 2013, the UN Security Council approved with unprecedented speed a request by Secretary-General Ban Ki-moon to boost the strength of the UNMISS to 12,500 troops and 1,323 police, up from 7,000 troops and 900 police. The perception of the lack of impartiality of the UN force by Juba has created acrimony. In January, South Sudan president Salva Kiir accused the UN peacekeeping mission of acting like a "parallel government" in his country. It did not help matters that in March, UN trucks that were supposedly carrying food were found to be carrying weapons and blankets that Juba suspected to be destined for the rebels. Offensive peacekeeping operations undermine UN credibility needed to resolve future crises Austin Bay, 12-13-13, Sun Journal (Lewiston, Maine), December 13, 2013 Austin Bay: U.N. trying peacekeeping with fangs But as for the U.N. ordering its well-equipped military units to destroy specific combatant factions? Critics of offensive mandates authorizing the Stefan Bauschard Offensive PKOs release 58 "neutralization" of specific factions contend, with good reason, that, when this occurs, the Security Council has overtly chosen sides. When its peacekeepers enter a sovereign country with the mandate to attack a rebel faction, the U.N. loses more than credibility as a mediator. Come the next dirty war, the critics argue, peacekeeping forces will be met as invaders. Stefan Bauschard Offensive PKOs release 59 Impartiality Impact Lack of impartiality prevents peacekeeping solvency Dr. Jeni Whalan, 2014, Partial Peace: The Politics of Taking Sides in UN Peacekeeping, Paper prepared for International Studies Association Annual Convention, Toronto, 26-29, https://www.academia.edu/6474185/Partial_Peace_The_Politics_of_Taking_Sides_in_UN_Peacekeeping DOA: 12-6-14 Lecturer in International Security and Development BA (UNSW), M.Phil (Oxon), D.Phil (Oxon) Similarly, Shashi Tharoor recognized that UN peacekeeping could not go ‘back to basics’ if it was to respond to the new security threats it faced, but nevertheless declared impartiality to be ‘the oxygen of peacekeeping’: the only way peacekeeping can work is by being trusted by both sides, being clear and transparent in their dealings, and keeping the lines of communication open. The moment they lose this trust, the moment they are seen by one side as the ‘enemy’, they become part of the problem they were sent to solve.’ Impartiality critical to consent and sustaining peacekeeping Dr. Jeni Whalan, 2014, Partial Peace: The Politics of Taking Sides in UN Peacekeeping, Paper prepared for International Studies Association Annual Convention, Toronto, 26-29, https://www.academia.edu/6474185/Partial_Peace_The_Politics_of_Taking_Sides_in_UN_Peacekeeping DOA: 12-6-14 Lecturer in International Security and Development BA (UNSW), M.Phil (Oxon), D.Phil (Oxon) At the local level, similar diversity among the purposes of impartiality exists, as do tensions among them. First, traditional impartiality has served to make peacekeeping acceptable to relatively strong host states, sufficient that they would consent to the deployment of peacekeepers. Ensuring the consent of the host state in one operation also had implications for the viability of future peacekeeping; as Alan James noted, considerations of precedent were crucial: if a peacekeeping force gets permission to enter a state to engage in impartial and non-violent activity and then moves in the direction of partiality and violence, other prospective hosts are going to be extremely cautious about issuing invitations.71 Impartiality critical to mediation Dr. Jeni Whalan, 2014, Partial Peace: The Politics of Taking Sides in UN Peacekeeping, Paper prepared for International Studies Association Annual Convention, Toronto, 26-29, https://www.academia.edu/6474185/Partial_Peace_The_Politics_of_Taking_Sides_in_UN_Peacekeeping DOA: 12-6-14 Lecturer in International Security and Development BA (UNSW), M.Phil (Oxon), D.Phil (Oxon) The final purpose of impartiality identified at the local level is the procedural legitimation expected to come from a peacekeeping operation that can mediate between warring factions as an honest broker, fairly and without bias to any side. For example, the Force Commander of the United Nations Transitional Authority in Cambodia (UNTAC), General John Sanderson, credits this type of impartiality with the mission’s ability to win confidence among senior members of the various Cambodian factions, which provided UNTAC with a new means of influence to influence their actions.76 This impartiality purpose is most often seen in conflicts among parties who Stefan Bauschard Offensive PKOs release are relatively evenly matched, where there is not a strong international interest in the victory of one side over another, and once the conflict has reached some form of stalemate.77 Effective mediation can, in turn, be expected to produce better outcomes, such as a negotiated ceasefire with which armed groups comply, which means this approach may also have a substantive legitimation function. 60 Stefan Bauschard Offensive PKOs release 61 Undermines Humanitarianism UN taking on a combat role undermines humanitarianism Africa Policy Brief, April 1, 2014, Partiality dilemma: The new model of UN intervention missions, http://www.africapi.org/wpcontent/uploads/2014/05/Combative-Peace-UN-Interventionism-CSP-brief-No-1-April2014.pdf DOA: 12-7-14 Criticism of UN interventionism has also come from the humanitarian aid agencies who fear that a combative UN force risks blurring the line between aid workers providing care and soldiers. "You can have a helicopter one day used to deliver the Force Intervention Brigade troops to attack a village and next day to deliver aid to that same village," said Michiel Hofman, a senior humanitarian specialist with Medicins sans Frontieres in Brussels. The UN bureaucracy can only take lightly the critics of interventionism at its own peril. In war situations, perception is everything. Interventionism hugely impacts the perception of the UN peacekeeping operations not just in Africa but globally. Offensive missions could turn aid workers into targets Sudarsan Raghavan, November 2, 2013, Washington Post, Raghavan has been The Post's Kabul bureau chief since 2014. He was previously based in Nairobi and Baghdad for the Post, In Volatile Congo, A New UN Force with Teeth, http://www.washingtonpost.com/world/africa/in-volatile-congo-a-new-un-forcewith-teeth/2013/11/01/0cda650c-423f-11e3-b028-de922d7a3f47_story.html DOA: 12-514 But the force is also an unparalleled gamble for the United Nations that challenges the basic principles of peacekeeping. It has orders to react offensively to enforce peace, essentially transforming peacekeepers into combatants. And it is openly supporting Congolese government forces, a move away from the principle of neutrality that has guided other U.N. missions. That could affect the United Nations’ ability to negotiate peace deals with the militias and risks deepening conflicts. Humanitarian agencies are worried that Congo’s brutal militias could see the entire U.N. mission, which also includes aid workers, monitors and civilian experts, as non-neutral potential targets. Stefan Bauschard Offensive PKOs release 62 Nationalism UN militarism in Africa triggers nationalism Africa Policy Brief, April 1, 2014, Partiality dilemma: The new model of UN intervention missions, http://www.africapi.org/wpcontent/uploads/2014/05/Combative-Peace-UN-Interventionism-CSP-brief-No-1-April2014.pdf DOA: 12-7-14 Although Africa is unlikely to resist external players in situations like the CAR, growing perceptions of increased UN militarism on the continent are likely to stir residual nationalism against external intervention. In recent decades, the continent, through the AU, has grown increasingly assertive of its independence vis-a-vis former colonial powers and the West. Stefan Bauschard Offensive PKOs release 63 Inconsistent With Peacekeeping Values Offensive PKOs inconsistent with the core principles of peacekeeping Courtney Brooks, March 28, 2013, Explainer: UN Move to Give Peacekeepers First Ever Combat Mandate, http://www.rferl.org/content/un-peacekeepers-combatresolution/24941095.html DOA: 12-5-14 Even though peacekeeping is nowhere to be found in the Charter of the United Nations, the UN has performed almost 70 peacekeeping operations to date. Thought of as existing between Chapter VI and VII, or Chapter VI ., peacekeeping was envisioned as a method to stave off wars and conflict in the hopes of pacific settlement of disputes in order to maintain international peace and security. All peacekeeping operations (PKOs) operate under three principles: (1) State parties consent to the PKO, (2) Peacekeepers are impartial observers, and (3) Use of force is prohibited except in self-defense and or if permitted under the mandate provided by the Security Council. UN Peacekeeping operations are only approved by the Security Council and may sometimes work in tandem with PKOs authorized by Regional Organizations. Stefan Bauschard Offensive PKOs release 64 Undermines Support for Peacekeeping It is difficult to get commitments to peacekeeping involving offensive PKOs Dr. Jeni Whalan, 2014, Partial Peace: The Politics of Taking Sides in UN Peacekeeping, Paper prepared for International Studies Association Annual Convention, Toronto, 26-29, https://www.academia.edu/6474185/Partial_Peace_The_Politics_of_Taking_Sides_in_UN_Peacekeeping DOA: 12-6-14 Lecturer in International Security and Development BA (UNSW), M.Phil (Oxon), D.Phil (Oxon) Substantively, robust peacekeepers operating under ‘new impartiality’ are intended to deliver on the expectations and promises implicit in peacekeeping: that they will protect populations, keep the peace, and deter conflict. But the procedural legitimacy of ‘new’ impartiality is more contested. First, it has been less acceptable to loose coalition of the UN’s most significant troop contributing countries. UN peacekeepers today are supplied overwhelmingly by developing countries; in recent years, Pakistan, Bangladesh and India have collectively contributed the lion’s share.55 These troop contributing countries have broadly resisted calls to accept the greater risks involved in using force in peacekeeping operations, and have regularly invoked the principle of impartiality to question such practice of ‘taking sides’. Dr. Jeni Whalan, 2014, Partial Peace: The Politics of Taking Sides in UN Peacekeeping, Paper prepared for International Studies Association Annual Convention, Toronto, 26-29, https://www.academia.edu/6474185/Partial_Peace_The_Politics_of_Taking_Sides_in_UN_Peacekeeping DOA: 12-6-14 Lecturer in International Security and Development BA (UNSW), M.Phil (Oxon), D.Phil (Oxon) Third, the traditional notion of impartiality is attractive to those countries that contribute the vast majority of UN peacekeepers, because it minimizes the risk to their security; becoming a belligerent party also means that peacekeepers become ‘targets for retaliation’.65 Since the Security Council’s peacekeeping decisions rely entirely for their implementation on the willingness of UN member states to contribute forces to a mission, it must also take into account the perceptions of troop contributing countries regarding the acceptability and appropriateness of the peacekeeping enterprise. For their part, member states derive a number of benefits from their contribution of troops to UN peacekeeping, but remain ‘highly sensitive’ to the character of these operations: Naturally, all contributing countries want to avoid casualties and hence exhibit greater reluctance to contribute troops to missions that are thought overly dangerous. Contributing states thus typically assess the degree of host government consent for a mission and might be deterred from participating in operations where this is questionable... National publics are also frequently intolerant of casualties sustained on peacekeeping operations. This poses a particular challenge to the emerging concept of ‘robust peacekeeping.66 Offensive PKOs reduce support for peacekeeping News Record, July 30, 2013, “United Nations Authorizes Offensive Operations in the Democratic Republic of Congo,” http://www.newsrecord.co/united-nationsauthorizes-offensive-operations-in-the-democratic-republic-of-the-congo/ Furthermore, most countries that supply troops for peacekeeping missions do so with the expectation of limiting casualties. Placing peacekeepers in a Stefan Bauschard Offensive PKOs release fighting role may make supplying troops less attractive for U.N. member states. 65 Stefan Bauschard Offensive PKOs release 66 Snowball One offensive intervention sets a precedent for another Brett D. Schaefer, is Jay Kingham Fellow in International Regulatory Affairs in the Margaret Thatch, April 10, 2013, Center for Freedom, a division of the Kathryn and Shelby Cullom Davis Institute for International Studies, at The Heritage Foundation and editor of ConUNdrum: The Limits of the United Nations and the Search for Alternatives (Rowman & Littlefield Publishers, 2009), U.S. Should Oppose a Return to U.N. Peace Enforcement, http://www.heritage.org/research/reports/2013/04/us-should-oppose-return-to-unpeace-enforcement DOA: 12-6-14 The UNSC has authorized missions in the gray area between traditional missions and peace enforcement, including the MONUSCO operation before creation of the intervention brigade, but Resolutions 2098 and 2100 go further toward peace enforcement than the U.N. has ventured since the 1990s. The U.N. is aware of the significance of this shift and has taken pains to disguise it. Resolution 2098 explicitly establishes the intervention brigade on “an exceptional basis and without creating a precedent or any prejudice to the agreed principles of peacekeeping.” The Under-Secretary-General for Peacekeeping Operations told journalists that MINUSMA “is not an enforcement mission.” Yet the very act of creating the intervention brigade establishes a precedent for future action, and asserting that MINUSMA is not an enforcement operation cannot overcome the facts that there is no peace to keep and that peacekeepers are mandated to impose authority on behalf of the Malian government where it is either weak or absent. Stefan Bauschard Offensive PKOs release 67 Alternatives Parallel mission alternative Dr. Jeni Whalan, 2014, Partial Peace: The Politics of Taking Sides in UN Peacekeeping, Paper prepared for International Studies Association Annual Convention, Toronto, 26-29, https://www.academia.edu/6474185/Partial_Peace_The_Politics_of_Taking_Sides_in_UN_Peacekeeping DOA: 12-6-14 Lecturer in International Security and Development BA (UNSW), M.Phil (Oxon), D.Phil (Oxon) Since the mid-1990s, states willing to deploy military forces with coercive mandates to conflict zones have overwhelmingly done so through parallel missions, often with UNa uthorization but not under UN command nor operating within the UN’s own conception of peacekeepers. It is notable that the southern African states who contributed forces to MONUSCO’s intervention brigade sought initially to deploy as a parallel mission of the Southern African Development Community (SADC). UN authorized intervention forces are superior Brett D. Schaefer, is Jay Kingham Fellow in International Regulatory Affairs in the Margaret Thatch, April 10, 2013, Center for Freedom, a division of the Kathryn and Shelby Cullom Davis Institute for International Studies, at The Heritage Foundation and editor of ConUNdrum: The Limits of the United Nations and the Search for Alternatives (Rowman & Littlefield Publishers, 2009), U.S. Should Oppose a Return to U.N. Peace Enforcement, http://www.heritage.org/research/reports/2013/04/usshould-oppose-return-to-un-peace-enforcement DOA: 12-6-14 With Srebrenica and Rwanda in mind, the U.N. since 1999 has instructed its peacekeepers to protect civilians from the imminent threat of violence. These debacles also led to a reexamination of U.N. peace enforcement culminating in the Report of the Panel on United Nations Peace Operations (Brahimi report), which acknowledged the need for robust peacekeeping operations at times but also unequivocally stated: “[T]he United Nations does not wage war. Where enforcement action is required, it has consistently been entrusted to coalitions of willing States, with the authorization of the Security Council, acting under Chapter VII of the Charter.” This report has guided peacekeeping policy for over a decade. Even as U.N. peacekeeping has been assigned broader responsibilities and expanded to historic highs in personnel and expense in the 2000s,[2] the U.N. has observed the principle that it should not engage in peace enforcement operations. Indeed, the U.N. reiterated the conclusions of the Brahimi report in the 2009 A New Partnership Agenda Charting a New Horizon for UN Peacekeeping: The single most important finding of the Brahimi report was that UN peacekeeping can only succeed as part of a wider political strategy to end a conflict and with the will of the parties to implement that strategy…. Peacekeeping is not always the right answer. In situations of high political tension, or in contexts where regional or national support is lacking, prevention, mediation, peacebuilding and conflict-sensitive development activities may be more effective. In active conflict, multinational coalitions of forces or regional actors operating under UN Security Council mandates may be more suitable. Successful crisis management rests on choosing the right tools and bringing them together in ways that maximize their respective strengths. Stefan Bauschard Offensive PKOs release 68 Alternative in the Congo Brett D. Schaefer, is Jay Kingham Fellow in International Regulatory Affairs in the Margaret Thatch, April 10, 2013, Center for Freedom, a division of the Kathryn and Shelby Cullom Davis Institute for International Studies, at The Heritage Foundation and editor of ConUNdrum: The Limits of the United Nations and the Search for Alternatives (Rowman & Littlefield Publishers, 2009), U.S. Should Oppose a Return to U.N. Peace Enforcement, http://www.heritage.org/research/reports/2013/04/usshould-oppose-return-to-un-peace-enforcement DOA: 12-6-14 Neither the DRC nor Mali is ripe for U.N. peacekeeping. The positive environment from a decade ago has been squandered by DRC President Joseph Kabila with ample help from spoilers inside and outside the country.[7] There is little prospect for peace in Mali until a new government is elected that incorporates adequate representation from long-ostracized groups.[8] While elections are scheduled for July, significant challenges persist that could derail them. The Obama Administration has a responsibility not to support the most convenient options but rather to support efforts that are most likely to result in international peace and security. Instead of peace enforcement through U.N. operations, the U.S. should explore and advocate alternatives that address these situations and support a U.N. mission only when the basic principles of peacekeeping are in place. Specifically, the U.S. should shift gears and demand that the MONUSCO intervention brigade be independently commanded in a manner similar to the French force in Mali or the African Union force in Somalia. International efforts should concentrate on addressing lack of governance in the DRC, and MONUSCO should be downsized and focused on less ambitious goals of protecting and providing security for humanitarian efforts until conditions are again ripe for a more traditional U.N. peacekeeping operation. In Mali, the U.S. should delay standing up MINUSMA until conditions improve while supporting the current French and African interventions. Although the Administration makes decisions in the Security Council, those decisions have financial implications. The U.N. charges the U.S. 28.38 percent of the U.N. peacekeeping budget, including the $1.4 billion annual budget for MONUSCO (now with an additional $140 million for the intervention brigade).[9] MINUSMA is projected to cost $800 million annually which is not currently factored into fiscal year 2014 budget proposals.[10] Congress should challenge the Administration over whether the U.N. should be entrusted with these situations and ask which alternatives were explored. Stefan Bauschard Offensive PKOs release 69 Bad to Support Congo Government Government is corrupt and its forces are accused of mass rapes Sudarsan Raghavan, November 2, 2013, Washington Post, Raghavan has been The Post's Kabul bureau chief since 2014. He was previously based in Nairobi and Baghdad for the Post, In Volatile Congo, A New UN Force with Teeth, http://www.washingtonpost.com/world/africa/in-volatile-congo-a-new-un-forcewith-teeth/2013/11/01/0cda650c-423f-11e3-b028-de922d7a3f47_story.html DOA: 12-514 There are also concerns that the U.N. force is propping up a corrupt government and aiding an undisciplined military that has a history of human-rights abuses, including mass rapes. Many Congolese remain skeptical of the new brigade’s potential to eradicate the militias. Others have lofty expectations that could bring disappointment and further antagonism toward the U.N. mission. Stefan Bauschard Offensive PKOs release 70 A2: Offensive PKOs Necessary to Stop Rebel Groups Defeat of M23 hasn’t deterred other groups Dr Robert Besseling, January 1, 2014, Besseling is a Senior Political Adviser to the IHS Country Risk and Forecasting Sub-Saharan Africa team, Jane’s Intelligence Review, Elusive riches - Continued threats to the DRC's minerals trade The defeat of the M23 has not succeeded in motivating many members of other rebel groups and community-based Maï-Maï self-defence militias that operate within the region to surrender and disarm. On 3 December, UN under-secretarygeneral for peacekeeping operations Hervé Ladsous said that the FIB would engage these other armed groups. The FIB is most likely to be deployed against collaborators of the M23, including some Maï Maï groups in North and South Kivu, and other groups that operate in areas now effectively under FARDC control, such as the Alliance des Patriotes pour un Congo Libre et Souverain (APCLS), based in the town of Masisi, North Kivu, and the Union des Patriotes Congolais pour la Paix/Forces Populaires Congolaises (UPCP/FPC) in Lubero, also in North Kivu. According to the UN Group of Experts, both of these groups are involved in the mining of columbite-tantalum and gold. Stefan Bauschard Offensive PKOs release 71 A2: Necessary to Defeat Rebels Can’t defeat all of the rebel groups in the Congo Sudarsan Raghavan, November 2, 2013, Washington Post, Raghavan has been The Post's Kabul bureau chief since 2014. He was previously based in Nairobi and Baghdad for the Post, In Volatile Congo, A New UN Force with Teeth, http://www.washingtonpost.com/world/africa/in-volatile-congo-a-new-un-forcewith-teeth/2013/11/01/0cda650c-423f-11e3-b028-de922d7a3f47_story.html DOA: 12-514 U.N. officials say a political solution is still the best path forward, but in a phone interview last week, Amani Kabasha, the rebels’ political spokesman, said his group had lost trust in the U.N. mission because it was supporting Congolese forces. “Even if they kill all of the M23, another group will rise in our place,” he warned. The intervention brigade is expected to go after more than 40 other militias who are committing atrocities, stealing Congo’s mineral wealth and preventing the government from functioning — a task that seems virtually impossible. There is also the problem of perception. The Enough Project, a human-rights group, said in a report last week that the brigade “risks being seen, or being used, as a pawn of Kinshasa,” the capital. Both Kobler and Cruz said the brigade would not work with any Congolese army units that have committed human-rights abuses. They also said the brigade would work at times on its own. Stefan Bauschard Offensive PKOs release 72 Con – Militarized Approaches Fail Militarized peacekeeping fails James Sloan, June 3, 2014 is a Senior Lecturer at the University of Glasgow, School of Law, and a former adviser to a UN peace mission. His book The Militarisation of Peacekeeping in the Twenty-First Century was published in 2011 by Hart Publishing, Oxford, UN Peacekeeping in Darfur: A ‘Quagmare’ That We Cannot Accept, http://www.e-ir.info/2014/06/03/un-peacekeeping-in-darfur-a-quagmire-that-we-cannotaccept/ As the author of a 2011 book lamenting the change in direction in UN peacekeeping since the turn of the century and warning that such operations would almost certainly fail, I was not surprised to read the articles. Deeply disturbed, of course, but not surprised. UNAMID is an example of a ‘militarized peacekeeping’ operation—also known as ‘Chapter VII peacekeeping’, ‘robust peacekeeping’, or ‘muscular peacekeeping’—a type of operation that has routinely been authorized by the Security Council since the late 1990s. The operations represent an attempt by the Security Council to prevent the recurrence of a Rwanda-type situation, where mass atrocities occurred in the presence of a UN peacekeeping operation, by moving away from the traditional policy that force may only be used by peacekeepers in selfdefense (or, sometimes, in defense of the mandate of the force), in favour of a policy authorizing the use of offensive force to protect civilians and others. As I argued in 2011, this type of operation is unlikely to be successful. Why Isn’t It Working? The argument put forward in my book is, in a nutshell, that UN peacekeeping operations are ill-suited to operations requiring the use of offensive force: they lack the personnel, the equipment, and the effective leadership required. Moreover, the tradition that peacekeeping operations may only operate with the consent and cooperation of the government of the host state means that it is extremely difficult for a militarized peacekeeping force to be even-handed in its resort to force: if it were to use force against the host state—even if the government of the host state was acting contrary to the interests of its civilian population—it would lose that government’s good will and its continued operation in the state would be extremely difficult. Stefan Bauschard Offensive PKOs release 73 It is generally agreed that the handful of peacekeeping operations in the 20th century that were vested with enforcement powers were disastrous; they were unable to achieve their mandated tasks and brought the Organization into disrepute. Examples here include ONUC (a peacekeeping operation in the Congo in the early 1960s) and two ill-fated operations in the 1990s: UNPROFOR, a peacekeeping operation charged with protecting civilians in ‘safe areas’ in the former Yugoslavia (including, tragically, the ‘safe area’ of Srebrenica where some 8,000 thousand men and boys were murdered while peacekeepers were pushed to one side), and UNOSOM II, a peacekeeping operation charged with using force to prevent the resumption of violence in Somalia (which withdrew in ignominy following the deaths of 18 US soldiers and over 25 UN peacekeepers). Of course, the UN did not use force in its peacekeeping operation in Rwanda— despite it being advocated by its ground commander, Canadian General Romeo Dallaire, in the months before the genocide broke out. Permission to use force was denied by the UN Secretariat on the basis that it was not provided for in the operation’s Security Council mandate. The stain left on the reputation of the UN by the Rwandan genocide was deep. With a view to ensuring that nothing in the nature of the Rwandan genocide occurred ‘under the noses’ of UN peacekeepers, the idea that peacekeeping operations should routinely be mandated to use offensive force in certain circumstances gained favour— despite the problems with earlier militarized peacekeeping operations. In 2000, the influential Brahimi Report on peacekeeping was published. On the question of the use of force by peacekeeping operations, it argued along the following lines: 1) the UN must never again stand by while civilians are killed, as had been the case with the Rwandan genocide; 2) peacekeepers must be made ‘robust’ and charged with taking sides—they must never again be mere ‘appeasers’; and 3) only once a sufficient number of well-trained and wellequipped peacekeepers have been contributed by states should the Security Council establish and deploy an operation. The first element of the argument is laudable: the UN must certainly not stand idly by in the face of mass atrocities. However, matters fall apart when one gets to the second and third elements. Simply adding a line or two to the mandates of peacekeeping operations, requiring peacekeepers to take on the unimaginably difficult task of preventing genocide or civilian harm is wildly unrealistic. The Stefan Bauschard Offensive PKOs release 74 nature of UN peacekeeping does not lend itself to the use of force: peacekeeping forces must be donated by states (and may be withdrawn by them at any time), peacekeeping forces tend to have little in the way of sophisticated equipment (that, again, in many cases, must be donated), and the command structure of peacekeeping forces is frequently problematic. For example, an order from a commander from State A may be ignored by a subordinate from State B—if that subordinate is able to have the order overruled by a government official from State B. A version of this scenario is outlined in the Foreign Policy investigation of UNAMID. The third element of the argument that emerged from the Brahimi Report, i.e., that the Security Council should wait until peacekeeping forces are sufficiently well-configured to be successful before establishing them or placing them in situ, is also problematic. It presumes a Security Council that is sufficiently circumspect to put political considerations to one side, as well as UN member states that are willing to contribute sufficient financial resources and personnel to the endeavor—despite the risk of the loss of life. It ignores the reality that many states may consider the contribution of personnel to operations where the forces will be in harm’s way to be politically damaging (the US contributes no personnel to UNAMID) and may even be begrudging when it comes to donating equipment. Moreover, it ignores the possibility that some members of the Security Council might consider it to be preferable to put in place an operation that is ill-suited to the task, rather than risk waiting until the time is right, lest they be seen to be doing nothing in the face of mass atrocity. Former Secretary-General Kofi Anan described the establishment of a militarized peacekeeping operation with a robust mandate, but little chance of fulfilling it, as creating an ‘alibi’ for the Security Council. Presumably, the idea is that if the UN is criticized for allowing another mass atrocity to occur, the Security Council can point to the fact that it did act: it established a militarized peacekeeping operation to prevent such an atrocity. In this regard, the title of the third article in the Foreign Policy investigation may be recalled: ‘A Mission That Was Set Up to Fail’. Even if we lived in a world where the leaders deciding what direction the Security Council would take were circumspect and uninfluenced by politics, and member states—including, of course, the Security Council’s permanent members—were willing to donate sufficient funding, equipment, and troops to Stefan Bauschard Offensive PKOs release 75 ensure the success of such operations, I am not convinced that assigning peacekeepers forceful tasks is a good idea. Imagine a mayor of a city with serious crime problems and an inadequate police force deciding that the way to protect the citizenry was to arm traffic wardens or ambulance attendants. While these newly robust city employees might very well prevent a number of crimes, it would not be long before they were no longer seen by the criminal population as unthreatening—instead, becoming the targets of the criminals. Militarized peacekeepers are in something of a ‘no-win’ situation: where they use force, they become the target of various forces; where they do not use force (because they are vastly outnumbered and to do so would be the equivalent of committing suicide), there is a substantial risk that the local population—which, for better or worse, has come to think of the peacekeeping force as their protector—will see them as failures or cowards. Recall the title of the first article in the Foreign Policy investigation: ‘They Just Stood Watching’. Stefan Bauschard Offensive PKOs release 76 Con – Solvency Answers No secondary support for offensive PKOs, failure collapses them David Bosco, April 1, 2013, Foreign Policy, When Peacekeepers Go to War, http://foreignpolicy.com/2013/04/01/when-peacekeepers-go-to-war/ DOA 12-6-14 Part of the problem with offensive U.N. operations is that the training and resources of the forces doing the fighting often doesn’t match the mandate. It’s one thing for the Security Council to authorize offensive operations from New York; it’s quite another thing for peacekeeping commanders to manage them successfully on the ground. During the U.N.’s Bosnia operation in the 1990s, that gap between the Council’s proclamations and the actual work of peacekeepers grew to tragic proportions. If peacekeepers get bogged down while on the offense — or, worse, commit abuses of their own — political will for the operation will likely melt away. The countries contributing the troops for the enforcement brigade may think twice. It’s doubtful that either the United States or cashstrapped European states will send their own forces to bolster peacekeepers in need of assistance. Stefan Bauschard Offensive PKOs release Con – Right to Protect (R2P) Bad 77 Stefan Bauschard Offensive PKOs release 78 Right to Protect Bad Link Offensive peacekeeping operation exist to protect civilians Midwest Model United Nations, 2013, http://mmun.files.wordpress.com/2013/12/ga4-a.pdf DOA: 12-6-14 The UN for the first time has authorized peacekeepers to conduct targeted offensive operations within the mandate of the UN Organization Stabilization Mission in the Democratic Republic of the Congo (MONUSCO). Security Council Resolution 2098 established a “Force Intervention Brigade” to assist the Democratic Republic of the Congo (DRC) in neutralizing armed groups that have been accused of sexual and gender-based violence, recruitment of child soldiers, violence against civilians, and other human rights abuses.6 These offensive operations are meant to provide protection of civilians until the DRC has created a Rapid Reaction Force that is able to take over duties from the Force Intervention Brigade. There are many critics that view the UN’s offensive operations as “peace enforcement” and that the UN may not be seen as an impartial party to the conflict in the DRC. Offensive PKOs based on the Responsibility to Protect (R2P) Midwest Model United Nations, 2013, http://mmun.files.wordpress.com/2013/12/ga4-a.pdf DOA: 12-6-14 The new mandate for offensive operations in MONUSCO has been part of a recent trend in strengthening peacekeeping’s ability to protect civilians. Protection of civilians is viewed as a key factor in the success of any peacekeeping mission. This recent trend stems from the 20045 World Summit Outcome’s endorsement of the Responsibility to Protect. The international community made a commitment to protect their own populations from genocide, war crimes, ethnic cleansing, and crimes against humanity. In places where civilians are subject to such atrocities, the international community agreed that the UN should act to protect civilians. Stefan Bauschard Offensive PKOs release 79 Right to Protect Undermines American Leadership An unconditional R2P obligation destroys US sovereignty, draining the military R2p kill us sovereignty, causes overstretch Groves 8 http://www.heritage.org/research/reports/2008/05/the-us-should-reject-the-unresponsibility-to-protect-doctrine Steven Groves works to protect and preserve American sovereignty, selfgovernance and independence as leader of The Heritage Foundation's Freedom Project. Groves, who is the Bernard and Barbara Lomas Senior Research Fellow in Heritage’s Margaret Thatcher Center for Freedom, also advocates American leadership on issues involving international political and religious freedom, human rights and democratic institutions. He has testified before Congress on international law, human rights, the United Nations and controversial treaties such as the U.N. Convention on the Law of the Sea, the Convention on the Rights of Persons with Disabilities, and the Convention on the Elimination of All Forms of Discrimination against Women. In 2013, Groves was awarded the Dr. W. Glenn and Rita Campbell Award for his work. The award is given annually to the Heritage employee who delivered “an outstanding contribution to the analysis and promotion of a free society.” Before joining Heritage in 2007, Groves was senior counsel to then-Sen. Norm Coleman (R-Minn.) on the U.S. Senate Permanent Subcommittee on Investigations. He played a lead role in the subcommittee's investigation of the U.N. "oil-for-food" scandal, the most extensive congressional probe ever conducted of the United Nations. Groves previously was an associate at Boies, Schiller & Flexner LLP, specializing in commercial litigation. Before that he served as assistant attorney general for the State of Florida, where he litigated civil rights cases, constitutional law issues and criminal appeals, among other matters, in state and federal court. Groves is a frequent guest commentator on domestic and international television and radio. He has appeared on ABC, BBC, CNBC, CNN and CNN International, Fox News Channel, National Public Radio, Voice of America, NHK, Al Jazeera, Alhurra and the Canadian Broadcasting Corp. His commentary and opinion pieces have been published by journals such as National Review, The Weekly Standard and Human Events, as well as by The Washington Times and other major newspapers across America. Groves holds a law degree from Ohio Northern University's College of Law and a bachelor of arts degree in history from Florida State University. If wholly accepted as official U.S. policy, the R2P doctrine would greatly expand U.S. obligations to prevent acts of genocide around the world. More important, adoption of R2P would effectively cede U.S. national sovereignty and decision-making power over key components of national security and foreign policy and subject them to the whims of the international community. The U.S. government, as a party to the Convention on the Prevention and Punishment of the Crime of Genocide (the Genocide Convention), is currently obligated to prevent acts of genocide that occur within U.S. territory.[29] The Genocide Convention Implementation Act of 1987 (the Proxmire Act), the legislation implementing the Genocide Convention, was signed into law by President Ronald Reagan in 1988.[30] The Proxmire Act defined the crime of genocide as an act committed "with the specific intent to destroy, in whole or in substantial part, a national, ethnic, racial, or religious group." The new law even criminalized the act of inciting another person to commit an act of Stefan Bauschard Offensive PKOs release 80 genocide.[31] Importantly, U.S. enforcement of these criminal offenses was limited to acts committed in the United States.[32] However, adoption of the R2P norm would obligate the United States to prevent all acts of genocide, ethnic cleansing, and war crimes even if they occur outside of the U.S. Such an obligation would impose unique responsibilities. As the world's preeminent military force, the United States would have to bear a disproportionate share of the R2P international commitment. In the event that acts of genocide and ethnic cleansing occur, the vast majority of nations in the international community could reasonably plead military inferiority on each such occasion, leaving the United States to bear the brunt of any intervention. Most members of the international community could also plead poverty, again leaving the United States to fund the intervention. Even if the intervention is funded through the United Nations system, the United States would still pay an unequal share of the cost.[33] The doctrinal dominance of r2p wrecks America’s global leadership BOTH structurally AND perceptually. Foreign policy must shift back to SELF-INTEREST Kaplan 8/1/13 http://nationalinterest.org/commentary/the-tragedy-us-foreign-policy-8810 Robert D. Kaplan is a foreign correspondent for The Atlantic, a senior fellow at the Center for a New American Security in Washington and a member of the Pentagon’s Defense Policy Board. His most recent book is Monsoon: The Indian Ocean and the Future of American Power (Random House, 2010). The 1990s were full of calls for humanitarian intervention: in Rwanda, which tragically went unheeded; and in Bosnia and Kosovo where interventions, while belated, were by and large successful. Free from the realpolitik necessities of the Cold War, humanitarians have in the past two decades tried to reduce foreign policy to an aspect of genocide prevention. Indeed, the Nazi Holocaust is only one lifetime removed from our own—a nanosecond in human history—and so post–Cold War foreign policy now rightly exists in the shadow of it. The codified upshot has been R2P: the “Responsibility to Protect,” the mantra of humanitarians. But American foreign policy cannot merely be defined by R2P and Never Again! Statesmen can only rarely be concerned with humanitarian interventions and protecting human rights to the exclusion of other considerations. The United States, like any nation—but especially because it is a great power—simply has interests that do not always cohere with its values. That is tragic, but it is a tragedy that has to be embraced and accepted. What are those overriding interests? The United States, as the dominant power in the Western Hemisphere, must always prevent any other power from becoming equally dominant in the Eastern Hemisphere. Moreover, as a liberal maritime power, the United States must seek to protect the sea lines of communication that enable world trade. It must also seek to protect both treaty and de facto allies, and especially their access to hydrocarbons. These are all interests that, while not necessarily contradictory to human rights, simply do not operate in the same category. Because the United States is a liberal power, its interests—even when they are not directly concerned with human rights—are generally moral. But they are only secondarily moral. For seeking to adjust the balance of power in one’s favor has been throughout history an amoral enterprise pursued by both liberal and illiberal powers. Nevertheless, when a liberal power like the United States pursues such a goal in the Stefan Bauschard Offensive PKOs release 81 service of preventing war among major states , it is acting morally in the highest sense . A telling example of this tension—one that gets to the heart of why Never Again! and R2P cannot always be the operative words in statesmanship—was recently provided by the foreign-affairs expert Leslie H. Gelb. Gelb noted that after Saddam Hussein had gassed close to seven thousand Kurds to death in northern Iraq in 1988, even a “truly ethical” secretary of state, George Shultz, committed a “moral outrage.” For Shultz basically ignored the incident and continued supporting Saddam in his war against Iran, because weakening Iran—not protecting the citizens of Iraq—was the primary American interest at the time. So was Shultz acting immorally? Not completely, I believe. Shultz was operating under a different morality than the one normally applied by humanitarians. His was a public morality; not a private one. He and the rest of the Reagan administration had a responsibility to the hundreds of millions of Americans under their charge. And while these millions were fellow countrymen, they were more crucially voters and citizens, essentially strangers who did not know Shultz or Reagan personally, but who had entrusted the two men with their interests. And the American public’s interest clearly dictated that of the two states, Iran and Iraq, Iran at the time constituted the greater threat. In protecting the public interest of even a liberal power, a statesman cannot always be nice; or humane. I am talking here of a morality of public outcomes, rather than one of private intentions. By supporting Iraq, the Reagan administration succeeded in preventing Iran in the last years of the Cold War from becoming a regional hegemon. That was an outcome convenient to U.S. interests, even if the morality of the affair was ambiguous, given that Iraq’s regime was at the time the more brutal of the two. In seeking good outcomes, policymakers are usually guided by constraints: a realistic awareness of what, for instance, the United States should and should not do, given its finite resources. After all, the United States had hundreds of thousands of troops tied down in Europe and Northeast Asia during the Cold War, and thus had to contain Iran through the use of a proxy, Saddam’s Iraq. That was not entirely cynical: it was an intelligent use of limited assets in the context of a worldwide geopolitical struggle. The problem with a foreign policy driven foremost by Never Again! is that it ignores limits and the availability of resources. World War II had the secondary, moral effect of saving what was left of European Jewry. Its primary goal and effect was to restore the European and Asian balance of power in a manner tolerable to the United States—something that the Nazis and the Japanese fascists had overturned. Of course, the Soviet Union wrested control of Eastern Europe for nearly half a century following the war. But again, limited resources necessitated an American alliance with the mass-murderer Stalin against the mass-murderer Hitler. It is because of such awful choices and attendant compromises—in which morality intertwines with amorality—that humanitarians will frequently be disappointed with the foreign policy of even the most heroic administrations. World War II certainly involved many hideous compromises and even mistakes on President Franklin D. Roosevelt’s part. He got into the war in Europe very late, he did not bomb the rail tracks leading to the concentration camps, he might have been more aggressive with the Soviets on the question of Eastern Europe. But as someone representing the interests of the millions of strangers who had and had not voted for him, his aim was to defeat Nazi Germany and Imperial Japan in a manner that cost the fewest American soldiers’ lives, and utilized the least amount of national resources. Saving the remnants of European Jewry was a moral consequence of his actions, but his methods contained tactical concessions that had fundamental amoral elements. Abraham Lincoln, for his part, brought mass suffering upon southern civilians in the last phase of the Civil War in order to decisively defeat the South. The total war waged by generals William Tecumseh Sherman and Ulysses S. Grant was evidence of that. Stefan Bauschard Offensive PKOs release 82 Simply put, there are actions of state that are the right things to do, even if they cannot be defined in terms of conventional morality. Amoral goals, properly applied, do have moral effects. Indeed, in more recent times, President Richard Nixon and his secretary of state, Henry Kissinger, rushed arms to Israel following a surprise attack by Arab armies in the fall of 1973. The two men essentially told the American defense establishment that supporting Israel in its hour of need was the right thing to do, because it was necessary to send an unambiguous message of resolve to the Soviets and their Arab allies at a critical stage in the Cold War. Had they justified the arms transfers purely in terms of helping embattled post-Holocaust Jewry—rather than in terms of power politics as they did—it would have made for a much weaker argument in Washington, where officials rightly had American interests at heart more than Israeli ones. George McGovern was possibly a more ethical man than either Nixon or Kissinger. But had he been elected president in 1972, would he have acted so wisely and so decisively during the 1973 Middle East war? The fact is, individual perfection, as Machiavelli knew, is not necessarily synonymous with public virtue. Then there is the case of Deng Xiaoping. Deng approved the brutal suppression of students at Beijing’s Tiananmen Square in 1989. For that he is not respected among humanitarians in the West. But the consolidation of Communist Party control that followed the clampdown allowed for Deng’s methodical, market-oriented reforms to continue for a generation in China. Perhaps never before in recorded economic history have so many people seen such a dramatic rise in living standards, with an attendant rise in personal (if not political) freedoms in so short a time frame. Thus, Deng might be considered both a brutal Communist and the greatest man of the twentieth century. The morality of his life is complex. The Bosnia and Kosovo interventions of 1995 and 1999 are frequently held out as evidence that the United States is most effective when it acts according to its humanitarian values—never mind its amoral interests. But those who make that argument neglect to mention that the two successful interventions were eased by the fact that America operated in the Balkans with the balance-of-power strongly in its favor. Russia in the 1990s was weak and chaotic under Boris Yeltsin’s incompetent rule, and thus temporarily less able to challenge the United States in a region where historically the czars and commissars had exerted considerable sway. However, Russia, even in the 1990s, still exerted considerable sway in the Caucasus, and thus a Western response to halt ethnic cleansing there during the same decade was not even considered. More broadly, the 1990s allowed for ground interventions in the Balkans because the international climate was relatively benign: China was only just beginning its naval expansion (endangering our Pacific allies) and September 11 still lay in the future. Truly, beyond many a moral response lies a question of power that cannot be explained wholly in terms of morality. Thus , to raise morality as a sole arbiter is ultimately not to be serious about foreign policy. R2P must play as large a role as realistically possible in the affairs of state. But it cannot ultimately dominate . Syria is the current and best example of this. U.S. power is capable of many things, yet putting a complex and war-torn Islamic society’s house in order is not one of them. In this respect, our tragic experience in Iraq is indeed relevant. Quick fixes like a no-fly zone and arming the rebels may topple Syrian dictator Bashar al-Assad, but that might only make President Barack Obama culpable in midwifing to power a Sunni-Jihadist regime, even as ethnic cleansing of al-Assad’s Alawites commences. At least at this late juncture, without significant numbers of Western boots on the ground for a significant period—something for which there is little public support—the likelihood of a better, more stable regime emerging in Damascus is highly questionable. Frankly, there are just no easy answers here, especially as the Stefan Bauschard Offensive PKOs release 83 pro-Western regime in Jordan is threatened by continued Syrian violence. R2P applied in 2011 in Syria might actually have yielded a better strategic result: it will remain an unknowable. Because moralists in these matters are always driven by righteous passion, whenever you disagree with them, you are by definition immoral and deserve no quarter; whereas realists, precisely because they are used to conflict, are less likely to overreact to it. Realists know that passion and wise policy rarely flow together. (The late diplomat Richard Holbrooke was a stunning exception to this rule.) Realists adhere to the belief of the mid-twentieth-century University of Chicago political scientist, Hans Morgenthau, who wrote that “ one must work with” the base forces of human nature, “not against them .” Thus, realists accept the human material at hand in any given place, however imperfect that material may be. To wit, you can’t go around toppling regimes just because you don’t like them. Realism, adds Morgenthau, “appeals to historical precedent rather than to abstract principles [of justice] and aims at the realization of the lesser evil rather than of the absolute good.” No group of people internalized such tragic realizations better than Republican presidents during the Cold War. Dwight Eisenhower, Richard Nixon, Ronald Reagan and George H. W. Bush all practiced amorality, realism, restraint and humility in foreign affairs (if not all the time). It is their sensibility that should guide us now. Eisenhower represented a pragmatic compromise within the Republican Party between isolationists and rabid anti-Communists. All of these men supported repressive, undemocratic regimes in the third world in support of a favorable balance of power against the Soviet Union. Nixon accepted the altogether brutal regimes in the Soviet Union and “Red” China as legitimate, even as he balanced one against the other. Reagan spoke the Wilsonian language of moral rearmament, even as he awarded the key levers of bureaucratic power to realists like Caspar Weinberger, George Shultz and Frank Carlucci, whose effect regarding policy was to temper Reagan’s rhetoric. The elder Bush did not break relations with China after the Tiananmen uprising; nor did he immediately pledge support for Lithuania, after that brave little country declared its independence—for fear of antagonizing the Soviet military. It was caution and restraint on Bush’s part that helped bring the Cold War to a largely peaceful— and, therefore, moral—conclusion. In some of these policies, the difference between amorality and morality was, to paraphrase Joseph Conrad in Lord Jim, no more than “the thickness of a sheet of paper.” And that is precisely the point: foreign policy at its best is subtle, innovative, contradictory, and truly bold only on occasion, aware as its most disciplined practitioners are of the limits of American power. That is heartrending, simply because calls to alleviate suffering will in too many instances go unanswered. For the essence of tragedy is not the triumph of evil over good, so much as the triumph of one good over another that causes suffering. http://www.heritage.org/research/reports/2008/05/the-us-should-reject-the-unresponsibility-to-protect-doctrine Steven Groves works to protect and preserve American sovereignty, selfgovernance and independence as leader of The Heritage Foundation's Freedom Project. Groves, who is the Bernard and Barbara Lomas Senior Research Fellow in Heritage’s Margaret Thatcher Center for Freedom, also advocates American leadership on issues involving international political and religious freedom, human rights and democratic institutions. He has testified before Congress on international law, human rights, the United Nations and controversial treaties such as the U.N. Convention on the Law of the Sea, the Convention on the Rights of Persons with Disabilities, and the Convention on the Elimination of All Forms of Discrimination against Women. In 2013, Groves was awarded the Dr. W. Glenn Stefan Bauschard Offensive PKOs release 84 and Rita Campbell Award for his work. The award is given annually to the Heritage employee who delivered “an outstanding contribution to the analysis and promotion of a free society.” Before joining Heritage in 2007, Groves was senior counsel to then-Sen. Norm Coleman (R-Minn.) on the U.S. Senate Permanent Subcommittee on Investigations. He played a lead role in the subcommittee's investigation of the U.N. "oil-for-food" scandal, the most extensive congressional probe ever conducted of the United Nations. Groves previously was an associate at Boies, Schiller & Flexner LLP, specializing in commercial litigation. Before that he served as assistant attorney general for the State of Florida, where he litigated civil rights cases, constitutional law issues and criminal appeals, among other matters, in state and federal court. Groves is a frequent guest commentator on domestic and international television and radio. He has appeared on ABC, BBC, CNBC, CNN and CNN International, Fox News Channel, National Public Radio, Voice of America, NHK, Al Jazeera, Alhurra and the Canadian Broadcasting Corp. His commentary and opinion pieces have been published by journals such as National Review, The Weekly Standard and Human Events, as well as by The Washington Times and other major newspapers across America. Groves holds a law degree from Ohio Northern University's College of Law and a bachelor of arts degree in history from Florida State University. Operational Flexibility vs. Precautionary Principles. Even if surrendering control of America's armed forces to the will of the world community were acceptable, the U.S. military could not operate effectively under the R2P doctrine. Once committed to a military operation with all of its attendant risks, U.S. armed forces must be allowed the operational freedom to create the conditions to succeed. However, the R2P doctrine espouses a "proportional means" limitation to the rules of engagement that would likely hinder the success of a military intervention. Specifically, the ICISS report suggests that the "scale, duration and intensity of the planned military intervention should be the minimum necessary to secure the humanitarian objective in question."[51] In other words, any intervening armed force may act only to end genocidal acts and ethnic cleansing -- and go no further. However, a combat environment is rarely so predictable. Some situations would require the total destruction of the forces perpetrating the genocide or the overthrow of the government providing command and control. Yet the ICISS report states that "[t]he effect on the political system of the country targeted should be limited...to what is strictly necessary to accomplish the purpose of the intervention."[52] Several instances of genocide and ethnic cleansing in recent history have occurred with the complicity and active involvement of a national government and its armed forces. It is unrealistic to mandate that a military intervention limit its effect on the political system and its leadership while stopping genocidal crimes. It is likewise naïve to believe that government forces that are complicit in genocidal acts would cease and desist from committing atrocities after a military intervention has ended and the intervening troops are withdrawn. In addition, the R2P doctrine demands that "all the rules of international humanitarian law should be strictly observed" in the event of a military intervention.[53] There is, however, widespread debate over certain crucial aspects of that law. For example, there are major differences of opinion regarding the classification, treatment, confinement, and trial of certain classes of enemy combatants. The use of certain weapons, such as cluster bombs and land mines, is also disputed. The R2P's requirement of strict observance of the law of armed conflict is therefore unachievable because there is broad disagreement on what "strict observance" would entail. Stefan Bauschard Offensive PKOs release 85 Adoption of r2p crushes US hegemony without improving security Holmes 11 http://www.heritage.org/research/commentary/2011/04/whose-responsibility-toprotect Kim R. Holmes, a Distinguished Fellow at The Heritage Foundation, oversaw the think tank’s defense and foreign policy team for more than two decades. Holmes was Heritage’s vice president for foreign and defense policy studies and director of the Davis Institute for International Studies from 1991 through 2012 except for his service, during most of the first term of President George W. Bush, as assistant secretary of state for international organization affairs. Holmes’ priority is writing a book, due in fall 2013, in which he hopes to lay out a compelling vision for America’s future by uniting Heritage’s domestic and foreign policy ideas. “Few people bring greater clarity and historical wisdom to thorny issues than Kim Holmes,” Heritage President Edwin J. Feulner said in announcing the new role on Dec. 5, 2012. Holmes previously directed Heritage's team of foreign and defense policy experts in four centers on the front lines of international affairs: the Douglas and Sarah Allison Center for Foreign Policy Studies, the Asian Studies Center, the Center for International Trade and Economics and the Margaret Thatcher Center for Freedom. Davis also includes the Washington Roundtable for the Asia-Pacific Press (WRAPP). Holmes joined Heritage in 1985 and rose to vice president in 1991. He was a founding editor of the annual Index of Economic Freedom, which has become a signature Heritage publication. He led the think tank’s efforts to convince the United States to withdraw from the Anti-Ballistic Missile Treaty. He launched Heritage’s widely respected homeland security program after September 11, as well as its program on international trade, and expanded the missile defense program to what it is today. Holmes left Heritage in late 2001 to serve as an assistant secretary of state. After rejoining the think tank in 2005, he authored the book “Liberty's Best Hope: American Leadership for the 21st Century.” Recognized around the globe as one of Washington’s foremost foreign and defense policy experts, Holmes is a member of the Council on Foreign Relations, where he formerly served on the Washington Advisory Committee. Previous appointments include the Defense Policy Board, which is the U.S. defense secretary’s primary resource for expert outside advice; the Board of Directors of the Center for International Private Enterprise; and public member of the U.S. delegation to the Organization for Security and Cooperation in Europe. While at the State Department, Holmes was responsible for developing policy and coordinating U.S. engagement at the United Nations and 46 other international organizations. Important goals achieved at that time included the U.N. mandates enabling Iraq to make the transition to democracy; the Security Council's first binding nonproliferation resolution; the U.N.'s first mandate requiring the Office of Internal Oversight Services to release reports to member states; an international outcry over Libya's assuming chairmanship of the Commission on Human Rights, which culminated in that body's refashioning; and establishment of the U.N. Democracy Caucus and U.N. Democracy Fund. Holmes earned his doctoral and master’s degrees in history from Georgetown University. He received a bachelor’s degree in history from the University of Central Florida in Orlando. He was a research fellow at the Institute for European History in Germany and adjunct professor of European security and history at Georgetown University What are these objectives? First, to undermine the idea that force should be used only to protect national security. Advocates argue that protecting civilians is the only “just Stefan Bauschard Offensive PKOs release 86 cause” for using force. Defending our allies from attack or even launching military interventions overseas to take out terrorist bases would, under this definition, be “illegitimate.” The second objective is to elevate the Security Council as the only body that can legitimately authorize the use of force by any nation, including the U.S. This has obvious implications for the U.S. Constitution, which recognizes the war-making powers only of the President and the Congress. Our nation has the bulk of the world’s military forces. This doctrine would constrain us from using force for our own protection (except for very obvious invasions). Worse, it leaves our forces on the hook to intervene overseas at the behest of the Security Council, at our expense. It relegates our military to the status of U.N.-mandated world police force. This makes no sense in terms of U.S. national security or in terms of the U.N. Charter. Article 51 of the Charter affirms that nations can use military force for self-defense. The Charter also says that when force is used for other purposes, it must do so to counter “international” threats and restore “international” peace. And it says “nothing contained in the present Charter shall authorize the United Nations to intervene in matters which are essentially within the domestic jurisdiction of any state.” In other words, internal abuses by states are no excuse to intervene. Advocates of the responsibility to protect may find this provision inconvenient, heartless or even “illegitimate.” But that’s what the Charter says. As envisioned by many of its supporters, this doctrine violates the U.N. Charter. The Security Council has pecked away at national sovereignty for years, justifying arms embargoes, no-fly zones and sanctions. But it has recently become far more willing to ignore this Charter restriction in response to perceived threats to civilian security. Before dismissing the “slippery slope” argument that the Security Council will someday claim exclusive jurisdiction over the use of force, remember how far we have drifted away from the original purposes of the U.N. Charter. “Responsibility to protect” is pure sophistry, riddled with contradictions. In reality, it is a cynical attempt to assert external decision-making powers over the use of U.S. military force. By trying to change the rules, advocates hope to delegitimize America’s traditional use of force to defend itself and its allies and to put that decision in the hands of an international body that includes France , Russia and China. It’s easy to see why Russia and China would want the U.N. to control U.S. decisions to use military force. It’s not at all clear why a U.S. president would want that. Stefan Bauschard Offensive PKOs release 87 R2P Bad: Sovereignty Accepting r2p destroys us sovereignty Groves 8 http://www.heritage.org/research/reports/2008/05/the-us-should-reject-the-unresponsibility-to-protect-doctrine Steven Groves works to protect and preserve American sovereignty, selfgovernance and independence as leader of The Heritage Foundation's Freedom Project. Groves, who is the Bernard and Barbara Lomas Senior Research Fellow in Heritage’s Margaret Thatcher Center for Freedom, also advocates American leadership on issues involving international political and religious freedom, human rights and democratic institutions. He has testified before Congress on international law, human rights, the United Nations and controversial treaties such as the U.N. Convention on the Law of the Sea, the Convention on the Rights of Persons with Disabilities, and the Convention on the Elimination of All Forms of Discrimination against Women. In 2013, Groves was awarded the Dr. W. Glenn and Rita Campbell Award for his work. The award is given annually to the Heritage employee who delivered “an outstanding contribution to the analysis and promotion of a free society.” Before joining Heritage in 2007, Groves was senior counsel to then-Sen. Norm Coleman (R-Minn.) on the U.S. Senate Permanent Subcommittee on Investigations. He played a lead role in the subcommittee's investigation of the U.N. "oil-for-food" scandal, the most extensive congressional probe ever conducted of the United Nations. Groves previously was an associate at Boies, Schiller & Flexner LLP, specializing in commercial litigation. Before that he served as assistant attorney general for the State of Florida, where he litigated civil rights cases, constitutional law issues and criminal appeals, among other matters, in state and federal court. Groves is a frequent guest commentator on domestic and international television and radio. He has appeared on ABC, BBC, CNBC, CNN and CNN International, Fox News Channel, National Public Radio, Voice of America, NHK, Al Jazeera, Alhurra and the Canadian Broadcasting Corp. His commentary and opinion pieces have been published by journals such as National Review, The Weekly Standard and Human Events, as well as by The Washington Times and other major newspapers across America. Groves holds a law degree from Ohio Northern University's College of Law and a bachelor of arts degree in history from Florida State University. While genocide, war crimes, and other atrocities will always be incompatible with American values, the McCain and Clinton statements raise the issue of whether preventing genocide and ethnic cleansing would necessarily constitute a vital U.S. national interest. In some situations, acts of large-scale ethnic cleansing in some remote nation may indeed affect U.S. national interests. However, the real question is whether or not the United States should obligate itself through an international compact to use its military forces as the rest of the world sees fit in cases of genocide and ethnic cleansing. Accepting such an obligation would arguably empower other nations to judge whether U.S. national interests or national values are at stake. That begs the question of who will decide whether the United States must commit its limited resources -- including its military forces -- to prevent atrocities occurring in a foreign land. The R2P doctrine is designed to take decision making on these crucial issues out of the hands of the United States and place it in the hands of the international community, operating through the United Nations. If the United States consented to such a doctrine, Stefan Bauschard Offensive PKOs release 88 it would effectively surrender its authority to exercise an essential , sovereign power. First Principles and National Sovereignty The United States must not surrender its independence and sovereignty cavalierly. The Founding Fathers and subsequent generations of Americans paid a high price to achieve America's sovereignty and secure the unalienable rights of U.S. citizens. The government formed by the Founders to safeguard American independence and protect individual rights derives its powers from the consent of the governed, not from any other nation or group of nations.[42] Having achieved its independence by fighting a costly war, America's Founders approached permanent alliances and foreign entanglements with a fair degree of skepticism. President George Washington, in his 1796 farewell address, favored extending America's commercial relations with other nations but warned against extensive political connections.[43] Washington well understood that legitimate governments are formed only through gaining the consent of the people. He therefore placed a high value on the independence that the United States had achieved and was rightfully dubious about involvement in European intrigues. Integral to national sovereignty is the right to make authoritative decisions on foreign policy and national resources, particularly the use of the nation's military forces. Many of the reasons why America fought the War of Independence against Great Britain revolved around Britain's taxation of the American people without their consent and its practice of "declaring themselves invested with power to legislate for us in all cases whatsoever."[44] Once America gained control of its revenue, natural resources, and industry and had formed a government separate and apart from any other, the Founders would not have compromised or delegated its prerogatives to any other nation or group of nations. Washington rightly warned his countrymen to "steer clear" of such foreign influence and instead to rely on "temporary alliances for extraordinary emergencies."[45] The R2P doctrine strikes at the heart of the Founders' notion of national sovereignty. The Founders would have deplored the idea that the United States would cede control -- any control -- of its armed forces to the caprice of the world community without the consent of the American people. Washington stated that the decision to go to war is a key element of national sovereignty that should be exercised at the discretion of the American government: Our detached and distant situation invites and enables us to pursue a different course. If we remain one people under an efficient government, the period is not far off...when we may choose peace or war, as our interest, guided by justice, shall counsel.[46] The U.S. interest, guided by justice and exercised with the consent of the American people, must remain the standard for making decisions of war and peace. The interest of the international community, which is guided by its own collective notion of justice and without the consent of the American people, should not serve as America's barometer, especially when placing the lives of U.S. military men and women in jeopardy.[47] The United States cannot rely on world opinion, as expressed through an emerging international norm such as R2P, to set the proper criteria for the use of U.S. military force. The commitment to use force must be made exclusively by the U.S. government acting as an independent, sovereign nation based on its own criteria for military intervention.[48] In sum, the R2P doctrine does not harmonize with the first principles of the United States. Adopting a doctrine that binds the United States to scores of other nations and dictates how it must act to prevent atrocities is the very sort of foreign entanglement against which Washington warned us. The United States would betray the Founding Fathers' achievement of independence and sovereignty if it wholly acceded to the R2P doctrine. Stefan Bauschard Offensive PKOs release 89 Actively rejecting r2p crucial to maintain sovereignty Groves 8 http://www.heritage.org/research/reports/2008/05/the-us-should-reject-the-unresponsibility-to-protect-doctrine Steven Groves works to protect and preserve American sovereignty, selfgovernance and independence as leader of The Heritage Foundation's Freedom Project. Groves, who is the Bernard and Barbara Lomas Senior Research Fellow in Heritage’s Margaret Thatcher Center for Freedom, also advocates American leadership on issues involving international political and religious freedom, human rights and democratic institutions. He has testified before Congress on international law, human rights, the United Nations and controversial treaties such as the U.N. Convention on the Law of the Sea, the Convention on the Rights of Persons with Disabilities, and the Convention on the Elimination of All Forms of Discrimination against Women. In 2013, Groves was awarded the Dr. W. Glenn and Rita Campbell Award for his work. The award is given annually to the Heritage employee who delivered “an outstanding contribution to the analysis and promotion of a free society.” Before joining Heritage in 2007, Groves was senior counsel to then-Sen. Norm Coleman (R-Minn.) on the U.S. Senate Permanent Subcommittee on Investigations. He played a lead role in the subcommittee's investigation of the U.N. "oil-for-food" scandal, the most extensive congressional probe ever conducted of the United Nations. Groves previously was an associate at Boies, Schiller & Flexner LLP, specializing in commercial litigation. Before that he served as assistant attorney general for the State of Florida, where he litigated civil rights cases, constitutional law issues and criminal appeals, among other matters, in state and federal court. Groves is a frequent guest commentator on domestic and international television and radio. He has appeared on ABC, BBC, CNBC, CNN and CNN International, Fox News Channel, National Public Radio, Voice of America, NHK, Al Jazeera, Alhurra and the Canadian Broadcasting Corp. His commentary and opinion pieces have been published by journals such as National Review, The Weekly Standard and Human Events, as well as by The Washington Times and other major newspapers across America. Groves holds a law degree from Ohio Northern University's College of Law and a bachelor of arts degree in history from Florida State University. Protecting American Sovereignty Given the recognition of the responsibility to protect doctrine in the 2005 World Summit Outcome Document, as well as the continuing efforts by certain actors in the international community to promote and operationalize R2P, the United States should clarify its position on its national sovereignty and the criteria for the use of its armed forces. To that end, the United States should: Maintain its current official position, as set forth in Ambassador Bolton's letter regarding the 2005 World Summit Outcome Document, that the R2P doctrine does not create a binding legal obligation on the United States to intervene in another nation for any purpose. Affirm that the United States need not seek authorization from the U.N. Security Council, the U.N. General Assembly, the international community, or any other international organization to use its military forces to prevent acts of genocide, ethnic cleansing, or other atrocities occurring in another country. Base its decisions to intervene in the affairs of other nations -- including punitive economic, diplomatic, political, and military measures -- on U.S. national interests, not on criteria set forth by the R2P doctrine or any other Stefan Bauschard Offensive PKOs release 90 international "test." Scrutinize ongoing efforts by certain actors within the international community to operationalize and otherwise promote the R2P doctrine in the United States, the United Nations, the international NGO community, and other international forums. Reject the notion thatthe R2P doctrine is an established international norm. Conclusion The United States should take no comfort from the fact that, as a party to the 2005 World Summit Outcome Document, it has committed itself only to being "prepared to take collective action" to end atrocities or that the ICISS report represents the obligation to prevent atrocities as a mere "responsibility." R2P advocates are attempting to achieve worldwide consensus that the international community has an obligation to intervene, with military force if necessary, in another country to prevent acts of genocide, ethnic cleansing, and other atrocities. R2P proponents may not be satisfied with anything less than a multilateral treaty -- a United Nations Convention on the Responsibility to Protect -- that creates binding legal obligations on its signatories. The United States should therefore continue to treat the responsibility to protect doctrine with grave skepticism. The independence won by the Founders and defended by subsequent generations of Americans should not be squandered, but rather should be safeguarded from furtive encroachments by the international community. Only by maintaining a monopoly on the deployment of diplomatic pressure, economic sanctions, political coercion, and military forces will the United States preserve its national sovereignty. Acceding to a set of criteria such as those set forth by the R2P doctrine would be a dangerous and unnecessary step toward bolstering the authority of the United Nations and the international community and would compromise the consent of the American people. Stefan Bauschard Offensive PKOs release 91 A2: “R2P Expands Sovereignty” Defense of r2p misdefine “sovereignty” – the redefinition still erodes it Gay 7/23/13 http://nationalinterest.org/blog/the-buzz/the-deceptive-appeal-theresponsibility-protect-8764 John Allen Gay is an assistant managing editor at The National Interest. His book (co-authored with Geoffrey Kemp) War with Iran: Political, Military, and Economic Consequences was released by Rowman and Littlefield in early 2013, The National Interest, July 23, The Deceptive Appeal of the Responsibility to Protect, DOA: 12-7-14 The third pillar is where the rub is. The notion that the international community has an obligation to become involved in a country under certain circumstances, regardless of what its government says, appears to erode national sovereignty. Albright and Williamson charge that this is a misperception—in fact, they say, R2P “is designed to reinforce, not undermine, national sovereignty. It places primary emphasis on the duty of states to protect their own people and its complementary focus on helping governments improve their capacities to fulfill their commitments.” In other words, R2P expands the concept of sovereignty—sovereignty includes not only rights, but also responsibilities, responsibilities which states should help each other fulfill. Sovereignty here is so sacrosanct that states failing to exercise it fully lose their title to it—“Only when a government fails or refuses to live up to the responsibility of sovereignty does it run the risk of outside intervention.” Yet this is a curious way to construe sovereignty. Sovereignty becomes not merely an empirical fact about states that is prudently respected, but a right entrusted from on high; given that the right passes to the international community when abused, it would seem this sovereignty sees the world as a federation. International institutions—treated in the report as the final authorities on third-pillar actions—graciously devolve their responsibilities to local viceroys and governors-general, whom it may relieve of their duties if their failures are severe enough. It’s not really sovereignty, then—it’s mere administrative convenience. Stefan Bauschard Offensive PKOs release 92 A2: “R2P Doesn’t kill Sovereignty - it’s Preventive” Even if it’s prevention, the doctrine still kills sovereignty Gay 7/23/13 http://nationalinterest.org/blog/the-buzz/the-deceptive-appeal-theresponsibility-protect-8764 John Allen Gay is an assistant managing editor at The National Interest. His book (co-authored with Geoffrey Kemp) War with Iran: Political, Military, and Economic Consequences was released by Rowman and Littlefield in early 2013, The National Interest, July 23, The Deceptive Appeal of the Responsibility to Protect, DOA: 12-7-14 Albright and Williamson might reply that all these worries repeat the error of assuming that R2P is mainly about its third pillar, when in fact “R2P is at its core an instrument of prevention. It does not mandate military action by the United States or others. The idea is to generate preventive diplomacy, increased development aid, sanctions, and other tools to avoid the military options that might be necessary when prevention fails and atrocities commence.” The second pillar, for them, bears the most weight. et the way Albright and Williamson envision this pillar working is also a threat to sovereignty . They imply this in the Politico op-ed they released to plug the report, as they note that “Syria today presents us with a stark reminder of the high human costs of equivocation. As Assad began to turn state organs into his own tool of repression, R2P’s preventive underpinnings were rightfully called into question...” Indeed. No preventive action could have kept Assad from turning the state’s institutions into tools of repression while also respecting Syrian sovereignty, because Assad’s rule was already repressive. As in most autocracies, the government could not become less repressive without endangering its continued hold on power. Assad was thus likely to regard the second-pillar efforts that would have been necessary to stabilize prewar Syria as a threat, and to refuse them. (Indeed, other autocracies, such as Russia and Egypt, have similarly refused such “help.”) So should these second-pillar measures be conducted over a government’s objections? If not, they’ll often be insufficient; if so, sovereignty is further eroded. Yet Albright and Williamson pass over this problem in silence. Stefan Bauschard Offensive PKOs release 93 A2: “Safeguards Protect Sovereignty” R2P safeguards AUGMENT erosion of sovereignty Menon 6/12/13 http://www.the-american-interest.com/articles/2013/06/12/its-fatally-flawed/ Rajan Menon is Anne and Bernard Spitzer Professor of Political Science, City College of New York/City University of New York, and a senior fellow at the Atlantic Council. R2P’s originators anticipated that any prescription perceived as proposing lax criteria for the use of force would be dead on arrival, so the ICISS report and follow-on publications of its ilk have bowed before the shrine of sovereignty. They affirm that the obligation to protect people rests in the first instance with the governments that have jurisdiction over them, but they add that when a state cannot or will not protect human rights, the responsibility shifts to the international community, which means, ideally, the UN girded with Security Council authorization, or in a pinch regional organizations if they promise subsequently to seek UNSCR approval. R2P proponents take pains to explain that the concept is not a pretext for military intervention. Force, Gareth Evans tirelessly reiterates, should be used only during human rights emergencies and only following the failure of diplomacy, mediation, naming and shaming, and sanctions. Even then, he stresses, feasibility, risks, proportionality and the prospects for success must be weighed. (There is more than a dollop of just war theory in R2P; Augustine and Aquinas would be proud.) R2P’s expositors also recommend various preventive measures: early-warning mechanisms, pre-crisis mediation, peacekeeping, economic assistance and post-conflict reconstruction.2 Yet the reassurances that force would be a rare, last-ditch response have not placated critics, for several reasons. R2P’s pre-intervention prescriptions merely repeat existing remedies and add nothing to diplomacy’s toolkit. What’s new is the casuistry of reframing and diminishing sovereignty in order to legitimize altruistic armed intervention in defense of the abstract rights that most political communities agree upon in theory. Given R2P’s emphasis on feasibility and the chances for success, weak states are its most likely proving grounds; powerful ones need not fear, no matter the magnitude of their misdeeds. Because idealism and power are inextricably intertwined, with the latter frequently corrupting the former, R2P provides powerful states one script for playing the Good Samaritan when intervention promotes their interests, and another for eschewing or opposing aid when it doesn’t. Stefan Bauschard Offensive PKOs release 94 A2: “N/U – Sovereignty is Down Now” Aff is unique – sovereignty is strong – HUMANITARIAN INTERVENTION is the ONLY cause Chirstensen 3/2/12 http://notesonliberty.com/2012/03/02/bizarre-love-triangle-towards-a-newinternationalism/ Brandon Christensen (follow him on Twitter) received his B.A. in cultural anthropology from UCLA in 2013, where he also minored in Middle Eastern and African studies. His writings have been featured in the Freeman and at RealClearHistory. He was born in the middle of Utah, raised in a small Northern California town, and spent two years attending a community college in Santa Cruz before moving to Los Angeles. He is interested in pre-colonial polities, property rights, ethnicity, and international trade. Perhaps, but I strongly disagree with Dr. Larison’s observations here. Not with the notion that weaker states have selfish interests too, but rather with the argument that state sovereignty has been eroding precipitously over the past twenty years. To the isolationist, free trade and international governance (including military alliances) are necessarily bad things for a state and its sovereignty, because these concepts are perceived to be taking away from the ability of a state to make decisions in its own interests. Yet the major powers and, to a lesser extent, the regional powers of the world are largely able to do what they want in terms of formulating domestic and foreign policies. Just think of the recent attempt by Brazil and Turkey to get Iran to play nice with its nuclear technology. With the exception of the United States in Iraq and Afghanistan, the “weak states” of the world and their predation by major powers seems only to be occurring along peripheries of the major powers’ territories, specifically in the region of the world traditionally under Russian influence. And even these predatory practices of the Russian state are largely aimed at defending Moscow’s peripheries from the incursions into region by the American state. So I would look at the situation of weak states outside the peripheries of great powers not as a steady erosion of state sovereignty, but as the last stage of colonization by Europeans a century ago. The weakness in these states was inherent from the beginning, as they were largely constructed to extract resources for shipment to European industry and to ensure that recently conquered non-Western rivals, whether monarchies, confederations, city-states, or empires, remained conquered once and for all. In order for a state to have sovereignty, it needs to be recognized by its own people as legitimate, and not by major powers (though it certainly helps!), and the structure of weak states, at least outside the peripheries of major powers, is illegitimate in the eyes of most the people living within these states. Dr. Larison continues: “If there is one thing more misguided than organizing foreign policy around ‘humanitarian’ and democratist meddling in the affairs of other nations, it has to be the revival of the liberal nationalist conceit that there should be an independent nation-state for every group that wants one.” Hardly. The Wilsonian notions of humanitarian intervention and democratic nation-building are easily the most misguided ideals being espoused throughout Washington today, and the fact that some of the idealists over at Foreign Policy have latched onto liberal nationalism as a way to promote their misguided policies should not deter us from the fact that the United States has not pursued nor promoted liberal nationalism in its foreign policy since Wilson’s disastrous meddling in Europe over (nearly) a Stefan Bauschard Offensive PKOs release 95 century ago. Let us be clear: the NATO excursions into the Balkans had nothing to do with promoting liberal nationalism, and everything to do with humanitarian intervention, democratic state-building, and geostrategic maneuvering. The military excursions into Iraq, Afghanistan, Haiti, Somalia, and God knows where else over the past twenty years have nothing to do with the concept of liberal nationalism and everything to do with humanitarian intervention, democratic state-building, and/or geostrategic maneuvering. Liberal nationalism, as it is promoted by the idealists, is extremely new on the scene in D.C. and is probably just one of the many, many fads that swing through the capital and are used to apply humanitarian intervention and democratic state-building to foreign policy proposals. Stefan Bauschard Offensive PKOs release 96 Sovereignty Impact Global adoption of R2P causes great power wars – denial of sovereignty. Trombly 11 Dan Trombly, GWU IR Grad Student, 8-27-2011 The upending of sovereignty http://slouchingcolumbia.wordpress.com/2011/08/27/the-upending-of-sovereignty/ The second dangerous element is that on the international scale, the potential for creating serious enmity among the great powers. The importance of consensus belies the reality of how consensus is formed, not by automatic recognition but by a careful negotiation of interests and calculation of threats. Yet the more we choose, falsely, to view R2P as simply a norm which automatically initiates a series of actions to enforce itself, the more tension we are likely to provoke when this imagined process hits against the friction of world politics as they actually are. While I have predicted that military limitations by US allies in power projection and the increasing ability of countries to deny the US ability to unilaterally project power itself will make the implementation of R2P unlikely beyond Africa or certain parts of the Middle East, even the attempts to apply it in the backyard of China or Russia could seriously destabilize the international system. For the US to seek to implement a norm which in theory only a UNSC veto prevents from being employed against China in that country’s backyard would be a serious escalation of tensions and in utter denial of the type of sovereign, qualified space China is seeking to create in its own neighborhood. R2P is not a plot by great powers. But it is a radical denial of the historic purpose of sovereignty, which was not to protect societies from foreign states, but to protect society from itself. But rather than empowering a global society, it will empower the great powers of the international system, along with those societies whose appeals suit their perceived interests. It is built on a fundamentally untenable illusion of consensus among great powers which will not endure a crisis in a more strategically meaningful area of the world. Should activists succeed in convincing great powers that societies of affected states can legitimize the actions of intervening states, and jus ad bello trump the need for the impossible-to-enforce consensus, the results will seriously challenge the basis of amicable great power relations in the first place. Stefan Bauschard Offensive PKOs release 97 R2O Increase War – Moral Hazard (Syria/Iran) R2P incentivizes war deal-making – it rules out compromise. Specifically drives Assad and militias Gay 7/23/13 http://nationalinterest.org/blog/the-buzz/the-deceptive-appeal-theresponsibility-protect-8764 John Allen Gay is an assistant managing editor at The National Interest. His book (co-authored with Geoffrey Kemp) War with Iran: Political, Military, and Economic Consequences was released by Rowman and Littlefield in early 2013, The National Interest, July 23, The Deceptive Appeal of the Responsibility to Protect, DOA: 12-7-14 The R2P concept of sovereignty can also give bad actors like Assad perverse incentives . A case in point is threats to bring those behind atrocities before international courts—threats made in Albright and Williamson’s report. Assad is hardly more likely to seek peace and step down if he thinks that might see him brought before the International Criminal Court and thrown in prison for decades. Such a risk is all the more reason to hang on desperately —and to keep inflicting horrors on his people. Second-pillar actions, too, could make him more troublesome. If the international community insists that states accept outside efforts to change their politics, autocracies will have incentives to resist the international community; those within autocratic regimes who benefit from their positions have incentives to spoil the deal. And the resistance can be quite destructive, endangering international stability and even causing atrocities. Iran’s support for terrorist groups and sectarian militias throughout the Middle East may be driven in part by this dynamic . Stefan Bauschard Offensive PKOs release 98 R2P Increases War – Moral Hazard Moral hazard blocks negotiated solutions Beaumont 5/4/13 http://www.theguardian.com/world/2013/may/04/un-syria-duty-to-intervene Peter Beaumont writes on foreign affairs for the Guardian and Observer. He has reported extensively from conflict zones including Africa, the Balkans and the Middle East, and has reported widely on human rights issues and the impact of conflict on civilians. The winner of the George Orwell Prize for his reports from Iraq he is the author of The Secret Life of War: Journeys Through Modern Conflict Jennifer Walsh, professor of international relations at Oxford University who has studied the development of R2P, agrees with Evans's analysis. But she also identifies a "moral hazard" inherent in R2P – that it can create a perception in conflicts that a rebel force may be only a regime-sponsored atrocity away from international interveners coming to its aid. The incentive for rebels to find a negotiated solution is thus reduced. Serbia proves moral hazard Menon 6/12/13 http://www.the-american-interest.com/articles/2013/06/12/its-fatally-flawed/ Rajan Menon is Anne and Bernard Spitzer Professor of Political Science, City College of New York/City University of New York, and a senior fellow at the Atlantic Council. Those who start wars are often confident that they know how they will end. They are just as often proved wrong. Idealistic humanitarian interveners, a subspecies of such hubristic planners, congratulate themselves on their highmindedness, which leads most of them to assume that if no self-interested motives attach to their intentions, then no self-interested consequences can emerge from them. Of course this is absurd. One result of NATO’s (eventual) decision to strike Bosnian Serb forces in 1995, very popular among the soon-to-be-hatched R2P brood, was to alter the political balance within the Kosovar Albanian opposition. The Dayton deal skirted Kosovo, confirming most Kosovars’ belief that the world couldn’t care less about their plight. The new context helped the KLA but, as already noted, shaped the ferocity of its tactics. In response, Serb forces mounted a major counterinsurgency campaign. Indeed, the multiplication of Western calls to “do something” had the perverse effect of inducing Slobodan Milosevic to ramp up the killings and expulsions. Once NATO started bombing, Milosevic moved even faster and more ruthlessly to quash the KLA, but NATO still limited itself to airpower and restricted pilots to safe altitudes. The result? In less than three months after NATO began bombing, Serbian troops killed some 10,000 people in Kosovo and drove another 1.4 million from their homes. The shallowness of the alliance’s commitment to humanitarian principles was revealed when it chose to conduct a campaign that would produce minimal, ideally zero, casualties for its own soldiers, no matter the horrendous consequences for the people it had intervened to protect. NATO’s defenders say that it did not do the killing and expelling, Stefan Bauschard Offensive PKOs release 99 that Milosevic was responsible and that he would have done what he did anyway. Yes, the Serbian leadership unquestionably bears responsibility; yes, atrocities occurred before NATO acted; but there can be no doubt that the scale and duration of Serbian atrocities owed much to NATO’s intervention. The selfexculpatory claim that what happened would have happened is unpersuasive. It is also worth noting in passing what the Kosovar victory enabled—a set of concerns almost universally ignored in Western accounts of the war. NATO defended the intervention as a response to killings and ethnic cleansing, but after the war Albanians killed many Serb civilians and forced thousands of Serbs and Roma from their homes even as NATO troops (organized as KFOR) were moving in to secure Kosovo. The KLA maintained detention centers in Albania where several hundreds of Serbs and other minorities, plus Albanians suspected of complicity with the Serb authorities, were held. Some were tortured, others killed—in some cases after their organs were removed for sale by Albanian criminal networks.6 High-ranking KLA officials participated in some of these activities. Before the war, in those parts of Kosovo not controlled by Serb forces, criminal clans, again involving KLA leaders, seized industries, natural resources and property, foreshadowing the massive corruption and criminality that mark Kosovo today. None of this ever excited much passion in Brussels or Washington; nor were European governments welcoming toward refugees fleeing Kosovo. Their focus was on Serb atrocities. The KLA, which had gained in stature partly because the United States and Europe embraced it as a war partner and as the legitimate representative of Kosovar resistance, got a pass. In humanitarian intervention’s Manichean world of artificial passion plays, there are no shades of gray. Unintended consequences are either ignored or blamed on others. Stefan Bauschard Offensive PKOs release 100 Moral Hazard: Secessionism R2P sparks global secessionism through moral hazard Janik 13 Janik, Ralph R. A., The Responsibility to Protect as an Impetus for Secessionist Movements: On the Necessity to Re-Think Territorial Integrity (December 6, 2013). Matthias Kettemann (ed), Grenzen im Völkerrecht (Jan Sramek Verlag, 2013). Available at SSRN: http://ssrn.com/abstract=2364478 Ralph Janik is research assistant of Prof. August Reinisch and lecturer at the University of Vienna. After completing his studies in law and political science at the University of Vienna and the Universidad Alcala de Henares (Madrid) , he has worked inter alia as a research assistant in the project “ International Law through the National Prism: The Impact of Judicial Dialogue” at the University of Vienna, Section for International Law and International Relations , as well as at the Law Faculty of the University of Amsterdam, where he also obtained his postgraduate LL.M. degree in international law The historical and political roots of such secessionist struggles will be briefly outlined in the next section, which is followed by a short overview on the legal framework regarding secessionist claims. After having discussed the extent to which law has a say in this subject matter and the possibility of secession as a » remedial «, ultima ratio right under extraordinary circumstances, the following part will then proceed to demonstrate that secession is increasingly gaining factual and legal importance in light of the increasing tendency to deal with intra-state conflicts on the international plane instead of treating these as essentially domestic matters. The last step in this development has been the emergence of the concept of the » Reponsibility to Protect « which essentially enshrines the duty of states to protect their respective populations from genocide, war crimes, ethnic cleansing, and crimes against humanity and also de lege ferenda obligations upon the international community to act once a state is unable or unwilling to protect its population from such acts or even carrying out these serious human rights violations itself. As will be shown however, this concept does not only have positive effects but may also constitute an incentive for secessionist movements to actively provoke the government they are fighting to react in a manner that might force the international community to step up with at least some kind of international support on their behalf. Here, one needs to bear in mind that such support might decisively shift the balance of power towards the otherwise clearly disadvantaged secessionist group. This incentive is further fostered by the fact that massive state retaliation may also provide the basis for the above-mentioned right to » remedial secession «, thereby also influencing the international community in its subsequent assessment of the pressing issue of recognition. Assuming that such a nexus of the Responsibility to Protect and the right to remedial secession indeed exists, the international community could thus often unknowingly and unintentionally become the midwife of new states. That would call for a fundamental re-conceptualization either of the attitude towards secessionism or that towards intervention on humanitarian grounds; this point will be addressed in the last part, which will be followed by a conclusion. Stefan Bauschard Offensive PKOs release 101 Secession: A2: Alternative Causality R2P is the CRUCIAL determinant of global secessionism Janik 13 Janik, Ralph R. A., The Responsibility to Protect as an Impetus for Secessionist Movements: On the Necessity to Re-Think Territorial Integrity (December 6, 2013). Matthias Kettemann (ed), Grenzen im Völkerrecht (Jan Sramek Verlag, 2013). Available at SSRN: http://ssrn.com/abstract=2364478 Ralph Janik is research assistant of Prof. August Reinisch and lecturer at the University of Vienna. After completing his studies in law and political science at the University of Vienna and the Universidad Alcala de Henares (Madrid) , he has worked inter alia as a research assistant in the project “ International Law through the National Prism: The Impact of Judicial Dialogue” at the University of Vienna, Section for International Law and International Relations , as well as at the Law Faculty of the University of Amsterdam, where he also obtained his postgraduate LL.M. degree in international law It is all too likely that, due to the change in attitude towards intervention in civil wars, often fought over secessionist demands, as well as regarding recognition of thereby possibly emerging states, such conflicts are here to stay and may well increase in the future. This would particularly – but not exclusively – affect countries composed by many ( easily ) separable groups living in more or less distinct territories without sharing any sense of community or even solidarity. The possibility of a doubled moral hazard caused by the interplay of remedial secession and the prospect of outside intervention is thus of crucial significance for the future of the international legal order. Yet, this effect in general and regarding secession in particular has largely remained ignored both by practitioners and theorists. Rather, scholars usually seem reluctant to voice fundamental criticism in connection with the advances in connection with the use of force on humanitarian grounds, especially upon authorization by the Security Council, in fear of being seen as advocates of oppressive regimes. At the same time, states seem to avoid or simply not consider the possibility of this very issue in their shortterm pursuance of strategic goals, while they are keen on avoiding the creation of any precedence at all costs and regardless of the facts. In the case of Kosovo for instance, the intervening countries simply emphasized that the conflict was not an issue of an attempt to secession but a humanitarian catastrophe that had made the use of force necessary to stop and prevent a regime from gross human rights abuses. 107 Nanda, Self-Determination, 279. 108 Stefan Bauschard Offensive PKOs release 102 Secession Spills Over Secession linked globally – spills over Larison 11 http://www.theamericanconservative.com/larison/the-wages-of-kosovo-and-southsudan/ Daniel Larison is a senior editor at TAC, where he also keeps a solo blog. He has been published in the New York Times Book Review, Dallas Morning News, Orthodox Life, Front Porch Republic, The American Scene, and Culture11, and is a columnist for The Week. He holds a PhD in history from the University of Chicago, and resides in Dallas. This is always very easy for others with nothing at stake to say. Sudan’s break-up doesn’t threaten the rest of Africa until it provides the precedent in other countries for similar independence movements. Kosovo was supposed to be exceptional, too, until recognition of its independence more or less directly led to the effective partition of Georgia. When the U.S. and other states recognized Kosovo, few believed that it could have an effect on South Ossetia and Abkhazia, but it did. How many countries will suffer from greater instability because self-determination prevailed in Sudan? Once major powers start re-drawing borders to satisfy the demands of selfdetermination or other concerns, there is no obvious place to stop . Kosovo’s example isn’t supposed to have any effect on the situation in Karabakh, either, but why are the people in Karabakh and Armenia bound by this Western assumption? Supporters of the secession of South Sudan have to take into account the possibility that the success of the southern Sudanese in achieving independence will encourage other separatist and automomist movements in Africa and elsewhere. In many ways, African nation-states are among the most arbitrary, artificial creations in the entire world, but that doesn’t mean that splitting them up into equally artificial, less viable statelets will make things any better. Kosovo’s separation from Serbia and eventual independence empowered a gang of criminals. Secession creates a domino effect Byman and Pollock 12 Byman, Daniel, and Kenneth Pollack. "The Syrian Spillover." Foreign Policy (2012). Kenneth Michael Pollack, PhD, is a noted former CIA intelligence analyst and expert on Middle East politics and military affairs. Dr. Daniel L. Byman is a professor at Georgetown University's Walsh School of Foreign Service in the Security Studies Program and Department of Government Secessionism: As the Balkan countries demonstrated in the 1990s, seemingly triumphant secessionist bids can set off a domino effect . Slovenia's declaration of independence inspired Croatia, which prompted Bosnia to do the same, which encouraged Macedonia, and then Kosovo. Strife and conflict followed all of these declarations. Sometimes it is the desire of one subgroup within a state to break away that triggers the civil war in the first place. In other cases, different groups vie for control of the state, but as the Stefan Bauschard Offensive PKOs release 103 fighting drags on, one or more groups may decide that their only recourse is to secede. At times, a minority comfortable under the old regime may fear discrimination from a new government. The South Ossetians, for example, accepted Russian rule but rebelled when Georgia broke off from the Soviet Union, as they feared they would face discrimination in the new Georgian state. After Russia helped South Ossetia defeat the Georgian forces that tried to re-conquer the area in 1991-1992, the next domino fell when ethnic Abkhaz also rebelled and created their own independent area in 1991-1992. The frozen conflict that resulted from this civil war finally burst into an international shooting war between Georgia and Russia in August 2008. Stefan Bauschard Offensive PKOs release 104 R2P Fails: A2 Good Self-interest and UN charter structurally precludes effective R2P Holmes 1/7/14 http://www.heritage.org/research/commentary/2014/1/the-weakness-of-theresponsibility-to-protect-as-an-international-norm Kim R. Holmes, a Distinguished Fellow at The Heritage Foundation, oversaw the think tank’s defense and foreign policy team for more than two decades. Holmes was Heritage’s vice president for foreign and defense policy studies and director of the Davis Institute for International Studies from 1991 through 2012 except for his service, during most of the first term of President George W. Bush, as assistant secretary of state for international organization affairs. Holmes’ priority is writing a book, due in fall 2013, in which he hopes to lay out a compelling vision for America’s future by uniting Heritage’s domestic and foreign policy ideas. “Few people bring greater clarity and historical wisdom to thorny issues than Kim Holmes,” Heritage President Edwin J. Feulner said in announcing the new role on Dec. 5, 2012. Holmes previously directed Heritage's team of foreign and defense policy experts in four centers on the front lines of international affairs: the Douglas and Sarah Allison Center for Foreign Policy Studies, the Asian Studies Center, the Center for International Trade and Economics and the Margaret Thatcher Center for Freedom. Davis also includes the Washington Roundtable for the Asia-Pacific Press (WRAPP). Holmes joined Heritage in 1985 and rose to vice president in 1991. He was a founding editor of the annual Index of Economic Freedom, which has become a signature Heritage publication. He led the think tank’s efforts to convince the United States to withdraw from the Anti-Ballistic Missile Treaty. He launched Heritage’s widely respected homeland security program after September 11, as well as its program on international trade, and expanded the missile defense program to what it is today. Holmes left Heritage in late 2001 to serve as an assistant secretary of state. After rejoining the think tank in 2005, he authored the book “Liberty's Best Hope: American Leadership for the 21st Century.” Recognized around the globe as one of Washington’s foremost foreign and defense policy experts, Holmes is a member of the Council on Foreign Relations, where he formerly served on the Washington Advisory Committee. Previous appointments include the Defense Policy Board, which is the U.S. defense secretary’s primary resource for expert outside advice; the Board of Directors of the Center for International Private Enterprise; and public member of the U.S. delegation to the Organization for Security and Cooperation in Europe. While at the State Department, Holmes was responsible for developing policy and coordinating U.S. engagement at the United Nations and 46 other international organizations. Important goals achieved at that time included the U.N. mandates enabling Iraq to make the transition to democracy; the Security Council's first binding nonproliferation resolution; the U.N.'s first mandate requiring the Office of Internal Oversight Services to release reports to member states; an international outcry over Libya's assuming chairmanship of the Commission on Human Rights, which culminated in that body's refashioning; and establishment of the U.N. Democracy Caucus and U.N. Democracy Fund. Holmes earned his doctoral and master’s degrees in history from Georgetown University. He received a bachelor’s degree in history from the University of Central Florida in Orlando. He was a research fellow at the Institute for European History in Germany and adjunct professor of European security and history at Georgetown University. Over the last 60 years, additional international conventions and United Nations’ Stefan Bauschard Offensive PKOs release 105 resolutions have also established norms and standards of international humanitarian law. These include the Geneva Conventions of 1949 and its subsequent Protocols. Although not sidestepping the respect for national sovereignty still embedded in the U.N. Charter (and thus the right of the Security Council to decide ultimately questions of international peace), these conventions and resolutions did quite consciously stretch the boundaries of old definitions of sovereignty. They not only diminished the legitimacy of national sovereignty but also broadened the scope of action that international bodies could take in defense of human rights and to protect against genocide and mass murder. It was always a balancing act, but there was inherent tension between the rights of national sovereignty—which the U.N. General Assembly and Security Council jealously protected— and the rights of individuals to protection—which were championed in such bodies as the Human Rights Council, the Office of the High Commissioner for Human Rights, and the human rights treaty bodies. The resolutions on R2P ratified by the U.N. General Assembly in 2005 tried to overcome these tensions, but it still recognized the ultimate authority of the Security Council. Each state had a responsibility to protect its population, the resolution said, but collective action was to be taken “through the Security Council, in accordance with the Charter, including Chapter VII, on a case-by-case basis.…” In other words, only the Security Council could decide whether an intervention of the international community should be undertaken, which implied not only the rights of the veto of the Permanent Five (P-5) members (including the United States), but also that the universal humanitarian legal principles supposedly established by the R2P resolution were still subordinate to the principles of national sovereignty--to rights of the P-5 members in particular. Why does this matter? Because it points to the fact that R2P is a mere aspiration, as opposed to a real principle of international norms or even law. R2P sometimes not only runs against the practices of Realpolitik (where national sovereignty still reigns supreme), but more importantly, it is at odds with a fundamental principle of the United Nations itself—namely, the ultimate legal deference to national sovereignty as decided by the national members of the Security Council. The Council may approve of the concept with respect to Libya but does not do so in Syria because certain members of the P-5 (namely Russia) object. In that difference is the ultimate weakness of R2P as a principle . The opposition of Russia to a Syria intervention, for example, reveals that no matter what Moscow may think about R2P as a principle, it will not adhere to it if it violates its national interests. Frankly, as a matter of principle, the United States as a P5 member more or less does the same thing. Regardless of what the General Assembly may say, it is the actions of the Security Council that count in international peace and stability. If there is no consensus among the P-5 on how R2P should be followed, or subsequent observance of any agreement on it in practice, then it will never survive as a viable legal or normative principle of international order. R2p fails – humanitarian intervention without the pretext solves better Holmes 1/7/14 http://www.heritage.org/research/commentary/2014/1/the-weakness-of-theresponsibility-to-protect-as-an-international-norm Stefan Bauschard Offensive PKOs release 106 Kim R. Holmes, a Distinguished Fellow at The Heritage Foundation, oversaw the think tank’s defense and foreign policy team for more than two decades. Holmes was Heritage’s vice president for foreign and defense policy studies and director of the Davis Institute for International Studies from 1991 through 2012 except for his service, during most of the first term of President George W. Bush, as assistant secretary of state for international organization affairs. Holmes’ priority is writing a book, due in fall 2013, in which he hopes to lay out a compelling vision for America’s future by uniting Heritage’s domestic and foreign policy ideas. “Few people bring greater clarity and historical wisdom to thorny issues than Kim Holmes,” Heritage President Edwin J. Feulner said in announcing the new role on Dec. 5, 2012. Holmes previously directed Heritage's team of foreign and defense policy experts in four centers on the front lines of international affairs: the Douglas and Sarah Allison Center for Foreign Policy Studies, the Asian Studies Center, the Center for International Trade and Economics and the Margaret Thatcher Center for Freedom. Davis also includes the Washington Roundtable for the Asia-Pacific Press (WRAPP). Holmes joined Heritage in 1985 and rose to vice president in 1991. He was a founding editor of the annual Index of Economic Freedom, which has become a signature Heritage publication. He led the think tank’s efforts to convince the United States to withdraw from the Anti-Ballistic Missile Treaty. He launched Heritage’s widely respected homeland security program after September 11, as well as its program on international trade, and expanded the missile defense program to what it is today. Holmes left Heritage in late 2001 to serve as an assistant secretary of state. After rejoining the think tank in 2005, he authored the book “Liberty's Best Hope: American Leadership for the 21st Century.” Recognized around the globe as one of Washington’s foremost foreign and defense policy experts, Holmes is a member of the Council on Foreign Relations, where he formerly served on the Washington Advisory Committee. Previous appointments include the Defense Policy Board, which is the U.S. defense secretary’s primary resource for expert outside advice; the Board of Directors of the Center for International Private Enterprise; and public member of the U.S. delegation to the Organization for Security and Cooperation in Europe. While at the State Department, Holmes was responsible for developing policy and coordinating U.S. engagement at the United Nations and 46 other international organizations. Important goals achieved at that time included the U.N. mandates enabling Iraq to make the transition to democracy; the Security Council's first binding nonproliferation resolution; the U.N.'s first mandate requiring the Office of Internal Oversight Services to release reports to member states; an international outcry over Libya's assuming chairmanship of the Commission on Human Rights, which culminated in that body's refashioning; and establishment of the U.N. Democracy Caucus and U.N. Democracy Fund. Holmes earned his doctoral and master’s degrees in history from Georgetown University. He received a bachelor’s degree in history from the University of Central Florida in Orlando. He was a research fellow at the Institute for European History in Germany and adjunct professor of European security and history at Georgetown University. Finally, there is the question of how R2P affects the United States. Since the U.S. has a veto on the U.N. Security Council, it will never be forced to send an armed force in defense of the R2P principle against its will. But that is not the real concern. Rather, it is that, over time, the norm will be established that the only proper use of American military force is for the kinds of humanitarian operations implied by the R2P principle. Woodward and Morrison imply such a norm when they say “R2P is arguably the most radical adjustment to sovereignty since the Peace of Westphalia was signed in 1648.” The authors see this as a positive development, rather than as a concern for the use of force. They envision it as a revolutionary advance, a “victory for democracy because it Stefan Bauschard Offensive PKOs release 107 pledges to support sovereign rule only when it protects the populace it governs.” Undermining national sovereignty as a principle is a double-edged sword for the United States. As any U.S. diplomat with U.N. experience will tell you, many nations around the world are all too happy to downplay national sovereignty if it means criticizing the internal practices of the United States or Israel. And yet they jealously defend that sovereignty when it comes to their own acts. More fundamentally, however, the purposes of U.S. armed forces are still, first and foremost, to defend the sovereignty, security and freedom of the American people. They are not primarily mercenary forces to be deployed at the behest of a U.N. body, no matter how well intended that mission may be. Therefore, significantly altering U.S. military missions or planning to accommodate the R2P doctrine would be misguided. After all is said and done, R2P is not really a principle but an aspiration , and a rather weak one at that. Its defenders often say, “The fact that we cannot protect people everywhere is no reason for doing nothing when we can.” In other words, they argue that intervening in the face of mass murder is an option that cannot be relinquished. That is true. But we don’t need R2P to have that option. Whether the U.N. Security Council authorizes such an intervention will always be a practical judgment, at the discretion of sovereign members of the UNSC, and depending on all sorts of circumstances. And it is these exceptions that illuminate the weakness of R2P as a principle. The problem with R2P is that its reality never lives up to its high-sounding principles. If it wanted to, the Security Council could have intervened to stop genocide in Rwanda and elsewhere. The reason it didn’t are the same ones that will likely keep it from doing so elsewhere in the future. Ultimately R2P is riddled with too many contradictions and practical problems to make it a serious doctrine for implementation by U.S. strategy. It mainly comes down to an argument of moral suasion to intervene against mass murder and genocide, which one can make without resorting to tortured arguments about supposed international principles or even the proper purposes of warfare, and certainly without damaging the vital notion of national sovereignty. Scattershot application means fail Holmes 11 http://www.heritage.org/research/commentary/2011/04/whose-responsibility-toprotect Kim R. Holmes, a Distinguished Fellow at The Heritage Foundation, oversaw the think tank’s defense and foreign policy team for more than two decades. Holmes was Heritage’s vice president for foreign and defense policy studies and director of the Davis Institute for International Studies from 1991 through 2012 except for his service, during most of the first term of President George W. Bush, as assistant secretary of state for international organization affairs. Holmes’ priority is writing a book, due in fall 2013, in which he hopes to lay out a compelling vision for America’s future by uniting Heritage’s domestic and foreign policy ideas. “Few people bring greater clarity and historical wisdom to thorny issues than Kim Holmes,” Heritage President Edwin J. Feulner said in announcing the new role on Dec. 5, 2012. Holmes previously directed Heritage's team of foreign and defense policy experts in four centers on the front lines of international affairs: the Douglas and Sarah Allison Center for Foreign Policy Studies, the Asian Studies Center, the Center for International Trade and Stefan Bauschard Offensive PKOs release 108 Economics and the Margaret Thatcher Center for Freedom. Davis also includes the Washington Roundtable for the Asia-Pacific Press (WRAPP). Holmes joined Heritage in 1985 and rose to vice president in 1991. He was a founding editor of the annual Index of Economic Freedom, which has become a signature Heritage publication. He led the think tank’s efforts to convince the United States to withdraw from the Anti-Ballistic Missile Treaty. He launched Heritage’s widely respected homeland security program after September 11, as well as its program on international trade, and expanded the missile defense program to what it is today. Holmes left Heritage in late 2001 to serve as an assistant secretary of state. After rejoining the think tank in 2005, he authored the book “Liberty's Best Hope: American Leadership for the 21st Century.” Recognized around the globe as one of Washington’s foremost foreign and defense policy experts, Holmes is a member of the Council on Foreign Relations, where he formerly served on the Washington Advisory Committee. Previous appointments include the Defense Policy Board, which is the U.S. defense secretary’s primary resource for expert outside advice; the Board of Directors of the Center for International Private Enterprise; and public member of the U.S. delegation to the Organization for Security and Cooperation in Europe. While at the State Department, Holmes was responsible for developing policy and coordinating U.S. engagement at the United Nations and 46 other international organizations. Important goals achieved at that time included the U.N. mandates enabling Iraq to make the transition to democracy; the Security Council's first binding nonproliferation resolution; the U.N.'s first mandate requiring the Office of Internal Oversight Services to release reports to member states; an international outcry over Libya's assuming chairmanship of the Commission on Human Rights, which culminated in that body's refashioning; and establishment of the U.N. Democracy Caucus and U.N. Democracy Fund. Holmes earned his doctoral and master’s degrees in history from Georgetown University. He received a bachelor’s degree in history from the University of Central Florida in Orlando. He was a research fellow at the Institute for European History in Germany and adjunct professor of European security and history at Georgetown University. The 1990s genocides in Srebrenica and Rwanda sparked U.N. debate on how to prevent such massacres. This led to a 2001 U.N.-commissioned study, “The Responsibility to Protect: Report of the International Commission on Intervention and State Sovereignty.” That report laid out the doctrine’s main ideas: All nations have a responsibility to protect their citizens from largescale loss of life or ethnic cleansing, and if a nation failed to do this, the “international community” — working through the U.N. — had a “responsibility” to protect the aggrieved population. The U.N. General Assembly enshrined this idea in the 2005 Millennium Summit Outcome Document. The U.S. accepted, but stipulated that the document did not “obligate” nations to intervene. The Security Council subsequently reaffirmed the “responsibility” lines on several occasions, most recently in this year’s first Libyan resolution. It referenced the “authorities’” responsibility to protect its population. There are many problems with this idea. First is the hypocrisy of protecting one population while ignoring others. Why intervene with force to stop a potential massacre in Libya and ignore real genocide in Sudan’s Darfur region? Why were some of the same people who advocate a responsibility to protect in Libya so fiercely opposed to intervening in Iraq, where Saddam Hussein killed about 300,000 civilians? Given its scattershot application, “responsibility to protect” fails as a principle . Stefan Bauschard Offensive PKOs release 109 Stefan Bauschard Offensive PKOs release 110 R2P Bad: Bias Prefer our evidence – r2p good cards tainted by promilitary bias Mahoney 10/22/13 http://www.opendemocracy.net/openglobalrights/liam-mahony/myth-of-militarymight-in-r2p-choices Liam Mahony has been working in the field of civilian protection and human rights since the 1980s. Author of Proactive Presence: Field Strategies for Civilian Protection, he has done extensive fieldwork in many countries, and is a pioneer in the theory and practice of international protection. A former lecturer in Human Rights at Princeton University, he co-founded Fieldview Solutions and through it has led analysis and training for hundreds of UN and NGO protection staff deployed in conflict zones. In the debate over “ Responsibility-to-Protect ”, assumptions, cultural myths and language conspire to promote unwise military action. The effectiveness of military responses to conflict has become unconsciously and widely assumed. Are military responses so popular because objective scientific study has proven their efficacy? Or does this debate mostly reflect the daily teaching in many cultures throughout the world, that the bigger stick always wins? The promotion of violent force as the problem-solving option of last resort pervades popular culture from Hollywood to school history curricula. And it pervades this debate . R2P proponents insist that their doctrine prefers non-military approaches. But the language of the debate suggests otherwise: robust by definition means strong and healthy, but in the international community’s debate over approaches to conflict it is usually a synonym for military and violent. The double-edged phrase last resort implies both that the military option has great risks but also that if all other means fail, this is the one that will work. Gareth Evans’ piece in this debate, for instance, refers to the military option as something to be considered when “no lesser measure” is available. With thousands of lives at stake, why would we settle for “lesser measures?” Such language, so frequently used even by those who are honestly committed to civilian protection, inevitably supports calls for military action, even if it is unwise. The implicit message is that the only really serious action is military action. Everything else is weak and half-hearted. This language also invites world powers like the US to clothe their military aspirations in humanitarian rhetoric, regardless of whether their intent or final impact helps civilians on the ground. Syria, with its consistent support to Hezbollah, has been considered an enemy by the US for decades. Can we seriously be considering that the US is all of a sudden engaging now out of concern for Syrians civilians? The US is already engaged militarily supporting one side in this war, and the civilian death toll has only increased as a result. If anything, the debate regarding how best to protect civilians in Syria is much too late – the balance of consequences for civilians should have been assessed before the first military or political support was offered to the rebels, back in 2011. I have had the opportunity to spend some time in the Democratic Republic of Congo in recent years, assessing strategies for the protection of civilians, in a situation where the international community and the UN have put all their eggs in the military basket. Many Congolese themselves are also Stefan Bauschard Offensive PKOs release 111 desperately hoping for military salvation. Yet after a decade of blue berets and billions of dollars spent, civilians remain totally vulnerable to privations from armed groups as well as from the (UN-supported) Congolese military. This year the UN was faced with broad-based pressure to do something more. Despite there being no objective assessment of the real protective impact on the Congolese people of the current militarized approach, the only “new” strategy they could come up with was to strengthen the military approach and approve a UN force with an explicit offensive mandate: more military, more “robustly” offensive. Interestingly, a recent study looking at a different type of conflict – resistance movements against repressive regimes – suggests that in the last hundred years, unarmed resistance movements were more successful at achieving their objectives than armed ones. (Chenoweth, Erica, and Maria J. Stephan. Why Civil Resistance Works: The Strategic Logic of Nonviolent Conflict.) With adequate research, the hypothesis of a correlation in international interventions between military force and protective impact might be shown to be valid, or it might not. But in the meantime it is largely a myth , a heuristic simplification that gives us a too-readily-available and simple answer to complex situations. It is also a myth that gives many people hope, because we deeply wish that there were a quick solution to the human suffering we are witnessing in the conflicts that prompt these debates. Decision-makers truly concerned with protecting civilians need to recognize this unconscious assumption that privileges the military option . Rather than reacting to knee-jerk pressures to do something, or to do more, policy decisions should be based on a careful context-based analysis of each particular case, and an extremely cautious assessment of reasonable expectations of consequences. This kind of assessment is necessary before military action, before economic sanctions, or any other pressure. Those in power who order atrocities - whether President Assad or an armed group leader in the Congo - are most often interested in sustaining or increasing their own power. Such power is political, economic, and military and it depends on their relationships with others. A strategy to protect civilians must examine the real interests of these people, identifying all the political, economic and military relationships they have that present opportunities for leverage. From that analysis, a nuanced and more complex strategy would combine the range of tools of leverage available. These in turn would be tailored to maximize their combined impact, and the strategy would assess the projected balance of consequences with an emphasis on minimizing negative impacts on civilians. Those in power who order violence against civilians are usually linked to a range of powerful economic interests, and may be even more sensitive to economic pressures than to military ones. (In fact, external military threats can sometimes serve to strengthen domestic support for a targeted group – consider how Hezbollah has benefitted from Israeli attacks on Lebanon.) Economic sanctions are not a panacea, either, and may well in some cases hurt civilians far more than can be justified by their impact. Further, just as military decisions tend to be based on geo-politics divorced from the interests of civilians, decisions about economic measures tend to be skewed in the interests of economic power brokers for whom sacrificing profits for humanitarian gain is unacceptable. It should not be surprising that we cannot control the arms trade, for instance, when huge multinational interests in the US and Europe make so much money from it; or that we have difficulty fully implementing other kinds of “smart” sanctions even when they have UN Security Council backing. The fact that sanctions so seldom effectively target the wealthy, but instead too often inflict greater suffering on the poor, is no accident. The point here is not that economic measures are better or worse than military ones, but rather that there is no self-evident hierarchy among Stefan Bauschard Offensive PKOs release 112 them. If wise decisions are to be made, the costs and benefits of different measures must be carefully assessed, based on past experiences and on the real dynamics of each current context. But this is not what is happening. Instead, the debate is dominated by myths, bias and rhetoric . The crucial assessment of the expected balance of consequences has become a phrase for s oundbite s, rather than an analytical prerequisite to action . As long as the military option is perceived as more potentially effective than it is in reality, and economic and political pressures considered less effective than they might be, unwise decisions result. That is the f undamental nature of bias. Stefan Bauschard Offensive PKOs release 113 R2P = Genocide (Sudan/Syria) R2p derails effective genocide prevention – abandoning it is key to Syria and Sudan De Waal 12 http://www.nytimes.com/2012/03/10/opinion/how-to-end-mass-atrocities.html?_r=0 Alex de Waal is executive director of the World Peace Foundation at the Fletcher School, Tufts University., How to End Mass Atrocities, New York Times, March 10, DOA: 12-7-14 High from last year’s interventions in Libya and Ivory Coast, Evans wrote triumphantly in Foreign Policy last December that those missions brought “an end to most of the confused debates” about humanitarian intervention. The vision he, Power and fellow idealists share is to send the cavalry over the hill not only to stop any massacres but also to herald justice and democracy. If only it were that simple. In the face of “evil,” the idealists tend to turn righteous and forget to ask important questions about what they want to achieve and how. The result is a misrepresentation of history and a misunderstanding of the measures that can most effectively halt atrocities today. One major problem is that the idealists tend to misconstrue or overlook the fundamental motivations of perpetrators. They typically see the killers as insatiable. This is understandable because they are driven by the memory of the Holocaust and the Rwandan genocide. But the Nazis and Hutus were exceptional for making the extermination of a people essential to their politics. Most mass killers have other goals. In many cases, the perpetrators simply stop killing when they have reached their goals, become exhausted, fallen out among themselves or been defeated. Take the Nigerian civil war of 1967-70. Despite a blockade of the secessionist province of Biafra and the genocidal rhetoric of some Nigerian leaders, the killing ended when the Biafran rebels finally fell to Nigerian forces. Having achieved their military aim, the Nigerians then began a process of reconciliation and reconstruction under the banner “no victor, no vanquished.” In Guatemala, the perpetrators of the 1980-83 massacres of Mayan communities suspected of supporting Communist insurgents called an end to the atrocities after defeating the rebels. In Indonesia, the generals stopped killing the Communists in 1966 once the group no longer posed a threat. The soldiers of President Milton Obote massacred tens of thousands of people in Uganda’s Luwero Triangle in 1983-4 — until they were defeated on the battlefield. Likewise, the killings in East Pakistan ended with India’s invasion in 1971 and the Khmer Rouge’s atrocities in Cambodia with Vietnam’s intervention in 1978-79. In other words, even once they are under way, mass atrocities do not lead inexorably to bottomless massacres. The killers usually have political goals: They are determined to kill until they have achieved their objectives, not until there’s no one else left standing. Their use of violence can be excessive, but more important, it is often instrumental. This creates an opportunity for negotiating an end to mass atrocities, through peace talks and with financial and diplomatic incentives and pressure. In recent history such dealmaking has brought to an end, albeit often an imperfect one, massacres in Burundi, East Timor, Kenya, Macedonia and South Sudan. Yet the idealists insist on pursuing a more ambitious agenda: nothing short of democracy and justice, imposed by military intervention. And this can undermine simply getting the killing to Stefan Bauschard Offensive PKOs release 114 stop. For perpetrators, the prospect of foreign intervention and prosecution rules out the possibility for compromise. For rebels, it creates a perverse incentive to escalate ethnic violence so as to provoke an international military response. The idealists’ blind spot about nonideal endings also means they cannot decide what do to when the killings do subside. In September 2004, Secretary of State Colin Powell announced that a genocide had occurred, and might be continuing, in Darfur. But by then the level of violence had already begun to drop, and it continued to diminish over the next few years. U.S. policy stayed stuck on trying to stop massacres that were no longer happening. In 2009, Scott Gration, the U.S. special envoy to Sudan, was saying there were “remnants of genocide.” But in 2010, Susan Rice, the U.S. ambassador to the United Nations, was still insisting there was an “ongoing genocide.” Unable to commit itself to either aggressive regime change or a program of reconstruction and reconciliation, the U.S. government hasn’t made any progress on either approach. And its indecision has delayed finding a workable political solution for Darfur. Western policy makers interested in stopping mass crimes should not overlook tools that can work. Where violence is used as an instrument for political gain, it is negotiable. Some perpetrators can be moderated through diplomacy. Others will stop killing if they defeat a rebellion or realize they cannot. The main aim should be to stop genocidal killing . Holding elections and prosecuting the perpetrators of crimes, however laudable those goals, aren’t the priority. Today, with civilians in Sudan’s Nuba Mountains threatened by mass hunger and violence, U.S. campaigners are calling for humanitarian intervention. They should remember to keep the political solution firmly in focus. The root of the crisis is a war between evenly matched adversaries who must recognize that they need to live with the other. The peace talks that stalled last July should be revived. This would require Khartoum to lift the ban against the Sudan People’s Liberation Movement in the northern sector and begin an inclusive constitutional reform process. The rebels and their South Sudanese backers, for their part, would have to repudiate the goal of regime change. Politics are also all-important in Syria. The crisis has evolved from a civilian uprising to a fully fledged civil war, with each side fearing annihilation if it loses. The regime of Bashar al-Assad needs a soft landing, and so the model for solving this crisis is the kind of patient mediation effort that was deployed in Yemen, not aggressive intervention as in Libya. Responding to mass atrocities, whether ongoing or imminent, is difficult enough, but the idealism of Evans and Power makes it that much more so. They have composed a story, based on ethics rather than evidence, that incorrectly assumes all perpetrators of mass political violence are insatiable killers and that dictates who should respond (Western nations), how (with military intervention) and why (for justice and democracy). It is a morality tale that undermines the best ways to deal with the worst crimes. Stefan Bauschard Offensive PKOs release 115 R2p Bad: Drone Strikes R2P legitimacy key to escalating globe drone strikes Brooks 1/14/13 http://www.globalpolicy.org/qhumanitarianq-intervention/52290-hate-obamas-dronewar.html?itemid=id#26087 Rosa Brooks is a law professor at the Georgetown University Law Center, a columnist and contributing editor for Foreign Policy and a Bernard L. Schwartz senior fellow at the New America Foundation. From April 2009 to July 2011, she served as Counselor to the Under Secretary of Defense for Policy, Michele Flournoy, and in May 2010 she also became [1] Special Coordinator for Rule of Law and Humanitarian Policy, running a new Pentagon office dedicated to those issues. Brooks wrote a weekly column for the Los Angeles Times from 2005 to 2009, and is an expert on national security, international law and human rights issues. At the Pentagon her portfolio included both rule of law and human rights issues and global engagement, strategic communication, and she received the Secretary of Defense Medal for Outstanding Public Service for her work. This notion of a " responsibility to protect" was embraced by the international community -- including the United States -- with surprising rapidity. In every way, it represents a radical assault on traditional legal concepts of sovereignty. The "responsibility to protect" doctrine -- often now referred to as R2P -- suggests that when a state fails to protect its own population, it can no longer claim any right to be free of external intervention (including, in extreme cases, military intervention) if intervention is needed to secure the safety of a threatened population. And by implication, that intervention need not necessarily be authorized by the U.N. Security Council. If the Security Council "fails to discharge its responsibility to protect in conscience-shocking situations crying out for action...concerned states may not rule out other means to meet the gravity and urgency of that situation," observed the 2001 ICISS report. The logic is clear enough: If failure to protect its population delegitimizes a state's legal claim to sovereignty, then the failure of collective security structures (such as the UNSC) to take appropriate corrective action would similarly delegitimize those collective institutions. Put a little differently, the Responsibility to Protect logically implies that both "the international community" and individual states have a right and a duty to intervene -- militarily, if necessary -- when another state is "unwilling or unable" to protect its own population. If the language justifying drone strikes in sovereign states appears to directly parallel the language of the Responsibility to Protect, it's no accident. Although the R2P doctrine was developed in response to genocide and other mass atrocities, the language of R2P was easily turned to other purposes . That's not entirely inappropriate, either: R2P's underlying logic is equally applicable to terrorism, which is itself a form of human rights abuse (and one that can have devastating consequences for civilian populations). As I have argued elsewhere, you "might even say that the R2P coin ought logically to be seen as having two sides . On one side lies a state's duty to take action inside its own territory to protect itsown population from violence and atrocities. On the other side lies a state's duty to take action inside its own territory to protect other states' populations from violence. Either way, a Stefan Bauschard Offensive PKOs release 116 state that fails in these duties faces the prospect that other states will intervene in its ‘internal' affairs without its consent." In a sense, then, it was the human rights community's critique of sovereignty that helped pave the way for drone strikes. Stefan Bauschard Offensive PKOs release 117 R2P = Imperialism R2p is a fig leaf for imperialism Global Policy Forum 14 http://www.globalpolicy.org/qhumanitarianq-intervention.html Global Policy Forum is an independent policy watchdog that monitors the work of the United Nations and scrutinizes global policymaking. We promote accountability and citizen participation in decisions on peace and security, social justice and international law. What is to be done in a crisis like the genocide in Rwanda, when the international community seeks to stop the killing? Can nations, acting through the UN Security Council, fulfill a "responsibility to protect" innocent civilians? Or is such a doctrine just a Trojan horse for great power abuse? When nations send their military forces into other nations' territory, it is rarely (if ever) for "humanitarian" purposes. They are typically pursuing their narrow national interest - grabbing territory, gaining geo-strategic advantage, or seizing control of precious natural resources. Leaders hope to win public support by describing such actions in terms of high moral purposes bringing peace, justice, democracy and civilization to the affected area. In the era of colonialism, European governments all cynically insisted that they acted to promote such higher commitments - the "white man's burden," "la mission civilisatrice," and so on and so forth. The appeal to higher moral purposes continues to infect the political discourse of the great powers. Today's " humanitarian intervention" is only the latest in this long tradition of political obfuscation . In 2003, the US-UK invasion and occupation of Iraq was labeled "humanitarian intervention" by UK Prime Minister Tony Blair Stefan Bauschard Offensive PKOs release 118 R2P = imperialism: Africa Indeterminacy of R2p allows repeated interventions against Africa Branch 11/6/12 http://www.globalpolicy.org/qhumanitarianq-intervention/52035-theresponsibility-to-protect-what-is-the-basis-for-the-emerging-norm-ofr2p.html?itemid=id#26087 Assistant Professor of Political Science, San Diego State University, 2008Research Associate, Makerere Institute of Social Re search, 2011EDUCATION Ph.D. (Political Science) Columbia University, 2007 A.B. (Social Studies) Harvard University, 1998 Africa has a long history of being 'protected' by the West. And today, with the precipitous rise of the so-called Responsibility to Protect (R2P), it appears that intervention in the name of protecting Africa has returned to the centre of Western concern – or regained its utility. Three-quarters of the crises in which R2P has been invoked or applied have been in Africa and the Special Advisor to the Secretary-General on R2P announced that “the responsibility to protect really came from Africa and the African experience" Africa also provided the military testing ground for R2P and following foreign military intervention in Libya in 2011, according to Ramesh Thakur, “R2P is closer to being solidified as an actionable norm". R2P’s privileged application in Africa bears comparison to the continent's experience with the International Criminal Court (ICC). Critics have argued that the Court targets Africa because it can operate there in an accountability-free zone, able to intervene in ongoing conflicts, take sides in civil wars, scuttle amnesties and peace processes, or align itself with US military forces – all without being held responsible for the consequences of its actions. But at least with the ICC, there is a concrete institution – prosecutors and judges who make statements and decisions that can be critiqued on legal, political, or moral grounds. With R2P, however, even this modicum of publicity and formalisation is absent. And this makes its expanding use in Africa all the more dangerous. The first problem is that no-one seems sure of what R2P even is. Its proponents have celebrated it as a norm, a doctrine, a concept, an idea, a principle, a framework, or a lens, while its critics have dismissed or condemned it as an excuse, an ideology, a fad, or an empty slogan. Illustrating this uncertainty is the fact that, while most agree that R2P enjoys no legal status of its own, others seem to give it an almost super-legal status. Take the statement by Susan Rice, current US Ambassador to the UN, for example, who in 2007 invoked R2P to justify a threatened US ground and air attack against Sudan without Security Council approval. Rice cited R2P to dismiss the possible legal problems of invading a sovereign state, asserting: “Still others insist that, without the consent of the UN or a relevant regional body, we would be breaking international law. Perhaps, but the Security Council last year codified a new international norm prescribing ‘the responsibility to protect’. It commits UN members to decisive action, including enforcement, when peaceful measures fail to halt genocide or crimes against humanity.” Not surprisingly, there is also no consensus on what actions R2P actually legitimates, nor by whom or when. The problem is compounded by the multiplicity of statements on R2P, from the Stefan Bauschard Offensive PKOs release 119 2001 International Commission on Intervention and State Sovereignty (ICISS) report to the United Nations’ 2004 A More Secure World: Our Shared Responsibility, to the 2005 World Summit Outcome Document, to the SecretaryGeneral’s 2009 Implementing the Responsibility to Protect. The original statement of R2P in the ICISS report explains: “State sovereignty implies responsibility, and the primary responsibility for the protection of its people lies with the state itself. Where a population is suffering serious harm, as a result of internal war, insurgency, repression or state failure, and the state in question is unwilling or unable to halt or avert it, the principle of nonintervention yields to the international responsibility to protect.” Of course, the statement poses more questions than it answers. What is the threshold at which responsibility is legitimately taken up by the international community? Who makes that decision? And who is the international community? The precise sequence of actions necessary to fulfil R2P is also left undefined. According to ICISS, R2P comprises three “specific responsibilities”: the responsibility to prevent, by addressing “both the root causes and direct causes” of crises; the responsibility to react to “situations of compelling human need” by employing “appropriate measures”, up to military intervention; and the responsibility to rebuild, which will help address “the causes of the harm the intervention was designed to halt or avert”. Given the increasingly expansive formulations of R2P, according to which R2P action is to help prevent, react, and rebuild countries, work with, pressure, and coerce states, and address root causes and prevent the recurrence of conflict, there seems to be little that is not included among the instruments that may be legitimately used in the name of R2P. This could span from development aid to diplomatic pressure, from direct budgetary assistance to invasion and occupation, from traditional reconciliation to international criminal prosecution. Even one of R2P’s most vocal academic supporters, Alex Bellamy, admits that, “it is seldom – if ever – clear what R2P requires in a given situation”. The result is a situation in which some analysts can condemn the AU-UN intervention in Darfur as a dismal failure of R2P while others can laud it as a success; some blame R2P as an excuse used to prevent effective intervention there while others credit it with enabling international involvement. The same ambiguity characterises discussions of the R2P in Kenya during the post-election violence in 2008. Some would agree with Kofi Annan that “Kenya is a successful example of R2P at work” but others deny that R2P played a role in the unfolding of international involvement, explaining that “the situation was only labelled a R2P situation retrospectively”. This fundamental indeterminacy of R2P was made even clearer, as was its danger, in the Libya intervention. The doctrine’s first full-scale deployment led to the bombing of civilian infrastructure, the deposing and killing of Muammar Gaddafi, the installing of a rebel government, and the arming of civilians – all in the name of protection. The last was justified by a senior French diplomatic source as: “an operational decision taken at the time to help civilians who were in imminent danger. A group of civilians were about to be massacred so we took the decision to provide self-defensive weapons to protect those civilian populations under threat…It was entirely justifiable legally, resolution 1970 and 1973 were followed to the letter." R2P is not only dangerous because it is flexible enough to be used to justify overthrowing governments and arming civilians, but also because it allows those using it to refuse accountability. States can engage in political and military intervention without having to justify those interventions on political or military grounds, only on protection grounds. And they can refuse responsibility for the consequences of their actions – all is fair when civilian protection is at stake. R2P can be used to justify military intervention or non-intervention, invasion or withdrawal. Thus, it is precisely R2P’s indeterminacy that makes it so popular today. This may suggest something about the West’s current approach to Africa: occasional violent engagement in Stefan Bauschard Offensive PKOs release 120 the name of protection when a state has been declared to have failed in its own protection role, complemented by military assistance to client states in the name of promoting their capacity to protect. This is combined with disengagement when convenient in the name of allowing states to fulfil the protection mandate themselves, all with no objective standards and no accountability. Mahmood Mamdani has argued that one consequence of R2P is to insti-tute a divided international system that distinguishes African states , whose legitimacy and sovereignty are to be judged by the “international community”, from Western states, whose sovereignty is beyond question and that judge and intervene in Africa. R2P institutes a divided international system in another way as well: one within Africa that distin-guishes those African states that are favoured by the West and tend to be labelled human rights protectors, responsible, and thus deserving support, from those that are out of favour with the West and are labelled human rights violators, failed or criminal, and meriting international coercion. This is not to say that every Western ally will be termed a human rights protector and every adversary a human rights violator. But, by grounding the judgment as to state legiti-macy in the flexible, informal language of R2P, giving that judgment to those who have the power to claim to speak in the name of the international community, and stripping away the need for the state or interveners to be accountable to African citizenries, this division remains an ever-present and dangerous possibility. Stefan Bauschard Offensive PKOs release 121 R2P =Imperialism – Kills International Law R2P is a pretext for interventionism – crushes collective security and ilaw Herman 11/9/13 http://www.voltairenet.org/article180927.html Edward S. Herman is professor emeritus of finance at the Wharton School, University of Pennsylvania and has written extensively on economics, political economy, and the media. Among his books are Corporate Control, Corporate Power (Cambridge University Press, 1981), The Real Terror Network (South End Press, 1982), and, with Noam Chomsky, The Political Economy of Human Rights (South End Press, 1979), and Manufacturing Consent (Pantheon, 2002). Both the Responsibility to Protect (R2P) and “Humanitarian Intervention” (HI) came into existence in the wake of the fall of the Soviet Union, which ended any obstruction that that contesting Great Power had placed on the ongoing power projection of the United States. In Western ideology, of course, the United States was containing the Soviets in the post-World War II years, but that was ideology. In reality the Soviet Union was always far less powerful than the United States, had weaker and less reliable allies, and was essentially on the defensive from 1945 till its demise in 1991. The United States was aggressively on the march outward from 1945, with the steady spread of military bases across the globe, numerous interventions, large and small, on all continents, engaged in building the first truly global empire. The Soviet Union was an obstruction to U.S. expansion, with sufficient military power to constitute a modest containing force, but it also served U.S. propaganda as an alleged expansionist threat. With the death of the Soviet Union new threats were needed to justify the continuing and even accelerating U.S. projection of power, and they were forthcoming, from narco-terrorism to Al Qaeda to Saddam’s weapons of mass destruction to the terrorist threat that encompassed the entire planet earth and its outer space. There was also a global security menace alleged, based on internal ethnic struggles and human rights violations, that supposedly threatened wider conflicts, as well as presenting the global community (and its policeman) with a moral dilemma and demand for intervention in the interests of humanity and justice. As noted, this morality surge occurred at a moment in history when the Soviet constraint was ended and the United States and its close allies were celebrating their triumph, when the socialist option had lost vitality, and when the West was thus freer to intervene. This required overriding the several hundred year old Westphalian core principle of international relations – that national sovereignty should be respected – which if adhered to would protect smaller and weaker countries from Great Power cross-border attacks. This rule was embodied in the UN Charter, and could be said to be the fundamental feature of that document, described by international law scholar Michael Mandel as ”the world’s constitution.” Over-riding this rule and Charter fundamental would clear the ground for R2P and HI, but it would also clear the ground for classic and straightforward aggression in pursuit of geopolitical interests, for which R2P and HI might supply a useful cover. It is obvious that only the Great Powers can cross borders in the alleged interest of R2P and HI, a point that is recognized and taken as an entirely acceptable premise in every case in which they have been applied in recent years. The Great Powers are the only ones with the knowledge and material resources to do this ‘benevolent’ global social work. As NATO public relations official Jamie Shea explained in May 1999, when the question came up as to Stefan Bauschard Offensive PKOs release 122 whether NATO personnel might be indicted for war crimes during NATO’s bombing war against Serbia, which seemed to follow from the letter of the International Criminal Tribunal for the Former Yugoslavia (ICTY) charter: NATO countries “organized” the ICTY and International Court of Justice, and NATO countries “fund these tribunals and support on a daily basis their activities. We are the upholders, not the violators, of international law.” This last is a contestable assertion, but Shea’s other points are clearly valid. It is enlightening that when a group of independent lawyers submitted an extensive dossier in 1999 showing probable NATO violations of ICTY rules, after a long delay and following open pressure from NATO authorities, the anti-NATO claims were disallowed by the ICTY prosecutor on the ground that with only 496 documented killings of Serbs by NATO bombs “there is simply no evidence of a crime base” for indicting NATO, although the original May 1999 indictment of Milosevic involved a crime base of only 344 deaths. It is of similar interest that International Criminal Court (ICC) prosecutor Luis Moreno-Ocampo declined to prosecute NATO officials for their attack on Iraq in 2003, despite over 249 requests for ICC action, on the ground that here also “the situation did not appear to meet the required threshold of the Statute.” These two cases illustrate the fact that the structures and laws that underlie the application of R2P (and HI) exempt the Great Power enforcers from the laws and rules that they enforce on the lesser powers. It also exempts their friends and clients. This means that in the real world there is nobody responsible for protecting Iraqis or Afghanis from the United States or Palestinians from Israel. When U.S. Secretary of State Madeleine Albright acknowledged on national TV in 1996 that 500,000 Iraqi children may have died as a result of UN (but really U.S.) -imposed sanctions on Iraq, declaring that U.S. officials felt these deaths were “worth it,” there was no domestic or global reaction demanding the end of these sanctions and the application of R2P or HI on behalf of the victimized Iraqi population. Similarly there was no call for any R2P intervention on behalf of the Iraqis when the United States and Britain invaded Iraq in March 2003, with direct and induced civil war killings of perhaps a million more Iraqis. When the Canadian-sponsored International Coalition for the Responsibility to Protect considered the Iraq war in relation to R2P, its authors concluded that abuses by Saddam Hussein within Iraq were not of a scope in 2003 to justify an invasion, but the coalition never even raised the question of whether the Iraqi people didn’t need protection from the invaders responsible for the death of vast numbers. They worked from the imperial premise that the Great Power enforcers, even when aggressing in violation of the UN Charter and killing hundreds of thousands, are exempt from R2P as well as the rule of law. This works from the top of the global power structure on down; Bush, Cheney, Obama, John Kerry, Susan Rice, Samantha Power at the top, then on the way down we have Merkel, Cameron, and Hollande, then further down Ban Ki-Moon and Luis Moreno-Ocampo, and with their power base to be found in the corporate leadership and media. Ban KiMoon and his predecessor Kofi Annan have been open servants of the Great NATO Powers, to whom they owe their status and authority. Kofi Annan was an enthusiastic supporter of the NATO attack on Yugoslavia, a believer in the enforcement responsibility of the NATO powers, and keen on the institutionalization of R2P; and Ban Ki-Moon works in the same mode. This same global power structure also means that ad hoc Tribunals will be formed and used against villains of choice, as well as international courts. Thus when the United States and its allies wanted to dismantle Yugoslavia and weaken Serbia, they were able to use the Security Council in 1993 to establish a tribunal, the ICTY, precisely for this service, which the ICTY carried out effectively. When they wanted to help their client Paul Kagame consolidate his dictatorship in Rwanda, they created a similar tribunal for this service, the ICTR. If these powers want to attack and bring about regime change in Libya, they can get the Stefan Bauschard Offensive PKOs release 123 ICC to accuse Gaddaffi of war crimes speedily and without independent investigation of any charges, and based mainly on anticipations of civilian killings. But as noted, the ICC couldn’t find any basis for action against the invaders of Iraq whose killings of civilians were large-scale and realized, not merely anticipated. There was, in fact, a major World Tribunal on Iraq organized to hear charges against the United States and its allies for their actions in Iraq, but it was privately organized and had a critical anti-war bent, so that although it held hearings in many countries and heard many prestigious witnesses, this tribunal was given negligible attention in the media. (Its final sessions and report in June 2005 were unmentioned in the major U.S, and British media.) R2P fits snugly into this picture of service to an escalating imperial violence, with the United States and its enormous militaryindustrial complex engaged in a Global War on Terror and multiple wars, and its NATO arm steadily enlarging and embarked on “out of area” service, despite the ending of its supposed role of containing the Soviet Union. It conveniently premises that the threats that the world needs to address come from within countries, not from cross-border aggression in the traditional mode that the makers of the UN Charter considered of first importance. They are wrong: William Blum lists 35 cases where the United States overthrew governments between 1945 and 2001 (thus not even counting the war-making of George W. Bush and Barak Obama; Blum, Freeing the World to Death [Common Courage, 2005], chaps. 11 and 15) In the real world, while R2P has a wonderful aura of benevolence, it will be put in play only at the instigation of the Great NATO Powers and it will therefore never be used in the interest of unworthy victims, defined as victims of the Great Powers or their clients (see Manufacturing Consent, chap 2, “Worthy and Unworthy Victims”). For example, it was never invoked to constrain Indonesian violence in its invasion and occupation of East Timor from 1975 onward, although this invasion-occupation accounted for an estimated 200,000 deaths on a population base of 800,000, thus exceeding the proportionate deaths under Pol Pot. In this case the United States gave the invasion a green light, gave further arms to the invaders, and protected them from any UN response. This is a case where the UN Charter was being violated and East Timorese desperately needed protection, but as the United States supported the invader no international response transpired. It is enlightening and amusing to see that Gareth Evans has been perhaps the leading spokesperson in support of R2P.as an instrument of justice. Evans is a former Foreign Minister of Australia, author of a book on R2P, past president of the International Crisis Group, a co-founder of the International Commission on Intervention and State Sovereignty, and a participant in several reports and debates on R2P. Evans was the Foreign Minister of Australia during the years of Indonesia’s genocidal occupation of East Timor, and in that role Evans honored and feted Indonesian leaders and worked with them in sharing the stolen oil rights of East Timor. (See John Pilger, “East Timor: a lesson in why the poorest threaten the powerful,” April 5, 2012, pilger.com.) So Evans was really a collaborator in a major genocide. Can you imagine the media’s response to a nonNATO human rights campaign that used as spokesperson a Chinese official who had maintained friendly relations with Pol Pot during his most deadly years? It is enlightening to see how Gareth Evans deals with the criteria for enforcing R2P. In answering questions on this subject at a UN General Assembly session on R2P, Evans appealed to common sense: R2P “defines itself,” and the crimes, including “ethnic cleansing,” are all “inherently conscience-shocking, and by their very nature of a scale that demands a response…It is really impossible to be precise about numbers here.” Evans notes that sometimes modest numbers will suffice: “We remember starkly the horror of Srebrenica… [with only 8,000 deaths]. Was Racak with its 45 victims in Kosovo in ’99 sufficient to trigger the response that was Stefan Bauschard Offensive PKOs release 124 triggered by the international community?” It was sufficient to trigger a response for the simple reason that it helped advance NATO’s ongoing program of dismantlement of Yugoslavia. But Evans dodges answering his own question. You may be sure that Evans does not ask or attempt to explain why there was no triggering of a response to East Timor with its 200,000 or Iraq’s 500,000 plus a million. The politicization of choices here is total, but Evans has apparently internalized the imperial perspective so completely that this huge double standard never reaches his consciousness. But the most interesting fact is that a man with such a record and such blatant bias can be accepted as an authority and his biased perspective is treated with respect. It is interesting, also, to see how Evans never mentions Israel and Neither Palestine, where ethnic cleansing has been in active process for decades, works openly and is deeply resented by vast numbers across the globe. do other members of the power pyramid suggest Israel-Palestine as an area where consciences are shocked and the nature and scale of abuse demands a response from the “international community.” In order to obtain her U.N. Ambassadorship, Samantha Power thought it was necessary to go before a group of pro-Israel U.S. citizens and assure them, with tears flowing, that she regretted any past suggestions that AIPAC was powerful and that its influence had to be over-ridden for developing a U.S.-interest policy toward Israel and Palestine. She pledged a devotion to Israel’s national security. The world will wait a long time for Power and her bosses to support R2P’s application to ethnic cleansing in Palestine In sum, the international power structure in the post-Soviet world has worsened global inequality and at the same time increased Great Power interventionism and literal aggression . The increased militarism may have contributed to the growing inequality, but it is also designed and serves to facilitate pacification at home as well as abroad. In this context, R2P and HI are understandable developments, providing a moral cover for actions that would repel many people and constitute a violation of international law if viewed in a cold light. R2P puts aggression in a benevolent light and thus serves as its useful instrument. In short, it is a cynical fraud and a constitution ( UN Charter)-buster Stefan Bauschard Offensive PKOs release 125 R22 Hypocritical R2P is necessarily a hypocritical fiction – only used against weak states Menon 6/12/13 http://www.the-american-interest.com/articles/2013/06/12/its-fatally-flawed/ Rajan Menon is Anne and Bernard Spitzer Professor of Political Science, City College of New York/City University of New York, and a senior fellow at the Atlantic Council. The world has not obliged Practical interests shape States and its democratic comes to R2P, they, just revolutionary liberals. Raison d’état is resilient: what states do, not abstract ideals. The United allies are not exceptions to this rule. When it as China and Russia have, will block punitive measures against friendly governments. Imagine that the so-called Arab Spring makes a delayed appearance in Saudi Arabia. Would the Saudis ever face a Security Council resolution with “R2P” in it? Would the United States, Britain or France back an R2P resolution occasioned by Israel’s use of force in the West Bank or Gaza? No and no. Those who doubt this might ponder recent events in Bahrain, where a Sunni-run state lords over its Shi‘a majority. The Obama Administration deemed Qaddafi’s violence against the Libyan opposition R2Pworthy but has been unmoved by the Bahraini regime’s repression of unarmed protestors. Nor is Washington’s stance likely to change so long as the U.S. Fifth Fleet is headquartered in Bahrain. Saudi Arabia played a decisive role in mobilizing Arab support for UNSCR 1973, which authorized the intervention against Qaddafi; but it sent troops into Bahrain to crush the Shi‘a rebellion three days before NATO’s intervention in Libya. Qatar, too, mustered Arab League support for the move against Qaddafi and provided combat aircraft to supplement NATO’s Libya intervention, but its troops joined the Saudi gendarmes’ march into Manama. What mattered for the Gulf monarchies was preventing the rise of a Shi‘a-dominated state in Bahrain aligned with Iran. Self-determination and liberty could wait—indefinitely. Egyptian security forces killed 840 unarmed civilians and injured some 6,000 during the uprising against Mubarak; no major government invoked R2P.Had Mubarak survived and unleashed his army in full, would he have shared Qaddafi’s R2P-tinged fate? Not likely. Strong horses don’t attract R2P attention; only weak or vulnerable ones do. Powerful democracies have long been willing to countenance the killing and expulsions of people and to arm governments that commit such acts. Consider some examples. Turkey’s war against the PKK has killed thousands of civilians since 1984 and displaced another 386,000. In 1988–89, Saddam Hussein gassed and deported thousands of Kurds, killing as many as 100,000 of them, and systematically razed their towns and villages. But Washington turned a blind eye because the Iraqi dictator was then providing a useful service by fighting Khomeini’s Iran. Consider, too, that between Indonesia’s annexation of East Timor in 1975 and the 1999 UN-sanctioned, Australian-led intervention, 18,600 East Timorese civilians were killed, and another 102,800 died from war-related hunger and disease, with the vast majority of the fatalities occurring before 1999. Australia was rightly complimented for leading the multilateral force that helped bring stability, and eventually independence, to East Timor. But the Australian government, its own documents have since revealed, knew that Indonesia was preparing to conquer East Timor in 1975, may have provided tacit approval, and certainly was willing to arm Suharto’s government in the years Stefan Bauschard Offensive PKOs release 126 preceding the annexation.Not only was Australia the only major Western democracy to officially recognize the annexation; Gareth Evans, then its Foreign Minister, signed a deal in 1989 with his Indonesian counterpart, Ali Alatas, giving Australian energy companies access to the seabed off East Timor. As for the United States, it armed the Indonesian army for years, even though between 500,000 and one million people perished following the 1965 coup that brought Suharto to power. It is now clear that Indonesia’s conquest of East Timor occurred with the Ford Administration’s foreknowledge—and acquiescence. American arms sales to Indonesia rose substantially after its occupation of East Timor. Britain’s dealings with Suharto followed a similar pattern. Stefan Bauschard Offensive PKOs release 127 R2P = White Supremacy R2p is a cover for global white supremacy Barake 9/9/13 http://www.fairobserver.com/article/humanitarian-intervention-us-imperialism Ajamu Baraka was the Founding Executive Director of the US Human Rights Network (USHRN) from July 2004 until June 2011. The USHRN became the first domestic human rights formation in the United States explicitly committed to the application of international human rights standards to the US. Under Baraka, the Network grew exponentially from a core membership base of 60 organizations to more than 300 US-based member organizations and 1,500 individual members who work on the full spectrum of human rights issues in the United States. Baraka has also served on the boards of various national and international human rights organizations, including Amnesty International (USA) and the National Center for Human Rights Education. He is currently on the boards of the Center for Constitutional Rights; Africa Action; Latin American Caribbean Community Center; Diaspora Afrique; and the Mississippi Workers’ Center for Human Rights. Baraka has taught political science at various universities, including Clark Atlanta University and Spelman College. He has been a guest lecturer at academic institutions throughout the US, and has authored several articles on international human rights. How is it that the administration can announce to the world its intentions to circumvent, and by doing so, subvert international prohibitions on war? By wrapping itself in the false flag of humanitarian concerns f or the suffering masses in Syria. President Barack Obama, the corporate and financial elite’s most effective propaganda weapon since Ronald Reagan, explains to the world that it is only the plight of people in Syria that drives the US decision to attack the country. No one asks the president to explain to the innocent human beings who are walking around today alive, but who will be the dead and maimed “collateral damage” of this pending attack, why their sacrifice is for the greater good of humanity. This justification for the latest breech of international law is yet another example of the sham that is “humanitarian intervention.” If “mass killings of its own people” constitutes a “crime against humanity” and “mass” in Syria means over a thousand people killed, surely the killing of over a thousand in Egypt must also constitute a serious crime against humanity. But that kind of rational calculation could only occur if there were one ethical standard for all states and an equal value placed on human life. Two Moral Standards The reality, however, is that there are two mutually exclusive moral standards: one for the vast majority of nations, and another for those comprising the dying but dangerous collection of European colonial capitalist nations. It is the naked pursuit of US geo-political interests like the gas off the coast of Syria, oil, and the desire to isolate Iran that drive policy and not some concern for the people in Syria. That is the context that shapes and informs US foreign policies globally. In the current context of relative US decline, international law related to non-economic functions and relationships – the Geneva accords and the law of war, human rights and the Charter of the United Nations are now constraints on the ability of the US to pursue its interests. And with no domestic checks on executive power with the capitulation and collaboration of Congress (despite this “feint” toward democratic accountability represented in seeking congressional approval from Congress before attacking Syria), a corporate media that serves as cheerleaders for the administration, and peace Stefan Bauschard Offensive PKOs release 128 and anti-imperialist movements that are marginal and in political disarray, US criminality is completely out of control with the result that the United States has become the quintessential Rogue State. Why has it been so easy for the State to obfuscate its interests and to create a bipartisan coalition united in its support for the essentials of US foreign policies, even while there may be disagreements on some of the tactical issues? This can be partially explained by the innovative discourses produced by Western propagandists during the last two decades, the most innovative being the concept of “ humanitarian intervention” and its dubious corollary, the “right to protect.” Humanitarian intervention and the right to protect evoke the unacknowledged white supremacist assumption that the “international community” – read as the governments of the capitalist/colonialist West – has a duty and a right to arrest, bomb, invade, prosecute, sanction, murder and violate international law anywhere on the planet to “save” people based on its own determinations and values. That is precisely why the question of what entitles the US to inflict punishments on the Syrian government is not even raised as part of a public discussion. That question and its answer are obvious to the victims of Western colonial and imperialist brutality: The US and its European allies have that right because they have always had the right over the last 500 years to universalize and impose their assumptions, world views and values. Normalization of White Supremacist Domination The normalization of white supremacist domination and its prerogatives are so completely inculcated in US and Western consciousness that not only is the question as to what right the US and the West have to attack Syria outside the framework of consideration, but alternative ways of viewing the world are beyond cognitive comprehension . This is the cultural and ideological foundation of “American exceptionalism and the intellectual framework and assumptions that informed Western-based human rights organizations and their theoreticians in the construction of the notion of humanitarian intervention. De-contextualized from the reality of globalized Euro-American domination, the idea that there is a collective responsibility on the part of states to protect people from gross and systemic human rights violations associated with war crimes, genocide, crimes against humanity, and ethnic cleansing, could be viewed as a progressive development for international relations and global morality – even if that protection if offered selectively. But in the hands of an arrogant minority that still dominates the international system and sees its civilizational project as representing the apex of human development, the right to protect has become a convenient cover for rationalizing and justifying continued Euro-American global hegemony through the use of armed interventions to refashion local realities in line with Western geopolitical interests. Stefan Bauschard Offensive PKOs release 129 R2P = Syria Intervention R2P crucial to selling Syrian intervention Thrall 2/22/12 http://nationalinterest.org/blog/the-skeptics/responsibility-protect-6559 A. Trevor Thrall is an associate professor of government and politics at George Mason University and director of the Biodefense Program. He is the coeditor of American Foreign Policy and the Politics of Fear: Threat Inflation since 9/11 and coeditor of the forthcoming book Why Did the United States Invade Iraq? Intervention in Syria is either a dangerous idea, an opportunity to further the cause of democracy promotion or nothing less than the moral duty of the international community. The Obama administration continues to act cagey about the prospects of a successful intervention and the potential for geopolitical fallout from Russia, China and Iran. But given European pressure and the recent Libyan precedent, it seems more than possible that the United States will come to embrace some sort of military intervention in Syria as the love child of regime-changing neoconservatives and genocide-preventing idealists . The real question then will be: Can Obama sell a Syrian intervention to the public? And if so, how? The likeliest pitch for Obama to use is some form of the responsibility-to-protect (R2P) ethic . Articulated after the international community’s tepid response to the Bosnian meltdown, R2P has become the liberal interventionist’s best friend, offering a justification for violating national sovereignty and taking foreign governments to task for failing to protect their people from violence. Obama used this line with Libya, arguing that: To brush aside America's responsibility as a leader and—more profoundly— our responsibilities to our fellow human beings under such circumstances would have been a betrayal of who we are. . . . Some nations may be able to turn a blind eye to atrocities in other countries. The United States of America is different. And as president, I refused to wait for the images of slaughter and mass graves before taking action. And indeed, the loudest voices so far urging intervention in Syria belong to the R2P crowd (Washington Post editorial here, for example), thanks in part to confidence engendered by what they viewed as success in Libya. But the question remains: Will the public buy this argument? Certainly, such “responsible rhetoric” resonates—at least on the surface—with the public. Though precise poll data are scanty, a couple of polls from the Pew Research Center illustrate that the public generally agrees that the United States has a responsibility to prevent genocide. Stefan Bauschard Offensive PKOs release 130 Ditching R2P Solves R2P is the worst path in Syria – moderate internationalism solves Chimini 9/11/13 http://www.opendemocracy.net/openglobalrights/bschimni/r2p-and-syriaimperialism-with-human-face B.S. Chimini is Professor of International Law at the School of International Studies, Jawaharlal Nehru University, New Delhi. Second, states have become wiser after the intervention in Libya. States that did not oppose the invocation of R2P in Libya are now unwilling to support it because the UNSC resolution 1973 was misinterpreted and used by NATO powers to bring about regime change. Third, there is the valid concern that military action will lead to an escalation of violence in Syria and the region, leading to a greater humanitarian crisis. Millions more will be displaced outside and inside Syria. Thousands more will lose their lives. It is believed that even the departure of Assad will bring little relief to the people of Syria. This has been the experience of the Libyan people, who have in the postGaddafi era been subjected to unceasing violence by armed militias holding sway in large parts of the country. Fourth, it is felt that military action will undermine the Geneva 2 process, which holds out the best possibility of bringing to an end the conflict in Syria. It could mean a long period of political uncertainty in which the Syrian people will be unable to take control of their political destiny. Fifth, it is pointed out that the support for ‘democratic forces’ in Syria comes from many Arab regimes that are anything but democratic. It strengthens the suspicion that what drives support for military action is a geopolitical agenda. Sixth, there is the genuine fear that arms supplied to rebels may end up with extremist groups who are a part of the rebel forces. And seventh, it is believed that there are no innocent parties in this conflict. Both the government and the rebel forces are contributing to the escalating violence and violating international humanitarian laws. Even in global civil society, there is resistance to the idea that the choice before the international community is between supporting military action or a brutal regime. This resistance emanates from a certain reading of history. It is believed that the false choice is a function of the geopolitics of imperialism with deep roots in colonialism. The roots of violence in post-colonial states goes back to the construction of the colonial state that saw the economy, bureaucracy, police and the army positioned to serve the state rather than the people. The structures of colonial state were never fully dismantled in the post-colonial era. However, where the post-colonial states are democracies, social and human rights movements are able to prevent gross violations of human rights (or, when it takes place, to use the legal system to bring the perpetrators to justice). But in cases where the postcolonial state transfigured into an authoritarian state, as in the case of Syria, this is not possible. These authoritarian states have often received support from hegemonic powers pursuing geopolitical ambitions. But when such regimes become a liability, the same states manipulate the politics of the postcolonial state by relying on the genuine grievances of the people to oppose the incumbent regime. The outcome often is increased violence by the state against its own people. It is against this backdrop that the lifting of the embargo by the EU to supply arms to rebels, and earlier to allow the use of oil revenues to fund the insurgency, together with the possibility of President Obama ordering Stefan Bauschard Offensive PKOs release 131 military action, are to be viewed. It is felt that despite denials, forces of imperialism are using the acute distress of the Syrian people to pursue the agenda of regime change. What we need today is not military intervention but prudent internationalism. It is an internationalism that refrains from undermining the normative consensus in the international community on when military action is permissible. Prudent internationalism also acknowledges that democracy and democratic practices cannot be exported to societies and that military action can undermine the future of democracy by sharpening sectarian and social divides. Prudent internationalism also takes cognizance of the past outcomes of military action, especially the continuing violence in societies that have been the subject of military action (e.g., Iraq, Afghanistan and Libya). Prudent internationalism also does not accept the view that nonsupport of military action is support for the brutal Assad regime. Prudent internationalism sees a third way , that of diplomatic and political action to resolve the conflict. It requires that states and civil society forces opposed to military action ensure that the Geneva 2 process gets under way. Indeed, there is a moral obligation on all those opposed to military action not to remain passive spectators to the unfolding tragedy in Syria. In this respect, it is particularly important that key developing countries such as Brazil, India, China and South Africa act immediately to garner support for the diplomatic process. The decision on convening the Geneva 2 process cannot be left to a few states, in particular the US. Egypt has shown how the same hegemonic power that speaks of the need to institute a democratic regime in Syria is a mute witness to its destruction in Egypt. Meanwhile, as efforts are being made to start the Geneva 2 process, the Syrian people must be offered increased humanitarian assistance to relieve their sufferings. Stefan Bauschard Offensive PKOs release 132 Syria Crisis Impact: Middle East War Continued Syrian crisis destabilizes Middle East, respawns al Qaeda Hashemi 2/20/14 Nader Hashemi is director of the Center for Middle East Studies at the Josef Korbel School of International Studies at the University of Denver. His latest book is The Syria Dilemma. The views expressed are his own. http://globalpublicsquare.blogs.cnn.com/2014/02/20/why-u-s-should-care-aboutsyria-crisis/ The moral case for why Syria matters is easy to make. The killing fields of Syria are now reminiscent of those in Bosnia. Over the past three years, we have witnessed state-sanctioned war crimes and crimes against humanity replete with chemical weapons, barrel bombs, the targeting of children, mass rape, a refugee crisis and according to a new report “industrial-scale” torture and killings. Indeed, the U.N. High Commissioner for Refugees has described Syria as “a disgraceful humanitarian calamity with suffering and displacement unparalleled in recent history.” But a new dimension to this conflict has emerged: Syria is now a global security problem. The Syrian conflict is destabilizing the Middle East . Lebanon has been convulsed, Iraq has been shaken and Jordan’s fourth largest city today is a Syrian refugee camp. To a lesser extent, Turkey has also been adversely affected – some 600,000 refugees are said to be currently living on the Turkish-Syrian border, and Turkey’s role in the conflict has become a major bone of contention in domestic Turkish politics. Meanwhile, the conflict has heightened sectarian tensions across the Arab-Islamic world, fueled in part by the regional maneuverings of Saudi Arabia and Iran and their respective allies. Both are fighting to expand their regional influence, and Syria today is the key battleground for the contest. Finally, al Qaeda has reemerged from the ashes of the Syrian conflict. “Al Qaeda now controls territory that stretches more than 400 miles across the heart of the Middle East,” CNN analyst Peter Bergen recently observed. This deeply troubling development has obvious implications for global security, especially for Europe and the United States. Al Qaeda makes conflict spread regionally Karam 1/8/14 http://www.dallasnews.com/news/local-news/20140108-jihadist-gains-in-syria-iraqraise-stakes-in-mideast.ece Zeina Karam, The Associated Press Al-Qaeda is positioning itself as a vanguard defending Sunni Muslims against persecution by Shiite-dominated governments in Syria, Lebanon and Iraq. As a result, a Syrian rebellion against President Bashar Assad is evolving into something bigger and more ambiguous: a fight increasingly led by Sunni jihadists determined to create an Islamic state. Battling these extremists is a coalition that includes Syrian moderates who are horrified that their cause has been discredited, with parts of the nation falling under strict religious Stefan Bauschard Offensive PKOs release 133 law. For moderates in the Middle East, the renewed assertiveness of the extremists is increasingly taking on the aspect of a regional calamity. “The war in Syria has poured gasoline on a raging fire in Iraq, and conflicts in both countries are feeding upon one another and complicating an already complex struggle,” said Fawaz Gergez, director of the Middle East Center at the London School of Economics. “Now the reverberations of the Syria war are being felt on Arab streets, particularly Iraq and Lebanon, and are aggravating Sunni-Shiite tensions across the Arab Middle East.” Why now? Experts see alQaeda characteristically taking advantage of social, religious and ideological divisions — of the kind that have been exposed by the Sunni-Shiite battle in Syria. Longer conflict causes Mideast explosion Kaplan 8/27/13 http://www.globaldashboard.org/2013/08/27/seven-scenarios-for-the-future-ofsyria/ Seth Kaplan is a Professorial Lecturer in the Paul H. Nitze School of Advanced International Studies (SAIS) at Johns Hopkins University. He teaches, writes, and consults on issues related to fragile states, governance, and development. He is the author of Fixing Fragile States: A New Paradigm for Development (Praeger Security International, 2008) and Betrayed: Politics, Power, and Prosperity (Palgrave Macmillan, 2013). A Wharton MBA and Palmer scholar, Seth has worked for several large multinationals and founded four companies. He speaks fluent Mandarin Chinese and Japanese. 6) Regional conflict. The likelihood of this also increases the longer the war goes on. Lebanon and Iraq have already suffered from spillover : bombs have gone off in South Beirut and Tripoli in the past week and Sunni extremists have been strengthened in Iraq in recent months. It is not out of the realm of possibility that these trends will continue and a broad Sunni-Shiite conflict will engulf the whole Levant. This is the worst result, and would have even greater consequences for the region. Over 50 million people would be directly affected. Stefan Bauschard Offensive PKOs release 134 Right to Protect Causes War Escalation R2P interventionism is uniquely destabilizing BECAUSE it’s ineffective Menon 6/12/13 http://www.the-american-interest.com/articles/2013/06/12/its-fatally-flawed/ Rajan Menon is Anne and Bernard Spitzer Professor of Political Science, City College of New York/City University of New York, and a senior fellow at the Atlantic Council. Yet the reassurances that force would be a rare, last-ditch response have not placated critics, for several reasons. R2P’s pre-intervention prescriptions merely repeat existing remedies and add nothing to diplomacy’s toolkit. What’s new is the casuistry of reframing and diminishing sovereignty in order to legitimize altruistic armed intervention in defense of the abstract rights that most political communities agree upon in theory. Given R2P’s emphasis on feasibility and the chances for success, weak states are its most likely proving grounds; powerful ones need not fear, no matter the magnitude of their misdeeds. Because idealism and power are inextricably intertwined, with the latter frequently corrupting the former, R2P provides powerful states one script for playing the Good Samaritan when intervention promotes their interests, and another for eschewing or opposing aid when it doesn’t. R2P’s defenders see this indictment as reflecting hyperbole or misunderstanding, or as the artifice of dictators who declaim about sovereignty and legality but in truth seek to avoid accountability. Yes, dictators have every reason to avoid accountability, but it doesn’t really matter which side is right. What matters is that in a world of diverse polities and cultures, such objections and anxieties have sufficient appeal to prevent the doctrine from acquiring the universal pragmatic applicability its supporters seek. Many states have signed on to R2P, but it does not follow that they will stand behind its sovereignty-eroding features when it is proposed as a plan for military action. Disrupting sovereignty destroying the basis for collective security Brooks 1/14/13 http://www.globalpolicy.org/qhumanitarianq-intervention/52290-hate-obamas-dronewar.html?itemid=id#26087 Rosa Brooks is a law professor at the Georgetown University Law Center, a columnist and contributing editor for Foreign Policy and a Bernard L. Schwartz senior fellow at the New America Foundation. From April 2009 to July 2011, she served as Counselor to the Under Secretary of Defense for Policy, Michele Flournoy, and in May 2010 she also became [1] Special Coordinator for Rule of Law and Humanitarian Policy, running a new Pentagon office dedicated to those issues. Brooks wrote a weekly column for the Los Angeles Times from 2005 to 2009, and is an expert on national security, international law and human rights issues. At the Pentagon her portfolio included both rule of law and human rights issues and global engagement, strategic communication, and she received the Secretary of Defense Medal for Outstanding Public Service for her work. Second, arguments premised on the Responsibility to Protect are transparent: Evidence that a state is unwilling or unable to protect its population from egregious harm can be examined by all, and R2P-based Stefan Bauschard Offensive PKOs release 135 interventions are publicly proclaimed, making it possible to hold interveners accountable for errors or abuses. Nonetheless, the parallels between R2P and the understanding of sovereignty that undergirds U.S. drone policy are troubling. I'm no fan of the traditional legal conception of sovereignty, which has been used to mask many abuses. But in a world with no meaningful international governance structures, sovereignty -- even a weak and hypocritical conception of sovereignty -- is one of the few bulwarks against unilateral overreaching by great powers. Our fragile international order rests less on "law" than on implicit bargains between states , and insofar as U.S. drone policy further undermines traditional norms relating to sovereignty and the use of force, it risks undermining those tenuous bargains. It risks sending the message -- to friends and foes alike -- that we will no longer even offer much pretence of respecting sovereignty. As a result, it risks undermining the fragile order we so desperately need. Sovereignty erosion = international wars Gay 7/23/13 http://nationalinterest.org/blog/the-buzz/the-deceptive-appeal-theresponsibility-protect-8764 John Allen Gay is an assistant managing editor at The National Interest. His book (co-authored with Geoffrey Kemp) War with Iran: Political, Military, and Economic Consequences was released by Rowman and Littlefield in early 2013, The National Interest, July 23, The Deceptive Appeal of the Responsibility to Protect, DOA: 12-7-14 Why is R2P’s gutting of national sovereignty a problem? Respect for sovereignty is generally a stabilizing force in the international community. It narrows the scope of acceptable disagreement between states—there are fewer things to fight about. This can lead, in turn, to fewer international armed conflicts—and fewer of their attendant atrocities. R2P’s disregard for sovereignty might empower the international community to, from time to time, actually stop a genocide by intervention. Yet all too often, no “international community” exists. Interventions can become proxy conflicts (this would happen in a Syria intervention, and was a danger in the Balkans). And these proxy conflicts can readily yield atrocities of their own, perhaps far worse than those the intervention was launched to prevent. WW III Johnstone 1/25/13 http://www.globalpolicy.org/qhumanitarianq-intervention/52236-responsibility-toprotect-is-a-power-play.html?itemid=id#26087 Johnstone gained a BA in Russian Area Studies and a Ph.D. in French Literature from the University of Minnesota.[1] She was active in the movement against the Vietnam War, organizing the first international contacts between American citizens and Vietnamese representatives. Most of Johnstone's adult life has been spent in France, Germany, and Italy. Johnstone was European editor of the U.S. weekly In These Times from 1979 to 1990. She was press officer of the Green group in the European Parliament from 1990 to 1996. Johnstone also regularly contributes to the online magazine CounterPunch.[further explanation needed]. Stefan Bauschard Offensive PKOs release 136 Opposing genocide has become a cottage industry in the United States. An example is a program called "World Without Genocide" at William Mitchell College of Law in St. Paul. The recent commentary by its executive director, Ellen Kennedy ("‘Never again,’ it’s been said of genocide. Do we finally grasp it?" Jan. 19), employs all the usual clichés of that well-meaning but misguided campaign. Misguided, and, above all, misguiding. The antigenocide movement is directing people of good intention away from the essential cause of our time -- to reverse the drift toward worldwide war . The Bible of this campaign is Samantha Power's book, "A Problem from Hell." Power's thesis is that the United States is too slow to intervene to "stop genocide." It is a suggestion the U.S. government embraces, to the point of taking on Power as a White House adviser. The reason is clear. Since the Holocaust has become the most omnipresent historical reference in Western societies, the concept of "genocide" is widely accepted as the greatest evil to afflict the planet. It is felt to be worse than war. Therein lies its immense value to the U.S. military-industrial complex , and to a foreign-policy elite seeking an acceptable pretext for military intervention. The obsession with "genocide" as the primary humanitarian issue in the world today relativizes war. It reverses the final judgment of the Nuremberg Trials that: "War is essentially an evil thing. Its consequences are not confined to the belligerent states alone, but affect the whole world. To initiate a war of aggression, therefore, is not only an international crime; it is the supreme international crime, differing only from other war crimes in that it contains within itself the accumulated evil of the whole." Instead, war is transformed into a chivalrous action to rescue whole populations from "genocide." At the same time, national sovereignty , erected as the barrier to prevent strong nations from invading weaker ones -- that is, to prevent aggression and "the scourge of war" -- is derided as nothing but a protection for evil rulers ("dictators") whose only ambition is to "massacre their own people." This ideological construct is the basis for the Western-sponsored doctrine, forced on a more or less reluctant United Nations, of " R2P, " the ambiguous shorthand for both the "right" and the "responsibility" to protect people from their own governments. In practice, this can give the dominant powers carte blanche to intervene militarily in weaker countries in order to support whatever armed rebellions they favor. Once this doctrine seems to be accepted, it can even serve as an incitement to opposition groups to provoke government repression in order to call for "protection." Kennedy blames "genocide" on the legal barrier set up to try to prevent aggressive war: national sovereignty. For more than 350 years," she writes, "the concept of 'national sovereignty' held primacy over the idea of 'individual sovereignty' ... The result has been an 'over and over again' phenomenon of genocide since the Holocaust, with millions of innocent lives lost in Cambodia, Bosnia, Rwanda, Congo, Guatemala, Argentina, East Timor ..." Yet Hitler initiated World War II precisely in violation of the national sovereignty of Czechoslovakia and Poland -- partly, he claimed, to stop alleged human-rights violations against ethnic Germans who lived there. It was to invalidate this pretext, and "save succeeding generations from the scourge of war," that the United Nations was founded on the basis of respect for national sovereignty. Of course, there is no chance that the United States will abandon itsnational sovereignty. Rather, other countries are called upon to abandon their national sovereignty to the United States. Kennedy's list includes events that do not remotely fit the term "genocide" and leaves out others that do -- all according to the official U.S. narrative of contemporary Stefan Bauschard Offensive PKOs release 137 conflicts. But the significant fact is that the worst of these slaughters -Cambodia, Rwanda and the Holocaust itself -- occurred during warsand as a result of wars. The systematic killing of European Jews took place during World War II. In Rwanda, the horrific slaughter was a response to an invasion by Tutsi forces from neighboring Uganda. The Cambodian slaughter was not the fault of "national sovereignty" but the direct result of the U.S. violation of Cambodia's national sovereignty. Years of secret U.S. bombing of the Cambodian countryside, followed by a U.S.-engineered overthrow of the Cambodian government, opened the way for takeover of that country by embittered Khmer Rouge fighters who took out their resentment against the devastation of rural areas on the hapless urban population, considered accomplices of their enemies. Some of the bloodiest events do not make Kennedy's genocide list. Missing is the killing of more than half a million members of the Indonesian Communist Party in 1965 and 1966. But the dictator responsible, Suharto, was "a friend of the United States," and the victims were communists. A principal danger of the R2P doctrine is that it encourages rebel factions to provoke repression, or to claim persecution, solely to bring in foreign forces on their behalf. It is certain that opposition militants exaggerated Moammar Gadhafi's threat to Benghazi to provoke the 2011 French-led NATO war against Libya. The war in Mali is a direct result of the brutal overthrow of Gadhafi, who was a major force for African stability. The sole purpose of R2P is to create a public opinion willing to accept U.S. and NATO intervention in other countries. It is not meant to allow the Russians or the Chinese, say, to intervene to protect housemaids in Saudi Arabia from being beheaded -- much less to allow Cuban forces to shut down Guantanamo and end U.S. violations of human rights (on Cuban territory). Intervention means war; war causes massacres and more wars . The sense of being threatened by U.S. power incites other countries to build up their own military defenses and to repress opposition militants who might serve as excuses for outside intervention. Today, the greatest threat to the peoples of the world is not "evil dictators," but the militarization of international relations which, unless reversed, is leading toward the unimaginable catastrophe of World War III. R2P incentivizes escalation to provoke an intervention Menon 6/12/13 http://www.the-american-interest.com/articles/2013/06/12/its-fatally-flawed/ Rajan Menon is Anne and Bernard Spitzer Professor of Political Science, City College of New York/City University of New York, and a senior fellow at the Atlantic Council. The point here is not to condemn particular states for their selective moral outrages or for putting interests before ethics. This is what states of all stripes tend to do. It’s not that they never act in defense of principles or altruistically; it’s that they don’t do so when important interests point another way, or when the costs and hazards of defending them are deemed prohibitive. R2P boosters and revolutionary liberals will reply that the inability to defend basic values everywhere does not mean they can’t be defended when possible. Examples of supposedly successful action (Bosnia, Kosovo, East Timor and Libya) are trotted out, perhaps supplemented by Emerson’s quip about consistency’s allure for “little minds.” But given the realities of power, what this riposte concedes is that if a weak and ally-bereft state kills its citizens, it risks falling into the R2P file and facing armed intervention. If Stefan Bauschard Offensive PKOs release 138 not, then not—which brings us to the problem of moral hazard inherent in R2P. The prospect of an external humanitarian intervention, as noted earlier, led the KLA to adopt tactics that bordered on terrorism , and Serbia in turn to adopt tactics that resembled migratory genocide . In Libya, once the UNsanctioned machinery of intervention began to move, anti-Qaddafi insurgents had no reason to compromise and Qaddafi had no motivation to hold back. R2P presents a theoretical continuum of measures with armed intervention at one end, but engaged antagonists know that the various intermediate steps can easily and rapidly be skipped, the continuum collapsed, and the concept applied expansively. That encourages opposition forces to magnify violence to attract and suborn outside help, and it encourages embattled regimes to accelerate efforts at repression before external intervention can be agreed upon and implemented. In short, the prospect of R2P interventions can easily make bad situations worse. onsider Syria in this light. The Assad government has certainly slaughtered enough of its own citizens to attract R2P attention. But no major power has proposed armed intervention or even arming the insurgents in a dramatic or open way. Why? Because, unlike Qaddafi, Assad has the equipment to make the establishment of a no-fly zone, let alone use of ground troops, a very hazardous venture. Syria also has reliable supporters and arms suppliers in Russia and Iran, and Beijing has joined Moscow in scuttling successive Security Council resolutions aimed at the Assad regime. Russia and China had not forgotten that in Libya what began as an R2P intervention to protect civilians turned quickly into one aimed at regime change. It’s impossible to prove, being a counterfactual, but had an R2P intervention in Syria ever seemed possible to the combatants, it might well have made the carnage worse by quickening the tempo of killing. Stefan Bauschard Offensive PKOs release 139 Right to Protect Triggers Nuclear Proliferation Strengthened R2P norm causes prolif. Bolfrass 9/12/11 Alexander K. Bollfrass is a visiting scholar at the Stimson Center 9-12-2011 Explaining Libya to Iran http://www.worldpoliticsreview.com/articles/9970/explaining-libya-to-iran Eight years after Moammar Gadhafi gave up his mail-order nuclear weapons program and chemical munitions in exchange for détente with the West, he has been chased from power by a ragtag rebel army backed by Western airpower. Chances are that Gadhafi regrets his decision to forgo his WMD programs. If he had been armed with nuclear or chemical weapons, NATO might not have intervened when he threatened to massacre his own people. While Gadhafi's fall is good news, the end of the eccentric colonel's dictatorship now heightens the challenge of getting the Irans and North Koreas of the world to give up their nuclear ambitions in exchange for better relations with the West. Before the bombs started falling on Tripoli, the intellectual and legal momentum behind such an intervention had been building for years. Through the work of academics and humanitarian advocates, the idea known as the "responsibility to protect," or R2P, has emerged as an increasingly mainstream norm among Western policymakers. R2P emphasizes the responsibility of states to protect their populations and permits international intervention if a government is unable or unwilling to prevent mass atrocities against its people. In March, the international community did not dither when Gadhafi appeared to be preparing a massacre in Benghazi. R2P was used to justify the first U.N.-sanctioned humanitarian intervention in a sovereign country against the wishes of its government. The architects of the intervention were some of the very same countries that had convinced Gadhafi to give up his weapons of mass destruction eight years earlier: France, Britain and the United States. Parallel to the humanitarian community's development of the R2P doctrine, another community of foreign policy thinkers, those worried about the spread of nuclear weapons, had worked to promote an idea with very different implications for sovereignty. They reached the conclusion that fear of outside intervention was among the many factors driving governments to build weapons of mass destruction. For this reason, they argued, it was necessary to assuage that fear with the offer of a security guarantee once the government could prove it had abandoned its WMD ambitions. In Libya, this security-assurance principle successfully brought the archpariah of the 1980s back into the international fold in 2003. The contradictory doctrinal developments in humanitarian and security circles are not abstract intellectual exercises; they have practical implications. In light of the Islamic Republic's crushing of the Green Movement in 2009, it takes little imagination to see a Libya-like situation emerge in Iran. Iranian leaders weighing the pros and cons of coming clean over their country's nuclear program might look closely at what happened to Gadhafi after he surrendered his weapons program. They might also consider Saddam Hussein and his nonexistent weapons of mass destruction, while contrasting both these dictators with Kim Jong Il and his unpunished nuclear roguery and human rights violations. They might come to the conclusion that nuclear weapons are useful. In fact, we need not speculate about such a scenario, for this is essentially what Iranian Supreme Leader Ayatollah Ali Khamenei said at the start of the Libyan campaign. The Iranians are not the only ones learning this lesson, one that sets the stage for a future in which nuclear weapons are prized as a counterweight to the threat of international intervention represented by R2P and its inherent challenge to state sovereignty. Instead of greater openness and West-friendly behavior, the response of the rogue states would be deeper retrenchment under the cover of asymmetric WMD capabilities. Stefan Bauschard Offensive PKOs release 140 Proliferation snowballs and puts everyone on hair trigger – every small crisis will go nuclear. Soloski 9 Sokolski, executive director of the Nonproliferation Policy Education Center, serves on the U.S. congressional Commission on the Prevention of Weapons of Mass Destruction Proliferation and Terrorism, ‘9 (Henry, Avoiding a Nuclear Crowd, Policy Review June & July, http://www.hoover.org/publications/policyreview/46390537.html) At a minimum, such developments will be a departure from whatever stability existed during the Cold War. After World War II, there was a clear subordination of nations to one or another of the two superpowers’ strong alliance systems — the U.S.-led free world and the Russian-Chinese led Communist Bloc. The net effect was relative peace with only small, nonindustrial wars. This alliance tension and system, however, no longer exist. Instead, we now have one superpower, the United States, that is capable of overthrowing small nations unilaterally with conventional arms alone, associated with a relatively weak alliance system ( nato) that includes two European nuclear powers (France and the uk). nato is increasingly integrating its nuclear targeting policies. The U.S. also has retained its security allies in Asia (Japan, Australia, and South Korea) but has seen the emergence of an increasing number of nuclear or nuclearweapon-armed or -ready states. So far, the U.S. has tried to cope with independent nuclear powers by making them “strategic partners” (e.g., India and Russia), nato nuclear allies (France and the uk), “non-nato allies” (e.g., Israel and Pakistan), and strategic stakeholders (China); or by fudging if a nation actually has attained full nuclear status (e.g., Iran or North Korea, which, we insist, will either not get nuclear weapons or will give them up). In this world, every nuclear power center (our European nuclear nato allies), the U.S., Russia, China, Israel, India, and Pakistan could have significant diplomatic security relations or ties with one another but none of these ties is viewed by Washington (and, one hopes, by no one else) as being as important as the ties between Washington and each of these nuclear-armed entities (see Figure 3). There are limits, however, to what this approach can accomplish. Such a weak alliance system, with its expanding set of loose affiliations, risks becoming analogous to the international system that failed to contain offensive actions prior to World War I. Unlike 1914, there is no power today that can rival the projection of U.S. conventional forces anywhere on the globe. But in a world with an increasing number of nuclear-armed or nuclear-ready states, this may not matter as much as we think. In such a world, the actions of just one or two states or groups that might threaten to disrupt or overthrow a nuclear weapons state could check U.S. influence or ignite a war Washington could have difficulty containing. No amount of military science or tactics could assure that the U.S. could disarm or neutralize such threatening or unstable nuclear states.22 Nor could diplomats or our intelligence services be relied upon to keep up to date on what each of these governments would be likely to do in such a crisis (see graphic below): Combine these proliferation trends with the others noted above and one could easily create the perfect nuclear storm: Small differences between nuclear competitors that would put all actors on edge; an overhang of nuclear materials that could be called upon to break out or significantly ramp up existing nuclear deployments; and a variety of potential new nuclear actors developing weapons options in the wings. In such a setting, the military and nuclear rivalries between states could easily be much more intense than before. Certainly each nuclear state’s military would place an even higher premium than before on being able to weaponize its military and civilian surpluses quickly, to deploy forces that are survivable, and to have forces that can get to their targets and destroy them with high levels of probability. The advanced military states will also be even more inclined to develop and deploy enhanced air and missile defenses and longrange, precision guidance munitions, and to develop a variety of preventative and preemptive war options . Certainly, in such a world, relations between states could become far less stable. Relatively small developments — e.g., Russian support for sympathetic near-abroad provinces; Pakistani-inspired terrorist strikes in India, such as those experienced recently in Mumbai; new Indian flanking activities in Iran near Stefan Bauschard Offensive PKOs release Pakistan; Chinese weapons developments or moves regarding Taiwan; state-sponsored assassination attempts of key figures in the Middle East or South West Asia, etc. — could easily prompt nuclear weapons deployments with “strategic” consequences (arms races, strategic miscues, and even nuclear war). As Herman Kahn once noted, in such a world “every quarrel or difference of opinion may lead to violence of a kind quite different from what is possible today.”23 In short, we may soon see a future that neither the proponents of nuclear abolition, nor their critics, would ever want. 141 Stefan Bauschard Offensive PKOs release 142 Right to Protect Destroys US-Brazil Relations Unchecked humanitarian intervention tanks US – Brazilian relations – overwhelms alt causes Spektor 12 http://www.americasquarterly.org/humanitarian-interventionism-brazilian-style Matias Spektor is assistant professor of international relations at Fundação Getulio Vargas in Rio de Janeiro, Brazil. While Washington saw the Libya episode as a successful model for future humanitarian interventions, Brasília saw it as a dangerous precedent . Brazil’s foreign policy elite believed the resolution was too broad, giving NATO free rein over the terms and conditions of the intervention. For Brazilian leadership, the thin rules governing the use of force on the part of the major powers represent a great threat to international stability. The idea stems from a belief that intrusive norms of humanitarian intervention will corrode the principles of sovereignty and national autonomy and threaten international stability—representing potentially even a greater risk than the rise of new powers, radical Islam and even nuclear terror. Brazil wants LIMITED and RESTRAINED r2p – syncing with the Brazilian position boosts relations and Brazilian soft power Spektor 12 http://www.americasquarterly.org/humanitarian-interventionism-brazilian-style Matias Spektor is assistant professor of international relations at Fundação Getulio Vargas in Rio de Janeiro, Brazil. Brazilian officials were sensitive to the criticism. By November 2011, they began to circulate a concept paper at the UN entitled “Responsibility While Protecting,” or RWP. The paper argued that without limits on what the powerful may do, the emerging ideology of humanitarian intervention could easily become a tool for foreign manipulation. It then went on to suggest that the international community ought to codify standards and procedures to govern humanitarian intervention in the future. In practice, RWP proposed the introduction of criteria—such as last resort, proportionality, and balance of consequences— before the Security Council authorized the use of force. The paper called for the creation of a system for monitoring and reviewing the intervention as it evolves. The RWP concept was not open- ended and it stopped short of specifying how to roll out the criteria it proposed. Brasília conceived it less as a finished doctrine and more as a broad message to the international community: if humanitarian interventions in the future are loosely regulated and big power coalitions intervene as they please, then R2P will divide the international community between north and south, rich and poor, strong and weak. There was nothing new here. Brazil’s core message that interventions need to be carefully regulated can in fact be found in the 2005 R2P initiative. The fact that the Brazilian government dusted off its old proposal and presented it to the public Stefan Bauschard Offensive PKOs release 143 demonstrated its willingness to engage constructively in the global debate over the rules that govern the use of force in the next decades. The reception of Brazil’s RWP in the U.S. and parts of Europe was negative at first. With the partial exception of Germany, Europe quickly dismissed the initiative as an attempt to block action and let tyrannical leaders hide behind the legal shield of sovereignty. So far, Brazil has done a poor job of explaining what RWP entails and answering suspicions that it is an attempt to paralyze global action against mass atrocities instead of what it claims it is: a tool to ensure interventions cause less damage than they set out to prevent. China, Russia and India did not show much sympathy for RWP either. They were unhappy to see Brazil go further than they were ready to go in criticizing the Assad regime in Syria, and in their eyes RWP only confirms Brazil’s unpredictability when it comes to defending the primacy of sovereignty. This is, of course, problematic for Brazil. Without the military or financial resources to be a major player in the business of intervention and peacekeeping operations, its ability to speak up in global councils rests on the tacit support of others. If it wants its new ideas to stick, then Brazil first needs to convince and influence powerful countries. RWP has yet to achieve this. Equally complicated is the reception of RWP at home. Brazil’s commitment to sovereignty is deeply rooted in and around the state apparatus, and talk of humanitarian intervention is bound to clash with embedded understandings of how the world works. It is among networks of activists and private foundations, however, that RWP seems to have found its closest friends. Anecdotal evidence suggests that networks of human rights NGOs active in Brazil and in and around the UN system welcomed the initiative and are keen to learn more about it. Among these activists, there is a sense that if R2P is ever going to become a key organizing principle of global order that is embraced by all, then part of the bargain will have to involve some form of criteria for intervention. On this view, weaker nations around the globe will only grant legitimacy to humanitarian intervention if the use of force on behalf of strangers is strictly regulated to ensure that the interests of the people come before those of powerful nations. Stepping Up or Stepping Out of Line? Future disagreement between the U.S. and Brazil over humanitarian intervention is not inevitable. Brazilian leaders have been sensitive to the accusation that they just want to be recognized as a major power without paying any of the costs. Instead, Brasília believes it has gone out of its way to demonstrate its burden-sharing credentials. To further the debate, though, Brazilian leaders will need to remain involved in the shaping of humanitarian intervention norms and avoid alienating the United States. As part of this process, Brazil is aiming to demonstrate that it is entitled to a permanent seat on the UN Security Council, based not only on its willingness to deploy military missions abroad to enforce peace and stability, but on the argument that it can bring to international and multilateral debates and decisions a new, modern perspective on security that is more in tune with the demands of a changing world. Along these lines, Brasília believes that it can add legitimacy to global order because it seeks to preserve humanitarian intervention while defending the weak from the selective geostrategic predations of the most powerful. This is a message that strikes a chord with large swaths of people around the globe. What is the implication for the United States? Since Brazil is more interested in adapting existing conceptions of intervention than in offering alternative ones, the U.S. would be wise to invest in greater dialogue and practical cooperation on the ground. A good example is the work currently conducted by the two countries in Haiti or in bilateral military cooperation in partner countries throughout Africa. Along these lines, Washington should not discard Stefan Bauschard Offensive PKOs release 144 RWP too quickly. If notions of civilian protection are going to become fixtures in the emerging normative landscape, then they will have to be embraced by major rising powers, first among them the members of the BRICS (Brazil, Russia, India, China, and South Africa). Among those countries Brazil has been the one most willing to engage on this topic. Rather than see RWP as an attempt to block progress toward better and more efficient humanitarian interventions, the U.S. should take it as an attempt to return to the initial spirit of R2P in the mid-2000s. At inception, the principle did not focus on the use of military force as the sole or primary instrument to cease violations of rights. Instead, it gave equal attention to building state capacity to address structural causes of violence, such as poverty. Brazil wants to emphasize that side of humanitarian intervention because it will not and cannot take active part in it through military force. But it is keen to make contributions in the fields where it has the ability to deliver, such as poverty alleviation, sustainable agriculture, public service reform, and international aid and cooperation. These may not be integral to current understandings of humanitarian intervention, but are likely to become so if R2P is to become a dominant norm in twenty-first century international society. The best response by the U.S. would be to take Brazil’s proposals seriously and engage Brasília in further specifying how the concept would work in practice. Dialogue with Brazil is a low-cost initiative to try bridging the gap between the Western industrial countries and the major developing states that now threatens the future survival of a global shared responsibility to protect. Constrained r2p boosts Brazilian prestige as global middleman Stuenkl 11/28/11 Oliver Stuenkel is an Assistant Professor of International Relations at the Getúlio Vargas Foundation (FGV) in São Paulo, where he coordinates the São Paulo branch of the School of History and Social Science (CPDOC) and the executive program in International Relations. He is also a non-resident Fellow at the Global Public Policy Institute (GPPi) in Berlin and a member of the Carnegie Rising Democracies Network. His research focuses on rising powers; specifically on Brazil’s, India’s and China's foreign policy and on their impact on global governance. He is the author of the forthcoming IBSA: The rise of the Global South? (2014, Routledge Global Institutions) and BRICS and the Future of Global Order (2014, Lexington). In this context, Brazil’s President Dilma Rousseff has offered an interesting concept that may bring the two sides together. During her opening speech at the UN General Assembly earlier this year, Rousseff argued that better mechanisms were needed to assure that in an intervention unwanted damage would be kept at a minimum, calling it “the responsibility while protecting ” (responsabilidade ao proteger). Since then, Brazil has been low-key about the idea, and it has attempted to integrate the concept into last month’s IBSA declaration. Brazilian President’s Rousseff argument during her speech that “while there was been a lot of talk (…) of the right to protect, there is little said about the responsibility while protecting” may seem insignificant, but in essence means that if carried out in a responsible manner, Brazil could, in principle, support intervention in the UN Security Council in the future – and India and South Africa are not fundamentally opposed to this idea. In an op- Stefan Bauschard Offensive PKOs release 145 ed in today’s Folha de São Paulo, Matias Spektor, professor at Fundação Getulio Vargas who coordinates the Center for International Relations, argues that the concept has the potential to turn into one of the Rousseff administration’s important contributions to the international debat e. If accepted by the P5, the Brazilian initiative would impose constraints on interventions that could help reluctant actors such as China and Russia support them, mitigating worries that interventions cause more damage than necessary or support a hidden agenda. In order to successfully launch the concept, Spektor argues, Brazil needs to promote it on many levels – such as the G20 and during the BRICS summit, which takes place in India next year. Whatever happens, the case shows Brazil is eager to turn into an international agenda-setter : It is not only willing to participate in international negotiations, but it also increasingly seeks to frame the debate and decide which issues should be discussed in the first place. Stefan Bauschard Offensive PKOs release Con – Positive Peace Kritik 146 Stefan Bauschard Offensive PKOs release 147 *** Links *** Stefan Bauschard Offensive PKOs release 148 Link – War Understanding war as a discrete event obscures the structural roots of violence Cuomo 96 (Chris J. Professor of Philosophy and Women's Studies, and Director of the Institute for Women's Studies at the University of Georgia, “War Is Not Just an Event: Reflections on the Significance of Everyday Violence”, Published in Hypatia 11.4 nb, pp. 31-48) Philosophical attention to war has typically appeared in the form of justifications for entering into war, and over appropriate activities within war. The spatial metaphors used to refer to war as a separate, hounded sphere indicate assumptions that war is a realm of human activity vastly removed from normal life, or a sort of happening that is appropriately conceived apart from everyday events in peaceful times. Not surprisingly, most discussions of the political and ethical dimensions of war discuss war solely as an event—an occurrence, or collection of occurrences, having clear beginnings and endings that are typically marked by formal, institutional declarations. As happenings, wars and military activities can be seen as motivated by identifiable, if complex, intentions, and directly enacted by individual and collective decision-makers and agents of states. But many of the questions about war that are of interest to feminists— including how large-scale, state-sponsored violence affects women and members of other oppressed groups; how military violence shapes gendered, raced, and nationalistic political realities and moral imaginations; what such violence consists of and why it persists; how it is related to other oppressive and violent institutions and hegemonies—cannot be adequately pursued by focusing on events. These issues are not merely a matter of good or bad intentions and identifiable decisions. “Risk of war” rhetoric privileges security over peacemaking, turning the case Waever 4 (Ole, Ph.D. in Political Science and Professor of International Relations at COPRI, “Peace and Security”, Contemporary Security Analysis and Copenhagen Peace Research, pg 62-63, http://books.google.com/books?id=L2GKw5JcmYQC&pg=PA53&lpg=PA53&dq=%E2%80%9CPeace+and+Security%E2%80%9D,+%22Contemp orary+Security+Analysis+and+Copenhagen+Peace+Research%22&source=bl&ots=7g5DLhB5ZY&sig=ujOh2GZXFvCSlxUWfsvrgOZyWWs& hl=en&ei=OMZXSo2ZN5GiswOqoanaBw&sa=X&oi=book_result&ct=result&resnum=3, 2004, AD: 7-10-9) President Bush senior declared in 1989, ‘Once again, it is a time for peace’ (quoted by Rasmussen 2001:341). The famous ‘New World Order’ speech at the end of the Gulf War (March 6, 1991) was phrased mostly in terms of peace- ‘enduring peace must be our mission’. Nato enlargement is so hard for Russia and others to oppose because it is presented apolitically as the mere expansion of the democratic peace community (Williams 2001). The war on terror after 11 September 2001 has surprisingly few references to either peace or security- operation ‘Enduring Freedom’- but President George W. Bush’s address on 7 October 2001 ended with ‘Peace and freedom will prevail’, and the (in)famous ‘axis of evil’ was presented (29 January, 2002) in terms of a ‘threat to peace’. Peace has become the overarching concept of the two examined in this chapter. Security in turn, is gradually swallowed up into a generalized concern about ‘risk’. Society’s reflections on itself are increasingly in terms of risk (risk society). More and more dangers are the product of our own actions, and fewer and fewer attributable to forces completely external to ourselves- thus threats become risks (Luhmann 1990). This goes for forms of production and their effects on the environment, and it goes for internal affairs, where it is hard to see the war on terrorism as a pure reaction to something coming to the West from elsewhere. Western actions in relation to Middle East peace processes, religion, migration and global economic policy are part of what might produce future terrorism. The short-term reaction to the 11 September attacks on the USA in 2001 might be re-assertion of single- minded aspirations for absolute security with little concern for liberty and and for boomerang effects on future security (Bigo 2002), but in general debates, the ‘risk’ way of thinking about international affairs is making itself increasingly felt. We have seen during the last twenty years a spread of the originally specifically international concept of security in its securitization function to more and more spheres of ‘domestic’ life, and now society takes its revenge by transforming the concept of security along lines of risk thinking (Waever 2002). Politically, the concepts of peace and security are changing places in these years. ‘Security studies’ and ‘peace research’ werer shaped in important ways by the particular Cold War context, though not the way it is often implied in fast politicians’ statements about the postCold War irrelevance of peace research. ‘Peace research’ and ‘security studies’ I(or rather ‘strategic studies’) meant, respectibley to oppose or to accept the official Western policy problematique. Today, it is the othe way round. ‘ Peace research’ might be dated because peace is so apologetic to be intellectually uninteresting, while security is potentially the name of a radical, subversive agenda. Stefan Bauschard Offensive PKOs release 149 Link – War They dehistoricize war making complex solutions to the structural roots impossible Gur-Ze’ev 1 (Ilan, Head of the Department of Education at the University of Haifa, Summer, http://construct.haifa.ac.il/~ilangz/peace23.html) Pacifist writers as diverse as Gandhi, Martin Luther King, Jr., and Barbara Deming have emphasized the fact that pacifism entails a critique of pervasive, systematic human violence. Despite its reductionist tendencies, there is much to learn from the ways in which pacifists conceive of war as a presence, as well as the pacifist refusal to let go of the ideal of peace. Characterizing pacifism as motivated by the desire to avoid specific events disregards the extent to which pacifism aims to criticize the preconditions underlying events of war. Following several initial moves in feminist philosophy, Peach rejects just war abstraction--of the realities, or "horrors," of war; dimensional evil, killable Others; and I the ethical responses needed to address the morality of war, such as a privileging of justice mil rights over love and caring. Following Elsluain, she believes that feminist just-war principles should be more particularized, contextualized, and individualized. But the abstraction of the particularities of war depends on an abstraction of war itself. The distance of such abstraction is created in part by willingness to think of war without considering the presence of war in "peaceful" times. Wars becomes conceptual entities—objects for consideration—rather than diverse, historically loaded exemplifications of the contexts in which they occur. In order to notice the particular and individual realities of war, attention must be given to the particular, individual, and contextualized causes and effects of pervasive militarism, as well as the patterns and connections among them A crisis-driven approach to war focused on timeframe and risk assessment obscures the omnipresence of militarism at the root of violence Cuomo 96 (Chris J. Professor of Philosophy and Women's Studies, and Director of the Institute for Women's Studies at the University of Georgia, “War Is Not Just an Event: Reflections on the Significance of Everyday Violence”, Published in Hypatia 11.4 nb, pp. 31-48) CH Ethical approaches that do not attend to the ways in which warfare and military practices are woven into the very fabric of life in twenty-first century technological states lead to crisis-based politics and analyses. For any feminism that aims to resist oppression and create alternative social and political options, crisis-based ethics and politics are problematic because they distract attention from the need for sustained resistance to the enmeshed, omnipresent systems of domination and oppression that so often function as givens in most people's lives. Neglecting the omnipresence of militarism allows the false belief that the absence of declared armed conflicts is peace, the polar opposite of war. It is particularly easy for those whose lives are shaped by the safety of privilege, and who do not regularly encounter the realities of militarism, to maintain this false belief. The belief that militarism is an ethical, political concern only regarding armed conflict, creates forms of resistance to militarism that are merely exercises in crisis control. Antiwar resistance is then mobilized when the "real" violence finally occurs, or when the stability of privilege is directly threatened, and at that point it is difficult not to respond in ways that make resisters drop all other political priorities. Crisis-driven attention to declarations of war might actually keep resisters complacent about and complicitous in the general presence of global militarism. Seeing war as necessarily embedded in constant military presence draws attention to the fact that horrific, state-sponsored violence is happening nearly all over, all of the time, and that it is perpetrated by military institutions and other militaristic agents of the state. Stefan Bauschard Offensive PKOs release 150 Link – War Their reduction of war to the entities and particularities of the aff abstracts war, preventing contextualized responses to structural violence Cuomo 96 (Chris J. Professor of Philosophy and Women's Studies, and Director of the Institute for Women's Studies at the University of Georgia, “War Is Not Just an Event: Reflections on the Significance of Everyday Violence”, Published in Hypatia 11.4 nb, pp. 31-48) CH But the abstraction of the particularities of war depends on an abstraction of war itself. The distance of such abstraction is created in part by willingness to think of war without considering the presence of war in "peaceful" times. Wars becomes conceptual entities—objects for consideration—rather than diverse, historically loaded exemplifications of the contexts in which they occur. In order to notice the particular and individual realities of war, attention must be given to the particular, individual, and contextualized causes and effects of pervasive militarism, as well as the patterns and connections among them. Like other feminists, Peach criticizes the dualisms and dichotomies that underlie war and the other evils of patriarchy, including dichotomies between male and female, combatant and non-combatant, soldier and citizen, ally and enemy and state and individual which have dominated just-war thinking. Rather than relying on traditional dichotomies, a feminist application of just-war criteria should emphasize the effects of going to war on the lives of particular individuals who would be involved, whether soldier or civilian, enemy or ally, male or female. (Peach 1994. 166) Stefan Bauschard Offensive PKOs release 151 Link – Hegemony Hegemony causes negative peace Tavares 8 (Rodrigo l, June, “Understanding regional peace and security: a framework for analysis.”, Vol. 14 Issue 2, p107-127, 21p, Contemporary Politics) The first instrument, armed violence, can be seen as a mechanism of state policy to shape the international system. In a paradoxical perspective, realist scholars and conservative policy makers tend to consider war as a rational tool to carve international order and stability (Waltz 1959; see also Howard 1970). The second instrument, balance of power, is an instrument (or a set of instruments) that states use to band together and pool their capabilities whenever one state or group of states appears to become a threat as it gathers a disproportionate amount of power. Although balance of power could be interpreted as a concept or a strategic doctrine, here the emphasis is on the mechanisms used by political agents to balance each other’s capabilities. In conjugation with this, hegemony is the dominance of one state over other states, with or without the threat of force, to the extent that, for instance, the dominant party can dictate the terms of relationship to its advantage. In the same line, alliances are military collective defence arrangements of states formed as a response to a common threat and as a way of maximizing security and minimizing the eventuality of an external attack. Modern military alliances are the subject of a significant body of literature (Osgood 1968, Walt 1987, 1997). Negative peace trades-off with a focus on the structural roots of violence Von Heinegg 4 (Wolff Heintschel, * Prof. Dr. iur., Europa-Universitat Frankfurt (Oder); Charles H. Stockton Professor of International Law, U.S. Naval War College, Newport, R.I., Summer“The Rule of Law in conflict and Post-Conflict Situations: Factors in war to peace transitions”, Harvard Society for Law & Public Policy) Before dealing with the different forms of terminating (and of suspending) an international armed conflict, it needs to be stressed that the end of a war merely means a return to peace insofar as the situation thus created is characterized by the absence of military operations, including occupation. This situation, often referred to as "negative peace," of course does not mean a return to normal or amicable relations between the former belligerents, often referred to as "positive peace." n17 The latter condition, while not apt for an abstract and comprehensive definition, n18 may be achieved through the exchange of diplomats and by the reestablishment of economic and cultural relations. There is, however, another aspect of this issue that is of importance in that context. A situation of "positive peace," which is, inter alia, based upon the principle of sovereign equality of States, regularly presupposes the reestablishment of the full sovereignty of all belligerents. While the termination of an international armed conflict implies that any further use of armed force not justified by the right of self-defense will be contrary to the fundamental prohibition of the use of force, n19 the existence of negative peace does not necessarily imply the return of the vanquished state to full sovereignty. While there may be an exchange of diplomats as well as other forms of establishing diplomatic relations, the situation may not be characterized as a return to, or the establishment of, positive peace so long as the State concerned has not regained its full sovereignty . This was the case with Germany until its reunification because all questions relating to "Germany as a whole" had been made subject to the so called "Allied reservations," which meant that neither the Federal Republic of Germany nor the German Democratic Republic were allowed to autonomously decide on that core question of their respective sovereignty. Moreover, Berlin remained under an [*848] occupational regime. n21 Only with the end of the Allied rights concerning Germany as a whole, including Berlin, did Germany and the Allies return to a situation of positive peace proper Stefan Bauschard Offensive PKOs release 152 Stefan Bauschard Offensive PKOs release 153 ***Impacts*** Stefan Bauschard Offensive PKOs release 154 Impact – No Solvency – War Militarism is the root cause – The Pro doesn’t solve Cuomo 96 (Chris J. Professor of Philosophy and Women's Studies, and Director of the Institute for Women's Studies at the University of Georgia, “War Is Not Just an Event: Reflections on the Significance of Everyday Violence”, Published in Hypatia 11.4 nb, pp. 31-48) Theory that does not investigate or even notice the omnipresence of militarism cannot represent or address the depth and specificity of the everyday effects of militarism on women, on people living in occupied territories, on members of military institutions, and on the environment. These effects are relevant to feminists in a number of ways because military practices and institutions help construct gendered and national identity, and because they justify the destruction of natural nonhuman entities and communities during peacetime. Lack of attention to these aspects of the business of making or preventing military violence in an extremely technologized world results in theory that cannot accommodate the connections among the constant presence of militarism, declared wars, and other closely related social phenomena, such as nationalistic glorifications of motherhood, media violence, and current ideological gravitations to military solutions for social problems. Their solutions backfire, turning the case Felice 98 (William F., Professor of International Relations and Human Rights at Eckerd College, “Militarism and Human Rights”, International Affairs, Vol. 74 No. 1, Blackwell Publishing, http://www.jstor.org/stable/2624664, A.D.: 7/10/09) JH The attitudes that sustain large and deadly military machines did not fall with the Berlin Wall . The logic is mesmerizing. The world is a dangerous place divided into sovereign nation-states, each seeking to improve its position in an anarchic international system. There are few opportunities for cooperation. Each state maintains the right to be free from the scrutiny and intervention of other states in its internal affairs. Each nation is surrounded by danger and must protect itself to survive, which gives rise to a preoccupation with power, particularly military power. Internalizing this acute sense of danger makes it easier to accept high taxation to pay for the militarization at the expense of social development. Yet such militarization in the name of security and peace often backfires and creates conditions of insecurity and conflict. Further, such expenditures consistently undermine the ability of nations to fulfil other international human rights, in particular economic and social rights. ‘Security’ defined solely as the heavily armed defence of one’s borders. How does a nation provide a basic right to physical security without compromising other human rights? What types of military and other expenses should be budgeted to attain physical security? Stefan Bauschard Offensive PKOs release 155 Impact – No Solvency – Poverty Structural violence outweighs the aff and a failure to address human security makes their harms inevitable – They treat the effect, not the cause Gilman 0 (Robert, President of Context Institute, “Structural Violence”, The Foundation of Peace IC #4, http://www.context.org/ICLIB/IC04/Gilman1.htm, 2000, AD: 7-9-9) How legitimate is it to ascribe these deaths to the structural violence of human institutions, and not just to the variability of nature? Perhaps the best in-depth study of structural violence comes from the Institute for Food and Development Policy (1885 Mission St, San Francisco, CA 94103). What they find throughout the Third World is that the problems of poverty and hunger often date back hundreds of years to some conquest - by colonial forces or otherwise. The victors became the ruling class and the landholders, pushing the vast majority either on to poor ground or into being landless laborers. Taxes, rentals, and the legal system were all structured to make sure that the poor stayed poor. The same patterns continue today. Additional support is provided by the evidence in the above figure, which speaks for itself. Also, according to Sivard, 97% of the people in the Third World live under repressive governments, with almost half of all Third World countries run by military dominated governments. Finally, as a point of comparison, Ehrlich and Ehrlich (Population, Environment, and Resources, 1972, p72) estimate between 10 and 20 million deaths per year due to starvation and malnutrition. If their estimates are correct, our estimates may even be too low. Some comparisons will help to put these figures in perspective. The total number of deaths from all causes in 1965 was 62 million, so these estimates indicate that 23% of all deaths were due to structural violence. By 1979 the fraction had dropped to 15%. While it is heartening to see this improvement, the number of deaths is staggeringly large, dwarfing any other form of violence other than nuclear war. For example, the level of structural violence is 60 times greater than the average number of battle related deaths per year since 1965 (Sivard 1982). It is 1.5 times as great as the yearly average number of civilian and battle field deaths during the 6 years of World War II. Every 4 days, it is the equivalent of another Hiroshima. Perhaps the most hopeful aspect of this whole tragic situation is that essentially everyone in the present system has become a loser. The plight of the starving is obvious, but the exploiters don't have much to show for their efforts either not compared to the quality of life they could have in a society without the tensions generated by this exploitation. Especially at a national level, what the rich countries need now is not so much more material wealth, but the opportunity to live in a world at peace. The rich and the poor, with the help of modern technology and weaponry, have become each others' prisoners. Today's industrialized societies did not invent this structural violence, but it could not continue without our permission. This suggests that to the list of human tendencies that are obstacles to peace we need to add the ease with which we acquiesce in injustice the way we all too easily look in the other direction and disclaim "response ability." In terms of the suffering it supports, it is by far our most serious flaw. Militarism is the root cause Felice 98 (William F., Professor of International Relations and Human Rights at Eckerd College, “Militarism and Human Rights”, International Affairs, Vol. 74 No. 1, Blackwell Publishing, http://www.jstor.org/stable/2624664, A.D.: 7/10/09) JH This human rights agenda can also only be implemented within a framework of peace. Militarism has neither created a world of peace and stability, nor protected the human right to physical security. Overemphasis on military superiority undermines the ability to build regimes of trust and harmony. The arsenals of the war system are symptoms of deep conflict. Arms control and disarmament and the demobilization of armed forces are prerequisites to providing the institutional framework within which nations may pursue implementation of the corpus of international human rights law. International security and stability are dependent on domestic security and stability. The roots of conflict within domestic societies are often the result of economic, social and environmental pressures which cause poverty and unemployment and pit one community, class, sex or ethnic group against another. Human rights as the core of domestic and foreign public policy can provide a route for the achievement of peace and stability. Preoccupations with ‘balance of power’ and military prowess can only continue to produce a world of insecurity and war. Policies based on outmoded notions of realpolitik exacerbate insecurities. The irony is that human rights policies provide the clearest road to achieve the ‘realist’ objectives of security and stability. Long-term interests in international stability should compel governments to explore human security and positive peace. It is commonly accepted that totalitarianism and human rights are incompatible. The negative impact of militarism on basic human rights must also be understood. A militarized society exists in contradiction to basic human rights and negates the opportunities for human freedom. Stefan Bauschard Offensive PKOs release 156 Impact – War Their conception of peace prescribes military solutions as violence control Sandy & Perkins 1 (Leo R and Ray, Co-Founder of Peace Studies at Plymouth State College and teacher of philosophy at Plymouth State College, “The Nature of Peace and it’s implication for peace education”, online journal of peace and conflict resolution 4.2, http://www.uio.no/studier/emner/jus/jus/ENGSEMJ/v08/undervisningsmateriale/IL%20&%20HR/Topic%202%20%20Reading.pdf, 2001, AD:7-10-9) Peace as the mere absence of war is what Woolman (1985) refers to as “negative peace.” This definition is based on Johan Galtung’s ideas of peace. For Galtung, negative peace is defined as a state requiring a set of social structures that provide security and protection from acts of direct physical violence committed by individuals, groups or nations. The emphasis is ...on control of violence. The main strategy is dissociation, whereby conflicting parties are separated...In general, policies based on the idea of negative peace do not deal with the causes of violence, only its manifestations. Therefore, these policies are thought to be insufficient to assure lasting conditions of peace. Indeed, by suppressing the release of tensions resulting from social conflict, negative peace efforts may actually lead to future violence of greater magnitude. (Woolman, 1985, p.8) The recent wars in the former Yugoslavia are testimony to this. The massive military machine previously provided by the U.S.S.R. put a lid on ethnic hostilities yet did nothing to resolve them thus allowing them to fester and erupt later. Defining war as an event implies that war can be justifies, guaranteeing militarized solutions to problems Cuomo 96 (Chris J. Professor of Philosophy and Women's Studies, and Director of the Institute for Women's Studies at the Univerity of Georgia, “War Is Not Just an Event: Reflections on the Significance of Everyday Violence”, Published in Hypatia 11.4 nb, pp. 31-48) CH Just-war theory is a prominent example of a philosophical approach that real-rim-the-assumption that wars are isolated from everyday life and ethics. Such theory, as developed by St. Augustine, Thomas Aquinas, and Hugo Grotius, and as articulated in contemporary dialogues by many philosophers, including Michael Walzer (1977), Thomas Nagel (1974), and Sheldon Cohen (1989), take the primary question concerning the ethics of warfare to be about when to enter into military conflicts against other states. They therefore take as a given the notion that war is an isolated, definable event with clear boundaries. These boundaries are significant because they distinguish the circumstances in which standard moral rules and constraints, such as rules against murder and unprovoked violence, no longer apply. Just-war theory assumes that war is a separate sphere of human activity having its own ethical constraints and criteria and in doing so it begs the question of whether or not war is a special kind of event, or part of a pervasive presence in nearly all contemporary life. Because the application of just-war principles is a matter of proper decisionmaking on the part of agents of the state, before wars occur, and before military strikes are made, they assume that military initiatives are distinct events. In fact, declarations of war are generally overdetermined escalations of preexist¬ing conditions. Just-war criteria cannot help evaluate military and related institutions, including their peacetime practices and how these relate to wartime activities, so they cannot address the ways in which armed conflicts between and among states emerge from omnipresent, often violent, state militarism. The remarkable resemblances in some sectors between states of peace and states of war remain completely untouched by theories that are only able to discuss the ethics of starting and ending direct military conflicts between and among states Stefan Bauschard Offensive PKOs release 157 Impact – War Understanding war as an event necessitates militarism which forecloses vital interrogation to determine true peace Richmond 7 (Oliver P., lecturer in the Department of International Relations, University of St. Andrews, Alternatives: Global, Local, Political, “Critical Research Agendas for Peace: The Missing Link in the Study of International Relations”, http://www.questiaschool.com/read/5023019836?title=Critical%20Research%20Agendas %20for%20Peace%3a%20The%20Missing%20Link%20in%20the%20Study%20of%20International %20Relations, AD: 7/10/09) As a consequence what has emerged has been an orthodox assumption that first the management of war must be achieved before the institutions of peace can operate, at a global, regional, state, and local level. Peace has, in Western political thought in particular, been enshrined first in the belief that only a limited peace is possible, even despite more utopian leanings, and recently that peace can now be built according to a certain epistemology. Militarization, force, or coercion have normally been the key mechanisms for its attainment, and it has been imbued with a hegemonic understanding of universal norms, now increasingly instilled through institutions of governance. It is generally assumed by most theorists, most policymakers, and practitioners, that peace has an ontological stability enabling it to be understood, defined, and thus created. Indeed, the implication of the void of debate about peace indicates that it is generally thought that peace as a concept is so ontologically solid that no debate is required. There is clearly a resistance to examining the concept of peace as a subjective ontology, as well as a subjective political and ideological framework. Indeed, this might be said to be indicative of "orientalism," in impeding a discussion of a positive peace or of alternative concepts and contexts of peace. (18) Indeed, Said's humanism indicates the dangers of assuming that peace is universal, a Platonic ideal form, or extremely limited. An emerging critical conceptualization of peace rests upon a genealogy that illustrates its contested discourses and multiple concepts. This allows for an understanding of the many actors, contexts, and dynamics of peace, and enables a reprioritization of what, for whom, and why, peace is valued. Peace from this perspective is a rich, varied, and fluid tapestry, which can be contextualized, rather than a sterile, extremely limited, and probably unobtainable product of a secular or nonsecular imagination. It represents a discursive framework in which the many problems that are replicated by the linear and rational project of a universal peace (effectively camouflaged by a lack of attention within IR) can be properly interrogated in order to prevent the discursive replication of violence. (19) This allows for an understanding of how the multiple and competing versions of peace may even give rise to conflict, and also how this might be overcome. One area of consensus from within this more radical literature appears to be that peace is discussed, interpreted, and referred to in a way that nearly always disguises the fact that it is essentially contested. This is often an act of hegemony thinly disguised as benevolence, assertiveness, or wisdom. Indeed, many assertions about peace depend upon actors who know peace then creating it for those that do not, either through their acts or through the implicit peace discourses that are employed to describe conflict and war in opposition to peace. Where there should be research agendas there are often silences. Even contemporary approaches in conflict analysis and peace studies rarely stop to imagine the kind of peace they may actually create. IR has reproduced a science of peace based upon political, social, economic, cultural, and legal governance frameworks, by which conflict in the world is judged. This has led to the liberal peace framework, which masks a hegemonic collusion over the discourses of, and creation of, peace. (20) A critical interrogation of peace indicates it should be qualified as a specific type among many. Stefan Bauschard Offensive PKOs release 158 Impact – Structural Violence Outweighs Structural violence outweighs nuclear war Gilman 83 (Robert, President of Context Institute, Founding Editor of IN CONTEXT, A Quarterly of Humane Sustainable Culture, “ Can we find genuine peace in a world with inequitable distribution of wealth among nations?”, The Foundations of Peace, p. 8, AD: 7-11-09)MT How legitimate is it to ascribe these deaths to the structural violence of human institutions, and not just to the variability of nature? Perhaps the best in-depth study of structural violence comes from the Institute for Food and Development Policy (1885 Mission St, San Francisco, CA 94103). What they find throughout the Third World is that the problems of poverty and hunger often date back hundreds of years to some conquest by colonial forces or otherwise. The victors became the ruling class and the landholders, pushing the vast majority either on to poor ground or into being landless laborers. Taxes, rentals, and the legal system were all structured to make sure that the poor stayed poor. The same patterns continue today. Some comparisons will help to put these figures in perspective. The total number of deaths from all causes in 1965 was 62 million, so these estimates indicate that 23% of all deaths were due to structural violence. By 1979 the fraction had dropped to 15%. While it is heartening to see this improvement, the number of deaths is staggeringly large, dwarfing any other form of violence other than nuclear war. For example, the level of structural violence is 60 times greater than the average number of battle related deaths per year since 1965 (Sivard 1982). It is 1.5 times as great as the yearly average number of civilian and battle field deaths during the 6 years of World War II. Every 4 days, it is the equivalent of another Hiroshima. Structural violence kills more people than have died in all acts of direct violence Pilisuk 1 (Marc, “GLOBALISM AND STRUCTURAL VIOLENCE” Peace, Conflict, and Violence: Peace Psychology for the 21st Century. Englewood Cliffs, New Jersey, PrenticeHall.) CH Limited material resources are not the only plight of poor people. Poverty inflicts psychological scars as well; it is an experience of scarcity amidst affluence. For many reasons, such as those discussed by Opotow (this volume), poverty produces the scorn of others and the internalized scorn of oneself. Indigence is not just about money, roads, or TVs, but also about the power to determine how local resources will be used to give meaning to lives. The power of global corporations in local communities forces people to depend on benefits from afar. Projected images of the good life help reduce different cultural values to the one global value of money. Meanwhile, money becomes concentrated in fewer hands. The world is dividing into a small group of “haves” and a growing group of paupers. This division of wealth inflicts a level of structural violence that kills many more persons than have died by all direct acts of violence and by war. Structural violence outweighs NW Evangelista 5 (Matthew, Professor of International and comparative politics, Harvard University, “Peace studies: Critical Concepts in Political Science”, 2005, http://books.google.com/books?id=9IAfLDzySd4C&pg=PA41&lpg=PA41&dq=%22structural+ violence%22+%22nuclear+war%22&source=bl&ots=m9wAXnUQqH&sig=4MnhVGRGJJ_Z8aS5SSmTp tgRqYM&hl=en&ei=YBJZSoSeKYuqswOQ9fjWBg&sa=X&oi=book_result&ct=result&resnum=6, AD: 7/11/9) TR But equally important is to recall that it is hardly possible to arrive at any general judgment, independent of time and space, as to which type of violence is more important. In space, today, it may certainly be argued that research in the Americas should focus on structural violence, between nations as well as between individuals, and that peace research in Europe should have a similar focus on personal violence. Latent personal violence in Europe may erupt into nuclear war, but the manifest structural violence in the Americas (and not only there) already causes an annual toll of nuclear magnitudes. In saying this, we are of course not neglecting the Stefan Bauschard Offensive PKOs release structural components of the European situation, (such as the big power dominance and the traditional exploitation of Eastern Europe by Western Europe) nor are we forgetful of the high level of personal violence in the Americas even though it does not take the form of international warfare (but sometimes the form of interventionist aggression). 159 Stefan Bauschard Offensive PKOs release 160 Impact – Structural Violence Outweighs Structural violence outweighs direct violence on magnitude and probability Pilisuk 97 (Marc, Fall, “The hidden structure of violence”, Fall97, Vol. 20 Issue 2, p25, 7phttp://web.ebscohost.com/ehost/detail?vid=8&hid=7&sid=9058ddcf-12214296-8d1b98c9d5856a77%40sessionmgr7&bdata=JnNpdGU9ZWhvc3QtbGl2ZQ%3d%3d#db=aph&AN=97120169 14) Poverty, inequality, social marginality, and domination of resources all produce unneeded suffering and death. These structures are not acts of nature but products of social arrangements created by people in ways not easily noticed. There are relationships among cultural, structural, and direct violence. Culture, the normative beliefs and practices of a society, can be a source of violence by allowing a dehumanization of certain persons or groups. Cultural violence leads to structural violence when it is incorporated into formal legal and economic exchanges. While individual acts of direct violence have many causes, their occurrence is frequently predicated upon a larger and often hidden structure that induces violence (Galtung 1996). The three types of violence differ temporally. Direct violence is an event; structural violence is a process with ebbs and flows; cultural violence remains more invariant, given the slow transformation of basic culture. In most cases, there is a flow from cultural violence to institutionalized structural violence, and finally to eruptions of direct violent acts. Direct violence is used by both underdogs and top dogs but serves quite different purposes for the two groups. Underdogs use violence as a way to get out of a "structural iron cage" of powerlessness and poverty or to get back at the society that put them there. Top dogs, on the other hand, use violence as a way to keep or gain power (Galtung 1996). Structural violence is harder to identify than direct violence. One can recognize acts of rape or murder as violent and we abhor them. Examples of structural violence, however, look normal on the surface. Therefore, more often than not, structural violence is left unchanged and the cycle of violence continues. Structural violence outweighs because it’s systemic Parson 7 (Kenneth, Peace Review, April-June, “Structural Violence and Power”, Peace Review; Apr-Jun2007, Vol. 19 Issue 2, p173-181, 9phttp://web.ebscohost.com/ehost/detail?vid=6&hid=7&sid=9058ddcf-1221-4296-8d1b98c9d5856a77%40sessionmgr7&bdata=JnNpdGU9ZWhvc3QtbGl2ZQ%3d%3d#db=aph&AN=25359940 ) CH Despite a “long century of violence”—rapid proliferation of the instruments of mass violence, the increasingly complex organization and accelerated deployment of the forces of violence, and the widespread mediazation of violence over the last three decades alone—our theoretical understanding and articulation of violence itself has progressed much more slowly. Johan Galtung is one particular theorist who takes seriously the project of clarifying how our discourses of violence perpetuate or provide alternatives to relations of violence. Given his longstanding attention to structural violence and the extensive thinking he has done on the relations between violence and power within the context of militarization, poverty, and political repression, his notions of peace and violence are not without substantial content and relevance to theorists of conflict and war Structural Violence has a greater impact than Direct Violence Maley 85 (William, The University of New South Wales at Duntroon, “Peace, Needs and Utopia”, Political Studies, XXXIIl, 578-591, http://web.ebscohost.com/ehost/pdf?vid=6&hid=7&sid=fbf7951e-fa9b-4ac2-ba3b2c07e8326bd2%40sessionmgr2) CH However, Galtung's major theoretical innovation was to posit a distinction between direct violence, where there is an actor committing the violence, and structural violence, where there is no such actor, On occasion he refers to this latter condition as 'social injustice', and he uses interchangeably the labels 'social injustice' and 'positive peace' to describe the absence of structural violence,-' However, he stressed that both the absence of direct violence and the absence of structural violence are significant goals, and that 'it is probably disservice to man to try, in any abstract way, to say that one is more important than the other'. Stefan Bauschard Offensive PKOs release 161 Impact – Sexism Militarism allows for the justification of violence against women Cuomo 96 (Chris J. Professor of Philosophy and Women's Studies, and Director of the Institute for Women's Studies at the University of Georgia, “War Is Not Just an Event: Reflections on the Significance of Everyday Violence”, Published in Hypatia 11.4 nb, pp. 31-48) To give one very clear example of the ways in which just-war evaluations of wars as events fail to address feminist questions about militarism, consider the widespread influence of foreign military bases on gendered national identities and interactions. In Bananas, Beaches and Bases: Making Feminist Sense of International Politics (1990), Cynthia Enloe illustrates how, while decision- making and economic power are held primarily by men, international relations and politics are inevitably played out on women's bodies in myriad ways, propagating racist, nationalist, and colonialist conceptions of femininity. One chapter, "Base Women," is devoted to a discussion of the ways in which local and global sexual politics shape and are shaped through the constant presence of thousands of military bases worldwide in the symbol of the soldier, the introduction of foreign conceptions of masculinity and femininity, the reproduction of family structures on military bases, and through systems of prostitution that universally coexist alongside military bases Enloe writes, "military politics, which occupy such a large part of international politics today, require military bases. Bases are artificial societies created out of unequal relations between men and women of different races and classes" and, one might add, different nations (Enloe 1990, 2). The constant, global presence of these bases is an example of the mundane givenness and subtle omnipresence of military violence. Most bases have managed to slip into the daily lives of the nearby community. A military base, even one controlled by soldiers of another country, can become politically invisible if its ways of doing business and seeing the world insinuate themselves into a community's schools, consumer tastes, housing patterns, children's games, adults' friendships, jobs and gossip. . . . Most have draped themselves with the camouflage of normalcy. . . . Rumors of a base closing can send shivers of economic alarm through a civilian community that has come to depend on base jobs and soldiers' spending. (Enloe 1990, 66) Just-war theory—even feminist just-war theory—cannot bring to light the ways ill which the politics of military bases are related to the waging of war, how militarism constructs masculinity and femininity, or how international politics are shaped by the microcosmic impacts of military bases. It therefore cannot address some of the most pressing ways in which militarism and war involve and affect women. Stefan Bauschard Offensive PKOs release 162 Impact – Environment Militarism justifies continual environmental destruction Cuomo 96 (Chris J. Professor of Philosophy and Women's Studies, and Director of the Institute for Women's Studies at the University of Georgia, “War Is Not Just an Event: Reflections on the Significance of Everyday Violence”, Published in Hypatia 11.4 nb, pp. 31-48) If environmental destruction is a necessary aspect of war and the peacetime practices of military institutions, an analysis of war which includes its embeddedness in peacetime militarism is necessary to address the environmental effects of war. Such a perspective must pay adequate attention to what is required to prepare for war in a technological age, and how women and other Others are affected by the realities of contemporary military institutions and practices Emphasizing the ways in which war is a presence, a constant undertone, white noise in the background of social existence, moving sometimes closer to the foreground of collective consciousness in the form of direct combat yet remaining mostly as an unconsidered given, allows for several promising analyses . To conclude, I will summarize four distinct benefits of feminist philosophical attention to the constancy of military presence in most everyday contemporary life. Militarism Destroys the Environment Cuomo 96 (Chris J. Professor of Philosophy and Women's Studies, and Director of the Institute for Women's Studies at the University of Georgia, “War Is Not Just an Event: Reflections on the Significance of Everyday Violence”, Published in Hypatia 11.4 nb, pp. 31-48) In Scorched Earth: The Military's Assault on the Environment, William Thomas, a U.S. Navy veteran, illustrates the extent to which the peacetime practices of military institutions damage natural environments and communities. Thomas argues that even "peace" entails a dramatic and widespread war on nature, or as Joni Seager puts it, "The environmental costs of militarized peace bear suspicious resemblance to the costs of war" (Thomas 1995, xi). All told, including peacetime activities as well as the immense destruction caused by combat, military institutions probably present the most dramatic threat to ecological well-being on the planet. The military is the largest generator of hazardous waste in the United States, creating nearly a ton of toxic pollution every minute, and military analyst Jillian Skeel claims that, "Global military activity may be the largest worldwide polluter and consumer of precious resources" (quoted in Thomas 1995, 5). A conventionally powered aircraft carrier consumes 150,000 gallons of fuel a day. In less than an hour's flight, a single jet launched from its flight deck consumes as much fuel as a North American motorist burns in two years. One F-16 jet engine requires nearly four and a half tons of scarce titanium, nickel, chromium, cobalt, and energy-intensive aluminum (Thomas 1995, 5), and nine percent of all the iron and steel used by humans is consumed by the global military (Thomas 1995, 16). The United States Department of Defense generates 500,000 tons of toxins annually, more than the world's top five chemical companies combined. The military is the biggest single source of environmental pollution in the United States. Of 338 citations issued by the United States Environmental Protection Agency in 1989, three-quarters went to military installations (Thomas 1995, 17). Stefan Bauschard Offensive PKOs release 163 Impact – Environment Military practices destroy the environment both during war and peace time Cuomo 96 (Chris J. Professor of Philosophy and Women's Studies, and Director of the Institute for Women's Studies at the University of Georgia, “War Is Not Just an Event: Reflections on the Significance of Everyday Violence”, Published in Hypatia 11.4 nb, pp. 31-48) There are many conceptual and practical connections between military practices in which humans aim to kill and harm each other for some declared "greater good," and nonmilitary practices in which we displace, destroy, or seriously modify nonhuman communities, species, and ecosystems in the name of human interests. An early illustration of these connections was made by Rachel Carson in the first few pages of The Silent Spring (1962), in which she described insecticides as the inadvertent offspring of World War II chemical weapons research. We can now also trace ways in which insecticides were put of the Western-defined global corporatization of agriculture that helped kill off the small family farm and made the worldwide system of food production dependent on the likes of Dow Chemical and Monsanto. Military practices are no different from other human practices that damage and irreparably modify nature. They are often a result of costbenefit analyses that pretend to weigh all likely outcomes yet do not consider nonhuman entities except in terms of their use value for humans and they nearly always create unforeseeable effects for humans and nonhumans. In addition, everyday military peacetime practices are actually more destructive than most other human activities, they are directly enacted by state power, and, because they function as unquestioned "givens," they enjoy a unique near-immunity to enactments of moral reproach. It is worth noting the extent to which everyday military activities remain largely unscrutinized by environmentalists, especially American environmentalists, largely because fear allows us to he fooled into thinking that "national security" is an adequate excuse for "ecological military mayhem" (Thomas 1995, 16). Stefan Bauschard Offensive PKOs release 164 Impact – Genocide The ideology of militarism guarantees genocide and unlimited violence Cuomo 96 (Chris J. Professor of Philosophy and Women's Studies, and Director of the Institute for Women's Studies at the University of Georgia, “War Is Not Just an Event: Reflections on the Significance of Everyday Violence”, Published in Hypatia 11.4 nb, pp. 31-48) The feminization, commodification, and devaluation of nature helps create a reality in which its destruction in warfare is easily justified. In imagining an ethic that addresses these realities, feminists cannot neglect the extent to which military ecocide is connected, conceptually and practically, to transnational capitalism and other forms of human oppression and exploitation. Virtually all of the world's thirty-five nuclear bomb test sites, as well as most radioactive dumps and uranium mines, occupy Native lands (Thomas 1995, 6). Six nuiltinationals control one-quarter of all United States defense contracts (Thomas 1995, 10), and two million dollars per minute is spent on the global military (Thomas 1995, 7). One could go on for volumes about the elleci of chemical and nuclear testing, military-industrial development and waste, and the disruption of wildlife, habitats, communities, and lifestyles that are inescapably linked to military practices. There are many conceptual and practical connections between military practices in which humans aim to kill and harm each other for some declared "greater good," and nonmilitary practices in which we displace, destroy, or seriously modify nonhuman communities, species, and ecosystems in the name of human interests. An early illustration of these connections was made by Rachel Carson in the first few pages of The Silent Spring (1962), in which she described insecticides as the inadvertent offspring of World War II chemical weapons research. We can now also trace ways in which insecticides were put of the Western-defined global corporatization of agriculture that helped k ill olf the small family farm and made the worldwide system of food production dependent on the likes of Dow Chemical and Monsanto. Military practices are no different from other human practices that damage and irreparably modify nature. They are often a result of cost-benefit analyses that pretend to weigh all likely outcomes yet do not consider nonhuman entities except in terms of their use value for humans and they nearly always create unforeseeable effects for humans and nonhumans . In addition, everyday military peacetime practices are actually more destructive than most other human activities, they are directly enacted by state power, and, because they function as unquestioned "givens," they enjoy a unique near-immunity to enactments of moral reproach. It is worth noting the extent to which everyday military activities remain largely unscrutinized by environmentalists, especially American environmentalists, largely because fear allows us to he fooled into thinking that "national security" is an adequate excuse for "ecological military mayhem" (Thomas 1995, 16). If environmental destruction is a necessary aspect of war and the peacetime practices of military institutions, an analysis of war which includes its embeddedness in peacetime militarism is necessary to address the environmental effects of war. Such a perspective must pay adequate attention to what is required to prepare for war in a technological age, and how women and other Others are affected by the realities of contemporary military institutions and practices. Stefan Bauschard Offensive PKOs release 165 Impact – Morality OW’s Extinction We have a moral obligation to help others in the face of structural violence even if that leads to extinction. Watson 77 (Richard, Professor of Philosophy at Washington University, World Hunger and Moral Obligation, p. 118-119) These arguments are morally spurious. That food sufficient for well-nourished survival is the equal right of every human individual or nation is a specification of the higher principle that everyone has equal right to the necessities of life. The moral stress of the principle of equity is primarily on equal sharing, and only secondarily on what is being shared. The higher moral principle is of human equity per se. Consequently, the moral action is to distribute all food equally, whatever the consequences. This is the hard line apparently drawn by such moralists as Immanuel Kant and Noam Chomsky—but then, morality is hard. The conclusion may be unreasonable (impractical and irrational in conventional terms), but it is obviously moral. Nor should anyone purport surprise; it has always been understood that the claims of morality—if taken seriously—supersede those of conflicting reason. One may even have to sacrifice one’s life or one’s nation to be moral in situations where practical behavior would preserve it. For example, if a prisoner of war undergoing torture is to be a (perhaps dead) patriot even when reason tells him that collaboration will hurt no one, he remains silent. Similarly, if one is to be moral, one distributes available food in equal shares (even if everyone then dies). That an action is necessary to save one’s life is no excuse for behaving unpatriotically or immorally if one wishes to be a patriot or moral. No principle of morality absolves one of behaving immorally simply to save one’s life or nation. There is a strict analogy here between adhering to moral principles for the sake of being moral, and adhering to Christian principles for the sake of being Christian. The moral world contains pits and lions, but one looks always to the highest light. The ultimate test always harks to the highest principle—recant or die—and it is pathetic to profess morality if one quits when the going gets rough. I have put aside many questions of detail— such as the mechanical problems of distributing food—because detail does not alter the stark conclusion. If every human life is equal in value, then the equal distribution of the necessities of life is an extremely high, if not the highest, moral duty. It is at least high enough to override the excuse that by doing it one would lose one’s life. But many people cannot accept the view that one must distribute equally even in f the nation collapses or all people die. If everyone dies, then there will be no realm of morality. Practically speaking, sheer survival comes first. One can adhere to the principle of equity only if one exists. So it is rational to suppose that the principle of survival is morally higher than the principle of equity. And though one might not be able to argue for unequal distribution of food to save a nation—for nations can come and go—one might well argue that unequal distribution is necessary for the survival of the human species. That is, some large group—say one-third of present world population—should be at least well-nourished for human survival. However, from an individual standpoint, the human species—like the nation—is of no moral relevance. From a naturalistic standpoint, survival does come first; from a moralistic standpoint—as indicated above—survival may have to be sacrificed. In the milieu of morality, it is immaterial whether or not the human species survives as a result of individual behavior. Stefan Bauschard Offensive PKOs release 166 ***Alternative*** Stefan Bauschard Offensive PKOs release 167 Alternative – Discourse Discourse is key to positive peace Gay 98 (William, University of North Carolina, Charlotte, December, “The Practice of Linguistic nonviolence”, Peace Review, 10402659, Dec98, Vol. 10, Issue 4, http://web.ebscohost.com/ehost/detail?vid=7&hid=7&sid=fbf 7951e-fa9b4ac2-ba3b-2c07e8326bd2%40sessionmgr2&bdata=JnNpdGU9ZWhvc3QtbGl2ZQ%3d %3d#db=ap h&A N=1426690) Many times the first step in reducing linguistic violence is to simply refrain from the use of offensive and oppressive terms. However, just because linguistic violence is not being used, a genuinely pacific discourse is not necessarily present. Nonviolent discourse, like the condition of peace, can be negative or positive. "Negative peace" refers to the temporary absence of actual war or the lull between wars, while "positive peace" refers to the negation of war and the presence of justice. The pacific discourse that is analogous to negative peace can actually perpetuate injustice. Broadcasters in local and national news may altogether avoid using terms like "dyke" or "fag" or even "homosexual," but they and their audiences can remain homophobic even when the language of lesbian and gay pride is used . A government may cease referring to a particular nation as "a rogue state," but public and private attitudes may continue to foster prejudice toward this nation and its inhabitants. When prejudices remain unspoken, at least in public thrums, their detection and eradication are made even more difficult . Of course, we need to find ways to restrain hate speech in order to at least stop linguistic attacks in the public arena. Likewise, we need to find ways to restrain armed conflicts and hostile name calling directed against an adversary of the state. However , even if avoidance of linguistic violence is necessary, it is not sufficient. Those who bite their tongues to comply with the demands of political correctness are often ready to lash out vitriolic epithets when these constraints are removed. T hus, the practice of linguistic nonviolence is more like negative peace when the absence of hurtful or harmful terminology merely marks a lull in reliance on linguistic violence or a shift of its use from the public to the private sphere. The merely public or merely formal repression of language and behavior that expresses these attitudes builds up pressure that can erupt in subsequent outbursts of linguistic violence and physical violence. Linguistic violence causes structural violence – Resistance solves Gay 98 (William, University of North Carolina, Charlotte, December, “The Practice of Linguistic nonviolence”, Peace Review, 10402659, Dec98, Vol. 10, Issue 4, http://web.ebscohost.com/ehost/detail?vid=7&hid=7&sid=fbf 7951e-fa9b4ac2-ba3b-2c07e8326bd2%40sessionmgr2&bdata=JnNpdGU9ZWhvc3QtbGl2ZQ%3d %3d#db=ap h&A N=1426690) CH The first step is breaking our silence concerning the many forms of violence. We need to recognize that often silence is violence; frequently, unless we break l he silence, we are being complicitous to the violence of the situation. However, in breaking the silence, our aim should be to avoid counter-violence, in its physical forms and in its verbal forms. Efforts to advance peace and justice should occupy the space between silence and violence. Linguistic violence can be overcome, but the care and vigilance of the positive practice of physical and linguistic nonviolence is needed if the gains are to be substantive, rather than merely formal, and if the goals of nonviolence are to be equally operative in the means whereby we overcome linguistic violence and social injustice. Stefan Bauschard Offensive PKOs release 168 Alternative – Reject Moving away from crisis-driven politics solves Cuomo 96 (Chris J. Professor of Philosophy and Women's Studies, and Director of the Institute for Women's Studies at the University of Georgia, “War Is Not Just an Event: Reflections on the Significance of Everyday Violence”, Published in Hypatia 11.4 nb, pp. 31-48) Moving away from crisis-driven politics and ontologies concerning war and military violence also enables consideration of relationships among seemingly disparate phenomena, and therefore can shape more nuanced theoretical and practical forms of resistance. For example, investigating the ways in which war is part of a presence allows consideration of the relationships among the events of war and the following: how militarism is a foundational trope in the social and political imagination; how the pervasive presence and symbolism of soldiers/warriors/patriots shape meanings of gender; the ways in which threats of statesponsored violence are a sometimes invisible/sometimes bold agent of racism, nationalism, and corporate interests; the fact that vast numbers of communities, cities, and nations are currently in the midst of excruciatingly violent circumstances. It also provides a lens for considering the relationships among the various kinds of violence that get labeled "war." Given current American obsessions with nationalism, guns, and militias, and growing hunger for the death penalty, prisons, and a more powerful police state, one cannot underestimate the need for philosophical and political attention to connections among phenomena like the "war on drugs," the "war on crime," and other state-funded militaristic campaigns. Rejecting negative peace opens the space for positive peace Salomon and Nevo 2 (Gavriel and Baruch, educational psychologists, University of Haifa, Lawrence Erlbaum Associates, “Peace Education: The Concept, Principles, and Practices around the World”, 2002, http://www.questiaschool.com/read/109637749?title=Peace%20Education%3a%20%20The% 20Concept%2c%20Principles%2c%20and%20Practices%20around%20the%20World, AD: 7/9/9) TR It is obvious that peace education is not a single entity. A variety of distinctions can be offered. For one, peace has more than one meaning, and so does its absence—violence. Galtung (1973) distinguished between positive and negative peace, with the former denoting collaboration, integration, and cooperation, and the latter denoting the absence of physical and direct violence between groups. He also coined the construct of "structural violence," denoting societal built-in inequalities and injustices. A second, possible distinction pertains to the sociopolitical context in which peace education takes place: regions of intractable conflict (Rouhana & Bar-Tal, 1998), regions of racial or ethnic tension with no overt actions of hostility (e.g., Leman, chap. 14, this volume), or regions of tranquility and cooperation. A third distinction can be made between desired changes: changes on the local, microlevel, for example, learning to settle conflicts and to cooperate on an interpersonal level, versus desired changes on a more global, macrolevel, for example, changing perceptions, stereotypes, and prejudices pertaining to whole collectives. Although in both cases individuals are the targets for change, the change itself pertains to two different levels: more positive ways of handling other individuals versus handling other collectives. Still another possible distinction is between the political, economic, and social status of peace education participants: racial or ethnic majority versus minority, conqueror versus conquered, and perpetrator versus victim. Clearly, peace education for the weak and dominated is not the same as for the strong and dominating (for important distinctions, see chapter 3 by Bar-Tal, this volume). Whereas these and other distinctions are of great importance, I think that the sociopolitical context in which peace education takes place supersedes the rest. It is the context that determines to an important extent (a) the challenges faced by peace education, (b) its goals, and (c) its ways of treating the different subgroups of participants. Thus, for example, a rough examination of peace education programs around the world suggests that whereas regions of relative tranquility emphasize education for cooperation and harmony (positive peace), promoting the idea of a general culture of peace, regions of conflict and tension emphasize education for violence prevention (negative peace), greater equality, and practical coexistence with real adversaries, enemies, and minorities. Whereas the former are likely to promote individual skills in handling local, interpersonal conflicts, the latter are more likely to address perceptions of and tolerance toward collectives. Stefan Bauschard Offensive PKOs release 169 Stefan Bauschard Offensive PKOs release 170 Alternative – Reject The ontopolitical act of rejection calls into question the negative peace worldview, prompting alternatives Burke 2 (Anthony, Senior Lecturer in International Relations at the University of New South Wales, Alternatives: Global, Local, Political, “Aporias of Security”, http://www.questia.com/read/5002461817?title=Aporias%20of%20Security, AD: 7/10/9) However, I believe that, more than ever, we do need to ask what it is to be secure. Surely we no longer know what security is--in that Platonic sense. Surely more than ten years after the end of the Gold War, after the Clinton Doctrine and the destruction of the Twin Towers, after humanitarian and policy disasters in Indochina, Africa, East Timor, the Middle East, and Central America, and after a growing body of humanist and critical scholarship has questioned security's unity, discursive structure, and political implications, security no longer possesses a credible wholeness. (1) This article begins from the premise that security's claims to universality and wholeness founder on a destructive series of aporias, which derive firstly from the growing sense that security no longer has a stable referent object, nor names a common set of needs, means, or ways of being, and secondly, from the moral relativism that lies at the center of dominant (realist) discourses of security that pretend to universality but insist that "our" security always rests on the insecurity and suffering of another. While this article argues strongly that security has no essential ontological integrity, it also argues that if the power and sweep of security are to be understood and challenged, its claims to universality must be taken seriously. They underpin and animate sweeping forms of power, subjectivity, force, and economic circulation and cannot be dismissed out of hand. Nor, in the hands of some humanist writers--who have sought to think human and gender security in radical counterpoint to realist images of national and international security--are such claims always pernicious. They have a valuable moral and political force that undermines, perhaps unwittingly, the logocentric presuppositions of the realist discourses they question. Yet a common assumption that security can be ontologically completed and secured does present a hurdle for the kind of "ontopolitical" critique that we really need. (2) The answer is not to seek to close out these aporias; they call to us and their existence presents an important political opening. Rather than seek to resecure security, to make it conform to a new humanist ideal--however laudable--we need to challenge security as a claim to truth, to set its "meaning" aside. Instead, we should focus on security as a pervasive and complex system of political, social, and economic power, which reaches from the most private spaces of being to the vast flows and conflicts of geopolitics and global economic circulation. It is to see security as an interlocking system of knowledges, representations, practices, and institutional forms that imagine, direct, and act upon bodies, spaces, and flows in certain ways-to see security not as an essential value but as a political technology. This is to move from essence to genealogy: a genealogy that aims, in William Connolly's words, to "open us up to the play of possibility in the present ... [to] incite critical responses to unnecessary violences and injuries surreptitiously imposed upon life by the insistence that prevailing forms are natural, rational, universal or necessary." (3) Stefan Bauschard Offensive PKOs release 171 Alternative – Small Actions Small acts of resistance are key to positive peace Duncan 2 (Grace, Student of Peace and Conflict, School of Political Science and International Studies, UQ, Winter, “Peace, Action and Consequences”, http://web.ebscohost.com/ehost/pdf?vid=9&hid=7&sid=fbf7951e-fa9b-4ac2-ba3b2c07e8326bd2%40sessionmgr2) So the causes of this violence are personal as well as societal. Aaron has problems—his unemployment and his family— but his reaction to those problems is far from inevitable. It can be argued that Aaron’s unhappiness has led to this violence as much as anything else. Any action that would reduce his unhappiness, a simple act of genuine kindness or compassion, would thus address this problem and contribute to positive peace. Such an act would be barely visible to the world at large, yet its contribution would be more durable because it goes closer to the source of the conflict. Clearly Aaron would not completely change his behaviour because one person was nice to him, but such an action can feed into the psychological web of human society and have ripple like effects. In this way, the action would be broad in its consequences and far less ambiguous than those mentioned above. While its results would be difficult to see, they should not be ignored. Clearly, this theory is a crude simplification of a complex situation, perhaps an oversimplification. It must be acknowledged that not all levels of action are appropriate or possible in all circumstances, nor are they available to all people. While ‘smaller’ actions can be undertaken by almost anyone, ‘bigger’ acts are reserved for those with political power or influence. The ethical stance generated by this theory is not that an individual should shun ‘bigger’ acts (if they are available to them), because of their ambiguity and short shelf-life, in favour of ‘smaller’ interpersonal actions. It is that ‘smaller’ acts have ethical priority because of the relative purity and durability of their consequences, and should not be compromised in pursuit of ‘big’ actions. They should not be forgotten or judged less important simply because they are subtle and unspectacular and do not occur in the more glamorous public or international spheres. People have different ideas about how best to pursue peace and these, at times, seem irreconcilable. This paper has explained, through the device of the continuum of action for peace, what I see as the connections and relationships between various types of acts that have this aim. It has dealt with the fact that actions undertaken with purely altruistic motives can sometimes have ambiguous results, particularly if they are ‘big actions, and especially if they lose sight of these connections and of the ultimate aim of positive peace. The hypothetical example used is intended only as a thoughtexperiment. It would be the task of further study to show how such ideas are manifested in the real world. Stefan Bauschard Offensive PKOs release 172 Alternative – Solves Politicians/Elites Gradualism is the only way to solve – preparing for conflicts brings them into existence, dragging the world into a nuclear holocaust – politicians cannot solve, the alternative must occur alone Groten and Jansen 81 (Hubert and Juergen, Doctorate in International Studies and Peace Lobbyist, “Interpreters and Lobbies for Positive Peace”, Journal of Peace Research, Vol. 18, No. 2, Special Issue on Theories of Peace 175-181, Sage Publications, http://www.jstor.org/stable/424209, A.D.: 7/9/09) With regard to peace research as we know it, we may conclude that nothing can be done. This does not seem to worry peace researchers unduly. As shown above, they have been allowed to settle down as a scholarly community, tolerated by the powers that be and by the public. In addi- tion, the impact that critical peace research can make is largely reduced by political pressure that faces the peace researchers with the alternative of either refraining from publishing any radical conclusions from their research or of seeing public acceptance and public funds withdrawn. This dampens any enthusiasm, especially as there is no positive feedback to cheer one up. This is because the rulers tolerate peace research, and the masses, the people who should be interested in it, know nothing about it. Not raising their voices too high to avoid disturbing the peace is what peace researchers seem to have resigned themselves to. All this is happening at a point of history when the world is poised on the brink of a holocaust; when the behaviour of man, under the influence of what Osgood calls 'psycho-logic',8 must be qualified as par- anoid; when the spiralling arms race has been allowed to take on a frightening reality of its own. This is happening when one of the leading German scholars and scientists, Carl F. von Weizsacker, who among other things has a well-earned reputation as a peace researcher, is setting energetically about the task of propagating the need for nuclear shelters for the people.9 He, too, seems to have resigned himself this time to yet another war taking its natural course - it cannot be helped, it is all so human. After that war is over, we must sit down and seriously think about preventing war. Now there is nothing we can do but construct shelters. Von Weizsacker surely knows that the speeding up of civilian de- fence adds momentum to the spiralling con- flict as it makes war a working proposition again in the minds of many. How can this suicidal folly be stopped? Our answer is gradualism. It makes suggestions that do not strain the social and political system or the individual too much. Its basic assumption, that symbolic uni- lateral steps can prepare the way to qual- itative disarmament, ought to be taken up again. New thinking, though, has to be added to gradualist theory where the addressees are concerned. So far the proponents of grad- ualism have been addressing themselves mainly to politicians. But most of the politi- cians in responsible positions have many conflicting interests to take care of and con- flicting pressures to respond to. What is more important, they are not so personally involved since they are the ones who are least affected by the effects of structural violence, and they are well-cushioned against the absence of positive peace. However, there is a small band of politicians who would be prepared to take up the cause of positive peace provided they are given encourage- ment and continuous support by their voters. There is no support for a positive peace policy from the dominant strata of society because they are not aware of the necessity of such a policy. Stefan Bauschard Offensive PKOs release 173 Stefan Bauschard Offensive PKOs release 174 A2: Positive Peace – Vagueness We must move forward toward positive peace – attempts to define the goal are only constructions of a flawed mindset Groten and Jansen 81 (Hubert and Juergen, Doctorate in International Studies and Peace Lobbyist, “Interpreters and Lobbies for Positive Peace”, Journal of Peace Research, Vol. 18, No. 2, Special Issue on Theories of Peace 175-181, Sage Publications, http://www.jstor.org/stable/424209, A.D.: 7/9/09) 'Peace is not merely the absence of war, collective violence or threats to use violence; the idea of peace must be rendered using terms like 'justice', 'freedom', 'development', and 'solidarity'.'5 Expanding the concept of peace in this way does not make it any more workable than does reducing it to a normative formula such as: peace is meeting man's basic needs or providing the minimum for subsistence.6 The difficulties that arise when one tries to define peace are aptly summarized in the following words: 'All the attempts at pro- ducing a comprehensive definition of what positive peace is must be seen in the light of the quest for an all-embracing political system which as a minimum guarantees the survival of mankind and as its maximum creates a social order in which the welfare and happiness of man are achieved.'7 Is it at all possible to find a useful and practicable definition of positive peace? As it embraces both the road and the goal, both the method or process and the aim, it would have to incorporate an analysis of present- day society and, at the same time, would have to trace the picture of a new, just society. Perhaps we are asking the wrong questions. What we ought to be concerned with cannot be a comprehensive definition but, rather, an analysis of the existing situation that would provide us with the tools to start changing society. Another idea becomes es- sential here. This is democratization which, like positive peace, is both the goal, i. e., a democratic society free from structural violence, and the road leading to it, i.e., a procedure that takes in the masses and is supported by them. The goal can be named but it need not be defined. What matters is the process, the road leading to it, the key to it, positive peace being the guideline . The idea then is not to use up one's energy trying to present people with a pic- ture of what may be in store for them but to prepare the way, advancing by small steps, taking first things first. Of course providing a clear analysis of the existing situation is more than many peace researchers ever do; but this is not sufficient in itself. It is, however, equally insufficient to point to a utopia . Doing first things first also implies that critical peace research cannot be 'neutral' or 'objective' in the sense that it appeals to all and sundry in bland scientific terms. It has to take sides. It has to prepare action. This means first of all realizing that there is nobody eagerly waiting for recipes or in- structions from peace research. Critical peace researchers have to under- stand that their aims are not the aims of the people dominating society. What critical peace research has to offer can only be put into practice with the help of those people who are most seriously affected by the absence of positive peace. Only they can initiate and implement any policy that com- bats structural violence. It is not to the rulers of society that positive peace appeals; it is to the dispossessed and oppressed that the value and the chances of positive peace must be proved. However, they are not aware of the terms' structural violence' and 'positive peace' that have so far been re- served to academic circles, as jargon, and to a few privileged people, as esoteric knowl- edge Stefan Bauschard Offensive PKOs release 175 A2: Aff Alone Doesn’t Solve A movement towards positive peace is a prerequisite to solving all harms – even a small transition solves the most intense impacts of structural violence Barash 0 (David P., Professor of Psychology at the University of Washington, “Approaches to peace: a leader in peace studies”, Oxford University Press, 2000, http://www.questiaschool.com/read/111756263?title=Approaches%20to%20Peace%3a%20% 20A%20Reader%20in%20Peace%20Studies, AD: 7-10-9) It is important to be against war. But it is not enough. We also need to be in favor of somethingsomething positive and affirming: namely, peace. Peace studies is unique not only because it is multidisciplinary and forthrightly proclaims its adherence to values, but also because it identifies positive visions of peace as being greater than the absence of war. The positive peace toward which peace studies strives may be, if anything,even more challenging than the prevention of war. It is a variation on what has been called the dog-car problem. Imagine a dog that has spent yars barking and running after cars. Then, one day, it catches one. What does it do with it? What would devotees of peace do with the world if they had the opportunity? This is not a useless exercise, as before any future can be established, it must first be imagined. And moreover, unlike our hypothetical car-chasing dog, the establishment of positive peace is not an all-or-nothing phenomenon. The movement toward positive peace is likely to be halting and fragmentary, with substantial success along certain dimensions, likely failures along others. On balance, the project is formidable, nothing less than a fundamental effort to rethink the relationship of human beings to each other and to their shared planet. If war and its causes are difficult to define- and this is assuredly the case- the positive peace is even more elusive. (It can even be dangerous, since disagreements over what constitutes a desirable peace can lead to war.) Earlier, we briefly considered just war doctrine. The conditions for a just peace are no less strenuous or important. The relevant issues include- but are not limited to- aspirations for human rights, economic fairness and opportunity, democratization, and what, specifically, is desire, or how much emphasis to place on each goal. The pursuit of positive peace nonetheless leads to certain agreed principles, one of which is a minimization of violence, not only the over violence of war, but also what has been called structural violence a condition that is typically built into many social and cultural institutions. A slave-holding society may be at peace in that it is not literally at war, but it is also rife with structural violence. Structural violence has the effect of denying people important rights such as economic opportunity, social and political equality, a sense of fulfillment and self-worth, and access to a healthy natural environment. When people starve to death, or even go hungry, a kind of violence is taking place. Similarly, when human beings suffer from diseases that are preventable when, they are denied a decent education, housing, an opportunity to play, to grow, to work, to raise a family, to express themselves freely, to organize peacefully, or to participate in their own governance, a kind of violence is occurring, even if bullets or clubs are not being used. Society visits violence on human rights and dignity when it forcibly stunts the optimum development of each human being, whether because of race, religion, sex, sexual preference, age, ideology, and so on. In short, structural violence is another way of identifying oppression, and positive peace would be a situation in which structural violence and oppression are minimized. In addition, social injustice is important not only in its contribution to structural violence, but also as a major contributor to war, often in unexpected ways. For many citizens of the United States and Europe, as well as privileged people worldwide, current lifestyles are fundamentally acceptable. Hence, peace for them has come to meant the continuation of things as they are, with the additional hope that overt violence will be prevented. For others- perhaps the majority of our planet- change of one sort or another is desired. And for a small minority, peace is something to fight for! A Central American peasant was quoted in the New York Times saying “I am for peace, but not peace with hunger.” Stefan Bauschard Offensive PKOs release 176 A2: Aff Alone Doesn’t Solve Positive peace is a process – We’re the necessary first step Bilgin 5 (Pinar, Assistant Professor, Ph.D, International Politics and Security, University of Wales, “Regional Security in the middle East: A Critical Perspective”, 2005, http://www.questia.com/read/108556832?title=Regional%20Security%20in%20the%20Mid dle%20East%3a%20%20A%20Critical%20Perspective, AD: 7/10/9) As an analytical move, broadening security entails questioning the military-focused security agendas of Cold War Security Studies and calling for opening up the agenda to include other non-military threats. In making this move, students of critical approaches to security have followed in the footsteps of Peace Researchers who, from the 1960s onwards, had gradually widened their conceptions of peace and violence. Distinguishing between 'negative' and 'positive' peace, John Galtung argued that peace defined as here by the absence of armed conflict is 'negative peace'. 'Positive peace', maintained Galtung, means the absence of not only direct physical violence but also indirect (and sometimes unintentional) 'structural violence' - that is, those socio-economic institutions and relations that oppress human beings by preventing them from realising their potential. Galtung (1969, 1996) also emphasised that to attain 'positive peace', it is not enough to seek to eliminate violence; existing institutions and relations should be geared towards the enhancement of dialogue, cooperation and solidarity among peoples coupled with a respect for the environment. It is also worth noting here that for Galtung (1996:265) peace is not a static concept; it is rather a process (as with security and emancipation for students of critical approaches to security; see Booth 1991b; Wyn Jones 1999). Building upon Peace Researchers' broadening of the concepts of violence and peace that took human beings as the referent, students of critical approaches to security broadened security to include in Ken Booth's words - 'all those physical and human constraints which stop them from carrying out what they would freely choose to do' (Booth 1991b: 319; Booth 1999b: 40). Such constraints may include human rights abuses, water shortage, illiteracy, lack of access to health care and birth control, militarisation of society, environmental degradation and economic deprivation as well as armed conflic t at the state- and sub-state level. Accordingly, the purpose behind broadening security, from a critical perspective, is to become aware of threats to security faced by referents in all walks of life and approach them within a comprehensive and dynamic framework cognisant of the interrelationships in between. Understood as such, broadening security does not simply mean putting more issues on governments' security agendas, but opening up security to provide a richer picture that includes all issues that engender insecurity. In other words, although the broadening of governmental security agendas is an offshoot of broadening security, it is not its main purpose. After all, the US Central Intelligence Agency also broadened its agenda in the 1990s (Johnson 1993), but sought to address them through its traditional practices. Stefan Bauschard Offensive PKOs release 177 A2: Positive Peace = Violence/Revolt Positive peace precludes the possibility of violence or revolution Groten and Jansen 81 (Hubert and Juergen, Doctorate in International Studies and Peace Lobbyist, “Interpreters and Lobbies for Positive Peace”, Journal of Peace Research, Vol. 18, No. 2, Special Issue on Theories of Peace 175-181, Sage Publications, http://www.jstor.org/stable/424209, A.D.: 7/9/09) Peace research is called upon to break this doubly vicious circle. It can do this if it takes its central concept, peace, more seriously. Only then will it take itself seriously. And only then will it accept its responsibilities to the people. To do this, it has to come down from its academic pulpit . It is here that the concept of 'positive peace' comes in.3 'Positive peace' is central to a peace re- search that claims to be a critical social science. When peace research started some twenty years ago there were the 'armers', who aimed at controlling military conflicts by calling for arms, and new arms at that; and there vere the 'disarmers'. This distinction was not sufficient. Only when Johan Galtung broke down the narrow concept of violence as personal, direct violence by introducing the concept of 'structural violence' could peace research develop into a critical social science. Those social scientists that have opted for critical peace research believe that structural violence is present wherever man is deprived of his potentiality by the working of the very structure of society itself . So this kind of violence is produced by the structure of society and it, in turn, supports this structure. According to this concept, any social injustice is structural violence. Direct, per- sonal violence is but one aspect of this violence. Starting from this concept, Dieter Senghaas developed his concept of 'organized peacelessness'. Critical peace research is more radically critical of society and considers a 'peace' policy that advocates deterrence as not only too limited but also as preserving the social status quo characterized by structural violence. This does not mean, however, that critical peace research, on a continuum of possible policies, is placed firmly at the end advocating revolution. On the contrary, it rules out revolution as this implies the use of direct violence. So on this continuum peace research stops short of revolution; it equally rejects the policy of deterrence as a means not capable of bringing about positive peace. This does not mean, however, that it does not take into account short and medium-term approaches as well. It has to in order to reach its addressees. At this point a somewhat closer inspection of the category central to peace research, positive peace, is called for. Positive peace can only be achieved in the absence of structural violence and the violent structures that go with it. Positive peace is social justice. Stefan Bauschard Offensive PKOs release 178 A2: Positive Peace = Authoritarianism Positive peace resists authoritarianism Potter 4 (Nancy Nyquist, PhD in Rhetoric from the University of Minnesota, “Putting Peace into practice”, pg. 14-15, http://books.google.com/books?id=uQ4Ab7drluQC&pg=PA5&lpg=PA5&dq=%22negative+peace%22+%22 positive+peace%22+%22inseparable%22&source=bl&ots=JyUFsQfWT3&sig=LtO877TxxXq2bEOC_aGIbd7_ kU0&hl=en&ei=WRRZSpChF4XcsgOZ5OCZCg&sa=X&oi=book_result&ct=result&resnum=4, A.D.: 7/11/09) The language of positive peace is quite compatible with the democratic spirit and is diametrically opposed to authoritarian traditions. Since the language of positive peace resists monologue and encourages dialogue, it fosters an approach to public policy debate that is receptive rather than aggressive and meditative rather than calculative. The language of positive peace is not passive in the sense of avoiding engagement; it is pacific in the sense of seeking to actively build lasting peace and justice. In this sense, while the language and practice of positive peace facilitates the continuation of politics rather than its abandonment, it also elevates diplomacy to an aim for cooperation and consensus rather than competition and compromise. The language of positive peace provides a way of perceiving and communicating that frees us to the diversity and openendedness of life rather than the sameness and finality of death that results when diplomacy fails and war ensues. The language of positive peace, by providing an alternative to the language of war and the language of negative peace, can introduce into public policy discourse shared social values that express the goals of a fully politicized and enfranchised humanity. Stefan Bauschard Offensive PKOs release 179 Positive Peace Good – Solves Root Cause (1/2) Positive peace resolves the underlying causes of conflicts and violence- facilitates the development of relationships which restore and preserve community values and needs. We should be encouraging the government to pass policies of peace and justice Sandy and Perkins 1 (Leo R and Ray, Co-Founder of Peace Studies at Plymouth State College and teacher of philosophy at Plymouth State College, “The Nature of Peace and it’s implication for peace education”, online journal of peace and conflict resolution 4.2, http://www.uio.no/studier/emner/jus/jus/ENGSEMJ/v08/undervisningsmateriale/IL%20&%20HR/Topic%202%20%20Reading.pdf, 2001, AD:7-10-9) Positive peace, in contrast, is “a pattern of cooperation and integration between major human groups....[It] is about people interacting in cooperative ways; it is about social organizations of diverse peoples who willingly choose to cooperate for the benefit of all humankind; it calls for a system in which there are no winners and losers--all are winners; it is a state so highly valued that institutions are built around it to protect and promote it” (O’Kane, 1991-92). It also “involves the search for positive conditions which can resolve the underlying causes of conflict that produce violence” (Woolman, 1985, p.8). The strategies used for this purpose are called “associative,” and they are characterized by “a high level of social interaction [which] enables more rapid resolution of conflict by providing maximum contacts through which solutions may arise” (Woolman, 1985, p.8). Woolman also describes the sort of social reorganization that would provide the best opportunity for real peace. Essentially, he espouses Galtung’s idea of smallness and decentralization of power and authority. Thus, “small scale social organization offers a better environment for encouragement of local autonomy, participation, and high levels of inter-group interaction. Big countries, corporations, and institutions are generally regarded as negative structures because they are prone to depersonalization, excessive centralization of decision-making, and patterns of center-periphery exploitation.” Gene Sharp (1980) in his Social Power and Political Freedom adroitly elaborates these points. The condition of smallness does much to reduce feelings of anonymity and powerlessness. It also facilitates the development of relationships which can restore and preserve community values and spiritual needs which “should take precedence over the materialism that is so central to Western culture.” (Woolman, 1985, p.12). Consistent with these approaches, Reardon (1988) places global justice as the central concept of positive peace and asserts that “justice, in the sense of the full enjoyment of the entire range of human rights by all people, is what constitutes positive peace” (p.26). In a similar vain, Trostle’s (1992) comprehensive definition of peace clearly places it within a positive context: “[Peace is] a state of well-being that is characterized by trust, compassion, and justice. In this state, we can be encouraged to explore as well as celebrate our diversity, and search for the good in each other without the concern for personal pain and sacrifice. ... It provides us a chance to look at ourselves and others as part of the human family, part of one world.” The role of the individual peacemaker from this perspective would involve people who, “. . . work toward promoting a world in which nonviolent interaction and social equality are the norm. . . . Individuals of conscience should work to create a “trickle up” theory. . . .by starting at the grassroots level to encourage corporate leaders, political figures, and government officials to establish policies promoting peace and justice. This includes not only participating in government by voting, etc., but also standing against a government that does not operate in the best interest of global harmony.” (Trostle, 1992) A peacemaking government would require “a system of nonmilitary national service (to). . . include the Peace Corps and exchange student or “exchange citizen” programs. . .as well as the duty of largely developed nations to share technology and surpluses of any kind with those countries in need and less developed” (Trostle, 1992). Offering another broad positive view of peace is MacLeod (1992) who defines it as, an awareness that all humans should have the right to a full and satisfying life. For an individual this means developing his own and his loved ones’ potential growth, and for reaching out to his neighbors to help assure that they have the same chance. For communities, this means developing fair regulations for living together, and encouraging programs that will enhance fellowship among its many diverse elements. For nations, this means encouraging its citizens to strive for enhancement of a benign attitude toward all elements of their own society and toward all other nations. Towards an adequate definition It is difficult not to see in these “positive” approaches to the definition of “peace” radical implications for a reorganization of our society and, indeed, our entire world. There is no denying that a positive conception of peace along the lines suggested by Galtung, Sharp, Reardon, et al. would involve fundamental changes on the level of the individual psyche and the nation-state as well. At both levels genuine peace requires the advent of a new self-lessness, a willingness to see our fellow humans as our brothers and sisters, and--as the traditional religions have always counciled-- to love them as we love ourselves. But besides this Stefan Bauschard Offensive PKOs release 180 subjective component of each individual’s altruistic love, there must be justice which depends on the right sort of social organization. This is Reardon’s point. It is also implied by Trostle’s “state of well-being ... of global harmony ... part of one world.” The suggestion here is that, at the very least, a state of (genuine) peace is something beyond what can be achieved by the traditional system of sovereign nation-states. The problem, of course, is that this system lacks a system of workable law, each state being the ultimate arbiter of whether it will wield force in its pursuit of national interest or not. Without workable world law it’s hard to see how there can be justice, and so, peace, in its true sense. The world federalists have expressed this point succinctly but powerfully: “There can be no world peace without international justice; no international justice without world law; and no effective world law without institutions to make, interpret and enforce it.”3 And the world federalists may be right when they make this requirement of enforceable world law a sine qua non for the abolition of the age-old institution of war itself. Certainly Albert Einstein thought so when he declared that “Peace is not merely the absence of war but the presence of justice, of law, of order--in short, of government” (Einstein, 1968). In conclusion, we believe that a proper definition of “peace” must include positive characteristics over and above the mere absence of belligerence. Rather, it must include those positive factors that foster cooperation among human groups with ostensibly different cultural patterns so that social justice can be done and human potential can freely develop within democratic political structures. And this--promoting social justice/freedom by democratic means--will almost certainly require more “selfless” concern at all levels: at the personal level, more brotherly love; and at the international level, less narrow national self-interest-- a goal which we believe will require a diminution of the current system of nation states and the gradual emergence of a world community self-governed by world law. In this way, a truly peaceful world will be a world where war has been made impossible--or, at least much less likely--by a new community where people not only see themselves in their hearts as part of one human “family,” but where, in (political-legal-moral) reality, they really are part of such a “family.” Lessons for peace education Finally, what do these insights about the definition of “peace” mean for peace makers, and peace educators generally, in the 21st Century? We think they mean first that peace makers must stress that the long range goal of peace education should be the elimination of war as a method of resolving disputes. Reardon (1988) anticipated this when she said that “peace education must confront the need to abolish the institution of war” (p.24). To date there has not been a widespread perceived need to do so. Establishing the need is a challenge that lies ahead. But, secondly and at least equally important, our reflections about the nature of peace also suggests that the abolition of war will require more than the mere cessation of hostilities among peoples--not that that would be bad if we could get it. The problem is, as we saw earlier, that we probably can’t get it without a radical reconstruction of interpersonal and international relations along the lines suggested by our earlier examination. And paramount among these relations are the ideas of social justice and world law. The importance of these ideas in successfully pursuing the quest of abolishing war is, we think, an equally important implication for the future of peace education. Of course, the quest for peace and the abolition of war will be a long one requiring us to dig deeper into the very depths of the human and institutional psyches which lead “civilized” peoples to resort to force and, hopefully, to find and build the elusive “peace”. This quest requires that we teach for peace and not just about peace. Stefan Bauschard Offensive PKOs release 181 Positive Peace Good – Solves Militarism Pursuit of positive peace minimizes “structural violence”, an inherent condition of injustice that is a major contributor to oppression and war Barash 00 (David P., Professor of Psychology, University of Washington, “Approaches to Peace: A Reader in Peace Studies”, 2000, http://www.questia.com/read/111756263?title=Approaches%20to%20Peace%3a%20%20A%20 Reader%20in%20Peace%20Studies, AD: 7/9/9) The pursuit of positive peace nonetheless leads to certain agreed principles, one of which is a minimization of violence, not only the overt violence of war, but also what has been called “structural violence,” a condition that is typically built into many social and cultural institutions. A slave-holding society may be at “peace” in that it is not literally at war, but it is also rife with structural violence. Structural violence has the effects of denying people important rights such as economic opportunity, social and political equality, a sense of fulfillment and self-worth, and access to a healthy natural environment. When people starve to death, or even go hungry, a kind of violence is taking place. Similarly, when human beings suffer from diseases that are preventable, when they are denied a decent education, housing, an opportunity to play, to grow, to work, to raise a family, to express themselves freely, to organize peacefully, or to participate in their own governance, a kind of violence is occurring, even if bullets or clubs are not being used. Society visits violence on human rights and dignity when it forcibly stunts the optimum development of each human being, whether because of race, religion, sex, sexual preference, age, ideology, and so on. In short, structural violence is another way of identifying oppression, and positive peace would be a situation in which structural violence and oppression are minimized. In addition, social injustice is important not only in its contribution to structural violence, but also as a major contributor to war, often in unexpected ways. For many citizens of the United States and Europe, as well as privileged people worldwide, current lifestyles are fundamentally acceptable. Hence, peace for them has come to mean the continuation of things as they are, with the additional hope that overt violence will be prevented. For others – perhaps the majority of our planet – change of one sort or another is desired. And for a small minority, peace is something to fight for! A Central American peasant was quoted in the New York Times as saying “I am for peace, but not peace with hunger.” There is a long tradition suggesting that injustice is a primary cause of war. The French philosopher Denis Diderot, for example, was convinced that a world of justice and plenty would mean a world free of tyranny and war. Hence, in his 18 thcentury treatise, the Encyclopedia, Diderot sought to establish peace by disseminating all the world’s technical information, from bee-keeping to iron forging. And, of course, similar efforts continue today, although few advocates of economic and social development claim that the problem of violence can be solved simply by spreading knowledge or even by keeping everyone’s belly full. Stefan Bauschard Offensive PKOs release Con – Imperialism Bad 182 Stefan Bauschard Offensive PKOs release 183 Racism Imperialism is grounded in racism and strips countries of their culture Narobi ‘86.[James, Professor of NHU, “Decolonising the Mind: The Politics of Language in African Literature”. July 6th, 2013 London:Heinemann Kenya, New Hampshire http://www.swaraj.org/ngugi.htm ] For these patriotic defenders of the fighting cultures of African people, imperialism is not a slogan. It is real; it is palpable in content and form and in its methods and effects. Imperialism is the rule of consolidated finance capital and since 1884 this monopolistic parasitic capital has affected and continues to affect the lives even of the peasants in the remotest corners of our countries. If you are in doubt, just count how many African countries have now been mortgaged to IMF — the new International Ministry of Finance as Julius Nyerere once called it. Who pays for the mortgage? Every single producer of real wealth (use-value) in the country so mortgaged, which means every single worker and peasant. Imperialism is total: it has economic, political, military, cultural and psychological consequences for the people of the world today. It could even lead to holocaust. The freedom for western finance capital and for the vast transnational monopolies under its umbrella to continue stealing from the countries and people of Latin America, Africa, Asia and Polynesia is today protected by conventional and nuclear weapons. Imperialism, led by the USA, presents the struggling peoples of the earth and all those calling for peace, democracy .and socialism with the ultimatum: accept theft or death. The oppressed and the exploited of the earth maintain their defiance: liberty from theft. But the biggest weapon wielded and actually daily unleashed by imperialism against that collective defiance is the cultural bomb. The effect of a cultural bomb is to annihilate a people’s belief in their names, in their languages, in their environment, in their heritage of struggle, in their unity, in their capacities and ultimately in themselves. It makes them see their past as one wasteland of non-achievement and it makes them want to distance themselves from that wasteland. It makes them want to identify with that which is furthest removed from themselves; for instance, with other peoples’ languages rather than their own. It makes them identify with that which is decadent and reactionary, all those forces which would stop their own springs of life. It even plants serious doubts about the moral rightness of struggle. Possibilities of triumph or victory are seen as remote, ridiculous dreams. The intended results are despair, despondency and a collective death-wish. Amidst this wasteland which it has created, imperialism presents itself as the cure and demands that the dependant sing hymns of praise with the constant refrain: ‘Theft is holy’. Indeed, this refrain sums up the new creed of the neo-colonial bourgeoisie in many ‘independent’ African states. The classes fighting against imperialism even in its neo-colonial stage and form, have to confront this threat with the higher and more creative culture of resolute struggle. These classes have to wield even more firmly the weapons of the struggle contained in their cultures. They have to speak the united language of struggle contained in each of their languages. They must discover their various tongues to sing the song: ‘A people united can never be defeated’Colonialism dehumanizes individuals of all races Hardt and Negri 2k [Michael and Antonio, Political Philosopher and Literary Theorist at Duke University, Political Philosopher, “Empire”, page 129] The work of numerous authors, such as Jean-Paul Sartre and Franz Fanon, who have recognized that colonial representations and colonial sovereignty are dialectical in form has proven useful in several respects. First of all, the dialectical construction demonstrates that there is nothing essential about the identities in struggle. The Stefan Bauschard Offensive PKOs release 184 White and the Black, the European and the Oriental, the colonizer and the colonized are all representations that function only in relation to each other and (despite appearances) have noreal necessary basis in nature, biology, or rationality. Colonialism is an abstract machine that produces alterity and identity. And yet in the colonial situation these differences and identities are made to function as if they were absolute, essential, and natural. The first result of the dialectical reading is thus the denaturalization of racial and cultural difference. This does not mean that once recognized as artificial constructions, colonial identities evaporate into thin air; they are real illusions and continue to function as if they were essential. This recognition is not a politics in itself, but merely the sign that an anti colonial politics is possible. In the second the dialectical interpretation makes clear that colonialism and colonialist representations are grounded in a violent struggle that must be continually renewed. The European place, Selfneeds violence and needs to confront its Other to feel and maintain its power, to remake itself continually. The generalized state of war that continuously subtends colonial representations is not accidental or even unwanted—violence is the necessary foundation of colonialism itself. Third, posing colonialism as a negative dialectic of recognition makes clear the potential for subversion inherent in the situation. For a thinker like Fanon, the reference to Hegel suggests that the Master can only achieve a hollow form of recognition; it is the Slave, through life-and-death struggle, who has the potential to move forward toward full consciousness. The dialectic ought to imply movement, but this dialectic of European sovereign identity has fallen back into stasis. The failed dialectic suggests the possibility of a proper dialectic that through negativity will move history forward. Stefan Bauschard Offensive PKOs release 185 Ethics Imperialism destroys ethics by valuing security risks over collateral damage McNally 6 (David, Professor of political science at York University “The new imperialists – Ideologies of Empire” Ch 5 Pg 92) JL Yet, even on Ignatieff ’s narrow definition, in which human rights are about stopping unmerited cruelty and suffering, the crucial question is how we are to do so. What if some means to this ostensible end – say, a military invasion – can reasonably be expected to produce tens of thousands of civilian casualties and an almost certain breakdown in social order? Ignatieff ’s doctrine of human rights provides absolutely no ethico-philosophical criteria in that regard. Instead, he offers a pragmatic judgement – and a highly dubious one – that only U.S. military power can be expected to advance human rights in the zones where “barbarians” rule. But note: this is an utterly ad hoc addition to his theory. In no respect can it be said to flow from any of his reflections on human rights per se. Moreover, others proceeding from the same principle of limiting cruelty and suffering have arrived at entirely opposite conclusions with respect to imperial war. Ignatieff ’s myriad proclamations for human rights thus lack any demonstrable tie to his support of empire and imperial war. This is convenient, of course, since the chasm between moralizing rhetoric and imperial advocacy allows Ignatieff to pump out empty platitudes as if these contained real ethical guidance. Concrete moral choices, involving historical study and calibrations of real human risk, never enter the equation. So, Ignatieff can drone on about the world being a better place without Saddam, never so much as acknowledging the cost of this result: some 25,000 Iraqis killed as a result of armed conflict since the start of the U.S. invasion, and probably more than 100,000 dead as a result of all the consequences of the U.S. war.24 Nowhere does he offer any kind of calculus for determining if these tens of thousands of deaths are ethically justified. Instead, banalities about being rid of Saddam are offered up without even countenancing the scale of human suffering that Ignatieff ’s preferred course of action – war and occupation – has entailed. But then, Ignatieff shows little regard for ordinary people in the zones of military conflict. His concern is for the security of the West and of the U.S.A. in particular. Ruminating about America’s new “vulnerability” in the world, for instance, he writes, When American naval planners looked south from the Suez Canal, they had only bad options. All the potential refuelling stops – Sudan, Somalia, Djibouti, Eritrea and Yemen – are dangerous places for American warships. As the attack on the U.S.S. Cole made clear, none of the governments in these strategically vital refuelling stops can actually guarantee the safety of their imperial visitors.25 Stefan Bauschard Offensive PKOs release 186 Indigenous Rights Stefan Bauschard Offensive PKOs release 187 Imperialism deteriorates the culture of indigenous people Galeota 2004 [Julia, The Humanist, Article “Cultural Imperialism: An American Tradition” http://www.thehumanist.org/humanist/articles/essay3mayjune04.pdf] In his 1976 work Communication and Cultural Domination, Herbert Chiller defines cultural imperialism as: the sum of the processes by which a society is brought into the modern world system, and how its dominating stratum is attracted, pressured, forced, and sometimes bribed into shaping social institutions to correspond to, or even to promote, the values and structures of the dominant center of the system. Thus, cultural imperialism involves much more than simple consumer goods; it involves the dissemination of ostensibly American principles, such as freedom and democracy. Though this process might sound appealing on the surface, it masks a frightening truth: many cultures around the world are gradually disappearing due to the overwhelming influence of corporate and cultural America. The motivations behind American cultural imperialism parallel the justifications for U.S. imperialism throughout history: the desire for access to foreign markets and the belief in the superiority of American culture. Though the United States does boast the world’s largest, most powerful economy, no business is completely satisfied with controlling only the American market; American corporations want to control the other 95 percent of the world’s consumers as well. However, one must question whether this projected society is truly beneficial for all involved. Is it worth sacrificing countless indigenous cultures for the unlikely promise of a world without conflict? Around the world, the answer is an overwhelming “No!” Disregarding the fact that a world of homogenized culture would not necessarily guarantee a world without conflict, the complex fabric of diverse cultures around the world is a fundamental and indispensable basis of humanity. Throughout the course of human existence, millions have died to preserve their indigenous culture. It is a fundamental right of humanity to be allowed to preserve the mental, physical, intellectual, and creative aspects of one’s society. A single “global culture” would be nothing more than a shallow, artificial “culture” of materialism reliant on technology. Thankfully, it would be nearly impossible to create one bland culture in a world of over six billion people. And nor should we want to. Contrary to Rothkopf ’s (and George W. Bush’s) belief that, “Good and evil, better and worse coexist in this world,” there are no such absolutes in this world. The United States should not be able to relentlessly force other nations to accept its definition of what is “good” and “just” or even “modern.” Fortunately, many victims of American cultural imperialism aren’t blind to the subversion of their cultures. Stefan Bauschard Offensive PKOs release 188 Terrorism Imperialism encourages fundamentalism which leads to terrorist organizations. Gagnon 12 [Jean, Honorary Research Fellow, Centre for Greater China Studies, “Journal of South Asian Development”, “The Taliban Did Not Create the Taliban, Imperialism Did”, vol. 7 no. 1] Sir Karl Popper’s (2002) method of historicism has been neglected in the analysis of the radicalization of Afghanistan’s society in the form of the Taliban. Popper’s historicism is the idea that the past may allow the forecasting of the future by understanding the state of the present in by analyzing periods of imperialism—those eras of social injustice, violence and oppression—it is seen that such imperialism led to radical fundamentalism, as many had no choice but to lash out. The push to strenuous religious identity, heavily laden with violent tactics, was the natural response of peoples trying to maintain their identities and collective destiny from imperial domination. Furthermore, as evidence continues to show, most often those individuals that are first to radicalize are the poorest of the poor, the dispossessed, or those who have experienced violent injustices. Using Popper’s method, it is possible to explain how imperialism breeds radicalism (using Afghanistan as an example) and as such provide some general one specific line of historical inquiry. It is argued herein that recommendations to swing the pendulum in reverse so as to minimize radical behavior. This article has implications for international relations, foreign policies and aid. Nuclear technology is easily accessible to terrorist groups, enabling them to inflict maximum damage. O'Neill 97 from the Institute for Science and International Security [Kevn, Editor at the Institute for Science and International Security, “The Nuclear Terrorist Threat” http://www.isisonline.org/publications/terrorism/threat.pdf] The proliferation of nuclear weapons or radiological dispersal devices to terrorist groups is perhaps one of the most frightening threats to U.S. security. Nuclear materials, technologies and know-how are more widely available today than ever before. Small quantities of both fissile materials and highly radioactive materials, sufficient to manufacture a radiological dispersal device, are actively traded on the black market. A nuclear detonation by a terrorist group would likely result in an unprecedented number of casualties. In contrast, a radiological dispersal attack would probably be less violent, but could significantly contaminate an urban center, causing economic and social disruption. Both types of attacks would have significant psychological impacts on the entire population.