Summer School on Law and Logic European University Institute & Harvard Law School 14-25 July, 2014 Florence, Italy Scott Brewer Session 8.1.2 (post 07-24-14) Legal-Theoretic approaches to the logic of legal interpretationJurisprudential issue: structural vs. practical enthymemicity (i) The theorist of informal (including legal) argument must reconstruct enthymematic arguments in order to explain, from a theoretical point of view, what logical form they have in general -- deductive, inductive, analogical, or abductive. That is, what is not perspicuous in the manner of presentation of an informal argument, and what therefore calls for theoretical explication, is its logical type (inductive, deductive, etc.). We may call this type of nonperspicuity 'structural enthymemicity'. (ii) The practical legal interpreter (the judge, the lawyer, etc.) must also engage in interpretive reconstruction of legal arguments, but from a point of view different from that of the theorist, and with different aims and criteria of success. The practical legal interpreter reconstructs judicial enthymemes in order to be guided in various ways (for example, to conform conduct to rules that may emerge from those arguments, or to apply rules to instant cases) by enthymematic legal arguments in particular circumstances. From the point of view of this practical interpreter, what is nonperspicuous in an argument (say, a precedential judicial opinion) is the guidance it provides in the case sub judice. Which type of enthymemicity seems to be addressed by Holmes in The Path of the Law, and by Dewey in Logical Method and the Law? 2 Structural is the central theme. Dewey, as we shall see, seems to believe that no legal argument, no "practical argument," is ever deductive. Defeasibility (factual defeasibility – contrast legal rule defeasibility) Exercise. Consider this argument: (P1) Jones confessed to shooting Smith (P2) Each of five witnesses testified that he or she saw Jones shoot Smith (P3) Jones' fingerprints were found on the gun recovered at the scene of Smith's shooting. Therefore, (C) Jones shot Smith (1) If P1, P2, and P3 were all true, how strong would they be as "evidence" for the Conclusion C (2) Now suppose that the whole set of P1 through P7 are true (including, that is, P1, P2, and P3). In that case, with the larger set of propositions as a background, how strong would P1, P2, and P3 be as "evidence" for C, under the conception of "evidence" reflected in the FRE? P4 Jones was beaten by the police and ordered to confess. P5 Each of the five witnesses was bribed by the prosecutor to testify that he she saw Jones shoot Smith. P6 Fingerprint evidence is reliable only 40% of the time. P7 The technicians in laboratory to which the gun was sent for fingerprint analysis were both incompetent and corrupt. 3 Defeasible argument: Less formal definition: An argument from premises to a conclusion is defeasible if and only if the argument is one in which it is possible that the addition of some premises to the argument's original premises can undermine the degree of evidential warrant that the original premises provide for the conclusion. More formal definition: An argument from premises P1-Pn to conclusion C is defeasible if and only if the argument is one in which it is possible that the addition of some premise(s), Pn+1, to P1-Pn, can undermine the degree of evidential warrant premises that P1-Pn provide for C. Queries: (i) Is it possible that a deductively valid inference is defeasible -i.e., is it possible to add any premise to a deductively valid inference that undermines the force of the evidential warrant the original premises provide for the conclusion? (ii) In the example of Jones and Smith offered above, is the argument from P1, P2, and P3 as premises to the conclusion h defeasible or indefeasible? One question has been central to both general jurisprudence and the jurisprudence of logical form: Whether and to what extent legal arguments, especially the legal arguments offered by judges, can be adequately represented as valid deductive inferences. Can some such arguments be thus represented? Many? A large percentage? None? Legal Realists like Holmes and John Dewey, as well as other major jurisprudential thinkers like H.L.A. Hart, Ronald Dworkin, and judge-theorists like Antonin Scalia, believe, and some of them explicitly argue, that something important is at stake in providing a philosophical explanation of legal argument that correctly answers this question. Why might they think this question important, and why might we? For the philosophers in this group (though this may motivate others less), one answer is just that, as a matter of increasing the 4 stock of philosophical knowledge, it is valuable to be able to understand and explain the structure of a type of reasoning, legal and more specifically, judicial, that seems (at least, seems "pretheoretically") to be a central component of legal decision-making. In this way answering the question derives some of its value from the value human communities have placed on the practices and institutions of law for thousands of years. That value, the millennial value of understanding legal practices and institutions, is reflected in the robustness of the debate about how best to explicate the concept of "law." Another answer, closely related to the first, links two values that are and have been widely held, indeed are and have been almost pervasive in many human cultures for thousands of years. One value is the value to a society of institutions and practices of law, the other is the value to a society of institutions and practices of reason and the faculty of reasoning. These values become linked synergistically: we want to know whether and to what extent the institutions and practices of law that seem so important to society are capable of being guided by reason and, for given legal systems, whether and to what extent they are in fact guided by reason. Now, the concept of "reason" itself is obviously highly abstract and has been the subject of never ending attention and speculation probably since humans acquired self-reflective cognitive powers. It certainly has been a core philosophical interest for several thousand years. And while it's long been clear there are many types of reason and many types of reasoning, one type has been regarded by many philosophers and others in the broader culture as prima inter pares: deductive reason and deductive reasoning. Perhaps the first time that philosophers and others saw the power of deductive reason literally graphically illustrated was with the publication of Euclid's Elements in ancient Greece. Geometric reasoning, and its axiomatic deductive method, came to be a dominant metonym for "reason" itself, or anyway reason at its 5 best. Since that time a great many disciplines, including empirical science, social science, philosophy, and law,1 have sought to harness the power of deductive systems to advance their projects of explanation and social coordination. So while it may seem to be a relatively technical and narrow concern, what a great many theorists -- including Legal Realists, Legal Positivists, and Natural Lawyers -- all regard the question (1) as of vital theoretical and practical importance. For reasons (!) just noted, question (1) has in turn been associated with another What did the legal realists deny?: Conceptualist vs. Legal Realist claims about deduction in legal argument John Maxcy Zane was a "conceptualist" legal theorist, as that term is defined by Hart.2 Zane seemed to believe that legal arguments could be accurately represented as an a priori deductive system. Zane's conceptualism is revealed in his succinct (if somewhat unclearly phrased) declaration that [I]t must be perfectly apparent to anyone who is willing to admit the rules governing rational mental action that unless the rule of the major premise exists as antecedent to the ascertainment of the fact or facts put into the minor premise, there is no judicial act in stating the judgment. (Zane, German Legal Philosophy, 16 Mich. L. Rev. 287 (1918) (emphasis added)) 1 See for example the very illuminating discussion in Hoeflich, Law and Geometry: Legal Science from Leibniz to Langdell 30 Am. J. Legal Hist. 95 (1986). 2 Hart's definition in The Concept of Law, Chapter VII, is: Different legal systems, or the same system at different times, may either ignore or acknowledge more or less explicitly . . .[the] need for further exercise of choice in the application of general rules to particular cases. The vice known to legal theory as formalism or conceptualism consists in an attitude to verbally formulated rules which both seeks to disguise and to minimize the need for such choice, once the general rule has been laid down." (COL, 2nd ed. @ 129) 6 It seems that the likeliest interpretation of Zane's phrase 'no judicial act' is that a judge who offers a legal argument to resolve a case that is not a deductive argument hasn't even succeeded in making a (judicial) legal argument at all. The "Zany" conceptualist view, as we might call it, seems to be that: (i) Deductive form is a necessary condition of a "judicial act." Note that proposition (i) entails: (ii) No judicial-legal arguments are defeasible. By sharp contrast to a Zane-like view, many legal theorists, including many or most or even all Legal Realists, hold the view that many, perhaps most or even all, judicial legal arguments are defeasible. We can articulate two possible versions of the claim that judicial legal arguments are defeasible (the "defeasibility thesis"), which I'll call the "strong version" and the "moderate version." Defeasibility thesis (two versions) Strong version: (iii) No judge's legal argument can be accurately represented as a valid deductive inference note that (iii) entails (iv) All judicial-legal arguments are defeasible. Moderate version: (v) In every set of a judge's legal arguments that are offered to resolve a case, there is at least one very important argument that cannot be adequately represented as a valid deductive inference; note that (v) entails (vi) In every set of a judge's legal arguments that are offered to resolve a case, there is at least one very important argument that is defeasible. 7 Query: to which version of the defeasibility thesis is Holmes, or Dewey, committed? To which version does they seem committed when they both assert that "general propositions do not decide concrete cases"? What does it even mean to say that a general proposition does not "decide" a concrete case? (What would it mean to say that a general proposition does "decide" a concrete case?) Perhaps it means that general propositions, applied as major premises in a syllogism (as the general proposition 'All men are mortal' appears in the syllogism "All men are mortal; Socrates is a man; therefore, Socrates is mortal") are never decisive in a "concrete" cases?3 But even on that reading questions remain. Does Holmes mean that general propositions, applied as major premises in a syllogism, play no role at all in deciding "concrete" cases (this would be what I called the strong version of the defeasibility thesis), or play no significant role in deciding concrete cases, even though they may play an incidental role (this would be the moderate version of the defeasibility thesis)? Dewey who offers the most focused discussion of the type of logic that is needed to represent adequately judges' legal arguments. Neil MacCormick correctly notes that Dewey's article Logical Method and Law "is one of the great foundational texts of American legal realism." [Rhetoric and the Rule of Law 33.] In the discussion that follows, my principal concern is Dewey's view of legal argument and the role of valid deductive inference therein. 3 Holmes seems to suggest something like this in this famous passage in The Path of the Law: "You can give any conclusion a logical form, " but "[b]ehind the logical form lies a judgment as to the relative worth and importance of competing legislative grounds, often an inarticulate and unconscious judgment, it is true, and yet the very root and nerve of the whole proceeding." 8 But like other Legal Realists, Dewey is unclear in which version of the defeasibility thesis he endorses.4 Nevertheless, for reasons I'll offer below, I believe he may fairly and accurately interpreted to endorse the strong version of that thesis, labeled (iiia) above. So now, from a logical point of view, the issue is joined between the conceptualist and the (Deweyan) Legal Realist about as starkly as possible. While the Deweyan Legal Realist endorses: Holmes-Dewey Legal Realist (???): (iv) All judicial-legal arguments are defeasible "Zany" conceptualist: (ii) No judicial-legal arguments are defeasible. We could not have a (logically) stronger opposition between a Zaney conceptualist view and a strong Legal Realist view like the view Dewey appears to hold. Encountering such a stark clash of claims about the nature of judicial legal arguments engenders for us this question: What kind of philosophical argument can we make to "adjudicate" such extremely opposed views? Both Hart and the "deductive punctuated equilibrium" model of legal argument provide such arguments, as does Dewey in Logical Method and Law. I now turn to consider Dewey's argument in detail. After doing so, and after having argued that there are very significant problems with his explanation of legal argument, I'll present two closely related competing views of legal argument that attempt to avoid the kind of mistake Dewey makes. 4 Neil MacCormkick notes this unclarity in Dewey's thesis and tentatively attributes to Dewey the weak thesis (iva), but to Legal Realism, for which Dewey was such a powerful influence, the strong thesis (ii): I follow [Dewey] in thinking the certainty we can have in law is, at best, qualified and defeasible certainty. Perhaps this was the very thing [Dewey] had in mind. Surely it was at leas part of what he had in mind. Anyway, it has become a dominant theme in American jurisprudence right through the twentieth century that logic and formalism had no place in law. [MacCormick, Rhetoric and the Rule of Law 33 (emphasis added)] 9 Holmesian anti-logic and the "fallacy of logical form" theses It is now a commonplace that Holmes’s declaration, "The life of the law has not been logic; it has been experience" is what Tom Grey has aptly called the "central slogan of legal modernism."5 Holmes first offered it in a review of Langdell's book on contracts,6 and repeated it prominently at the opening of The Common Law, where it serves as part of an extended admonition about the limitations of "logic" in the best explanation of common law doctrines: "The object of this book is to present a general view of the Common Law. To accomplish that task, other tools are needed besides logic. It is something to show that the consistency of a system requires a particular result, but it is not all. The life of the law has not been logic: it has been experience. The felt necessities of the time, the prevalent moral and political theories, intuitions of public policy, avowed or unconscious, even the prejudices which judges share with their fellow men, have had a good deal more to do than the syllogism in determining the rules by which men should be governed. The law embodies the story of a nation's development through many centuries, and it cannot be dealt with as if it contained only the axioms and corollaries of a book of mathematics."7 I shall refer to this basic thesis as Holmes’s "anti-logic." The anti-logic thesis is not a passing fancy on Holmes part. Rather, he maintained and repeated it (though not always in the 5 Thomas Grey, "Langdell's Orthodoxy," University of Pittsburgh Law Review 45 (1983): 1-3. 6 Oliver W. Holmes, Book Review, American Law Review 14 (1880): 233-234 (reviewing C.C. Langdell, Summary of the Law of Contracts (1880)). 7 Oliver W. Holmes, The Common Law, ed. Mark DeWolfe Howe (Boston: Little, Brown and Company, 1963), 5. Holmes iterates the assertion, with an application to contract law, about logic and experience: "The distinctions of the law are founded on experience, not on logic." Ibid., 244. Again, in slightly different terms, he repeats it, observing (optimistically) that "the law is administered by able and experienced men . . . who know too much to sacrifice good sense to a syllogism." Ibid., 32. 10 same words) for at least twenty-five years, from an 1880 review of Langdell's contracts book to his 1905 dissent in Lochner, in which he declared that "[g]eneral propositions do not decide concrete cases. The decision will depend on a judgment or intuition more subtle than any articulate major premise."8 The anti-logical thesis is of course, also a centerpiece of The Path of the Law (hereinafter Path).9 Holmes’s Anti-Logic Within the Larger Structure of Path of the Law: Path's Four Jurisprudential Theses Path's Four Main Jurisprudential Theses To understand the content of Holmes’s anti-logic thesis in Path, it will be helpful to locate it among the other major theses that make up the essay. Holmes was not a careful systematic jurisprudential thinker, although he certainly had many flashes of brilliant jurisprudential insight, both with regard to relatively narrow doctrinal issues and with regard to more abstract and traditional issues of the sort addressed by legal positivists and natural lawyers. Despite Holmes’s lack of systemic attentiveness, Path can profitably be read and examined for its insights into systemic jurisprudence. Path advances at least four major theses, all of which concern one overarching topic: the best explanation of legal institutions, doctrines, and reasoning. The four theses are: 8 Lochner v. New York, 198 U.S. 45, 76 (1905). That this is the same theme as "law is not logic but experience" is revealed by comparing it to Holmes’s second explicit reference to logic and experience in the chapter on void contracts in The Common Law. There, he asserts that the "distinctions of law are founded on experience, not on logic." Holmes, The Common Law, 244. 9 Oliver W. Holmes, "The Path of the Law," in Collected Legal Papers (New York: Harcourt, Brace and Howe, 1920), 167. 11 (1) Prediction Thesis. Law (at least, the law from the point of view of a lawyer) is a prediction of the decisions courts will make, backed by the use public force. (2) Separation Thesis. Legal norms (rules, doctrines, principles, etc.) are not identical with moral norms, and their conflation has caused much confusion in the study of actual legal systems. (3) Anti-Logic Thesis. The law of a living legal system, such as that in the U.S., cannot be adequately explained as an axiomatic deductive system, in large part because there is inevitably a significant role played by the "inarticulate" in a judge's discernment and application of the law. (Note that Holmes offers the (in)famous "bad man" as a heuristic device to illustrate and argue for theses 1, 2, and 3.) (4) Rational Reform Thesis. It is (a) possible and (b) normatively desirable to effect rational reform in the law – reform that is both properly attentive to and properly critical of history and tradition. "Anti-logic" Thesis and the "Fallacy of Logical Form" After advancing and illustrating the Separation Thesis, Holmes turns to the second of his two "principles for the proper understanding of law," a principle to which he refers as "the fallacy of logical form."10 According to Holmes, the "fallacy" is "the notion that the only force at work in the development of the law is logic." This argument is of central concern and I shall consider it in detail below. Five Senses of 'Logic' in Path There is much wisdom and insight in the four theses Holmes proffers, but along the Path there are also some crucial missteps. 10 Ibid., 184. 12 Among them, in my view, is Holmes’s analysis of the role of "logic"11 in legal reasoning, doctrine, and institutions. That analysis comes in his treatment of the second of what he refers to as two "first principles for the study of this body of dogma or systematized prediction which we call the law,"12 which he also calls "two pitfalls" that "lie perilously close to the narrow path of legal doctrine"13 and two "fallacies." The first "first principle" is the Separation Thesis (the associated "fallacy," apparently, is failure to recognize its truth). The second is the "fallacy of logical form" -- "the notion that the only force at work in the development of the law is logic."14 To assess the cogency of Holmes arguments about this "fallacy," we must first discern what exactly Holmes meant in speaking of "logic" and "logical form." This is no small task, since Holmes used the term 'logic' in the essay in several rather different senses without being defining and explaining which sense of the term he had in mind at different points.15 This lack of systemic care is important. The anti-logical 11 I follow the standard philosophical convention of using single quotation marks to mention words, and double quotation marks to quote a speaker's (or group of speakers') use of a term. (Thus, logic is the systematic study of rational inference patterns; 'logic' is a five letter word; a good deal of talk about "logic" in American legal academia is misguided.) 12 Holmes, "The Path of the Law," 169. 13 Ibid., 178. 14 Ibid., 180. The analysis of the "fallacy of logical form" takes up about five pages, about 14% of the total pages of the essay. Ibid., 180-84. This is roughly equal to the space Holmes devotes to the prediction thesis (pages 168-73) and to the separation thesis (pages 173-79). Of course discussions of these theses overlap substantially, so it is hard (and unnecessary) to fashion an accurate measurement of space Holmes devoted to each. I offer the rough calculation only because it is worth noting that Holmes devotes nearly 50% of the essay to arguing the possibility and desirability of rational reform and of sketching a program therefor. 15 Holmes was, in many ways, a master of language, as witness the terse and powerful aperus that have earned him that reputation. But on a broader scale his language is full of pitfalls. The meaning of the most central concepts in his writings, such as "philosophy," "principles," "logic," and "experience" would have to be clearly defined from within Holmes’s own argument before an attempt to explicate his ideas in a more coherent and consistent way could possibly succeed. 13 thesis has such a misleading but powerful impact on the thinking of generations of law students, lawyers, judges, and scholars about the ways in which it is both possible and normatively desirable to recognize and promote the life of articulate reason in legal decision making.16 Obviously Holmes did not explain his understanding of logic in legal decision making only in Path; rather, the discussion in Path reflects a view that Holmes repeatedly articulated, and it will be helpful occasionally to repair to passages in other works to help discern his various meanings of 'logic'. In Path, Holmes used the term 'logic' in at least five significantly different senses. What he said about "logic" is true of only some of the varied referents for that term. He thus slides quite close to a logical "fallacy" of his own (namely, equivocation). The five uses are these: (i) 'Logic' as one of a set of roughly synonymous terms, including 'sensible,' 'reasonable,' 'warranted,' 'advisable.’ For example, “this really was giving up the requirement of a trespass, and it would have been more logical, as well as truer to the present object of the law, to abandon the requirement altogether";17 "there are some cases in which a logical justification can be found for speaking of civil liabilities as imposing duties in an intelligible sense."18 (ii) "Logic" as syllogistic inference (or some other type of deductive inference). For example, "there is a concealed, half conscious battle on the question of legislative policy, and if any one thinks that it can be settled only deductively, or once and for all, I only can say that I think he is theoretically wrong."19 Mathias Reimann, "The Common Law and German Legal Science," in The Legacy of Oliver Wendell Holmes, ed. Robert Gordon, (Stanford: Stanford University Press, 1992), 146. 16 See the discussion below in Section Error! Reference source not found..Error! Reference source not found.. 17 Holmes, "The Path of the Law," 188. 18 Ibid., 175. 19 Ibid., 182-83. Although the interpretive evidence for it is slightly indirect, Holmes does use 'logic' in Path in sense (ii). At the start of page 180, Holmes introduces the concept of a "fallacy" in the "notion that the only force at work in the development of the law is logic." (Later, at page 184, he refers to this fallacy by the phrase "the fallacy of logical form.") Further down the page, in 14 (iii) "Logic" as a formal deductive system, with axioms, rules of inference, and theorems, as in geometry. For example, "the danger of which I speak is . . . the notion that a given [legal] system, ours for instance, can be worked out like mathematics from some general axioms of conduct."20 (iv) "Logic" as a rationally discernible pattern of cause and effect. For example, "The condition of our thinking about the universe is that it is capable of being thought about rationally, or, in other words, that every part of it is effect and cause in the same sense in which those parts are with which we are most familiar. So in the broadest sense it is true that the law is a logical development, like everything else."21 (v) "Logic" as a set of argument types, individually invariant but distinct from one another. For example, "The training of lawyers is a training in logic. The processes of analogy, discrimination, and deduction are those in which they are most at home. The language of judicial decision is the language of logic. And the logical method and form flatter that longing for certainty and for repose which is in every human mind."22 Query: which Sense of 'Logic' is an appropriate target for a claim of "fallacy" (the "Fallacy of Logical Form")? what is clearly an explication of the "fallacious" view of "logic," he refers to the mistaken view that a given [legal] system . . . can be worked out like mathematics from some general axioms of conduct. . . . So judicial dissent often is blamed, as if it meant simply that one side or the other were not doing their sums right, and, if they would take more trouble, agreement inevitably would come. Ibid., 180 (emphasis added). The salient feature in Holmes simile – legal reasoning is mistakenly thought to be "like mathematics" – is that mathematics (and "doing sums") is a deductive process. Thus, I take Holmes’s reference to deduction at the end of page 180 to be a exegesis of his use of 'logic' at the start of that page, and in that way he uses 'logic' in sense (i). Ibid. 20 Ibid. 21 Ibid. 22 Ibid., 181. 15 Senses (i) and (ii) – Unproblematic Use (i) is a common, non-technical use of 'logic' and plays no troublesome role in Holmes’s anti-logic. Nor does use (ii) present any real problem. Deduction is of course one type of "logical" inference (only one among several, as I shall discuss in greater detail below), and it would surely be a serious jurisprudential mistake to believe that "the only force at work in the development of law" is deductive logic. (Pace Holmes, it is difficult to find theorists who endorse this belief, and Langdell is pretty clearly not among them – again, more on this later.) What Holmes intends to label the "fallacy of logical form" is what he takes to be a particular jurisprudential view about deduction – namely, the view that an actual legal system can be formalized in a way that allows deductive inference of results in particular cases.23 Thus, Holmes’s real target is not deduction per se but some view – exactly what view we shall have to consider – about the role that deduction either does actually play in legal argument (a descriptive claim), or can possibly play in legal argument (a conceptual claim), or should play in legal argument (a conceptual and normative claim). The problems come with senses (iii) and (iv). Senses (iii) and (iv) – Very Problematic It might seem that the target of Holmes’s anti-logic is sense (iii) of 'logic' – more precisely, the view that actual legal systems are deductively axiomatizable. But here the assertions that comprise Holmes’s anti-logic become problematically unclear. Holmes concedes that the proposition "the only force at work in the development of the law is logic" is true "in the broadest sense" (broad along what metric, one wonders) for sense (iv) of 'logic'.24 This proposition is true, Holmes seems to believe, by virtue of the rather Kantian view that "the postulate on which we think about the universe is that there is a fixed quantitative relation between every phenomenon and its antecedents and consequents."25 As Holmes also seems to recognize, this 23 See text at note ***. See Holmes, "The Path of the Law," 180. 25 Ibid. We know that Holmes admired Kant, at least in part, for at the end of Path Kant is a central part of his epideictic tribute to the power of the intellect: "To an imagination of any scope the most far-reaching form of power is not money, it is the command of ideas. . . . Read the works of the great German 24 16 concession is a significant threat to the coherence of his antilogical and prediction theses. To see why, note that the prediction thesis relies, at least implicitly, on the idea that judicial behavior, like other motions and behaviors of the universe (whether products of the intentional mind or not – Holmes does not appear to distinguish the intentional from the purely physical), has a rationally discernible causal structure.26 The whole idea of "prophesying" the law seems to rely on the assumption that, in discerning the causal structure of judicial behavior, the lawyer or judge must examine examples of judicial behavior encountered in experience and recorded in case reports, generalize inductively, and predict, "prophesy," on the basis of deduction ('logic' in sense (ii)). Thus if 'logic' is used in sense (iv), Holmes’s own prediction thesis would be an instance of the "fallacy of logical form" unless he can distinguish this use from a different use of 'logic' by other theorists who, in Holmes’s view, really did commit the "fallacy." Does he distinguish his thesis successfully? I think not. He does tell us that the "danger of which I speak is not the admission that principles governing other phenomena also govern the law, but the notion that a given [legal] system, ours for instance, can be worked out like mathematics from some general axioms of conduct."27 That is, those who commit the fallacy of logical form, unlike Holmesian predictors, think that the law is or could be deductively axiomatized – sense (iii) of 'logic'. But this brings up a tricky issue for the anti-logic thesis. As many scholars have observed, Langdell was a chief target for Holmes’s anti-logic.28 It is also well remarked that jurists, and see how much more the world is governed to-day by Kant than by Bonaparte." Ibid., 201-02. Reimann argues that Kant, in the very influence he exercised over the "great German jurists," was at least the superficial target of Holmes anti-logical thesis in The Common Law. His real target, suggests Reimann, was Langdell, but Holmes the mere HLS lecturer could not, for political reasons, directly attack the dean of Harvard Law School, where Holmes might like a permanent job. Reimann also points out that Langdell's view of the role of logic in law was quite different from that of many of the "great German jurists," and that the views of at least one of them, von Savigny, were very consonant with Holmes’s own views, though Holmes never conceded the point. See Reimann, "German Legal Science," 146. 26 See text at note ***. 27 Holmes, "The Path of the Law," 180. 28 See Grey, "Holmes and Legal Pragmatism," 818. In correspondence with Pollock, Holmes said of Langdell's book on contracts: 17 Langdell, in the brief passages in which he discusses the matter (probably too brief to get a clear picture of his view), seemed to think of the system of legal concepts as one that was generated by means of inductive generalization from decided cases, rather than from some a priori axiomatic structure, and only later applied deductively.29 Langdell, like Holmes, saw a crucial role for logic in sense (iv) in the "legal scientist's" discernment of legal rules and principles. Langdell also saw a crucial role for the subsequent use of deductive inference (logic in sense (ii)), when the inductively discovered30 rules and principles were later applied to individual cases; surely Holmes’s prediction thesis sees an important role for deductive inference working on the rules and principles discovered from experience. In this way, Langdell's conception of the role of "logic" was much closer to Holmes’s than Holmes acknowledged. Despite these similarities, real differences of opinion about the role of logic in legal argument seemed to remain between Holmes and Langdell. Langdell was far more sanguine than Holmes about the possibility of organizing the inductivelygenerated rules and principles into a coherent conceptual order that could later be applied to individual cases apodictically. In the helpful terms Tom Grey brought to the analysis of "Langdell's orthodoxy," Langdell may have believed, along with other "legal scientists" of his day, that empirically (and inductively) generated A more misspent piece of marvelous ingenuity I never read, yet it is most suggestive and instructive. I have referred to Langdell several times in dealing with contracts because to my mind he represents the powers of darkness. He is all for logic and hates any reference to anything outside of it, and his explanations and reconciliations of the cases would have astonished the judges who decided them. But he is a noble old swell whose knowledge, ability and idealist devotion to his work I revere and love. Oliver W. Holmes to Frederick Pollock, Boston, 10 April 1881, HolmesPollock Letters: The Correspondence of Mr. Justice Holmes and Sir Frederick Pollock, 1874-1932, ed. Mark DeWolfe Howe (Cambridge: Belknap Press, 1961), 16-17. 29 See M. H. Hoeflich, "Law and Geometry: Legal Science from Leibniz to Langdell," American Journal of Legal History 30 (1986): 95. See Reimann, "German Legal Science," 108-110; Grey, "Langdell's Orthodoxy," 29-30; Anthony J. Sebok, "Misunderstanding Positivism," Michigan Law Review 93 (1995): 2054. 30 Actually, the inductions that both Holmes and Langdell contemplated relied on an initial abductive inference as well, as do all inductive inferences. 18 legal rules and principles could in fact be organized into a system that was "complete" (i.e., such as to provide one right answer to every case), "conceptually ordered" (i.e., consisting of lower level rules that could be derived from a smaller set of higher order principles that were themselves coherent), and "formal" (i.e., such as to provide apodictic certainty for individual legal decisions).31 Although Holmes himself aspired in much of his work to render areas of law into conceptually ordered systems, he was also quite skeptical of the ability of any "legal scientist," himself included, actually to organize legal rules and principles so as to allow for one right and certain resolution – such as deduction could in theory provide – of every case.32 For Holmes, blind, "inarticulate" and irrational forces were too powerfully present in legal decisionmaking for Langdell's conceptualistic goals to be realizable: [T]he logical method and form flatter that longing for certainty and for repose which is in every human mind. But certainty generally is an illusion, and repose is not the destiny of man. Behind the logical form lies a judgment as to the relative worth and importance of competing legislative grounds, often an inarticulate and unconscious judgment, it is true, and yet the very root and nerve of the whole proceeding.33 This is a real disagreement, but if it is this view that Holmes was targeting as the "fallacy of logical form," then the fit between the Langdellian ontology and epistemology of law (inductive discovery, conceptual ordering, deductive application) and the fallacy of logical form Holmes is tenuous at best. Again, in Holmes’s terms, the "fallacy" is "the notion that the only force at work in the development of law is logic."34 If 'logic' in this proposition is being used in either sense (ii) (deductive inference) or sense (iii) (a deductive system), then that proposition seems not to describe Langdell's view at all; as noted above, Langdell accorded a vital role to both inductive inference (close kin to 'logic' in Holmes’s sense (iv) – rationally discernible causal) and 31 32 33 34 See Grey, "Langdell's Orthodoxy," 6-11. See text at note ***. Holmes, "The Path of the Law," 181. Ibid., 180 (emphasis added). 19 to deductive inference ('logic' in sense (ii)), operating in a system conceptually ordered by the "legal scientist" ('logic' in sense (iii)). But Holmes conceded that in sense (iv) of 'logic', which Langdell thought a vital part of legal analysis, logic was a vital force in the development of law (indeed, he even suggested, "the only force," albeit only "in the broadest sense"35). In sum, though there was genuine disagreement between Holmes and Langdell about the role of deductive logic in legal reasoning, the disagreement was not nearly as great as Holmes made it out, in part because Holmes mischaracterized the complexity of Langdell's own views about the role of different modes of logical inference in legal argument. (I discuss those different modes in some detail in the next section.) **Sense (v) – Most Promising This brings me to a final point. Holmes seems unclear about what he himself understood to be within the scope of the kind of "logic" involved in the "fallacy of logical form." The "fallacy of logical form" seems to be the view that law can be organized into an axiomatic system in such a way as to allow for apodictic resolution of individual cases. But at a crucial point in the antilogic section of the paper, Holmes speaks as if it is neither solely deduction ('logic' in sense (ii)) nor solely a deductive system (logic in sense (iii)) that he has targeted, but rather something much more inclusive, namely, 'logic' in sense (v): [J]udicial dissent is often blamed, as if it meant simply that one side or the other were not doing their sums right, and, if they would take more trouble, agreement inevitably would come. This mode of thinking is entirely natural. The training of lawyers is a training in logic. The processes of analogy, discrimination, and deduction are those in which they are most at home. The language of judicial decision is mainly the language of logic. And the logical method and form flatter that longing for certainty and repose which is in every human mind.36 35 36 Ibid. Ibid., 181. 20 Now, it seems, the fallacious view about the possible role of "logic" in legal argument that Holmes is challenging embraces not only "deduction" but also "the processes of analogy and discrimination" – i.e., disanalogical argument! A critique of the role of "logic" in legal reasoning that is this inclusive is surely a far cry from the narrower and much more plausible view that law cannot be organized into an axiomatic system that is deductively applicable in every case. One has to be not just skeptical, but skeptical to an implausible extreme, to deny that logic in the broad sense of a patterned form of inference (including deduction and analogy) plays a vital role "in the development of law." And if the response on behalf of Holmes is that he is not critiquing the view that "logic" plays a vital role in the development of law, but is instead critiquing the literal belief that "the only force at work in the development of law is logic," well, we must ask who ever believed that logic, in any sense, was the only force at work in the development of law? If the proposition Holmes uses to describe the "fallacy of logical form"37 is taken literally, it seems no one, including the most "formalist" and deductivist of the legal scientists – German, British, or American – could have believed or endorsed that. The ball is in Holmes’s court: if he really means it literally, he must show us that he is not attacking a straw theory. Ironically, perhaps, it is this last of the five conceptions of logic that is the most promising for a deep and cogent explanation of the role of different modes of logical inference in legal argument. As so often, even when Holmes is misguided and somewhat confused, his suggestions are fertile. In Part II of this paper I take up that "suggestion" and explore the role, not just of "logic" in the narrow sense of deduction, but in the broad sense of patterned inference. Marking the different patterns of logical inference that can be used in legal argument, that are used in legal argument, and that should be used in legal argument comprises the work of an ongoing intellectual enterprise. I call that enterprise the jurisprudence of logical form. Dewey's defense of Holmes' general anti-deductivism The most challenging claim, and the most suggestive about his view of the role of defeasibility and deduction in judicial legal 37 I have quoted that proposition several times. See, for example, the text at note 14. 21 argument, comes in this following passage in the Dewey article, Logical Method and Law: Take the case of Socrates being tried before the Athenian citizens, and the thinking which had to be done to reach a decision. Certainly the issue was not whether Socrates was mortal; the point was whether this mortality would or should occur at a specified date and in a specified way. Now that is just what does not and cannot follow from a general principle or a major premise. Again to quote Justice Holmes, "General propositions do not decide concrete cases." No concrete proposition, that is to say one with material dated in time and placed in space, follows from any general statements or from any connection between them. [Logical Method and Law, p. 22.5 (emphasis added)] Does this assertion have direct implications for structural enthymemicity, practical enthymemicity, or both? (See definitions above.) The Scope of Dewey's claim Dewey's assertion raises at least two questions of interpretation. First, what is the scope of Dewey's claim? Does he intend to limit the scope of his claim to the domain of legal reasoning (including legal reasoning in 5th century Athens and in early 20th century America – or maybe including legal reasoning everywhere and everywhen?) but not extend the claim to reasoning in other domains, such as the domain of moral reasoning, instrumental ("prudential") reasoning, or reasoning in the empirical sciences? Second, what exactly is the meaning of the claim, or, more precisely, what does Dewey intend to be the referent of 'them' in his assertion that "No concrete proposition, that is to say one with material dated in time and placed in space, follows from any general statements or from any connection between them"? Does 'them' refer to any connection between general propositions, or does it refer to any connection between general and concrete propositions? Did Dewey intend his claim to be limited to legal reasoning? To legal and moral reasoning? To all types of practical reasoning? 22 It seems likely that Dewey does not intend to limit his claim to legal reasoning, nor even to the more general category of practical reasoning (practical reasoning is reasoning about what one ought to do -- this includes as "sub domains," as species within its genus, moral reasoning, legal reasoning, and instrumental-prudential reasoning See for example Dewey's characterization of "'practical' reasonings" as "reasonings leading up to decision as to what is to be done," Logical Method and Law, 10 Cornell L. Q. at 18.9 Also compare Joseph Raz' related distinction of "practical" and "theoretical" authorities, Raz, Authority, Law, and Morality, at 195.9). But the views Dewey advances in this article are striking in that he seems committed to absorbing all theoretical reasoning (reasoning about what one ought to believe) into the domain of practical reasoning. Some evidence for this comes in his assertion, quoted above, quoting Holmes and referring to Socrates. Dewey's reference to Socrates' execution surely is intended to evoke the syllogism so familiar (in Dewey's day too, one speculates) to students of traditional syllogistic logic: All men are mortal Socrates is a man Therefore, Socrates is mortal And his deliberate invocation of that non-legal deductive syllogism when explaining his claim about general and concrete propositions suggests that he believes that his thesis is not limited to legal argument. Additional evidence is found later in the article, where he explicitly considers the scope of his inquiry into “logical method,” and defines ‘logical theory’ as an account of the procedures followed in reaching decisions . . . in which subsequent experience shows that they were the best [procedures] which could have been 23 used under the conditions. [Logical Method and Law, 10 Cornell L. Q. at 17-18.] In like vein, he asserts: It will be said that [the foregoing] definition [of ‘logical theory’] . . . , in confining logical procedure to practical matters, fails to take even a glance at those cases in which true logical method is best exemplified: namely, scientific, especially mathematical, subjects.” [Logical Method and Law, 10 Cornell L. Q. at 18 (emphases added)] Note the dialectic here: Dewey He considers one possible challenge to this conception of "logic": Challenge: The scope of his analysis of "logic" is "logical method in legal reasoning and legal decision," and in those cases the legal reasoner is engaged in practical reasoning, the type of reasoning that confronts "the necessity of settling upon a course of action to be pursued." [Logical Method and Law, 10 Cornell L. Q. at 18.3] So perhaps not all "logic" is assimilable to practical reasoning, and Dewey is claiming to offer a philosophical explanation only of the species of practical logical reasoning and not of the genus of all logical reasoning, including theoretical reasoning? Dialectic: Dewey's reply: No. Having offered that suggestion, Dewey chooses not to rest his analysis of "logic" on that answer, which he characterizes as "partial" and "ad hoc." [Logical Method and Law, 10 Cornell L. Q. at 18.3.] Having acknowledged that others might regard his definition of logical theory as ill-suited to explain reasoning in "scientific and mathematical subjects," he still suggests that even the mathematician’s “logical procedures” can be assimilated to practical reasoning, since “every thinker, as an investigator, mathematician or 24 physicist as well as ‘practical man,’ think in order to determine his decisions and conduct—his conduct as a specialized agent working in a carefully delimited field.” [Logical Method and Law, 10 Cornell L. Q. at 18-19] After offering these preliminary remarks, Dewey considers what he clearly understood was then – and is still today – the far more dominant explication of the concept of logic , namely, "an affair of propositions which constitute . . . with a view to the utmost generality and consistency of propositions.” [Logical Method and Law, 10 Cornell L. Q. at 19]. But again, while acknowledging some utility for this conception of “logic,” he seems to suggest that logic so conceived is always only a means, not an end in itself, a “means of improving, facilitating, clarifying the inquiry that leads up to concrete decisions.” [Logical Method and Law, 10 Cornell L. Q. at 19]. Dewey also invokes the case of legal reasoning to advance an argument whose conclusion seems to be that logic is always “ultimately an empirical and concrete discipline” (Logical Method and Law, 10 Cornell L. Q. at 19), and that “logic must be . . . a logic relative to consequences rather than antecedents, a logic of prediction of possibilities rather than a deduction of certainties.” (Logical Method and Law, 10 Cornell L. Q. at 26). Later in his argument, he asserts the more general proposition that and “logic is really a theory about empirical phenomena, subject to growth and improvement like any other empirical discipline.” [Logical Method and Law, 10 Cornell L. Q. at 27 (emphasis added)]. In this striking claim Dewey seems aligned with the extreme empiricist view advanced, for example, by John Stuart Mill: [T]he foundation of all sciences, even deductive or demonstrative sciences, is Induction; . . . every step in the 25 ratiocinations even of geometry is an act of induction; . . .a train of reasoning is but bring many inductions to bear upon the same subject of inquiry, and drawing a case within one induction by means of another. [J. S. Mill, A System of Logic 147 (8th ed. 1959).38] Is this view of deductive logic -- assimilating it either to practical reasoning (as Dewey suggests at several points) or to empirical reasoning (as he suggests at other points) convincing? Here are some reasons to doubt his claim. Dewey seems to trade on the vagueness of the idea of the kind of "concrete decision" that is a mathematician or logician must make when attempting to offer a formal mathematical or logical proof. If Dewey means to include within the scope of “concrete decisions" Andrew Wiles’ “decision” to offer the proof he offered of Fermat’s last theorem, then maybe Dewey is right in some sense. But something seems off here, for that kind of “decision” does not seem to support Dewey's contention that “logic is ultimately an empirical and concrete discipline.” 38 Compare also the striking and intriguiging assertion by Chalres Sanders Peirce, one of America's greatest formal logicians, also, like Holmes and Felix Cohen, a theorist in the "pragmatist" tradition: It may seem strange that I should put forward three sentiments, namely, interest in an indefinite community, recognition of the possibility of this interest being made supreme, and hope in the unlimited continuance of intellectual activity, as indispensable requirements of logic. Yet, when we consider that logic depends on a mere struggle to escape doubt, which, as it terminates in action, must begin in emotion, and that, furthermore, the only cause of our planting ourselves on reason is that other methods of escaping doubt fail on account of the social impulse, why should we wonder to find social sentiment presupposed in reasoning? As for the other two sentiments which I find necessary, they are so only as supports and accessories of that. It interests me to notice that these three sentiments seem to be pretty much the same as that famous trio of Charity, Faith, and Hope, which in the estimation of St. Paul, are the finest and greatest of spiritual gifts. Neither Old nor New Testament is a textbook of the logic of science, but the latter is certainly the highest existing authority in regard to the dispositions of heart which a man ought to have. [Charles S. Peirce, Three Logical Sentiments [CP 2.655] 26 What Dewey’s (and Mill's) hyper-empiricism fails to account for is the distinction between an a priori and a posteriori discipline. Empirical support is need for empirical disciples but empirical support does not seem needed for a priori disciplines. Indeed it's hard to imagine what kind of empirical support one could get for such logical inference rules such as modus ponens and universal instantiation. However convincingly (or not) Dewey does seem to endorse the thesis that all "logical" reasoning, even reasoning in mathematics, is a species of practical reasoning and a species of empirical reasoning. This leads us to our next interpretive challenge in understanding Dewey's explanation of legal argument: when he says that "[n]o concrete proposition, that is to say one with material dated in time and placed in space, follows from any general statements or from any connection between them," what is the referent of 'them'? Does he intend "them" to refer to general and concrete propositions, or instead only to concrete propositions? Is Dewey's claim coherent? Immediate and fairly straightforward counter-example? Premise: Everything is identical to itself at all times and in all places. Conclusion: Socrates was identical to himself in Athens in 399 B.C. This argument has the logical form of what logicians refer to as the inference rule of “universal instantiation” (x) Fx Fa If so, is Dewey committed to denying that the conclusion of this argument follows deductively from its premise? It's hard to imagine a more general proposition than the proposition asserted in the premise of this argument. And the 27 conclusion also seems to be a paradigm instance of a "concrete proposition" in Dewey's sense. Rule skepticism and induction: Holmes, Dewey, Cohen The basic patterns of inductive inference: generalization and inductive specification inductive Recall that in an inductive argument, the truth of the premises cannot guarantee the truth of the conclusion, but when they are well chosen, their truth can warrant belief in the truth of the conclusion to some degree of probability. There are two main varieties of inductive inference: inductive generalization and inductive specification. Inductive generalization Inductive generalization involves generalizing from particular instances. The premises of this type of argument report features of the particulars, and its conclusion states a probabilistic generalization that is inferred from those particulars. In the notes below we'll use two examples to illustrate the form of inductive generalization. One is the Knapp judge's analysis of logical relevance in the case he was deciding, the other is a simplified example from empirical science (induction is one of the foundations of all empirical scientific reasoning). Where '1 . . . n' instances stands for a set of individual ' ' stands for one property that the individuals 1 . . . n have been noted to possess '' stands for another property the individuals 1 . . . n have been noted to possess, the pattern of inductive generalization is: 28 (1 ) 1 is both and (i.e., has both characteristics, and ) [e.g., Person A made a factual assertion and Person A spoke truly.] [e.g., Bird A was a raven and Bird A was black.] (2 ) 2 is both and [e.g., Person B made a factual assertion and Person B spoke truly.] [e.g., Bird B was a raven and Bird B was black.] (3 ) 3 is both and [e.g., Person C made a factual assertion and Person C spoke truly.] [e.g., Bird C was a raven and Bird C was black.] . . . (n) n is both and [e.g., Person N made a factual assertion and Person N spoke truly.] [e.g., Bird N was a raven and Bird N was black.] (n+1) There were [few or no] observed instances of an that was and also was not- [e.g., There were few persons who made a factual assertion and did not speak truly -Knapp: "even in the greatest liars, . . . where they lie once they speak truth 100 times."] 29 [e.g. No ravens were observed to be nonblack] h: [Probably] [All or Most] 's are [e.g., Knapp: Probably, most persons who make factual assertions are persons who speak truly.] [e.g. Probably, all ravens are black.] Note that inductive arguments are arguments about evidence and the hypotheses the evidence is said to support. Thus, the premises of an inductive argument are evidentiary propositions (the " " in our - h schema) and the conclusion is a hypothesis that the evidence is offered to support the "h" in our - h schema. Inductive specification The other type of inductive inference is inductive specification. Instead of reaching a conclusion about a class of individuals, an inductive specification offers a conclusion about one individual, based on a generalization about the classes to which that individual belongs. Again, we illustrate the form of this argument by reference to the two examples offered above: In the Knapp example, the inductive specification is the argument that a great many persons (Knapp endorses the claim that the ratio is 100 to 1!) who made factual assertions spoke truly, therefore, some individual person D who made a factual assertion (or perhaps the next individual person who will makes a factual assertion -- see the note in the following paragraph) is also likely to have spoken truly (or likely will speak truly). In the raven example, the inductive specification is the argument that a great many (actually, in this example, all) ravens were black, therefore, some individual raven was black (or perhaps the next observed individual raven will be black -- again, see the note in the following paragraph). 30 Note that inductive analogies are a basic form of argument for making predictions based on empirical evidence -- predictions, for example, about the next person we encounter who will make a factual assertion, or the next raven we will see. The abstract form of the argument is this: (1 through n ) 1 through n have all been both and (i.e., has both characteristics, and ). [e.g., Person A through Person N all made a factual assertion and spoke truly.] [e.g., Bird A through Bird N all were ravens and black.] (n+1) There were few observed instances of an that was and also was not- [e.g., There were few Persons who made a factual assertion and did not speak truly.] [e.g. No ravens were observed to be nonblack.] Therefore, h: Some individual n+1 probably has both and . Some Person (perhaps some person we encounter in the future) who makes a factual assertion probably spoke (or probably will speak) truly. Some Bird (perhaps some bird we encounter in the future) who is a raven probably is black. 31 Characteristic common to specification inductive generalization and inductive In order for to assess how convincing an inductive inference is, one must assess the premises or conclusion according to several criteria (cf. Steven Barker, Elements of Logic (5th ed. p. 187)): the number of observed instances the degree of shared characteristics among the identified characteristics the degree of unshared characteristics among the identified characteristics the logical strength of the conclusion ("all," "some," "probably," "very likely" etc.) the explanatory relations among the identified characteristics Note that probabilistic judgments ("probably," "almost certainly," "more likely than not," etc.) are always relative to some evidence. See Barker, op. cit. p. 184: "[P]robability when understood as rational credibility is a relative matter . . . . The very same conjecture takes on different degrees of probability relative to different amounts of evidence." Note also that there is (or should be) a close relation between our judgment regarding how probable we think a conclusion is relative to the evidence offered in the inductive argument and the logical strength of the conclusion (e.g., the conclusion "All individuals that have property have property " is logically stronger than the conclusion "Some individuals that have property have property "; in the examples above, the conclusion in raven induction was logically stronger than the conclusion in the Knapp induction). Although it may be counter-intuitive, note that the greater the logical strength of the conclusion of an inductive argument, the lower is the probability of that conclusion relative to the evidence stated in the argument's premises. (Logician Stephen Barker makes this point as follows: "The more sweeping the generalization that we seek to establish, the less is its probability relative to our evidence." (see Barker op. cit. p. 187)). Do you see why this is true? 32 Some uses of inductive inference in legal argument Using induction to find the law (the lawyer) -- Holmes' bad man "Take the fundamental question, What constitutes the law? You will find some text writers telling you that it is something different from what is decided by the courts of Massachusetts or England, that it is a system of reason, that it is a deduction from principles of ethics or admitted axioms or what not, which may or may not coincide with the decisions. But if we take the view of our friend the bad man we shall find that he does not care two straws for the axioms or deductions, but that he does want to know what the Massachusetts or English courts are likely to do in fact. I am much of his mind. The prophecies of what the courts will do in fact, and nothing more pretentious, are what I mean by the law." [The Path of the Law] Using induction to make the law (the lawyer, the judge, the legislator, the administrative agent, the constitutional adopter): Dewey on the practical, experiential, inductive nature of "logical" method -- in law and elsewhere "If we recur then to our introductory conception that logic is really a theory about empirical phenomena, subject to growth and improvement like any other empirical discipline, we recur to it with, an added conviction: namely, that the issue is not a purely speculative one, but implies consequences vastly significant for practice. I should indeed not hesitate to assert that the sanctification of ready-made antecedent universal principles as methods of thinking is the chief obstacle to the kind of thinking which is the indispensable prerequisite of steady, secure and intelligent social reforms in general and social advance by means of law in particular. If this be so infiltration into law of a more experimental and flexible logic is a social as well as an intellectual need." [Logical Method and the Law 26] "If we trust to an experimental logic, we find that general principles emerge as statements of generic 33 ways in which it has been found helpful to treat concrete cases. The real force of the proposition that all men are mortal is found in the expectancy tables of insurance companies, which with their accompanying rates show how it is prudent and socially useful to deal with human mortality. The 'universal' stated in the major premise is not outside of and antecedent to particular cases; neither is it a selection of something found in a variety of cases. It is an indication of a single way of treating cases for certain purposes or consequences in spite of their diversity." [Logical Method and the Law 22] Question for Dewey: Is that true of 'F = MA' as well? Using induction to find "legislative facts" – recall "Dewey's Dream": Brown v. Board of Education, 347 U.S. 483, 493-95 (1954) "We come then to the question presented: Does segregation of children in public schools solely on the basis of race, even though the physical facilities and other 'tangible' factors may be equal, deprive the children of the minority group of equal educational opportunities? We believe that it does. . . . To separate [Negro schoolchildren] from others of similar age and qualifications solely because of their race generates a feeling of inferiority as to their status in the community that may affect their hearts and minds in a way unlikely ever to be undone. The effect of this separation on their educational opportunities was well stated by a finding in the Kansas case by a court which nevertheless felt compelled to rule against the Negro plaintiffs: 'Segregation of white and colored children in public schools has a detrimental effect upon the colored children. The impact is greater when it has the sanction of the law; for the policy of separating the races is usually interpreted as denoting the inferiority of the negro group. A sense of inferiority affects the motivation of a child to learn. Segregation with the sanction of law, therefore, has a tendency to (retard) the educational and mental development of Negro children and to deprive them of some of the benefits they would receive in a racial(ly) integrated school system.' . . . . 34 Whatever may have been the extent of psychological knowledge at the time of Plessy v. Ferguson, this finding is amply supported by modern authority. [FN11] Any language in Plessy v. Ferguson contrary to this finding is rejected. FN11. K. B. Clark, Effect of Prejudice and Discrimination on Personality Development (Midcentury White House Conference on Children and Youth, 1950); Witmer and Kotinsky, Personality in the Making (1952), c. VI; Deutscher and Chein, The Psychological Effects of Enforced Segregation: ASurvey of Social Science Opinion, 26 J.Psychol. 259 (1948); Chein, What are the Psychological Effects of Segregation Under Conditions of Equal Facilities?, 3 Int. J. Opinion and Attitude Res. 229 (1949); Brameld, Educational Costs, in Discrimination and National Welfare (MacIver, ed.,1949), 44--48; Frazier, The Negro in the United States (1949), 674--681. And see generally Myrdal, An American Dilemma (1944). We conclude that in the field of public education the doctrine of 'separate but equal' has no place. Separate educational facilities are inherently unequal. Therefore, we hold that the plaintiffs and others similarly situated for whom the actions have been brought are, by reason of the segregation complained of, deprived of the equal protection of the laws guaranteed by the Fourteenth Amendment. This disposition makes unnecessary any discussion whether such segregation also violates the Due Process Clause of the Fourteenth Amendment. . . . . Is there no deductive reasoning in legal reasoning? Cohen's challenge in The Ethical Basis of Legal Criticism pages 216-219 (1931) But elementary logic teaches us that every legal decision and every finite set of decisions can be subsumed under an 35 infinite number of different general rules, just as an infinite number of different curves may be traced through any point or finite collection of points. Every decision is a choice between different rules which logically fit all past decisions but logically dictate conflicting results in the instant case. Logic provides the springboard but it does not guarantee the success of any particular dive. If the doctrine of stare decisis means anything, and one can hardly maintain the contrary despite the infelicitous formula tions which have been given to the doctrine, the consistency which it demands cannot be a logical consistency. The consistency in question is more akin to that quality of dough which is necessary for the fixing of a durable shape. Decisions are fluid particular decision. See WAMBAUGH, STUDY OF CASES (2d ed. 1894) c. 2; Salmond, T h e o r y o f J u d i c i a l P r e c e d e n t s (1900) 16 L. Q. REV. 376; GRAY, op. cit. supra note 11, at § 555; BLACK, JUDICIAL PRECEDENTS (1912) 40; MORGAN, op. cit. supra note 29, at 109-10; Goodhart, Determining the Ratio Decidendi of a Case (1930) 40 YALE L. J. 161. Logical objections to this conception are dismissed by Professor Morgan as "hypercritical" and 'too refined for practical purposes." But Professor Oliphant, who refuses to be deterred by such warnings (see his reply in M u t u a l i t y o f Ob l i g a tion in Bilateral Contracts at Law (1928) 28 COL. L. REV. 997 n. 2 to Professor Williston's charges of scholasticism, The Effect of One Void -Promise in a Bilateral Agreement (1925) 25 COL. L. REV. 857, 869) has suggested an alternative conception that is logically sound and practically far more useful. Rules of increasing generality, each of them linking the given result to the given facts, spread pyramid-wise from a decision. The possibility of alternative modes of anaylsis makes a decision the apex not of one but many such pyramids. No one of these rules has any logical priority; courts and lawyers choose among competing propositions on extra-logical grounds. Oliphant, A Return to Stare Decisis (1928) 6 AM. LAW SCHOOL REV. 215, 217-18; and cf. LLEWELLYN, BRAMBLE BUSH (1930) 61-66; Bingham, What is the Law? (1912) 11 MICH. L. REV. 1, 109, 111 n. 31. The picture clearly suggests that the decision bears to the rules the same relation that Professor Whitehead has traced between a point and the surfaces that would ordinarily be said to include the point. See THE PRINCIPLES OF NATURAL KNOWLEDGE (1919) c. 8; THE CONCEPT OF NATURE (1919) c. 4. 40 Loc. cit. supra, note 39. 36 1931] LEGAL CRITICISM 217 until they are given "morals." It is often important to conserve with new obeisance the morals which lawyers and laymen have read into past decisions and in reliance upon which they have acted. We do not deny that importance when we recognize that with equal logical justification lawyers and laymen might have attached other morals to the old cases had their habits of legal classification or their general social premises been different. But we do shift the focus of our vision from a stage where social and professional prejudices wear the terrible armor of Pure Reason to an arena where human hopes and expectations wrestle naked for supremacy. No doubt the doctrine of stare decisis and the argument for consistency have a significance which is not exhausted by the social usefulness of predictable law. Even in fields where past court decisions play a negligible role in molding expectations, courts may be justified in looking to former rulings for guidance. The time of judges is more limited than the boundaries of injustice. At some risk the results of past deliberation in a case similar to the case at bar must be accepted. But again we invite fatal confusion if we think of this similarity as a logical rather than an ethical relation. To the cold eyes of logic the difference between the names of the parties in the two decisions bulks as large as the difference between care and negligence. The question before the judge is, "Granted that there are differences between the cited precedent and the case at bar, and assuming that the decision in the earlier case was a desirable one, is it desirable to attach legal weight to any of the factual differences between the instant case and the earlier case?" Obviously this is an ethical question. Should a rich woman accused of larceny receive the same treatment as a poor woman? Should a rich man who has accidentally injured another come under the same obligations as a poor man? Should a group of persons, e. g., an unincorporated labor union, be privileged to make all statements that an individual may lawfully make? Neither the ringing hexameters of Barbara Celarent nor the logic machine of Jevons nor the true-false patterns of Wittgenstein will produce answers to these questions. What then shall we think of attempts to frame practical legal issues as conflicts between morality, common sense, history or sociology, and logic (logic playing regularly the Satanic role) ? One hesitates to convict the foremost jurists on the American bench of elementary logical error. It is more likely that they have simply used the word "logic" in peculiar ways, as to which they may find many precedents in the current logic textbooks.41 See M. R. Cohen, The Subject Matter of Formal Logic (1918) 15 JOUR. OF PHIL. 673. 4' 37 218 YALE LAW JOURNAL [Vol. 41 Bertrand Russell has warned us : "When it is said, for example, that the French are 'logical', what is meant is that, when they accept a premise, they also accept everything that a person totally devoid of logical subtlety would erroneously suppose to follow from that premise. . . . Logic was, formerly, the art of drawing inferences ; it has now become the art of abstaining from inferences, since it has appeared that the inferences we feel naturally inclined to make are hardly ever valid." 42 If we construe the word "logic" in the light of this warning, we may readily agree with Mr. Justice Holmes when he asserts that "the whole outline of the law is the resultant of a conflict at every point between logic [viz. hasty generalization] and good sense",43 and find some meaning in the statement of Judge. Cardozo that "the logic of one principle" prevails over the logic of another 44 or in his pride that "We in the United States have been readier to subordinate logic to utility." 13 42 RUSSELL, SKEPTICAL ESSAYS (1928) c. 7 (Behaviorism and Values) HOLMES, COLLECTED LEGAL PAPERS (1920) (Agency) 49, 50. CARDOZO, NATURE OF THE JUD ICIAL PROCESS, (1921) C. 1 (Introduction. 99. The Method of Philosophy) 41. Judge Cardozo illustrates (op. cit. 38-39) the method of logic or philosophy, which is distinguished from the methods of history or evolution, of custom or tradition, and of sociology, with the rule that one who contracts to purchase real property must pay for it even though, before the sale is actually completed, the property is substantially destroyed. This, he maintains, is the projection to its logical outcome of the principle that "equity treats that as done which ought to be done," a principle which does not apply to the sale of chattels which did not come under the jurisdiction of Chancery. But what sort of princip le is this? It is certainly not a logical principle, i.e., a proposition certifiable on logical grounds alone, since it is obviously false. If it were true no plaintiff in equity could ever obtain a judgment since he could never in the face of such a rule show that the defendant had not done what he ought to have done. Would it not be quite as logical for a court to say "equity does not treat that as done which has not been done"? If a rule is undesirable we do not make it less undesirable by deducing it from another rule too vague to be liked or disliked and then concentrating our attention on the process of inference rather than the premise. What is in question in the case proposed is not a logical probleim or a choice of judicial methods but a conflict of social interests, and there is much that may be said in favor of throwing upon the party who contemplates future enjoyment of a definite piece of real property the risk of its destruction and the necessity of insurance. But what may thus be said bears no peculiar imprimcitur of logic. See also CARDOZO, THE GROWTH OF THE LAW (1924) 79-80. 44 C AR D O Z O , T H E G R O W T H O F T H E LAW ( 1 9 2 4 ) 7 7 . This is said with regard to the tendency in recent decisions (of which Judge Cardozo's opinion in MacPherson v. Buick Mfg. Co., 217 N. Y. 382, 111 N. E. 1050 (1916) is a noteworthy landmark) to extend the scope of a manufacturer's obligations to the ultimate consumer with regard to the quality of the product. 4 ' 38 19311 LEGAL CRITICISM 219 We may have to interpret the word "logical" as synonymous with "aesthetically satisfying" in order to understand the statement of Mr. Justice Brandeis and Mr. Warren that a distinction between cases where "substantial mental suffering would be the natural and probable result" of an act and cases "where no mental suffering would ordinarily result" is not logical though very practical.46 Such an identification of the rules of logic with those of intellectual aesthetics seems to be assumed at times by Judge Cardozo as well.47 No verbal definition is intrinsically objectionable. But it seems fair to suggest that the use of the word "logic" in the senses exemplified in these typical passages seriously lowers the probability of clear thinking on the relation between law and ethics. Most of us think of logic as the most general and formal of the sciences.48 Upon that basis we may say, paraphrasing a remark of Mr. Justice Holmes, that conformity with logic is only a necessity and not a duty. The bad judge is no more able to violate the laws of logic than he is to violate the laws of gravitation. He may, of course, ignore both. It is not our purpose to deny that there would be less judicial stumbling were courts more constantly aware of the logical relations between particular and universal, between premise and conclusion, between form and content. IV The theory which denies ethical justiciability to law, in whole or in part, cannot be maintained. Its superficial plausibility Again the rejected "privity" analysis of the situation seems to be peculiarly "logical" because it permits the deduction of an undesirable rule from another undesirable rule which is too vague to arouse the resentment which the deduced rule arouses. See also ibid. 83, where "adherence to logical and advancement of utility" are balanced in terms of "the social interest which each is capable of promoting." ' , Warren and Brandeis , The Right of Privacy (1890) 4 HARV. L. REV. 193, reprinted in SELECTED ESSAYS IN THE LAW OF TORTS (1924) 122, 126. 4 "If I am seeking logical consistency, the symmetry of the legal struc ture, how far shall I seek it?" CARDOZO, NATURE OF THE JUDICIAL PROCESS 10, and cf. ibid. 33-34. "If it was so, it might be; and if it were so, it would be, but as it isn't, it ain't. That's logic." CARROLL, THROUGH THE LOOKING GLASS C. 4. And see WITTGENSTEIN, TRACTATUS LOGICO-PHILOSOPHICUS (1922)1 §§ 6.1, 6.1262; M. R. Cohen, op. cit. supra note 41; Hoernle, Review of SCIENCE OF LEGAL METHOD (1918) 31 HARV. L. REV. 807; Russell, PRINCIPLES OF MATHEMATICS, (1 9 0 3 ) c . 1 ; Ad ler, La w a n d t h e M o d e r n M i n d : A S y mp o s i u m (1 9 3 1 ) 31 CoL. L. REV. 99-101; Keyser, On the Study of Legal Science (1929) 38 YALE L. J. 413. 47 48 220 YALE LAW JOURNAL [Vol. 41 arises from the narrow connotation given to the terms ethics and morality when they are extruded from the field of legal criticism. The falsity of the theory arises from the fact that, along with the promptings of "conscience", the principal values of life are banished from the juristic consciousness and an inadequate "practical" ethics substituted. The invalidity of the inference by which this theory is established arises from the fallacy (guaternio terminorum) by which the extrusion from legal criticism of "ethics" in its broadest sense is inferred from a denial of its legal importance in its narrower connotation. Finally, the confusion of the theory lies in the indeterminate character of the system of values substituted by our jurists for what they call "ethics" and "morality." Law is just as much a part of the domain of morality as any other phase of human custom and conduct. It has no special purpose, end, or function, no restriction of moral scope, other than that variable restriction which its positive and practical nature may impose in the way of limitations of efficacy and applicability. We may, if we like, call the good which law can achieve "justice." But if "justice" means anything less than that total, it is not a valid basis of legal criticism. To say that something or other is beyond the "proper scope" of law is either to say that law on that subject will bring about more harm than good or it is to indulge in meaningless verbiage. The evaluation of law must be made in terms of the good life, and to demonstrate the nature of this standard is the task of ethics, and more particularly, of morality. Difficult as that task is and uncertain as its conclusions have been, it is a vicious illusion to suppose that the task of statesman or judge is less difficult, or that his conclusions can be more certain.