Moral Psychology Seminar

advertisement

Jean

Nicod

Lectures

2007

Moral Theory Meets Cognitive

Science

How the Cognitive Sciences Can

Transform Traditional Debates

Stephen Stich

Dept. of Philosophy

& Center for Cognitive Science

Rutgers University

1

Prologue

 In recent years a number of researchers have urged that we can use the methods of

cognitive science

to make

progress

in traditional debates in

moral theory

 In these Lectures, I propose to support this contention by offering

four case studies

illustrating how traditional debates can indeed be

advanced

– and often

transformed

– by

theories and findings in the cognitive sciences

2

Prologue

 One of the many ways in which this work differs from traditional work in moral theory is that it is

resolutely collaborative

 So before I begin let me acknowledge some of the

friends

and

colleagues

who have

contributed in important ways

to these

Lectures

3

Prologue

Dan Kelly John Doris Josh Greene Joshua Knobe

Edouard Machery

Chandra Sripada

Shaun Nichols Jesse Prinz 4

Jean

Nicod

Lectures

2007

Lecture 1

The Definition of Morality

5

Philosophical Background

 In the first sentence of an article called “What

Morality Is Not,” first published in 1957,

Alasdair MacIntyre wrote:

“The central task to which contemporary moral philosophers have addressed themselves is that of listing the distinctive characteristics of moral utterances .”

6

Philosophical Background

 In 1970, MacIntyre’s article was reprinted in an anthology called The Definition of Morality which also reprinted a dozen other papers by such leading figures as

 Elizabeth Anscombe

 Kurt Baier

 Philippa Foot

 William Frankena

 Peter Strawson all of which, in one way or another, tackled the question of how ‘morality’ is best defined

7

Philosophical Background

 As one might expect from this distinguished list of authors, many of the arguments to be found in this book are careful and sophisticated

 And as one might expect in just about any group of 13 philosophers,... no consensus was reached

8

Philosophical Background

 In addition to debate about how the notions of moral utterance , moral rule and moral norm are to be defined, many of the contributors to the volume also discuss a cluster of metaphilosophical questions :

What is a definition of morality supposed to do?

What counts as getting the definition right?

 And here again, there was no consensus reached

9

Philosophical Background

 In 1978 the debate was still going strong

 In that year the philosopher Paul Taylor published a long paper in Midwest Studies in

Philosophy

Taylor’s goal was to elaborate and defend an account of what it is for a norm to be a moral norm for a group of people

10

Philosophical Background

For our purposes, Taylor’s article is particularly useful because it includes a helpful taxonomy of various positions one might take on the metaphilosophical issue

What are philosophers trying to do , Taylor asks, when they offer a definition of ‘morality’ or ‘moral rule’?

Here are some of the options he distinguishes

11

Philosophical Background

1. Linguistic analysis:

Capture how the word ‘moral’ (or the phrase

‘moral rule’) is used by English speakers (or by some particular group of English speakers)

2. Conceptual analysis:

Make explicit the concept of morality held by

“(most?)” people in our society

12

Philosophical Background

3.

Specify the essence of morality

Those who pursue this project believe that moral rules or norms constitute a natural kind all of whose members share some essential property (or most of some cluster of properties)

The goal of the project is to discover what the essential properties are

Taylor insists that this is a fool’s project , since he believes that “morality has no essence”

13

Philosophical Background

 The Debate Continues

 Philosophical discussion of the definition of morality did not, of course, come to an end with Taylor’s paper

In 2005, Bernard Gert published a long, feisty article on “The Definition of Morality” in the

Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy

In his challenging & important book, The Evolution of Morality (2006), Richard Joyce rightly takes the project of defining “moral judgment” to be of central importance for anyone who wants to ask whether and how the capacity to make moral judgments evolved – and devotes a long chapter to developing a definition

14

Philosophical Background

 Enter Psychology

 While the philosophical debate was raging, a group of developmental psychologists who had read and been influenced by some of the philosophical literature began developing defending their own definition of morality

 On one reading, what these psychologists were claiming is that Taylor was wrong

Morality IS a natural kind

And they had determined what the essential properties of moral rules are

15

Philosophical Background

 For about two decades, this psychological research tradition was all but unknown to philosophers

 But in the last few years it has become increasingly well known and increasingly influential in the work of philosophers and psychologists, including

16

From Philosophy to Psychology:

The Turiel Project

Turiel’s Definitions

 The central figure in this research tradition is Elliot Turiel

 In the mid-1970s he proposed a definition of “moral rule”

 He also proposed a definition of

“conventional rule” – another notion on which philosophers, like

David Lewis, had recently lavished a fair amount of attention

17

From Philosophy to Psychology:

The Turiel Project

 Turiel did not defend his definitions using abstract philosophical arguments

Nor did he make claims about how the words

‘moral’ and ‘conventional’ are used

 Rather, he used his definitions to design psychological experiments

And those experiments produced some very extraordinary results

18

An Overview of Research in the M/C

Tradition

The core ideas in the definitions that Turiel & his followers have offered are as follows:

Moral rules are held to have an objective, prescriptive force ; they are not dependent on the authority of any individual or institution

Moral rules are taken to hold generally, not just locally ; they not only proscribe behavior here and now, they also proscribe behavior in other countries and at other times in history

Violations of moral rules involve a victim who has been harmed , whose rights have been violated, or who has been victim of an injustice

Violations of moral rules are typically more serious than violations of conventional rules

19

An Overview of Research in the M/C

Tradition

 The core features in the definition of conventional rules are these:

Conventional rules are taken to be arbitrary or situation-dependent; they do not have an objective, prescriptive force , and they can be suspended or changed by an appropriate authoritative individual or institution

Conventional rules are often geographically & temporally local ; those applicable in one community often will not apply in other communities or at other times in history

Violations of conventional rules do not involve a victim who has been harmed , whose rights have been violated, or who has been victim of an injustice.

Violations of conventional rules are typically less serious than violations of moral rule

20

An Overview of Research in the M/C

Tradition

 Guided by these definitions, Turiel and his associates developed an experimental paradigm that has become known as

“the moral / conventional task”

 In the m/c task, participants are presented with examples of transgressions of prototypical moral rules & prototypical conventional rules, and are asked series of probe questions designed to determine

21

An Overview of Research in the M/C

Tradition

1) Whether the participants consider the transgressive action to be wrong , and if so, how serious it is

2) Whether the participants think that the wrongness of the transgression is “authority dependent”

For example, a participant who has said that a specific rule-violating act is wrong might be asked:

“What if the teacher said there is no rule in this school about [that sort of rule violating act], would it be right to do it then?

22

An Overview of Research in the M/C

Tradition

3) Whether the participants think the rule is general in scope ; is it applicable to everyone, everywhere, or just to a limited range of people, in a restricted set of circumstances?

4) How the participants would justify the rule

 do they invoke harm, justice, or rights , or do they invoke other factors?

 participants’ answers to these probe questions are often called “criterion judgments”

23

An Overview of Research in the M/C

Tradition

 Early results suggested that the categories of moral and conventional rules, as defined by Turiel, are indeed psychologically significant

24

An Overview of Research in the M/C

Tradition

 When asked about prototypical moral transgressions like

 one child hitting another

 one child pushing another child off a swing and prototypical conventional transgressions like

 a child talking in class when she has not been called on by the teacher

 a boy wearing a dress to school participants’ responses differed systematically , and in just the way suggested by the Turiel’s definitions

25

An Overview of Research in the M/C

Tradition

 Transgressions of prototypical moral rules (almost always involving a victim who has clearly been harmed) were judged to be

 wrong and to be more serious than transgressions of prototypical conventional rules

 the wrongness of the transgression was judged not

“authority dependent”

 the violated rule was judged to be general in scope

 judgments were justified by appeal to harm

26

An Overview of Research in the M/C

Tradition

 Transgressions of prototypical conventional rules were judged to be:

 wrong but usually less serious

 the rules were judged to be authority dependent

 & not general in scope

 judgments were not justified by appeal to harm

27

An Overview of Research in the M/C

Tradition

 During the last 30 years this pattern of results has been found in an impressively diverse range of participants

28

An Overview of Research in the M/C

Tradition

 participants of different ages

 young children -- 3 ½ years, perhaps earlier

 grade school children

 high school students

 university students

 adults

29

An Overview of Research in the M/C

Tradition

 participants of different nationalities & cultures , including

Chinese preschoolers

Korean children

Ijo children in Nigeria

Urban & kibbutz children in Israel

Virgin Islanders -- children, teen-agers & adults

Children in India

Brazilian adults

30

An Overview of Research in the M/C

Tradition

31

An Overview of Research in the M/C

Tradition

 participants of different religions , including

Roman Catholic high school & university students

Amish & Mennonite children & teenagers

Dutch Reformed children & teenagers

Conservative Jewish children & teenagers

32

An Overview of Research in the M/C

Tradition

What conclusions have been drawn from these results?

The answer is not straightforward, since Turiel & his followers are heavily influenced by the work of

Piaget & Kohlberg, and are partial to the obscure terminology and philosophically tendentious concepts that prevail in that intellectual tradition

33

An Overview of Research in the M/C

Tradition

Rather than getting bogged down in textual exegesis, I’ll offer some conclusions which are plausible to draw from these findings

 philosophers who are impressed by the m/c task results apparently accept

34

An Overview of Research in the M/C

Tradition

(C1) The first set of conclusions generalize the results

I.e. they maintain that the results are specific instances of more general patterns

 (C2) The second conclusion maintains that these generalizations support an important claim about the nature (or definition) of morality

35

An Overview of Research in the M/C

Tradition

(C1) The first set of conclusions generalize the results

I.e. they maintain that the results are specific instances of more general patterns

 (C2) The second conclusion maintains that the generalizations support conclusions about the nature (or definition) of morality

36

An Overview of Research in the M/C

Tradition

 (C1-i) The Clustering of “Criterion Judgments” : In m/c task experiments participants will typically exhibit one of two signature response patterns

 The signature moral pattern : Rules are judged to be

 authority in dependent

 general in scope

 violations are wrong and typically judged to be serious

 judgments are justified by appeal to harm, justice and rights

37

An Overview of Research in the M/C

Tradition

 The signature conventional pattern : Rules are judged to be

 authority dependent

 and not general in scope

 violations are wrong but usually less serious

 and judgments are not justified by appeal to harm, justice, or rights

38

An Overview of Research in the M/C

Tradition

These signature response patterns are

“nomological clusters” or

“homeostatic clusters”

– there is a strong (“lawlike”) tendency for the members of the cluster to occur together

39

An Overview of Research in the M/C

Tradition

 (C1-ii) Response Patterns and Transgression Types :

Not only will criterion judgments cluster into two distinct response patterns, but each pattern is reliably evoked by a certain type of transgression

 (C1-ii)(a) transgressions involving harm , justice, or rights

( HJR ) evoke the signature moral pattern

 (C1-ii)(b) transgressions that do not involve harm , justice, or rights evoke the signature conventional pattern

40

An Overview of Research in the M/C

Tradition

 (C1-iii) Universality:

 The regularities described in (C-1) and (C-2) are pancultural , and they emerge quite early in development

41

An Overview of Research in the M/C

Tradition

The first set of conclusions generalize the results

I.e. they maintain that the results are specific instances of more general patterns

 (C2) The second conclusion maintains that the generalizations support conclusions about the nature (or definition) of morality

42

An Overview of Research in the M/C

Tradition

 (C2) Moral Rules and Conventional Rules are

Natural Kinds

 The essential properties of the kind are those specified in

Turiel’s definitions

Moral rules

 have objective, prescriptive force ; they are not authority dependent *

 hold generally, not just locally *

 violations of moral rules involve a victim who has been harmed , whose rights have been violated, or who has been participant to an injustice

 violations of moral rules are typically more serious than violations of conventional rules

43

Tradition objective prescriptive force, be authority dependent, etc. (or judged to have them under ideal circumstances.

(C2) Moral Rules and Conventional Rules are

Natural Kinds

 careful about metaphysical distinctions that loom large in philosophy.)

Turiel’s definitions

Moral rules

 have objective, prescriptive force ; they are not authority dependent *

 hold generally, not just locally *

 violations of moral rules involve a victim who has been harmed , whose rights have been violated, or who has been participant to an injustice

 violations of moral rules are typically more serious than violations of conventional rules

44

Tradition essential properties of moral rules

 (C2)

Moral Rules and Conventional Rules are

Natural Kinds and types of transgressions.

The essential properties of the kind are those specified in

Turiel’s definitions

Moral rules

 have objective, prescriptive force ; they are not authority dependent *

 hold generally, not just locally *

 violations of moral rules involve a victim who has been harmed , whose rights have been violated, or who has been participant to an injustice

 violations of moral rules are typically more serious than violations of conventional rules

45

Tradition essential properties of moral rules

 (C2)

Moral Rules and Conventional Rules are

Natural Kinds and types of transgressions.

The essential properties of the kind are those specified in

Turiel’s definitions

Moral rules

 have objective, prescriptive force ; they are not authority dependent *

 hold generally, not just locally *

 violations of moral rules involve a victim who has been harmed , whose rights have been violated, or who has been participant to an injustice

 violations of moral rules are typically more serious than violations of conventional rules

46

An Overview of Research in the M/C

Tradition

 The conclusion that Moral Rules are a Natural

Kind plausibly follows from the facts that

 They are a class of rules which exhibit a homeostatic cluster of properties

 There is an important nomological generalization about members of the class

Viz. all members of the class involve harm (or rights or justice)

47

An Overview of Research in the M/C

Tradition

 An entirely parallel argument leads to the conclusion that

Conventional Rules are a Natural Kind

48

An Overview of Research in the M/C

Tradition

 It is not surprising that work in the M/C tradition has had a profound influence on many naturalistically inclined philosophers and also on many psychologists not trained in the Paiget-Kohlberg-

Turiel tradition

 The conclusion that Moral Rules and Conventional

Rules are Natural Kinds is profoundly important

 But, alas

It just ain’t true!

49

The Theories Confront the Data

 Despite the wealth of evidence gathered by researchers in the M/C tradition, not everyone has been convinced of (C1) – the conclusions that generalize the results of M/C task experiments

Dissenters have focused on (C1-ii)(b)

50

The Theories Confront the Data

 (C1-ii) Response Patterns and Transgression Types :

Not only will criterion judgments cluster into two distinct response patterns, but each pattern is reliably evoked by a certain type of transgression

 (C1-ii)(a) transgressions involving harm , justice, or rights evoke the signature moral pattern

 (C1-ii)(b)

transgressions that do not involve harm , justice, or rights evoke the signature conventional pattern

51

The Theories Confront the Data

 Dissenters maintain that there are many societies in which transgressions that do not involve harm (or justice or rights) [= non-HJR ] do not evoke the full conventional response pattern

 Rather, such transgressions evoke one or more of the signature moral responses

 There are a number of examples in the literature, but since time is limited I’ll mention only three

52

The Theories Confront the Data

 Nisan (1987), reports a series of studies on Israeli children that closely followed the methodology adopted by Turiel and his followers

 Kibbutz kids & urban secular kids gave the standard signature responses for both HJR & non-HJR rules

 Children in traditional Arab villages judged that ALL rules including clear examples of non-HJR rules (e.g. coed swimming, addressing a teacher by his first name) are

 authority independent generally applicable

These are central components of the signature moral response pattern

53

The Theories Confront the Data

 Jon Haidt (1993) used a famously colorful range of non-HJR transgressions

 eating the family dog

 cleaning the toilet bowl with the national flag

 f*cking a dead chicken

54

The Theories Confront the Data

 Jon Haidt (1993) used a famously colorful range of non-HJR transgressions

 eating the family dog

 cleaning the toilet bowl with the national flag

 f*cking a dead chicken

55

The Theories Confront the Data

 Jon Haidt (1993) used a famously colorful range of non-HJR transgressions

 eating the family dog

 cleaning the toilet bowl with the national flag

 f*cking a dead chicken

 Low SES participants in Brazil & the USA judged all of these nonHJR (“conventional”) transgressions to be

 authority independent

 generally applicable

These are central components of the signature moral response pattern

56

The Theories Confront the Data

Nichols

(2002, 2004) studied reactions to another class of

non-HJR

rules, viz.

rules of etiquette

 He compared rules that prohibit disgusting behavior

 e.g. a dinner guest snorting and spitting into his glass of water, then taking a drink

 with rules that prohibit behavior that is not disgusting

 e.g. a dinner guest drinks tomato soup out of a bowl

57

The Theories Confront the Data

 With children , Nichols found the disgusting transgressions evoked three of the signature MORAL responses

 they were impermissible & more serious than

“conventional” transgressions

 they were NOT authority dependent

 they generalized to other groups

 The non-disgusting transgressions evoked the signature conventional responses

58

The Theories Confront the Data

 With adults , disgusting transgressions evoked two of the signature moral responses

 they were impermissible & more serious than

“conventional” transgressions

 they were NOT authority dependent

 but they did not generalize to other groups

 The non-disgusting transgressions again evoked the signature conventional responses

59

The Theories Confront the Data

 Nichols’ data add to the mounting evidence

against (C1-ii)(b)

 NonHRJ (“conventional” etiquette) transgressions often DO NOT evoke the signature conventional response pattern

60

The Theories Confront the Data

 Nichols’ results also pose a clear

challenge to (C1-i) – The Clustering of “Criterion

Judgments”

 The putative nomological or homeostatic clusters posited in (C1-i) come apart in two different ways

61

The Theories Confront the Data

 Taken together, these findings pose a significant challenge to (C1-i), (C1-ii)(b) & (C1-iii)

I believe that the data we’ve reported are just the tip of the iceberg

 For a variety of reasons, m/c theorists have looked at only a narrow range of Non-HJR rules & transgressions

I’m betting that if one looked at a wider range of Non-

HJR violations in the appropriate communities, we’d find that (C1-ii)(b) would be massively disconfirmed

62

The Theories Confront the Data

 Some examples

 sibling incest

 for just about everyone

 homosexuality

 for the 50%+ of Americans who believe it is morally wrong

 taboo violation

 for people in traditional societies in which taboos are taken seriously e.g. reacting improperly to “polluting acts” – e.g. not being purified after being touched by a low caste person

63

Part II: An Overview of Research in the M/C

Tradition

But what about (C1-ii)(a)?

(C1-ii) Response Patterns and Transgression Types :

Not only will criterion judgments cluster into two distinct response patterns, but each pattern is reliably evoked by a certain type of transgression

 (C1-ii)(a)

transgressions involving harm , justice, or rights evoke the signature moral pattern

 (C1-ii)(b) transgressions that do not involve harm , justice, or rights evoke the signature conventional pattern

64

The Theories Confront the Data

 We have found no studies reporting data that challenge the claim that transgressions involving harm, welfare, justice or rights evoke the signature moral response

 Possible explanation : (C1-ii)(a) is both true and pan-cultural , i.e. HJR rules reliably and cross-culturally evoke the signature moral response

 3 reasons to doubt that (C1-ii)(a) is true

65

The Theories Confront the Data

1. Even more so than with transgressions of Non-HJR rules, the range of HJR transgressions used in m/c task experiments has been remarkably narrow

All of the HJR transgressions studied have been

“schoolyard” transgressions such as hair pulling or pushing someone off of a swing

66

The Theories Confront the Data

James Blair has used such “schoolyard” transgressions when the participants were incarcerated psychopathic murderers!

67

The Theories Confront the Data

2. Philosophic views (Williams’ “relativism of distance” and Harman’s sophisticated moral relativism) suggest there may be many HJR rules that people do not

generalize to other cultures or historical periods

Slavery

Corporal punishment

Treating women as chattel

68

The Theories Confront the Data

3. Current public debate surrounding issues like the treatment of detainees at Guantanamo Bay suggests that a significant number of people do not consider rules prohibiting harmful treatment in such cases to be authority independent

69

The Theories Confront the Data

 To explore the possibility that many harmful transgressions that are not of the schoolyard variety would not evoke the signature moral response pattern, Kelly, Stich, Haley, Eng & Fessler ran a web based experiment in which participants were asked about a number of such transgressions

70

The Theories Confront the Data

 For example, to explore whether rules prohibiting use of corporal punishment are judged to be authority independent , participants were presented with following pair of questions

71

It is against the law for teachers to spank students. Ms.

Williams is a third grade teacher, and she knows about the law prohibiting spanking. She has also received clear instructions from her Principal not to spank students. But when a boy in her class is very disruptive and repeatedly hits other children, she spanks him.

Is it OK for Ms. Williams to spank the boy?

YES NO

On a scale from 0 to 9, how would you rate Ms. Williams' behavior?

Not at all bad Very bad

0 1 2 3 4 5 6 7 8 9

(B) Now suppose that it was not against the law for teachers to spank students, and that Ms. Williams' Principal had told her that she could spank students who misbehave if she wanted to.

Is it OK for Ms. Williams to spank the boy?

YES NO

On a scale from 0 to 9, how would you rate Ms. Williams' behavior?

Not at all bad Very bad

0 1 2 3 4 5 6 7 8 9

The Theories Confront the Data

 The results were quite dramatic

74

The Theories Confront the Data

 The results were quite dramatic

50

 8% of participants said it was OK to spank the boy in response to question (A) and 48% said it was OK to spank the boy in response to question (B)

40

30

20

10

0

OK to Spank?

Prohibited by

Authorities

NOT Prohibited p = 0.000 !

75

The Theories Confront the Data

 To explore whether actions that are judged to be wrong now also judged to be wrong in the past (= the Williams / Harman conjecture) participants were presented with the following pair of questions

76

Three hundred years ago, whipping was a common practice in most navies and on cargo ships. There were no laws against it, and almost everyone thought that whipping was an appropriate way to discipline sailors who disobeyed orders or were drunk on duty.

Mr. Williams was an officer on a cargo ship 300 years ago. One night, while at sea, he found a sailor drunk at a time when the sailor should have been on watch. After the sailor sobered up,

Williams punished the sailor by giving him 5 lashes with a whip.

Is it OK for Mr. Williams to whip the sailor?

YES NO

On a scale from 0 to 9, how would you rate Mr. Williams' behavior?

Not at all bad

0 1 2 3

Very bad

4 5 6 7 8 9

B) Mr. Adams is an officer on a large modern American cargo ship in 2004. One night, while at sea, he finds a sailor drunk at a time when the sailor should have been monitoring the radar screen. After the sailor sobers up, Adams punishes the sailor by giving him 5 lashes with a whip.

Is it OK for Mr. Adams to whip the sailor?

YES NO

On a scale from 0 to 9, how would you rate Mr. Adams’ behavior?

Not at all bad

0 1 2 3

Very bad

4 5 6 7 8 9

The Theories Confront the Data

 Again the results were dramatic – clearly confirming Williams’ claim about the relativism of distance

79

The Theories Confront the Data

 Again the results were dramatic – clearly confirming Williams’ claim about the relativism of distance

 52% of participants said that it was OK to whip a drunken sailor

300 years ago, but only 6% said it was

OK to do it today!

60

50

40

30

20

10

0

OK to Whip?

Today

300 Years Ago p = 0.000 !

80

The Theories Confront the Data

 Kelly et al. used one additional scenario to test whether actions judged to be wrong now are also judged to be wrong long ago or far away

 And five other scenarios to explore whether participants treat harm transgressions as authority independent

 In EACH case the data were similar

81

The Theories Confront the Data

 We maintain that these findings poses a serious challenge to (C1-ii)(a) , which claims that harm norms evoke the signature moral pattern

 When we go beyond the narrow range of schoolyard transgressions that have been used in previous studies, many participants think that rules prohibiting harmful actions are neither authority independent nor general in scope

82

The Theories Confront the Data

The upshot of all this is that

83

The Theories Confront the Data

(C1) The first set of conclusions generalize the results

I.e. they maintain that the results are specific instances of more general patterns

 (C2) The second conclusion maintains that the generalizations support conclusions about the

Every member of the first set of conclusions drawn from M/C task experiments is FALSE

84

The Theories Confront the Data

 (C2) Moral Rules and Conventional Rules are

Natural Kinds

 The essential properties of the kind are those specified in

Turiel’s definitions

Moral rules

 have objective, prescriptive force ; they are not authority dependent*

 hold generally, not just locally*

Since the second conclusion depends on the first, we have no

 violations of moral rules are typically more serious than

reason to believe it is TRUE

85

Conclusion

Is Morality a Natural Kind?

Research using the M/C Task give us no reason to think that the answer is

YES

86

Post-Script

After talks on this topic, I am often asked:

“So are you claiming that there is no moral / conventional distinction?”

The answer is not straightforward since it is not clear how the question is to be understood

87

Post-Script

 If the question is:

Do moral rules and conventional rules constitute a natural kinds?

 The answer is:

88

Post-Script

 Research using the “moral / conventional task” gives us no reason to think the answer is YES … but

 In the next lecture, I’ll sketch a theory about the psychological mechanisms underlying NORMS which suggest that there is a natural kind in this vicinity … though

 whether

“moral rules” is an appropriate label for that kind depends (in part) on how the term “moral rule” is ordinarily used

89

Post-Script

 At present, very

little is known

about that

 However, Edouard Machery & I have an hypothesis

 We think that usage of the term is governed by both a

prototype detailing typical reactions to transgressions

of rules AND a set of

exemplars of culturally familiar rules

90

Post-Script

 If we are right, then

middle-class liberals

, will use the term in a way that is significantly different from

 Observant Mormons

 Conservative Muslims

 Ultra-Orthodox Jews

91

Post-Script

 If our hypothesis is correct, then there is an important sense in which

 the term “moral rule” is multiply ambiguous

 there is no (single) concept of MORAL RULE

 the traditional project of providing a “definition of morality” which captures ordinary usage must be radically reconceived

92

Post-Script

 Is our hypothesis correct?

 With a bit of luck, I’ll be able to offer you some data on my

next trip to Paris

93

Download