From “What Is The Name Of This Book” by Raymond Smullyan Chapter 8 pages 99 to 103 Many of the puzzles in this chapter deal with so-called conditional statements: statements of the form “If P is true then Q is true,” where P, Q are statements under consideration. Before turning to puzzles of this type, we must carefully clear up some ambiguities which might arise. There are certain facts about such statements which everyone agrees on, but there are others about which there appears to be considerable disagreement. Let us turn to a concrete example. Consider the following statement: (1)If John is guilty, then his wife is guilty. Everyone will agree that if John is guilty and if statement (1) is true, then is wife is also guilty. Everyone will also agree that if John is guilty and his wife is innocent, then statement (1) must be false. Now, suppose it is known that his wife is guilty, but it is not known whether John is guilty or innocent. Would you then say that statement (1) is true or not? Would you not say that whether John is guilty or whether he is innocent, his wife is guilty in any case? Or would you not say: If John is guilty then his wife is guilty, and if John is innocent then his wife is guilty? Illustrations of this use of language abound in the literature: In Rudyard Kipling’s story Riki-Tiki-Tavi, the cobra says to the terrified family, “If you move I will strike, and if you don’t move I will strike.” This means nothing more less than: “I will strike.” There is also the story of the Zen-master Tokusan, who used to answer all questions as well as nonquestions, with blows from his stick. His famous saying is: “Thirty blows when you have s something to say; thirty blows just the same when you have nothing to say.” The upshot is that if a statement Q is true outright, then so is the statement, “If P then Q” (as well as the statement, “If not P, then Q”). The most controversial case of all is this: Supposing P, Q are both false. Then is the statement, “If P then Q” true or false? Or does it depend on what P and Q are? Returning, to our example, if John and his wife are both innocent, then should statement (1) be called true or not? We shall return to this vital question shortly. A related question is this: We have already agreed that if John is guilty and his wife innocent, then statement (1) must be false. Is the converse true? That is, if statement (1) is false, does it follow that John must be guilty and his wife innocent? Put otherwise, is it the case that the only way that (1) can be false is that John be guilty and his wife innocent? Well, according to the way most logicians, mathematicians, and scientists use the words “if...then,” the answer is “yes,” and this is the convention we shall adopt. In other words, given any two statements, P and Q, whenever I write “If P then Q” I shall mean nothing more nor less than “It is not the case that P is true and Q is false.” In particular, this means that if John and his wife are both innocent, then statement (1) is to be regarded as true. For the only way the statement can be false is that John is guilty and his wife is innocent, and this state of affairs can’t hold if John and his wife are both innocent. Stated otherwise, if John and his wife are both innocent, then it is certainly not the case that John is guilty and his wife is innocent, therefore the statement cannot be false. The following is an even more bizarre example: (2) If Confucius was born in Texas, then I am Dracula. All statement (2) is intended to mean is that it is not the case that Confucius was born in Texas and that I am not Dracula. This indeed is so, since Confucius was not born in Texas. Therefore statement (2) is to be regarded as true. Another way to look at the matter is that the only way (2) can be false is if Confucius was born in Texas and I am not Dracula. Well, since Confucius was not born in Texas, then it can’t be that Confucius was born in Texas and that I am not Dracula. In other words, (2) cannot be false, so it must be true. Now let us consider two arbitrary statements P, Q, and the `following statement formed from them: (3) If P then Q. This statement is symbolized: P->Q, and is alternatively read: “P implies Q.” The use of the word “implies” may be somewhat unfortunate, but it has found its way into the literature in this sense. All the statement means, as we have seen, is that it is not the case that P is true and Q s false. Thus we have the following facts: Fact Fact Fact true 1: If P is false, then P->Q is automatically true. 2: If Q is true, then P->Q is automatically true. 3: The one and only way that P->Q can be false is that P is and Q is false. Fact 1 is sometimes paraphrased: “A false proposition implies any proposition.” This statement came as quite a shock to many a philosopher. Fact 2 is sometimes paraphrased: “A true proposition is implied by any proposition.” A Truth-Table Summary Given any two statements, P, Q, there are always exactly four possibilities: (1) P, Q are both true; (2) P is true and Q is false; (3) P is false and Q is true; (4) P, Q are both false. One and only one of these possibilities must hold. Now let us consider the statement, “If P then Q” (P->Q). Can it be determined in which of the four cases it holds and in which ones it doesn’t? Yes it can, by the following analysis: Case 1: P and Q are both true. In this case Q is true; hence P>Q is true by Fact 2 Case 2: P is true and Q is false. In this case, P->Q is false by Fact 3. Case 3: P is false and Q is true. Then P->Q is true by Fact 1 (also by Fact 2) Case 4: P is false and Q is false. Then P-> Q is true by Fact 1. These four cases are all summarized in the following table, called the truth-table for implication. P T T F F Q T F T F P -> Q T F T T The first row, T,T,T (true, true, true), means that when P is true and Q is true, P->Q is true. The second row, T, F, F means that when P is true and Q is false then P->Q is false. The third row, F,T,T (false, true, true) says that when P is false and Q is true, P-> Q is true, and the fourth row, F,F,T (false, false, true) says that when P is false and Q is false, then P->Q is true. We note that P->Q is true in three out of four of those cases; only in the second is it false. Another Property of Implication Another important property of implication is this: To show that a statement “If P then Q” holds, it suffices to assume P as premise and then show that Q must follow. In other words, if the assumption of P leads to Q as a conclusion, then the statement “If P then Q” is established. We shall henceforth refer to this fact as Fact 4 Boolean functions are like other functions F(x,y)= x + y F(1,2) = ? F(1,2) = 1 + 2 = 3 Propositional Logic What are the truth tables for P T T F F Q T F T F Q unless P F T T T ~Q or ~P F T T T P T T F F Q T F T F Q if P T F T T P T T F F Q T F T F P is sufficient for Q T F T T Q or ~P | or(Q, ~P) T F T T P->Q T F T T P T T F F Q T F T F P is necessary for q T T F T ~Q or P T T F T ~P->~Q T T F T Q->P T T F T P T T F F Q T F T F Q only if P T T F T ~Q or P T T F T ~P->~Q T T F T Q->P T T F T P Q p is necessary and sufficient for q p->q and q->p p ≡ q T T F F T F T F T F F T T F F T T F F T Q if and only if P T F F T q if and only if p What is logical equivalence? p is a sufficient and necessary conditions for q Predicate Logic A singular statement makes an assertion about a specifically named person, place, thing, or time. Socrates is mortal Ms Fred is mortal Mf Jane is mortal Mj Tokyo is populous Pt The Sun-Times is a newspaper Ns King Lear is not a fairy tale ~F Berlioz was not a German ~Gb If Paris is beautiful then Andre told the truth Bp -> Ta Irene is either a doctor or a lawyer Di or Li Lx means x is a lawyer but you don’t know what x represents Senator Wilkins will be elected only if he campaigns Ew ->Cw General Motors will prosper if either Nissan is crippled by a strike or Subaru declares bankruptcy (Cn or Ds)-> Pg (C or D) -> P rewrites the predicate logic as propositional logic Indianapolis gets rain if and only if Chicago and Milwaukee gets snow Ri ≡ (Sc * Sm) Quantifiers Existential Quantifier Some s have property P Universal Quantifier All s have property P What is the relation between negation and the universal and existential quantifiers? ~∀π₯∃π¦π(π₯, π¦) ≡ ∃π₯~∃π¦π(π₯, π¦) ≡ ∃π₯∀π¦π(π₯, π¦) ~∃π₯∀π¦π(π₯, π¦) ≡ ∀π₯~∀π¦π(π₯, π¦) ≡ ∀π₯∃π¦π(π₯, π¦) To translate statements involving quantifiers, first translate the statement as a singular statement and then try to add the quantifiers. All triangles have 180 degrees D means “triangle has 180 degrees” Dt means the triangle t has 180 degrees ∀π₯π·π₯ where x is a triangle There exist triangles with 180 degrees ∃π₯π·π₯ where x is a triangle