106758581 3/9/2016 11:31 PM BOOK REVIEW IF AT FIRST YOU DON’T SECEDE, TRY, TRY AGAIN ROBERT C. BLACK* The Vermont Manifesto: The Second Vermont Republic By Thomas H. Naylor Philadelphia: Xlibris Corp., 2003, 128 pages INTRODUCTION Vermont was not part of the United States during the American Revolution and the Confederation period. It was an independent republic from 1777 until 1791, when it entered the Union as the fourteenth state. Drawing upon this heritage, Thomas H. Naylor, a retired economics professor, has issued a manifesto to Vermonters to reassert their historic independence and secede from the United States. Their alleged historic virtues—an incongruous amalgam of communitarian harmony and rugged individualism—would flourish afresh, he believes, in an independent state.1 The independent Vermont Republic was not independent by choice. It was, in the words of a sympathetic historian, “the Reluctant Republic.”2 Vermont became independent because it was not allowed to join the United * 1. 2. B.A., University of Michigan; J.D., Georgetown University; M.A. (Jurisprudence and Social Policy), University of California (Berkeley) School of Law; M.A. (Criminal Justice), State University of New York (Albany); member, New York and California bars. Portions of this text were previously published in The Thought, and appear here with the permission of its editor and publisher, Ronald C. Tobin. THOMAS H. NAYLOR, THE VERMONT MANIFESTO: THE SECOND VERMONT REPUBLIC 41 (2003). See generally FREDERIC F. VAN DE WATER, THE RELUCTANT REPUBLIC: VERMONT 1724–1791, at iii (1941) (intending “to lighten a shadowed chapter in American general history and to emphasize the implausible attainments of a remarkable and independent people”). 839 106758581 840 3/9/2016 11:31 PM NEW ENGLAND LAW REVIEW [Vol. 39:839 States during the period of the Second Continental Congress or the Articles of Confederation, and it was not immediately admitted to the United States under the Constitution. The involuntary independence of Vermont resembles, in our time, the independence of Singapore. Singapore, whose Prime Minister had declared that “secession is out,” was nonetheless expelled from Malaysia.3 Professor Naylor makes a plausible, if not entirely convincing, case that Vermont would be better off outside the United States. These pragmatic policy considerations will not, however, be discussed here. Nor will I discuss the realistic prospects for secession, given that “secession varies inversely with the centralization of the state,”4 and the American State is today far more centralized than it was in 1776, 1791, or 1861. Professor Naylor does not expect secession anytime soon.5 He acknowledges, and deplores, the fact that “[s]ince 1791 Vermont has become a lot less independent and considerably less sustainable economically, agriculturally, environmentally, and culturally than it once was.”6 Indeed, he is not the first or the only modern advocate of Vermont independence.7 Rather, Professor Naylor’s assertions and assumptions about the constitutionality of secession will be taken seriously enough to be explored. He is certain that the United States Constitution does not now, and never did, prohibit secession from the Union.8 This is hardly untilled ground, but lawyers, as I have argued, should take seriously popular movements based on legal ideas, even ideas remote from the legal mainstream.9 Professor Naylor reviews a variety of contemporary movements for independence 3. 4. 5. 6. 7. 8. 9. C.M. TURNBULL, A HISTORY OF SINGAPORE 1819–1975, at 297 (2d ed. 1989). DONALD BLACK, THE BEHAVIOR OF LAW 86 (1976). NAYLOR, supra note 1, at 19. Id. at 73. See, e.g., FRANK BRYAN & BILL MARES, OUT! THE VERMONT SECESSION BOOK 3 (1987) (predicting “the coming secession of Vermont from the Union in 1991”). NAYLOR, supra note 1, at 79. See Robert C. Black, “Constitutionalism”: The White Man’s Ghost Dance, 31 J. MARSHALL L. REV. 513, 520 (1998) (book review) (noting that “the very absurdity of so-called Constitutionalism should be more alarming than amusing to lawyers”). Yet another of these fringe populist movements fixated on a particular conception of the Constitution—this one has a much better argument than Professor Naylor’s or the Constitutionalists’—is the “fully informed jury” movement, which expects great things from juries once they are informed of their power to nullify the law, i.e., to decide not only if a law is constitutional but, even if it is, to decide if it is just to apply it in a particular case. See, e.g., Robert C. Black, FIJA: Monkeywrenching the Justice System?, 66 UMKC L. REV. 11, 18–20 (1997) (attempting “to advance and improve the resurgent debate over jury nullification in two ways: empirical and conceptual”). 106758581 2005] 3/9/2016 11:31 PM IF AT FIRST YOU DON’T SECEDE, TRY, TRY AGAIN 841 from the United States.10 It is entirely possible for intelligent laymen like Professor Naylor, who have not undergone our professional socialization— especially if they approach law and history with a preformed ideology—to read that law and its history, in the view of historians and lawyers, in unusual ways. I believe, for two reasons, that such arguments deserve the courtesy of a refutation. The first is that it is a professional responsibility of lawyers to educate the public about the law.11 The second is that lawyers themselves might want a refresher course on the great constitutional issues the Civil War was fought over, but which they might not be able to debate effectively with Professor Naylor or his followers. A lawyer who does not thoroughly understand what is wrong with Professor Naylor’s arguments is a lawyer who does not really understand the constitutional order. And there are such lawyers. Law review articles upholding the right of secession were published in 1986 and 1992.12 A Constitutional History of Secession, apparently the work of a Southern lawyer, was published in 2002.13 The 10. 11. 12. 13. NAYLOR, supra note 1, at 82–84. MODEL RULES OF PROF’L CONDUCT pmbl. ¶ 6 (2005) (“[A] lawyer should further the public’s understanding of and confidence in the rule of law and the justice system because legal institutions in a constitutional democracy depend on popular participation and support to maintain their authority.”). The ABA, always controlled by the lawyerly elite although always pretending to speak for all lawyers, does not entertain the possibility that these mandates are inconsistent. It is by no means obvious that the more the public knows about the legal system, the more it supports it. Usually, experience with the courts—which is a learning experience—erodes support for them. Austin Sarat, Studying American Legal Culture: An Assessment of Survey Evidence, 11 LAW & SOC’Y REV. 427, 439 (1976). Robert W. McGee, The Theory of Secession and Emerging Democracies: A Constitutional Solution, 28 STAN. J. INT’L L. 451, 452 (1992) (advancing “an expansive theoretical view of the right of secession,” and concluding that “secession is a workable option for minority groups, although practical obstacles exist”); H. Newcomb Morse, The Foundations and Meaning of Secession, 15 STETSON L. REV. 419 (1986) (discussing the theoretical underpinnings of secession and nullification with an analysis of states’ rights). JOHN REMINGTON GRAHAM, A CONSTITUTIONAL HISTORY OF SECESSION (2002). Graham’s book is mainly a justification of Southern secession. The dedication states in part: “Sacred to the memory of the Army of Northern Virginia and the Army of Tennessee.” Id. at 5. Hold on to your Confederate money! Other titles available from the same publisher include JAMES RONALD KENNEDY & WALTER DONALD KENNEDY, THE SOUTH WAS RIGHT! 9 (1994) (arguing in favor of “the legitimacy of the South’s claim of … right to recall [its] delegated powers and to establish a new government”). Presumably Graham’s book was unavailable to Professor Naylor when he wrote his Manifesto, as it is not cited. But more recently, he has recommended the book. Thomas H. Naylor, The Second Vermont Republic, Frequently Asked Questions (n.d.) (on file with New England Law Review). 106758581 842 3/9/2016 11:31 PM NEW ENGLAND LAW REVIEW [Vol. 39:839 recent Presidential election, once again evidencing a deeply divided electorate, has already occasioned proposals for the “blue” states to secede from the “red” states.14 Professor Naylor’s book has been lauded by liberal economist John Kenneth Galbraith, by conservative economist Walter E. Williams (why does this topic so interest economists?), by diplomat George F. Kennan,15 and by the editor of Utne magazine, who calls Professor Naylor a “Tom Paine for the 21st century.”16 Secession is a recurring temptation. Professor Naylor’s constitutional position is that the United States of America has always been the creation of a compact of states and that the national government is only their agent.17 The limited powers delegated to the national government may be “recalled” by the principals, the states, from their agent, the general government. From that premise follows Vermont’s, or any state’s, “Constitutional right to leave the Union.” The best summary of this position was made by John C. Calhoun: “Ours is a system of governments, compounded of the separate governments of the several States composing the Union, and of one common government of all its members, called the Government of the United States. The former preceded the latter, which was created by their agency.”18 Although Calhoun never advocated secession, he believed in, as the logic of his analysis supports, a state’s right of secession.19 I. BEFORE THE BEGINNING Professor Naylor effectively commences his argument with the Declaration of Independence20—but the independence of the states was already compromised before July 4, 1776. From 1775 on, the Second Continental Congress acted as the first national government of the United 14. 15. 16. 17. 18. 19. 20. See, e.g., Joseph Curl, Blue States Buzz Over Secession, WASH. TIMES, Nov. 9, 2004, at A1; Ian Williams, The Day After, METROLAND (Albany, N.Y.), Nov. 4, 2004, at 8. See Christopher Ketcham, Long Live Secession!, SALON.COM, Jan. 20, 2005, available at http://archive.salon.com/news/feature/2005/01/25/secession. Jay Walljasper, How to Be an Expat Without Leaving Home: An Independence Movement Arises in Vermont, UTNE, Jan.–Feb. 2004, at 66. NAYLOR, supra note 1, at 77–78, 113. JOHN C. CALHOUN, A DISQUISITION ON GOVERNMENT AND A DISCOURSE ON THE CONSTITUTION AND GOVERNMENT OF THE UNITED STATES 111 (Legal Classics Library 1993) (1851) [hereinafter CALHOUN, DISQUISITION AND DISCOURSE]; see also John C. Calhoun, Rough Draft of an Address to the People of South Carolina, in 11 THE PAPERS OF JOHN C. CALHOUN 264, 270 (Clyde N. Wilson ed., 1978) (advocating the view that “the Constitution is in fact, but a compact between the people of the States, as distinct political bodies”). CALHOUN, DISQUISITION AND DISCOURSE, supra note 18, at 300–01. NAYLOR, supra note 1, at 17, 77. 106758581 2005] 3/9/2016 11:31 PM IF AT FIRST YOU DON’T SECEDE, TRY, TRY AGAIN 843 States.21 It authorized a Continental Army and appointed its officers, notably its Commander-in-Chief, George Washington.22 That is how a Virginian came to command the New England troops besieging the British in Boston. The Congress arranged for the army’s supply, or tried to, and prescribed its rules and regulations.23 The Congress regulated American trade, established a Continental postal system, and established policies for the treatment of Loyalists and relations with the Native Americans.24 It borrowed money and issued currency.25 It initiated diplomatic dealings with foreign nations.26 Much later, the Supreme Court would hold that even back then the national government inherently possessed, under the law of nations, “external sovereignty,” exclusive control of foreign relations.27 And that position was also advanced in the early Republic. In 1795, Supreme Court Justice William Paterson maintained that, even prior to the Articles of Confederation, the Second Continental Congress exercised the “high powers” of “external sovereignty.”28 At the Federal Convention, Rufus King stated, The states were not “sovereigns” in the sense contended for by some. They did not possess the peculiar features of sovereignty,—they could not make war, nor peace, nor alliances, nor treaties. Considering them as political beings, they were dumb, for they could not speak to any foreign sovereign whatever. They were deaf, for they could not hear any propositions from such sovereign. They had not even the organs or faculties of defence or offence, for they could not of themselves raise troops, or equip vessels, for war. 29 Of course, the Continental Congress was deficient in some powers which today, and to some extent even then, would be adjudged essential to full sovereignty. Notably, it had no taxing power, and depended upon voluntary state compliance with its requisitions. But the point is not whether the national government had full sovereignty. The point is whether 21. 22. 23. 24. 25. 26. 27. 28. 29. PAULINE MAIER, AMERICAN SCRIPTURE: MAKING THE DECLARATION OF INDEPENDENCE, at xxi (1997). Id. at 11. Id. Id. at 13. Id. at 14. See id. at 42; SAMUEL FLAGG BEMIS, A DIPLOMATIC HISTORY OF THE UNITED STATES 21–23 (3d ed. 1950). United States v. Curtiss–Wright Corp., 299 U.S. 304, 316 (1936). Penhallow v. Doane, 3 U.S. (3 Dall.) 54, 90 (1795). Curtiss–Wright Corp., 299 U.S. at 317 (quoting 5 ELLIOTT’S DEBATES 212). 106758581 844 3/9/2016 11:31 PM NEW ENGLAND LAW REVIEW [Vol. 39:839 the states did. They clearly did not. As Thomas Paine put it in 1783: “In short, we have no other national sovereignty than as United States.”30 On May 15, 1776, the Second Continental Congress resolved that Crown authority “should be totally suppressed.”31 On June 7, Richard Henry Lee moved a resolution that the colonies “are absolved from all allegiance to the British crown, and that all political connection between them and the State of Great Britain is, and ought to be, totally dissolved ….”32 The resolution further called for efforts to form foreign alliances, and that a committee be appointed “to prepare and digest the form of a Confederation to be entered into between the colonies ….”33 It was approved on July 2, 1776.34 This was the legally effective declaration of independence. When the vote on Lee’s resolution was postponed for three weeks (in the hope that more states would approve independence, as they did), the Congress also appointed a committee to draw up what we know as the Declaration of Independence—just in case Congress should vote for independence. Only after it did so, on July 2, did Congress debate the Declaration of Independence, approving it on July 4, 1776.35 Independence was the national act of the states collectively, “in General Congress, Assembled.”36 II. THE DECLARATION OF INDEPENDENCE A. Secession or Revolution? John Locke is the ultimate source of the “social compact” theory of government.37 The colonies might be said to have “seceded” from the British Empire—although they never did say so, and there was no such legal entity as the British Empire. They asserted no right to renounce at will the connection to Britain. No language in the Declaration of Independence 30. 31. 32. 33. 34. 35. 36. 37. The American Crisis XIII, in 1 THE COMPLETE WRITINGS OF THOMAS PAINE 230, 234 (Philip S. Foner ed., 1945). MAIER, supra note 21, at 37 (quoting 4 JOURNALS OF THE CONTINENTAL CONGRESS 1774–1789, at 357–58 (Worthington Chauncey Ford ed., 1906)). MAIER, supra note 21, at 41; see also 1 JONATHAN ELLIOT, THE DEBATES ON THE ADOPTION OF THE FEDERAL CONSTITUTION 55 (Burt Franklin Reprints, 2d ed. 1974) (1836). ELLIOT, supra note 32, at 55. Id. at 55–56. Id. at 56. THE DECLARATION OF INDEPENDENCE para. 4 (U.S. 1776). See generally JOHN LOCKE, TWO TREATISES OF GOVERNMENT (Peter Laslett ed., Cambridge Univ. Press 1970) (1690). 106758581 2005] 3/9/2016 11:31 PM IF AT FIRST YOU DON’T SECEDE, TRY, TRY AGAIN 845 suggests or implies that independence is a matter of withdrawal from a political compact, much less withdrawal from a political compact as a matter of right. Americans had no notion of, or even a word for secession to draw upon. Instead, they invoked a right of revolution—something entirely different, and something far from the idea that portions of a polity might come and go as they please, as Locke made quite clear: [S]uch Revolutions happen not upon every little mismanagement in publick affairs. Great mistakes in the ruling part, many wrong and inconvenient Laws, and all the slips of humane frailty will be born by the People, without mutiny or murmer. But if a long train of Abuses, Prevarications, and Artifices, all tending the same way, make the design visible to the People, and they cannot but feel, what they lie under, and see, whither they are going; ‘tis not to be wonder’d, that they should then rouze themselves, and endeavour to put the rule into such hands, which may secure to them the ends for which Government was at first erected ….38 Locke’s language is noticeably similar to Jefferson’s in the Declaration: Prudence, indeed, will dictate that Governments long established should not be changed for light and transient causes; and accordingly all experience hath shewn, that mankind are more disposed to suffer, while evils are sufferable, than to right themselves by abolishing the forms to which they are accustomed. But when a long train of abuses and usurpations, pursuing invariably the same Object evinces a design to reduce them under absolute Despotism, it is their right, it is their duty, to throw off such Government, and to provide new Guards for their future security.39 The Declaration recites “a long train of abuses”—real, exaggerated, and imaginary grievances—because the Americans believed that they had to make out a strong case of oppression in order to justify their revolution according to their own values. Professor Naylor recites some contemporary abuses of Vermont by the United States. Whether or not they rise to the level of oppression required by Locke or Jefferson, which is doubtful, the point is, the requirement of severe, protracted abuses implies that, without them, there is no right of revolution. Professor Naylor’s assumption about the impetus for the Declaration exemplifies an ancient confusion in the 38. 39. Id. § 225, at 433. THE DECLARATION OF INDEPENDENCE para. 2 (U.S. 1776). Contemporaries noted the resemblance. Richard Henry Lee said the Declaration had been “copied from Locke’s treatise on government.” MAIER, supra note 21, at 124. 106758581 846 3/9/2016 11:31 PM NEW ENGLAND LAW REVIEW [Vol. 39:839 meanings of the word “declare.”40 It might mean to ordain, to effectuate, to accomplish. It might be constitutive. But it might also mean, and in this case it does mean, merely to announce or proclaim. The Declaration of Independence did not establish American independence—it only justified it. “It was a paper issued subsequent to an action in order to explain that action.”41 And “[t]he problem of sovereignty was not solved by the Declaration of Independence.”42 Nor has anything else. B. Constitutional Status of the Declaration The Declaration of Independence is, in any event, not part of the law of the United States. Strictly speaking, it did not declare independence in the sense that it was the legislation which made America independent of Great Britain. The Second Continental Congress had already accomplished that when it approved Richard Henry Lee’s resolution two days before. Rather, Jefferson and his colleagues were, in effect, expected to produce a declaration about independence—a justification of an independence already accomplished. Thus, the Declaration did not have—and was not supposed to have—any legal effect. It is in the nature of a resolution or a legal brief, not a statute. It does not purport to declare independence. Moreover, the Declaration has never been held to be an independent source of justiciable rights.43 But the Declaration has sometimes been invoked for the opposite purpose: to subordinate the states. At the Philadelphia Convention, James Wilson—one of only six men to sign both the Declaration and the Constitution—argued that the Declaration characterized the United States collectively as vested with the powers of war and peace, and thus was paramount to the state constitutions.44 This argument I find unconvincing: it goes too far. However, it does indicate how essentially contested is almost every claim about sovereignty (a word not appearing in the Declaration or the Constitution) or paramount authority in the arguments eventuating in secession. And it refutes Professor Naylor’s claim that what 40. 41. 42. 43. 44. MAIER, supra note 21, at 160–61. GARRY WILLS, INVENTING AMERICA: JEFFERSON’S DECLARATION OF INDEPENDENCE 334 (1978). GORDON S. WOOD, THE CREATION OF THE AMERICAN REPUBLIC 1776–1787, at 354 (1972). Troxel v. Granville, 530 U.S. 57, 91 (2000) (Scalia, J., dissenting); Mark David Hall, The Declaration of Independence in the Supreme Court, in THE DECLARATION OF INDEPENDENCE: ORIGINS AND IMPACT 142, 145 (Scott Douglas Gerber ed., 2002). See JOHN LANSING, JR., THE DELEGATE FROM NEW YORK 69 (Joseph Reese Strayer ed., 1939). 106758581 2005] 3/9/2016 11:31 PM IF AT FIRST YOU DON’T SECEDE, TRY, TRY AGAIN 847 he calls the “nationalist theory” was not articulated until the 1830s.45 James Madison, Alexander Hamilton, James Wilson, Rufus King, and others articulated it during and after the Federal Convention. It is rather the compact theory which was unknown to the Framers and was first articulated by Madison and Jefferson in the Kentucky and Virginia Resolutions of 1798.46 III. FROM THE DECLARATION TO THE CONSTITUTION The United States of America, as some sort of loose political union, was created by the Articles of Confederation, which Vermont was not allowed to sign. Professor Naylor ignores the Articles, which recognized a confederation of states—albeit not quite fully sovereign states—but which also provided that the union, such as it was, would “be perpetual.” If it was a perpetual union, secession was of course forbidden. In the Northwest Ordinance of 1787, the perpetuity of the Union, its territories, and any states created from its territories was likewise affirmed: The said territory, and the States which may be formed therein, shall forever remain a part of this confederacy of the United States of America, subject to the articles of Confederation, and to such alterations therein as shall be constitutionally made; and to all the acts and ordinances of the United States in Congress assembled, conformable thereto.47 The powers conferred on Congress by the Articles, as limited as they were, certainly precluded full state sovereignty. Congress had total control over foreign relations, treaties (states could not impose taxes inconsistent with national treaties), and decisions as to war and peace, military and naval forces (with some limitations). It had authority over boundary disputes between states (such as the New York/Vermont controversy). It had authority over weights and measures, the post office, and it could regulate the value of coin struck by states.48 It could requisition funds from the states. True, there was no enforcement mechanism, but the states had nonetheless assumed the obligation to comply with these requests.49 45. 46. 47. 48. 49. NAYLOR, supra note 1, at 78. JOHN C. MILLER, CRISIS IN FREEDOM: THE ALIEN AND SEDITION ACTS 170 (1951). Northwest [Territorial] Ordinance, in 1 SOURCES AND DOCUMENTS OF UNITED STATES CONSTITUTIONS, 2d ser. 383, 388 (William F. Swindler ed., 1982). ARTICLES OF CONFEDERATION, arts. VI, IX.; see also WOOD, supra note 42, at 359. ARTTICLES OF CONFEDERATION, arts. VIII, XIII; KEITH L. DOUGHERTY, COLLECTIVE ACTION UNDER THE ARTICLES OF CONFEDERATION 5 & n.7 (2001). 106758581 848 3/9/2016 11:31 PM NEW ENGLAND LAW REVIEW [Vol. 39:839 IV. THE CONSTITUTION The Constitution which replaced the Articles was intended and universally understood, by friends and foes alike, to strengthen the Union. It did not purport to make the Union less binding. The Framers took it for granted that the Union was perpetual and indissoluble. This was the Union which Vermont freely chose to enter in 1791. Professor Naylor, invoking the always-suspect argument from omission, asserts that nowhere in the Constitution do the states renounce their “sovereignty.”50 Nowhere do they affirm their sovereignty either. Indeed, to assume that the language of the Constitution is the language of the states is to beg the question. The word “sovereignty” is not in the Constitution. As Supreme Court Justice James Wilson stated, “To the constitution of the United States the term SOVEREIGN is totally unknown.”51 The argument from omission is actually an argument against Professor Naylor: sovereignty—state sovereignty—had been affirmed, explicitly, by the Articles.52 Its omission from the Constitution could hardly have been an oversight. As for Professor Naylor’s claim that “[b]y international law sovereignty cannot be surrendered by implication, but only by an express act,”53 it is unreferenced and apparently false. Many clauses of the Constitution, as discussed below, could be considered express acts of renunciation of sovereignty. Besides, why would an advocate of the independence of self-constituted groups such as Professor Naylor pay any more heed to international law than he does to national law? John Remington Graham, a neo-Confederate secessionist polemic recommended by Professor Naylor,54 quotes Alexander Hamilton in The Federalist No. 22 as offering some support for the state compact theory— “that a party to a compact has a right to revoke that compact”55—, at least in allowing that “the doctrine itself has had respectable advocates.”56 This could not be more wrong, or more perverse. Hamilton is bringing to a rhetorical climax a strong denunciation of government under the Articles for its incapacity to enact credible economic policies: 50. 51. 52. 53. 54. 55. 56. NAYLOR, supra note 1, at 86. Chisholm v. Georgia, 2 U.S. (2 Dall.) 419, 454 (1793). ARTICLES OF CONFEDERATION, art. II (“Each State retains its sovereignty, freedom and independence, and every power, jurisdiction and right, which is not by this confederation expressly delegated to the United States, in Congress assembled.”). NAYLOR, supra note 1, at 86. See supra note 13. THE FEDERALIST NO. 22, at 146 (Alexander Hamilton) (Jacob E. Cooke ed., 1961). Id., quoted in GRAHAM, supra note 13, at 99. 106758581 2005] 3/9/2016 11:31 PM IF AT FIRST YOU DON’T SECEDE, TRY, TRY AGAIN 849 It has not a little contributed to the infirmities of the existing federal system, that it never had a ratification by the PEOPLE. Resting on no better foundation than the consent of the several Legislatures; it has been exposed to frequent and intricate questions concerning the validity of its powers; and has in some instances given birth to the enormous doctrine of a right of legislative repeal. Owing its ratification to the law of a State, it has been contended, that the same authority might repeal the law by which it was ratified. However gross a heresy it may be, to maintain that a PARTY to a COMPACT has a right to revoke that COMPACT, the doctrine itself has had respectable advocates. The possibility of a question of this nature, proves the necessity of laying the foundations of our national government deeper than in the mere sanction of delegated authority. The fabric of American Empire ought to rest on the solid basis of THE CONSENT OF THE PEOPLE. The streams of national power ought to flow immediately from that pure original fountain of all legitimate authority. 57 In the first place, for Hamilton, the doctrine of state “legislative repeal,” i.e., nullification or secession revoking the compact, is a gross heresy, even under the Articles of Confederation. Although it has “respectable advocates,” they are fundamentally wrong.58 But the mere “possibility” of entertaining this heresy proves the necessity of founding a new national government under the Constitution on another basis than an interstate compact. The new government must derive its authority from the consent of the people, not from the state legislatures. Hamilton cannot mean (as John C. Calhoun would later argue) the consent of the people in and of the states from “the peoples,” not “the people” of the United States.59 If that were so, the peoples of the states, presumably in conventions, could withdraw their states from the compact—as in 1861. But Hamilton clearly says that the asserted right to revoke the so-called compact is a gross heresy, without qualifying that in favor of conventions as opposed to legislatures.60 The new government, deriving its authority directly from “We, the People of the United States,” is not a compact between states. It is an independent expression of the will of the American people, just as the state governments are expressions of their will at another level. Or, as Supreme Court Justice Paterson explained in 1795: “[T]he 57. 58. 59. 60. Id. at 145–46. Id. See id. Id. 106758581 850 3/9/2016 11:31 PM NEW ENGLAND LAW REVIEW [Vol. 39:839 people of the United States … are … the people of a single state.”61 By definition, the atom cannot be split; by definition, sovereignty cannot be divided. But the atom has been split, and sovereignty has been divided. Divided sovereignty is what Hamilton called “the political monster of an imperium in imperio.”62 Yet he believed, or at least wrote, that the states “would clearly retain all rights” of sovereignty “not exclusively delegated” to the national government.63 John C. Calhoun, far removed from Hamilton’s centralizing nationalism, agreed that sovereignty could not be divided, although he too believed that sovereign powers could be divided.64 Since sovereignty is by definition political power, any distinction between sovereignty and sovereign rights or sovereign powers is meaningless. Politics is about power. If, for instance, all the powers of sovereignty are delegated, what remains of sovereignty? Also meaningless is what Alexis de Tocqueville called “the doctrine of the sovereignty of the people,”65 the traditional American doctrine that “the people” are sovereign, something even Calhoun affirmed.66 But that was how the proponents of the Constitution tried to escape the question whether the national government or the states were sovereign.67 Then, the next question is, which people? The people of the nation or the people of the states? The Preamble to the Constitution states that one of its purposes is “to form a more perfect union.”68 More perfect than what? More perfect than the Articles of Confederation, obviously. As the Supreme Court stated in Texas v. White in 1868, “It is difficult to convey the idea of indissoluble unity more clearly than by these words. What can be indissoluble if a perpetual Union, made more perfect, is not?”69 61. 62. 63. 64. 65. 66. 67. 68. 69. Penhallow v. Doane, 3 U.S. (3 Dall.) 53, 93 (1795). THE FEDERALIST NO. 15, at 93 (Alexander Hamilton) (Jacob E. Cooke ed., 1961). THE FEDERALIST NO. 32, at 200 (Alexander Hamilton) (Jacob E. Cooke ed., 1961). CALHOUN, DISQUISITION AND DISCOURSE, supra note 18, at 138–39. See ALEXIS DE TOCQUEVILLE, DEMOCRACY IN AMERICA 36–39 (Henry Reeve trans., Legal Classics Library spec. ed. 1988) (1835). CALHOUN, DISQUISITION AND DISCOURSE, supra note 18, at 138; THOMAS M. COOLEY, A TREATISE ON THE CONSTITUTIONAL LIMITATIONS WHICH REST UPON THE LEGISLATIVE POWER OF THE STATES OF THE AMERICAN UNION 28 (Leslie B. Adams 1987) (1868); see also EDWARD S. CORWIN, LIBERTY AGAINST GOVERNMENT: THE RISE, FLOWERING AND DECLINE OF A FAMOUS JURIDICAL CONCEPT 10 (1948). See WOOD, supra note 42, at 530–32. U.S. CONST. pmbl. Texas v. White, 74 U.S. (7 Wall.) 700, 725 (1869). Remarkably, the pro-Southern (“doughface”) lame-duck Democratic President James Buchanan articulated all these arguments in his last message to Congress on December 3, 1860. See JAMES M. MCPHERSON, BATTLE CRY OF FREEDOM: THE CIVIL WAR ERA 246 (1988). However, Buchanan believed he had no power to coerce seceding states whereas his successor, 106758581 2005] 3/9/2016 11:31 PM IF AT FIRST YOU DON’T SECEDE, TRY, TRY AGAIN 851 The states clearly renounced their sovereignty in Article VI, Section 1, which provides that the Constitution and laws of the United States “shall be the supreme Law of the Land; and the Judges in every State shall be bound thereby, any Thing in the Constitution or Laws of any State to the Contrary notwithstanding.”70 Thus, all Congress has to do to thwart secession is to pass a law against it. Professor Naylor asserts, “Just as a group has a right to form, so too does it have a right to disband, to subdivide itself, or withdraw from a larger unit.”71 This might be good moral law,72 were there such a thing, but it is bad constitutional law. The Constitution provides that “no new State shall be formed or erected within the Jurisdiction of any other State; nor any State be formed by the Junction of two or more States, or Parts of States, without the Consent of the Legislatures of the States concerned as well as of the Congress.”73 John C. Calhoun pointed to a feature of the original Constitution, which, he maintained, indicated what he called the “federal” character of the Union, i.e., its character as a confederacy of sovereign states. He referred to the original arrangement whereby U.S. Senators were elected by state legislatures.74 But the Seventeenth Amendment, providing for the popular election of Senators, altered that arrangement in 1913.75 Other Constitutional amendments, notably the Reconstruction Amendments, arguably rule out secession even if it had been previously permissible. Under the Guarantee Clause, “[t]he United States shall guarantee to every State in this Union a Republican Form of Government ….”76 At first 70. 71. 72. 73. 74. 75. 76. Abraham Lincoln, believed otherwise. U.S. CONST. art. VI, § 1, cl. 2. NAYLOR, supra note 1, at 77. See, e.g., ALLEN BUCHANAN, SECESSION: THE MORALITY OF POLITICAL DIVORCE FROM FORT SUMTER TO LITHUANIA AND QUEBEC ch. 4 (1991); LUDWIG VON MISES, NATION, STATE, AND ECONOMY: CONTRIBUTIONS TO THE POLITICS AND HISTORY OF OUR TIME 34 (Leland B. Yeager trans., 1983) (discussing the liberal nationalism of “freedomminded” people outside political associations); MURRAY N. ROTHBARD, THE ETHICS OF LIBERTY 181 (1982) (questioning whether Laissez-fairists would recognize secession as a moral right of government). Buchanan, however, imposes stringent conditions on the right to secede—he does not, as do Rothbard and Professor Naylor, believe that a group has a moral right to secede at pleasure. U.S. CONST. art. IV, § 3, cl. 1. U.S. CONST. art. I, § 3, cl. 1; see CALHOUN, DISQUISITION AND DISCOURSE, supra note 18, at 155. U.S. CONST. amend. XVII. U.S. CONST. art. IV, § 4. See generally WILLIAM M. WIECEK, THE GUARANTEE CLAUSE OF THE U.S. CONSTITUTION 290–91 (1972) (noting that the Framers “did make it clear that the [Guarantee Clause] established federal supremacy over the states, 106758581 852 3/9/2016 11:31 PM NEW ENGLAND LAW REVIEW [Vol. 39:839 blush, that looks like Federal support for state sovereignty, especially since the Clause further provides for protection against invasion and, on application by the state, “domestic Violence.”77 That is its character, according to James Madison in The Federalist No. 43.78 But Madison also portrayed the Guarantee Clause in another light: “In cases where it may be doubtful on which side justice lies, what better umpires could be desired by two violent factions, flying to arms and tearing a State to pieces, than the representatives of confederate States not heated by the local flame?”79 Bluntly restated, the message is that the Federal Government may determine the outcome of political conflicts within a state, which is exactly what happened in Rhode Island.80 During Reconstruction, Congress literally reconstructed the governments of the secessionist states, and the Supreme Court upheld the program on the authority of the Guarantee Clause.81 Surely the feeblest of Professor Naylor’s arguments is that, because three states ratified the Constitution conditionally, all the states reserved the right to secede: “Each of these states explicitly retained exit rights.”82 However, no states “explicitly retained” any such rights.83 Indeed, 77. 78. 79. 80. 81. 82. 83. which was to be preserved by the use of force to put down insurrectionary challenges, if necessary”). U.S. CONST. art. IV, § 4. THE FEDERALIST NO. 43, at 291–93 (James Madison) (Jacob E. Cooke ed., 1961) (noting that “protection against invasion is due from every society to the parts composing it” and “[p]rotection against domestic violence is added with equal propriety”). Id. at 294. See Luther v. Borden, 48 U.S. (7 How.) 1 (1849). See generally GEORGE M. DENNISON, THE DORR WAR: REPUBLICANISM ON TRIAL, 1831–1861, at xiii (1976) (focusing “on a pivotal moment in the historical career of the idea of popular sovereignty and its corollary of peaceable revolution”). Texas v. White, 74 U.S. (7 Wall.) 700, 729 (1869). NAYLOR, supra note 1, at 86–87. The only language which even comes close to asserting a right to secede is in the Virginia Form of Ratification, which declared “that the powers granted under the Constitution being derived from the people of the United States may be resumed by them whensoever the same shall be perverted to their injury or oppression and that every power not granted thereby remains with them and at their will ….” 10 THE DOCUMENTARY HISTORY OF THE RATIFICATION OF THE CONSTITUTION 1546 (John P. Kaminski & Gaspare J. Saladino eds., 1993). But all this does is reiterate the Lockean right of revolution as rehashed by Jefferson in the Declaration of Independence language that nearly all Americans would assent to, in the abstract: the Lockean/Jeffersonian position of a right of revolution when oppressions become intolerable, not an unconditional right of secession. See supra Part II.A. It does not even hint at the compact theory of the Federal Union. It refers to the people of the 106758581 2005] 3/9/2016 11:31 PM IF AT FIRST YOU DON’T SECEDE, TRY, TRY AGAIN 853 Professor Naylor does not cite any such reservations of rights because there is nothing to cite. For one thing, New York replaced its conditional ratification with unconditional ratification plus “recommendatory amendments,”84 so we are down to two states. If conditional ratification implies a right to secede, then unconditional ratification renounces the right to secede. That means that forty-eight states other than Virginia and Rhode Island—including Vermont!—have no right to secede. Professor Naylor also neglects to mention what the “condition” was. The reluctant ratifying states demanded a Bill of Rights as their condition of ratification, and they got one. So even the conditionally ratifying states have no right to secede—a deal is a deal. Nothing suggests that Virginia and Rhode Island supposed that the Bill of Rights did not satisfy their conditions for ratification. They claimed no right to secede, and they made no moves to secede. The resolves of the ratifying states, whether they ratified conditionally or unconditionally, never claim or refer to a right of secession. The issue before them was not getting out of a Federal Union, but getting into one. We know what they chose to do. Perhaps most importantly, the Constitution nowhere acknowledges a right of secession. Indeed, the subject was never even mentioned at the Federal Convention.85 If it was ever mentioned in the debates of the state ratifying conventions, no secessionist has ever found these mentions. And the right was never claimed in any state constitution. V. FROM RATIFICATION TO THE NULLIFICATION CRISIS The first stirrings of ideas which even intimate the constitutionality of secession are to be found in the Kentucky and Virginia Resolutions of 1798—resolutions of the legislatures of those states condemning as unconstitutional the Alien and Sedition Acts.86 They were denounced by all Northern legislatures, and all the other Southern legislatures responded to them with silence.87 They assert state sovereignty and the compact theory 84. 85. 86. 87. United States, not the state of Virginia. John P. Kaminski, New York: The Reluctant Pillar, in THE RELUCTANT PILLAR: NEW YORK AND THE ADOPTION OF THE FEDERAL CONSTITUTION 48, 111, 114 (Stephen L. Schechter ed., 1985). MAX FARRAND, THE FRAMING OF THE CONSTITUTION OF THE UNITED STATES 206 (1913). Kentucky Resolutions, 10 Nov. 1798, 14 Nov. 1799, in 5 THE FOUNDERS’ CONSTITUTION 131–35 (Philip B. Kurland & Ralph Lerner eds., 1987); James Madison, Virginia Resolutions, 21 Dec. 1798, in 5 THE FOUNDERS’ CONSTITUTION supra, at 135–36. MILLER, supra note 46, at 171–72 n.30; FORREST MCDONALD, STATES’ RIGHTS AND THE UNION: IMPERIUM IN IMPERIO, 1776–1876, at 43 (2000). 106758581 854 3/9/2016 11:31 PM NEW ENGLAND LAW REVIEW [Vol. 39:839 of the Federal Union, and Jefferson’s Kentucky Resolution deduces from that a state power of “nullification,” a word he here introduced into political discourse.88 But neither Jefferson’s nor Madison’s resolutions (Madison wrote the Virginia Resolution) asserts a right of secession. On the contrary, the resolutions confirm each state’s attachment to the Union. Nullification is not secession. Significantly, Madison had denounced the secession doctrine in Philadelphia in 1787: The doctrine laid down by the law of Nations in the case of treaties is that a breach of any one article by any of the parties, frees the other parties from their engagements. In the case of a union of people under one Constitution, the nature of the pact has always been understood to exclude such an interpretation.89 In other words, if international law allows secession, as Professor Naylor has claimed,90 then the U.S. Constitution overrides international law as to secession. Nothing in the Constitution subjects the United States to international law as such. But anyway, Professor Naylor’s unreferenced opinion is belied by all the constitutions of real nation–states. None recognizes a right of secession, not even Switzerland’s, which is Professor Naylor’s acknowledged model for an independent Vermont.91 How can international law, the law of nations, affirm a right which no nation affirms? In fact international law, though it is not perfectly clear on this point as on so many others, is hostile to secession.92 That the Constitution was, in some sense, a “compact”—Professor Naylor has picked up on the word93—it was a commonplace in the political discourse of the day. Even Alexander Hamilton used that language, 88. 89. 90. 91. 92. 93. Kentucky Resolutions, supra note 86, at 135. 2 THE RECORDS OF THE FEDERAL CONVENTION OF 1787, at 93 (Max Farrand ed., rev. ed. 1966). See supra text accompanying note 53. See NAYLOR, supra note 1, at 89–94. “Any attempt aimed at the partial or total disruption of the national unity and the territorial integrity of a country is incompatible with the Purposes and Principles of the Charter of the United Nations.” Declaration on the Granting of Independence to Colonial Countries and Peoples, G.A. Res. 1514, 15 U.N. GAOR, 15th Sess., Supp. 16, at 66, art. 6, U.N. Doc. A/4684 (1960), quoted in LEE C. BUCHHEIT, SECESSION: THE LEGITIMACY OF SELF-DETERMINATION 86 (1978). This is not to say that the world community has never sympathized with some secessionist movements, such as those of the Soviet republics (ironically, the Soviet Constitution was unique in purporting to recognize a right of secession). But it has not recognized a general right of secession in international law. See NAYLOR, supra note 1, at 77–78. 106758581 2005] 3/9/2016 11:31 PM IF AT FIRST YOU DON’T SECEDE, TRY, TRY AGAIN 855 although he was then referring to the Confederation under the Articles.94 That this arch-nationalist spoke in those terms suggests that social compact language does not necessarily entail a right of secession, especially since the Articles of Confederation, to which he was referring, explicitly preclude secession. At the Federal Convention, Oliver Ellsworth, a future Federalist and U.S. Supreme Court Chief Justice, thought that the act of unification “becomes a compact from which no one of the parties can recede of itself.”95 Nobody contradicted him. Supreme Court Justice Henry Baldwin, for instance, in his Charles River Bridge concurrence in 1837, stated that the Constitution was not merely a compact—it was a corporation created by charter or grant from the states; and yet, “The state has made an irrevocable restriction on its own once plenary sovereignty, which it cannot loosen, without the concurrence of such a number of states, as are competent to amend the constitution.”96 For states, the Federal Union is like a Roach Motel: they check in, but they do not check out. As a practical matter, that was settled by the Civil War. Professor Naylor also invokes, as a precedent for secession, the proceedings of the Hartford Convention in 1815, without going into the issues there.97 It was a gathering of delegates from the New England states, which were opposed to the War of 1812.98 The Convention never did more than hint at secession.99 With the almost simultaneous arrival of news of a peace treaty and the spectacular American victory in New Orleans, Americans turned away with revulsion from the Hartford Convention and the secessionism it was supposed to stand for.100 Secessionism was everywhere discredited for almost a generation. The flirtation with secession—which was diametrically opposed to the party’s nationalist 94. See THE FEDERALIST NO. 21, at 130 (Alexander Hamilton) (Jacob E. Cooke ed., 1961). 95. 2 THE RECORDS OF THE FEDERAL CONVENTION OF 1787, at 91 (Max Farrand ed., rev. ed. 1966). 96. Proprietors of the Charles River Bridge v. Proprietors of the Warren Bridge, 9 L. Ed. 773, 940 (1837) (Baldwin, J., concurring). Justice Baldwin’s concurrence appears in HENRY BALDWIN, A GENERAL VIEW OF THE ORIGIN AND NATURE OF THE CONSTITUTION OF THE UNITED STATES 134, 138 (Da Capo Press 1970) (1837), reprinted in 9 L. Ed. 938 (1837). See also generally STANLEY I. KUTLER, PRIVILEGE AND CREATIVE DESTRUCTION: THE CHARLES RIVER BRIDGE CASE (1971) (providing legal, political and historical background). 97. See NAYLOR, supra note 1, at 78. 98. MCDONALD, supra note 87, at 69–70. 99. RICHARD BUEL, JR., SECURING THE REVOLUTION: IDEOLOGY IN AMERICAN POLITICS, 1789–1815, at 285 (1972). 100. Id. at 289–91; DONALD R. HICKEY, THE WAR OF 1812: A FORGOTTEN CONFLICT 308 (1989). 106758581 856 3/9/2016 11:31 PM NEW ENGLAND LAW REVIEW [Vol. 39:839 principles—eliminated the Federalist Party from national and, for the most part, state politics.101 VI. NULLIFICATION VS. SECESSION Professor Naylor asserts that “numerous” states nullified federal acts prior to the Battle of Fort Sumter,102 which occurred on April 12, 1861.103 Such incidents were not numerous, however. In citing Kentucky (1799) as his first example, Professor Naylor must be construing Jefferson’s Kentucky Resolution as nullifying the Alien and Sedition Acts.104 But it did not purport to do so. Rather, it invited the other states to join Kentucky in collectively nullifying the Acts.105 It was only a resolution—a statement of principle—like the other one Jefferson wrote in 1776. What has often happened is that individuals violated federal law—and state law—when they could, with the complicity of state officials (such as during Prohibition). That is not nullification. States have sometimes connived at violations of federal law. Georgia defied federal law by expelling its Native Americans, despite contrary Supreme Court decisions—setting a bad example for South Carolina.106 But defiance is not nullification, any more than organized crime is legislation. Only one state—South Carolina—ever purported formally to nullify a federal statute, the Tariff of 1828.107 South Carolina was not successful, although the state’s intransigence eventually influenced the amendment of the Tariff. Still, frequent or not, this kind of “nullification” does not strengthen the legal case for secession because it was a simple matter of “might-makes-right.” That is an argument Professor Naylor does not want to rely on because now the federal government has the “might.” The argument for nullification is not an argument for secession, as even John C. Calhoun acknowledged. Nullification, as Calhoun explained, is a way of working through the system. Secession is a rejection of the 101. See SAMUEL ELIOT MORISON, HARRISON GRAY OTIS 1765–1848: THE URBANE FEDERALIST 342–46, 362 (1969). 102. NAYLOR, supra note 1, at 78, 85–86. 103. See generally RICHARD N. CURRENT, LINCOLN AND THE FIRST SHOT 11, 207–08 (1963) (discussing the immediate run-up to Fort Sumter and the Civil War). 104. NAYLOR, supra note 1, at 85. 105. MILLER, supra note 46, at 170. Actually, there were two Kentucky Resolutions. See supra note 86. The second one, not authored by Jefferson, contained the proposal for joint state action. Id. Jefferson’s Resolution was not even that practical. 106. JOHN NIVEN, JOHN C. CALHOUN AND THE PRICE OF UNION: A BIOGRAPHY 187–88 (1988). 107. See WILLIAM W. FREEHLING, PRELUDE TO CIVIL WAR: THE NULLIFICATION CONTROVERSY IN SOUTH CAROLINA 1816–1836, at 1 (1966). 106758581 2005] 3/9/2016 11:31 PM IF AT FIRST YOU DON’T SECEDE, TRY, TRY AGAIN 857 system. They are, he wrote, “totally dissimilar.”108 Besides, a right of state nullification—meaning, a state’s right to nullify a federal statute as unconstitutional—does not include a right of secession, unless secession is already part of the constitutional order (which begs the question). Nullification is an argument within, not against, constitutional discourse. If anything, nullification implies acquiescence in the Constitution, as Calhoun appreciated. Nullification is merely a method of neutralizing an allegedly unconstitutional statute, like judicial review. Which federal statutes does Professor Naylor want Vermont to nullify? All of them? VII. SECESSION IN PRACTICE: THE CIVIL WAR Every provision of the U.S. Constitution relied on, then or later, to justify secession has its counterpart in the Confederate Constitution of the states which made secession a reality—for a while. The Confederate Constitution includes the Supremacy Clause and the Guarantee Clause. In lieu of the reference to forming “a more perfect Union,” the Confederate Constitution states: “We, the people of the Confederate States, each state acting in its sovereign and independent character, in order to form a permanent federal government ….”109 The reference to forming a “permanent federal government” comes closer to proclaiming an indissoluble Union than does any language in the U.S. Constitution. Given the previous discordant interpretations of these provisions, the Confederate Constitution might be expected to assert explicitly the right to secession upon which its legitimacy, if it had any, rested. Remarkably, it did nothing of the sort. And, in fact, the Confederacy repressed those who would secede from secession—the Southern Unionists, who were in the majority in certain areas. The Confederacy sought to conquer the Appalachian Unionists under Governor Andrew Johnson in eastern Tennessee. The Appalachian Unionists, in turn, petitioned the state legislature to secede from Tennessee—to secede from secession.110 The Confederacy vainly resisted the secession from Virginia by the Unionists in the area that was reconstituted as West Virginia.111 Clearly, Confederate 108. John C. Calhoun, [Letter] to James Hamilton, Jr., [Governor of South Carolina], in 11 THE PAPERS OF JOHN C. CALHOUN 613, 630–32 (Clyde N. Wilson ed., 1978). Professor Naylor’s constitutional source, H. Newcomb Morse, agreed that nullification “falls far short of secession.” MORSE, supra note 12, at 419. 109. CONST. CONFEDERATE STATES OF AMERICA, in 3 SOURCES AND DOCUMENTS OF THE UNITED STATES CONSTITUTION, 2d ser. 125 (Donald J. Musch ed., 1985). 110. CARLETON BEALS, WAR WITHIN A WAR: THE CONFEDERACY AGAINST ITSELF 81 (1965). 111. Which, in turn, set up a situation ripe for secession from secession from secession: twenty-four counties (with sixty percent of the population) were Unionist, and 106758581 858 3/9/2016 11:31 PM NEW ENGLAND LAW REVIEW [Vol. 39:839 secession was not principled. It was self-interested, opportunistic, and hypocritical. Professor Naylor even rehashes the wails of pro-Confederate nostalgics about the circumstances surrounding the ratification of the Fourteenth Amendment. To be sure, the states in rebellion were required to ratify the Thirteenth and Fourteenth Amendments as conditions for readmission to the Union; and there were some irregularities.112 But if states can set conditions for entry into the Union, as Professor Naylor approved for the 1780s, why should not the states, in Congress assembled, set conditions for (re)entry into the Union in the 1860s? Congress had often done so before. Texas was admitted subject to several conditions, among them territorial concessions.113 Consent is mutual. The South’s name for the Civil War—the War Between the States—has some truth to it. It was not just a war between the national government and the states. If it were, the states would have quickly triumphed, because a national American state scarcely existed.114 It was a war waged by most of the states rallying to what they considered their federal government against other states. Vermont was one of those states. Professor Naylor overlooks that the national government was differently composed in the 1860s than it is today, in a way that John C. Calhoun considered important. It was truly what James Madison called it, “in strictness neither a national nor a federal constitution; but a composition of both.”115 U.S. Senators were not elected by popular vote until 1913. Previously, they were elected by state legislatures. Thus, they represented the states directly. In order to return to the Union, the renegade states had to satisfy their fellow states (including Vermont), not a national 112. 113. 114. 115. twenty-four were pro-Confederate and opposed “dismemberment.” RICHARD ORR CURRY, A HOUSE DIVIDED: A STUDY OF STATEHOOD POLITICS AND THE COPPERHEAD MOVEMENT IN WEST VIRGINIA 5–6, 137 (1964). The gratuitous incorporation of the latter counties, which were contiguous to (what was left of) Virginia, shows that neither side held a principled opinion in favor of self-determination through secession. It was reminiscent of Westside Vermont’s domination of the Eastside. See infra text accompanying notes 166-75. MCDONALD, supra note 87, at 212; see GRAHAM, supra note 13, at 389–93, 401–02. Joint Resolution for Annexing Texas to the United States, S.J. Res. 8, 28th Cong., 5 Stat. 797–98 (1845) (referring to the “terms” and “conditions” to which Texas had to accede in order to be admitted to the Union). STEPHEN SKOWRONEK, BUILDING A NEW AMERICAN STATE: THE EXPANSION OF NATIONAL ADMINISTRATIVE CAPACITIES, 1877–1920, at 5 (1982); see also GEORG WILHELM FRIEDRICH HEGEL, THE PHILOSOPHY OF HISTORY 84–87 (Dover Pubs.1956) (1899). THE FEDERALIST NO. 39, at 257 (James Madison) (Jacob E. Cooke ed., 1961). 106758581 2005] 3/9/2016 11:31 PM IF AT FIRST YOU DON’T SECEDE, TRY, TRY AGAIN 859 bureaucracy or an imagined cabal of vindictive Radical Republican politicians. And Professor Naylor’s beloved Vermont, which he encourages to secede, was as opposed to secession as any state in the Union during the Civil War. Out of a population of 300,000,116 Vermont provided 30,000 men to the Union army.117 Vermont “rose” to repress secession: The people of Vermont rose with the grand uprising of the North; and thence forward for four years the main thought of the people of the State, without distinction of party, sex or condition, was how they should do the most to aid the Government in the task of quelling rebellion, and preserving the union of the States.118 Relative to population, Vermont incurred a higher rate of fatalities than any state in the Union.119 With no sense of irony, Professor Naylor pays tribute to the tremendous effort made by Vermont to suppress secession.120 Historians have long since discredited the deplorable “Birth of a Nation” fantasies,121 although Professor Naylor recommends a volume which exhumes them.122 The Reconstruction governments made 116. 117. 118. 119. 1 G.G. BENEDICT, VERMONT IN THE CIVIL WAR 1861–1865, at 25 n.1 (1886). See generally id. Id. at 17. FRANK M. BRYAN, YANKEE POLITICS IN RURAL VERMONT 16 (1974). Professor Bryan is now a supporter of Vermont independence. See supra note 7. 120. See NAYLOR, supra note 1, at 48. 121. See generally ERIC FONER, RECONSTRUCTION: AMERICA’S UNFINISHED REVOLUTION, 1863–1877 (Henry Steele Comminger & Richard B. Morris eds., 1988); JOHN HOPE FRANKLIN, RECONSTRUCTION: AFTER THE CIVIL WAR (1961) (offering a balanced view of American life during the Reconstruction era); KENNETH M. STAMPP, THE ERA OF RECONSTRUCTION, 1865–1877, at viii (1965) (discussing the “brief political history of reconstruction [in] an attempt to give more general currency to the findings of scholars during the past few decades”). 122. Naylor, supra note 13. Graham has really gone over the top with his nostalgia for the antebellum and Civil War South. He explains that vast numbers of newly freed slaves “were confused and broken-hearted, for they had seen the bottom fall out of their world. And so they died like flies.” GRAHAM, supra note 13, at 386. The “darkies” had been so happy—thoughtless of tomorrow, as Robert E. Lee is quoted as explaining—because the master took care of all their needs, and after they put in a little work picking cotton, they could dance and sing, strummin’ on the old banjo. See id. at 385–87. I kid you not—this book makes Gone With the Wind look like Glory. Graham is a conspiracy theorist. Both the American Revolution and the Civil War were brought on, he insists, by conspiracies by “monied interests”—in the former, the East India Company and the Bank of England, id. at 76–78, 85–89; in the latter, financiers like Jay Cooke, Jacob Rothschild, and Junius Morgan, whose 106758581 860 3/9/2016 11:31 PM NEW ENGLAND LAW REVIEW [Vol. 39:839 improvements in education,123 tax reform, women’s rights, reapportionment, democratization of the franchise, penal reform, 124 per capita income, housing, diet, and other areas. Despite the same scandals and corruption which plagued railroad promotion in the North, the Reconstruction governments increased the mileage of railroad tracks in the ex-Confederate states from 8336 miles in 1865 to 11,015 miles by 1871.125 I will not affirm, because I lack the space to defend, the opinion that the Reconstruction governments were the best governments that the South ever had. But I will relate the opinion of Kenneth M. Stampp that, “granting all their mistakes, the radical governments were by far the most democratic the South had ever known.”126 The majority of Southerners, who were poor whites and freed slaves, supported the Reconstruction amendments. But it is all legally irrelevant to the secession issue, because the Fourteenth Amendment is irrelevant to the secession issue. The Amendment placed new limitations on the states, but no one has ever claimed that its purpose was to rebut the right to secede. For those who enacted it, there was no right to rebut. In Texas v. White,127 for example, the Supreme Court did not even mention the Fourteenth Amendment when it held that secession was unconstitutional.128 VIII. SECESSION AS ANARCHY: VERMONT AS A TEST CASE The argument for secession is its own best refutation. It can always be asserted against those who have asserted it. Virginia seceded from the United States, so a disgruntled Unionist minority, in effect, seceded from Virginia by creating West Virginia. During South Carolina’s nullification crisis, the majority “nullificationists” persecuted and disenfranchised the minority Unionists: “In the end, the theory of nullification succeeded in 123. 124. 125. 126. 127. 128. purchases of war bonds enabled them (somehow) to take over the banking system, id. at 345–48. The Civil War “was produced neither by secession nor by slavery, not even by cultural distinctiveness, but by a hidden cause.” Id. at 342. The occult influence is amplified by a slew of horribly-mixed metaphors he uses to claim that the conspirators’ “tentacles eventually control[led] the vital organs of the United States, with strings pulled by unseen hands ….” Id. at 347. FRANKLIN, supra note 121, at 108–09, 140–41. See also generally ROBERT C. MORRIS, READING, ’RITING, AND RECONSTRUCTION: THE EDUCATION OF FREEDMEN IN THE SOUTH, 1861–1870, at ix (1981) (detailing the Northern-based movements to educate Southern blacks and the controversies this created). STAMPP, supra, note 121, at 172–73, 182. MARK W. SUMMERS, RAILROADS, RECONSTRUCTION, AND THE GOSPEL OF PROSPERITY: AID UNDER THE RADICAL REPUBLICANS, 1865–1877, at 136 (1984). STAMPP, supra note 121, at 184–85. 74 U.S. (7 Wall.) 700 (1868). Id. at 724–25. 106758581 2005] 3/9/2016 11:31 PM IF AT FIRST YOU DON’T SECEDE, TRY, TRY AGAIN 861 establishing the majority despotism on the state level which it sought to destroy nationally.”129 In principle, the revolutionary—better yet, devolutionary—doctrine of secession can be successively applied repeatedly and indefinitely. Every creation of a majority out of a minority also creates a new minority. The multiplication of statelets is not likely to promote liberty, as Professor Naylor perhaps assumes. Small states are often more oppressive than large ones. One reason is that, as James Madison argued, they are more homogeneous and therefore less tolerant of minorities.130 Even a prosecessionist admits that “[t]he right to secession cannot be practically reconciled with a democratic form of government unless the population is perfectly homogeneous.”131 Insofar as secession is always undertaken in the name and in the direction of greater homogeneity, it tends to weaken minority rights.132 In homogeneous democratic city-states like ancient Athens, the very concept of individual rights was unknown, and the citizen was always at the disposal of the state.133 Thomas Hobbes wrote scornfully that there is no more personal freedom in democracies than in monarchies.134 Despite its homogeneity—it is the whitest as well as the most rural state in the Union135—it is possible to contemplate an independent Vermont with equanimity. This may not be so if some other states “resume” their independence. “Many Texans,” according to Professor Naylor, want to restore their republic.136 One might be uneasy about a Texas republic unrestrained by the U.S. Constitution and federal laws. But one must be 129. FREEHLING, supra note 107, at 171. 130. THE FEDERALIST NO. 10, at 63–64 (James Madison) (Jacob E. Cooke ed., 1961). Extend the sphere, and you take in a greater variety of parties and interests; you make it less probable that a majority of the whole will have a common motive to invade the rights of other citizens; or if such a common motive exists, it will be more difficult for all who feel it to discover their own strength, and to act in unison with each other. 131. 132. 133. 134. 135. 136. Id. at 64. This is perhaps the most famous, and the most important single argument in American political philosophy. McGee, supra note 12, at 473. See Martin Ostwald, Shares and Rights: “Citizenship” Greek Style and American Style, in DĒMOKRATIA: A CONVERSATION ON DEMOCRACIES, ANCIENT AND MODERN 49, 54–57 (Josiah Ober & Charles Hedrick eds., 1996) [hereinafter DĒMOKRATIA]. Robert W. Wallace, Law, Freedom, and the Concept of Citizens’ Rights in Democratic Athens, in DĒMOKRATIA, supra note 132, at 105, 106–07. THOMAS HOBBES, DE CIVE 135 (Howard Warrender, ed., Oxford 1983) (English version) (1651). NAYLOR, supra note 1, at 48. Id. at 82. Really? They control the United States; why should they want to leave it? 106758581 862 3/9/2016 11:31 PM NEW ENGLAND LAW REVIEW [Vol. 39:839 alarmed at the restoration of the state of Deseret, much of which is now the state of Utah. Deseret—and, to a great extent, the subsequent Utah territorial government—was a Mormon theocracy autocratically ruled by Brigham Young (who, like church founder Joseph Smith, was born in Vermont). The Constitution of Deseret included counterparts to the Establishment and Free Exercise Clauses,137 but that was just to placate American public opinion and improve the chances of eventual statehood. Mormon theology espoused, not the separation, but the fusion of church and state.138 In the 1860s and 1870s, non-Mormons (“Gentiles”) comprised ten to fifteen percent of the population of what had become a federal territory, yet they complained constantly of violations of their political and civil rights. The proportion of Gentiles is higher now, but they are still in the minority. A Utah subject to the unrestrained rule of its Mormon majority might reintroduce theocratic features beyond anything seen in the United States in centuries. For example, in the late 1830s, well before their arrival in Utah, the Mormons formed the Sons of Dan, or Danites, while they sojourned in Missouri. These were clandestine terrorists and death squads set up “to use violence against external foes and internal dissenters.”139 They were active in Utah throughout the 1850s.140 Who is to say they might not resume their activities in the second state of Deseret?141 There is no intent to disparage Mormons here. They have their values as I have mine. But if Utah seceded, it could only be at the behest of the Mormon majority. Its traditions are theocratic. The presence of 137. DESERET CONST. art. VIII, § 3, reprinted in 9 SOURCES AND DOCUMENTS OF UNITED STATES CONSTITUTIONS 375, 380 (William F. Swindler ed., 1979). 138. GUSTIVE O. LARSON, THE “AMERICANIZATION” OF UTAH FOR STATEHOOD 3–4 (1971) (discussing the “easy transition of high Church leaders into high civil officials” and how “the separation of executive, legislative, and judicial powers was more apparent that real” under the constitution of the Mormon state); DALE L. MORGAN, THE STATE OF DESERET 13 (1987) (discussing the overlap among religious and civic leadership). 139. Marvin S. Hill, The Rise of the Mormon Kingdom of God, in UTAH’S HISTORY 97, 102 (Richard D. Poll et al. eds., 1978). 140. NORMAN F. FURNISS, THE MORMON CONFLICT, 1850–1859, at 2, 46 & passim (1960). Sir Arthur Conan Doyle assigned the Danites a central and sensational role in his first Sherlock Holmes story. See A Study in Scarlet, in THE COMPLETE SHERLOCK HOLMES 15–86 (n.d.). 141. Another problem, which I will do no more than identify here, is state boundaries. Deseret included a far larger area than the present state of Utah. It included parts of eight other states, such as the southernmost part of California (another former republic), including San Diego. Parts of these lost territories, such as southern Idaho, even contain Mormon majorities. Texas also reluctantly relinquished much land upon admission to the Union. See supra note 113. If these states secede, they might want the return of land they relinquished as the quid pro quo of admission to the Union. 106758581 2005] 3/9/2016 11:31 PM IF AT FIRST YOU DON’T SECEDE, TRY, TRY AGAIN 863 counterparts to the Establishment and Free Exercise Clauses in the Utah Constitution142 no more assures religious freedom than did their counterparts in the Deseret Constitution.143 It is likely that if Utah seceded, the intended goals—or at least the almost certain consequences—of independence would include a much closer relationship between state and church: and not with just any, or every, church, but with the Church of Jesus Christ of Latter-day Saints.144 Secession would likely endanger minority rights. The ultimate logical consequence of secession—or its “essence,” as Abraham Lincoln put it—is anarchy.145 The principle of secession justifies unlimited political divisibility.146 The anarchist economist Murray N. Rothbard agrees: “Once admit any right of secession whatever, and there is no logical stopping-point short of the right of individual secession, which logically entails anarchism, since then individuals may secede and patronize their own defense agencies, and the State has crumbled.”147 Alexander Hamilton deplored minority obstruction of the majority will under the Articles of Confederation as a “situation” which will “sometimes border upon anarchy.”148 I use the word “anarchy” in no pejorative sense, but in its philosophical sense of a stateless society. It has had noteworthy American exponents, such as Henry David Thoreau, and it has even been claimed that a deep streak of anti-authoritarianism in the Americans’ history and character (Professor Naylor may be an example) is essentially, if often 142. UTAH CONST. art. I, § 4. Indeed, the Utah provision, while including it, elaborates on 143. 144. 145. 146. 147. 148. the First Amendment language: “There shall be no union of Church and State, nor shall any church dominate the State or interfere with its functions.” Id. Article III, peculiar to Utah, contains an irrevocable ordinance forever banning polygamy. This was a prerequisite to admission to the Union. James T. McHugh, A Liberal Theocracy: Philosophy, Theology, and Utah Constitutional Law, 60 ALB. L. REV. 1515, 1516 (1997) (noting that “[t]he express political and religious price of statehood for Utah was the abandonment of both the practice of polygamy and the theocratic system of government within that territory that had been established there by the Church of Jesus Christ of Latter Day Saints”). If the ordinance is irrevocable enough to survive secession—becoming, in effect, a bilateral international treaty—query whether the seceded state is fully sovereign. See supra note 137 and accompanying text. See Maxwell v. Dow, 176 U.S. 581, 615–16 (1900) (Harlan, J., dissenting) (citing the establishment of the Mormon Church in Utah as a hypothetical example of a violation of the privileges and immunities of citizens). MCPHERSON, supra note 69, at 247. See BUCHHEIT, supra note 92, at 28 (discussing the troubling legal and political aspects of “secessionist self-determination” and “the threat of indefinite divisibility”). ROTHBARD, supra note 72, at 181. THE FEDERALIST NO. 22, supra note 55, at 141. 106758581 864 3/9/2016 11:31 PM NEW ENGLAND LAW REVIEW [Vol. 39:839 unconsciously, anarchistic.149 Anarchists find majority rule little better than minority rule, and the majority of a majority, they observe, is usually a minority anyway.150 However, most anarchists espouse voluntary collective forms of social organization.151 What happens when majority and minority disagree? They discuss the matter. They may decide to make no decision for the time being, in case a community consensus forms. An anarchist community is not an artificial aggregation of strangers as is an electorate; it is a community. The minority, because it values the society it shares with the majority more than it does a favorable decision on a particular issue, may recede. If all else fails, the best solution, if it is possible, is for the majority and the minority to each implement its own preference.152 The political trajectory of Lysander Spooner dramatizes the anarchist logic of secession.153 In 1845, Spooner, a Massachusetts lawyer, published Part I of an unlikely best-seller, The Unconstitutionality of Slavery, whose improbable thesis is stated in its title.154 Other radical abolitionists, like 149. See generally DAVID DELEON, THE AMERICAN AS ANARCHIST: REFLECTIONS ON 150. 151. 152. 153. 154. INDIGENOUS RADICALISM (1978) (identifying varieties of radicalism as intellectual imports while showing that others represent enduring traditions); JAMES J. MARTIN, MEN AGAINST THE STATE: THE EXPOSITORS OF INDIVIDUALIST ANARCHISM IN AMERICA, 1827–1908 (Ralph Myles Pub., Inc. 1970) (discussing the lives and work of numerous American anarchists during this time period); WILLIAM O. REICHERT, PARTISANS OF FREEDOM: A STUDY IN AMERICAN ANARCHISM (1976) (providing a comprehensive and detailed history of American anarchism). ERRICO MALATESTA, THE ANARCHIST REVOLUTION: POLEMICAL ARTICLES 1924–1931, at 78 (Vernon Richards ed., 1995). The ethnographic record leaves no doubt that functioning anarchist societies are not only possible, but were common until recently. Hunter-gatherer, horticultural, and some tribal societies were anarchist. See generally HAROLD BARCLAY, PEOPLE WITHOUT GOVERNMENT: AN ANTHROPOLOGY OF ANARCHISM (1982) (describing a number of anarchist societies). The human race lived in anarchy for at least its first one million years. If anarchy were impossible, none of us would be alive today. See, e.g., ALEXANDER BERKMAN, WHAT IS COMMUNIST ANARCHISM? (1972); Peter Kropotkin, Anarchist Communism: Its Basis and Principles, in KROPOTKIN’S REVOLUTIONARY PAMPHLETS 46–78 (photo. reprint Dover Books, 1970) (Roger N. Baldwin ed., 1927) (discussing how anarchists are drawn to a communist–type society where individuals and not the state control); RUDOLPH ROCKER, ANARCHO– SYNDICALISM 82–86 (1989) (rejecting socialism as an effective way of implementing anarchist ideals and supporting syndicalism instead). See GIOVANNI BALDELLI, SOCIAL ANARCHISM 96 (1971); ERRICO MALATESTA: HIS LIFE AND IDEAS 72 (Vernon Richards ed., 1984). See REICHERT, supra note 149, at 117–40. From 1845 until its completion in 1860, Spooner revised The Unconstitutionality of Slavery several times: Part I was republished in 1846; Part II was published in 1853, 1856, and two editions appeared in 1860 (the second contained two appendices and prefatory material from 1857). For the complete version, see Lysander Spooner, The 106758581 2005] 3/9/2016 11:31 PM IF AT FIRST YOU DON’T SECEDE, TRY, TRY AGAIN 865 William Lloyd Garrison, more plausibly argued the opposite, that the Constitution protected slavery and was thus to be denounced as a “covenant with death.”155 However, many antislavery Americans naturally would agree with Spooner rather than Garrison. Then, as now, most Americans were enchanted by the Constitution as a symbol, although they might not know very much about its meaning.156 The antislavery mainstream, rejecting both extremes, acknowledged that slavery was constitutional in the states where it was already established, but that it should not be allowed to spread, and the Constitution allowed for various ways of undermining the institution. This became the ideology of the Republican Party.157 But Spooner, along with Joel Tiffany, contributed to abolitionism the “constitutional doctrine of paramount national citizenship,” with distinct state and national citizenships158— ironically, as Spooner evolved into an anarchist. By 1868, Spooner had become an anarchist. From 1867 to 1870, he published three tracts under the general title No Treason, the last with the subtitle The Constitution of No Authority.159 His main argument was that 155. 156. 157. 158. 159. Unconstitutionality of Slavery (1860), reprinted in 4 THE COLLECTED WORKS OF LYSANDER SPOONER (Charles Shively ed., unpaginated photo. reprint 1971) (arguing that natural justice and natural law, as well as the omission of any reference to slavery in the text of the Constitution, made slavery unconstitutional). PHILLIP S. PALUDAN, A COVENANT WITH DEATH: THE CONSTITUTION, LAW, AND EQUALITY IN THE CIVIL WAR ERA 3 (1975) (quoting Garrison’s abolitionist newspaper, THE LIBERATOR, July 7, 1854); see also The United States Constitution, in SELECTIONS FROM THE WRITINGS AND SPEECHES OF WILLIAM LLOYD GARRISON 302– 15 (1852). See generally MICHAEL KAMMEN, A MACHINE THAT WOULD GO OF ITSELF: THE CONSTITUTION IN AMERICAN CULTURE, at xi (1987) (describing “the place of the Constitution in the public consciousness and symbolic life of the American people” including “the perceptions and misperceptions, uses and abuses, knowledge and ignorance of ordinary Americans”). See generally ERIC FONER, FREE SOIL, FREE LABOR, FREE MEN: THE IDEOLOGY OF THE REPUBLICAN PARTY BEFORE THE CIVIL WAR 5 (1970) (discussing the Republican Party’s beliefs and values in the 1850s); Arthur Bestor, The American Civil War as a Constitutional Crisis, 69 AM. HIST. REV. 327 (1964) (discussing the Republican Party’s stance on slavery and the constitutional crises created between 1845 and 1877 by irreconcilable constitutional doctrines). JACOBUS TENBROEK, EQUAL UNDER LAW 108–15 (new enlarged rev. ed. 1965). See, e.g., Lysander Spooner, No Treason No. 1. (1867) (explaining the relationship between treason and rebellion in 1776 and 1861); Lysander Spooner, No Treason No. II. (1867) (discussing treason and the Constitution); Lysander Spooner, No Treason No. VI.: The Constitution of No Authority (1870) (arguing that the Constitution is of no significance since it has no authority). Photoduplicated reprints of these articles are available in 1 THE COLLECTED WORKS OF LYSANDER SPOONER (Charles Shively ed., 1971). 106758581 866 3/9/2016 11:31 PM NEW ENGLAND LAW REVIEW [Vol. 39:839 the Constitution was an instrument to which no contemporary Americans had given their personal express consent.160 It was therefore not an authority that anyone was obligated to respect. The old abolitionist drew from his thesis the startling corollary that the South had been right: it had the right to secede!161 By the same sort of natural law arguments that showed that slavery was unconstitutional, Spooner now sought to show that the Constitution was, in effect, unconstitutional.162 In a final irony, at exactly the time that the anarchist lawyer was repudiating the Constitution in a more fundamental way than Garrison ever did, his doctrine of paramount national citizenship became part of the Constitution as the first section of the Fourteenth Amendment.163 Thoughtful anarchists, then, hold that secession leads to anarchy. Thoughtful secessionists will likely disagree. We need evidence. We have it from the best possible place: Vermont. The Republic of Vermont was a wild place, conspicuously lacking the tranquility and civility of the state today. New York, New Hampshire, and even Massachusetts laid claim to part or all of the state, and at one time or another, various Vermont towns offered their allegiance to all of these states.164 New York was the most insistent, and its claim to Vermont kept it out of the Union until 1791.165 The Green Mountains bisect the state from north to south, and settlers with distinct social origins occupied the Eastside and the Westside.166 Political differences between the Eastside and the Westside have always played a prominent role in Vermont politics, at least until recently.167 160. 161. 162. 163. Spooner, No Treason No. VI.: The Constitution of No Authority, supra note 159. Spooner, No Treason No. II., supra note 159, at 8–9, 12. MARTIN, supra note 149, at 180–97. See TENBROEK, supra note 158, at 114–15. Section 1 of the Fourteenth Amendment states: All persons born or naturalized in the United States, and subject to the jurisdiction thereof, are citizens of the United States and of the State wherein they reside. No State shall make or enforce any law which shall abridge the privileges or immunities of citizens of the United States; nor shall any State deprive any person of life, liberty, or property, without due process of law; nor deny to any person within its jurisdiction the equal protection of the laws. U.S. CONST. amend. XIV, § 1. 164. PETER S. ONUF, THE ORIGINS OF THE FEDERAL REPUBLIC: JURISDICTIONAL CONTROVERSIES IN THE UNITED STATES, 1775–1787, at 139–41 (1983). 165. Id. at 127–28. 166. See BRYAN, supra note 119, at 7–8, 63. 167. Id. at 63–67. Under the “Mountain Rule,” many statewide political offices were alternated between East and West. Id. Reapportionment seems to have upset the 106758581 2005] 3/9/2016 11:31 PM IF AT FIRST YOU DON’T SECEDE, TRY, TRY AGAIN 867 Easterners resented Western domination, and “[e]very foreign policy initiative provoked disgust and dissension in one part of the state or another.”168 Few Westerners, but many Easterners, were “Yorkers,” supporters of the New York claim. Even the East/West cleavage understates the dissension. In the Eastside alone there were, at one point, five factions: (1) Vermont nationalists, (2) Yorkers, (3) pro-New Hampshire, (4) pro-Massachusetts, and (5) the “College Party,” which sought a new state consisting of eastern Vermont and western New Hampshire.169 Later many members of the College and pro-New Hampshire parties became allies with the objective of joining the state of Vermont.170 Meanwhile, Vermont, controlled by Ethan Allen and his Westside supporters, annexed sixteen New Hampshire towns (the Eastern Union) as well as New York territory west to the Hudson River (the Western Union), acquisitions which were renounced under pressure from Congress in 1782.171 Unlike Professor Naylor, the first Vermont republicans wanted nothing more than to gain admission to the American Union or, as a last resort, even to return to the British Empire.172 Few Vermonters believed that their small, isolated, landlocked, faction-wracked republic could survive without the protection and assistance of a “higher authority.”173 The Westside-based Vermont Establishment did not share Professor Naylor’s beliefs in the rights of dissent and secession. Between 1782 and 1783, punitive expeditions crossed the Green Mountains and arrested, prosecuted, expropriated, and imprisoned some Yorker dissidents; others went into exile.174 Almost every Vermonter was, from the perspective of some other Vermonter, a traitor. I suggested above that devolution is logically limitless. Republican Vermont might be said to have originated in secession (although to say from what, would embroil me in the squabbles of the time—it does not matter). Fragments of Vermont chronically sought to secede from Vermont, 168. 169. 170. 171. 172. 173. 174. balance of power, at least in the legislature. Id. at 54, 134; see also Baker v. Carr, 369 U.S. 186 (1962) (mandating one-person, one-vote in the apportionment of state legislative districts). The Westside now has a much higher population than the Eastside. See BRYAN, supra note 119, at 134. ONUF, supra note 164, at 129. VAN DE WATER, supra note 2, at 224–26. Id. at 227. ONUF, supra note 164, at 128, 132–37. This was done in exchange for a Congressional offer of statehood which Congress reneged on. Id. at 137. Id. at 135. Id. at 131. Id. at 143–44. 106758581 868 3/9/2016 11:31 PM NEW ENGLAND LAW REVIEW [Vol. 39:839 although usually to attach themselves to other states, not to assert their own independence. In the town of Guilford (population 4000), Cumberland County, Yorkers set up a “miniature republic.” Vermont dispatched troops. Five men were banished and their property confiscated.175 CONCLUSION At the Federal Convention, future Supreme Court Justice James Wilson exclaimed, “Can we forget for whom we form Governments—for Men not imaginary Beings called States.”176 Professor Naylor reminds us that the U.S. Constitution is a means, not an end, and that the federal government is an expedient.177 But I remind Professor Naylor that the same is true of Vermont or any other state. Like the federal government, it is, for all its power, in a certain sense what James Wilson called it—an imaginary or at least an artificial being.178 That is the implication of all the failed attempts to apply the concept of sovereignty to Madison’s “composite” system. Who has what power? Who ought to have it? Whatever the answers to these questions, they have nothing to do with whether the states were sovereign at any particular time before, during, or after the Revolution or the ratification of the Constitution. What does the Declaration of Independence declare? The radical doctrine “[t]hat whenever any Form of Government becomes destructive of these ends, it is the Right of the People to alter or abolish it ….”179 The question which has always haunted secessionists is which “people”? Professor Naylor answers, any people.180 A “people,” as opposed to a mere population of arbitrarily agglomerated individuals, is supposedly selfconstituted, although in practice it is usually minorities of politicians and intellectuals who do the constituting, creating the nationalist ideologies which typically precede nationhood and national consciousness.181 Ivor 175. 176. 177. 178. 179. 180. 181. VAN DE WATER, supra note 2, at 299–306. See LANSING, supra note 44, at 96. See supra note 17 and accompanying text. See supra Part III.B. THE DECLARATION OF INDEPENDENCE para. 2 (U.S. 1776). NAYLOR, supra note 1, at 17, 77–79. Take, for example, Lithuania: Lithuanian nationalism is a recent development. Lithuanian has always been the language of the peasantry, but until the present [20th] century the educated class spoke Polish or Russian. About the beginning of the century a few educated people, influenced by modern nationalism, decided that they were Lithuanians, began to speak the Lithuanian language and recalled the military glories of the early Lithuanian State, founded by pagan princes who extended their dominions to the Black 106758581 2005] 3/9/2016 11:31 PM IF AT FIRST YOU DON’T SECEDE, TRY, TRY AGAIN 869 Jennings, referring to Wilsonian principles of self-determination, has written: “On the surface it seemed reasonable: let the people decide. It was in fact ridiculous because the people cannot decide until somebody decides who are the people.”182 In principle, the people might be as numerous as “We, the People of the United States,” or as few as the 4000 treasonable townspeople of secessionist Guilford. Maybe “the people” can even be “the person,” as advocated by Murray N. Rothbard and perhaps Henry David Thoreau. Despite the opinions of John C. Calhoun and, implicitly, Professor Naylor, and even granting that it is meaningful to speak of the several “peoples” of the states, nonetheless, the peoples of the states occupy no privileged position relative to the people of the nation or the people of smaller districts or localities. The right of secession belongs to everyone or no one. Professor Naylor says it belongs to everyone.183 That, as the anarchist economist Murray Rothbard argued and as the distinguished anarchist lawyer Lysander Spooner exemplifies, leads to anarchy. In American history, secessionists for themselves have invariably opposed secessionists from themselves. Were states like Utah or even Vermont to secede, they would likely make a travesty of Professor Naylor’s generous principles. Secession does not solve the problem of centralized nation-states, or even diminish it; it only fragments it. As our inquiry has led us to the threshold of anarchy, let the anarchist Errico Malatesta have the last word: “Not knowing how to solve a problem does not oblige one to accept unconvincing solutions ….”184 Sea before the Union with Poland. A fortunate combination of circumstances gave the small body of Lithuanian nationalists the opportunity after the First World War to create an independent Lithuanian State. For twenty years the new rulers devoted themselves to creating a new educated Lithuanian class, to turning the sons of apathetic and primitive peasants into Lithuanian nationalist intellectuals. HUGH SETON-WATSON, EASTERN EUROPE BETWEEN THE WARS 1918–1941, at 325–26 (3d ed., rev. 1962). This is not an exceptional case: most Asian and nearly all African nationalisms follow this pattern. 182. IVOR JENNINGS, THE APPROACH TO SELF-GOVERNMENT 56 (1956). 183. NAYLOR, supra note 1, at 17, 77–79. 184. MALATESTA, supra note 152, at 43. Or as H.L. Mencken put it, “The fact that I have no remedy for all the sorrows of the world is no reason for my accepting yours.” H.L. MENCKEN, MINORITY REPORT: H.L. MENCKEN’S NOTEBOOKS 63 (1997). 106758581 870 3/9/2016 11:31 PM NEW ENGLAND LAW REVIEW *** [Vol. 39:839