D:\533582156.doc Created on 10/9/2006 11:33:00 AM Last printed 3/9/2016 2:16:00 AM Page 1 of 158 Words 47,586 This is a preliminary draft, not to be quoted without permission of author The 5th Amendment in the Age of Terrorism: Do We Still Have the Right to Remain Silent? by Alan M. Dershowitz Introduction .......................................................................................... 2 What is the Right Against Self-Incrimination? ................................ 4 The Different Meanings of the Fifth ................................................ 9 The Supreme Court’s Recent Decision .......................................... 14 Chapter 1: The Limits of Textual Analysis in Constitutional Interpretation ...................................................................................... 31 Chapter 2: The limits of precedent: Which way does “immunity” cut? ............................................................................................................ 44 The immunity precedent and analogy ............................................ 44 Chapter 3: The Limits of Historical Inquiry....................................... 61 The Earliest History of the Right Against Self-Incrimination ....... 68 The Levy Hypothesis ..................................................................... 73 The Langbein Hypothesis ............................................................... 79 Ships Passing in the Night .............................................................. 81 The Marbury and Burr Precedent ................................................... 96 Historical conclusions .................................................................. 101 The Privilege as Symbol .............................................................. 109 Rights as Specific Limitations on Particular Governmental Actions Versus Rights as General Guides to Governance ......................... 122 Should Any Provisions of the Constitution be Interpreted Symbolically? ............................................................................... 129 Our Accidental Constitution......................................................... 134 A Functional Analysis of the Constitutional Right Against Selfincrimination ................................................................................ 138 A Matter of Interpretation ............................................................ 141 Policy Considerations ................................................................... 146 Deconstructing the privilege against self-incrimination .............. 146 An Anti-disestablishmentarian Defense of the 5th Amendment ... 155 Broader Trends ............................................................................. 159 D:\533582156.doc Created on 10/9/2006 11:33:00 AM Last printed 3/9/2016 2:16:00 AM Page 2 of 158 Words 47,586 Introduction “You have the right to remain silent.” It’s probably the best known phrase ever to emanate from our Constitution. Every school child, movie goer and TV watcher knows that the Bill of Rights, most particularly the Fifth Amendment, grants every American the right to remain silent. The Supreme Court, in a foundational case applying the privilege against self-incrimination to the states, defined its core as “the right of a person to remain silent unless he chooses to speak in the unfettered exercise of his own will….”1 In reaffirming the constitutional status of the Miranda decision in 2000, the late Chief Justice William Rehnquist observed that the Miranda warnings— which begin with the categorical statement that “you have the right to remain silent”—have “become part of our national culture.”2 He was correct, as evidenced by one of the most reliable barometers of contemporary American culture, Jerry Seinfeld: Aren’t you a little surprised that cops still have to read that whole “You have the right to remain silent” speech to every criminal they arrest? I mean is there anybody who doesn’t know that by now? Can’t they just go, “Freeze, you’re under arrest. You ever seen Baretta?” “Yeah.” “Good, get in the car.”3 Justice Scalia agreed with Seinfeld that “[i]n the modern age of frequently dramatized ‘Miranda’ warnings, [it] is implausible” that a “person under investigation may be unaware of his right to remain silent….”4 But do Americans actually have the right that police officers are constitutionally obliged to tell them they have? Not according to a recent Supreme Court decision, largely unnoticed not only by the general public but by the academy as well. A majority of Supreme Court Justices ruled that whatever the courts might have said and whatever most people might believe, Americans never did have a right to remain silent. And if perchance they ever did, they certainly don’t have it now. Thus, in one fell swoop the Supreme Court— employing highly questionable interpretive mechanisms—told 1 Malloy v. Hogan, 378 U.S. 1 (1964), at 8. Dickerson v. United States, 530 U.S. 428, 443 (2000). 3 Jerry Seinfeld, SeinLanguage (New York: Bantam, 1993), pp. 92-93. 4 Brogan v. U.S., 522 U.S. 398, 405 (1998) 2 D:\533582156.doc Created on 10/9/2006 11:33:00 AM Last printed 3/9/2016 2:16:00 AM Page 3 of 158 Words 47,586 Americans, in effect, the following: “You may believe you have the right to remain silent. Policemen may have the obligation to advise you that you have the right to remain silent. But you do not have the right to remain silent. You do not even have the right not to be compelled or coerced into confessing your crimes. All you have is the right to exclude the fruits of compelled self-incrimination at your criminal trial — if you ever have a criminal trial.” And, as we shall see, there is a big difference between the fundamental human right to remain silent and a narrow trial remedy limited to the exclusion of evidence by criminal defendants. This difference is becoming increasingly important as coercive interrogation is used more frequently to obtain information deemed necessary to prevent future crimes (especially terrorism) than to secure evidence with which to prosecute past crimes. As we shall also see, this may be part of a more general trend toward narrowing what many have long understood to be fundamental human rights – such as the presumption of innocence and the prohibition against cruel and unusual punishments – into limited trial and post-trial rights for criminal defendants. Taken together, these developments enhance the power of government at the expense of the individual when it is acting preventively, as distinguished from punitively. They threaten to leave a gaping “black hole” in our system of constitutional protections as prevention takes on an increasingly important role in the war against terrorism. We shall also explore the implications for democracy of wide disparities between what citizens believe are their rights (rights as symbols) and what courts actually enforce as rights (rights as operative limitations on government). What does it say about a nation when the vast majority of its citizens—even its well educated citizens—understand an important constitutional protection so much more broadly than its courts do? D:\533582156.doc Created on 10/9/2006 11:33:00 AM Last printed 3/9/2016 2:16:00 AM Page 4 of 158 Words 47,586 What is the Right Against Self-Incrimination? The Fifth Amendment contains a hodge-podge of rights, some of which apply only to criminal defendants, while others have a more general application. It is an example of Churchill’s pudding without a theme.5 It reads, in whole, as follows: No person shall be held to answer for a capital, or otherwise infamous crime, unless on a presentment or indictment of a grand jury, except in cases arising in the land or naval forces, or in the militia, when in actual service in time of war or public danger; nor shall any person be subject for the same offense to be twice put in jeopardy of life or limb; nor shall be compelled in any criminal case to be a witness against himself, nor be deprived of life, liberty, or property, without due process of law; nor shall private property be taken for public use, without just compensation. Notwithstanding its wide assortment of rights, the Fifth Amendment, in common parlance has come to refer specifically to the provision against self-incrimination. As the late Leonard Levy, the respected historian of the right against self-incrimination, has correctly observed: “One who “pleads the Fifth” is not insisting on grand jury indictment, freedom from the double jeopardy, or just compensation for property taken by the government – all safeguarded by the Fifth. He is saying that he will not reply to an official inquiry because his truthful answer might expose him to criminal jeopardy.”6 The fifteen words that constitute the constitutional right against selfincrimination are: “no person…shall be compelled in any criminal case to be a witness against himself.” Although it is called a “privilege,” which suggests a revocable concession given by the government to its subjects, in the United States it is a constitutional “And he insisted on a proper pudding. Mary and I remember once when a pudding was served up to him, he turned to Clementine and said, ‘Clemmie! Take this pudding away—it has no theme!” Anthony Browne, Memories of Winston Churchill. Finest Hour 50. 6 Levy, Origins of the Fifth Amendment, at p. vii which won the Pulitzer Prize. 5 D:\533582156.doc Created on 10/9/2006 11:33:00 AM Last printed 3/9/2016 2:16:00 AM Page 5 of 158 Words 47,586 right that imposes irrevocable limitations on the government.7 Read literally and narrowly, this right would be limited to precluding the prosecution in a criminal case from compelling the defendant to testify, presumably under oath, against himself. As we shall see, such an interpretation would have rendered the right meaningless at the time it was written and ratified, since defendants were disqualified from testifying under oath at their own trials whether they wanted to or not. Thus, even if there were no Constitutional right not to be compelled to testify against oneself, no defendant could be compelled to do so at the time the 5th Amendment became part of our constitution. As one commentator has aptly put it: “To suggest that the privilege cannot be claimed except by one on trial is to confine the privilege to the only context in which it was unavailable at the founding.”8 It is unlikely that the framers of the 5th Amendment intended to include in the Bill of Rights a protection that had no applicability to the legal system as they knew it. Accordingly, despite its words, the right had never, until this recent decision, been interpreted so literally. Instead, the courts have “construed the clause as if its framers neither meant what they said nor said what they meant.” “Seeking the spirit and policy of the fifth, the [Supreme] Court has, on the whole, given it an ever-widening, liberal interpretation, on the principle that ‘it is as broad as the mischief against which it seeks to guard.” 9 For example, shortly after it was ratified, the right was interpreted to apply to witnesses who might become criminal defendants, as well as to those who already were criminal defendants. 10 In subsequent decisions, it was also held applicable to out of court police interrogation of suspects, as well as to in court questioning of defendants by prosecutors or judges.11 As we shall see, the origin of the right grew out of three somewhat different privileges, with different histories and current applications. There was the defendant's privilege, which precluded the prosecution from compelling a criminal defendant to be a witness at his own trial. There was the witness’ privilege, which granted any witness in any legal proceeding the right to refuse to answer specific At common law, there was a “privilege” against self-incrimination. The Fifth Amendment turned that privilege into a Constitutional “right.” See Levy pp. VIIVIII. I will use these words interchangeably while agreeing with Levy that it is a right. 8 Donald Dripps, “Akhil Amar on Criminal Procedure and Constitutional Law: ‘Here I Go Down That Wrong Road Again,’” 74 North Carolina Law Review 1559 (1996), at 1625. 9 Levy, Pol. Sci. Q. p 18 _____ quoting Counselman v. Hitchcock 10 See Infra pp ___ ___. 11 See Infra pp ___ ___. 7 D:\533582156.doc Created on 10/9/2006 11:33:00 AM Last printed 3/9/2016 2:16:00 AM Page 6 of 158 Words 47,586 questions that might tend to incriminate him in a subsequent criminal case, unless he is given immunity that is at least as extensive as his privilege. And there was the suspect’s privilege, which (at the very least) prohibited the government from using involuntary statements that were elicited from the defendants by coercion.12 Taken together, these privileges and their several variations have been summarized by courts and commentators as bestowing “the right of a person to remain silent.” This characterization makes the privilege somewhat greater than the sum of its parts. The Supreme Court’s recent decision makes the privilege considerably smaller than the sum of its parts, and reduces it from an array of rights protecting all “persons” to a specific remedy, available only to criminal defendants. When the right against self-incrimination was included in the Bill of Rights, it generated little controversy or debate. Yet in recent times, it has created a hailstorm of criticism, from academics, politicians and the general public. Levy has observed that when someone invokes “The Fifth,” he: “seems to be saying that he has something to hide, making the Fifth Appear to be a protection of the guilty and raising the question why the framers of the Bill of Rights should have wanted to protect the guilty. Without doubt the right against self-incrimination is the most misunderstood, unrespected, and controversial of all rights. Over a half-century ago, during the era of McCarthyism, when the United States underwent one of its periodic red scares, politicians and newspapers collaborated in giving the utmost publicity to the number of time some socalled “hostile” witness before a legislative investigating committee invoked the Fifth Amendment. Dozens of individuals were censured before the bar of public opinion as “Fifth Amendment Communists,” a term then infamous. Demagoguery is fairly easy to comprehend, but not a nationwide contempt for a constitutional right.”13 Levy has acknowledged that during the McCarthy period he himself: “wondered why the Bill of Rights contained a provision that benefited criminals and enemies of the United States. I knew 12 As we shall also see, there are two types of statements that are subject to exclusion - - those that are coerced and/or involuntary; and those obtained in violation of the Miranda rule. Different consequences flow, depending on whether the statements fall into the former or latter category. 13 Levy, p. vii D:\533582156.doc Created on 10/9/2006 11:33:00 AM Last printed 3/9/2016 2:16:00 AM Page 7 of 158 Words 47,586 enough about those who framed and ratified the Bill of Rights to understand that they could not be dismissed as fools, starryeyed idealists, or mushy liberals. I knew too that the Bill of Rights, which protects mainly the rights of the criminally accused, was added to the Constitution as a result of an overwhelming popular demand that Washington, Hamilton, and others in the first administration could not possibly ignore.”14 Levy, who was primarily an American historian, decided to learn about the British origins of this right. That curiosity led him to write the first scholarly book on the history of the Fifth Amendment -- a book that has been subject to much recent scholarly criticism.15 I too became interested in the Fifth Amendment during the McCarthy era. I was in high school and then in college at the time and so I did not write a book, merely a term paper. In it, I explored the history, policies and applications of the privilege, especially in the context of legislative investigations, where many of the battles over the scope of the 5th Amendment were then being fought. I pointed out that the privilege had “traversed many cycles” over the years and had been “adapted to changing times and needs,” and concluded that though we “are considering the very same constitutional phrase, we are dealing with a completely new and hitherto unknown privilege.”16 I now believe, with Ecclesiastics, that there is rarely anything completely new under the sun, but it is true that the right against selfincrimination has undergone frequent reinterpretation and redefinition as our legal and political systems have changed over time, and as we as a nation have experienced abuses of different kinds. Recently a prominent judge told me that while he understood the history and policies underlying all of the other rights in our constitution, he did not understand why a guilty defendant should have the right to refuse, without consequence, to answer relevant questions properly put to him by a government official. This judge is joined by many academics and ordinary citizens who wonder about this and other questions that are naturally raised by the somewhat unnatural right against self-incrimination.17 It is among the most controversial and misunderstood rights in our constitution. Many 14 Levy, p. vii See Infra. p. ___ 16 (Brooklyn College Archive) 17 I do not believe in “natural” right or “divine” rights. I believe that rights are human responses to human wrongs. See Alan Dershowitz, Rights from Wrongs (2004, p. 230). 15 D:\533582156.doc Created on 10/9/2006 11:33:00 AM Last printed 3/9/2016 2:16:00 AM Page 8 of 158 Words 47,586 Americans do not even know its scope—and, as we shall see, for good reasons. D:\533582156.doc Created on 10/9/2006 11:33:00 AM Last printed 3/9/2016 2:16:00 AM Page 9 of 158 Words 47,586 The Different Meanings of the Fifth The Delphic words of the Fifth Amendment’s privilege against self-incrimination have been interpreted by courts and commentators to mean radically different things over the years. Here are some of the most common interpretations and understandings from the broadest to the narrowest. 1.) The Right to Remain Silent: “[T]he Fifth Amendment guarantees…the right of a person to remain silent unless he chooses to speak in the unfettered exercise of his own will, and to suffer no penalty … for such silence.”18 2.) The right to a private enclave into which the government may not pry: “The privilege against self-incrimination … reflects many of our fundamental values and most noble aspirations [including] [o]ur respect for the inviolability of the human personality and of the right of each individual to ‘a private enclave where he may lead a private life.’”19 3.) The right not to be compelled to expose one’s own guilt: “The essential and inherent cruelty of compelling a man to expose his own guilt is obvious to every one, and needs no illustration. It is plain to every person who gives the subject a moment’s thought. “A sense of personal degradation in being compelled to incriminate one’s self must create a feeling of abhorrence in the community at its attempted enforcement.”20 18 Malloy v. Hogan, 378 U.S. 1 (1964), at 8. Murphy at 55. 20 Brown v. Walker, 161 U.S. 591 (1896), at 637 (Field, J. dissenting). Commentators have also held this view. See also Telford Taylor, “The Constitutional Privilege against Self-Incrimination,” Annals of the American Academy of Political and Social Science, Vol. 300 (July 1955), at p. 117: “Why does an innocent man really need this privilege? Does it not raise the inference of his probably guilt if he uses it? Why does he not stand up like a man and say what the facts are? “I think on this point we now have to recall that whether you are guilty or innocent is not a philosophical absolute; it is what the jury decides. And what the jury decides might be right or might be wrong. They decide it on the basis of the evidence before them. If you yourself under accusation are the source of the evidence which arouses suspicion, which might establish guilt, then you have put yourself in a worse position before the jury.” 19 D:\533582156.doc Created on 10/9/2006 11:33:00 AM Last printed 3/9/2016 2:16:00 AM Page 10 of 158 Words 47,586 4.) The right not to be compelled under oath to make selfincriminating statements, unless granted immunity co-extensive with the privilege: “Our unwillingness to subject those suspected of crime to the cruel trilema of self-accusation, perjury or contempt…”21 “The privilege assures that a citizen is not compelled to incriminate himself by his own testimony. It usually operates to allow a citizen to remain silent when asked a question requiring an incriminatory answer. This [immunity] statute, which operates after a witness has given incriminatory testimony, affords the same protection by assuring that the compelled testimony can in no way lead to the infliction of criminal penalties.”22 5.) The right not to be coerced by the police into making an involuntary self-incriminating statement “Interrogation of people by the police is an indispensable aspect of criminal investigations. But there is no right to interrogate — by the police any more than by the courts — when the privilege against selfincrimination is invoked. Knowing this, the police have set up in its place a system of administrative detention that has no constitutional justification. It is detention incommunicado, a system which breeds oppression. In the present case this illiterate petitioner was not given the modicum of protection afforded in England where a prisoner is warned that statements made may be used against him and where the police are enjoined not to hammer away at a prisoner nor even to cross-examine him when he makes a voluntary statement except to clear up ambiguities. The flow of cases coming here shows that detention incommunicado is often accompanied by illegality and brutality.”23 “The ultimate test remains that which has been the only clearly established test in Anglo-American courts for two hundred years; the test of voluntariness. Is the confession he product of an essentially free and unconstrained choice by its maker? If it is, if he has willed to confess, it may be used against him. If it is not, if his will has been overborne and his capacity for self-determination critically impaired, the use of his confession offends due process.”24 21 Murphy at 55 Kastigar v. United States, 406 U.S. 441, at 461 (note omitted). 23 Culombe v. Connecticut, 367 U.S. 568 (1961), at 639-40 (Douglas, J. concurring) (notes and internal citations omitted). 24 Culombe v. Connecticut, 367 U.S. 568 (1961), at 602. 22 D:\533582156.doc Created on 10/9/2006 11:33:00 AM Last printed 3/9/2016 2:16:00 AM Page 11 of 158 Words 47,586 6.) The right to be advised of Miranda Rules “Prior to any questioning, the person must be warned that he has a right to remain silent, that any statement he does make may be used as evidence against him, and that he has a right to the presence of an attorney, either retained or appointed.”25 7.) The right not to be tortured into providing incriminating information. “[The Fifth Amendment is] the most specific provision in the Bill of Rights ‘that protects all citizens from the kind of custodial interrogation that was once employed by the Star Chamber, by ‘the Germans of the 1930’s and early 1940’s, and by some of our own police departments only a few decades ago.’ Whenever it occurs, as it did here, official interrogation of that character is a classic example of a violation of a constitutional right ‘implicit in the concept of ordered liberty.”26 “In my view the Self-Incrimination Clause is applicable at the time and place police use compulsion to extract a statement from a suspect. The Clause forbids that conduct.”27 8.) Right of a criminal defendant not to testify and not to have factfinder draw inference of guilt from his decision: “For comment on the refusal to testify is a remnant of the inquisitorial system of criminal justice, which the Fifth Amendment outlaws. It is a penalty imposed by courts for exercising a constitutional privilege. It cuts down on the privilege by making its assertion costly.”28 25 Miranda v. Arizona, 384 U.S. 436 (1966), at 444. 26 Chavez v. Martinez (Stevens Opinion) 27 Chavez v. Martinez (Kennedy Opinion) 28 “Our views on the proper scope of the Fifth Amendment’s SelfIncrimination Clause do not mean that police torture or other abuse that results in a confession is constitutionally permissible so long as the statements are not used at trial; it simply means that the Fourteenth Amendment’s Due Process Clause, rather than the Fifth Amendment’s Self-Incrimination Clause, would govern the inquiry in those cases and provide relief in appropriate circumstances.” Chavez vs. Martinez, 538 U.S. 760 (2003), at 773. D:\533582156.doc Created on 10/9/2006 11:33:00 AM Last printed 3/9/2016 2:16:00 AM Page 12 of 158 Words 47,586 9.) Right to have prosecution bear heavy burden of proving defendant’s guilt without relying on defendant’s testimony. “Requiring the government in its contest with the individual to shoulder the entire load…”29 “The privilege against self-incrimination [is] the essential mainstay of our adversary system…”30 10.) Right to enjoin or seek damages against government officials who violate these rights. “The police may not prolong or increase a suspect's suffering against the suspect's will. That conduct would render government officials accountable for the increased pain. The officers must not give the impression that severe pain will be alleviated only if the declarant cooperates, for that, too, uses pain to extract a statement. In a case like this one, recovery should be available under § 1983 if a complainant can demonstrate that an officer exploited his pain and suffering with the purpose and intent of securing an incriminating statement.”31 11.) Right to exclude self-incriminatory statements and its fruits from any use in criminal prosecution against defendant. “Statements compelled by police interrogations of course may not be used against a defendant at trial…but it is not until their use in a criminal case that a violation of the Self-Incrimination clause occurs.”32 12.) Right to exclude self-incriminating statements obtained in violation of Miranda, but not its fruits from government’s case in chief against defendant, and not even the statement if defendant takes the stand. “In this case we must decide whether a failure to give a suspect the warnings prescribed by Miranda v. Arizona requires suppression of the physical fruits of the suspect’s unwarned but voluntary statements…. Because the Miranda rule protects against violations of the Self-Incrimination Clause, which, in turn, is not implicated by the introduction at trial of physical evidence resulting from voluntary 29 Murphy at 55 Miranda at 460 31 Chavez v. Martinez, 538 U.S. 760 (2003), at 797 (Kennedy, J. concurring in part and dissenting in part). 32 Chavez v. Martinez, 538 U.S. 760 (2003), at 767. 30 D:\533582156.doc Created on 10/9/2006 11:33:00 AM Last printed 3/9/2016 2:16:00 AM Page 13 of 158 Words 47,586 statements, we answer the question presented in the negative.”33 “Some comments in the Miranda opinion can indeed be read as indicating a bar to use of an uncounseled statement for any purpose, but discussion of that issue was not at all necessary to the Court's holding and cannot be regarded as controlling. Miranda barred the prosecution from making its case with statements of an accused made while in custody prior to having or effectively waiving counsel. It does not follow from Miranda that evidence inadmissible against an accused in the prosecution's case in chief is barred for all purposes, provided of course that the trustworthiness of the evidence satisfies legal standards…. The shield provided by Miranda cannot be perverted into a license to use perjury by way of a defense, free from the risk of confrontation with prior inconsistent utterances. We hold, therefore, that petitioner's credibility was appropriately impeached by use of his earlier conflicting statements.”34 As we shall see, the scope and application of the rights against selfincrimination has varied over time with the intensity of governmental efforts and the means employed to elicit information from individuals. The Supreme Court’s recent decision—following a more general trend--adopted a extremely narrow view of the constitutional right against self-incrimination, limiting it to a trial remedy available only to criminal defendants at their own trials and affording the government enormous latitude to secure information not necessarily intended for use in criminal trials. 33 34 United States v. Patane, 542 U.S. 630 (2004), at 633-34. Harris v. New York, 401 U.S. 222 (1971), at 224, 226. D:\533582156.doc Created on 10/9/2006 11:33:00 AM Last printed 3/9/2016 2:16:00 AM Page 14 of 158 Words 47,586 The Supreme Court’s Recent Decision The case is Chavez v. Martinez,35 decided on May 27, 2003. It was a civil, not a criminal, case, but it definitely decided an important constitutional issue regarding the meaning and scope of the right against self-incrimination. The victim of police coercion sued the police officer under a federal statute. The law grants a police officer “qualified immunity” from such a lawsuit unless his conduct violated a constitutional right. It was necessary therefore for this Supreme Court to determine whether the police officer had violated the victim’s constitutional right. The lower courts had ruled that the police officer had violated the plaintiff’s constitutional rights by subjecting him to coercive interrogation after he had been shot by another officer. The Supreme Court granted review in order to decide whether police coercion alone, without the subsequent use of the fruits of such coercion against the person in the criminal case, constitutes a violation of the Fifth Amendment. There were six opinions, none of which alone reflected a majority view, but the opinion of Justice Thomas—joined by then-Chief Justice Rehnquist and Justices O’Conner and Scalia—carried the day and is likely to reflect the views of a majority of the current High Court.36 That opinion concluded that Martinez’s privilege against self-incrimination had not been violated by police officers who had coerced him— according to Justice Stevens, essentially tortured him—into making statements that were self-incriminating, because the statements were never used against him in a criminal case. (Martinez was never charged with a crime.37) Justice Souter “concurred” in the Court’s judgment that mere compulsion does not violate the privilege against self-incrimination so long as the resulting “testimony”38 is not admitted into evidence at the person’s criminal trial. Justice Breyer joined Souter’s opinion. Three Justices—Stevens, Kennedy, and Ginsburg—concluded, in dissent, that the privilege could be violated whenever “torture or its close equivalents are brought to bear” on a person, regardless of whether its fruits are ultimately admitted against him in a criminal case. Not a single justice accepted the view, asserted by [DID ANYONE ASSERT THIS? CHECK BRIEFS 35 538 U.S. 760 (2003). Since Chavez was decided, two new Justices have been confirmed. Both replaced Justices who joined the Thomas decision. Chief Justice Roberts replaced Chief Justice Rehnquist and Justice Alito replaced Justice O’Connor. 37 Martinez, 538 U.S. at 764. 38 Justice Souter confuses “testimony” with “evidence.” “Martinez’s testimony” would not be at issue if the police testified as to his unsworn earlier statements. 36 D:\533582156.doc Created on 10/9/2006 11:33:00 AM Last printed 3/9/2016 2:16:00 AM Page 15 of 158 Words 47,586 INCLUDING AMICUS]39 that the use of coercion that would be sufficient to exclude its fruits from a criminal trial but that is short of “torture or its close equivalent,” would constitute a stand-alone violation of the privilege, absent subsequent use. The nose-count therefore was 6-3 on the fundamental constitutional issue of whether the privilege against self-incrimination bestows any right to remain silent. The majority said no. Nor does the privilege grant a correlative right not to be compelled or coerced into making statements that are self-incriminating. All it requires is that if compulsion has been employed against a person by government officials—police or judges—the resulting statements may not be admitted into evidence against that person at a subsequent criminal trial, if there ever is one.40 Absent such use of coerced statement, there has been no violation of the privilege in the coercion itself, no matter how extreme. Even the three dissenters would require more than a mere violation of a citizen’s right to remain silent, or not to be coerced into making incriminating statements, for there to be a violation of the privilege. According to the Stevens standard, unless the government employed “torture or its close equivalents,” there would be no violation of the privilege. Even if a suspect were brutally coerced into involuntarily confessing a crime, his right against self-incrimination would not be violated so long as the coercion did not rise to the level of torture. All nine justices therefore rejected the widespread belief that Americans have the right to remain silent, even in the face of coercive questions.41 Justice Souter’s opinion ended with a one-sentence conclusion remanding the case for a determination of whether Martinez “may pursue a claim of liability for a substantive due process violation….”42 This final paragraph constituted “the opinion of the Court.”43 In other words, a majority of the Court, while clearly deciding that coercion—even coercion of the kind employed against Martinez—does not violate the privilege against self-incrimination, left open the question of whether the coercion at issue in this case rose to the level of a due process violation. Justices Thomas, Scalia, Rehnquist, and O’Connor voted against the remand, being “satisfied 39 CHECK THIS It also means that no criminal defendant may be compelled to testify—to be an actual trial witness—against himself at his criminal trial. That much is literally required by the words of the privilege. More about this infra at pp. ___. 41 Kennedy’s view is less than completely clear, because [FILL IN] 42 Martinez, 538 U.S. at 779. 43 Martinez, 538 U.S. at 777. 40 D:\533582156.doc Created on 10/9/2006 11:33:00 AM Last printed 3/9/2016 2:16:00 AM Page 16 of 158 Words 47,586 that [the interrogation in this case, though coercive] did not violate Martinez’s due process rights.”44 In other words, according to these justices, there was absolutely nothing unconstitutional about an interrogation which Justice Stevens characterized as “the functional equivalent of … torturous methods.”45 The actual facts of the case were essentially undisputed, because the crucial moments of the interrogation were tape recorded. Although the interplay between the officer and Martinez in the police car on the way to the hospital was not recorded, and the recorder was turned off whenever the emergency room staff took Martinez out of his room, the Court of Appeals accepted its finding that “The transcript of the recorded conversation totals about ten minutes and provides an incontrovertible account of the interview.”46 The disagreement was primarily over the application of the Fifth Amendment to those facts. It was this disagreement that gave rise to the multiplicity of opinions and the sharp division over the proper constitutional result. Here are the facts as set out, somewhat antiseptically47, by Justice Thomas: On November 28, 1997, police officers Maria Peña and Andrew Salinas were near a vacant lot in a residential area of Oxnard, California, investigating suspected narcotics activity. While Peña and Salinas were questioning an individual, they heard a bicycle approaching on a darkened path that crossed the lot. They ordered the rider, respondent Martinez, to dismount, spread his legs, and place his hands behind his head. Martinez complied. Salinas then conducted a patdown frisk and discovered a knife in Martinez’s waistband. An altercation ensued.48 There is some dispute about what occurred during the altercation. The officers claim that Martinez drew Salinas’ gun 44 Martinez, 538 U.S. 774. Martinez, 538 U.S. 783. 46 Martinez v. City of Oxnard, 270 F.3d 852 (9th Circuit 2001), at 855. 47 ALEX: GET WALL STREET JOURNAL., Article about “when there is blood on an opinion” FN about judges distort facts to make their points. (ALAN: I EMAILED YOU THE ARTICLE. LET ME KNOW HOW YOU WANT TO WORK IT IN.) 48 [Note to copy editor: This should be a footnote, NOT an endnote.] [This footnote is from the opinion:] The parties disagree over what triggered the altercation. The officers maintain that Martinez ran away from them and that they tackled him while in pursuit; Martinez asserts that he never attempted to flee and Salinas tackled him without warning. 45 D:\533582156.doc Created on 10/9/2006 11:33:00 AM Last printed 3/9/2016 2:16:00 AM Page 17 of 158 Words 47,586 from its holster and pointed it at them; Martinez denies this. Both sides agree, however, that Salinas yelled, “‘He’s got my gun!’” Peña then drew her gun and shot Martinez several times, causing severe injuries that left Martinez permanently blinded and paralyzed from the waist down. The officers then placed Martinez under arrest. Petitioner Chavez, a patrol supervisor, arrived on the scene minutes later with paramedics. Chavez accompanied Martinez to the hospital and then questioned Martinez there while he was receiving treatment from medical personnel. The interview lasted a total of about 10 minutes, over a 45minute period, with Chavez leaving the emergency room for periods of time to permit medical personnel to attend to Martinez. At first, most of Martinez’s answers consisted of “I don’t know,” “I am dying,” and “I am choking.” Later in the interview, Martinez admitted that he took the gun from the officer’s holster and pointed it at the police. He also admitted that he used heroin regularly. At one point, Martinez said “I am not telling you anything until they treat me,” yet Chavez continued the interview. At no point during the interview was Martinez given warnings under Miranda v. Arizona.49 Justice Stevens provides a far more graphic and detailed description, quoting extensively from the English translation of the tape-recorded questioning in Spanish that occurred in the emergency room of the hospital when Martinez was suffering great pain and believed he was dying: “Chavez: What happened? Olivero, tell me what happened. “O[liverio] M[artinez]: I don’t know. “Chavez: I don’t know what happened (sic)? “O. M.: Ay! I am dying. Ay! What are you doing to me? “No, . . .! (Unintelligible scream). 49 Martinez, 538 U.S. at 763-64 (citations omitted). D:\533582156.doc Created on 10/9/2006 11:33:00 AM Last printed 3/9/2016 2:16:00 AM Page 18 of 158 Words 47,586 “Chavez: What happened, sir? “O. M.: My foot hurts. . . “Chavez: Olivera. Sir, what happened? “O. M.: I am choking. “Chavez: Tell me what happened. “O. M.: I don’t know. “Chavez: ‘I don’t know.’ “O. M.: My leg hurts. “Chavez: I don't know what happened (sic)? “O. M.: It hurts. . . “Chavez: Hey, hey look. “O. M.: I am choking. “Chavez: Can you hear? look listen, I am Benjamin Chavez with the police here in Oxnard, look. “O. M.: I am dying, please. “Chavez: OK, yes, tell me what happened. If you are going to die, tell me what happened. Look I need to tell (sic) what happened. “O. M.: I don’t know. “Chavez: You don’t know, I don’t know what happened (sic)? Did you talk to the police? “O. M.: Yes. “Chavez: What happened with the police? “O. M.: We fought. D:\533582156.doc Created on 10/9/2006 11:33:00 AM Last printed 3/9/2016 2:16:00 AM Page 19 of 158 Words 47,586 “Chavez: Huh? What happened with the police? “O. M.: The police shot me. “Chavez: Why? “O. M.: Because I was fighting with him. “Chavez: Oh, why were you fighting with the police? “O. M.: I am dying. . . “Chavez: OK, yes you are dying, but tell me why you are fighting, were you fighting with the police? ..... “O. M.: Doctor, please I want air, I am dying. “Chavez: OK, OK. I want to know if you pointed the gun [to yourself] at the police. [CHECK THIS] “O. M.: Yes. “Chavez: Yes, and you pointed it [to yourself]? (sic) at the police pointed the gun? (sic) Huh? “O. M.: I am dying, please. . . ..... “Chavez: OK, listen, listen I want to know what happened, ok?? “O. M.: I want them to treat me. “Chavez: OK, they are do it (sic), look when you took out the gun from the tape (sic) of the police. . . “O. M.: I am dying. . . “Chavez: Ok, look, what I want to know if you took out (sic) the gun of the police? D:\533582156.doc Created on 10/9/2006 11:33:00 AM Last printed 3/9/2016 2:16:00 AM Page 20 of 158 Words 47,586 “O. M.: I am not telling you anything until they treat me. “Chavez: Look, tell me what happened, I want to know, look well don’t you want the police know (sic) what happened with you? “O. M.: Uuuggghhh! my belly hurts. . . ..... “Chavez: Nothing, why did you run (sic) from the police? “O. M.: I don’t want to say anything anymore. “Chavez: No? “O. M.: I want them to treat me, it hurts a lot, please. “Chavez: You don’t want to tell (sic) what happened with you over there? “O. M.: I don’t want to die, I don’t want to die. “Chavez: Well if you are going to die tell me what happened, and right now you think you are going to die? “O. M.: No. “Chavez: No, do you think you are going to die? “O. M.: Aren’t you going to treat me or what? “Chavez: Look, think you are going to die, (sic) that’s all I want to know, if you think you are going to die? Right now, do you think you are going to die? “O. M.: My belly hurts, please treat me. “Chavez: Sir? “O. M.: If you treat me I tell you everything, if not, no. D:\533582156.doc Created on 10/9/2006 11:33:00 AM Last printed 3/9/2016 2:16:00 AM Page 21 of 158 Words 47,586 “Chavez: Sir, I want to know if you think you are going to die right now? “O. M.: I think so. “Chavez: You think (sic) so? Ok. Look, the doctors are going to help you with all they can do, Ok?. That they can do. “O. M.: Get moving, I am dying, can’t you see me? come on. “Chavez: Ah, huh, right now they are giving you medication.” The sound recording of this interrogation, which has been lodged with the Court, vividly demonstrates that respondent was suffering severe pain and mental anguish throughout petitioner’s persistent questioning.50 Justice Stevens concluded that it “is evident from the text [that] both parties believed that [Martinez] was about to die,”51 and characterized the interrogation as “the functional equivalent of an attempt to obtain an involuntary confession from a prisoner by torturous methods.”52 The findings of the trial court would seem to confirm Justice Stevens’s characterization. It found that Martinez had been “shot in the face, both eyes were injured; he was screaming in pain and coming in and out of consciousness while being repeatedly questioned….” Justice Kennedy elaborated on these findings: “The transcript…and other evidence considered by the District Court demonstrate that the suspect thought his treatment would be delayed, and thus his pain and condition worsened, by refusal to answer questions…. His blinding facial wounds made it impossible for him visually to distinguish the interrogating officer from the attending medical personnel. The officer made no effort to 50 Martinez, 538 U.S. at 784-86 (citation omitted). 51 Martinez, 537 U.S. at 784. 52 Martinez, 537 U.S. at 783. D:\533582156.doc Created on 10/9/2006 11:33:00 AM Last printed 3/9/2016 2:16:00 AM Page 22 of 158 Words 47,586 dispel the perception that medical treatment was being withheld until Martinez answered the questions put to him. There was no attempt through Miranda warnings or other assurances to advise the suspect that his cooperation should be voluntary. Martinez begged the officer to desist and provide treatment for his wounds, but the questioning persisted despite these pleas and despite Martinez’s unequivocal refusal to answer questions…. In this case no reasonable police officer would believe that the law permitted him to prolong or increase pain to obtain a statement. The record supports the ultimate finding that the officer acted with the intent of exploiting Martinez’s conditions for purposes of extracting a statement.”53 Martinez did not die, but he was permanently paralyzed and blinded. All the justices agreed that the answers given by Martinez were “compelled,” “coerced,” “involuntary,” and obtained without the necessary Miranda warnings. All agreed therefore that nothing Martinez said in response to this interrogation could be admitted against him in a criminal case and that admission of any such coerced responses would violate his privilege against self-incrimination. All agreed as well that since Martinez was never prosecuted, the statements that were coerced from him were never used against him at a criminal trial. But here the agreement ends and the major dispute begins: namely what is the extent of Martinez’s rights under the Fifth Amendment? Did he have a right “to remain silent”? Did he have a right not to be coerced into making self-incriminating statements? Or was his only right not to have his coerced statements used against him in a criminal case? Put another way, does the Fifth Amendment provide a primary right to remain silent, or only a secondary right to a particular remedy — namely exclusion of coerced statements? Is the privilege against self-incrimination only an exclusionary rule or does it also contain an important substantive right to remain silent? Or not to be coerced or compelled to admit crimes? Put yet another way: what is the point of impact of the privilege? When compulsion is employed? Or only when its fruits are admitted against the coerced person at his criminal trial? On the answers to those questions did the outcome of the case turn: if Martinez had a primary right to remain silent, or not to be coerced, that right was plainly violated by the admitted police coercion. But if his only right was to exclude the 53 Martinez, 538 U.S. at 797-99. D:\533582156.doc Created on 10/9/2006 11:33:00 AM Last printed 3/9/2016 2:16:00 AM Page 23 of 158 Words 47,586 evidentiary fruits of such coercion from his criminal trial, then he suffered no violation of his rights, since he never had a criminal trial. Nor is this merely a “technical,” “verbal,” or “legalistic” disagreement. The stakes for all Americans are extremely high, especially in an age of terrorism, when preventive intelligence – information not intended to be used in criminal cases -- is often gathered by coercive means. As we move closer to the preventive state and further from the deterrent state - - as the paradigm begins to shift from after-the-fact punishment to before-the-fact prevention54 - there will be more emphasis on securing preventive intelligence information than on securing self-incriminating confessions to be used in criminal cases.55 Accordingly, the Martinez case is a perfect vehicle with which to explore the terrain of the right against self-incrimination, to view the panoramic landscape of historical abuses that provide the background for the development of this important right, and to peer over this horizon in an effort to glimpse its future in the age of terror prevention. The Thomas view (shared by five other justices), taken to its logical conclusion, means that the privilege against self-incrimination has absolutely nothing to say about the means employed by government to extract information from an American citizen (or anyone else), so long as the information is not used against the citizen at his criminal trial. In other words, the government may — without violating the privilege against self-incrimination — torture a citizen into providing intelligence information deemed necessary to prevent a terrorist attack or any other feared harm. (Recall that the Martinez case did not involve the prevention of terrorism or any other physical harm; the concern that motivated the police to use coercion was that evidence that could help the police in a possible civil suit could be lost if Martinez died without admitting that he was at fault.) There are no apparent limits to this power under the majority views of the privilege, except that the fruits of the coercion may not then be admitted in a criminal case against the person coerced. Since eventual admissions of the fruits in a subsequent criminal trial is often not the object of the interrogation – as it was not in the Martinez case – there 54 See Preemption: A Knife That Cuts Both Ways 55 FN on Israel where the fruits of preventive intelligence is not used in criminal cases. Also England. D:\533582156.doc Created on 10/9/2006 11:33:00 AM Last printed 3/9/2016 2:16:00 AM Page 24 of 158 Words 47,586 will be little disincentive to the police to forbear from coercion, especially if they are immunized from civil liability.56 To be sure, there may be other provisions of the Constitution, particularly the “due process” clause, that prohibit or limit torture (or other forms of coercive interrogation). That remains to be seen.57 The words themselves — “due process” — are quite subjective, meaning, literally, the “process” that is “due” a citizen.58 That process may vary with circumstances. It is not an absolute prohibition, such as the one apparently contained in the privilege against self-incrimination, which provides that “no person…shall be compelled in any criminal case to be a witness against himself….”59 Some Justices and scholars reject the view that due process imposes any substantive — as distinguished from procedural — constraints on government.60 Others take the view that only the most extreme forms of torture — and certainly not the conduct at issue in the Martinez case — are violative of due process. Justice Thomas, in his opinion for four justices, takes an extremely narrow view of due process: “We are satisfied that Chavez’s questioning did not violate Martinez’s due process rights. Even assuming arguendo, that the persistent questioning of Martinez somehow deprived him of a liberty interest, we cannot agree with Martinez’s characterization of Chavez’s behavior as “egregious” or “conscience shocking.” As we noted in [County of Sacramento v.] Lewis, the official conduct “most likely to rise to conscience-shocking level” is the “conduct intended to injure in some way unjustifiable by any government interest.” Here, there is no evidence that Chavez acted with a purpose to harm Martinez by intentionally interfering with his medical treatment. Medical personnel were able to treat Martinez throughout the interview, and Chavez ceased his questioning to allow tests and other procedures to be performed. Nor is there any evidence that Chavez’s conduct exacerbated 56 Complex issue: federal civil rights actions, state tort suits [FN ON WHAT HAPPENED ON REMAND.] 58 The text of the due process clause suggests that it is procedural. The Fifth Amendment says that “no person shall be deprived of life, liberty or property without due process of law.” The 14th Amendment uses similar language but applies it to the states. Thus, the substantive values of life, liberty and property may not be taken away except by compliance with the procedural requirements of due process. This much debated interpretation will be considered infra. 59 Emphasis added. History may show it has been a relative concept at common law, varying with the prior evidence. 60 TRYTO FIND SUPPORT FOR THIS 57 D:\533582156.doc Created on 10/9/2006 11:33:00 AM Last printed 3/9/2016 2:16:00 AM Page 25 of 158 Words 47,586 Martinez’s injuries or prolonged his stay in the hospital. Moreover, the need to investigate whether there had been police misconduct constituted a justifiable government interest given the risk that key evidence would have been lost if Martinez had died without the authorities ever hearing his side of the story.”61 (emphasis added) Under this standard, coercive interrogation would be constitutionally permissible if its purpose were to serve a “justifiable government interest.” This would certainly seem to cover the government’s interest in obtaining information deemed necessary to prevent not only terrorism, but any crime or social evil. Here the government interest was relatively minor – protecting police officers from possible liability by getting Martinez to admit he was at fault. If the governmental interest were far more compelling – the prevention of terrorism, for example – the degree of coercion could presumably exceed even that used here without violating either due process or the privilege against self-incrimination.62 At least that was the view of Justice Thomas and his three colleagues. The five majority justices on the issue of due process did not conclude that the conduct in this case necessarily rose to the level of a substantive due process violation. They simply remanded the case to the lower court for a determination of whether Martinez could “pursue a claim” that his right to substantive due process had been violated by the police interrogation itself. [ALEX: CHECK WHAT HAPPENED ON REMAND] The current law of substantive due process, as it relates to police interrogation, is in a state of disarray. The court has “always been reluctant to expand the concept of substantive due process.”63 Accordingly it ruled in Graham v. Conner, 490 U.S. 386 (1985) that where “a particular amendment provides an explicit textual source of constitutional protection against a particular sort of government behavior, that amendment, not the more generalized notion of substantive due process, must be the guide for analyzing these claims.” What does this ruling mean with regard to the claim made by Martinez in this case? Martinez argued that the interrogation in his 61 538 U.S. 760, at 774-75 (citations omitted). Nor would torture constitute “cruel and unusual” punishment, since the Court has ruled that this prohibition applies only to punishment imposed after trial and with a “punitive purpose.” [CITE] [Charlie: SOMEONE, PLEASE CHECK THIS FOR ME. I THINK ALAN IS LOOKING FOR Hope v. Pelzer, 536 U.S. 730.] 63 Colins v Harker U.S. 386(19) 503 U.S. 115,125 (1992) 62 D:\533582156.doc Created on 10/9/2006 11:33:00 AM Last printed 3/9/2016 2:16:00 AM Page 26 of 158 Words 47,586 case violated the privilege against self-incrimination, which in his view provides “an explicit textual source of constitutional protection against [the] government behavior” in his case. A majority of the Supreme Court disagreed. Does that mean that the case can now be decided under substantive due process? Or must it still be decided - against Martinez - - under the privilege against self-incrimination, because it is the text of that more specific provision of the Fifth Amendment that “must be the guide for analyzing” his claims? In 199764 the Court stated that the Graham principle: “does not hold that all constitutional claims relating to physically abusive government conduct must arise under either the Fourth or Eighth Amendments; rather, Graham simply requires that if a constitutional claim is covered by a specific constitutional provision, such as the Fourth or Eight Amendment, the claim must be analyzed under the standard appropriate to that specific provision, not under the rubric of substantive due process.”65 In 1998, the Court applied that ruling in a case involving a police chase that resulted in the death of the fleeing suspect. It ruled that police chases that do not culminate in a “seizure” of the suspect are not “covered” by the Fourth Amendment.66 Accordingly, the case could be considered under the rubric of substantive due process. The court held, however, that there was no violation of substantive due process, even though the actions of the police involved “deliberate or reckless indifference to life.” The Martinez case is somewhat different. The interrogation is plainly “covered” by the privilege against self-incrimination, as evidenced by the conclusion - - agreed to by all nine justices - - that its fruits would be inadmissible in any criminal prosecution against Martinez. But that “cover” does not provide a remedy other than exclusion. Nor does it provide a stand alone right not to be coerced. It is difficult to predict, therefore, whether the Supreme Court will hold, in a case like Martinez’s, that the privilege “covers” the interrogation and that that provision of the Fifth Amendment rather than “the more generalized notions of substantive due process must be the guide for analyzing these claims.” The fact that a majority of the justices remanded the Martinez case for a determination of 64 Describe case: U.S. v. Lanier, 520 U.S. 259 (1997) United Sates v. Lanier, 520 U.S. 259, n. 7 (1997). 66 “Substantive due process analysis is therefore inappropriate in his case only if respondent’ claim is “covered by” the Fourth Amendment”. 523 U.S. 833 (1998) 65 D:\533582156.doc Created on 10/9/2006 11:33:00 AM Last printed 3/9/2016 2:16:00 AM Page 27 of 158 Words 47,586 whether Martinez may pursue a claim of substantive due process, suggests that his case may not be “covered”, by the privilege, in the sense used by the court in Lanier. Even if claims of abusive interrogation can survive the “covered by” a specific amendment test, and be considered under “substantive due process,” the criteria for establishing a violation of substantive due process, are not easy to satisfy. The test for determining whether government action violates substantive due process has long been whether it “shocks the conscience.” That test was first articulated by Justice Felix Frankfurter in the 1952 case of Rochin v. California67, which involved an effort by three California deputy sheriffs to retrieve capsules - - reasonably believed to be unlawful drugs - - from the stomach of a suspect who had swallowed them during a police search: “When asked “whose stuff is this?” Rochin seized the capsules and put them in his mouth. A struggle ensued, in the course of which the three officers “jumped upon him” and attempted to extract the capsules. The force they applied proved unavailing against Rochin’s resistance. He was handcuffed and taken to a hospital. At the direction of one of the officers a doctor forced an emetic solution through a tube into Rochin’s stomach against his will. This “stomach pumping” produced vomiting. In the vomited matter were found two capsules which proved to contain morphine.”68 The Supreme Court ruled that: “This is conduct that shocks the conscience. Illegally breaking into the privacy of the petitioner, the struggle to open his mouth and remove what was there, the forcible extraction of his stomach’s contents – this course of proceeding by agents of government to obtain evidence is bound to offend even hardened sensibilities. They are methods too close to the rack and the screw to permit of constitutional differentiation.”69 In so ruling, the court analogized the conduct at issue in the Rochin case to coercing a confession: “It would be a stultification of the responsibility which the course of constitutional history has cast upon this Court to hold that in order to convict a man the police cannot extract by 67 342 U.S. 165 (1952) Rochin v. California 342 U.S. (1951) 69 Rochin v. California 342 U.S. (1951) 68 D:\533582156.doc Created on 10/9/2006 11:33:00 AM Last printed 3/9/2016 2:16:00 AM Page 28 of 158 Words 47,586 force what is in his mind but can extract what is in his stomach.”70 This analogy would seem to suggest that it could violate substantive due process for the police to “extract by force what is in [a suspect’s] mind,” but that might well depend on the nature and degree of the force employed. The Rochin case is no longer good due process law under the Graham principle. Indeed in Lewis, decided in 1998, the Court explicitly said that a Rochin-type case, involving an intrusive body search, would “today be treated under the Fourth Amendment,” but it added that it would have the “same result.”71 The reason it would have the same result, however, is that a Fourth Amendment search would have to satisfy the criteria of not being “unreasonable,” but unreasonableness alone might not satisfy the much more demanding “shocks the conscience” test of substantive due process. The “shocks the conscience” test has been controversial from the very beginning.7273 These days, Justice Scalia mocks it mercilessly. In Lewis, he accused the majority opinion of: “resuscitat[ing] the ne plus ultra, the Napoleon Brandy, the Mahatma Ghandi, the Cellophane of subjectivity, th’ ol’ “shocks-the-conscience” test.”74 He explained his references in a footnote: “For those unfamiliar with classical music, I note that the exemplars of excellence in the test are borrowed from Cole Porter’s “You’re the Top,” copyright 1934.” The bottom line is that it is impossible to predict with any level of confidence how the current Supreme Court (or its successors) will evaluate claims of substantive due process brought by alleged victims of police abuses in preventive interrogation cases or other interrogations in which the fruits of the coercion are not used against the suspect in a subsequent criminal prosecution.75 In light of this 70 71 Rochin v. California 523 U.S. at 849, N.9 72 73 Cite Criticism of it County of Sacramento v. Lewis, 523 U.S. 833, at 861 (1998) [Charlie: SOMEONE PLEASE CHECK] 75 Under the Supreme Court’s approach to coercive interrogation, the lower courts now will have to make a dual determination with regard to every challenge interrogation. If the fruits of the interrogation are sought to be introduced against the defendant, the court will have to decide whether impermissible coercion was used and the resulting confession was involuntary. This will involve an analysis of 74 D:\533582156.doc Created on 10/9/2006 11:33:00 AM Last printed 3/9/2016 2:16:00 AM Page 29 of 158 Words 47,586 uncertainty over substantive due process, the Court’s decision that coercion alone does not violate the right not to incriminate oneself, will encourage police to employ coercion in situations involving the perceived need for preventive intelligence. This is especially true, since the Court has also said that: “Qualified immunity seeks to ensure that defendants “reasonably can anticipate when their conduct may give rise to liability,” id., at 195, by attaching liability only if “[t]he contours of the right [violated are] sufficiently clear that a reasonable official would understand that what he is doing violates that right” Uncertainty, therefore, is a defense in a case of this sort, both against civil and criminal liability.76 And there is considerably uncertainty now, as the result of the multiple opinions in the Chavez case and the confusion in the law of substantive due process. In deciding that the privilege against self-incrimination does not prohibit the government from coercing incriminating information from a person, so long as that information (and presumably its fruits) are not admitted against that person in a criminal prosecution, Justice Thomas relied primarily on the “text of the Fifth Amendment.” He concluded that “mere coercion does not violate the text of the SelfIncrimination Clause absent use of the compelled statements in a criminal case and against the witness.” He also relied, but to a lesser the privilege against self-incrimination. If the interrogation was not coerced and the confession not involuntary, the court will have to decide whether it nonetheless violated the Miranda rule. The exclusionary consequences will be different depending on whether the confession was involuntary or merely a violation of Miranda. This was the law prior to Martinez and it continues to be the law today. But if the defendant is not prosecuted and seeks a civil remedy for the improper interrogation, the court will have to make an entirely different determination. It will not suffice to conclude that his confession was coerced or elicited in violation of Miranda. The court will now have to decide whether the interrogation also meets the far more difficult standard of a substantive due process violation, namely whether it shocks the conscience and was conducted for no legitimate governmental purpose. This is a new burden on the courts and will complicate its … [ALAN HAS TO COMPLETE THIS.] 76 U.S. v. Lanier, 250 U.S. 259, 270: “So conceived, the object of the “clearly established” immunity standard is not different from that of “fair warning” as it relates to law “made specific” for the purpose of validly applying £242. The fact that one has a civil and the other a criminal law role is of no significance; both serve the same objective, and in effect the qualified immunity test is simply the adaptation of the fair warning standard to give officials (and, ultimately, governments) the same protection from civil liability and its consequences that individuals have traditionally possessed in the face of vague criminal statutes.” D:\533582156.doc Created on 10/9/2006 11:33:00 AM Last printed 3/9/2016 2:16:00 AM Page 30 of 158 Words 47,586 degree, on precedential analogy: namely the precedent that permits “an immunized witness [to be] forced to testify on pain of contempt,” and the analogy between such legally compelled testimony and the kind of physically coerced statements elicited from Martinez in the case at issue. Surprisingly, Justice Thomas — who considers himself something of an “originalist”77 — did not invoke the original history or understanding of the privilege. Nor did Thomas employ any kind of a functional analysis of the privilege or consider the impact of his decision on its application or scope. In the chapters to come, I will use the Martinez case as a window into broader issues relating to the history and policies underlying the privilege against self-incrimination, as well as into the trend toward turning what many citizens have long regarded as broad human rights into narrow criminal trial rights. I will also use the Martinez case to explore the various modes of constitutional analysis used by the Justices and by mainstream scholars in interpreting the Constitution in general and the privilege against self-incrimination in particular. Finally, I will use the Martinez case as a prism through which to glimpse the future of the privilege in the preventative state toward which we seem to be moving. I will begin with the textual analysis employed by Justice Thomas. David G. Savage, “Engaged in a Very Civil War: The Federalist Society has reshaped the legal system without ever going to court,” Los Angeles Times, November 11, 2005, p. A1. 77 D:\533582156.doc Created on 10/9/2006 11:33:00 AM Last printed 3/9/2016 2:16:00 AM Page 31 of 158 Words 47,586 Chapter 1: The Limits of Textual Analysis in Constitutional Interpretation No serious judge or scholar would disagree with the proposition that any effort to interpret a constitutional provision must begin with its text. The problem is that many such provisions are ambiguous, unclear, cryptic, open-ended, and subject to multiple interpretations which may all be reasonable, at least on their face. Human language, particularly legal and political language, cannot begin to capture the complexity and nuance of human thought, action and interaction.78 Oliver Wendell Holmes Jr. wisely observed, “A word is not a crystal, transparent and unchanged. It is the skin of a living thought and may vary greatly in color and context according to the circumstances and time in which it is used.”79 Lewis Carroll put it more contentiously: “When I use a word,” said Humpty Dumpty in a rather scornful tone, “it means just what I choose it to mean – nothing more nor less….” “That’s a great deal to make one word mean,” Alice said in a thoughtful tone. “When I make a word do a lot of work like that,” said Humpty Dumpty, “I always pay it extra.”80 As we shall see, some words that appear in our Constitution are entitled to significant overtime pay plus bonuses. According to one school of constitutional interpretation, the words of that document must be interpreted as the framers81 understood them at the time they became part of the Constitution. But it is not always easy to retrieve the meaning or to adapt it to a legal (or political) system that has changed considerably over the centuries. For example, the prohibition against “cruel and unusual punishments” contained in the Eighth Amendment was written before there were prisons, capable of holding convicted defendants for long periods of time. The punishments of the time included death, branding, stockades, warning out and ____________, but not long term As Democritus wrote more than 2000 years ago: “word is a shadow of deed.” Quoted in America Declares Independence, p.4 80 Lewis Carroll, The Annotated Alice (New York: Norton, 2000), p. 213. 81 Broadly defined to include ratifiers etc. – CITE AUTHORITY 78 79 D:\533582156.doc Created on 10/9/2006 11:33:00 AM Last printed 3/9/2016 2:16:00 AM Page 32 of 158 Words 47,586 imprisonment. It is difficult to extrapolate the understanding of the framers to the current situation in which repeat petit offenders can be sentenced to life imprisonment under “three strikes” statutes. Another example would be the prohibition against “excessive bail,” which the framers understood as permitting no bail - - i.e. no pre-trial release - - in capital cases. It is difficult, if not impossible, to determine whether this understanding would translate into denial of pre-trial release for today’s non-capital defendants charged with drug crimes. Many crimes that are today not capital were capital at the time of the enactment of the Bill of Rights precisely because there were no prisons and therefore no long prison sentences. Once longterm imprisonment became an available alternative, many crimes previously punished by death, became punishable by life imprisonment. What is uncertain is whether capital crimes were deemed non-bailable because the extreme punishment the defendant faced—namely execution—provided a strong incentive for fleeing, or whether capital crimes were non-bailable because of the supposed dangerousness of the crimes and the fear that the defendant might commit harmful dangerous crimes while awaiting trial? If the former, the historical argument for pre-trial release of non-capital defendants today would be strong. If the latter, the case for preventive pre-trial detention of dangerous defendants would be compelling. But because nearly all dangerous crimes were also capital crimes at the time the Bill of Rights were ratified, it is unlikely that the framers ever focused on which of these two possible reasons explained the non-bailability of capital crimes. If that is the case, then there as no original understanding with regard to the bailability of non capital, dangerous crimes. Yet another example might be the guarantee of trial by jury in criminal cases, which was clearly understood by the framers to require a unanimous twelve man jury (also a jury of property owning, Christian, white, males). Yet the Court has now permitted nonunanimous, six person juries (with poor, non-Christian, non-white, non-male jurors). It is certainly possible that some of the framers of some open-ended provisions — like “equal protection of the laws,” “due process,” “cruel and unusual punishment,” “excessive bail,” “unreasonable searches and seizures” — deliberately wrote them in a manner that would permit common-law courts to do what commonlaw courts have always done: namely to “evolve”82 differing I use the term “evolve” because it is a word commonly used by common law courts. It is, in fact, a poor metaphor because biological evolution is purposeless, 82 D:\533582156.doc Created on 10/9/2006 11:33:00 AM Last printed 3/9/2016 2:16:00 AM Page 33 of 158 Words 47,586 interpretations over time, place, and circumstance. After all, the framers certainly knew how to write unambiguous provisions that do not permit of varying judicial interpretations. The age requirements for president, senators, and members of Congress are not “maturity,” “experience,” or “seniority” - - words that would not require some interpretation. They are “thirty five,” “thirty,” and “twenty five” years of age - - words that are self-defining. The requirement for ratifying a treaty is not “a substantial majority,” a “supermajority,” or a “consensus.” It is “two thirds of the Senators present.” The amount in controversy that triggers a jury trial in civil cases is not “substantial” or “considerable.” It is “twenty dollars” – not even adjusted for inflation! Into which category, then, do the words of the right against self-incrimination fit? The provision is quite short. “No person … shall be compelled in any criminal case to be a witness against himself.” The Supreme Court, in the 1897 decision Bram v. United States, characterized the provision as “concise” and “generic.”83 Some of its words are relatively simple to interpret. The courts have long ruled that “persons” includes not only citizens but “resident aliens.”84 The framers could, of course, have used the term they used in the Sixth Amendment, “the accused,” but they chose the more general word “person.” And they placed the privilege not within the Sixth Amendment, which deals only with criminal defendants, but instead in the Fifth Amendment which deals both with criminal defendants and ordinary people. “Shall be compelled” is a bit more difficult, because it can bear several interpretations. It could refer only to lawful or formal compulsion, such as that ordered by a judge. Or it could also include extrajudicial and informal compulsion, such as that employed by police in the interrogation room. (As we shall see, there were no police at the time of the framers, but there was a long history of coercive interrogation). “In any criminal case”—words that were added at the last minute without debate85—could be defined narrowly to include only criminal trials, or more broadly to encompass any investigation into criminal conduct, or even any random and accidental, whereas common law development is guided by purposive human hands. 83 Bram v. United States, 168 U.S. 532, 548, 543 (1897). 84 United States v. Balsys, 524 U.S. 666, 671 (1998). 85 Give Explanation that was offered [ALAN: DID YOU HAVE ANY IN MIND? OR DID YOU JUST WANT ME TO QUOTE THE RECORDS OF THE DEBATE?] FROM ALAN: [THERE IS SOME MATERIAL IN THE 5th AMENDMENT COLLECTION, CITE IT- D:\533582156.doc Created on 10/9/2006 11:33:00 AM Last printed 3/9/2016 2:16:00 AM Page 34 of 158 Words 47,586 proceeding that could eventuate in a criminal prosecution. “To be a witness” could be interpreted to mean only a sworn witness who gives testimony,” or it could include unsworn witnesses as well. But giving the word “witness” the former meaning would render the provision meaningless at the time it was written, since defendants were not allowed to testify as sworn witnesses at their own trials, even if they wanted to. Interpreted literally and narrowly, the words of the Fifth Amendment do not grant a person the right to remain silent. And that is what Justice Thomas concluded. But that cannot properly end the inquiry, because the same sort of literal, narrow reading would also permit the introduction of evidence obtained by police or judicial coercion prior to trial. Indeed, it would allow the government to use the unsworn recorded statements admittedly coerced from Martinez, were he to have been placed on trial for assault with a deadly weapon – a conclusion categorically rejected by the majority in Martinez. The words of the 5th Amendment say absolutely nothing at all about evidence, though some contemporaneous state prohibitions used that word.86 The 5th Amendment refers only to “a witness.” Read literally, it prohibits the government87 only from compelling a person to testify—that’s what “a witness” does—“against himself” in “any criminal case.” Its words do not prohibit the police from testifying about — or playing a recording of — what the defendant said (At that point he was not a witness, but rather a suspect.) after the police compelled him to speak, but before the criminal trial or case began.88 Nor does it prohibit a clerk from reading the transcript of testimony the person was compelled by a judge to give in a non-criminal case. So long as the defendant himself is not called as an actual witness by the prosecution and compelled to be a live witness against himself at the criminal trial itself, the text of the Constitution — literally read, as Justice Thomas said it should be — is not violated.89 Yet Justice Thomas had no doubt that “statements compelled by police interrogations of course may not be used against a defendant 86 CITE [ALAN: NEED TO LOOK AT LEONARD LEVY BOOK, IN OFFICE, IN ORDER TO FILL THIS IN.] 87 Literally, only the federal government. See Brown v. Mississippi, 297 U.S. 278 (1936). But, as we shall see, the Fourteenth Amendment has been interpreted to apply some, though not all, provisions of the Bill of Rights to the states. In Malloy v. Hogan, 378 U.S. 1 (1964), the Court held the privilege applicable to the states. 88 Justice Thomas said that a “criminal case” begins no earlier than “the initiation of legal proceedings” and that “police questioning does not constitute a case….” 89 At the time of the ratification of the 5th Amendment, defendants did not testify under oath [and], so it is difficult to understand the use of the word “witness” in the context of a criminal case. D:\533582156.doc Created on 10/9/2006 11:33:00 AM Last printed 3/9/2016 2:16:00 AM Page 35 of 158 Words 47,586 at trial….” But why not? Certainly not because of the text itself, which would seem to authorize the admissibility of such “statements,” as long as they were testified to by the police and not the defendant — so long as the defendant was not compelled to be “a witness against himself.” Yet Thomas seems to be saying that “the admission into evidence in a criminal case of confessions obtained through coercive custodial questioning” would violate “the right protected by the text of the Self-Incrimination Clause.” No it wouldn’t, because “the text” of that clause says nothing about evidence of confessions secured by the police before trial by coercive questioning. Thomas simply makes up his textual reference. Justice Thomas chides Justice Stevens for his “indifference to the text of the Self-Incrimination Clause, as well as [for his] conspicuous absence of a single citation to the actual text of the Fifth Amendment.” But what Thomas did was worse: he selectively cites and then selectively shows indifference to the text, as it fits his result. He cites “the text” for a proposition it simply does not contain — namely the exclusion of testimony by the police of out of court confessions they coerced from the defendant. For the text of the 5th Amendment to support the exclusion of evidence produced by the prior out-of-court compulsion or coercion of the defendant, it would have to include words such as the following: “and no evidence that is the product of compulsion or coercion of the defendant shall be admitted against him at his criminal trial”. Several state constitutionals at the time of the framing contained language that would support the exclusion of all “evidence” that derived from compelled self-incrimination90, but the text of the Fifth Amendment is silent about evidence and is limited to prohibiting the government from compelling a person “to be a witness against himself.” Indeed, a 1936 Supreme Court decision, rendered before the privilege had been applied to the states through the Fourteenth Amendment, read the clause literally as having no application to the admission into evidence of confessions coerced by the police prior to trial. In Brown v. Mississippi91 — a state case which dealt with the constitutionality of convicting someone based on a confession extracted through torture — the Court said that the self-incrimination clause of the Fifth Amendment is limited to “the processes of justice by which the accused may be called as a witness and required to testify.” The Court went on to say that “compulsion by torture to extort a confession is a different matter.” That “different matter” was to be decided under the “due process” clause, not the privilege against 90 91 Quote several state constitutions. Brown v. Mississippi, 297 U.S. 278 (1936). D:\533582156.doc Created on 10/9/2006 11:33:00 AM Last printed 3/9/2016 2:16:00 AM Page 36 of 158 Words 47,586 self-incrimination.92 (This view has not been followed,93 and Brown has been understood as applying the due process clause because the 5th Amendment had not yet been held applicable to the states. I cite it here only to show that a prior Supreme Court decision, of which Justice Thomas was aware, read the text of the self-incrimination narrowly to apply only to in-court testimony by the defendant.) Justice Thomas cites several cases — including Brown — to support his view that the privilege does require the exclusion of statements compelled by police interrogations as well as testimony compelled by judges, but that it does not prohibit the compulsion itself. As we shall see, those cases (and others, not cited by Thomas) are inconsistent and inconclusive as to the proper interpretation of the privilege. By citing judicial precedents, however, Justice Thomas seemed to acknowledge that the text alone is not dispositive. According to Justice Thomas and the other Justices who joined his opinion, precedent matters as well — at least sometimes. Justices Thomas and Scalia have argued that precedent should be ignored, indeed overruled, when it is inconsistent with the text — at least sometimes.94 This time, these justices chose to rely primarily on 92 Brown is a confusing opinion because it was a state case decided before the privilege was ruled applicable to the states [elaborate] 93 See Malloy v. Hogan, 378 U.S. 1 (1964), at 6-7 (citations omitted): Brown v. Mississippi was the first case in which the Court held that the Due Process Clause prohibited the States from using the accused’s coerced confessions against him. The Court in Brown felt impelled, in light of Twining, to say that its conclusion did not involve the privilege against self-incrimination. “Compulsion by torture to extort a confession is a different matter.” But this distinction was soon abandoned, and today the admissibility of a confession in a state criminal prosecution is tested by the same standard applied in federal prosecutions since 1897, when, in Bram v. United States, the Court held that “in criminal trials, in the courts of the United States, wherever a question arises whether a confession is incompetent because not voluntary, the issue is controlled by that portion of the Fifth Amendment to the Constitution of the United States, commanding that no person ‘shall be compelled in any criminal case to be a witness against himself.’” Under this test, the constitutional inquiry is not whether the conduct of state officers in obtaining the confession was shocking, but whether the confession was “free and voluntary: that is, [it] must not be extracted by any sort of threats or violence, nor obtained by any direct or implied promises, however slight, nor by the exertion of any improper influence….” In other words the person must not have been compelled to incriminate himself. We have held inadmissible even a confession secured by so mild a whip as the refusal, under certain circumstances, to allow a suspect to call his wife until he confessed. 94 Scalia reportedly said the following about Thomas: “He does not believe in stare decisis, period…. If a constitutional line of authority is wrong, he would say let’s D:\533582156.doc Created on 10/9/2006 11:33:00 AM Last printed 3/9/2016 2:16:00 AM Page 37 of 158 Words 47,586 precedent — at least selectively — rather than literal textual analysis, in concluding that police may not testify about incriminating statements they compelled the defendant to make prior to his trial.95 But they chose to rely primarily on literal textual analysis in concluding that a person — in this case Martinez — had no right not to be compelled or coerced to answer self-incriminating questions, so long as his answers could not be admitted against him at a criminal trial in which he was a defendant. To be sure, there is considerable precedent — Both before and after Brown — supporting the view that evidence of pre-trial coerced confessions cannot be admitted against a criminal defendant at his trial, despite the absence of specific textual support for that conclusion in the relevant words, of the Fifth Amendment. There is no direct precedential support for the conclusion that the privilege against self-incrimination is violated at the point when compulsion is employed, rather than at the point when its fruits are admitted at the criminal trial.96 But nor is there any direct support for the opposite get it right. I wouldn’t do that.” Ken Foskett, Judging Thomas: The Life and Times of Clarence Thomas (New York: HarperCollins, 2004), p. 281-82. Yet, Scalia wrote the following in a dissent: With some reservation concerning decisions that have become so embedded in our system of government that return is no longer possible … I agree with Justice Douglas: A judge looking at a constitutional decision may have compulsions to revere past history and accept what was once written. But he remembers above all else that it is the Constitution which he swore to support and defend, not the gloss which his predecessors may have put on it. South Carolina v. Gathers, 490 U.S. 805, 825 (1989) (Scalia dissenting). 95 They also purported to rely on “the text” but failed to explain how any plausible reading of the text alone would require the exclusion of out of court coerced confessions testified to by a witness other than the defendant. 96 In his dissenting opinion, Justice Kennedy said that the majority position, “finds some support in a single statement in United States v. VerdugoUrquidez, 494 U.S. 259, 264 (1990) (“Although conduct by law enforcement officials prior to trial may ultimately impair that right [against compelled self-incrimination], a constitutional violation occurs only at trial”). That case concerned the application of the Fourth Amendment, and the extent of the right secured under the Self-Incrimination Clause was not then before the Court. Ibid. Furthermore, Verdugo-Urquidez involved a prosecution in the United States arising from a criminal investigation in another country, id., at 274-275, so there was a special reason for the Court to be concerned about the application of the Clause in that context, id., at 269 (noting the Court had “rejected the claim that aliens are entitled to Fifth Amendment rights outside the sovereign territory of the United States” (citing Johnson v. Eisentranger, 339 U.S. 763 (1950))). In any event, the decision cannot be read to support the proposition that the D:\533582156.doc Created on 10/9/2006 11:33:00 AM Last printed 3/9/2016 2:16:00 AM Page 38 of 158 Words 47,586 view. It was an open question prior to Martinez,97 though there was language - - dictum - - that could support either view98. In deciding to employ a largely textual analysis, the Court disregarded earlier precedents pertaining to the proper mode of interpreting the cryptic words of the Fifth Amendment. An 1897 (pre-Brown) Supreme Court decision interpreting the privilege in a federal criminal case expressly considered whether it only prohibited the government from calling a defendant as a witness at his own criminal trial — the literal meaning of the words used in the Fifth Amendment — or whether it also prohibited the government from introducing, through other witnesses, evidence of statements the defendant was compelled to make prior to trial. The Court rejected the literal interpretation and concluded that “the generic language of the Amendment was but a crystallization of the doctrine as to [out-ofcourt] confessions, well settled when the Amendment was adopted….”99 The Court went on to say that: application of the Clause is limited in the way JUSTICE SOUTER and JUSTICE THOMAS describe today. A recent case illustrates that a violation of the Self-Incrimination Clause may have immediate consequences. Just last Term, nine Justices all proceeded from the premise that a present, completed violation of the Self-Incrimination Clause could occur if an incarcerated prisoner were required to admit to past crimes on pain of forfeiting certain privileges of being assigned harsher conditions of confinement. McKune v. Lile, 536 U.S. 24 (2002); id., at 48 (O’CONNOR, J., concurring in judgment); id., at 54 (STEVENS, J., dissenting). Although there was disagreement over whether a violation occurred in the circumstances of that case, there was no disagreement that a present violation could have taken place. No Member of the Court suggested that the absence of a pending criminal proceeding made the Self-Incrimination Clause inquiry irrelevant. This is not to say all questions as to the meaning and extent of the Clause are simple of resolution, or that all of the cited cases are easy to reconcile. Many questions about the application of the Self-Incrimination Clause are close and difficult. There are instances, moreover, when incriminating statements can be required from a reluctant witness, see, e.g., Gardner, supra, at 276, and others where information may be required even absent a promise of immunity, see, e.g., Shapiro v. United States, 335 U.S. 1, 19 (1948). JUSTICE SOUTER and JUSTICE THOMAS are correct to note that testimony may be ordered, on pain of contempt, if appropriate immunity is granted. It does not follow that the Clause establishes no present right. The immunity rule simply shows that the right is not absolute.” 97 See Murphy v. Waterfront Commission, 378 U.S. 52 (1964), 104 n. 6. 98 Cite Language in cases 99 Bram v. United States, 168 U.S. 532, 543 (1897). D:\533582156.doc Created on 10/9/2006 11:33:00 AM Last printed 3/9/2016 2:16:00 AM Page 39 of 158 Words 47,586 The well settled nature of the rule in England at the time of the adoption of the Constitution and of the Fifth Amendment, and the intimate knowledge had by the framers of the principles of civil liberty which had become a part of the common law, aptly explain the conciseness of the language of that Amendment.100 In other words, the “generic” and “concise[]” constitutional text did not exhaust its intended or understood meaning. Its future applications had been left “to be evolved from the facts of each particular case”101 — a process well-known to the common law framers of the Constitution. The “generic” and “concise” words of the privilege had to be read against the background of law and practice at the time of the enactment of the Bill of Rights. They could not be wrenched out of their literal context and read abstractly as if they were simply a collection of syllables, as Thomas essentially did. Put another way, these exact same words would mean something very different if they had been written by the framers of the French, German, Russian or Louisiana [check this] constitutions, since those framers would understand these same words to mean something quite different because of their very different legal systems. As Wittgenstein once observed, “If a lion could talk, we could not understand him.”102 As we shall soon see, if a framer of the 5th Amendment could talk about how he understood the criminal justice system, and how the words of the 5th Amendment fit into it, we would have considerable difficulty understanding him, as we shall soon see when we examine the nearcontemporaneous opinion of Chief Justice John Marshall in the Aaron Burr case.. In focusing primarily on the text, the Court also disregarded, in the words of Justice Kennedy, “the understanding that has prevailed for generations now,” namely that Americans have a “right to remain silent,” or at least “a right not to be compelled to incriminate themselves.” Even the late Chief Justice William Rehnquist — who just three years earlier had characterized the 100 168 U.S. 532, 548. 168 U.S. 532, 549. The Court used the word “evolved” in the context of “the courts [having] left the rule to be evolved,” but the framers understood that courts would be playing that role, especially with a rule so closely related to the criminal trial process. 102 Ludwig Wittgenstein, Philosophical Investigations: The German Text, With a Revised English Translation, (Oxford: Blackwell, 2002), p. 241. 101 D:\533582156.doc Created on 10/9/2006 11:33:00 AM Last printed 3/9/2016 2:16:00 AM Page 40 of 158 Words 47,586 Miranda warning as part of American culture — joined the Thomas opinion, 103 as did Justice Scalia who just four years earlier had mocked those who feigned ignorance of their well-known “right to remain silent.” To be sure, the right to remain silent has never been thought to be unconditional or unlimited, as we shall see in the next chapter. Even if there were such a right, it would be difficult to define its parameters. What exactly would a “right to remain silent” entail? When would it come into operation? Would it exist even in the absence of compulsion or coercion? Or would it merely provide a shield against the government’s power to compel or coerce selfincrimination? But, regardless of how the right may be defined and limited, most Americans would be shocked to learn that the 5th Amendment is totally silent on, and utterly irrelevant to, any claim not to be coerced by the police into making self-incriminating statements. Justice Kennedy was correct in observing that: The conclusion that the Self-Incrimination Clause is not violated until the government seeks to use a statement in some later criminal proceeding strips the Clause of an essential part of its force and meaning. This is no small matter. It should come as an unwelcome surprise to judges, attorneys, and the citizenry as a whole that if a legislative committee or a judge in a civil case demands incriminating testimony without 103 Chief Justice Rehnquist was all over the lot when it came to interpreting the privilege against self-incrimination. In a 1990 case, United States v. VerdugoUrquidez, 494 U.S. 259, involving the Fourth Amendment, he wrote the following dictum about the Fifth Amendment: Before analyzing the scope of the Fourth Amendment, we think it significant to note that it operates in a different manner than the Fifth Amendment, which is not at issue in this case. The privilege against selfincrimination guaranteed by the Fifth Amendment is a fundamental trial right of criminal defendants. Although conduct by law enforcement officials prior to trial may ultimately impair that right, a constitutional violation occurs only at trial. The Fourth Amendment functions differently. It prohibits “unreasonable searches and seizures” whether or not the evidence is sought to be used in a criminal trial, and a violation of the Amendment is “fully accomplished” at the time of an unreasonable governmental intrusion. For purposes of this case, therefore, if there were a constitutional violation, it occurred solely in Mexico. Whether evidence obtained from respondent’s Mexican residences should be excluded at trial in the United States is a remedial question separate from the existence vel non of the constitutional violation. United States v. Verdugo-Urquidez, 494 U.S. 259 (1990), at 264 (citations omitted). Taking his opinions together, they seem to mean that suspects in custody have a constitutional right under Miranda to be told that they have a constitutional right to remain silent—which they don’t in fact have! D:\533582156.doc Created on 10/9/2006 11:33:00 AM Last printed 3/9/2016 2:16:00 AM Page 41 of 158 Words 47,586 offering immunity, and even imposes sanctions for failure to comply, that the witness and counsel cannot insist the right against compelled self-incrimination is applicable then and there. Justice Souter and Justice Thomas, I submit, should be more respectful of the understanding that has prevailed for generations now. To tell our whole legal system that when conducting a criminal investigation police officials can use severe compulsion or even torture with no present violation of the right against compelled self-incrimination can only diminish a celebrated provision in the Bill of Rights. A Constitution survives over time because the people share a common, historic commitment to certain simple but fundamental principles which preserve their freedom. Today’s decision undermines one of those respected principles.104 Surely this widespread and long-term understanding of “the right to remain silent” in the face of police or judicial compulsion should be given some weight in interpreting the privilege, especially since the words alone — stripped of context and understanding — provides an even narrower meaning than the one the majority is prepared to accept. This view, that the widespread understanding of a constitutional provision that “has prevailed for generations now” should be taken into account, was accepted by a majority of the Supreme Court just three years prior to Martinez, in the decision reaffirming Miranda.105 In response to this argument, the majority makes the peculiar claim that “the core” rights protected by the privilege are limited to the defendant not being compelled to be an actual witness, and not having his coerced or compelled confessions admitted against him at his own criminal trial. But to “safeguard” those “core” rights, the Court has “created prophylactic rules.” These rules, according to the majority, have a somewhat lower constitutional status and include the following: ď‚· 104 “No ‘penalty’ may ever be imposed on someone who exercises his core Fifth Amendment right not to be a ‘witness’ against himself in a ‘criminal case.’ Griffin v. California 380 U.S. 609 (1965).” Chavez v. Martinez, 538 U.S. 760 (2003), at 793-94 (Kennedy concurring in part and dissenting in part). 105 Dickerson v. United States, 530 U.S. 428 (2000) D:\533582156.doc Created on 10/9/2006 11:33:00 AM Last printed 3/9/2016 2:16:00 AM Page 42 of 158 Words 47,586 ď‚· “Immunity [which] is not a right secured by the text of the Self-Incrimination Clause, but rather a prophylactic rule we [? sic] have constructed to protect the Fifth Amendment’s right from invasion.”106 ď‚· “We have likewise established the Miranda exclusionary rule as a prophylactic measure to prevent violations of the right protected by the text [sic] of the Self-Incrimination Clause – the admission into evidence in a criminal case of a confession obtained through coercive custodial questioning.” Each of these references to the distinction between “core rights” and “prophylactic rules” is wrong. First, the Court fails to address the question why the exclusion of confessions coerced by the police or compelled by judges prior to the criminal trial – a result not required by the text of the 5th Amendment – is a “core”, and not a “prophylactic” rule? What makes some non-textual extensions of the words core and others prophylactic? Surely the rule forbidding a penalty from being imposed on a defendant who exercises his textual right not to be a witness against himself is at least as close to the core as is the exclusion of evidence produced by pre-trial coercion107. If the Miranda exclusionary rule is indeed “a prophylactic measure” rather than a core of the privilege, then an act of Congress, substituting other “prophylactic measure[s]” should have been given far more weight than it was given in Dickerson. As far as immunity is concerned, whatever else it may be it is neither a “right” nor a “prophylactic measure.” It is a legislative authorization of immunity in an exercise of power designed to neutralize a claim of privilege under the 5th Amendment. Moreover, as we shall soon see, the logic of the majority opinion would seem to eliminate any semblance of a “right” to immunity. 106 It was the legislature that constructed—enacted—immunity provisions. The Courts merely ruled that if a person has immunity that is coterminous with his privilege, he can be compelled to answer questions that would otherwise be incriminating. This is hardly “a prophylactic rule … to protect the Fifth Amendment’s right from invasion.” Rather, it is a clever legislative mechanism designed to aid prosecutors in obtaining otherwise privileged information. 107 This is especially so since prior to Miranda, state compulsion cases were generally decided under the Fourteenth Amendment’s due process clause, rather than the Fifth Amendment’s privilege against self-incrimination. D:\533582156.doc Created on 10/9/2006 11:33:00 AM Last printed 3/9/2016 2:16:00 AM Page 43 of 158 Words 47,586 Chapter 2: The limits of precedent: Which way does “immunity” cut? The immunity precedent and analogy In addition to its rather sterile and unconvincing textual analysis – which is either too narrow or too broad – the plurality opinion invokes the concept of immunity as a precedential analogy. On its face, this argument seems like a slam-dunk. After all, if a person’s “right to remain silent” may be trumped by simply granting him derivative use immunity – namely a legislatively authorized and judicially enforced promise that whatever self-incriminating statements he is compelled by the law to make will not be used against him at his subsequent criminal trial108 -- then he never really had an absolute constitutional right to remain silent. All he ever had was a constitutional right not to have compelled testimony used against him at this criminal trial. 109 This follows from the universally accepted view that a statute may not trump a constitutional right. Since immunity is statutory and it does apparently trump any socalled right to remain silent, that right cannot be constitutional. End of argument! But it too is an argument that goes too far. If there were indeed no constitutional right to remain silent, why would there need to be legislation to trump it? Why couldn’t the court – even absent an immunity statute – simply compel any person (other than a criminal defendant at his own criminal trial) to answer any self-incriminatory question? The consequences of such compulsion would be the constitutionally required exclusion of the answer in his subsequent criminal case, but the person would have no right, even without a grant of immunity, to refuse to answer any otherwise proper question put to him in a civil case, a legislative hearing, or someone else’s criminal trial. This would seem to follow if he indeed had no right either to remain silent or not to be compelled to answer selfincriminatory questions in the first place. His only right would be the subsequent remedy of exclusion, which he retains. To be sure, the person being compelled might be required to raise some objection at the time of the compulsion in order to preserve the issue for trial, or to make it clear that he did not volunteer the information. But that is a This assures that testimony compelled by a judge before the defendant’s criminal trial cannot – under the 5th Amendment – be admitted against him at his criminal trial. As I previously showed, this result cannot be justified by the text of the 5th Amendment alone. 109 Nor will its fruits. That is what derivative means. 108 D:\533582156.doc Created on 10/9/2006 11:33:00 AM Last printed 3/9/2016 2:16:00 AM Page 44 of 158 Words 47,586 separate issue from the constitutional requirement of a statutory grant of immunity. Yet the Supreme Court has been crystal clear – for more than a century – that absent a formal grant of immunity, a person has an absolute right to remain silent when a judge or another public official seeks to compel him to answer incriminating questions. As the Supreme Court said in Kastigar v. United States:110 “The privilege…usually operates to allow a citizen to remain silent when asked a question requiring an incriminatory answer.”111 Indeed, the Supreme Court has been clear that the scope of the immunity must be at least “coterminous” with the scope of the privilege, or else the person retains the right to remain silent. These cases rest on the assumption – sometimes expressed, more often implied – that absent a grant of immunity, a person has a constitutional right to remain silent in the face of an incriminating question. Indeed, the Supreme Court, in one of its foundational cases with regard to the privilege—holding it fully applicable to the states—used the following broad language: The Fourteenth Amendment secures against state invasion the same privilege that the Fifth Amendment guarantees against federal infringement—the right of a person to remain silent unless he chooses to speak in the unfettered exercise of his own will, and to suffer no penalty … for such silence.112 Numerous other decisions, written by the widest array of Justices across the ideological and political spectrum have defined the Fifth Amendment privilege to include “the right to remain silent,” in the absence of a grant of immunity.113 Has a majority of the Court now overruled, sub silentio, this long line of cases? Can a judge now compel a witness in a civil case, a legislative committee, or someone else’s criminal trial to answer incriminating questions, even absent a formal grant of immunity?114 Why not, if the privilege includes only an exclusionary right and not any primary right to remain silent? Justice Kennedy raised this issue 110 406 U.S. 441 (1972). 406 U.S. 441, at 461 (emphasis added). 112 Malloy v. Hogan, 378 U.S. 1 (1964), at 8. 113 See appendix of more than 100 Supreme Court opinions referring to a right to remain silent. 114 You can be sure that in my next criminal case in which the defense seeks the testimony of a witness who pleads the fifth, I will raise the argument that under Martinez, the witness has no right to refuse to testify - - but only a right to have his testimony and its fruits excluded at any subsequent trial. (See infra pp. _______) 111 D:\533582156.doc Created on 10/9/2006 11:33:00 AM Last printed 3/9/2016 2:16:00 AM Page 45 of 158 Words 47,586 during the oral argument, asking the lawyer for the policeman the following question: Well, suppose in a civil case, the judge orders the witness confined to custody until he testifies in violation of what we can say in common parlance is his Fifth Amendment right to self-incrimination. Is that not a violation then and there to – to confine the – the defendant until he testifies?115 In his answer, the lawyer said the following: I suggest, Justice Kennedy, that the result – that the holding in Murphy against the Waterfront Commission is inexplicable if you believe, as the Ninth Circuit does, that it is sufficient simply to coerce an otherwise incriminating statement because in Murphy against the Waterfront Commission, the holding of that case is that the State court was correct in requiring the witness to testify even though there wasn’t a statute that protected him against incrimination because the Fifth Amendment itself provides the fail-safe that if you are coerced into giving an otherwise incriminating statement, it cannot be used against you.116 In fact, the actual holding of Murphy was quite different. The Court ruled that “[a]t the time they refused to answer” the incriminating questions put to them by the state, the witnesses “had a reasonable fear,” based on the existing case law, “that the federal authorities might use the answers against them in connection with a federal prosecution.”117 Accordingly, it reversed the contempt conviction, and “afforded [the witnesses] an opportunity,” in light of the newly announced rule granting them derivative use immunity, “to 115 Justice Kennedy’s concern that the majority opinion might make it possible to imprison for contempt an unimmunized witness who refused to answer an incriminating question is equally applicable to his own opinion. After all, he and his two dissenting colleagues did not conclude that there was a stand-alone right not to be coerced or compelled into making a self incriminating statement. This would seem to suggest that absent the use of torture or its equivalence, the government can compel a witness to make incriminating statements so long as it then does not use those statements or its fruits against the witness in a subsequent criminal case. The need for formal immunity would seem as irrelevant to Justice Kennedy’s approach as it would be to Justice Thomas’ approach. 116 Lawrence S. Robbins, oral argument for Chavez v. Martinez, 2002 U.S. TRANS LEXIS 69, at p. 5 (emphasis added). 117 Murphy v. Waterfront Commission, 378 U.S. 52 (1964), at 79-80. D:\533582156.doc Created on 10/9/2006 11:33:00 AM Last printed 3/9/2016 2:16:00 AM Page 46 of 158 Words 47,586 answer the questions.”118 In other words, before a witness can be lawfully compelled to answer an incriminating question—or be held in contempt for refusing to do so—he must at the very least know that the answer could not be used against him.119 This certainly suggests that there is a constitutional right to remain silent in the absence of a formal assurance of immunity. In fact, the Court in Murphy acknowledged—in a footnote—that there may be some “conceptual difficulty of pinpointing the alleged violation of the privilege on ‘compulsion’ or ‘use’”120 — the precise issue that eventually came before the Court in Martinez some 40 years later. The Court in Murphy stated that “The constitutional privilege against selfincrimination has two primary interrelated facets: The Government may not use compulsion to elicit self-incriminating statements; and the Government may not permit the use in a criminal trial of selfincriminating statements elicited by compulsion.”121 The Court said, however, that since the states and the federal government are now both constitutionally bound by the privilege, it was not necessary to be “concern[ed]” with deciding the precise point of impact of the privilege—compulsion or use.122 It also said that it “will not do … to assign one isolated policy to the privilege, and then to argue that since ‘the’ policy may not be furthered measurably by applying the privilege across state-federal lines, it follows that the privilege should not be so applied.”123 The Court in Murphy articulated several important policies underlying the privilege: It reflects many of our fundamental values and most noble aspirations: our unwillingness to subject those suspected of crime to the cruel dilemma of self-accusation, perjury or contempt; our preference for an accusatorial rather than inquisitorial system of criminal justice; our fear that selfincriminating statements will be elicited by inhumane treatment and abuses; our sense of fair play which dictates “a 118 Murphy v. Waterfront Commission, 378 U.S. 52 (1964), at 80. Moreover that case arose in the context of a federalism problem, where compromises in the interests of comity are often made. 120 Murphy v. Waterfront Commission, 378 U.S. 52 (1964), at 57, n. 6. 121 Murphy v. Waterfront Commission, 378 U.S. 52 (1964), at 57, n. 6 (citations omitted) (emphasis added). 122 Murphy v. Waterfront Commission, 378 U.S. 52 (1964), at 57, n. 6. In the interests of full disclosure, I must acknowledge that as Justice Goldberg’s law clerk in 1964, I drafted that footnote. 123 Murphy v. Waterfront Commission, 378 U.S. 52 (1964), at 56-57, n. 5. 119 D:\533582156.doc Created on 10/9/2006 11:33:00 AM Last printed 3/9/2016 2:16:00 AM Page 47 of 158 Words 47,586 fair state-individual balance by requiring the government in its contest with the individual to shoulder the entire load”; our respect for the inviolability of the human personality and of the right of each individual “to a private enclave where he may lead a private life”; our distrust of self-deprecatory statements; and our realization that the privilege, while sometimes “a shelter to the guilty,” is often “a protection to the innocent.”124 Murphy does not support the majority position in Martinez, despite the glib response given by Chavez’s lawyer to Justice Kennedy’s question. If anything, it lends at least some verbal support to the conclusion that the Fifth Amendment contains “two primary” limitations on governmental actions: 1) it may “not use compulsion to elicit self-incriminating statements;” and 2) it may not “use” such statements in a criminal trial. Murphy does, however, lend some support to the argument that - - at least in the context of federalism - - there may be no requirement of an immunity statute in order to compel selfincrimination. All that may be required is that the witness be told authoritatively by the judge, before he is compelled to answer the question, that either the constitution or a statute guarantees him derivative use immunity. Absent that formal assurance, he retains his constitutional right to remain silent. The basic right to remain silent in the absence of formal immunity was reaffirmed in Kastigar, decided eight years after Murphy. Kastigar reaffirmed the right of witnesses to assert the privilege against self-incrimination “in any proceeding, civil or criminal, administrative or judicial, investigatory or adjudicatory; and it protects against any disclosures that the witness reasonably believes could be used in a criminal prosecution [against him] or could lead to other evidence that might be so used.”125 This formulation certainly suggests that there is a basic right to remain silent in response to incriminating questions, as the Court had plainly articulated in the foundational case of Malloy v. Hogan.126 The Court then went on to analyze how immunity statutes impact this right: Immunity statutes, which have historical roots deep in Anglo-American jurisprudence, are not incompatible with these values. Rather, they seek a rational accommodation 124 Murphy v. Waterfront Commission, 378 U.S. 52 (1964), at 55 (citations omitted). 125 Kastigar v. United States, 406 U.S. 441, at 445 (1972) (notes omitted). 126 Malloy v. Hogan, 378 U.S. 1 (1964). D:\533582156.doc Created on 10/9/2006 11:33:00 AM Last printed 3/9/2016 2:16:00 AM Page 48 of 158 Words 47,586 between the imperatives of the privilege and the legitimate demands of government to compel citizens to testify….127 The constitutional inquiry, rooted in logic and history, as well as in the decisions of this Court, is whether the immunity granted under this statute is coextensive with the scope of the privilege. If so, petitioners’ refusals to answer based on the privilege were unjustified, and the judgments of contempt were proper, for the grant of immunity has removed the dangers against which the privilege protects. If, on the other hand, the immunity granted is not as comprehensive as the protection afforded by the privilege, petitioners were justified in refusing to answer, and the judgments of contempt must be vacated.128 The Court then went on to rule that derivative use immunity is coextensive with the scope of the privilege: This is a very substantial protection, commensurate with that resulting from invoking the privilege itself. The privilege assures that a citizen is not compelled to incriminate himself by his own testimony. It usually operates to allow a citizen to remain silent when asked a question requiring an incriminatory answer. This statute, which operates after a witness has given incriminatory testimony, affords the same protection by assuring that the compelled testimony can in no way lead to the infliction of criminal penalties.129 In other words, a citizen has the right to remain silent unless he has formally been given — either by the legislature or the court — a functionally coextensive right via the mechanism of derivative use immunity. That is the Kastigar rule, a rule that has been applied now in a long line of cases.130 Kastigar certainly does not support Justice Thomas’ inclusion of “immunity” as a “prophylactic” right analogous to the Miranda and Griffin rules. Immunity statutes, as Justice Powell correctly Significantly, immunity statutes do not “seek a rational accommodation” between the privilege and the constitutional rights of other criminal defendants to secure exculpatory evidence under the 6th Amendment [EXPAND]. 128 Kastigar v. United States, 406 U.S. 441, at 445-46, 449 (notes omitted) (citation omitted). 129 Kastigar v. United States, 406 U.S. 441, at 461 (note omitted) (emphasis added). 130 FOOTNOTE ON BALSYS CASE. [ALAN: WHAT ABOUT BALSYS DO YOU WANT DISCUSSED?] 127 D:\533582156.doc Created on 10/9/2006 11:33:00 AM Last printed 3/9/2016 2:16:00 AM Page 49 of 158 Words 47,586 characterized them, empower the government to compel testimony it would otherwise be unable to elicit. They reflect “a rational accommodation” — a compromise — “between the imperatives of the privilege and the legitimate demands of government to compel citizens to testify.” Hardly a “right” or “prophylactic” protection! It is no wonder that few witnesses seek derivative use immunity (as opposed to transactional immunity). It is imposed on them, generally against their will. This is not the case with true rights. Justice Stevens, in his opinion in Martinez, seemed to worry that the majority has indeed overruled the entire Kastigar line of immunity cases that presupposes a constitutional right to remain silent in the absence of coterminous immunity. He observed that “[i]t should come as an unwelcome surprise to judges, attorneys, and the citizenry as a whole that if a legislative committee or a judge in a civil case demands incriminating testimony without offering immunity, and even imposes sanctions for failure to comply, that the witness and counsel cannot insist the right against compelled self-incrimination is applicable then and there.” It is possible, of course, that a majority of Justices will eventually rule that although there is no absolute stand-alone right to remain silent, there is some sort of conditional right. In other words, absent a formal grant of appropriate immunity, every witness has the right to remain silent, but that right disappears when he is given such immunity. But what is a conditional constitutional right and how can a legislative enactment, namely, the authorization to grant immunity, trump any right granted by the Constitution? One possible answer is, it doesn’t! The person being compelled to answer with a grant of immunity knows that his answer is no longer self-incriminating, since there is an advanced legislative or judicially announced constitutional guarantee that it will never be used against him in any subsequent criminal case. In the very different context of the Martinez case, the person had no such advanced legislative or judicial guarantee. So far as Martinez knew – if he “knew” anything, considering the pain and fear he was expressing – he was being compelled to confess to the serious crimes of resisting arrest, and taking a gun from and pointing at a police officer. Neither the police officer nor Martinez understood that the statement he was being coerced into making could not be used against him if he were charged with a crime. The Thomas opinion says that this doesn’t matter: We fail to see how Martinez was any more “compelled in any criminal case to be a witness against himself” than an immunized witness forced to testify on pain of contempt. One difference, perhaps, is that the immunized witness knows that D:\533582156.doc Created on 10/9/2006 11:33:00 AM Last printed 3/9/2016 2:16:00 AM Page 50 of 158 Words 47,586 his statements will not, and may not, be used against him, whereas Martinez likely did not. But this does not make the statements of the immunized witness any less “compelled” [sic?]131 and lends no support to the Ninth Circuit’s conclusion that coercive police interrogations, absent the use of the involuntary statements in a criminal case, violate the Fifth Amendment’s Self-Incrimination Clause. Moreover, our cases provide that those subjected to coercive police interrogations have an automatic protection from the use of their involuntary statements (or evidence derived from their statements) in any subsequent criminal trial…. This protection is, in fact, coextensive with the use and derivative use immunity mandated by Kastigar when the government compels testimony from a reluctant witness. Accordingly, the fact that Martinez did not know his statements could not be used against him does not change our view that no violation of the Fifth Amendment’s Self-Incrimination Clause occurred here.132 There are so many logical, empirical, precedential and historical errors contained in this one paragraph, that it is difficult to know where to begin. First, it begs the question of why immunity is required—if it still is—in the context of judicial compulsion. If a judge were to simply compel a witness to answer incriminating questions, without mentioning immunity, exclusion of that testimony and its fruits would be just as “automatic,” under the Thomas interpretation of the privilege. Why then, is a formal grant of immunity required to engage in the redundant act of assuring subsequent exclusions when such exclusions are constitutionally “automatic” anyway? Or to ask the questions somewhat differently, why is a formal grant of immunity not required before the police may compel a suspect to make a self-incriminating statement? Why does a suspect in police custody not have the same conditional right to remain silent as a witness in a legal proceeding? And why does such a conditional privilege not require a formal grant of immunity to overcome it? To test Justice Thomas’ analogy between formal immunity and police coercion, consider what the situation would be like if the Justice Thomas must have meant to say “Any less ‘self-incriminating’,” rather than “any less compelled.” Surely immunity doesn’t eliminate the compulsion element; it is, however, supposed to eliminate the self-incrimination element. 132 538 U.S. 760, at 769-70 (citations omitted). 131 D:\533582156.doc Created on 10/9/2006 11:33:00 AM Last printed 3/9/2016 2:16:00 AM Page 51 of 158 Words 47,586 legislature were to enact a statute (or a judge issue an order) explicitly authorizing the sort of compulsion employed against Martinez – according to Justice Stevens “the functional equivalent [of] torture methods” – but providing the sole remedy of exclusion. This would be something like the “ticking bomb torture warrant” proposal I made several years ago that generated much controversy and general disapproval.133 No legislature has seriously considered “legitimating” torture by enacting a “torture warrant” or “torture immunity” procedure. The reason why legislators are willing to authorize grants of immunity in the context of judicial and other formal proceedings, is because they are prepared to say that it is right for a government official to compel answers to otherwise incriminatory questions under a judicial threat of contempt if everyone knows that these answers cannot be used against the person in a criminal case, and are thus no longer incriminatory. The same legislators would be far more reluctant to say that it is right to torture a person into confessing any crime (even a trivial crime) simply because the confession would be excluded from a subsequent criminal trial. Immunity may well eliminate the gravamen (or at least a gravamen) of the selfincrimination violation in the context of an orderly judicial or other formal proceeding, but it would not eliminate it in the context of torture or other forms of extreme coercion. The visual image of a violation of the privilege for most Americans remains the police beating or torturing a confession out of a person in their custody – the old “third degree.” And, as we shall see, the founding generation understood the privilege as being directly related to concerns about the introduction of “judicial torture.”134 Moreover, it would seem to follow from the Thomas analogy that once a person was given immunity, he could be compelled by any means to provide incriminating evidence. Yet the only means available by law is the threat of contempt, fine, and imprisonment. If these means fail—as they did, for example, in the well-known case of Susan McDougal—could the state then resort to physical compulsion, See Alan M. Dershowitz, “Is It Necessary to Apply ‘Physical Pressure’ to Terrorists — And to Lie About It?,” 23 Israel Law Review 193 (1989); Alan M. Dershowitz, Why Terrorism Works (New Haven: Yale University Press, 2002), chap. 4; and Alan M. Dershowitz, “Is There a Torturous Road to Justice?” Los Angeles Times, November 8, 2001, part 2, p. 19. [ALAN: DO YOU WANT TO LIST ARTICLES CRITICIZING YOUR PROPOSAL?] 134 Eben Moglen, “The Privilege and Common Law Criminal Procedure: The Sixteenth to the Eighteenth Centuries,” in R.H. Helmholz, et al., The Privilege Against Self-Incrimination: Its Origins and Developments (Chicago: The University of Chicago Press, 1997), pp. 135, 136. 133 D:\533582156.doc Created on 10/9/2006 11:33:00 AM Last printed 3/9/2016 2:16:00 AM Page 52 of 158 Words 47,586 even torture? Could it compel the reluctant witness to be injected with truth serum? Could it threaten to kill him? If Justice Thomas’s analysis of the privilege is taken to its logical conclusion, the answer would be yes—at least under the privilege.135 Yet no one would seriously consider authorizing torture, truth serum, or death threats following a grant of immunity and the failure of imprisonment to compel the testimony in routine cases. Going back to Justice Thomas’ narrow reading of the text of the privilege, it would seem to support the conclusion that immunity is not constitutionally required before a witness can be compelled to answer self-incriminating questions. The text limits the privilege to “any criminal case.” In a civil case or a legislative hearing, there is no textual prohibition against compelling testimony. And since compelled or coerced testimony will - - according to Thomas - - be “automatically" excluded from “any criminal case” in which the witness is a defendant, it would follow that a formal grant of immunity is no longer required as a prerequisite for imprisoning a witness who refuses to provide answers to self-incriminating questions. Justice Thomas’s analogy between the kind of coercive interrogation employed in the Martinez case and a legislative grant of immunity is deeply flawed, despite Justice Thomas’s confident assertion that there is no difference between compelling “an immunized witness” to “testify on pain of contempt,” and torturing a suspect into making self-incriminating statements, giving him “an automatic protection from [their use] in any subsequent criminal trial.” There must be a constitutionally significant difference between the lawful act of a legislature in explicitly authorizing immunity, and the unlawful and unauthorized crime of a rogue policeman beating up a citizen, even if that unlawful act may have a consequence similar to that resulting from the lawful grant of immunity. Justice Thomas is also wrong in confidently asserting that the protection in the case of a police beating is “automatic.” Any experienced criminal lawyer knows that exclusion is anything but “automatic” in such cases. The fact that immunity has been given to a witness cannot be disputed by the prosecution. It is part of a court record. It shifts a heavy burden of proof to the prosecution to show an 135 If contempt is deemed criminal, then the prohibition of cruel and unusual punishment might come into play (in addition to due process), but civil contempt might not be categorized as punitive. These distinctions, though highly questionable, are part of the “labeling game” the Supreme Court often plays. D:\533582156.doc Created on 10/9/2006 11:33:00 AM Last printed 3/9/2016 2:16:00 AM Page 53 of 158 Words 47,586 independent source for all of its evidence. [CITE NORTH CASE. Alex has filled this in in Memo 15 and is waiting for Alan to approve it.] A claim of police coercion, on the other hand, faces difficult, sometimes insurmountable obstacles. Coercion is a matter of degree. Immunity, on the other hand, has either been bestowed or it hasn’t. You can’t be a “little bit immunized.” But you can be a little coerced, and in close cases no one can know for certain where the Courts will find excludable coercion or not.136 The alleged coercion will often occur in a setting where the only witnesses, other than the defendant, are police officers who have a motive to minimize or deny the use of coercive methods. Having the defendant testify at a coercion hearing is often risky.137 Judges often err on the side of believing the police, especially when it is the defendant who has the burden of proving coercion in most cases. As the late Chief Justice Warren Burger wrote (when he was on the Court of Appeals): “[I]t would be a dismal reflection on society to say that when the guardians of its security are called to testify in court under oath, their testimony must be viewed with suspicion.”138 An experienced trial judge, Irving Younger, disagreed: “With all possible deference, I disagree. When there are grounds for believing that ‘the guardians of its security’ sometimes give deliberately false testimony, it is no ‘dismal reflection on society’ for Judges to acknowledge what all can see.”139 Judge Younger ended up accepting the policemen’s testimony in the case before him despite grave concerns about the pervasiveness of what many New York police officers call “testilying.” 136 On several occasions, the U.S. Supreme Court has ruled that cases of coercion did not rise to the level of being unconstitutional. For example, the court has ruled that requiring an inmate to participate in a treatment program that includes admitting criminal conduct — and having privileges revoked if he does not participate — is not unconstitutional coercion. McKune v. Lile, 536 U.S. 24 (2002). In another case, a police officer brandished a blackjack before an arrestee, and a park foreman later slapped the suspect and knocked off his glasses. Soon thereafter, the police questioned him and he confessed to murder. The U.S. Supreme Court ruled that no unconstitutional coercion occurred. Stroble v. California, 343 U.S. 181 (1952). In a third case, police disallowed a detained suspect to call an attorney while he was being interrogated. It was not until 5:00 a.m., after he had signed a confession, that he was permitted to sleep. The Supreme Court again ruled this conduct constitutional. Crooker v. California, 357 U.S. 433 (1958). [ALAN: YOU HAD ASKED FOR EXAMPLES IN ADDITION TO THE FIRST ONE. DO THESE LATTER TWO SUFFICE?] 137 FN explaining rules for exclusionary hearings. [ALAN: WHAT IS THE GIST OF WHAT YOU WANT HERE?] 138 Bush v. United States, 375 F.2d 602 (1967), at 604. 139 People v. McMurty, 64 Misc. 2d 63 (1970). D:\533582156.doc Created on 10/9/2006 11:33:00 AM Last printed 3/9/2016 2:16:00 AM Page 54 of 158 Words 47,586 Even when the police interrogation is recorded - - which it rarely is in instances of real coercion and physical abuse - - there will be difficult issues of line-drawing and interpretation. Consider the Martinez case itself. Although all the justices agreed that the statements elicited from Martinez would have been inadmissible against him had he been tried for a crime, there was considerable disagreement about the nature and degree of the abuse that was tape recorded. Justice Stevens agreed with the lower courts’ characterization [FILL IN – WHAT DO YOU WANT FILLED IN?]. Justice Thomas, on the other hand, tended to minimize the abuse [FILL IN]. In Dickerson v. United States, Scalia opined, (Thomas joined) argued that since Miranda we have explicitly, and repeatedly, interpreted that decision as having announced, not the circumstances in which custodial interrogation runs afoul of the Fifth or Fourteenth Amendment, but rather only “prophylactic” rules that go beyond the right against compelled self-incrimination. Of course the seeds of this “‘prophylactic’ interpretation of Miranda were present in the decision itself.”140 Justice Thomas, on the other hand, tended to minimize the abuse [FILL IN]. Indeed, it is possible that Justice Thomas would have found only a violation of Miranda’s “prophylactic rule” and not necessarily an involuntary confession [CHECK]. If a defendant cannot prove that his confession was “involuntary,” but can establish that no Miranda warnings were given, the defendant certainly does not get the functional equivalent of derivative use immunity. Even though the Court has ruled that Miranda is a constitutional doctrine, it has also ruled that statements obtained in violation of Miranda can be used to impeach a defendant if he takes the stand, and their fruits can be used against him even if he does not take the stand. Justice Thomas deceptively cites Oregon v. Elstad141 to support his assertion that “our cases provide that those subjected to coercive police interrogations have an automatic protection from the use of their involuntary statements (or evidence derived from their statements) in any subsequent criminal trial.”142 But he omits the reality that the case stands for a very different proposition; the fruits of statements obtained merely in violation of 140 Dickerson v. United States, 530 U.S. 428 (2000), at 450 (Scalia, J. dissenting). Oregon v. Elstad, 470 U.S. 298 (1985). 142 Chavez v. Martinez, 538 U.S. 760 (2003), at 769 (emphasis original); citing Oregon v. Elstad, 470 U.S. 298 (1985), at 307-308. 141 D:\533582156.doc Created on 10/9/2006 11:33:00 AM Last printed 3/9/2016 2:16:00 AM Page 55 of 158 Words 47,586 Miranda—which “creates a presumption of compulsion”143—may be admitted against a defendant. The majority in Kastigar recognized the difference between a grant of immunity and a coerced confession: [A] defendant against whom incriminating evidence has been obtained through a grant of immunity may be in a stronger position at trial than a defendant who asserts a Fifth Amendment coerced-confession claim. One raising a claim under this statute need only show that he testified under a grant of immunity in order to shift to the government the heavy burden of proving that all of the evidence it proposes to use was derived from legitimate independent sources. On the other hand, a defendant raising a coerced-confession claim under the Fifth Amendment must first prevail in a voluntariness hearing before his confession and evidence derived from it become inadmissible.144 The trial dynamics are very different, as any experienced criminal lawyer would know. Yet Justice Thomas rejects this reality and accepts instead the highly questionable conclusion—previously rejected by the Court—that a defendant who has been coerced into making self-incriminating statements is in at least as favorable a position as a defendant who has been compelled into making such statements by a formal grant of immunity. Moreover, Justice Thomas overrules this critical aspect of Kastigar without even mentioning it. Indeed, he cites Kastigar in support of his conclusion that there is no difference between a formal grant of immunity and the supposedly automatic immunity that follows from police coercion, see pages 76970, when Kastigar explicitly says the opposite. Even if the exclusion of coerced testimony were automatic— which it is not—it does not follow, under the governing case law, that a prediction of future judicial exclusion is the constitutional equivalent of legislatively authorized formal immunity. The Supreme Court addressed this precise issue in Pillsbury Co. v. Conboy145 and ruled that a witness retained his right to remain silent even though it was virtually certain that his answers—derived directly from testimony he had given under a prior grant of immunity—would be 143 Oregon v. Elstad, 470 U.S. 298 (1985), at 307. Kastigar v. United States, 406 U.S. 441, at 461-62 (notes omitted). 145 459 U.S. 248 (1983). 144 D:\533582156.doc Created on 10/9/2006 11:33:00 AM Last printed 3/9/2016 2:16:00 AM Page 56 of 158 Words 47,586 excluded from his criminal trial as the derivative fruits of his earlier immunity: Unless the grant of immunity assures a witness that his incriminating testimony will not be used against him in a subsequent criminal prosecution, the witness has not received the certain protection of his Fifth Amendment privilege that he has been forced to exchange. No court has authority to immunize a witness. That responsibility, as we have noted, is peculiarly an executive one, and only the Attorney General or a designated officer of the Department of Justice has authority to grant use immunity. Nor should a court, at the time of the civil testimony, predetermine the decision of the court in a subsequent criminal prosecution on the question whether the Government has met its burden of proving that “the evidence it proposes to use is derived from a legitimate source wholly independent of the compelled testimony.” Yet in holding Conboy in contempt for his Fifth Amendment silence, the District Court below essentially predicted that a court in any future criminal prosecution of Conboy will be obligated to protect against evidentiary use of the deposition testimony petitioners seek. We do not think such a predictive judgment is enough…. As the Court stated in Maness v. Meyers, compelling a witness to testify in “reliance upon a later objection or motion to suppress would ‘let the cat out’ with no assurance whatever of putting it back.” We believe Conboy acted properly in maintaining his silence in the face of the District Court's compulsion order and by testing the validity of his privilege on appeal.146 The court reiterated its Pillsbury holding in the 1998 case of United States v. Balsys: Of course, the judicial exclusion of compelled testimony functions as a fail-safe to ensure that compelled testimony is not admitted in a criminal proceeding. The general rule requires a grant of immunity prior to the compelling of any testimony. We have said that the prediction that a court in a future criminal prosecution would be obligated to protect against the evidentiary use of compelled 146 Pillsbury Co. v. Conboy, 459 U.S. 248 (1983), at 261-62 (citations omitted). D:\533582156.doc Created on 10/9/2006 11:33:00 AM Last printed 3/9/2016 2:16:00 AM Page 57 of 158 Words 47,586 testimony is not enough to satisfy the privilege against compelled self-incrimination. Pillsbury Co. v. Conboy, 459 U.S. 248, 261…. The suggestion that a witness should rely on a subsequent motion to suppress rather than a prior grant of immunity “would [not] afford adequate protection. Without something more, [the witness] would be compelled to surrender the very protection which the privilege is designed to guarantee.” This general rule ensures that we do not “let the cat out with no assurance whatever of putting it back,” and leaves the decision whether to grant immunity to the Executive in accord with congressional policy, see Pillsbury, supra, at 262.147 Yet Justice Thomas in Martinez ignores Pillsbury, citing only a concurring opinion in that case, while overruling it sub silentio.148 The analogy between legislatively authorized formal immunity and “automatic” exclusion that supposedly follows from unlawful police coercion is not only incomplete, it is fundamentally flawed. At best, the precedent of immunity cuts both ways in the context of the Martinez decision.149 The immunity case law — 147 United States v. Balsys, 524 U.S. 666 (1998), at 683, n. 8 (some citations omitted). 148 CITE 149 The dissent by Justice Thurgood Marshall in Kastigar also rejects the analogy between immunity and coerced confessions: In my view the Court turns reason on its head when it compares a statutory grant of immunity to the “immunity” that is inadvertently conferred by an unconstitutional interrogation. The exclusionary rule of evidence that applies in that situation has nothing whatever to do with this case. Evidence obtained through a coercive interrogation, like evidence obtained through an illegal search, is excluded at trial because the Constitution prohibits such methods of gathering evidence. The exclusionary rules provide a partial and inadequate remedy to some victims of illegal police conduct, and a similarly partial and inadequate deterrent to police officers. An immunity statute, on the other hand, is much more ambitious than any exclusionary rule. It does not merely attempt to provide a remedy for past police misconduct, which never should have occurred. An immunity statute operates in advance of the event, and it authorizes — even encourages — interrogation that would otherwise be prohibited by the Fifth Amendment. An immunity statute thus differs from an exclusionary rule of evidence in at least two critical respects. First, because an immunity statute gives constitutional approval to the resulting interrogation, the government is under an obligation here to remove the danger of incrimination completely and absolutely, whereas D:\533582156.doc Created on 10/9/2006 11:33:00 AM Last printed 3/9/2016 2:16:00 AM Page 58 of 158 Words 47,586 especially Kastigar, Pillsbury, and Balsys — cuts strongly against it. It is certainly not the argument stopper or slam-dunk Thomas makes it appear. Justice Thomas’s misuse of the immunity precedent as a dispositive analogy justifying his conclusion in Martinez illustrates the limitations of analogy as a tool of constitutional interpretation. [EXPAND AND GENERALIZE] [Explain how one Court used negative analogy to support Kastigar and then another CT used positive analogy to undercut it. Pre-trial juvenile detention to adult detention - - other analogies] [HASN’T SCALIA ARGUED AGAINST ANALOGIES? I THINK SO IN HIS BOOK A MATTER OF INTERPRETATION: PLEASE CHECK, OR I’LL CHECK - - I HAVE THE BOOK] As with his textual argument, the immunity argument either goes too far or doesn’t go far enough. Taken to its logical conclusion, in the case of the exclusionary rules it may be sufficient to shield the witness from the fruits of the illegal search or interrogation in a partial and reasonably adequate manner. For when illegal police conduct has occurred, the exclusion of evidence does not purport to purge the conduct of its unconstitutional character. The constitutional violation remains, and may provide the basis for other relief, such as a civil action for damages, or a criminal prosecution of the responsible officers. The Constitution does not authorize police officers to coerce confessions or to invade privacy without cause, so long as no use is made of the evidence they obtain. But this Court has held that the Constitution does authorize the government to compel a witness to give potentially incriminating testimony, so long as no incriminating use is made of the resulting evidence. Before the government puts its seal of approval on such an interrogation, it must provide an absolutely reliable guarantee that it will not use the testimony in any way at all in aid of prosecution of the witness. The only way to provide that guarantee is to give the witness immunity from prosecution for crimes to which his testimony relates. Second, because an immunity statute operates in advance of the interrogation, there is room to require a broad grant of transactional immunity without imperiling large numbers of otherwise valid convictions. An exclusionary rule comes into play after the interrogation or search has occurred; and the decision to question or to search is often made in haste, under pressure, by an officer who is not a lawyer. If an unconstitutional interrogation or search were held to create transactional immunity, that might well be regarded as an excessively high price to pay for the “constable’s blunder.” An immunity statute, on the other hand, creates a framework in which the prosecuting attorney can make a calm and reasoned decision whether to compel testimony and suffer the resulting ban on prosecution, or to forgo the testimony. Kastigar v. United States, 406 U.S. 441, at 470-71 (citations omitted) (Marshall dissenting). D:\533582156.doc Created on 10/9/2006 11:33:00 AM Last printed 3/9/2016 2:16:00 AM Page 59 of 158 Words 47,586 its reasoning overrules more than 100 years of firm precedent requiring an explicit grant of coterminous immunity before a witness can be compelled to answer self-incriminating questions. That goes too far. If its reasoning does not overrule the immunity cases, then it is difficult to understand why the police should be empowered to coerce a suspect into making self-incriminating statements without some prior formal approval akin to immunity. Moreover if exclusion is not the sole remedy for a violation of the witness’ right to remain silent in the absence of immunity, why should it be the sole remedy for a violation of the suspect’s right not to be coerced into surrendering his right to remain silent? The majority opinions do not satisfactorily address these issues in their rush to deny coerced individuals the right to sue for a violation of their constitutional right. D:\533582156.doc Created on 10/9/2006 11:33:00 AM Last printed 3/9/2016 2:16:00 AM Page 60 of 158 Words 47,586 Chapter 3: The Limits of Historical Inquiry Many of the foundational cases interpreting the meaning and scope of the 15 “concise” and generic words of the 5th Amendment’s that constitute the privilege against self-incrimination purport to rely on history, since as Justice Felix Frankfurter correctly observed: “The privilege against self-incrimination is a specific provision of which it is peculiarly true that ‘a page of history is worth a volume of logic.’”150 History cannot however, always be found on “pages”- - or even websites. It is often more complex, multifaceted and inaccessible than judicial opinions or legal briefs make it appear. Advocates’ history, or as one prominent scholar has called it “law office history,” often consists of the artful selection of “historical facts from one side only, ignoring contrary data, in order to support, rationalize, or give the appearance of respectability to judgments resting on other grounds.”151 Another misuse of history is citing it when it supports the desired conclusion but completely ignoring it when it undercuts it. The majority opinion in the Martinez case never mentions history. Nor does it seek to unearth the Amendment’s original understanding, though its author and his colleagues who joined his opinion are often the first to cite history when it supports their views. This selective resort to history raises important questions regarding the appropriate uses of history in constitutional interpretation that I shall address in the coming pages. Any honest attempt to reconstruct the relevant history underlying the privilege against self-incrimination will necessarily be incomplete, selective, impressionistic and probabilistic. This will be especially so when the sources consulted are primarily judicial and secondary. The object of such an inquiry can rarely be the discovery of a singular truth or even pattern. Historians seek coherent stories, but history itself generally unfolds in a more disorderly and even random way. The privilege against self-incrimination and its several components and variations, developed over a period of time when recordkeeping was spotty, when practice often differed from theory, when necessity sometimes trumped articulated norms and when law enforcement was relatively primitive. The early history of what came to be the modern right against self-incrimination also developed against the background of European 150 151 Justice Felix Frankfurter in Ullman v. U.S., 350 U.S. 422, at 438 (1956). Levy, Political Science Quarterly, at p. 1 D:\533582156.doc Created on 10/9/2006 11:33:00 AM Last printed 3/9/2016 2:16:00 AM Page 61 of 158 Words 47,586 political, religious and ideological conflicts, some of which were less familiar to the new world. As Leonard Levy summarized the context: “The American origins derive from the inherited English common-law system of criminal justice. But the English origins, so much more complex, spilled over legal boundaries and reflected the many-sided religious, political, and constitutional issues that racked England during the sixteenth and seventeenth centuries: the struggles for supremacy between Catholicism and Protestantism, between Anglicanism and Puritanism, Between King and Parliament, between arbitrary rule and limited or constitutional government, between the suppression of heresy and sedition and freedom of conscience and press.”152 As Justice Robert Jackson described the quest to recapture history in the context of discerning the understanding of the framers: “Just what our forefathers did envision, or would have envisioned had they foreseen modern conditions, must be divined from materials almost as enigmatic as the dreams Joseph was called upon to interpret for Pharaoh.”153 The object of any historical inquiry must therefore be modest: to convey a sense of how the relevant issues were understood, considered, addressed, and rationalized during the period of time in which the privilege developed and the constitutional provision drafted and ratified. It is far easier to identify factors that could not have been, or in fact were not, part of the calculus in balancing the need for information and evidence, against the rights of defendants and witnesses. Identifying historical errors – especially the common error of judging history through the prism of modernity – is not a difficult task. Reconstructing the prisms through which the framers and their contemporaries actually viewed the problems associated with the privilege is a for more daunting task The historical questions can be posed in several ways, and the way the question is posed may affect the outcome of the inquiry. For example, the question can be put quite specifically in an effort to 152 Levy, p. 42 Youngstown Sheet & Tube Co. v. Sawyer, 343 U.S. 579 (1952), at 634 (Jackson concurring). 153 D:\533582156.doc Created on 10/9/2006 11:33:00 AM Last printed 3/9/2016 2:16:00 AM Page 62 of 158 Words 47,586 respond to the precise question that as before the court in Martinez: at the time of the framing was there an independent or primary right, under the privilege against self-incrimination, not be compelled (tortured) or coerced by government officials into providing information that was self-incriminating? Or was the only right a dependent and secondary one that merely prohibited the government from using any such compelled or coerced information against the witness at this criminal trial (if there was a trial)? That specific question may be difficult to answer, since no one in the framing generation may actually have posed or considered the question in this dichotomous fashion. Indeed, I have come across no explicit recognition of the dichotomy that was central to the issue posed in Martinez until it was raised by Justice Arthur Goldberg in a footnote to his 1964 opinion in Murphy v. Waterfront Commission and left unresolved. Several legal historians with whom I conferred acknowledged as well that they had seen no explicit reference to this dichotomy before or at the time of the ratification of the Fifth Amendment. There are, however, several testing sub-questions that may help answer the primary question: • Could a person who was being subjected to coercion bring an injunctive legal action to prevent or stop the coercion – or was his only remedy exclusion at a subsequent criminal trial? • Could such a person bring a lawsuit for damages resulting from coercive or compelled interrogation – even if the fruits of such interrogations where never used against him at a criminal trial? • Were judges or other officials ever disciplined or punished for improperly compelling witnesses to testify? • Was the remedy of exclusion mandated for all violations of the privilege (or privileges), or only for some? If only for some, what remedies, if any, were available for the others? • Did the law explicitly authorize the use of coercion or compulsion under any circumstances? If so, which? • Were certain methods of interrogation or information gathering absolutely prohibited, regardless of the use to which it would eventually be put? If so, how was the prohibition enforced? • Was there any explicit discussions, in the scholarly or judicial literature, of the difference between the application of compulsion (or coercion) and the evidentiary use of the resulting information or evidence? • Were there any explicit references at common law to the gathering of preventive intelligence information, as contrasted with information to be used to incriminate the suspect at his own trial? D:\533582156.doc Created on 10/9/2006 11:33:00 AM Last printed 3/9/2016 2:16:00 AM Page 63 of 158 Words 47,586 • Was there any articulation of a right to remain silent at common-law, and if so, were witnesses ever warned or advised of this right? • Were there any analogies to immunity at the relevant times? If so, was compulsion authorized in cases in which a witness had the functional equivalent of today’s immunity? Was any kind of compulsion - - such as torture - - forbidden even in such cases? • In situations where it was unclear whether a witness would eventually become a criminal defendant, was he accorded a privilege not to respond to potentially incriminating questions? • If a witness in a state proceeding claimed fear of being prosecuted by a sister state or by the federal government, could he refuse to answer incriminating questions? • Were the relevant words of the Fifth Amendment understood by the framers to prohibit certain methods of interrogation? Or were they intended only to provide a remedy of exclusion if these methods were employed? If the former, was there any understanding about the remedy or remedies available to enforce such a prohibition? • How was the word “person,” in the Fifth Amendment - - as distinguished from the word “accused,” in the Sixth Amendment - understood? • How was the word “compelled” understood? Was it limited to judicial compulsion, or did it include extra-judicial coercion? • How were the words “any criminal case” understood? Were they limited to criminal trials, or did they include the Grand Jury and/or investigative phases of a case? • How were the words “witness against himself” understood? Were they limited to sworn witnesses at the trial itself, of did they include the introduction hearsay testimony by other witnesses about statements made before trial by the defendant? [ADD SUB QUESTIONS] Sub-questions of this kind designed to help reconstruct the framing generation’s understanding (or understandings) of the privilege (and its variants) fall into several categories. The first asks what the contemporaneous institutions—especially the courts— actually did, rather than said. If there were remedies—in addition to or instead of exclusion—for alleged violations of a right to remain silent or a right not to be coerced or compelled into making selfincriminating statements, that would be fairly compelling evidence of an independent, primary right. If there were no such remedies, that fact alone would not conclusively negate the existence of such a right because there were many rights in those days without well-developed D:\533582156.doc Created on 10/9/2006 11:33:00 AM Last printed 3/9/2016 2:16:00 AM Page 64 of 158 Words 47,586 remedies. It was thought by some that rights were self-enforcing, since they were deemed binding on all public officials, not just the courts.154 But the absence of any remedy would surely weaken the claim that there was an independent right. The question of whether a right was recognized and if so how it was understood by the framing generation is a daunting one. The framers clearly intended, or said they intended, to codify and constitutionalize certain existing common law rights and privileges as they understood them. Not all the framers were lawyers and certainly not all the ratifiers were lawyers. Some had a technical, legal understanding of existing rights, while others had a broader, more philosophical or political understanding of such rights. To suggest an analogy to the current situation, if a legislative body were today to seek to codify “the right to remain silent” or “the presumption of innocence” or the prohibition against “cruel and unusual punishments,” there would be different contemporaneous understandings of these rights. Knowledgeable lawyers, aware of the recent case law, would understand them narrowly, as trial or postconviction rights. Ordinary citizens, including many legislators, would probably understand them more broadly, as fundamental protections against governmental overreaching that transcend the criminal trial process. In every era, there will be differences between what is preached and what is practiced. For example, Jeremy Waldron, in arguing recently that it is “dispiriting as well as shameful to have to turn our attention to [the] issue of torture” in the post-9/11 world, quotes an article in the 1911 edition of the Encyclopedia Britannica that asserts that the “whole subject [of torture] is now of only historical interest as far as Europe is concerned.”155 That absurd position could only be maintained if one looked exclusively at what Europeans were saying about torture, and not at what they were doing. Torture by Europeans was being extensively practiced by the French in North Africa, by the British in India, and by the Belgians in the Congo. [Alan: You wanted me to fill in more examples of Europeans using torture. Do these latter two suffice?] It continued to be used during the First and Second World Wars. It is probably fair to characterize the twentieth century as the “torture 154 There is some evidence that the witness privilege was thought to be selfenforcing by judges and did not require as exclusionary rule. See Henry Smith. 155 Qtd. in Jeremy Waldron, “Torture and Positive Law: Jurisprudence for the White House,” 105 Columbia Law Review 1681 (2005), at 1683-1684. D:\533582156.doc Created on 10/9/2006 11:33:00 AM Last printed 3/9/2016 2:16:00 AM Page 65 of 158 Words 47,586 century” and Europe as its “capital.” But one would not recognize this reality by reading proclamations, statutes, judicial decisions, encyclopedias, or law review articles. Perhaps if we talked about torture more, we would practice it less. De Rochefaucault understood the disparity between parchment preaching and down-and-dirty reality nearly a third of a millennia ago when he quipped, “Hypocrisy is the homage which vice renders to virtue.” The way of the hypocrite - - proclaiming virtue while quietly tolerating vice - - has never proved an effective tactic for bringing practice closer to principle. R.H. Helmholz is far more perceptive than Jeremy Waldron when he observes that “[l]egal history is filled with instances where in hindsight practice in the courts does not seem to measure up to the ideals professed by thoughtful men and women of the time.”156 And if one adds to “practice in the courts,” practice in the streets, back alleys, detention centers, lockups, and military theaters, the disparity becomes even greater. It is for this reason, among others, that posing focused questions about what the courts were doing in fact – a variant on Holmes’ famous definition of law as “the prophecies of what the courts will do in fact” – is an important window into the contemporaneous understanding of the right that was constitutionalized by the 15 words of the 5th Amendment dealing with self-incrimination. If the historical answers to those and other relevant subquestions were to point uniformly and definitively in one direction (as, for example, the history of trial by jury in criminal cases points uniformly to twelve men, unanimous juries), and if there is a high level of confidence in the accuracy of the material, as well as in the absence of other material that might point in a somewhat different direction, then it might be possible to conclude that history answers the specific historical question posed in this case: did the framing generation understand there to be a right not to be coerced, or only a right to exclude the fruits of compulsion? But if the answers to the sub-questions point in differing directions, or if there is no compelling R.H. Helmholz, “The Privilege and Common Law Criminal Procedure: The Sixteenth to the Eighteenth Centuries,” in R.H. Helmholz, et al., The Privilege Against Self-Incrimination: Its Origins and Developments (Chicago: The University of Chicago Press, 1997), p. 12. 156 D:\533582156.doc Created on 10/9/2006 11:33:00 AM Last printed 3/9/2016 2:16:00 AM Page 66 of 158 Words 47,586 evidence that those in the framing generation ever posed the question in this dichotomous manner, or if there is evidence that the framers (or some of them) understood the right as broader than how the courts applied it, then the historical material may be inferentially relevant but not definitive. That state of affairs – which is probably more usual than not – is rife with potential for abusing history, by picking and choosing only these elements that suggest a particular outcome, while ignoring elements that may undercut it. Judicially opinions are filled with examples of such selective misuses of historical material. The “ransacking” of history – as one expert has put it – is a game played by ideologues of every stripe. As Maitland quipped more than a century ago, the “seamless web” of history is torn by telling only a piece of it.157 The web is torn even more when the piece to be told is selectively picked by an ideologue with a contemporary agenda. Another common method of misusing history is to cite it only when it supports one’s ideology and to ignore it when it undercuts one’s ideology. This ideologically selective recourse to history has characterized the opinions of many justices over time, including the author of the Martinez case and his colleagues who joined his opinion.158 This is part of a larger problem of judicial interpretation: every method of interpretation is selectively invoked or ignored as it serves the interests of ideological result orientation.159 In this analysis of the scope of the privilege I rely on the primary research of others who are more expert than I am at accessing, translating, and contextualizing the original sources. My own expertise lies in my extensive experience as a practicing criminal lawyer over many decades and my ability to see practical connections that may be more difficult for the academic historian to find in the existing historical record, which is necessarily incomplete, especially as to the dynamics of typical, as distinguished from high-profile, cases. It may also lie in my experientially induced skepticism about believing that the preserved written records always mirrored the practices they were purporting to record and report. 157 Quoted in Levy at p. 42 [CITE EXAMPLES] 159 [CITE EXAMPLES] 158 D:\533582156.doc Created on 10/9/2006 11:33:00 AM Last printed 3/9/2016 2:16:00 AM Page 67 of 158 Words 47,586 The Earliest History of the Right Against Self-Incrimination Elements of what eventually became the right or privileges against self-incrimination appear in early religious jurisprudence even before the emergence of the Anglo-American system of criminal justice. In the trial of John Lilburn – to which, according to Dean Erwin Griswold, “we owe the privilege of today”160: -- reliance was placed on the laws of God and the rules prevailing in ancient Israel. In the original report of Lilburn’s Trial, it will be remarked that one of the strongest arguments Lilburn used to justify his refusal to answer to incriminating questions or to take an oath to answer truly, was that “such practice would be contrary to the laws of God, for that law requires no man to accuse himself.” Lilburn seems to indicate that such was the practice of the courts in Palestine, “for Christ himself in all his examinations before the high priest would not accuse himself but upon their demands returned back, Why ask you me? Go to them that heard me.” The numerous references in Lilburn’s Case suggest the possibility that “many of our common law principles and many of the legal forms and customs which we find difficult to explain, trace their origin more or less directly to sources in the Written and Oral Law of the Jewish people,” and, specifically, that “there is a striking coincidence in the legal thinking in evidence in both systems.”161 In the Miranda decision, Chief Justice Earl Warren, in asserting that the “roots” of the privilege “go back into ancient times,” specifically cited Jewish law, as enunciated by Maimonides: “The principle that no man is to be declared guilty on his own admission is a divine decree.”162 The traditional Jewish approach to self-incrimination is, however, significantly different than the Anglo-American approach. E. Griswold, “Fifth Amendment,” 40 A.B.A.J. (1955) 502,533, 39 Mass. L.Q. (1054) 414, cited in Simcha Mandelbaum, “The Privilege Against SelfIncrimination in Anglo-American and Jewish Law,” 5 American Journal of Comparative Law 115 (winter 1956), at p.116. This conclusion has been challenged by [FILL IN] 161 Simcha Mandelbaum, “The Privilege Against Self-Incrimination in AngloAmerican and Jewish Law,” 5 American Journal of Comparative Law 115 (winter 1956), at p. 119 (notes omitted). 162 384 U.S. 458, n. 27. See also Norman Lamm, “The 5 th amendment and its equivalent in the Halakah,” 5 Judaism 53 (winter 1956) 160 D:\533582156.doc Created on 10/9/2006 11:33:00 AM Last printed 3/9/2016 2:16:00 AM Page 68 of 158 Words 47,586 Under Jewish law, confessions are absolutely prohibited, even if they are completely voluntary. The principle is “a man cannot represent himself as wicked” (“ein adam messim atsmo rasha.”) This principle grows out of the very different legal system established by the Bible – a system that demands two external witnesses and that disqualifies the defendant himself as well as his close relatives from testifying at all. “The issue, then, is not compulsion, but the whole idea of legal confession.”163 It is also possible that the Jewish prohibition against voluntary self-condemnation may reflect the religious prohibition against suicide. Maimonides, a twelfth century doctor and codifier, wrote of those who confess as perhaps being among “those who are in misery, bitter in soul,, who long for death, thrust their sword into their bellies or cast themselves down from roofs.”164 The rule against selfincrimination may have been designed, in part, to preclude the legal system from becoming a vehicle for judicial suicide. (At common law as well “to furnish testimonial evidence against himself with or without oath, was likened to drawing one’s blood, running oneself upon the pikes, or cutting one’s own throat with one's tongue.”165) Analogies to other legal systems, therefore, are relevant but imperfect. There are, however, some insights that can be gained by looking at common concerns. Several relevant cases are recounted in the Talmud: “[A] person was charged with setting fire to a neighbor’s property on Sabbath. Judgment was requested166 for money damages as well as penalties for the violation of the rules of the Sabbath.167 The defendant offered his own confession in evidence. It was decided that the testimony should be admitted only as it related to the civil suit and not for the purpose of criminal conviction.168 A similar solution was offered by the Jewish court in another case where a woman was seeking the court’s permission to remarry. She contended that her former husband, who had disappeared from home, was dead. To establish the husband’s death, she called a witness who testified that he himself killed the husband. The court granted the Norman Lamm, “The 5th amendment and its equivalent in the Halakah,” 5 Judaism 53 (winter 1956), p. 10 164 Quoted in Levy at p. 438 165 Levy at p. 330 166 Jewish law permitted civil and criminal actions to be brought together in one proceeding. 167 Setting a fire on the Shabbath was considered by the Torah as a criminal violation. Exodus 35 (3). 168 Maimonides, Mishneh Torah, Evidence, Ch. 12 (2) (1168) 163 D:\533582156.doc Created on 10/9/2006 11:33:00 AM Last printed 3/9/2016 2:16:00 AM Page 69 of 158 Words 47,586 requested permission to the woman. The court in its opinion stated that although the testimony was self-incriminatory in nature, the court could split the testimony and accept the part which established the death of the husband. The court added that such testimony could not be used to convict the witness for murder.169”170 These cases suggest an early, commonsense variation on what eventually became “immunity.” The witnesses were permitted to make self-incriminatory statements for use in civil cases, but the statements were excluded in the criminal cases. Even here, however, the analogy to the modern privilege is incomplete, because the witnesses in these cases were not compelled to make selfincriminating statements; they volunteered to do so. Under Jewish law the gravamen of the violation was not compulsion; it was disqualification in the context of criminal cases. Since the confession was not being used in the criminal case, there was no violation of the disqualification principle and the gravamen never occurred. It would beg the question to assume that in the context of the modern privilege, compulsion is not at last part of the gravamen of the violation.171 Many legal systems developed pragmatic ways to circumvent or limit constraints on prosecuting the factually guilty. In Jewish law, for example, not only are two witnesses required but advance warning must have been given to convict a murderer before he could be convicted. But if there was only one reliable witness and no advanced warning, the murderer would not simply be let free, perhaps to kill again. An informal mechanism of incapacitation was developed by the Rabbis to mitigate the rigors of the Biblical requirements.172 The same must have been true for the privilege. When societies desperately needed information – for example, when the King’s life was believed to be in danger – they got it, regardless of what the law permitted or forbade. Sometimes, the law provided explicitly for exceptional situations, as with the “torture warrant” in ___ century England or the 1641 statutory directive in Massachusetts to employ torture to elicit the names of “confederates” from convicted capital 169 T. Yebamot, 25b. Simcha Mandelbaum, “The Privilege Against Self-Incrimination in AngloAmerican and Jewish Law,” 5 American Journal of Comparative Law 115 (winter 1956), at p. 118-119 171 As we shall see, disqualification of the defendant as a sworn witness was also as an issue at the time of the framing, but the voluntary, unsworn self-incriminating statements of a defendant were admissible against him. 172 DESCRIBE, CITE MCNACHEM ELON 170 D:\533582156.doc Created on 10/9/2006 11:33:00 AM Last printed 3/9/2016 2:16:00 AM Page 70 of 158 Words 47,586 offenders, as long as the torture was not “barbarous and inhumane.” Blackstone justified the use of torture to elicit preventive intelligence as an act of “state,” rather than “law.”173 Mostly, the law was simply ignored or circumvented through various means. The way of the hypocrite—proclaiming virtue while practicing vice—has been a constant throughout history. As I have shown elsewhere, most legal systems have had both formal and informal tracks. With regard to Anglo-American justice: “[T]wo criminal justice systems have operated side-byside. The more formal system (the one we are most familiar with) has been characterized by high visibility, by progressive common law development through appellate decisions, by frequent legislative revision, and by bookshelves of treatises and other scholarly descriptions and discussions of its philosophy, substance, and procedure. Perhaps most important, it has been characterized by a well-developed jurisprudence imposing principled limits on its employment.”174 *** “There has always been, however, a parallel system that has played a significant role in the Anglo-American legal process. It was less formal and less visible. That is why we know so little about it today, though it was probably well known in its own day. It was characterized by the absence of published opinions and appellate review. It has always been less principled or at least less willing to articulate governing principles. Few Treatises or commentaries have been written about it. Most important, it has never developed an articulated jurisprudence that imposes principled limits on its employment. Its primary function has been to fill the gaps that inevitably occur in any formal system of criminal justice.”175 We shall see a similar dichotomy in the history of what became the modern privilege against self-incrimination. There were considerable differences between what lawyers, judges, and treatise writers said about the right to remain silent and how that right, if it 173 CITE Alan M. Dershowitz, Preemption: A Knife That Cuts Both Ways, (New York: Norton, 2006), pp. 40-41. 175 Id at pp. 41-42 174 D:\533582156.doc Created on 10/9/2006 11:33:00 AM Last printed 3/9/2016 2:16:00 AM Page 71 of 158 Words 47,586 was indeed a right, operated in practice. That dichotomy continues to this day. D:\533582156.doc Created on 10/9/2006 11:33:00 AM Last printed 3/9/2016 2:16:00 AM Page 72 of 158 Words 47,586 The Levy Hypothesis Professor Leonard W. Levy, whose book on the origins of the Fifth Amendment won the Pulitzer Prize in History, traces the American right against self-incrimination back to the struggle for religious and political freedom by English dissidents. In his view the right grew out of reaction to the wrongs associated with the prosecution of such dissidents, most particularly with the oath ex officio, which was an important tool of the inquisitorial system of justice (or injustice), It required dissidents to swear to tell the truth before they were charged with a crime, and it empowered their inquisitors to plumb the depths of their most secret thoughts. In other words, after they were compelled to take this open-ended oath, they could be asked, in effect, to confess all of their secret crimes, sins and disloyal or heretical thoughts, as if to a priest - - except that these “priests” could administer earthly punishments, including death. Levy dates the origin of the English privilege as far back as the thirteenth century when the oath ex officio, or inquisitorial oath was given as “A gift of Pope Gregory IX”176: “The new oath procedure was first used in 1246 when Bishop Robert Grosseteste conducted “strict Inquisitions” into the sexual misconduct and general immorality of the people in his diocese of Lincoln. To discover all who were guilty of any of the seven deadly sins, the noble and humble alike were put to the oath de veritate dicenda, “an innovation never used in the Realm before,” and were questioned about themselves and others “to the enormous defamation and scandal of many.”177 The oath ex officio continued to be used over the subsequent centuries not only by ecclesiastical courts, but by secular tribunals, such as the Star Chamber. It proved to be a powerful, if controversial, weapon against religious and political dissidents. One important shield against this weapon was principled silence, as manifested by an old maxim of the cannon law, nemo tenetur seipsum pordere. Levy, like Dean Erwin Griswold, points to “Freeborn” John Lilburne - - a seventeenth century Puritan “leveler” - - as “the most remarkable person connected with the history of the origins of the right against self-incrimination” and credits his “sensational trial” with being “the immediate reason for the abolition of the oath ex 176 177 Levy p. 46 Levy p. 47 D:\533582156.doc Created on 10/9/2006 11:33:00 AM Last printed 3/9/2016 2:16:00 AM Page 73 of 158 Words 47,586 officio.”178 Lilburne was the “catalytic agent in the history of the right against self-incrimination” and its hero. Among its other heroes was Lord Edward Coke and even King Henry III who “issued writs of prohibition against Bishop Grosseteste of Lincoln in 1246 and 1252 commanding that laymen not be examined under oath in ecclesiastical courts except in matrimonial and testamentary causes.”179 Although Levy himself does not believe that the right against self-incrimination can be traced back to Magna Carta, which granted rights only to nobles in relation to their king,180 he credits the spirit of The Great Charter with providing a stimulus for the invocation of the right as part of the guarantee that no man shall be condemned except by the law of the land. The Court of Star Chamber - - as the King’s council came to be called because it met in a room “whose ceiling was ornamented with stars”181 - - employed an oath similar to the one that was so central to the ecclesiastic courts. These oaths in essence, required those who came before these courts to incriminate himself by acknowledging his guilt under oath. The widespread opposition to this inquisitional process was, at least in part responsible for a fourteenth century reinterpretation of the thirteenth century words of the Magna Carta: “The very remarkable transformation of Magna Carta in the fourteenth century from a feudal aristocratic document to an embodiment of common-law liberties can be ascribed only partly to the opposition to the oath procedure of the Council and the ecclesiastical courts. Yet it is no exaggeration to conclude that the opposition to inquisitional procedures, of which the inquisitional oath was a part, had a great deal to do with the burgeoning idea that Magna Carta’s famous “law of the land” clause of the twenty-ninth chapter guaranteed to every subject and indictment by grand jury and trial by jury in a common-law court by common-law procedure. Two centuries later men would claim with as little historical justification ‘that by the Stature of Magna…this othe for a man to accuse himself was and is uterlie inhibited.’”182 178 Levy, p. 271 Levy, p. 217 180 And specifically denied them to Jews [cite] 181 Levy p. 49 182 Levy, p. 51 The broadening of the narrow words and original understanding of the Magna Carta [originally intended to enhance the feudal power of Lords] illustrates a process much closer to the “living Constitution” approach to Constitutional interpretation than to Justice Scalia’s narrow textualims based on the original understanding. The framers of the U.S. Constitution were certainly familiar with how the Magna Cara was consistently reinterpreted by subsequent generations: 179 D:\533582156.doc Created on 10/9/2006 11:33:00 AM Last printed 3/9/2016 2:16:00 AM Page 74 of 158 Words 47,586 Levy pointed to numerous dissidents who invoked the Magna Carta in support of their right against self-incrimination, “Because the cannon law was against them, suspects had to be creative and invented the claim that conscience and the Magna Carta authorized a right against self-incrimination…As for the Magna Carta, Robert Beale, clerk of the Privy Council and an aggressive champion of Puritan victims of the High commission, was the first, in 1589, to conscript the Magna [837] Carta into service against the oath ex officio and all inquisitorial proceedings by the High Commission. Beale invented a significant fiction which in time reached the stature of an article of constitutional faith that the Magna Carta outlawed forcing a person to be a witness against himself. James Morice, another Puritan lawyer, published a book in 1598 in which he argued at length that the nemo tenetur maxim derived from the Magna Cart. A third Puritan lawyer, Nicholas Fuller, who had served in the Commons with Beale and Morice, elaborately advocated the same thesis.”183 Lord Coke also invoked Magna Carta, associating freedom of conscience and thought - - and thus the right to refuse to answer questions about that would criminalize these freedoms - - with chapter 29 of The Great Charter.184 “Slowly a constitutional basis was being forged for the assault of a later era on the practice of forcing men to incriminate themselves.” (Levy p. 53) “In Tyndale’s principal book, The Obedience of a Christian Man (1528), there is a passage on tyrants breaking into the heart and consciences of men and compelling them to swear. In 1591 a group of imprisoned Puritan Ministers, protesting against the oath ex officio, cited this passage and extended it to read that no man should be compelled ‘to sweare to accuse him selfe.’ The same ministers, like others of their time, relied on similar statements from Tyndale’s book. Tyndale flatly asserted that a man should refuse an oath put to him by a judge to answer all that is demanded of him. He also protested the practice of ‘antichrist’s disciples’ in breaking into men’s consciences by compelling them to forswear themselves ‘or to testify against themselves.’ The latter phrase incidentally, has the same tone as the provisions in early American state bills of rights and in the Fifth Amendment, enjoining against forcing men to be witnesses against themselves or to give evidence against themselves. In another passage Tyndale explained that it was ‘a cruel thing to break up into a man’s heart, and to compel him to put either soul or body in jeopardy, or to shame himself.’ This is probably the earliest statement equating selfincrimination with self-infamy.” (Levy pp. 63-64) 183 Levy, Cardoza Law Review, p. 8 184 Levy, p. 246 D:\533582156.doc Created on 10/9/2006 11:33:00 AM Last printed 3/9/2016 2:16:00 AM Page 75 of 158 Words 47,586 The origins of the right against self-incrimination, according to Levy, cannot be fully comprehended without considering its religious and political background: “The claim to the right emerged in inquisitorial examinations, initially conducted by the Church, then by the State. It emerged also in the context of the great political struggle for constitutional limitations on arbitrary prerogative; during the late sixteenth century and early seventeenth, it was a focal point in that struggle to establish individual liberties and more representative government. ...The claim to this right also emerged in the context of a whole cluster of criminal procedures whose object was to ensure fair play to the criminally accused. It harmonized with the principles that the accused was innocent until proved guilty and that the burden of proof was on the prosecution. It was related to the idea that a man’s home should not be promiscuously broken into and rifled for evidence of his reading and writing. It was intimately connected to the belief that torture or any cruelty in forcing a man to expose his guilt was unfair and illegal. It was indirectly associated with the right to counsel and to have witnesses on behalf of the defendant, so that his lips could be sealed against the government’s questions or accusations. …Above all, the right was most closely linked to freedom of religion and speech. It was, in its origins, unquestionably the invention of those who were guilty of religious crimes, like heresy, schism, nonconformity, and, later, of political crimes like treason, seditious libel, and breach of parliamentary privilege - - more often than not, the offense was merely criticism of the government, its policies, or its officers. The right was associated then with guilt for crimes of conscience, of belief, and of association. In the broadest sense it was a protection not of the guilty, or of the innocent, but of freedom of expression, of political liberty, of the right to worship as one pleased. In sum, its subtle and slow emergence in English law was, in the words of Dean Erwin N. Griswold, ‘one of the great landmarks of man’s struggle to make himself civilized,’ ‘an expression of the moral striving of the community,’ and ‘an ever-present reminder of our belief in the importance of the individual.’ The symbolic importance and practical function of the right was certainly a settled matter, taken for granted, in the eighteenth century. And before that it was part D:\533582156.doc Created on 10/9/2006 11:33:00 AM Last printed 3/9/2016 2:16:00 AM Page 76 of 158 Words 47,586 of the heritage of liberty which the common law bequeathed to the English settlers in America. ”185 In light of this rendition of history, it is not surprising that Levy concludes that although the right against self-incrimination “was but shakily or unevenly established in America by the close of the seventeenth century,”186 it was well established by the time the Bill of Rights was ratified at the close of the eighteenth century. He quotes a 1735 pamphlet by Benjamin Franklin that supported a minister’s right to refuse to submit his dissident sermons to a commission of inquiry, arguing that such compulsion “is contrary to the common rights of mankind, no man being obliged to furnish matter of accusation against himself.”187 He also cites several cases from colonial New York, Pennsylvania, Massachusetts and other colonies to the effect that, “the right against self-incrimination was…firmly fixed…”188 By 1776, “several states elevated the common-law right against selfincrimination to the status of a constitutional right.”189 Thus, when the privilege was included in the Fifth Amendment in 1793, it was uncontroversial. According to Levy, it was, at the very least, “a ban on torture and a security for the criminally accused,”190 but “these were not the whole of its functions:” “The framers understood that without fair and regularized procedures to protect the criminally accused, there could be no liberty. They knew that from time immemorial, the tyrant’s first step was to use the criminal law to crush his opposition. Vicious and ad hoc procedures had always been used to victimize nonconformists and minorities of differing religions, radical or political persuasion. The Fifth Amendment was part and parcel of the procedures that were so crucial, in the minds of the framers to the survival of the most treasured rights. One’s home could not be his “castle,” his property be his own, his right to express his opinions or to worship his God be secure, if he could be searched, arrested, tried, or imprisoned in some arbitrary or ignoble manner. ….The framers of the Bill of Rights saw their injunction, that no man should be a witness against himself in a criminal case, as a central feature of the accusatory system of criminal justice. While deeply committed to perpetuating a system that 185 Levy, pp. 331-332 Levy, p. 368 187 Levy, p. 383 188 Levy, p. 385 189 Levy, p. 405 190 Levy, p. 430 186 D:\533582156.doc Created on 10/9/2006 11:33:00 AM Last printed 3/9/2016 2:16:00 AM Page 77 of 158 Words 47,586 minimized the possibilities of convicting the innocent, they were not less concerned about the humanity that the fundamental law should show even to the offender. Above all, the Fifth Amendment reflected their judgment that in a free society, based on respect for the individual, the determination of guilt or innocence by just procedures, in which the accused made no unwilling contribution to his conviction, was more important than punishing the guilty.”191 Further, the fifteen relevant words of the Fifth Amendment constituted “the statement of a bare principle…in order to allow for its expansion as the need might arise.”192 This broad view of the political and religious history of the right against self-incrimination and of its established status by 1793 has been vigorously disputed by some legal historians, prominent among them Professor John Langbein of Yale Law School (and for purposes of full disclosure a former criminal law student of mine). 191 192 Levy, pp. 430-431 Levy p. 430 D:\533582156.doc Created on 10/9/2006 11:33:00 AM Last printed 3/9/2016 2:16:00 AM Page 78 of 158 Words 47,586 The Langbein Hypothesis John H. Langbein, whose groundbreaking research has revolutionized our understanding of the development of the adversary system of criminal justice, argues that the origins of the contemporary privilege against self-incrimination lie not so much in the dissent battles over the oath ex officio, as in the increasing role of defense counsel following the ratification of the Bill of Rights. He sees the privilege, therefore, much more in the context of the criminal justice system than in the broader context of political and religious dissent. His primary argument is that prior to the eighteenth century, there could be no effective privilege since the defendant was, as a practical matter, required to speak for himself at trial. This was the case because an attorney could not speak for him. Unless the defendant personally “respond[ed] to the charges against him,”193 he would effectively be presumed guilty and convicted, since he also “lacked the protection of the modern judicial instruction on the standard of proof....194” Thus, as Langbein picturesquely summarizes the situation: “The right to remain silent when no one else can speak for you is simply the right to slit your throat, and it is hardly a mystery that defendants did not hasten to avail themselves of such a privilege.”195 Langbein researched the “pamphlet reports of trials from the 1670s through the mid-1730s”—and then “into the 1780s”—and found no case in “which an accused refused to speak on asserted grounds of privilege, or in which he makes the least allusion to a privilege against self-incrimination.” He concluded therefore that criminal defendants could not, as a practical matter, assert any privilege against self-incrimination. “In a word, they sang.”196 John H. Langbein, “The Privilege and Common Law Criminal Procedure: The Sixteenth to the Eighteenth Centuries,” in R.H. Helmholz, et al., The Privilege Against Self-Incrimination: Its Origins and Developments (Chicago: The University of Chicago Press, 1997), p. 84. 194 John H. Langbein, “The Privilege and Common Law Criminal Procedure: The Sixteenth to the Eighteenth Centuries,” in R.H. Helmholz, et al., The Privilege Against Self-Incrimination: Its Origins and Developments (Chicago: The University of Chicago Press, 1997), pp. 89-90. 195 John H. Langbein, “The Privilege and Common Law Criminal Procedure: The Sixteenth to the Eighteenth Centuries,” in R.H. Helmholz, et al., The Privilege Against Self-Incrimination: Its Origins and Developments (Chicago: The University of Chicago Press, 1997), p. 87. 196 John H. Langbein, “The Privilege and Common Law Criminal Procedure: The Sixteenth to the Eighteenth Centuries,” in R.H. Helmholz, et al., The Privilege 193 D:\533582156.doc Created on 10/9/2006 11:33:00 AM Last printed 3/9/2016 2:16:00 AM Page 79 of 158 Words 47,586 This all changed, according to Langbein, as criminal defense lawyers became more actively involved in the defense of persons accused of crime. The system transformed itself from the “accused speaks” model – which had little room for a privilege – to the “testing the prosecution model,” in which lawyers did the talking and eventually “suppressed the defendant’s testimonial role.” It was under this latter model that the modern privilege against selfincrimination developed in practice. Langbein acknowledges that the theoretical basis for a privilege ante-dated the emergence of defense counsel and the modern adversary system. The maxim Nemo Tenetur Prodere Seipsum (no one is obliged to accuse himself) has roots deep in Christian as well as Jewish law. A Christian was obliged to confess his sins to God (or his priestly surrogate) but not to admit his crimes to secular authorities. But Langbein’s “key insight” is that “the maxim did not make the privilege. It was rather the privilege – which developed much later – that absorbed and perpetuated the maxim. The ancestry of the privilege has been mistakenly projected backwards on the maxim, whereas the privilege against self-incrimination in common law criminal procedure was, in truth, the achievement of defense counsel in the late eighteenth and early nineteenth centuries.”197 Langbein relates the theoretical privilege to its practical utility in a nuanced summary: Against Self-Incrimination: Its Origins and Developments (Chicago: The University of Chicago Press, 1997), p. 95. 197 John H. Langbein, “The Privilege and Common Law Procedure: The Sixteenth to the Eighteenth Century” in R. H. Helmholz, Charles M. Gray, John H. Langbein, Eben Moglen, Henry E. Smith, Albert W. Alschuler (eds.), “The Privilege Against Self-Incrimination: Its Origins and Development,” (Chicago & London: The University of Chicago Press, 1997), p. 107. “Without defense counsel, a criminal defendant’s right to remain silent was the right to forfeit any defense; indeed, in a system that emphasized capital punishment, the right to remain silent was tantamount to the right to commit suicide. Only when defense counsel succeeded in restructuring the criminal trial to make it possible to silence the accused did it finally become possible to fashion an effective privilege against self-incrimination at common law.” John H. Langbein, “The Privilege and Common Law Procedure: The Sixteenth to the Eighteenth Century” in R. H. Helmholz, Charles M. Gray, John H. Langbein, Eben Moglen, Henry E. Smith, Albert W. Alschuler (eds.), “The Privilege Against Self-Incrimination: Its Origins and Development,” (Chicago & London: The University of Chicago Press, 1997), p. 107 D:\533582156.doc Created on 10/9/2006 11:33:00 AM Last printed 3/9/2016 2:16:00 AM Page 80 of 158 Words 47,586 “The better way to encapsulate the theme…is not to say that there was no privilege but rather to recognize that the structure of criminal procedure in the early modern epoch made it impossible to implement the privilege. The “accused speaks” criminal trial stood in perpetual tension with the notion of a right to remain silent. The privilege against selfincrimination became functional only as a consequence of the revolutionary reconstruction of the criminal trial worked by the advent of defense counsel and adversary criminal procedure. The privilege as we understand it is an artifact of the adversary system of criminal procedure. The error has been to expect to find the privilege in operation before the adversary system was in place.”198 Ships Passing in the Night There are several missing pieces in Langbein’s innovative analysis. In the first place, he deals with only one aspect of the privilege, namely the right of an already-charged criminal defendant to refuse to speak (Langbein sometimes says “testify” - - but a defendant was not generally allowed to “testify” under oath at his own criminal trial.) The so called “defendants privilege” is an important privilege, but it is not the only one. In reality there are three relatively distinct privileges against self-incrimination: the first is the one on which Langbein focuses, the criminal defendant’s privilege. As understood today, it has several components: it precludes the government (the prosecution or the court) from calling the defendant as a witness at his criminal trial. The defendant does not even have to invoke this right. It is a limitation on the government, pure and simple. If a prosecutor were to say, in front of a jury, “I now call my next witness, the defendant,” the right would be violated without more, and a mistrial would almost certainly be declared. Closely related to this limitation on the government is the right of the criminal defendant to decide whether or not to testify on his own behalf, and if he decides not to testify, to have no adverse influence drawn from the exercise of this right.199 If John H. Langbein, “The Privilege and Common Law Procedure: The Sixteenth to the Eighteenth Century” in R. H. Helmholz, Charles M. Gray, John H. Langbein, Eben Moglen, Henry E. Smith, Albert W. Alschuler (eds.), “The Privilege Against Self-Incrimination: Its Origins and Development,” (Chicago & London: The University of Chicago Press, 1997), p. 108 199 Defendant is entitled to an instruction to that effect if he requests one. 198 D:\533582156.doc Created on 10/9/2006 11:33:00 AM Last printed 3/9/2016 2:16:00 AM Page 81 of 158 Words 47,586 he decides to testify on his own behalf, he now has that right under the current interpretation of the Sixth Amendment, although he did not have it at the time of the framing. Related to this is the right of a defendant to a jury instruction squarely placing the burden of proof on the prosecution, because if the burden were to be on the defendant, that would undercut his right not to testify. Finally, there is the right to counsel, also under the Sixth Amendment, because in the absence of that important right, there would be no one other than the defendant himself to present the defense case. This broad defendant’s right is not limited to selfincrimination or being a witness against himself. It is an absolute right not to be called or required to testify at all, even if his testimony would be completely self-exonerating or in his favor. A criminal defendant need not assert, suggest or even believe that his testimony could be self-incriminating as a condition to exercising his right not to testify. He can simply decide, as a tactical matter, that it is in his best interest not to testify. To test this proposition, let us assume that a defendant confides in his lawyer that the only reason he does not want to testify at his trial is that he is afraid his testimony will hurt his friend, or will reveal an embarrassing but not criminal act (say adultery in a state where that is not criminal). It would be entirely appropriate for a criminal defendant to decide not to testify under these circumstances, and it would be entirely ethical for a lawyer to go along with that decision (so long as it did not compromise his ability to effectively represent his client – a somewhat more complex issue.200) As we shall soon see, this would not be the case with the witness’ privilege: a witness can only refuse to answer specific questions that could tend to incriminate him. If a lawyer asserted the witness privilege to protect a third person or to protect the witness from mere embarrassment, he would be acting unethically. Another example that demonstrates that the defendant’s decision not to testify need not be based on the self-incriminatory substance of his testimony is provided by the defendant who would simply make a poor impression because of his evasiveness, arrogance or other personal characteristics. The lawyer for such a defendant might well decide that it was too risky to put him on the stand, even if the substance of his testimony would be exculpatory. A mere witness could not claim the privilege on this ground. 200 Florida v. Nixon (03-931) 543 U.S. 175 (2004) [What else do you need added? Would you like to quote from this piece?] D:\533582156.doc Created on 10/9/2006 11:33:00 AM Last printed 3/9/2016 2:16:00 AM Page 82 of 158 Words 47,586 Getting back to Langbein and the defendants’ privilege, he is surely right that a self-interested defendant would be unlikely to decline to speak at all if his voice was the only one that could be heard in his defense. But to waive one’s right to silence may not always be the same as waiving one’s right against self-incrimination. A defendant could, at least in theory, speak exculpatory – that is assert his innocence and tell an exculpatory story, such as an alibi. Experienced criminal lawyers know of course that what sounds exculpatory to a lay client will often sound inculpatory – that is selfincriminating – to a judge or jury. This would be especially true if the defendant, after telling his exculpatory story, could be questioned about it by the judge or prosecutor. Langbein, in a conversation with me, said that he was not certain how much if any questioning of the unsworn accused took place during the “accused speaks” era, but it is logical to assume that some questioning must have been allowed [CHECK THIS] and that the truthful answers to at least some of the questions would be self-incriminating. It would be interesting to see whether any defendants who chose to speak on their own behalf and told an exculpatory story, then tried to assert the privilege in response to incriminating questions; and if so, whether judges allowed selective invocation of silence after the accused had spoken.201 Levy does not fully address this issue in his book, but in a subsequent law review article, responding to Langbein and other critics, he makes a related point: “The fact that defendants spoke does not mean that defendants were forced to confess guilt at their trials. Defendants spoke to deny the charges against them and to repudiate the prosecution’s evidence. They invoked the right only when necessary to respond to a question the answer to which might incriminate. … Langbein cannot distinguish between a defendant’s answering a question by denying the charges and a defendant’s refusal to answer on grounds of selfincrimination. Langbein says that defendants claimed the right in isolated remarks, while ‘utterly disregarding any supposed privilege against self-incrimination.’ Supposed? Is Langbein implying that the ‘privilege’ was just a fiction? Indeed, Langbein’s point misleads, for the defendant spoke to answer charges, invoking his right only when an answer might incriminate him.”202 201 202 prophylactic rule Levy, [Cardoza Law Review??] D:\533582156.doc Created on 10/9/2006 11:33:00 AM Last printed 3/9/2016 2:16:00 AM Page 83 of 158 Words 47,586 Moreover, Langbein neglects one of the earliest manifestations of the privilege that is central to Levy’s hypothesis: the right of a person not to reveal crimes of which the authorities had no knowledge. One of the great evils of the oath ex officio was that it required the person to take “an oath to tell the truth before knowing the charges and accusers.”203 Religious and political dissenters (and in an age when religion and politics were barely distinguishable, dissenters tended to be both) were summoned before eccliastical tribunals and required to take this oath. If they took it they — as believing Christians — would be religiously and morally obliged to tell the truth. “In the seventeenth century men did not take oaths lightly.” Once the person was under oath, the tribunal would probe them about their opinions, ideas, beliefs, heresies and loyalties. In that way, they would “ensnare” dissidents into becoming selfconfessed criminals. In 1607 the Privy Council, on a motion by the House of Commons, sought an advisory opinion from Chief Justices Edward Coke and John Poplam, about whether an ecclesiastical judge could employ the oath ex officio. This was their opinion: “1. That the Ordinary [another name for an ecclesiastical judge – (CHECK THIS)]cannot constrain any man, ecclesiastical or temporal, to swear generally to answer to such interrogatories as shall be administered unto him; but ought to deliver unto him the articles upon which he is to be examined, to the intent that he may know whether he ought by the law to answer to them: and so is the course of the StarChamber and Chancery; the defendant that the copy of the bill delivered unto him, or otherwise he need not to answer to it. 2. No man ecclesiastical or temporal shall be examined upon secret thoughts of his heart, or of his secret opinion: but something ought to be objected against him what he hath spoken or done. No lay-man may be examined ex officio, except in two causes, and that was grounded upon great reason: for lay-men for the most part are not lettered, wherefore they may easily be inveigled and entrapped, and principally in heresy and errors of faith: and this appears by an ordinance made in the time of Edward I. Tit. Prohibition in Rastal.”204 203 Levy p. 284 ???? P. 231 204 D:\533582156.doc Created on 10/9/2006 11:33:00 AM Last printed 3/9/2016 2:16:00 AM Page 84 of 158 Words 47,586 Thus, an early version of the privilege was that “no man had to reveal an unknown crime, but if strongly suspected he was obliged to answer truthfully under oath.”205 The latter part of this formulation soon disappeared, but the earlier has, of course, remained an essential part of the constitutional right.206 Langbein ignores the reality that this aspect of the privilege - not to be compelled to reveal an unknown crime - - could operate to the advantage of a suspected dissident even without his having access to counsel. The “accused speaks” system operated only after the accused was, in fact accused - - of a specific crime. At that point, absent counsel, he had every incentive to speak, and whatever privilege he may have had in theory did him little good in practice. But a dissident, who was merely suspected - - without external proof - of holding heretical or treasonous views, had an incentive to remain silent, and many did, even without advise of counsel.207 This right not to reveal unknown or merely suspected crimes became important during the McCarthy era when people suspected of communist affiliations were compelled to take loyalty oaths or to testify about their beliefs and affiliations. It has also been important in the context of police “roundups” of suspected criminals, which still occur from time to time. It is certainly among the root sources of the current privilege and dates this aspect of it well before the late eighteenth century, when defense lawyers began to play a more active role in the trials of defendants who would pay for them. In some respects Levy and Langbein are ships passing in the night. Each is dealing primarily with different aspects of the privilege and different historical sources of what eventually became the multifaceted constitutional right against self-incrimination. Levy, the historian, focuses on the larger political and religious roots of the privilege and on its “symbolic importance.” Langbein, the lawyer (and legal scholar) emphasizes it practical applications and its role as part of the adversarial process in action. The second privilege against self-incrimination - the witness privilege was not the focus of either Levy’s or Langbein’s hypotheses, but it has played a central role in the American history of the privilege. The witness’ privilege does not provide an absolute right to remain silent. If a witness in a case in which he is not the criminal defendant – say a civil case, a legislative hearing or someone else’s criminal case – is subpoenaed, he must take the stand208. He cannot 205 Levy, Cardoza Law Review, p. 2 With some exceptions, see Byers, Jenkins 207 See Levy Cardoza p. 12 208 In some situations, a judge will permit a witness not to take the stand if the judge knows that the witness will properly invoke the privilege as to all questions. 206 D:\533582156.doc Created on 10/9/2006 11:33:00 AM Last printed 3/9/2016 2:16:00 AM Page 85 of 158 Words 47,586 refuse to answer questions that might incriminate others or that would merely embarrass him. Nor can he claim nervousness or other personal characteristics. In order to invoke the witness privilege, as distinguished from the criminal defendant’s privilege, he must have a good faith basis for believing that the answer to a specific question or series of questions might incriminate him. He has no blanket privilege not to testify, as the criminal defendant does, but only a privilege not to incriminate himself. This privilege can be neutralized by derivative use immunity. The defendants’ privilege cannot. (A criminal defendant cannot be given derivative use immunity, called as a witness in front of the petit jury and then have the jury instructed to disregard his testimony and its fruits; he could, at least in theory, be called before the grand jury, given immunity, and be compelled to answer questions whose answers and their fruits would be kept from the petit jury. But indictment is almost certainly part of “any criminal case”, and so he would have been improperly compelled to be a witness against himself before the grand jury.209 The witnesses’ privilege has assumed a political role, since it is often invoked in legislative hearings such as those conducted during the McCarthy era. But it also plays an important role in the legal system, because witnesses frequently invoke it in civil cases and when subpoenaed by the prosecution and/or defense in the criminal trials of others. The third privilege, which grows out of the oath ex officio as described by Levy, is the suspect’s privilege - - something called “the confession rule” - - and it focuses on an entirely different manner of compulsion, from the defendant’s and witnesses’ privileges. The suspect is being interrogated by the police, who generally have no subpoena or legal authority to require him to answer any questions.210 He can simply refuse, not because of any constitutional privilege he has, but because of the lack of power the police generally have to compel him to answer. The power of the police comes not from the [See Furman] This is highly questionable in light of the general rule that a fact finder can draw negative inferences from a witness’ invocation of the privilege, but not from the defendant’s in a criminal case. 209 To complicate matters even further, what if a criminal defendant were granted derivative use immunity and compelled to answer incriminating questions before one grand jury (call it the investigative grand jury) and then be indicted by another grand jury (call it the indicting grand jury). Would that violate the privilege under Justice Thomas’ approach? It’s unclear. FN ON RIGHT IN FROM OF GRAND JURY. GOV’T CAN’T CALL A “TARGET.” 210 FN ON HUBBEL, ANDRESON, BYERS D:\533582156.doc Created on 10/9/2006 11:33:00 AM Last printed 3/9/2016 2:16:00 AM Page 86 of 158 Words 47,586 authority of the subpoena or judicial compulsion211, but rather from the psychological advantage they have in an encounter of this sort. The courts, therefore, have articulated a suspect’s privilege that purports to regulate the use of police compulsion – usually called “coercion” – in the context of in-custody interrogation. In the Brown case, (discussed supra at pages ___), the court said that “compulsion by torture to extort a confession” before trial is “a different matter” from the defendants’ or witnesses’ privilege, and is not governed by any privilege against self-incrimination, but subsequent decisions have regarded the suspects’ privilege as part of the constitutional jurisprudence of the right against self-incrimination. Conceptually, the suspects' privilege is in some respects “a different matter” from the defendants' and witness’ privileges and in other respects it is quite similar. It is different in that the defendants and the witness are being compelled by judges to testify under oath, while the suspect is being coerced by policemen to provide unsworn evidence that will be used against him at trial. They are similar in that the suspect is functionally in the same position as the person who was questioned under the oath ex offiico regime: both were suspected; neither was yet charged; and the questioners were seeking to obtain information they did not have or could not prove. It is correct therefore, certainly as a matter of history, to consider the suspects’ privilege in tandem with the other privileges as part of the overall right against self-incrimination. These three privileges, which have now coalesced into the modern 5th Amendment privilege against self-incrimination, originated from three distinct, but overlapping, common law rules with somewhat different histories and policies.212 Langbein is surely correct that it was not until sometime after the ratification of the 5th Amendment, when defense lawyers began to play a more active role in criminal trials and the police emerged as an important investigative institution, that the modern privilege became recognizable in its current manifestations. But Levy is correct in dating the roots of the privilege much further back in time. Moreover, as the wrongs change the rights change along with it. The early history of the privilege was 211 Some statutes now require a suspect to respond to certain limited police inquiries. See Hibel, Beyers. 212 Henry E. Smith: “The Modern Privilege: Its Nineteenth-Century Origins,” in: John H. Langbein, “The Privilege and Common Law Procedure: The Sixteenth to the Eighteenth Century” in R. H. Helmholz, Charles M. Gray, John H. Langbein, Eben Moglen, Henry E. Smith, Albert W. Alschuler (eds.), “The Privilege Against Self-Incrimination: Its Origins and Development,” (Chicago & London: The University of Chicago Press, 1997), chap. 6. D:\533582156.doc Created on 10/9/2006 11:33:00 AM Last printed 3/9/2016 2:16:00 AM Page 87 of 158 Words 47,586 inexorably intermeshed with political and religious persecutions in which men’s thoughts and ideas were on trial. These wrongs, with some striking exceptions, were not carried to the new world. The right against self-incrimination in the new world became more of a legal than a political right, invoked more often by common criminals than by heroic dissidents. During periods in our own history when thoughts and loyalties were again placed on trial, the right took on a more political coloration.213 All this makes it quite difficult to discern the understanding the framers had when they drafted and ratified the relevant words of the Fifth Amendment, and to decide how their understanding (or understandings) can be translated and made applicable to the very different system of criminal justice that operates today. Albert Alschuler has well summarized the situation: “In a very different world from that of the early American Republic, restoring the original understanding of the Fifth Amendment privilege is impossible.”214 It may be possible however to shed some historical light some of the narrower questions set out earlier on pages _____________ including the following: Whatever the content or contents of the various rules that were reflected in the 15 words of the 5th amendment, were they enforced only through evidentiary exclusionary rules at trial, or did they contain stand alone rights or limitations on governmental action, enforceable directly against those who violated the rules by employing improper compulsion or coercion? There is some very early historical evidence to suggest the latter. “Before the consistory court of the Diocese of Ely in 1375. disciplinary action was initiated against the archdeacon of Ely for having violated the prohibition. He was said to have habitually interrogated men and women under oath in circumstances where their “pretended excesses were wholly secret.” A similar charge was brought against an official in the Diocese of Carlisle early in the next century…. That the canonical form of the privilege also made itself known outside the world of ecclesiastical lawyers during the Middle Ages is 213 FN ABOUT ALIEN & SEDITON ACT Albert W. Alschuler: “A Peculiar Privilege in Historical Perspective,” in: John H. Langbein, “The Privilege and Common Law Procedure: The Sixteenth to the Eighteenth Century” in R. H. Helmholz, Charles M. Gray, John H. Langbein, Eben Moglen, Henry E. Smith, Albert W. Alschuler (eds.), “The Privilege Against SelfIncrimination: Its Origins and Development,” (Chicago & London: The University of Chicago Press, 1997), p. 202 214 D:\533582156.doc Created on 10/9/2006 11:33:00 AM Last printed 3/9/2016 2:16:00 AM Page 88 of 158 Words 47,586 suggested by a long-remembered incident involving Robert Grosseteste, bishop of Lincoln between 1235 and 1253. Grosseteste was a famous and earnest bishop, but as Sir Richard Southern has shown, the rigorous but unconventional approach characteristic of Grosseteste’s thought put him slightly outside the mainstream. Exactly that approach is seen his attempts to root out abuses and immoral conduct in his diocese. He went too far. He imposed oaths on the laity, requiring them to reveal their secret faults. In this, it was widely alleged, the bishop’s practice stood contrary to the law. Grosseteste was confusing the public courts of the church with the confessional, precisely in the way the ius commune forbade. Objections from the laity, objections that ultimately took the form of royal prohibitions, ended this experiment in pastoral control.”215 But as Charles M. Gray has pointed out, these cases involving writs of prohibition most often involved interjurisdictional disputes between religious and secular courts, and the writs were designed to preserve the prerogatives of the secular courts. In other words, they were at least as much about power as they were about rights. But still they suggest there was more to the privilege and its antecedents than a mere exclusionary right. The focus was not only on subsequent use of the evidence but also on the means used to compel or coerce the selfincriminating statements. This was certainly the case when it came to torture, which was seen as a stand-alone evil, and which, according to Levy, came to an end in 1640.216 It was probably also true of interrogation under oath, which, at least for some, was seen as analogous to torture: R. H. Helmholz, “The Privilege and Ius Commune: The Middle Ages to the Seventeenth Century,” in: R. H. Helmholz, Charles M. Gray, John H. Langbein, Eben Moglen, Henry E. Smith, Albert W. Alschuler (eds.), “The Privilege Against Self-Incrimination: Its Origins and Development,” (Chicago & London: The University of Chicago Press, 1997), p. 32-33 216 It is interesting to note that although the use of torture to obtain confessions or information “died out [in England] after 1640,” it continued to be used as an acceptable form of punishment following conviction: “Similarly, ‘cruel and unusual punishment,’ in the words of the Bill of Rights of 1689, were not torture either. The barbaric butchery, for example, that followed conviction for treason was regarded as a penalty inflicted on one who had been tried and found guilty by the ordinary processes of the law. Aggravated forms of the death penalty for murder, as well as treason, persisted long after the Bill of Rights, but in the eighteenth century gibbeting, mutilation, dissection, and the like were performed only after the doomed victim was hanged until dead. In any case, his punishment was in no legal sense regarded as a form of torture and had nothing to do with self-incrimination.” (Levy, p. 326) 215 D:\533582156.doc Created on 10/9/2006 11:33:00 AM Last printed 3/9/2016 2:16:00 AM Page 89 of 158 Words 47,586 “The claim that incrimination interrogation under oath is forbidden for the same reason that torture is forbidden was asserted by religious dissenters in England and embraced by religious dissenters in America. In about 1591, Thomas Cartwright and eight Puritan colleagues objected that the ex officio oath “put the conscience upon the racke.” In 1637, John Lilburne declared before the Start Chamber that “no man’s conscience ought to be racked by oaths imposed.”’217 The American historical evidence is consistent with the British. There was a close association between the principles underlying the privilege, as it came to be incorporated into the 5th amendment, and the fear of torture and other impermissible methods of interrogation: “[I]n legislative and convention proceedings, in letters, newspapers, and tracts, in judicial opinions and law books, the whole period from 1776 to 1791 reveals neither sufficient explanation of the scope of such a clause or the reasons for it. That it was a ban on torture and a security for the criminally accused were the most important of its functions, as had been the case historically…”218 In State v. Hobbs,219 an 1803 Vermont case, the Supreme Court of Vermont seemed to conclude that the state constitution’s self-incrimination clause was understood to prohibit the use of torture as a means of extracting evidence, regardless of whether its fruits were subsequently admitted into a judicial proceeding. Vermont’s clause read: “That in all prosecutions for criminal offenses…nor can he be compelled to give evidence against himself.” The court held: In this concise and luminous display of the rights of the citizens of this State, especially in the penultimate clause, all compulsory process to enforce an acknowledgment of guilty is for ever excluded, not only from our judicial proceedings, but Albert W. Alschuler: “A Peculiar Privilege in Historical Perspective,” in: John H. Langbein, “The Privilege and Common Law Procedure: The Sixteenth to the Eighteenth Century” in R. H. Helmholz, Charles M. Gray, John H. Langbein, Eben Moglen, Henry E. Smith, Albert W. Alschuler (eds.), “The Privilege Against SelfIncrimination: Its Origins and Development,” (Chicago & London: The University of Chicago Press, 1997), p. 191 (notes omitted) 218 Alschuler, citing Levy at 430 219 2 Tyl. 380 217 D:\533582156.doc Created on 10/9/2006 11:33:00 AM Last printed 3/9/2016 2:16:00 AM Page 90 of 158 Words 47,586 all attempts of individuals to extort confessions by bodily suffering is reprobated.220 (emphasis added) The case raised the issue of whether the defendant could be criminally punished for torturing the accused, who was suspected of theft: “The Court, in delivering sentence, observed, that there was no statute against the crime, as the Legislature never could have contemplated its commission in an enlightened age, and amongst a free people.” Id. Nonetheless, the Court ruled that “the indictment is founded on the common law, and must be followed by the common law punishment.” Had a statute prohibiting the conduct exited, “it would probably have been in the power of the court to award a punishment more adequate to the enormity of the offense.”221 In short, torture to extract evidence was itself a violation of the common law for which the torturer could be punished. The point of impact of the violation was when the torture was employed against the suspect, not when its fruits were admitted against him. The court explained its view of the history of the privilege: However the practice of torture to extort confession had prevailed in various governments, it certainly never was sanctioned by the common or statute law of our English ancestors for although the rack was occasionally resorted to in the reign of Henry VI and even in the reign of Queen Elizabeth, yet Judge Blackstone observes, it was used as an engine of state, not of law; and upon the assassination of the Duke of Buckingham by Felton in the reign of Charles I, it was proposed in the privy council to put the assassin to the rack, in order to discover his accomplices; but the Judges being consulted declared unanimously, to their own honour and the honour of the English law, that no such proceeding was allowable by the laws of England,. But in all ages and countries where the inhuman and unreasonable process has been in use, men of enlightened minds, so far as they have had occasion to mention it, have borne testimony against it; principally however, on account of its uncertainty as a criterion of truth.222 220 Id. (the case lacks page numbers for citation). Id. 222 Id. (emphasis in original). 221 D:\533582156.doc Created on 10/9/2006 11:33:00 AM Last printed 3/9/2016 2:16:00 AM Page 91 of 158 Words 47,586 This case presents a close analogue to Chavez. The common law understanding of the privilege, which was arguably constitutionalized in the Bill of Rights, was sufficient to punish the interrogator for torture. The court found that the use of torture to extract confessions was “against law, the constitution, and the peace and dignity of the state of Vermont.”223 It is unclear whether the person tortured in that case was ever prosecuted, whether he confessed, or whether any confession was excluded, but it clear that Vermont’s self-incrimination provision was violated by “all attempts of individuals to extort confession by bodily suffering.” Though the court said that an important part of the privilege’s justification was the unreliability of a torturously extracted confession, the privilege was cast as a primary right to be free from such coercion, not exclusively as a trial right. Its point of impact was the moment of coercion. It would have been interesting to see what a court would have done if torture had produced self-proving evidence - - say an admission of a fact that only the criminal could know. If there were no concern about “its uncertainty as a criterion of truth”, would the torturer have been commended for the truth he elicited or still condemned for the means he employed to produce that truth? Such are the vagaries of history that we can only speculate on the answer to this unasked question. Professor Levy may well be correct when he observes that “where there is a right against self-incrimination there is necessarily a right against torture,”224 but the courts and commentators have often less than clear about whether the “right against torture” stands alone and gives rise to an independent cause of action, regardless of any subsequent evidentiary use. The right not to be tortured was certainly on the mind of American Revolutionaries at the time the Bill of Rights was being considered. Torture was not a distant danger associated by the colonist with the old regimes of Europe, as Patrick Henry apparently believed when he warned of the potential power of Congress to: “Introduce the practice of the civil law, in preference to that of the common law. They may introduce the practice of France, Spain, and Germany – of torturing, to extort a confession of the crime…. [T]hey will tell you that there is such a necessity of strengthening the arm of government, that they must have a 223 224 Id. Levy, p. 326 D:\533582156.doc Created on 10/9/2006 11:33:00 AM Last printed 3/9/2016 2:16:00 AM Page 92 of 158 Words 47,586 criminal equity, and extort confession by torture, in order to punish with still more relentless severity.”225 Torture had, in fact, been authorized, in special cases, by article 45 of the 1641 Massachusetts Body of Liberties: No man shall be forced by Torture to confess any Crime against himself nor any other unless it be in some Capital case whether he is first fully convicted by clear and sufficient evidence to be guilty, After which if the cause be of that nature, That it is very apparent there by other conspirators, or confederates with him, Then he may be tortured, yet not with such Tortures as be Barborous and inhumane.226 By 1793, however, a strong consensus had been developed against torture and other impermissible means of securing evidence. Alschuler summarizes the situation as follows: “When the privilege was embodied in the United States Constitution, its goal was simply to prohibit improper methods of interrogation.”227 Even if that was not its only goal – and there is some dispute about this – it seems clear that it was at least one important goal. “Americans of the founding generation unmistakably saw the privilege as a safeguard against torture.”228 Indeed, Thomas Jefferson “would have replaced [George] Mason’s words on compelled self-incrimination by a ban on the use of judicial torture.”229 For these framers, the issue was not only whether coerced statements could be used in a criminal trial, but also whether the process of coercion – and especially torture – should be prohibited by the United States Constitution. It might still be argued that although the purpose of the privilege was to prohibit torture and other improper methods of interrogation, the means selected by the framers was an exclusionary rule. There is, however, no convincing contemporaneous historical evidence in support of that argument. Indeed, there is some evidence that not all governmental conduct that was thought to be prohibited by the privilege had an exclusionary rule as its remedy.230 And it is 225 Id. at 447-48. Id at 120-21. 227 Alschuler, The Privilege at 185 228 Alschuler, The Privilege at 192 n. 61 229 Privilege at 135 230 CITE SUPPORT 226 D:\533582156.doc Created on 10/9/2006 11:33:00 AM Last printed 3/9/2016 2:16:00 AM Page 93 of 158 Words 47,586 unlikely that the framers understood the self-incrimination provision of the Fifth Amendment as authorizing the use of torture for obtaining preventive information, as the ____ Century British torture warrant procedure and the 17th Century Massachusetts procedure had done. One prominent English treatise, apparently influential in the U.S., described the common law as prohibiting all torture, even that directed against a non-defendant: “By the common law of England, and that law is by adoption, confirmed by statutes, the common law of Ireland, no such engine of power as the rack, or nay other instrument of torture, can be used to furnish the crown with evidence, extorted out of the prison’s mouth against himself or any other person.” (MacNally at 275) (emphasis added) This certainly suggests that an exclusionary rule - - which would provide no remedy for a non-defendant - - was not understood to be the only means of enforcing a right not to be tortured.231 Nor is there any compelling evidence that the framers understood the due process clause of the Fifth Amendment to be the appropriate vehicle for safeguarding against torture. [AMPLIFY].232 If there was any provision of the Bill of Rights that was understood to prohibit torture it was the privilege against self-incrimination. 233 That much seems clear from the history. It would be much easier for historians, lawyers and judges today if the framers of the Fifth Amendment had explicitly considered and resolved the precise question, whether the application of torture to a suspect was a stand-alone, independent violation of his constitutional right against self-incrimination - - or whether the introduction into evidence of the fruits of such torture was required to complete the violation. But history does not always ask the precise 231 A debate between George Nicholas and George Mason (who drafted the Virginia Bill of Rights) may also shed some light on the original understanding. George Nicholas argued that the Bill of Rights “is but a paper check,” which was frequently violated. The Debates in the Several State Conventions on the Adoption of the Federal Constitution, 446. He went on: “If we had no security against torture but our declaration of rights, we might be tortured to-morrow; for it has been repeatedly infringed and disregarded. Id. at 451. Mason responded as follows: “the worthy gentleman was mistaken in his assertion that the bill of rights did not prohibit torture; for that one clause expressly provided that no man can given evidence against himself;’ and that the worthy gentleman must know that, in those countries where torture is used, evidence was extorted from the criminal himself.” Id. at 452. 232 This was no different with regard to the due process clause of the Fourteenth Amendment. 233 Perhaps the “cruel or unusual punishment” prohibition of the Eighth Amendment [AMPLIFY] D:\533582156.doc Created on 10/9/2006 11:33:00 AM Last printed 3/9/2016 2:16:00 AM Page 94 of 158 Words 47,586 questions to which the current generation seeks answers. We must be satisfied with the historical material that is accessible and reliable, and we must acknowledge that the available sources often provides incomplete answers, as a consideration of two early, important American cases demonstrates. D:\533582156.doc Created on 10/9/2006 11:33:00 AM Last printed 3/9/2016 2:16:00 AM Page 95 of 158 Words 47,586 The Marbury and Burr Precedent Among the most authoritative sources of the original understanding of the privilege are the judicial opinions of Chief Justice John Marshall, one of the nation’s greatest jurists who lived during the founding era and headed the Supreme Court in the Years following the ratification of the Bill of Rights. It just so happens that he opined on aspects of the privilege in two of the most important cases in American History. The first was Marbury v. Madison. the decision that established the power of the Supreme Court to review the unconstitutional actions of the executive. In that case, decided just ten years after the ratification of the Bill of Rights, one of the collateral issues was whether the acting secretary of state could be compelled “to respond to the Chief Justice’s question regarding what he had done with the commission at issue in the case. According to historian Leonard W. Levy, he “probably had burned it.” The secretary refused to answer on the ground, among others, that he should not be “compelled to answer anything which might tend to criminate himself.”234 The Court agreed, ruling that he was not “obliged to state anything which would criminate him.”235 Clearly then, Marshall understood the right (or the privilege, since he did not specifically cite the Fifth Amendment) to extend beyond criminal defendants at their own trials and to apply to witnesses in civil cases. This application of the privilege clearly preceded the development of the adversarial system and the right to counsel as we know them and could be mastered, to the benefit of the witness without the application of counsel. The witness in the Marbury case was, in fact, a lawyer. Indeed he was “in the peculiar position of being both a witness and counsel for the government” in that case. Yet he had no obligation of disclosure because a truthful answer might incriminate him. The second opinion was written fourteen years after the ratification of the Fifth Amendment — in the treason trial of Aaron Burr, which has been called, “the greatest criminal trial in American history.”236 234 Levy p.429 5 U.S. 137 236 Albert J. Beveridge, The Life of John Marshall (Cambridge, MA: Riverside P, 1919), vol. 3, p. 275. Another commentator notes: While under criminal indictment for the murder [of Alexander Hamilton, whom he killed in a duel] in New York and New Jersey, he had presided over the 1804 impeachment trial of Justice Samuel Chase. This had led one Federalist newspaper to quip that traditionally it was “the practice in 235 D:\533582156.doc Created on 10/9/2006 11:33:00 AM Last printed 3/9/2016 2:16:00 AM Page 96 of 158 Words 47,586 Marshall’s opinion centered as well on the witness’ privilege, but it also touched on the defendant’s privilege. The issue was defined by the Court in the following terms: “The attorney for the United State offers a paper in cipher, which he supposed to have proceeded from a person against whom he has preferred an indictment for high treason, and another for a misdemeanor, both of which are now before the grand jury, and produces a person said to be the secretary or clerk of the accused, who is supposed either to have copied this paper by his direction, or to be able to prove, in some manner, that it has proceeded from his authority. To a question demanding whether he understands this paper the witness has declined giving an answer, saying that the answer might criminate himself; and it is referred to the court to decide whether the excuse he has offered be sufficient to prevent his answering the question which has been propounded to him.”237 Marshall began his analysis by articulating the “settled maxim of law,” namely that “no man is bound to criminate himself.” This maxim, he continued, “forms one exception to the general rule…that every person is compellable to bear testimony in a court of justice.”238 It is interesting to note that Marshall did not cite the Fifth Amendment, or any provision of the Constitution, in support of this maxim. This might give rise to the inference that the witness’ privilege — as distinguished from the defendant’s privilege — was not originally understood to be included within the words of the Fifth Amendment. But Marshall then went on to discuss an aspect of the defendant’s privilege, which is undoubtedly covered by the words of Courts of Justice to arraign the murderer before the Judge, but now we behold the Judge arraigned before the murderer.” John C. Yoo, “The First Claim: The Burr Trial, United States v. Nixon, and Presidential Power,” 83 Minnesota Law Review 1435 (1999), at p. 1439. 237 U.S. v. Burr 25 Fed. Case. 38, no 14, 692e C.C.D. Va. 1807 238 The Court answered the question put to it regarding the witness’ privilege as follows: “The gentlemen of the bar will understand the rule laid down by the court to be this: It is the province of the court to judge whether any direct answer to the question which may be proposed will furnish evidence against the witness. If such answer may disclose a fact which forms a necessary and essential link in the chain of testimony, which would be sufficient to convict him of any crime, he is not bound to answer it so as to furnish matter for that conviction. In such a case the witness must himself judge what his answer will be; and if he says on oath that he cannot answer without accusing himself, he cannot be compelled to answer.” D:\533582156.doc Created on 10/9/2006 11:33:00 AM Last printed 3/9/2016 2:16:00 AM Page 97 of 158 Words 47,586 the Fifth Amendment, also without referencing the constitution.239 Perhaps this was because he understood the Fifth Amendment simply as constitutionalizing the common law and believed that the constitution should be invoked only as a last resort, if the ordinary law conflicted with it. The grand jury sought to obtain from the defendant Burr himself the ciphered letter. The grand jury “are perfectly aware,” according to its foreman, “that they have no right to demand any evidence from the prisoner under prosecution (i.e. the defendant) which may tend to criminate himself.” (emphasis added) Marshall confirmed the grand jury’s view of the law: “the grand jury were perfectly right in the opinion, that no man can be forced to furnish evidence against himself…” (emphasis added) This broad view - - namely that a defendant need not produce physical evidence, even documents, that might incriminate him - - is not the law today, though it was the law through much of our history.240 As Justice Oliver Wendell Holmes Jr. put it in 1913: “A party is privileged from producing the evidence but not from its production.”241 [PARAGRAPH ON BOYD CASE AND ITS OVERRULING WARDEN V. HAYDEN.] Another issue that arose in the Burr Case was whether the grand jury could “examine” the defendant on issues that were not selfincriminating. The Chief Justice “presumed that the grand jury wished to know whether the person under prosecution could be examined on other questions not criminating himself?” (p.95). The answer will be surprising to the modern ear: “The Chief Justice knew not that there was any objection to the grand jury calling before them and examining any man as a witness who laid under an indictment.” (pp.95-96). It is not clear whether the proposed examination would be under oath or unsworn, but it does seem clear that Marshall believed 239 Marshall did cite the constitution in his opinion on whether the president could be subpoenaed, but interestingly, he cited the wrong amendment: “The Constitution and laws of the United States will now be considered for the purpose of ascertaining how they bear upon the question. The eighth amendment to the Constitution gives to the accused, “in all criminal prosecutions, a right to a speedy and public trial, and to compulsory process for obtaining witnesses in this favor.” (p. 43) It is the Sixth, not the Eighth Amendment to accords those rights. 240 Cite Boyd and other cases, as well as Warden v. Hayden. Johnson v. United States, 228 U.S. 457 (1913), at 458. It is still true that a defendant need not respond to a subpoena if the act of production itself, as distinguished from what is produced, might be incriminating. [expand and explain production immunity] 241 D:\533582156.doc Created on 10/9/2006 11:33:00 AM Last printed 3/9/2016 2:16:00 AM Page 98 of 158 Words 47,586 that a criminal defendant who was not yet indicted could be examined, like any other witness, by the grand jury that was considering his indictment, but that, also like any other witness, he could refuse to answer those questions that might be incriminating. We cannot be certain about any of this, because in the end the issue was mooted by Burr’s representation to the court that “the letter is not at this time in my possession….” (p. 96). He added that he “did not put this letter out of my possession because I expected the grand jury would take up this subject but from a suspicion that they might do so.” (p. 97) (emphasis in original). Under today’s law, Burr’s admission would almost certainly establish an obstruction of justice, but apparently under the law at the time, a defendant was free to rid himself of possibly incriminating evidence if he merely suspected, rather than knew, that the grand jury was interested in the evidence. Another perplexing aspect of Marshall’s view of the privilege is his apparent limitation of its application to serious felonies such as treason. He opined that “if the letter should relate to misdemeanor and not to the treason, the court is not apprized that a knowledge and concealment of the misdemeanor would expose the witness to any prosecution whatsoever.” It is not clear whether Marshall meant that fear of incrimination for a misdemeanor is never covered by the privilege — an unlikely reading since there were serious misdemeanors at the time that subjected defendants to harsh punishment, even impeachment. The more likely reading is that a prosecution of this particular witness on misdemeanor charges was remote, perhaps because it would not be a crime to “conceal” a misdemeanor.242 This latter reading would support a narrower interpretation of the privilege, and one that would authorize immunity as a technique for trumping the witness privilege.243 These opinions by America’s greatest Chief Justice in America’s greatest criminal trial should give pause to anyone seeking to discern the original understanding of the Fifth (or any other) Amendment. Few contemporary American judges would recognize the current privilege against self-incrimination in the rulings of Chief 242 Misprision of felony was a crime, but misprision of misdemeanor may not have been—at least in Marshall’s view. [CHECK LAWS.] 243 Another episode that occurred during the Burr trial could also lend some support to immunity: “the President took the extraordinary step of personally interrogating one of the key witnesses, of striking a plea bargain with him that exchanged a pardon for testimony, and then of instruction the prosecutor on how to examine him at trial.” (Letter from Thomas Jefferson to George Hay (May 20, 1807), in 10 Words of Thomas Jefferson pp. 394-401 {Paul Leicester Ford ed., 1905}; see also Leonard W. Levy, Jefferson & Civil Liberties: The Darker Side pp. 70-73 (1963).) D:\533582156.doc Created on 10/9/2006 11:33:00 AM Last printed 3/9/2016 2:16:00 AM Page 99 of 158 Words 47,586 Justice Marshall. Even so central a figure in our own constitutional jurisprudence as Marshall is Wittgenstein’s lion when it comes to understanding the late eighteenth and early nineteenth century privilege against self-incrimination. Its broad outlines are discernable in the maxim that “no man is bound to criminate himself,” but the details and applications of the modern privilege (or privileges) are difficult to identify. D:\533582156.doc Created on 10/9/2006 11:33:00 AM Last printed 3/9/2016 2:16:00 AM Page 100 of 158 Words 47,586 Historical conclusions Legal history rarely speaks with one clear voice. This is especially so with regard to the history of rights. Rights are often rooted in a recognition of wrongs and a desire to avoid their recurrence. It should follow that the development of rights will be as sporadic, episodic and inconsistent as the acknowledgement of wrongs. The history of the privilege confirms this thesis. Consider for example the issue of whether the privilege protected a person from revealing information that was shameful, but not criminal. In Ullman v. U.S, The Supreme Court ruled, in an opinion by Justice Felix Frankfurter that, “The interdiction of the Fifth Amendment operates only where a witness is asked to incriminate himself - - in other words, to give testimony which may possibly expose him to a criminal charge. But if the criminality has already been taken away, the Amendment ceases to apply.”244 Justices William O. Douglas and Hugo Black argued in dissent that, “The Fifth Amendment was designed to protect the accused against infamy, as well as against prosecution. …[T]he Italian jurist Baccaria, and his French and English followers, influenced American though in the critical years following our Revolution. The history of infamy as a punishment was notorious. Luther had inveighed against excommunication. The Massachusetts Body of Liberties of 1641 had provided in Article 60: No church censure shall degrade or depose any man from any Civil [p.451] dignities, office, or Authorities he shall have in the Commonwealth. Loss of office, loss of dignity, loss of face were feudal forms of punishment. Infamy was historically considered to be punishment as effective as fine and imprisonment. The Beccarian attitude toward infamy was a part of the background of the Fifth Amendment. …It was in this tradition that Lord Chief Justice Treby 244 Ullman v. U.S. 350 U.S. 422 D:\533582156.doc Created on 10/9/2006 11:33:00 AM Last printed 3/9/2016 2:16:00 AM Page 101 of 158 Words 47,586 ruled in 1696 that ‘…no man is bound to answer any questions that will subject him to a penalty, or to infamy.” Trial of Friend, 13 How. St. Tr. 1, 17. …It is no answer to say that a witness who exercises his Fifth Amendment right of silence and stands mute may bring himself into disrepute. If so, that is the price he pays for exercising the right of silence granted by the Fifth Amendment. The critical point is that the Constitution places the right of silence beyond the reach of government. The Fifth Amendment stands between the citizen and his government. When public opinion casts a person into the outer darkness, as happens today when a person is exposed as a Communist, the government brings infamy on the head of the witness when it compels disclosure. That is precisely what the Fifth Amendment prohibits.”245 Accordingly, Justice Douglas and Black concluded that immunity from prosecution is not sufficient to protect a witness from the evils that the Fifth Amendment was designed to protect against. The historian Leonard W. Levy argued that Douglas and Black had come to the right result, but for the wrong historical reasons.246 He cites numerous instances of dissidents and others refusing to admit conduct that might be shameful but not criminal. He concluded that, “history was on the side of Douglas and Black, dissenting, with respect to the question of whether the “privilege” embraced public infamy, but they did not know it.” He also concluded that history was on the side of those who argued that “a full grant of immunity superseded the witness’ right to refuse to answer on grounds of self-incrimination.”247 As a matter of logic, however, these two conclusions are irreconcilable. If the privilege protected against self-revelation of shameful but non-criminal acts, then immunity could not trump the privilege, since immunity cannot protect against shame. Under a grant of immunity, the person must admit to his shameful behavior, he simply can’t be criminally prosecuted for it. Ullman v. U.S. 350 U.S. 422 There are numerous examples throughout early British and American history of the privilege being invoked against infamy. See eg. Levy at pp. __________ ____________ 247 Levy, Political Science Quarterly p. 23 245 246 D:\533582156.doc Created on 10/9/2006 11:33:00 AM Last printed 3/9/2016 2:16:00 AM Page 102 of 158 Words 47,586 These two conclusions are irreconcilable therefore as a matter of logic, but they may both be correct as a matter of history. History does not unfold logically, consistently or singularly. This was especially so in systems, like the British or the American Colonial, which lacked hierarchal judicial review in which a single Supreme Court authoritatively interpreted a written constitution. There will often be historical incident and events - - some even contemporaneous with the other - - that speak with different voices or at least with different tones. Advocates seize on the material that supports their view while ignoring material that undercuts it. Good historians present all the conflicting data and rarely expect a singular view. Current research on the history of the Fifth Amendment’s prohibition on compelled self-incrimination suggests that in 1793 it was very much a work in progress. The right against selfincrimination, as we know it today, had not yet developed fully, either in theory or in practice. The relevant words of the Fifth Amendment purported to constitutionalize the existing common law - - to take a snapshot of a streaming video. They also reflected several principles that were deeply rooted in religion and history but were inchoate in practice. The criminal justice system (or systems) then in existence in the colonies was so dramatically different from our current approach that direct analogies are inevitably misleading. The limited role of counsel in most run of the mill criminal cases, the pressures on defendants to speak in their own defense, the prohibition on defendants testifying as sworn witnesses, the absence of instructions on not drawing adverse inferences from silence and on the presumption of innocence, the absence of police as we know them and of back-room interrogation, and other contemporaneous differences relegated the privilege to a largely symbolic role in most cases. These symbols, however, were apparently of considerable importance to the generation of framers who were well aware of the abuses still prevalent in parts of Europe and only recently ended in England. Over the years following the adoption of the Fifth Amendment, the role of the privilege was to change considerably. The fifteen words came to be understood as incorporating several different principles, all of which grew out of the history of the various rules and principles that eventually gave rise to the modern privilege, but none of which were completely developed by 1793. In light of this complicated background, it is difficult to find specific historical answers to every contemporary question of interpretation posed by the amendment’s words, but a few conclusions seem plausible, if not certain: D:\533582156.doc Created on 10/9/2006 11:33:00 AM Last printed 3/9/2016 2:16:00 AM Page 103 of 158 Words 47,586 1. The framers do not appear to have actually considered the precise question posed directly by the Martinez case, namely whether the privilege includes an independent stand-alone right not to be subjected to coercion or compulsion, or whether the exclusive right is not to have the fruits of such compulsion or coercion admitted against the defendant at his criminal trial. There is no historical evidence of which I am aware that this issue was discussed, debated or decided by the framers, or that the words of the Fifth Amendment purported to answer this question. 2. The framers, or at least many of them, probably understood the amendment’s words as including a standalone independent right not to be subjected to “judicial torture.” It seems likely that one purpose of the amendment was to impose a limitation on government against the introduction of torture as part of the American criminal justice system. It is uncertain, however, what understanding, if any, the framers might have had about the remedy or remedies for violating this prohibition, but there is no evidence that they understand exclusion as the sole remedy for torture. 3. The framers, or many of them, probably also intended some sort of independent right not to be subjected to compelled judicial oaths in at least some contexts. Again there is little historical evidence of the framers’ understanding with regard to remedies. There is some historical evidence that exclusion was not the remedy against compelled judicial oaths.248 4. Some aspects of the early privilege, most particularly the “confession” rule - - or what I call the “suspect’s privilege” - - carried with it an exclusionary remedy. Others, most particularly the “witness” rule probably did not.249 248 CITE PRIVILEGE “The witness could raise the objection and might not be subject to contempt of court, but there is no evidence until several decades later that exclusion of the testimony from use in a subsequent proceeding against the witness was a consequence of a violation of the witness privilege. IF a third-party witness was wrongfully compelled to testify, the witness privilege did not bar the use of that testimony in his subsequent criminal prosecution. And, as we will see, the ideas 249 D:\533582156.doc Created on 10/9/2006 11:33:00 AM Last printed 3/9/2016 2:16:00 AM Page 104 of 158 Words 47,586 5. There is some evidence, but it is certainly not conclusive, that courts sometimes, but rarely, enjoined the compulsion or coercion of witnesses and allowed suits for damages by those who were coerced, or even criminal prosecutions against the coercers. But these tended to be unusual cases that often grew out of inter-jurisdictional disputes, and so not much can be derived from them. 6. There are early hints of a sort of pragmatic recognition of functional “immunity” as a tool for compelling selfincriminating statements from witnesses, though the doctrine itself was not formally enacted into law until much later. In summary therefore, there is considerable disagreement among historians and other scholars about the original understanding, or understandings, of the words of the Fifth Amendment that deal with compelled self-incrimination. Was it understood to convey a right to remain silent? And if so, what was the precise nature and scope of that right?250 Was it understood to apply only to criminal that exclusion would be a remedy was treated as a novelty in the 1847 Gorbett case, suggesting strongly that the early-nineteenth-century witness privilege was not backed up by the exclusionary rule that led to later exclusion of the confession obtained.” (Smith p. 157) 250 Albert Alschuler wrote: …in the winter of 1641-42, the governor of the Plymouth Colony asked the colony’s ministers and magistrates “how far a magistrate may extract a confession from the delinquent to accuse himself of a capital crime seeing nemo tenetur prodere seipsum.” One of the three surviving responses exhibited little shyness about asking incriminating questions of unsworn suspects or about pressing these suspects through “force of argument.” It declared, however, that physical force, threats of increased punishment, and interrogation under oath were all impermissible: I conceive that a magistrate is bound, by careful examination of circumstances and weighing of probabilities, to sift the accused; and by force of argument to draw him to an acknowledgement of the truth. But he may not extract a confession of a capital crime from a suspected person by any violent means, whether it be by an oath imposed, or by any punishment inflicted or threatened to be inflicted, for so he may draw forth an acknowledgment of a crime from a fearful innocent. If guilty, he shall be compelled to be his own accuser, when no other can, which is against the rule or justice. D:\533582156.doc Created on 10/9/2006 11:33:00 AM Last printed 3/9/2016 2:16:00 AM Page 105 of 158 Words 47,586 defendants at their own criminal trials? And if so, how can that understanding be reconciled with the practice at this time of not permitting defendants to testify under oath at their own trials? Did it apply to witnesses in legal proceedings other than criminal trials if their witnesses could be subject to later criminal prosecution based on their testimony? (Marshall answered yes.) If so, could this aspect of the privilege be trumped by some sort of immunity? Did the privilege apply to suspects who were being informally interrogated - - not under oath - - by officials who were more like the police of a later generation (e.g. constable, sheriffs etc.) than they were like judges? If so, were there any limits on the nature of the interrogations that could Summarizing the responses that the governor received, John Winthrop saw two principles at work: first, a principle that one might call “the Greenawalt principle,” affording suspects a right to silence in cases of light suspicion but not when a strong evidentiary basis for interrogation existed; and second, an unqualified prohibition of torture and of requiring suspects to answer under oath: [When a crime has been committed] and one witness or strong presumptions do point out the offender, there the judge may examine him strictly, and he is bound to answer directly, though to the peril of his life. But if there be only light suspicion, &c. then the judge is not to press him to answer… but he may be silent, and call for his accusers. But for examination by oath or torture in criminal cases, it was generally denied to be lawful. In 1677, the Virginia House of Burgesses declared that forcing suspects to answer incriminating questions under oath was incompatible with their natural rights. In the aftermath of Bacon’s Rebellion and its suppression, the House resolved “that a person summoned as a witness against another, ought to answer upon oath, but noe law can compell a man to sweare against himselfe in any matter wherein he is lyable to corporall punishment.” These sources and others discussed below support this judgment: The Fifth Amendment privilege prohibited (1) incriminating interrogation under oath, (2) torture, and (3) probably other forms of coercive interrogation such as threats of future punishment and promises of leniency. The Amendment prohibited nothing more, or at least the sources mention nothing more. The Self-Incrimination Clause neither mandated an accusatorial system nor afforded defendants a right to remain silent. It focused on improper methods of gaining information from criminal suspects. Albert W. Alschuler, “A Peculiar Privilege in Historical Perspective: The Right to Remain Silence,” 94 Michigan Law Review 2625 (1996), at 2649-2652. D:\533582156.doc Created on 10/9/2006 11:33:00 AM Last printed 3/9/2016 2:16:00 AM Page 106 of 158 Words 47,586 be conducted? The one historical issue about which there appears to be little disagreement among experts is that the privilege - - whatever else it entailed - - was understood to include, in the words of Professor Albert Alschuler, “an unqualified prohibition of torture…”251 A fair reading of the historical material does not support the conclusion that the only remedy understood by the framers to be available to enforce the prohibitions against torture252 or its equivalents was an exclusionary rule limited to a criminal defendant. Nor does the material support the conclusion that the only nonexclusionary remedy for torture would be under the due process clause. It seems likely, though not certain, that the framers understood torture as an evil separate from and in addition to the use to which it incriminating statements could be put at a defendants subsequent criminal trial. They probably viewed torture as an evil even if it was employed to gather evidence or information for use other than in a criminal trial against the defendant who was subjected to torture. There is certainly no compelling historical evidence to support the conclusion that the framers understood the Fifth Amendment privilege to authorize — or to put it more negatively to not prohibit — the use of torture against persons who would not become defendants in criminal trials. At the time of the ratification of the Fifth Amendment, there was some historical precedent for the use of torture against already convicted defendants to obtain information against their confederates253, as well as to secure preventive intelligence against traitors and others who posed security threats. There were also those, most prominent among them the philosopher Jeremy Bentham in England, who were publicly advocating the return of torture for convicted killers who refused to reveal the whereabouts of their dangerous confederates.254 There is nothing in the historical record to suggest that the framers intended to incorporate these controversial precedents and proposals as exceptions to the prohibition against torture. The historical record on the issue of torture is clearer than in the issues of mere compulsion and coercion. There is no compelling Albert W. Alschuler, “The Privilege and Common Law Criminal Procedure: The Sixteenth to the Eighteenth Centuries,” in R.H. Helmholz, et al., The Privilege Against Self-Incrimination: Its Origins and Developments (Chicago: The University of Chicago Press, 1997), p. 192. 252 Add the judicial oath 253 See Mass Law and Bentham 254 See Jeremy Bentham, “On Torture” (c. 1780), in W.L. Twining and P.E. Twining, “Bentham on Torture,” 24 Northern Ireland Legal Quarterly 305 (1973), at 316-318. 251 D:\533582156.doc Created on 10/9/2006 11:33:00 AM Last printed 3/9/2016 2:16:00 AM Page 107 of 158 Words 47,586 historical evidence to support the conclusion that coercion short of torture (or compulsion short of the judicial oath) were seen by the framers as independent evils separate from and in addition to the evil of using the fruits of such coercion or compulsion against the defendant at his criminal trial. Nor can it fairly be said that the historical record clearly supports the opposite conclusion. There appears to be insufficient historical material on the issues of coercion and compulsion short of torture. Nor is there much historical guidance on how to draw the line between torture and extreme coercion, as the Massachusetts legislature tried to do in 1641 when it authorized the use of torture as long as it was not “barbarous and inhumane.”.255 255 This is somewhat reminiscent of the distinction made by the Bush Administrations [CITE & DESCRIBE] D:\533582156.doc Created on 10/9/2006 11:33:00 AM Last printed 3/9/2016 2:16:00 AM Page 108 of 158 Words 47,586 The Privilege as Symbol In addition to the original understanding of the right against self-incrimination - - which is ambiguous on several important issues - - it may be useful to look at the understanding over time, and most particularly over recent generations. Justice Kennedy pointed to “the understanding that has prevailed for generations now,” and chided the majority for not being “more respectful” of that understanding. After quoting Dean Erwin Griswold’s broad and somewhat symbolic understanding of the “place the self-incrimination clause has secured in our legal heritage.”256 Justice Kennedy argued that it, “damages the law, and the vocabulary with which we impart our legal tradition from one generation to the next, to downgrade our understanding of what the Fifth Amendment requires.” The reality, however, is that the “understanding” of the right against self-incrimination has varied considerably with the times, and especially with the abuses experienced in a particular era. It has also varied with the level of abstraction at which the right is described. At one level, there is the privilege as “symbol,” and at another there is the privilege as “law in action.” Put another way, there is what lawyers and judges “say” about the privilege in the abstract, and what lawyers and judges “do” about it in concrete cases. To illustrate this difference, I will chart some of the most authoritative and influential hortatory statements made about the privilege throughout our history, and then contrast these broad statements with the far narrower holdings of the courts in actual cases. What has been said about the What the Court has held privilege: about the privilege: The privilege as symbol The right in action “…the Fifth Amendment can serve as a constant reminder of the high standards set by the Founding Fathers, based on their experience with tyranny. It is an ever-present reminder of our belief in the “The Fifth Amendment has been very nearly a lone sure rock in a time of storm. It has been one thing which has held quite firm, although something like a juggernaut has pushed upon it. It has, thus, through all its vicissitudes, been a symbol of the ultimate moral sense of the community, upholding the best in us, when otherwise there was a good deal of wavering under the pressures of the times.” E. Griswold, The Fifth Amendment Today 73 (1955). 256 D:\533582156.doc Created on 10/9/2006 11:33:00 AM Last printed 3/9/2016 2:16:00 AM Page 109 of 158 Words 47,586 importance of the individual, a symbol of our highest aspirations. As such it is a clear and eloquent expression of our basic opposition to collectivism, to the unlimited power of the state. It would never be allowed by communists, and thus it may well be regarded as one of the signs which sets us off from communism…. Let us never forget the great tradition of individual liberty in this country. There are few clearer symbols of this tradition than the Fifth Amendment.”257 (emphasis added) “It is truly an old friend, with an ancient and I believe useful history…. I would like to venture the suggestion that the privilege against self-incrimination is one of the great landmarks in man’s struggle to make himself civilized.”258 [TO BE ADDED] “I believe the Fifth Amendment is, and has been through this period of crisis, an expression of the moral striving of the community. It has been a reflection of our common conscience, a symbol of the America which stirs our hearts…. (emphaisis added) 257 Erwin N. Griswold, The 5th Amendment Today (Cambridge, MA: Harvard UP, 1955), pp. 81-82. 258 Erwin N. Griswold, The 5th Amendment Today (Cambridge, MA: Harvard UP, 1955), p. 7. D:\533582156.doc Created on 10/9/2006 11:33:00 AM Last printed 3/9/2016 2:16:00 AM Page 110 of 158 Words 47,586 “The fundamental value that the privilege reflects is intangible, it is true; but so is liberty, and so is man’s immortal soul. A man may be punished, even put to death, by the state; but if he is an American or an Englishman or a free man anywhere, he should not be made to prostrate himself before its majesty. Mea culpa belongs to a man and his God. It is a plea that cannot be exacted from free men by human authority. To require it is to insist that the state is the superior of the individuals who compose it, instead of their instrument.”259 “The reprobation of compulsory self-incrimination is an established doctrine of our civilized society. As stated by appellant’s counsel, it is the ‘result of the long struggle between the opposing forces of the spirit of individual liberty, on the one hand, and the collective power of the State, on the other.’ As such, it should be condemned with great earnestness. [CHECK THIS QUOTE] [Alan, this quote is right. -Alex] “The essential and inherent cruelty of compelling a man to expose his own guilt is obvious to every one, and needs no illustration. It is plain to every person who gives the subject a moment’s thought. “A sense of personal Abe Fortas, “The Fifth Amendment: Nemo Tenetur Prodere Seipsum,” 25 Journal (Cleveland Bar Association) 91 (1954), at pp. 99-100. 259 D:\533582156.doc Created on 10/9/2006 11:33:00 AM Last printed 3/9/2016 2:16:00 AM Page 111 of 158 Words 47,586 degradation in being compelled to incriminate one’s self must create a feeling of abhorrence in the community at its attempted enforcement.”260 “[The privilege against selfincrimination] is a part of the historical establishment of a balance, a balance between the power of the state and the rights of the individual, which I suppose more than anything else is the essence of modern democracy.”261 “The appearance of the privilege against self-incrimination — the guaranty that no person ‘shall be compelled in any criminal case to be a witness against himself’ — was a landmark event in the history of Anglo-American criminal procedure.”262 “The privilege against selfincrimination [is] the essential mainstay of our adversary system….”263 “This command of the Fifth Amendment… registers an 260 Brown v. Walker, 161 U.S. 591 (1896), at 637 (Field, J. dissenting). Telford Taylor, “The Constitutional Privilege against Self-Incrimination,” Annals of the American Academy of Political and Social Science, Vol. 300 (July 1955), p. 116. 262 John H. Langbein, “The Historical Origins of the Privilege Against SelfIncrimination at Common Law,” 92 Michigan Law Review 1047 (1994). 263 Miranda v. Arizona, 384 U.S. 436 (1966), at 460 (Warren, C.J. majority). 261 D:\533582156.doc Created on 10/9/2006 11:33:00 AM Last printed 3/9/2016 2:16:00 AM Page 112 of 158 Words 47,586 important advance in the development of our liberty….”264 “[T]he American system of criminal prosecution is accusatorial, not inquisitorial, and … the Fifth Amendment privilege is its essential mainstay.”265 “An experienced civil officer observed, ‘There is a great deal of laziness in it. It is far pleasanter to sit comfortably in the shade rubbing red pepper into a poor devil’s eyes than to go about in the sun hunting up evidence.’ This was a new view to me, but I have no doubt of its truth.”266 “The makers of our Constitution undertook to secure conditions favorable to the pursuit of happiness. They recognized the significance of man’s spiritual nature, of his feelings and of his intellect. They knew that only a part of the pain, pleasure and satisfactions of life are to be found in material things. They sought to protect Americans in their beliefs, their thoughts, their emotions and their sensations. They conferred, as against the government, the right to be let alone — the most comprehensive of rights and the 264 Ullmann v. United States, 350 U.S. 422 (1956), at 426 (Frankfurter, J. majority). Malloy v. Hogan, 378 U.S. 1 (1964), at 7 (Brennan, J. majority). 266 James Fitzjames Stephen, A History of the Criminal Law of England (London: Macmillan, 1883), vol. 1, p. 442 n. 1, writing in the context of a prohibition on questioning prisoners. 265 D:\533582156.doc Created on 10/9/2006 11:33:00 AM Last printed 3/9/2016 2:16:00 AM Page 113 of 158 Words 47,586 right most valued by civilized men. To protect that right, every unjustifiable intrusion by the government upon the privacy of the individual, whatever the means employed, must be deemed a violation of the Fourth Amendment. And the use, as evidence in a criminal proceeding, of facts ascertained by such intrusion must be deemed a violation of the Fifth.”267 “It reflects many of our fundamental values and most noble aspirations: our unwillingness to subject those suspected of crime to the cruel trilemma of selfaccusation, perjury or contempt; our preference for an accusatorial rather than an inquisitorial system of criminal justice; our fear that self-incriminating statements will be elicited by inhumane treatment and abuses; our sense of fair play which dictates ‘a fair stateindividual balance by requiring the government to leave the individual alone until good cause is shown for disturbing him and by requiring the government in its contest with the individual to shoulder the entire load’; our respect for the inviolability of the human personality and of the right of each individual ‘to a private enclave where he may lead a private life’; our distrust of self-deprecatory statements; and our realization that the privilege, while sometimes ‘a 267 Olmstead v. United States, 277 U.S. 438 (1928), at 478-79 (Brandeis, J., dissenting). D:\533582156.doc Created on 10/9/2006 11:33:00 AM Last printed 3/9/2016 2:16:00 AM Page 114 of 158 Words 47,586 shelter to the guilty,’ is often ‘a protection to the innocent.’”268 “This history demonstrates that the fight for the privilege against selfincrimination was a part, and an important part, of the great struggle against the oppression of the individual by the church and state…. It is my view that the privilege against self-incrimination represents a basic adjustment of the power and rights of the individual, and of the state. That, it seems to me, is the lesson to be drawn from its history.”269 ““Few people, I believe, would suggest that the 4th Amendment, protecting people against unreasonable searches and seizures, should be repealed, even although its primary effect, in practice, it the protect the guilty. Most of us would agree that even if a stock of narcotics is in a man’s house, the police should not be authorized summarily to force an entrance and to obtain this incriminating evidence. There is little difference in theory, I suggest, between breaking into a man’s house and forcing an entry into his mind into compel him to testify against himself. Both, I think, are instruments that may properly be denied to the state even although 268 Murphy v. Waterfront Commission, 378 U.S. 52 (1964), at 55 (citations omitted) (Goldberg, J. majority). 269 Abe Fortas, “The Fifth Amendment: Nemo Tenetur Prodere Seipsum,” 25 Journal (Cleveland Bar Association) 91 (1954), at p. 97. D:\533582156.doc Created on 10/9/2006 11:33:00 AM Last printed 3/9/2016 2:16:00 AM Page 115 of 158 Words 47,586 they would be effective methods of law enforcement. Indeed, it is interesting to note that in the course of man’s battle for his individual sanctity, history has given preferred position to the individual’s right to defend himself by withholding incriminating evidence. This right is not subject to defeasance upon a showing of probable cause, as is a man’s right to be protected against search of his household and person.”270 “I am confident that we should resolutely oppose any effort to repeal it, and that we should patiently and devotedly attempt to spread an understanding of its glorious history and its profound importance to a tradition which, although English in origin, is peculiarly American: the sanctity of the individual against the collective power of the state… It is this, after all, that is the basic principle which we assert in our mortal struggle with Communism.”271 “Totalitarian states, no matter the name they bear, always utilize coerced testimony wherever necessary to arrive at their desired verdicts because to them the ends justify the means. This is not true in the democratic republics of the world, and this is a principal Abe Fortas, “The Fifth Amendment: Nemo Tenetur Prodere Seipsum,” 25 Journal (Cleveland Bar Association) 91 (1954), at p. 99 271 Abe Fortas, “The Fifth Amendment: Nemo Tenetur Prodere Seipsum,” 25 Journal (Cleveland Bar Association) 91 (1954), at p. 104. 270 D:\533582156.doc Created on 10/9/2006 11:33:00 AM Last printed 3/9/2016 2:16:00 AM Page 116 of 158 Words 47,586 distinction between freedom and dictatorship.”272 “[T]he establishment of the privilege is closely linked historically with the abolition of torture. Now we look upon torture with abhorrence. But torture was once used by honest and conscientious public servants as a means of obtaining information about crimes which could not otherwise be disclosed. We want none of that today, I am sure.”273 The police officer “drew her gun and shot Martinez several times, causing severe injuries that left Martinez permanently blinded and paralyzed from the waist down…. Chavez accompanied Martinez to the hospital and then questioned Martinez there…. At first, most of Martinez’s answers consisted of ‘I don’t know,’ ‘I am dying,’ and ‘I am choking.’… Because we find that Chavez’s alleged conduct did not violate the SelfIncrimination Clause, we reverse the Ninth Circuit’s denial of qualified immunity as to Martinez’s Fifth Amendment claim.”274 The Fifth Amendment privilege is so fundamental to our system of constitutional rule and the expedient of giving an adequate warning as to the availability of the privilege so simple, we will not pause to inquire in individual cases whether the defendant was aware of his rights without a warning being given.”275 “The Miranda rule is not a code of police conduct, and police do not violate the Constitution (or even the Miranda rule, for that matter) by mere failures to warn.”276 Adrian B. Fink, Jr., “The Privilege Against Self-Incrimination — A Critical Reappraisal,” 13 Western Reserve Law Review 722 (1962). 273 Erwin N. Griswold, The 5th Amendment Today (Cambridge, MA: Harvard UP), p. 7. 274 Chavez v. Martinez, 538 U.S. 760 (2003), at 764, 773. 275 Miranda v. Arizona, 384 U.S. 436 (1966), at 444, 468. 276 United States v. Patane, 542 U.S. 530 (2004), at 637. 272 D:\533582156.doc Created on 10/9/2006 11:33:00 AM Last printed 3/9/2016 2:16:00 AM Page 117 of 158 Words 47,586 “[T]he basic purposes that lie behind the privilege against selfincrimination do not relate to protecting the innocent from conviction, but rather to preserving the integrity of a judicial system in which even the guilty are not to be convicted unless the prosecution ‘shoulder the entire load.’”277 “The real objection is that any system of administration which permits the prosecution to trust habitually to self-disclosure as a source of proof must itself suffer morally thereby. The inclination develops to rely mainly upon such evidence, and to be satisfied with an incomplete investigation of other sources. The exercise of the power to extract answers begets a forgetfulness of the just limitations of that power.”278 “In this case we must decide whether a failure to give a suspect the warnings prescribed by Miranda v. Arizona requires suppression of the physical fruits of the suspect’s unwarned but voluntary statements…. Because the Miranda rule protects against violations of the Self-Incrimination Clause, which, in turn, is not implicated by the introduction at trial of physical evidence resulting from voluntary statements, we answer the question presented in the negative.”279 Many of the most powerful of these hortatory statements were made during or after the abuses of McCarthyism. During the century an a half following the ratification of the 5th Amendment, little was said about the importance of the right against self-incrimination. This should not be surprising because an appreciation of rights often follows a recognition of wrongs. As I have written elsewhere: “It is incontestable that rights change over time and place, but they do not change at a steady pace or in a symmetrical manner. Long periods of time pass with few or no changes in rights. Then, suddenly, there is a burgeoning of new rights. My late colleague Stephen Jay Gould observed a phenomenon in nature that he called “punctuated equilibrium,” pursuant to which evolutionary changes “happen in fits and starts.” Though I am generally wary of using scientific observations of 277 Tehan v. United States, 382 U.S. 406 (1966), at 415. John Henry Wigmore, Evidence in Trials at Common Law (Boston: Little, Brown, 1961), §2251. (ORIGINAL MUST BE CHECKED.) 279 United States v. Patane, 542 U.S. 630 (2004), at 633-34. 278 D:\533582156.doc Created on 10/9/2006 11:33:00 AM Last printed 3/9/2016 2:16:00 AM Page 118 of 158 Words 47,586 natural phenomena as metaphors for human inventions, there are some striking similarities between Gould’s observations about evolution and my observations about rights.280 Gould’s approach has been summarized as follows: Darwin saw evolution as a slow, continuous process, without sudden jumps. However, if you study the fossils of organisms found in subsequent geological layers, you will see long intervals in which nothing changed (“equilibrium”), “punctuated” by short, revolutionary transition, in which species became extinct and replaced by wholly new forms. Instead of a slow, continuous progression, the evolution of life on Earth seems more like the life of a soldier: long periods of boredom interrupted by rare moments of terror.281 …. Though human inventions such as rights, and the wrongs that stimulate them, are neither as unintelligent nor as purposeless as natural changes, they too seem “to happen in fits and starts.” The history of rights shows long periods during which few changes seem to occur. Then a grievous human wrong, like the Holocaust, suddenly takes place. The world eventually acknowledges the wrong and responds with a burgeoning of rights, as occurred following the Second World War, when international human rights took giant steps forward. Sometimes the wrong is not sudden, but rather of long duration, such as slavery. It is the recognition of the wrong – or its defeat after a conflict – that serves as a stimulus for the development of the right. The post-Civil War constitutional amendments quickly turned a right to won slaves into a right not to be owned as a slave. There are numerous historical examples of rights burgeoning immediately after the acknowledgment of grievous wrongs, though this has certainly not always been the case. There have also been some historical examples of rights 280 This is, perhaps, no accident since I taught a course with Gould and with Robert Nozick over several years in which we compared and contrasted the epistemologies of science, philosophy, and law. 281 Stephen Jay Gould and Niles Eldredge, “Punctuated Equilibria: The Tempo and Mode of Evolution Reconsidered,” Paleobiology 3 (1997), pp. 115-151. See also “Punctuated Equilibrium” by Francis Heylighen at Principia Cybernetica Web (http://pespmc1.vub.ac.be/Punctueq.html; accessed August 25, 2004). The GouldEldredge Theory was not without its critics, one of whom, unfairly but cleverly, called it “evolution by jerks.” D:\533582156.doc Created on 10/9/2006 11:33:00 AM Last printed 3/9/2016 2:16:00 AM Page 119 of 158 Words 47,586 quickly contracting in the aftermath of wrongs that were believed to be caused by excessive rights. We may experience such a contraction in response to the terrorist attacks of recent years, and the contraction may become more extreme and widespread if terrorism were to escalate.” 282 Both aspects of this phenomenon are apparent in the history of attitudes toward the privilege against self-incrimination, which has gone through various cycles over time. It began as closely associated with the religious and political rights. John Lambert, who was burned at the stake as a heretic in 1537, argued this association in defense of his refusal to answer questions about his religious and political beliefs: “For it is in the law thus: ‘No man is bound to betray himself.’ Also in another place of the law it is written, ‘Cogitationis poenam nemo patiatur,’ ‘No man should suffer punishment of men for his thought.’ To this agreeth the common proverb, that is thus:’ Thoughts be free, and need pay no toll.’283 In nineteenth and early twentieth century America, it was primarily a trial right. Then, with the advent of congressional investigations, culminating in the McCarthy era, its focus was largely on political investigations. Now it is once again primarily a trial right that is in danger of contraction because of the war on terrorism and the perceived need to employ coercion in order to secure preventive intelligence.284 At another level, the fifteen words of the privilege have been understood, on one end of the continuum, as reflecting broad political rights of all persons, and on the other end of the continuum, as granting a narrow procedural trial remedy only to criminal defendants at their own trials. The Supreme Court’s six to three majority in the Martinez case interpreted the privilege in its narrowest possible way. The three person partial dissent interpreted the privilege only slightly more broadly by recognizing a stand-alone right, enforceable by a damage remedy not to be subject to “torture or its close equivalents.” The 282 Alan Dershowitz, Rights from Wrongs (New York: Basic, 2004), pp. 93-95. Levy, p. 4 284 It is interesting that the right against self-incrimination seems to have played no significant role during the period of the Alien and Sedition laws, when men’s thoughts and allegiances [?] were subjected to government sanctions. Perhaps this is because few of the cases actually went to trial before the laws were rescinded [expand and cite]. [See Charlie’s Memo 283 D:\533582156.doc Created on 10/9/2006 11:33:00 AM Last printed 3/9/2016 2:16:00 AM Page 120 of 158 Words 47,586 dissenters apparently agreed that the privilege did not contain a standalone right not to be compelled by the threat of contempt or coercion (short of torture or its close equivalents) to make self-incriminating statements. The only right a person has is to exclude the fruits of such compulsion from his criminal case. Not a single justice suggested any broader political right to remain silent or to keep the government out of any private or political enclave, as prior judicial and academic statements had suggested. This disconnect between what the courts have said about the right against self-incrimination and what they have ruled about that right raises broader questions - - questions that transcends the right against selfincrimination - - of the general role of constitutional rights in the context of our system of governance. D:\533582156.doc Created on 10/9/2006 11:33:00 AM Last printed 3/9/2016 2:16:00 AM Page 121 of 158 Words 47,586 Rights as Specific Limitations on Particular Governmental Actions Versus Rights as General Guides to Governance The entire Constitution, and most especially the Bill of Rights, contains numerous provisions that have multiple meanings at varying levels of abstraction. They can be read quite narrowly as entrenching a particular right in a specific, often time-bound, context. The same words can also be read quite broadly as enshrining a more general approach to governance. In 1962, I edited285 a Yale Law Journal note by my friend, colleague and sometime co-author John Hart Ely that made this point with regard to an apparently obscure provision of the Constitution prohibiting any “bill of attainder” from being enacted by congress or by state legislatures. (Article I 99, 10) At one level, this prohibition could be read as merely disempowering legislatures from doing what the British Parliament had regularly done: namely enacting laws that sentenced traitors to death and “attainted” their blood without a judicial trial. Read so narrowly, the Constitutional provision would not have current relevance since our legislatures have not passed bills of attainder since revolutionary times. To avoid such a dead letter approach, some courts have given the bill of attainder clause a broader reading designed to prevent “the kinds of evils" caused by such bills, even if the form was somewhat different. As the Supreme Court said in 1866: “If the [bill of attainder] inhibition can be evaded by the form of the enactment its insertion in the fundamental law was a vain and futile proceeding.”286 This “functional approach”287 — identifying “the kinds of evils” that were the focus of the framers and determining whether 285 See Footnote 1, The Bounds, p. 330 Quoted in The Bounds at p. 333 287 Ely was clear what he meant by functional: “The word ‘functional’ is sometimes used to mean “result-oriented.” This is not the meaning here intended, for of course the “literalist” position is as result-oriented as the position here described. Rather, “functional” is used to designate that approach which interprets a Constitutional provision in light of the sort of evil against which it was directed. It thus might perhaps be termed “historical functionalism.” (The Bounds at p. 333) 286 D:\533582156.doc Created on 10/9/2006 11:33:00 AM Last printed 3/9/2016 2:16:00 AM Page 122 of 158 Words 47,586 similar or comparable evils were present in contemporary legislative actions — was employed by Chief Justice John Marshall as far back as 1810, when he suggested, in dictum, that the “bill of attainder” clause may prohibit not only laws that fall technically within that narrow category, but rather all legislatively imposed punishments that are inflicted without judicial trial.288 John Hart Ely argued that the clause should be read even more broadly, as an important aspect of the separation of powers that serves as a structural protection against tyranny: “[T]he dual rationale of the separation of powers – fear of overconcentration of power in any one branch, and a feeling that the methods of selection and instructional trappings render the various departments suited for different jobs – is reflected in the bill of attainder clause. Not only was there a general fear of legislative power on the part of the founding fathers, but there was also a specific realization that the legislative branch of government is more susceptible than the judiciary to such influences as passion, prejudice, personal solicitation, and political motives, and that it is not bound to respect all the safeguards placed upon judicial trials. The bill of attainder clause is an implementation of their judgment that these factors render the legislature a tribunal inappropriate to decide who comes within the purview of its general rules.”289 He saw the bill of attainder clause (taken together with the ex post facto clause) as “serving a function analogous to Article III’s “Restriction of Judicial Action”: “Roughly, article III, by limiting federal courts to cases and controversies, tells them, at least in theory, two things. First, they – unlike the legislature – may not create broad rules; they must content themselves with applying the laws, either statutory or Constitutional, to the particular disputes before them. And second, because they are restricted to adjudicating the rights of the litigants before them, they can act only retrospectively. On the other hand, the prohibition of ex post facto laws (and notions rooted in due process and the obligation of contracts clause) tell the legislature that in general it can act only prospectively. The bill of attainder clause, it is submitted, is a broad prohibition completing the 288 289 Quoted in The Bounds at p. 333 The Yale Law Journal Vol. 72, 330 at p. 346. D:\533582156.doc Created on 10/9/2006 11:33:00 AM Last printed 3/9/2016 2:16:00 AM Page 123 of 158 Words 47,586 legislative analogue of article III. For it tells legislatures that they may not apply their mandates to specific parties; they instead must leave the job of application to other tribunals.”290 Other scholars, and several courts, have disagreed with the Ely analysis, and this is not the place to debate its merits. I cite it merely to illustrate the observation that Constitutional provisions may bear both a narrow technical reading and a somewhat broader structural reading.291 Similar dichotomous readings have been accorded virtually every one of the provisions of the Bill of Rights. Many Americans understand the First Amendment to guarantee them the “right of free speech.” But as I have written elsewhere (in response to arguments that the Commissioner of Baseball violated the First Amendment by suspending a player for making bigoted remarks in an interview): “Despite the common myth that we can say anything we please in this country, the fact is that our Bill of Rights does not grant Americans any general right of free speech. That’s why bud Selig, the baseball commissioner, can suspend and fine John Rocker, the Atlanta Braves pitcher, for expressing bigoted views in a magazine interview. … But to conclude that baseball has the right to suspend Rocker does not mean that it was right to do so. The First Amendment prohibits “Congress” and, by modern interpretation, federal and state governments from "abridging the freedom of speech, or of the press.” The amendment, then, is a restriction on government power, not on 290 The Bounds at p. 347. Justice Felix Frankfurter, who read the bill of attainder clause narrowly, proposed a different division: “Broadly speaking, two types of Constitutional claims come before this Court. Most Constitutional issues derive from the broad standards of fairness written in to the Constitution (e.g., “due process,” “equal protection of the laws,” “just compensation”), and the division of power as between States and Nation. Such questions, by their very nature, allow a relatively wide play for individual legal judgment. The other class gives no such scope. For the second class of Constitutional issues derives from very specific provisions of the Constitution. These had their source in definite grievances and led the Fathers to proscribe against recurrence of their experience. These specific grievances and the safeguards against their recurrence were not defined by the Constitution. They were defined by history. Their meaning was so settled by history that definition was superfluous. Judicial enforcement of the Constitution must respect these historic limits.” (Lovett, 328 U.S. at 321, Quoted in The Bounds at 341) 291 D:\533582156.doc Created on 10/9/2006 11:33:00 AM Last printed 3/9/2016 2:16:00 AM Page 124 of 158 Words 47,586 a right to say anything without fear of all consequences. The First Amendment says nothing about the power of private employers, universities, or sports leagues to censor or punish speakers who express views with which they disagree. Thus Selig was well within his rights as the chief executive of a private corporation to make an independent decision to suspend Rocker. The problem is that his decision violated the spirit of free speech that animates the First Amendment. The Constitution may impose limits only on government, but the First Amendment is premised on the idea that there should be a free marketplace of ideas.”292 [Emphasis added] A similar analysis can be applied to the establishment clause of the First Amendment which begins with the command that “Congress shall make no law…respecting an establishment of religion.” The concept of establishing a religion had a specific, technical meaning in 1793, when several colonies and states had recent histories of selecting one particular protestant sect - Anglicanism, Baptism, Congregationalism - - as the “official” religion of the government. The established religion received governmental funding supported by the revenues raised from all tax-paying citizens, including members of other faiths that were “tolerated,” at best and discriminated against or even banned at worst. It was a crime in Massachusetts as late as _______-- for a Catholic priest openly to celebrate mass. The narrow understanding of the establishment clause at the time of its ratification merely forbade the federal government from establishing one branch of Protestantism as the single official religion of the United States. It left each state free to establish a particular religion of its choice. Although several state Constitutions prohibited establishing an official state religion, ____________, _____________, and ___________ did have established religions until _____________. [Fill in and specify which states and which religions with cites]. Today, only extremists from the religious right and a few right-wing politicians and academics would limit the establishment clause to its original narrow understanding (even as amended by the 292 Shouting Fire, pp. 139-140 D:\533582156.doc Created on 10/9/2006 11:33:00 AM Last printed 3/9/2016 2:16:00 AM Page 125 of 158 Words 47,586 Fourteenth Amendment which - - according to Supreme Court decisions - - applies the First Amendment to the states through the due process clause).293 Even Justices Scalia and Thomas now acknowledge that the establishment clause has been given a far broader interpretation by history and precedents. Scalia has written: [FILL IN WHAT SCALIA AND THOMAS HAVE WRITTEN] There continues to be considerable controversy over the precise interpretation of the establishment clause, but even the narrowest current interpretation goes well beyond the technical prohibition that probably constituted the original understanding - - at least by many of those who framed and ratified the First Amendment.294 It has become an important symbol of the separation of church and state. Other aspects of the First Amendment - - the free press, assembly and petition- provisions - - also have both narrow technical and broader structural interpretations. At the broadest level, they - like the bill of attainder clause - - can be viewed as part of our system of checks and balances. Not only does each branch of government check and balance the other branches, but non governmental institutions - - especially the so called “Fourth estate” - - can serve as checks on government. As John Hart Ely wrote in his masterful book Democracy and Distrust, one of the important functions of the courts is to keep open the channels of democracy, which surely include all the institutions and practices protected by the First Amendment.295 The Second Amendment is a paradigmatic illustration of a provision with both a narrow and broad meaning. In this instance - as contrasted with most others296 - - it is generally the conservatives who interpret its words broadly and the liberals who interpret them narrowly. The Amendment reads as follows: “A well regulated militia, being necessary to the security of a free state, the right of the people to keep and bear arms, shall not be infringed.” 293 Quote Meese and others - - Alan Keyes There is a plausible argument that the text of the establishment clause - - the deliberate use of the inelegant phrase “respecting an establishment of religion” rather than the more common “establishing any religion” - - was intended to prohibit a broader array of actions beyond technical establishments. See ___________ 295 Ely, Democracy and Distrust 296 Another example of this “flip” is when property rights are involved. See ______________294 D:\533582156.doc Created on 10/9/2006 11:33:00 AM Last printed 3/9/2016 2:16:00 AM Page 126 of 158 Words 47,586 The narrow reading, favored by gun control advocates, focuses on the initial clause, and would limit the right to a collective one designed to preserve well-regulated state militias by prohibiting the federal government from disarming them. The broad reading, favored by gun advocates, focuses on the latter clause and reads the initial words as merely hortatory. It would grant not only “the people,” but each individual as well, the stand-alone right to keep and bear arms without abridgment by the federal government, and following the enactment of the Fourteenth Amendment, by state governments.297 As Charlton Heston, the president of the National Rifle Association, has argued that the second amendment was a symbolic significance that transcends its specific words: I believe every good journalist needs to know why the Second Amendment must be considered more essential than the First Amendment…. I say that the Second Amendment is, in order of importance, the first amendment. It is America's First Freedom, the one right that protects all the others. Among freedom of speech, of the press, of religion, of assembly, of redress of grievances, it is the first among equals. It alone offers the absolute capacity to live without fear. The right to keep and bear arms is the one right that allows “rights” to exist at all.298 There are, of course, textual problems with the NRA’s broad interpretation. The word “people” suggests a collective right and the words “keep and bear arms” suggests a military context, since hunters and sportsmen do not “bear arms.” As Professor Akhil Amar has demonstrated, “state Constitutions on the books in 1785 consistently used the phrase ‘bear arms’ in military contexts and no other.”299 There are also textual problems with the narrower interpretation: the words “shall not be abridged” modify the “the right of the people,” rather than the necessity of a militia. I respectfully disagree with Professor Amar’s suggestion that the word “people,” as contrasted with the word “person,” connotes a collective, as contrasted with an individual, right. After all, the 297 The Fourteenth Amendment issues proves something of a dilemma for some conservatives - - such as Edwin Meese - - who do not believe that the Fourteenth Amendment applies the Bill of Rights to the states, but would like to interpret the Constitution as prohibiting state abridgment of the right to keep and bear arms. 298 Charlton Heston, speech to the National Press Club, February 11, 1997, accessible at http://www.save-now.com/news/archives/Charlton-Heston-GunControle.htm. 299 America’s Constitution, p. 323 D:\533582156.doc Created on 10/9/2006 11:33:00 AM Last printed 3/9/2016 2:16:00 AM Page 127 of 158 Words 47,586 Fourth Amendment begins with “the right of the people to be secure in their persons, houses and effects against unreasonable searches and seizures.”300 Surely this includes an individual right, as does the First Amendment’s “right of the people…to petition the government for a redress of grievances.” But Amar is surely correct that the “slippery” words of the Second Amendment were based on “legal and social foundations” that have “washed away over the years.” The Supreme Court, which has not yet provided a definitive interpretation of this amendment, will be faced with a daunting challenge against the background of overheated political and ideological conflict. Part of this challenge will be whether to accord the Second Amendment a narrow, technical, and time-bound interpretation, or a broader, more functional and contemporary relevant construction. Even the Third Amendment - - which seems as narrow, technical and anachronistic as any amendment - - has been given a broad interpretation by some. The Amendment reads as follows: “No soldier shall, in time of peace be quartered in any house, without the consent of the owner, nor in time of war, but in a manner to be prescribed by law.” In Griswold v. Connecticut, TO BE CONTINUED 300 Amar responds to this argument as follows: “Why then, did the Fourth even mention the more republican-sounding phrase “the people”? Perhaps to highlight the part that civil jurors, acting collectively and representing the electorate, were expected to play in deciding which searches and seizures were reasonable and how much to punish government officials who searched or seized improperly. Private “persons” would remain the core rightsholders, but “the people on civil juries would retain a vital role in shaping the boundaries of the right.” (Amar, America’s Constitution at p. 326) D:\533582156.doc Created on 10/9/2006 11:33:00 AM Last printed 3/9/2016 2:16:00 AM Page 128 of 158 Words 47,586 Should Any Provisions of the Constitution be Interpreted Symbolically? Justice Scalia has opined on the question of whether the words of the Constitution should be interpreted broadly as the aspirational views of the framers or narrowly as a codified catalogue of specific and limited rights. He articulated his position as follows in response to a quite different approach proposed by my colleague Lawrence Tribe: Professor Tribe describes these roaming provisions as designed to “reflect[] … the aspirations of the former colonists about what sorts of rights they and their posterity would come to enjoy against their own government” (emphasis added). I do not believe that. If you want aspirations, you can read the Declaration of Independence…. Or you can read the French Declaration of the Rights of Man and of the Citizen, adopted two years before our Bill of Rights…. There is no such philosophizing in our Constitution, which, unlike the Declaration of Independence and the Declaration of the Rights of Man, is a practical and pragmatic charter of government. The aspirations of those who adopted it are set forth in its prologue—“to insure domestic Tranquility,” among other things, and “to secure the Blessings of Liberty to ourselves and our Posterity.” The operative provisions of the document, on the other hand, including the Bill of Rights, abound in concrete and specific dispositions. In addition to those described earlier, see, for example, the Third Amendment (“[n]o Soldier shall, in time of peace be quartered in any house, without the consent of the Owner”), the Fourth Amendment (“no Warrants shall issue, but upon probable cause, supported by Oath or affirmation, and particularly describing the place to be searched, and the persons or things to be seized”), and the Seventh Amendment (“[i]n Suits at common law, where the value in controversy shall exceed twenty dollars, the right of trial by jury shall be preserved”). It would be most peculiar for aspirational provisions to be interspersed randomly among the very concrete and hence obviously nonaspirational prescriptions that the Bill of Rights contains—“jury trials in suits at common law for more than twenty dollars,” followed by “all men are created equal,” followed by “no quartering of troops in homes.” It is more D:\533582156.doc Created on 10/9/2006 11:33:00 AM Last printed 3/9/2016 2:16:00 AM Page 129 of 158 Words 47,586 reasonable to think that the provisions are all of a sort. Professor Tribe emphasizes that such provisions as the guarantees of “the freedom of speech” and of “due process of law” are abstract and general rather than specific and concrete; but abstraction and generality do not equate with aspiration. The context suggests that the abstract and general terms, like the concrete and particular ones, are meant to nail down current rights, rather than aspire after future ones….301 Scalia’s list of illustrations – no quartering of troops, the warrant requirement, the twenty dollar criteria for civil trials – can of course be used to support precisely the opposite conclusion: namely, that the framers knew how to use narrow language when they wanted to disempower the courts from changing specific rules, such as the age requirements for office and the twenty dollar criteria (though I am personally convinced the latter was a simple drafting error). The fact that they used more open-ended language-- precisely of the sort they knew common law courts would have to interpret over time-suggests that they may not necessarily have meant to “nail down” all rights, such as those mandating “equal protection,” “due process” and the prohibition against “cruel and unusual punishments” or “excessive bail.” There is nothing “peculiar” or unusual for “aspirational provisions to be interspersed randomly among the very concrete… provisions.” Random interspersion is typical of our Constitution, as illustrated by the placement of the right against self-incrimination in an amendment that covers the rights of persons, rather than the rights of the accused. It is also typical of constitutions in general, as illustrated by [CITE OTHER CONSTITUTIONS, CANADA, SOUTH AFRICA, and PROPOSED ISRAEL CONSTITUTION] [See Charles Memo 4] One obvious example in the Bill of Rights that undercuts Scalia’s generalization that constitutional provisions were written “in concrete and specific dispositions” designed to “nail down” rights as they were understood at the time, is the provision against double jeopardy that appears in the Fifth Amendment. These are its words, “Nor shall any person be subject for the same offense to be twice put in jeopardy of life or limb.” [emphasis added] These twenty words have caused no end of interpretive litigation. The two words “same offense” have divided judges bitterly over the years. Is it the “same offense” if all the facts are the same, and the same 301 Antonin Scalia, A Matter of Interpretation (Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1997), pp. 134-35. D:\533582156.doc Created on 10/9/2006 11:33:00 AM Last printed 3/9/2016 2:16:00 AM Page 130 of 158 Words 47,586 crime is prosecuted by the federal government and then by a state? Is it the “same offense” if the facts are the same but the “elements” of the crime are different? These questions have been answered by looking at history—not always to the satisfaction of all historians.302 But what about the words “life or limb?” Must they be interpreted literally? Now that several states have abolished capital punishment and all states have abolished corporal punishment, can any person ever be placed in jeopardy of his “life or limb” in these jurisdictions? Does the double jeopardy clause not apply to imprisonment? Can a person be subjected to a ten year prison sentence and then tried again after he has served his term, since he was never in jeopardy of life or limb? Or should the words be read symbolically or metaphorically to apply to any form of punishment? [HAS JUSTICE SCALIA WRITTEN OR SPOKEN TO THIS ISSUE? CHECK] [Scalia has written about the phrase “of life and limb” See Charles Memo 1] The courts have been unanimous in interpreting these words more inclusively, despite the fact that punishments other than those jeopardizing lives and limbs were known to the framers who were fully capable of “nailing” down the broader interpretation by using the word “punishments” as they did in the Eighth Amendment. Instead they chose a somewhat literary, even poetic, formulation to express their views. A determined literalist would hold them to their choice of words and interpret the double jeopardy provision as narrowly protecting against only the death penalty, ear cropping and the like. (Branding would present a close question.) Yet no court has done this, and Justice Scalia has never explained why. [CHECK THIS] Phrases like “equal protection under the laws,” “due process,” “cruel and unusual punishments,” “the freedom of speech,” “secure in their persons,” “speedy trial” and “be a witness against himself” are also somewhat literary in their choice of words. They too could have been “nailed down” by more technical formulations. Yet the framers selected somewhat malleable, open-ended, vague and symbolic language. What were furture generations expected to make of that decision? What does the section of these words—as distinguished from other available words that are far narrower and more technical-tell us about the original understanding of the Bill of Rights? Professor Eben Moglen reminds us that the most basic right sought by American colonialists was “a constitutional right to the common law,”303 which suggests a dynamic rather than a static 302 [CITE] Eben Moglen, “The Privilege and Common Law Criminal Procedure: The Sixteenth to the Eighteenth Centuries,” in R.H. Helmholz, et al., The Privilege 303 D:\533582156.doc Created on 10/9/2006 11:33:00 AM Last printed 3/9/2016 2:16:00 AM Page 131 of 158 Words 47,586 constitutional law. They understood, as those who came after them understood, that it is a constitution, not a last will and testament, that the courts would be expounding. As a wise man once put it: “If we read the constitution like a last will and testament it will surely become one.”304 They also understood that they were drafting an enduring charter of government that would be difficult to amend. As Alexander Hamilton wrote: “Constitutions should consist only of general provisions; the reason is that they must necessarily be permanent, and that they cannot calculate for the possible change of things.”305 In the end our constitution did not consist only of general provisions; it contained some of the rather narrow particularistic provision cited by Scalia, but it also contained more general provisions designed to assure the enduring nature of the document. Henry Clay remarked on this shortly before the Civil War, “The Constitution of the United Sates was made not merely for the generation that then existed, but for posterity – unlimited, undefined, endless, perpetual posterity.”306 Moreover, any enduring Constitution must balance between security and liberty, and that balance may vary with the threats to each. Justice Jackson once observed that “[t]here is danger that, if the Court does not temper its doctrinaire logic with a little practical wisdom, it will convert the constitutional Bill of Rights into a suicide pact.”307 Justice Goldberg put it more simply: “While the Constitution protects against invasions of individual rights, it is not a suicide pact.”308 [PLEASE FIND A QUOTE ABOUT “LAST WILL AND TESTAMENT] Justice Scalia seems to acknowledge – indeed to welcome – the “last will and testament” approach, proudly describing the Constitution not as a “living document,’ but rather as a “dead” one all of whose provisions have been “nail[ed] down” — an apt metaphor for a dead constitution. He rejects Emily Dickinson’s living approach to words: Against Self-Incrimination: Its Origins and Developments (Chicago: The University of Chicago Press, 1997), p. 129. 304 Professor Paul Freund expressed this idea aptly when he admonished the American courts "not to read the provisions of the Constitution like a last will and testament lest it become one". 11 D.L.R. (4th) 641, 649 (D.L.R. 1984) [CITE ORGINAL] 305 Alexander Hamilton quoted in Jonathan Elliot, ed., The debates in the several state conventions on the adoption of the federal Constitution. (Philadelphia, J.B. Lippincott & co.; Washington, Taylor & Maury, 1836-59.), 2nd ed. p. 364. 306 Henry Clay Speech, U.S. Senate, 1850 307 Dissenting in Terminiello v. City of Chicago (1949). 308 For the Court, In Kennedy v. Mendoza-Martinez (1963). D:\533582156.doc Created on 10/9/2006 11:33:00 AM Last printed 3/9/2016 2:16:00 AM Page 132 of 158 Words 47,586 “A word is dead When it is said, Some say. I say it just Begins to live That day.”309 Justice Scalia argues that if the Constitution, when read as a last will and testament, would not serve the needs of modern America, then it should be amended or scuttled, not stretched, accordion-like, to fit the times. That, says Scalia, is the only democratic way. This approach views the issue of constitutional interpretation through the prism of modern democracy – certainly post-Jacksonian democracy. This was not necessarily the prism through which the framers understood the role of courts and judicial review. Many of the framers distrusted democracy or “mobocracy” as some called it.310 They viewed the courts--comprised of learned men appointed for life-as a elitist check on the people. They wanted to constitutionalize the common law, which would empower the courts to interpret constitutional provisions without the need for repeated amendments or constitutional conventions. As Alexander Hamilton put it in Federalist no. 78, “It is far more rational to suppose, that the courts were designed to be an intermediate body between the people and the legislature, in order, among other things, to keep the latter within the limits assigned to their authority. The interpretation of the laws is the proper and peculiar province of the courts.”311 It is somewhat “peculiar” for Justice Scalia to argue that the mode of interpretation most consistent with modern conceptions of democracy is to seek the original understanding of framers who had a very different conception of democracy. [ELABORATE AND EXPAND] 309 No. 1212[c. 1872] “Your people, sir, is nothing but a great beast”—Alexander Hamilton [CITE]. “In all very numerous assemblies, of whatever character composed, passion never fails to wrest the scepter from reason. Had every Athenian citizen been a Socrates, every Athenian assembly would still have been a mob.” James Madison, Federalist Papers no. 55. 311 Alexander Hamilton, Federalist Papers no. 78. 310 D:\533582156.doc Created on 10/9/2006 11:33:00 AM Last printed 3/9/2016 2:16:00 AM Page 133 of 158 Words 47,586 Our Accidental Constitution The U.S. Constitution, and its accompanying Bill of Rights, may have been intended for the ages, but it was written in its time and for its time. That is inevitably the case with any document, regardless of how future-looking and farsighted it may have been. The frame of reference for our constitution was late eighteenth century, post revolutionary America - - a nation with slavery, male domination, Protestant sensibilities, and economic and other qualifications for voting, jury service and office holding. Its frame of reference also included a criminal justice system that was relatively primitive, even by British standards. Trained lawyers were few and far between; the police – as we know them - - were non-existent; professional prosecutors were rare; judges were not well educated; prisons for long-term confinement had not yet been constructed; alternative to the death penalty were largely inefficient; the parchment rights of criminal defendants were ignored in many cases. It is quite remarkable that the constitution - - laden with regional and other compromises, written hastily, filled with drafting errors and sloppiness, combining time-bound, even anachronistic, provisions with broad, asperational words - - has outlived all others, and with so few amendments. Part of the reason for this longevity is John Marshall’s foresighted decisions that empowered the Court to engage in judicial review of a broad range of governmental actions. It was no accident that these decisions included the phrase, “we must never forget that it is a constitution we are expounding…, a constitution intended to endure for ages to come, and consequently, to be adapted to the various crises of human affairs.”312 McCulloch v. MD 4 Wheaton, 316, 407, 415 (1819). The idea of “judicial review” and constant reinterpretation of old texts dates at least to the Talmudic period as evidenced by the following apocryphal story from Baba Mezi’a: A legend is told in the Talmud about an argument between a rabbi who believed in a “dead” Bible and a group of rabbis who believed in “living” Bible. The focus of the argument was an arcane law about an oven. To support his interpretation of the law, Rabbi Eliezer implored, “If the halachah [the authoritative meaning of the law] agrees with me, let it be proved by heaven!”—whereupon a heavenly voice cried out to the others: “Why do ye dispute with R[abbi] Eliezer, seeing that…the halachah agrees with him!” (Pretty authoritative evidence of the original intent!) But another rabbi rose up and rebuked God for interfering in this very human dispute. “Thou hast long since written the Torah” and “we pay no attention to a Heavenly Voice.” The message was clear: God’s children were telling their father, 312 D:\533582156.doc Created on 10/9/2006 11:33:00 AM Last printed 3/9/2016 2:16:00 AM Page 134 of 158 Words 47,586 The adaptability of many of the constitution’s most important provisions, coupled with the difficulty of the amending process, has resulted in the text of the constitution taking on different meanings over the years. The constitution today is a very different document than it was in 1793, in 1860, in 1900 and in 1950. Some of the difference is attributable to external events and the amending process. These include, most importantly, the Civil War, the post Civil War Amendments, the massive immigration movements beginning at the mid-nineteenth century and ending in the early part of the twentieth century, then beginning again in the post World War II era, the enfranchisement of women, the resurrection of the moribund Bill of Rights during the twentieth century, the civil rights movement, the reappointment decisions, the abortion and gay rights decisions. However, Justice Scalia and some of his colleagues may feel about it (and try to change it), the framers of our original constitution (even the most farsighted among them) would hardly recognize the way it has been “expounded” over the centuries. Some of the reasons for its adaptability have been largely accidental, a product of the law of unintended consequences. (In that respect, it may be somewhat analogous to evolution.) The privilege against self-incrimination is a perfect example of accidental adaptability. At the time it was ratified, the Fifth Amendment’s privilege against self-incrimination was, according to Langbein and others, rarely invoked by criminal defendants at their own trials. Its words could not have been understood to mean what the defendant’s privilege means today: as precluding the prosecutor from calling the defendant as a sworn witness, since even without the privilege, the defendant was disqualified from testifying as a sworn witness whether he wanted to or not. It is not entirely clear, therefore, what the fifteen words were understood to mean in the context of the eighteenth century “accused speaks” model of the criminal trial. Although its words, literally read, apply only to a criminal defendant not being compelled to be a witness against himself at his own trial, as Donald Dripps has astutely observed: “To suggest that the privilege cannot be claimed except by one at trial is to confine the privilege to the only context in which it was unavailable at the founding.”313 The same fifteen words now have a plain meaning that makes sense in the context of our modern system of criminal justice in which, absent the privilege, the defendant could be called as a witness by either side. It “It is our job, as rabbis, to give meaning to the Torah that you gave us. You gave us a document to interpret, and a methodology for interpreting it. Now leave us to do our job.” God agreed, laughing with joy, “My [children] have defeated me in argument.” 313 Dripps at 1625 D:\533582156.doc Created on 10/9/2006 11:33:00 AM Last printed 3/9/2016 2:16:00 AM Page 135 of 158 Words 47,586 was probably not the plan of the framers to write words that would eventually make sense in a system they did not contemplate - - though a teleological argument could be made that by including the right to counsel and the right to call witnesses in the Sixth Amendment, the framers laid the foundation for a criminal justice system in which the lawyer would speak for the defendant and the defendant, with the advice of his lawyer, would decide whether to testify in his own behalf. But this argument sounds like the kind of “just so” stories told to explain why the leopard has spots or why the snake walks on its belly.314 The reality is that it is largely an accident that the words of the privilege fit comfortably into our current adversarial trial. (This is not an argument for or against the privilege on its merits or demerits; it is rather an argument as to its largely accidental relevance--for better or worse--to the current system.) Not all provisions have fared as well against the contingencies of history. The Third Amendment’s prohibition against the quartering of troops has become an anachronism in the modern age, and efforts to interpret it as metaphor for the privacy of the home have fallen largely on deaf ears.315 The Seventh Amendment’s financial criteria for jury trial in civil cases at common law--$20--has trivialized that right, since what was a considerable sum in 1793 is now less than the filing fee. It’s uncertain how other provisions will fare. For example the Second Amendment may well have been understood by the framers (or at least some of them) to be limited to “well regulated militias,” but its words are open to a broader interpretation bestowing a generalized individual “right to bear arms.” This has given rise to a large and powerful political and ideological movement that can point to the words of that amendment as its justification. This “right to bear arms” movement has in turn given rise to a countermovement favoring gun control that points to other words—such as “well regulated” as its justification. That dispute has yet to be resolved definitively by the Supreme Court. [Expand with more examples of accidental constitution— abortion, gay rights.] 314 Cite Gould But see Griswold v. Connecticut, where the Supreme Court referred to the Third Amendment as “another facet of that privacy”: “Various guarantees create zones of privacy. The right of association contained in the penumbra of the First Amendment is one, as we have seen. The Third Amendment in its prohibition against the quartering of soldiers ‘in any house’ in time of peace without the consent of the owner is another facet of that privacy.” Griswold v. Connecticut, 381 U.S. 479 (1965), at 484. 315 D:\533582156.doc Created on 10/9/2006 11:33:00 AM Last printed 3/9/2016 2:16:00 AM Page 136 of 158 Words 47,586 A Functional Analysis of the Constitutional Right Against Selfincrimination A functional analysis of a constitutional right should be different from a pure policy evaluation of that right. A functional analysis of a constitutional right done properly, is part and parcel of an entirely legitimate mode of constitutional interpretation. It must be rooted in the policies underlying the constitutional rule. It interprets these policies by reference to what the framers (however defined) understood to be the evils addressed by the constitutional provision and not by reference to the values and policies of the current interpreters. A pure policy evaluation may be done without considering the constitution, or by considering it as only one datum among others. In the final chapter of this book, I shall attempt a pure policy analysis of the right against self-incrimination, but in this chapter—which is part of the material on the constitutional interpretation of the relevant words of the 5th amendment--I shall attempt the kind of constitutional functional analysis employed by Justices—ranging from Chief Justice John Marshall to current Justice Antonin Scalia—throughout history. To be sure, there is always the danger that a constitutional functional analysis will serve merely as a cover for a pure policy evaluation, allowing the interpreter to slip his own policy preferences into the mix, but this risk is present with any mode of constitutional analysis, as we have repeatedly seen with regard to textual and historical interpretations. The temptation may be somewhat greater with functional analyses, since policies play a more explicit role in this mode of interpretation than in others, but a rigorous and intellectually honest analysis can minimize this risk. A functional analysis of a constitutional provision must begin—as all modes of interpretation must—with the text and history of the provision. [ELABORATE] In a recent (June 15, 2006) opinion for the Court, Justice Scalia purported to employ a functional analysis in deciding an important constitutional issue.316 He employed this analysis in the context of deciding whether a violation of the “knock and announce” requirement of the Fourth Amendment warranted application of the exclusionary rule. He (along with Justices Thomas, Kennedy, Roberts and Alito) ruled that the exclusionary rule was not applicable in situations where the police, with a search warrant, failed to satisfy the knock and announce requirement. He acknowledged that this “ancient” requirement had “its origins in our English legal heritage” 316 Hudson v. Michigan No. 04 -1360. D:\533582156.doc Created on 10/9/2006 11:33:00 AM Last printed 3/9/2016 2:16:00 AM Page 137 of 158 Words 47,586 and was “also a command of the Fourth Amendment.” But he then listed a number of recent developments that proved, in his view, that the cost of applying the exclusionary rule to such violations outweighed their benefits. Among those developments are the availability of a tort remedy under 42 U.S.C §1983 - - a remedy that he said was experiencing a “slow but steady expansion.” It was, of course, precisely this remedy that the Court, with his approval, denied to Oliverio Martrinez just three years earlier. Another change that he pointed to is “the increasing professionalism of police forces…” He did not cite as evidence of this supposed improvement the behavior of Officer Ben Chavez--whose interrogation of Martinez was characterized by Justice Stevens as the “functional equivalent [of] torturous methods.” Scalia concluded that the Court, “cannot assume that exclusion in this context is necessary deterrence simply because we found that it was necessary deterrence in different contexts and long ago. That would be forcing the public today to pay for the sins and inadequacies of a legal regime that existed almost half a century ago.” Yet he was prepared to conclude that exclusion is a sufficient deterrence in the context of torture or other coercive mechanisms for eliciting compelled self-incriminatory statements. The dynamic approach to constitutional interpretation--things change, so constitutional interpretation must keep up—employed by Scalia in the Hudson case fits more comfortably into the “living constitution” school that Scalia eschews than to the “dead constitution” school of which he is the dean.317 It employs the kind of functional approach 317 Moreover Scalia is simply wrong when he says that the only function of the exclusionary rule is to “deter” police misconduct and that, “the exclusionary rule has never been applied except ‘where its deterrence benefits outweigh its ‘substantial social costs.’” By definition, an exclusionary rule cannot deter; it can merely remove an incentive. Consider an example from the criminal law. Assume that a bank thief is considering a heist that will net him $100,000. Assume further that the only punishment, if he were to be caught, would be to return what he stole. How could that punishment possibly deter a calculating criminal? If the odds on his being caught were 80%, that would still net him $20,000 on each heist over time. In order to deter a calculating actor, the punishment (discounted by the improbability of being caught) must exceed the expected gain. The exclusionary rule provides no punishment that exceeds the expected gain, especially for the calculating cop (as distinguished from the bungling constable) who believes that he could not secure the evidence by complying with the constitution. All the exclusionary rule can ever D:\533582156.doc Created on 10/9/2006 11:33:00 AM Last printed 3/9/2016 2:16:00 AM Page 138 of 158 Words 47,586 and cost-benefit analysis that he often condemns as more appropriate to legislators than to judges.318 This approach looks at the broad policy behind a constitutional rule and then seeks to apply that policy to changing circumstances. Let us then consider how such a functional approach, which is selectively employed by Supreme Court Justices when it supports results they advocate and was not employed in Martinez, might have informed the decision in that case. do is to disincentivize the calculating cop, and it can do that only if cops are caught nearly all the time - - which is not the case. 318 Often but not always. See Kylo [Describe Kylo] See also Craige. D:\533582156.doc Created on 10/9/2006 11:33:00 AM Last printed 3/9/2016 2:16:00 AM Page 139 of 158 Words 47,586 A Matter of Interpretation How then should an honest Justice committed to non-ideological interpretation of constitutional provisions set out to interpret a provision, like the privilege against self-incrimination, when after a thorough analysis, she comes to the following conclusions: 1. The text itself is subject to multiple, reasonable interpretations, some of which appear too narrow to fit the precedents while some appear too broad to fit them. The text alone does not point unerringly to a single result. 2. The precedents are not directly on-point, but could sustain multiple interpretations of the particular issue, none of which precisely fits all of the precedents, and none of which seems more consistent with them than others. 3. Analogies are incomplete, flawed, or cut in multiple directions. No analogy to established law or practice leads inexorably to one interpretation. 4. The original understanding of the clause leads to no singular interpretation since it does not appear as if the framers considered the particular issue precisely. Although there is language among the framers which could support either interpretation, their actual understanding appears inaccessible to history, at least to the extent that it would clearly point in one direction. There does seem to be some historical support for the conclusion that the framers understood the privilege to prohibit judicial torture and judicial oaths, though there is no definitive evidence of their understanding with regard to remedies. 5. The historical research uncovers materials supportive of multiple interpretations and do not precisely address the issue in its current context. Because the current system of criminal justice, and most particularly those parts of it that relate most directly to the privilege against self-incrimination, is so different from the various systems in operation at the founding, it is impossible to extrapolate reliably from the history to the current situation. 6. More recent “understandings” of the right have varied with the political climate of the times and most particularly with the wrongs--such as McCarthyism on the one hand, and the freeing of guilty defendants, on the other hand--that have been experienced. D:\533582156.doc Created on 10/9/2006 11:33:00 AM Last printed 3/9/2016 2:16:00 AM Page 140 of 158 Words 47,586 7. Functional considerations of constitutional policy cut both ways depending on one’s political, ideological, and other preferences. Considering the text at different levels of abstraction may provide different answers, but there is no definitive guide to the proper level of abstraction. Functional considerations also depend on an empirical assessment of how different constitutional policies may impact on such issues as the use of torture in terrorist prevention efforts, the international law and treaty obligations of the United States, and other contentious contemporary concerns. 8. Consideration of other modes of constitutional interpretation that have been employed by courts and advocated by scholars fail to produce a satisfactory singular result that is not merely a cover for ideological and political preferences. It is agreed that the framers did not incorporate in the constitution a single proper mode or modes of interpreting its text. Other constitution makers did precisely that. [DANZIG OTHERS] Nor is there a single definitive and widely-accepted cannon of interpretation that is mandated by precedent. In light of this state of the law, a decision must be made by any interpreter as to which mode or modes he will employ. Such a decision – and the theory on which it is based – should be articulated and subject to accountability and criticism. There are several kinds of theories of interpretation. Some purport to be deontological – that is morally compelled without regard to consequences. Others are consequentialist – based on assumptions about costs and benefits. Some have elements of both – containing assumptions that depend to some degree on empirical assumptions. The more consequentialist or utilitarian a theory of interpretation is, the more it should contain testable propositions that – at least in theory – are subject to validation and invalidation. They should include nul hypotheses. There are several techniques of invalidation that seem to have widespread, if often implicit, acceptance. One of these techniques purports to test any proposed theory of constitutional interpretation against a handful of constitutionally given results. If the particular theory of interpretation would not have led to these results without doing violence to its methodology, it fails the test – or at least, it must acknowledge that it is an imperfect theory of interpretation (even an D:\533582156.doc Created on 10/9/2006 11:33:00 AM Last printed 3/9/2016 2:16:00 AM Page 141 of 158 Words 47,586 imperfect theory can be accepted if it is less imperfect than the others.) The primary testing result, under this technique, is Brown v. Board of Education and its progeny. Under this test, it is taken as a given (although this wasn’t always the case)319 that legally-mandated segregation of public schools, parks, transportation, bathrooms, water fountains and the like could not be deemed constitutional. Nor could legally enforced anti-miscegenation laws. Any accepted theory of constitutional interpretation must pass the test of demonstrating how its mode of constitutional interpretation would have required the striking down of such apartheid laws, despite the indisputable reality that virtually all of the framers of the 14th amendment understood “equal” to mean “separate” and “equal,” and that they did not understand or intend that amendment to require the integration of schools, parks, transportation, bathrooms and water fountains - and certainly not sex and marriage. Some of the most creative (and convoluted) intellectual (and sophistic) efforts have been undertaken by scholars to square this circle.320 The two extreme positions are easy to defend. The first acknowledges that there is no way of reconciling the text of the 14th amendment, as the framers understood its words, with judicially mandated interrogation. It concludes therefore that Brown and its progeny were wrong as a matter of constitutional interpretation, (though perhaps understandable – maybe even justifiable – as a matter of pragmatic realpolitik.).321 Under this view, a constitutional amendment or at least legislation, would be required to compel integration. The fact that neither could possibly have succeeded – especially with the malapportioned legislatures of 1954 – is not the concern of these advocates of this restrictive view of interpretation. Democracy requires the people to make these decisions, unless the text of the Constitution, as understood by its framers, mandates a different result. This is the position Justices Scalia and Thomas should be taking on Brown and its progeny, but I am not aware they have expressly done so.322 The other extreme view is the expanding or living constitution. This view acknowledges that the framers themselves understood equality to mean separation and that they explicitly See Herbert Wechsler, “Toward Neutral Principles of Constitutional Law,” 73 Harvard Law Review 1 (1959), at 26-35. 320 CITE 321 CITE, SEE POSNER 322 Textual FN on Scalia’s and Thomas’ statements about Brown etc. CHECK POSNER ON BROWN 319 D:\533582156.doc Created on 10/9/2006 11:33:00 AM Last printed 3/9/2016 2:16:00 AM Page 142 of 158 Words 47,586 intended segregation – indeed that many of them would never have voted for an amendment that they even suspected would one day strike down anti-miscegenation statutes in which they strongly believed as a matter of morality (misplaced as that may be). But it concludes that history is largely irrelevant to the court’s current interpretive job, unless the text of the constitution absolutely requires the regressive result - - which it rarely does. That job is to keep the constitution relevant to changing times, conditions, and attitudes. So long as the words of the constitution will plausibly bear an interpretation that will keep it relevant, that interpretation should govern, regardless of the original understanding, intent or meaning of the text. [EXPAND] Another technique of invalidation is the one often cited by Justice Scalia (and previously cited by Justice Black). It demands that any proposed mode of interpretation deny justices the power to impose their own personal, political, religious, or ideological views on the decision-making process.323 The Supreme Court’s benighted decision in Bush v. Gore demonstrates—if any demonstration was necessary—that no methodology of judicial review will prevent a determined justice from imposing his views. The purpose of this section is to demonstrate that no one mode of constitutional interpretation, and indeed no combination of such modes, inexorably leads to “the right constitutional result” in many situations of textual and historical ambiguity. It leaves open the challenge of how a Justice or judge should make interpretive decisions in this kind of situation. One thing seems perfectly clear to me, though I know there is some dispute even with regard to it: namely, judges owe an obligation of complete candor, honesty, and openness in telling the public that there is no single right answer and in informing them as to why, in light of the availability of multiple answers, a particular one was chosen. Few Justices and judges are so open about these ambiguities, uncertainties and choices. Most prefer a “Wizard of Oz” approach, pretending that they are oracles whose role it is to discover, rather than invent or construct (or, God forbid, advocate), the “true,” “correct,” and “constitutionally mandated” result. It is important, according to this view, for the general public to believe that there is only one right result. If there are choices available, these choices—according to this view—should be left to democratic, as distinguished from judicial, processes. Nor can the matter of interpretation be decided by reference to the preference for democratic, over elitist judicial, resolutions. Even if one prefers democratic resolutions to judicial ones, still the court must interpret 323 Cite SCALIA & quote him [Supreme Injustice p. 131] D:\533582156.doc Created on 10/9/2006 11:33:00 AM Last printed 3/9/2016 2:16:00 AM Page 143 of 158 Words 47,586 the relevant provision. Sometimes, one interpretation leaves more to the democratic processes than another interpretation. In such situations, it may be arguable that the interpretation that leaves open democratic resolution should be the preferred one. It is not clear, however, that this was the original understanding or intent of the framers, many of whom distrusted democracy and saw the judiciary as an elitist check on the people. Those who advocate democratic resolutions of issues that could or could not be constitutionalized often fail to mention the extremely undemocratic composition of the original electorate (male, landowners, whites, etc.) and the limited role the electorate played in electing the President, senators and other policymakers. They view the dispute through the prism of modern democracy, while purporting to view the understanding through the prism of the framers. In a case like Martinez, neither interpretation is more likely to result in legislative or executive actions. The court must, as an initial matter in a system of checks and balances, interpret the Constitution as honestly and objectively as is possible, openly employing acceptable canons of interpretation. In the Martinez Case, Justice Thomas employed selective textualism, selective use of precedent and questionable analogy to interpret the privilege as not granting a stand alone right to remain silent or to be free from police coercion. He eschewed all references to history or original understanding, despite his frequent resort to such interpretive tools in other cases. Had he honestly looked to history and original understanding, he would have a far more difficult time justifying the narrow interpretation he gave to the privilege, limiting it to an exclusionary rule without regard to the nature of degree of the coercion. In the end, the decision in Martinez reflected pure policy preferences by the justices, both those in the majority and those in the minority. But those preferences went largely unexpressed. Not are the justices—none of whom is experienced in an area of the law in which the privilege plays an important role—particularly well qualified to make policy choices regarding self-incrimination. These choices, as we shall see in the next chapter, should be based on complex factors, many of which are inaccessible to the justices. D:\533582156.doc Created on 10/9/2006 11:33:00 AM Last printed 3/9/2016 2:16:00 AM Page 144 of 158 Words 47,586 Policy Considerations Deconstructing the privilege against self-incrimination The policy arguments for and against the privilege against self-incrimination fall into several distinct categories: constitutional (previously discussed), civil liberties, moral and political. All of these overlap, but also raise somewhat distinctive questions. The privilege must also be deconstructed functionally. First there is the supposed right to remain silent. This raises question of what such a right would entail and whether it could ever be anything more than symbolic. Second, what constraints should be placed on governmental efforts to elicit information that may be selfincriminating but that may also be important in achieving goals other than prosecuting the person being interrogated? Third there is the question of remedies, namely, whether violations of the privilege should be subject to injunction, criminal punishment, civil liability, etc. Or whether the only remedy should be exclusion from a criminal trial. Then there is the issue of immunity and its functional analogues. Is derivative use immunity really coterminous with the privilege? Are there valid analogies between immunity and improper means of interrogation. Underlying all these issues is the broad question of whether the privilege, narrowly or broadly defined, can be justified, whether it has become anachronistic, whether there is any historical basis for its current scope, and whether there might be better ways to achieve the goals of the privilege than by its current formulation and interpretation. I shall explore each of these issues in turn. It has become a staple of academic literature to criticize the privilege against self incrimination, to argue that it serves no contemporary purpose and to call for its abolition or limitation.324 In order to assess the current utility of the privilege, and balance it against its obvious costs, it will be useful to imagine what a criminal justice system would look like without the privilege. It would also be useful to deconstruct the privilege into its several different components and to assess each of them separately. In the end, it may turn out that one or more of the components is more (or less) justified than others. 324 CITE D:\533582156.doc Created on 10/9/2006 11:33:00 AM Last printed 3/9/2016 2:16:00 AM Page 145 of 158 Words 47,586 Let us begin therefore with the defendant’s privilege. That privilege, which is directly mandated by the text of the Fifth Amendment, prohibits the prosecution from calling the defendant as a witness at his own criminal trial. When evaluated in the context of the criminal justice system as it operated at the time of the framing, the defendant’s privilege seems utterly redundant and unnecessary - at least if interpreted literally. Even absent the privilege, prosecutors could not call defendants as a “witness” at their own criminal trials. This is because criminal defendants were disqualified from testifying under oath at their own trials, even if they chose to do so. The defendant simply had the option of speaking in his own defense as an unsworn advocate. Most defendants did not have lawyers and the only person who could speak for them was themselves. If they chose not to speak, they would be presumed guilty, especially since there was no instruction advising the jury not to draw an inference of guilt from the defendant’s silence. Today the right not to be called as a witness by the prosecution is an important right that profoundly impacts current trials. It is accompanied by an instruction requiring the jury to draw no inference from the defendant’s exercise of that right, and also by an instruction placing a heavy burden of proof on the prosecution in order to overcome the defendant’s presumption of innocence. All defendants facing serious charges must be provided lawyers if they cannot afford them. The vast majority of defendants today plead guilty, but among the small percentage who go to trial most exercise both their right to be represented by counsel and their right to remain silent. The vast majority of the small minority of defendants who go to trial are convicted, regardless of whether they chose to testify or exercise their right to remain silent. It may well be true [CHECK THIS] that defendants who exercise their right to remain silent are more likely to be convicted than defendants who exercise their right to testify on their own behalves. But if this is true, it may be explained by the fact that defendants without criminal records are more likely to take the witness stand on their own behalf than defendants with a long criminal records and that defendants with long criminal records are more likely to be guilty than defendants with no records. It may also be more likely that innocent defendants will be more willing to undergo cross examination. It would be virtually impossible to construct a double blind experiment isolating as the only variable the decision of equally situated defendants to testify or not to testify. It is certainly also possible that despite the jury instruction, many jurors do take into account a defendant’s suspicious silence in evaluating guilt or innocence. D:\533582156.doc Created on 10/9/2006 11:33:00 AM Last printed 3/9/2016 2:16:00 AM Page 146 of 158 Words 47,586 It is far from clear therefore whether the defendant’s privilege has any real impact on the accuracy of criminal trial verdicts. It is clear however that it reduces the amount of perjury at criminal trials. A silent defendant is a non perjuring defendant. A testifying defendant, if he is guilty, is likely to be a perjuring defendant. (Even if he is innocent, it is possible that he may perjure himself). I have written elsewhere about the irony that so much judicial and academic concern has been expressed about perjury committed by defendants - and about the dilemma a defense lawyer faces when he suspects or knows that his client intends to testify falsely - - when the reality is that far more perjury is today committed by prosecution witnesses than by defense witnesses (and even more by civil litigants). This is not because defendants or their witnesses are more honest than prosecutorial witnesses (or civil litigants). The opposite is probably true as a general matter. The sole reason is that prosecutors must put on witnesses, including “testalying” police officers, “bought”, “rented” and “flipped” witnesses and other sorted associates of the defendant, (all civil litigants must testify and many commit perjury). Whereas the defense need not put on any witnesses and in many trials limit themselves to cross-examining government witnesses. This would all change if the defendant were required to testify. The dynamics of the trial would change in other ways as well. In some cases the prosecutor would call the defendant as a hostile witness expecting him to commit perjury. In other cases the defense would call the defendant, fearful that failure to do so would create a presumption of guilt. If the defense attorney called the defendant as a witness, he would have to vouch for his truthfulness: he could not call him if he knew that he would be testifying falsely. If the defense attorney did not call the defendant to the stand it would be a red flag signifying that the lawyer knew that his client would commit perjury. This would entirely change the dynamic of the lawyer/client privilege, discouraging (even more than today) the defendant from disclosing his guilt to his attorney. The defendant’s privilege, on balance, does less harm than would its abolition. It “ain’t broke”, and there is no good reason to “fix” it by constitutional amendment. Although it serves quite different purposes than it did at the time of its inclusion in the Bill of Rights, it fits comfortably into our current system of criminal justice. Its abrogation would violate the law of unintended consequences. It would also tamper with an important balancing mechanism in our adversary system. The second component of the privilege that warrants reconsideration is the witness’s privilege. It permits a sworn witness in any legal proceeding to refuse to answer specific questions on the D:\533582156.doc Created on 10/9/2006 11:33:00 AM Last printed 3/9/2016 2:16:00 AM Page 147 of 158 Words 47,586 ground that a truthful answer might tend to incriminate him. The witness’s privilege does not derive directly from the text of the Fifth Amendment. Nor does it flow inexcerbibly from the language or policies of the defendant’s privilege. It must stand or fall on its own merits and on its historical lineage. Unlike the defendant’s privilege, which is absolute and has no mechanism for circumvention, the witness’s privilege is easily overcome by a grant of derivative use immunity, which is supposed to put the witness in precisely the same situation he would have been in had he invoked the privilege. When immunity is granted the government loses no information. Nor does it, at least in theory, diminish its prospects for securing a criminal conviction. It may use any evidence independently discovered and not derived from information obtained from the defendant after he has been granted immunity. In reality neither the government nor the defendant are really in the same position. The government must satisfy a heavy burden of demonstrating independent source, and the defendant has been compelled to reveal embarrassing, damaging, and even bankrupting information. But the policies of the privilege have been served. This still leaves open the question whether the policies of the witness’s privilege are worth their costs, even if the costs are relatively minimal. There is one context in which it can be clearly demonstrated that the cost of the witness’s privilege exceeds its benefits: when the defendant in a criminal case seeks exculpatory evidence from an alleged accomplice who is cooperating with the government. In such cases the government almost never grants immunity, even if it has no intention of prosecuting the witness. It refuses immunity purely on self serving tactical grounds: namely that the witness’s testimony will benefit the defendant. Moreover, it often encourages the witness to invoke his privilege—and because it has extraordinary leverage over cooperating witnesses, its “encouragement” translates into compulsion. Although some courts have said that in extreme cases the Sixth Amendment may require the government to grant “defense immunity” to an exculpatory defense witness, these extreme cases are rarely if ever found by the courts.325 It is surprising that the specific language of the Sixth Amendment - - “in all criminal prosecutions, the accused shall enjoy the right…to have compulsory process for obtaining witnesses in his favor” - - does not always trump the witness’s privilege, which is not mandated by the text of the Fifth Amendment. Since derivative use immunity is supposed to put both 325 ?? D:\533582156.doc Created on 10/9/2006 11:33:00 AM Last printed 3/9/2016 2:16:00 AM Page 148 of 158 Words 47,586 sides in the position they would have been in had the witness’s privilege been exercised, it seems difficult to justify the government’s refusal to grant this immunity in cases where the defendant can make a plausible showing of need for the testimony of an accomplice or any other witness who plans to invoke the witness’s privilege. I have seen this process improperly manipulated by prosecutors who have no intention of ever prosecuting the witness but who simply refuse to grant derivative use immunity in order to block the defendant from securing exculpatory testimony. This is one context in which the current case law on the privilege against self incrimination should be modified in the interests of fairness and of the Sixth Amendment. Some courts have argued that they are not empowered to grand immunity, because that decision must be made by the executive branch, and for a court to preclude prosecution would violate the separation of power. This argument might have some force if transactional immunity were required, but all that is required is derivative use immunity, and such immunity - - at least in theory - places the prosecution in the same position it would have been in without immunity. Now that states, cities, interstate agencies and other units of government can impose derivative use immunity on federal prosecutors, why cannot a federal judge - - in the interest of protecting a defendant’s Sixth Amendment rights - - impose that same kind of immunity on federal prosecutors? The separation of powers argument cannot trump a defendant’s valid claim, any more than a federalism argument can. Accordingly, whenever a criminal defendant can make a plausible showing that his defense would benefit from the testimony of a witness who is claiming the Fifth Amendment, the judge should compel the witness to provide that testimony. This would leave federal prosecutors in precisely the same situation - - at least in theory - - they would be in if the witness were allowed to plead the fifth. Hence the argument falls by its own weight. Put another way, the government which has long argued that derivative use immunity places both parties in the same position should not be heard to argue that it is disadvantaged by a grant of defense immunity. Moreover, the force of this defense immunity argument has been considerably strengthened by the Court’s analysis of the privilege in the Martinez case. If a witness has no right to remain silent - - only a right to exclude compelled self-incriminating statements and their fruits - - and if the point of impact of the right is the criminal trial of the witness who has been compelled or coerced to make a self-incriminating statement, then it would seem to follow that a potentially favorable witness at another person’s criminal trial has no right to refuse to testify. His only right is a future, contingent right D:\533582156.doc Created on 10/9/2006 11:33:00 AM Last printed 3/9/2016 2:16:00 AM Page 149 of 158 Words 47,586 to exclude self-incriminating statements and their fruits from his own criminal trial, if he were ever to be prosecuted. And that right is preserved with derivative use immunity. Even if the witness has some conditional right not to testify, that right should certainly be subordinate to the defendant’s unconditional Sixth Amendment right to obtain witness in his defense. The third component to the privilege and perhaps its most controversial is what I call the “suspects privilege” and what history calls the “confession rule.” This component has the weakest claim to constitutional status under the text and perhaps under the original understanding of the Fifth Amendment. It presupposes physical, psychological or other forms of police coercion being employed against a suspect in a station house, the police car or the street. When the Fifth Amendment was enacted, however, there were no police (at least as we now know them) and no informal interrogation of the kind made famous by such shows as NYPD Blue in which officer Sipowicz browbeats guilty suspects into admitting their horrible crimes. There was of course a long history of torture, but it was judicial torture, authorized and supervised by the courts. Despite the absence of historical records, I am certain that there must have been informal torture as well done outside of the legal system. Indeed one early commentator referred to torture as a matter of “State” rather than as a matter of law. But the contemporary context that has generated the rules governing the suspect’s privilege--most especially the Miranda Rule--was unknown to the framers. It is not surprising therefore that at least one early 20th Century Supreme Court decision said that the entire issue of police coercion and torture does not come under the rubric of the privilege of self incrimination but rather under the rubric of due process. In evaluating the policies underlying the suspect’s privilege, consider the following “thought experiments.” First, imagine the following “reform” to our criminal justice system. All police interrogation of suspects is banned on the ground that such interrogation is inherently coercive and unfair. The fruits of any police interrogation are excluded from evidence. Instead, all suspects (against whom a certain threshold of incriminating evidence has been reached) are required to go before a judge with his lawyer present. If he cannot afford a lawyer one is appointed. The entire proceeding is videotaped. The judge wearing a robe, asks the suspect in a low and respectful voice, to respond to a series of relevant, fairly framed questions, based on the available evidence. For example: “Sir, it has been alleged that on such and such a day in such and such a place you killed so and so. Witnesses such and such claim to have observed the D:\533582156.doc Created on 10/9/2006 11:33:00 AM Last printed 3/9/2016 2:16:00 AM Page 150 of 158 Words 47,586 killing. Are they telling the truth? Did you kill the alleged victim? If so why?” etc. The lawyer is permitted to object to the form of the question, to its relevance etc. He is also permitted to confer with his client after each question is asked. The suspect is required to answer the questions truthfully. If he refuses to answer he can be held in contempt and imprisoned until he answers, and his refusal can be made known to the jury. If he answers falsely, he can be prosecuted for perjury. The resulting video will be shown to the jury if there is a criminal trial. This heuristic is, of course, functionally similar in some respects to the current process of questioning a witness after he has received immunity — with one important difference: the suspect in the thought experiment doesn’t get the benefits of immunity. His answers (and their fruits) can be used against him if he is prosecuted. Putting aside the constitutional privilege against self incrimination, what would be the policy arguments for and against such a process? In what ways would it change our current system - for better or worse? Would it increase or decrease the overall accuracy of the criminal process? Would it increase or decrease the number of false negatives — i.e. guilty people who are currently not convicted? Would it increase or decrease the number of false positives — i.e. not guilty people who are currently convicted? Would it increase or decrease perjury? Would it change the nature of investigations? What other values would it impact? Now, consider the following variation on the above “thought experiment.” Instead of requiring the suspect to answer judicially posed questions, imagine a system in which a so called “truth serum” is perfected to the point where it is 100% accurate and totally harmless and painless.326 What would be the policy considerations in favor of and against the use of such a serum and the admissibility of its fruits? There are, of course, considerable differences between compelling a suspect to answer questions by threatening him with contempt, and forcing him to accept truth serum. In the former situation he retains the ability to exercise some choice, even though it is choice with consequences. Even the proverbial “offer that can’t be 326 This hypothetical was suggested by my colleague Charles Fried. D:\533582156.doc Created on 10/9/2006 11:33:00 AM Last printed 3/9/2016 2:16:00 AM Page 151 of 158 Words 47,586 refused” can be refused, as evidenced by the brave people throughout history who chose torture and death over collaboration and confession. Responding to questions under the influence of truth serum denies all choice. The bravest or most stubborn of suspects cannot refuse to answer, if the serum really works. In this respect, it is more than truth serum, it is compulsion serum. Imagine for heuristic purposes, another serum that does not compel the suspect to answer, but if he chooses to answer denies him the option of lying. That would be truth serum or more precisely an anti-lying serum. If the unfairness and coercion inherent in most police interrogations were truly to be eliminated — along with the threat of physical abuse, torture, bribery and lies — what policy arguments would remain against compelling truthful answers to incriminating questions? Recall that today police are allowed to employ trickery, outright lies, threats of certain kinds, promises and other forms of deception and psychological manipulation, in order to get suspects first to waive their illusory right to counsel — counsel is never actually provided but the interrogation is terminated if counsel is requested — and then to admit their crimes. In practice, the interrogation room is often imbued with an atmosphere of violence and physical coercion. (Remember Sipowicz!) None of this would be permitted in the judicial model (lawfully compelled truthful answers to incriminating questions) or in the scientific model (truth serum). By isolating the right to remain silent from the abuses of police interrogation, these heuristics force us to think about whether there should be a stand-alone right to remain silent, or merely a right not to be physically or psychologically coerced into making selfincriminating statements. The nature of the right also bears on the nature of the remedy or remedies for its violation. They also force us to think about why today the police remain so free to employ such questionable means of inducing waivers and confessions in the stationhouse and on the street, while judges remain so constrained in eliciting waivers and confessions in the courtroom. Some of these differences may grow out of the divergent histories of the three privileges and particularly the emphasis placed on the judicial oath by the originators of the privilege. Recall that at the time of the ratification of the Fifth Amendment, there were no police and hence no stationhouse interrogations. The abuses of that D:\533582156.doc Created on 10/9/2006 11:33:00 AM Last printed 3/9/2016 2:16:00 AM Page 152 of 158 Words 47,586 age were judicial abuses committed by magistrates and justices of the peace. The primary abuses were interrogation under oath and — to use Jefferson’s phrase — “judicial torture.” Today’s abuses are committed largely by police, F.B.I. agents and military interrogators. Tomorrow’s abuses may be committed by scientists and other experts at eliciting preventive intelligence. The challenge is to devise processes that strike appropriate balances between the legitimate needs of government for different types of information and the legitimate policies underlying the privilege (or privileges) against self-incrimination. The Fifth Amendment imposes constraints on what we may do but not on how we may think, and how we think about these issues has some influence on how the courts interpret the Delphic words of the privilege against self-incrimination. An Anti-disestablishmentarian Defense of the 5th Amendment When I was a kid, we were taught that the longest word in the English language was “antidisestablishmentarianism,” but we were never told what it meant. Curiosity led me to look it up and discover that it referred to a group of British political figures who might not have favored—as an original matter—the establishment of the Anglican church as the official (established) religion of England, but who were opposed—as a matter of then current policy—to the disestablishment of that church. It was a subtle, but important D:\533582156.doc Created on 10/9/2006 11:33:00 AM Last printed 3/9/2016 2:16:00 AM Page 153 of 158 Words 47,586 distinction: being against or uncertain about whether an action should have been taken years earlier, but now being against undoing that action years later. Jefferson, who strongly favored disestablishing the Anglican church in Virginia, took a “disestablishmentarian” position with regard to slavery: he wished that the institution of slavery had never been introduced to the American colonies and he opposed its adoption anywhere else or its spread to new areas, but he also opposed its immediate abolition in places where slavery had become part of accepted folkways, fearing that freeing the slaves and allowing them to live side by side with whites would result in a race war, with better-armed and better-trained whites slaughtering the former slaves, but with many white deaths as well.327 Though the issues of religion and slavery are not analogous to the 5 Amendment, I am making an antidisestablishmentarian case for the preservation of the right against self-incrimination in the United States in the 21st century. Reasonable people might well have been opposed to, or uncertain about, the adoption of the right against self-incrimination as an original matter back in 1793. They could plausibly have argued that we would have been better off adopting an approach to criminal justice that did not accord criminal defendants, witnesses or suspects the right to refuse to acknowledge their guilt or to provide the government with testimonial evidence that might form a link in the chain of self-incrimination. But the framers believed differently, and for whatever reasons—historical, moral, religious, empirical—they established a system of criminal justice that required the prosecution to prove the defendant’s guilt without requiring him to acknowledge it.328 This system, as it developed over time, placed a heavy burden of proof---beyond a reasonable doubt—on the prosecution. It also adopted other rules, practices and approaches that became part of what we call the adversarial system of criminal justice and that grew out of, or were related to, the right against selfincrimination. These rules, practices and approaches have not been adopted by nations that have rejected the right against selfincrimination, including nations that have eminently fair systems of criminal justice. Some of these differences flow inexorably from the th He pointed to the ‘deep prejudices entertained by whites’ and the ‘ten thousand recollections by the blacks of injuries sustained,’ as well as ‘new provocations,’ and ‘the real distinctions which Nature has made.’ He feared ‘convulsions which will probably never end but in the extermination of one or the other race.’ Alan M. Dershowitz, American Declares Independence (Wiley 2003), pp 125. 328 Another alternative would have been to establish this Adversarial System for the federal government, but to leave its various states the option of establishing—or experimenting with—other systems [ELABORATE] 327 D:\533582156.doc Created on 10/9/2006 11:33:00 AM Last printed 3/9/2016 2:16:00 AM Page 154 of 158 Words 47,586 right against self-incrimination itself: for example the rule prohibiting the prosecution of judges from commenting on, or the jury from inferring guilt from, the defendant’s decision not to testify. Others of these differences are less directly related to the right against selfincrimination, but are part of the adversarial system to which the right is central. These include the presumption of innocence, the heavy burden of proof on the prosecution and the right to pro-active counsel at a relatively early stage in the criminal process.329 They also include the criminalization and prosecution of false exculpatory statements made by defendants and suspects in this country—a practice alien to most systems that do not have a right against self-incrimination. In other words, in the U.S. a defendant or suspect has the right to remain silent in response to questions that seek incriminating answers, but if he elects to speak, he must speak truthfully at the risk of criminal prosecution. In most continental countries, the defendant or suspect has no right to refuse to answer incriminating questions, but if he answers them falsely, he does not expose himself to criminal prosecution.330 It is this important difference that gives rise to the “cruel trilemma” faced by a defendant or suspect whose truthful answers might tend to incriminate him: if he refuses to answer he an be imprisoned for contempt of court; if he answers truthfully, he can be convicted of the substantive crime; and if he answers falsely, he can be prosecuted and convicted of perjury. The third horn of this trilemma has been eliminated from—or more precisely never added to—most systems that lack the right against self-incrimination. Accordingly, if we were now to eliminate the right against self-incrimination, we would not be adopting the continental system. We could instead be adopting a hybrid system that would be much more onerous to the defendant or suspect than either the current U.S. or continental system. We would also be adopting a system in which perjury (and related) prosecutions would play a much larger role than they currently do in either the American or continental system. As a condition to pleading not guilty—to putting the prosecution to its proof—a defendant would have to risk a perjury prosecution (with an extended statute of limitations). This 329 Criminal lawyers in the U.S. (at least good ones) behave involved in a pro-active way at a far earlier point than their continental counterparts. Indeed what American lawyers routinely do—and are often required to do by ethical rules and guidelines— would constitute an obstruction of justice in some European countries. [expand and cite] 330 [PLEASE DOCUMENT THIS] D:\533582156.doc Created on 10/9/2006 11:33:00 AM Last printed 3/9/2016 2:16:00 AM Page 155 of 158 Words 47,586 would be true not only of guilty defendants, but of any defendant— whether innocent or guilty, or somewhere in between—who might possibly be convicted. It would also apply to defendants who were acquitted, but against whom the prosecution could subsequently bring a perjury prosecution based on new evidence or simply a belief that a second (or third, or fourth) jury might be less favorable to its defendant. This new hybrid system—under which the price of pleading not guilty would be risking a perjury prosecution—would thus undercut the double jeopardy protection of the constitution, would extend statutes of limitations, and would dramatically increase the amount of perjury in the American criminal justice system. Today, criminal defendants rarely commit perjury, for the very simple reason that they rarely testify on their own behalf at their criminal trials. Experienced lawyers believe—and I am among them—that far more perjury is committed by litigants in civil trials and by prosecution witnesses at criminal trials than by criminal defendants. This is so not because criminal defendants are more honest or honorable than civil litigants or prosecution witnesses—the opposite is almost certainly the case. It is so only because criminal defendants, and not civil litigants or prosecution witnesses, have a right not to testify, a right that most of them assert.331 If that right were eliminated perjury by criminal defendants would become pervasive throughout the criminal justice system. This change would dramatically affect the role of the criminal defense lawyer, who is ethically and legally prohibited from knowingly allowing his client to testify falsely. Today an ethical criminal defense lawyer can generally—though not always—convince his client to assert his right against self-incrimination and thus avoid the ethical (and legal) dilemma of suborning perjury by knowingly eliciting false testimony from his client.332 In summary, therefore, disestablishing the right against selfincrimination, after more than two centuries of development and elaboration, could have cataclysmic consequences--some intended or others unintended—on our complex, ongoing and uniquely American system of criminal justice. Whenever one important moving part is taken out of an interactive mechanism, it will affect other parts of that 331 See Dershowitz, Hofstra Law Review FN about ethical dilemma of persuading a client who could testify falsely but convincingly. 332 D:\533582156.doc Created on 10/9/2006 11:33:00 AM Last printed 3/9/2016 2:16:00 AM Page 156 of 158 Words 47,586 mechanism. The question, therefore, is not whether as a matter of first principles the continental system is better than ours. The question is whether it would now be better to eliminate a central right upon which so much of our current system has long been built.333 333 FN on adopting the continental system whole hog—including eliminating perjury prosecutions. D:\533582156.doc Created on 10/9/2006 11:33:00 AM Last printed 3/9/2016 2:16:00 AM Page 157 of 158 Words 47,586 Broader Trends The Supreme Court’s rejection of the fundamental right of all persons to remain silent, or not to be coerced, in favor of a narrow trial right of only criminal defendants to exclude compelled testimony from their criminal trials is part of several larger trends. The first is a general narrowing of apparently human rights to trial rights: the presumption of innocence is now fairly established as merely an evidentiary trial right, rather than a pervasive presumption that cloaks all citizens in their relationship to government. [DESCRIBE BAIL DETENTION AND ITS IMPLICATIONS FOR A BROADER PREVENTIVE DETENTION]. The “cruel and unusual punishment” clause is now limited to post-conviction sanctions. The “due process” clause is seen by some as merely a procedural protection applicable primarily in the context of trials and other legal proceedings, rather than a substantive limitation on government actions. Another, related, trend is to limit rights – even among criminal defendants – to the truly innocent, or at least to the arguably innocent. The broadening of the harmless error rule, the narrowing of habeas corpus, the limitation of reasonable expectation of privacy in the context of the 4th amendment, and the return to Wigmore’s narrow concept of the privilege all reflect this trend. This trend raises even broader issues regarding the increasing marginalization of the Constitution with regard to policy debates, academic discourse and legislative resolutions of important issues of criminal procedure. Over the past half century the Constitution has dominated consideration of these issues. The arguments tended to be about the constitutionality of governmental actions, rather than about their desirability. Because courts played such an active role in striking the balance between security and liberty, other institutions tended to abdicate their responsibility as policy makers. Legislators and executives rarely considered the constitutionality of their actions: “If what we’re doing is unconstitutional, the courts will stop us,” has become a common mantra.334 If an action was found unconstitutional, that ended the debate, because it left no option other than the unrealistic one of constitutional amendment. But if an action was found to be constitutional, that too tended to end the debate. The operative assumption seemed to be that if it was constitutional, it must be desirable. The narrowing of the constitutional rights by the Courts makes it increasingly important for other institutions to broaden the debate over policies. [EXPAND AND EXPLAIN] 334 Goldberg & Dershowitz, Harvard Law School D:\533582156.doc Created on 10/9/2006 11:33:00 AM Last printed 3/9/2016 2:16:00 AM Page 158 of 158 Words 47,586 ……………………….END………………………