Econ 522 Economics of Law Dan Quint Fall 2015 Lecture 15 Reminders HW3 due next Thursday (November 12) at midnight Second midterm Wednesday November 18 in class 1 Let’s recap our story so far… 2 Our story so far Efficiency Maximizing total surplus realized by everyone in society Scarce resources are owned by whoever values them most (net of externalities, if any) Actions are taken if social benefit exceeds social cost Design a legal system that leads to efficient outcomes Once we set up the rules, we don’t expect people to act based on what’s efficient We expect people to do whatever’s in their own best interest So the goal is set up the rules such that people acting in their own best interest will naturally lead to efficiency 3 Our story so far Coase gives us one way to do that If property rights are clearly defined and tradable, and there are no transaction costs, people have incentive to trade until each resource is efficiently owned So initial allocation of rights doesn’t matter for efficiency But if there are transaction costs, we may not get efficiency this way 4 Our story so far Coase gives us one way to do that If property rights are clearly defined and tradable, and there are no transaction costs, people have incentive to trade until each resource is efficiently owned So initial allocation of rights doesn’t matter for efficiency But if there are transaction costs, we may not get efficiency this way Led us to two normative views of the legal system: 1. Minimize transaction costs (“lubricate” private exchange) 2. Allocate rights as efficiently as possible Tradeoff between injunctive relief and damages 5 Our story so far Property law works well for simultaneous trade Contracts allow for non-simultaneous trade Contract law can… Enable cooperation Encourage efficient disclosure of information Secure optimal commitment to performance Secure efficient reliance Supply efficient default rules and regulations Foster enduring relationships 6 Our story so far So far, we’ve been talking about voluntary exchange Coase is predicated on exchange being voluntary for both parties Contracts are an extension of voluntary trade Up next: “involuntary trade” You’re bicycling to class, I’m texting while driving and I hit you You didn’t want to deal with me, I didn’t want to deal with you… 7 Our story so far To put it another way… Property law covers situations where transaction costs are low enough to get agreement ahead of time Exceptions to property law – private necessity, eminent domain – when this isn’t the case Contract law covers situations when transaction costs are low enough for us to agree to a contract, high enough that we may not want to renegotiate the contract later Tort law covers situations where transaction costs are too high to agree to anything in advance 8 Tort law 9 An example 10 An example punish the choice • criminal law • regulations Choice + Bad Luck Outcome 11 An example punish the choice punish the outcome • criminal law • “strict liability” • regulations Choice + Bad Luck Outcome punish the combination of choice and outcome • “negligence” 12 Tort law Tort, noun. from French word meaning injury Contract law: situations where someone harms you by breaking a promise they had made Tort law: situations where someone harms you without having made any promises “If someone shoots you, you call a cop. If he runs his car into yours, you call a lawyer.” 13 As always, we’ll be focused on achieving efficiency I hit you with my car, do $1,000 worth of damage You’re $1,000 worse off (No damage to me or my car) Should I have to pay you damages? I owe nothing I owe $1,000 I owe $50,000 –1,000 0 49,000 My payoff 0 –1,000 –50,000 Combined payoffs –1,000 –1,000 –1,000 Your payoff 14 Something to remember distribution but not efficiency efficiency 15 Tort law Question: how to structure the law to get people to behave in a way that leads to efficient outcomes? Deliberate harms: make punishment severe (criminal law) Accidental harms: trickier Goal isn’t “no accidents”; goal is “efficient number of accidents” 16 Tort law Question: how to structure the law to get people to behave in a way that leads to efficient outcomes? Deliberate harms: make punishment severe (criminal law) Accidental harms: trickier Goal isn’t “no accidents”; goal is “efficient number of accidents” Unlike nuisance law, injunctive relief is not an option Unlike contract law, no agreement ahead of time Cooter and Ulen: essence of tort law is “the attempt to make injurers internalize the externalities they cause, in situations where transaction costs are too high to do this through property or contract rights” 17 Cast of characters Plaintiff – person who brings a lawsuit Defendant – person who is being sued In a nuisance case, the defendant caused a nuisance, plaintiff was bothered by it, might be asking for injunction or damages In a contract case, defendant breached a contract or violated its terms In a tort case, defendant caused some harm to plaintiff, plaintiff is asking for damages Plaintiff is the victim (person who was harmed) Defendant is the injurer (person who caused the harm) 18 “Classic” legal theory of torts Harm Causation Breach of Duty 19 Element 1: Harm For a tort to exist, the plaintiff needs to have been harmed “Without harm, there is no tort” Gas company sold gas with a defective additive Dangerous for cars with turbocharged carburetors You have a car with normal carburetors You might be angry; but you weren’t harmed, so you can’t sue Similarly, no compensation for exposure to risk Manufacturer exposed workers to some chemical Exposure will cause 15% of them to develop cancer later in life Can’t sue now – have to wait, see who gets cancer, then they can sue 20 Element 1: Harm Money Health Perfect compensation restores victim to original level of well-being generally done through money damages 21 Perfect Compensation Tangible harms • Medical costs • Lost income • Damaged property Intangible harms • Emotional harm • Pain and suffering • Loss of companionship In theory, perfect compensation should cover all losses Historically, courts have been less willing to compensate for intangible or hard-to-measure losses Over time, U.S. courts have started compensating for more intangible harms 22 Perfect Compensation Tangible harms • Medical costs • Lost income • Damaged property Intangible harms • Emotional harm • Pain and suffering • Loss of companionship In theory, perfect compensation should cover all losses Historically, courts have been less willing to compensate for intangible or hard-to-measure losses Over time, U.S. courts have started compensating for more intangible harms Pro: the closer liability is to actual harm done, the better the incentive to avoid these harms Con: disparity in award sizes, unpredictability 23 “Classic” legal theory of torts Harm Causation Breach of Duty 24 Element 2: Causation For a tort to exist, the defendant needs to have caused the harm to the plaintiff Cause-in-fact “But for the defendant’s actions, would the harm have occurred?” 25 Element 2: Causation For a tort to exist, the defendant needs to have caused the harm to the plaintiff Cause-in-fact “But for the defendant’s actions, would the harm have occurred?” 26 Element 2: Causation For a tort to exist, the defendant needs to have caused the harm to the plaintiff Cause-in-fact “But for the defendant’s actions, would the harm have occurred?” Proximate cause Immediate cause – defendant’s action can’t be too distant from the harm Palsgraf v Long Island Railway (NY Ct Appeals, 1928): Guard pushed a passenger to help him onto train, passenger dropped fireworks he was carrying, they went off, explosion knocked down scales at the other end of the platform, which fell on Mrs. Palsgraf Guard’s actions were not the proximate cause 27 Element 2: Causation “A tree fell on a moving trolly, injuring passengers. One of them sued. He succeeded in demonstrating that in order for the trolly to be where it was when the tree fell on it the driver had to have driven faster than the speed limit at some point during the trip. Breaking the law is per se negligence, so the driver was legally negligent whether or not his driving was actually unsafe. If he had not driven over the speed limit, the trolly would not have been under the tree when it fell, so, the plaintiff argued, the driver’s negligence caused the injury.” Court ruled driver’s negligence “had not caused the accident in the legally relevant sense” 28 “Classic” legal theory of torts Harm Causation Breach of Duty 29 Element 3: Breach of Duty (Sometimes required, sometimes not) Strict Liability Negligence • Harm • Causation 30 Element 3: Breach of Duty (Sometimes required, sometimes not) Strict Liability • Harm • Causation Negligence • Harm • Causation • Breach of duty (fault) When someone breaches a duty he owes to the defendant, and this leads to the harm, the injurer is at fault, or negligent Injurers owe victims the duty of due care Negligence rule: I’m only liable if I failed to take the required standard of care – not if I was careful and the accident happened anyway 31 Hence the language in the trolly example “A tree fell on a moving trolly, injuring passengers. One of them sued. He succeeded in demonstrating that in order for the trolly to be where it was when the tree fell on it the driver had to have driven faster than the speed limit at some point during the trip. Breaking the law is per se negligence, so the driver was legally negligent whether or not his driving was actually unsafe. If he had not driven over the speed limit, the trolly would not have been under the tree when it fell, so, the plaintiff argued, the driver’s negligence caused the injury.” 32 So under a negligence rule… If I breach my duty of due care and injure you, I am liable If I exercise the appropriate level of care but still injure you, I’m not liable How is the standard of care determined? That is, how careful do I have to be to avoid liability, and who decides? Is it negligent to drive 40 MPH on a particular road at a particular time of day? What about 41 MPH? 42? 33 How is the standard of care determined? Some settings: government imposes safety regulations that are also used as standard for negligence Speed limits for highway driving Requirement that bicycles have brakes Workplace regulations Some standards are left vague “Reckless driving” may depend on road, time of day, weather… Common law focuses on duty of reasonable care Level of care a reasonable person would have taken (Civil law relies less on “reasonableness” tests, tries to spell out what level of care is required) 34 Strict liability versus negligence Strict liability rule: plaintiff must prove harm and causation Negligence rule: must prove harm, causation, and negligence A little history Early Europe: strict liability was usual rule By early 1900s, negligence became usual rule Second half of 1900s, strict liability became more common again, especially for manufacturer liability in American consumer products U.S. manufacturers now held liable for harms caused by defective products, whether or not they were at fault 35 “Classic” legal theory of torts Harm Causation Breach of Duty 36 Next question Like with contract law, our main concern is with the incentives created by liability rules So… what incentives are we interested in? 37 Precaution 38 Precaution The more carefully I drive, the less likely I am to hit you But, driving more carefully is also more costly to me Must be some efficient level of care Similarly… Construction company can reduce accidents with better safety equipment, better training, short workdays, all of which cost money Manufacturer can reduce accidents by designing/inspecting products more carefully – again, more expensive 39 Actions by both injurer and victim impact number of accidents • speed like hell • drive slowly • drive drunk while texting • drive carefully • cheap, hasty manufacturing • careful quality control • save money • install smoke detectors, other safety equipment • wear helmet and use light • bicycle at night wearing black LESS EFFORT TO PREVENT ACCIDENTS “LESS PRECAUTION” GREATER EFFORT TO PREVENT ACCIDENTS “MORE PRECAUTION” 40 We will call all these things precaution Precaution: anything either injurer or victim could do to reduce likelihood of an accident (or damage done) The next two questions should be obvious… How much precaution do we want? What is efficient level of precaution? How do we design the law to get it? 41 Simple economic model for thinking about tort law 42 To answer these questions, we’ll introduce a very simple model of accidents Car hits a bicycle In real life: driver probably has insurance In real life: some damage to bicycle, some damage to driver’s car In real life: driver and bicyclist may not even know what the law is We’ll simplify things a lot, by assuming… Only one party is harmed Parties know the law, don’t have insurance (for now) We’ll focus on one party’s precaution at a time 43 Model of unilateral harm x w p(x) A level of precaution marginal cost of precaution probability of an accident cost of an accident Unilateral harm – just one victim Precaution – costly actions that make accident less likely Could be taken by either victim or injurer We’ll consider both, but one at a time Notation x – the amount of precaution that is taken w – the cost of each “unit” of precaution p(x) – probability of an accident, given precaution x so total cost of precaution is wx p is decreasing in x A – cost of accident (to victim) so expected cost of accidents is p(x) A 44 Model of unilateral harm x w p(x) A level of precaution marginal cost of precaution probability of an accident cost of an accident efficient precaution: minx { wx + p(x) A } $ w + p’(x) A marginal social cost of precaution w marginal social benefit of precaution = 0 = – p’(x) A wx + p(x) A (Total Social Cost) wx (Cost of Precaution) p(x) A (Cost of Accidents) x* (Efficient Level of Precaution) x < x* x > x* Precaution (x) 45 A technical note (clarification) We’re thinking of bilateral precaution, just “one at a time” So really, xinjurer, xvictim, problem is minxi, xv { p(xi, xv) A – wi xi – wv xv } “Hold fixed” one party’s action and consider the other: minxi { p(xi, xv) A – wi xi – wv xv } given xv (and v.v.) This has same solution as minxi { p(xi, xv) A – wi xi } Our result will generally be “efficient given what the other guy is doing” 46 Effect of liability rules on precaution We know what’s efficient Level of precaution that minimizes total social cost = wx + p(x) A We’ll consider what happens if there is… no liability rule in place a strict liability rule a negligence rule 47 Benchmark: what happens without any liability rule? Skip 48 Benchmark: No Liability In a world with no liability… Injurer does not have to pay for accidents So, bears cost of any precautions he takes, but does not receive any benefit Injurer has no incentive to take precaution Victim bears cost of any accidents, plus cost of precaution he takes (Victim precaution imposes no externality on injurer) Victim precaution will be efficient 49 Benchmark: No Liability $ Injurer’s private cost is just wx Private cost to injurer Private cost to victim Minimized at x = 0 Victim’s private cost is p(x) A + wx wx + p(x) A wx Minimized at efficient precaution level x = x* p(x) A x* x So rule of no liability leads to efficient precaution by victims, no precaution by injurers 50 Benchmark: No Liability No Liability Injurer Precaution Victim Precaution Zero Efficient 51 Precaution isn’t the only thing that determines number of accidents Precaution – actions which make an activity less dangerous Driving carefully Wearing bright-colored clothing while bicycling The amount we do each activity also affects the number of accidents I decide how much to drive You decide how much to bicycle Liability rules create incentives for activity levels as well as precaution 52 With no liability rule… With no liability, I’m not responsible if I hit you I don’t consider cost of accidents when deciding how fast to drive… …and I also don’t consider cost of accidents when deciding deciding how much to drive So I drive too recklessly, and I drive too much (or: if there is no liability, social cost of driving includes cost of accidents, but private cost to me does not; driving imposes negative externality, so I do it too much) So with no liability, injurer’s activity level is inefficiently high 53 What about victims? With no liability, victim bears full cost of accidents Greater activity by victim (more bike-riding) leads to more accidents Victim weighs cost of accidents when deciding how carefully to ride, and when deciding how much to ride (Private cost = social cost) Victim takes efficient level of precaution, and efficient level of activity A rule of no liability leads to an inefficiently high level of injurer activity, but the efficient level of victim activity 54 Benchmark: No Liability No Liability Injurer Precaution Victim Precaution Injurer Activity Victim Activity Zero Efficient Too High Efficient 55 Next up: Strict Liability and Negligence 56