106756829 3/9/2016 2:03 AM ARTICLE THE ATTRIBUTES OF CARE AND CARELESSNESS: A PROPOSED NEGLIGENCE JURY INSTRUCTION NELSON P. MILLER* The “care” that is at the heart of tort law’s great and ancient civil duty deserves more study and clearer definition from the lawyers who are its advocates and guardians. Care deserves greater attention in the instruction of law students, in the practical selection and presentation of tort cases, in the judicial and legislative shaping of tort law, and most specifically in the instruction of juries, because it occupies the central place justifying tort law as a tool of ordered liberty. We teach torts, we argue tort cases to juries, and we reform tort law, all without an adequate understanding of what it means for one person to show reasonable care for another. There dwells at the center of tort law this enormously powerful enigma. Other disciplines study care. Physiotherapists find care’s meaning in the enabling and rehabilitative maximizing of their patients’ well being.1 Pharmacists see in care its empathy, support, compassion, protection, trust, cooperation, and education.2 Recognizing care as one of the most important, universal, and yet least understood forms of human expression,3 * 1. 2. 3. Nelson P. Miller is an assistant dean and associate professor at Thomas M. Cooley Law School, who has practiced and written about tort law since his graduation from the University of Michigan Law School in 1987. Mick Skelly, The Definition of Care, PHYSIOTHERAPY FRONTLINE, Oct. 2, 1996, at 2. See Kimberly A. Galt, The Need to Define “Care” in Pharmaceutical Care: An Examination Across Research, Practice and Education, 64 AM. J. PHARMACEUTICAL EDUC. 223, 223-25 (2000). See Madeline Leininger, Foreword to JEAN WATSON, NURSING: THE PHILOSOPHY AND SCIENCE OF CARING, at xi-xii (1979) (“It is time that we study the implicit and explicit meanings associated with the concepts of care and caring so that we can reduce their ambiguities.”); see also Merren Stockdale & Philip J. Warelow, Is the Complexity of 795 106756829 796 3/9/2016 2:03 AM NEW ENGLAND LAW REVIEW [Vol. 39:795 nurses define care as an interpersonal activity satisfying human needs, promoting growth and health, and preserving self-determination, especially for those who are weakened or suffering.4 Even in the face of modern procedural demands and specialization, nurses still see the value of structuring their profession around sensitive, altruistic value systems, which instill hope through supportive relationships based on problem solving and education, and are grounded on the universals of kindness, concern, and love for others.5 Some professions, at least, still understand the value of giving attention and definition to care as the core enlivening value. So why not lawyers? There is precious little written by tort law commentators or even in the broader legal field about the attributes of care. Some have made brief attempts to describe a few characteristics of the reasonably prudent person. Half a century ago, Fleming James listed judgment, knowledge and experience, perception of risk, skill, and sanity as the reasonable man’s common attributes.6 The Restatement (Second) of Torts includes “qualities of attention, knowledge, intelligence, and judgment”7 among care’s attributes. More recently, treatise writer Dan B. Dobbs noted the reasonably prudent person’s intelligence, perception, memory, and knowledge.8 And commentator Heidi Li Feldman sees in the standard of care the virtues of reasonableness, prudence, and carefulness.9 But right where much of our tort law study might have been profitably focused on these and the many other attributes of care, a clear, definite study of care itself seems oddly lacking in our legal writings. As a result, juries (for instance) have little guidance on what constitutes care,10 despite that “most pattern jury instructions . . . [use] both 4. 5. 6. 7. 8. 9. 10. Care a Paradox?, 31 J. ADVANCED NURSING 1258, 1258-60, 1263 (2000) (explaining that care is essential to human survival and a worthwhile ideal for nursing but not adequately defined by the profession). Watson’s 1979 exposition of ten “carative factors” is today recognized as the dominant model in nursing. Galt, supra note 2, at 223, 225. JEAN WATSON, NURSING: THE PHILOSOPHY AND SCIENCE OF CARING 8-9 (1979). Id. at 8-10. Fleming James, Jr., The Qualities of the Reasonable Man in Negligence Cases, 16 MO. L. REV. 1 passim (1951). RESTATEMENT (SECOND) OF TORTS § 283 cmt. b (1965). DAN B. DOBBS, THE LAW OF TORTS § 118 (2000). Heidi Li Feldman, Prudence, Benevolence, and Negligence: Virtue Ethics and Tort Law, 74 CHI.-KENT L. REV. 1431 (2000), cited in Patrick J. Kelley & Laurel A. Wendt, What Judges Tell Juries About Negligence: A Review of Pattern Jury Instructions, 77 CHI.-KENT L. REV. 587, 592 (2002). See Kelley & Wendt, supra note 9, at 587 (arguing that jury instructions on the negligence standard are “murky, at best”). “The meaning of the basic ordinary 106756829 2005] 3/9/2016 2:03 AM THE ATTRIBUTES OF CARE AND CARELESSNESS 797 the concept[s] of ordinary care and . . . of a reasonably careful person.”11 Commentators have recognized that “[e]ach of the recurring critically important phrases in these pattern [jury] instructions, ordinary care and the conduct of a reasonably prudent or a reasonably careful person, seem to refer to a preexisting standard.”12 But even those linguists and social scientists who have proposed revising pattern jury instructions on negligence have not done so to further define care. Rather they have attempted only to simplify the usual negligence language,13 leaving commentators searching for a descriptive theory.14 Worse, we label the reasonably prudent person “odious” and “unsalvageable,”15 and fashionably denigrate terms like “justice” and “care” as if they were little more than empty vessels. We continue to offer the standard of reasonable care to our clients and juries without understanding it ourselves, and perhaps not even believing in it. One would think that a study of care would be an integral part of the education of tort law students, as well as the working knowledge of practicing civil litigators and judges. When we see care exercised in the hands of a fine surgeon treating an accident victim, a skilled pilot landing in a storm, a well-versed engineer designing a foundation, or an attendant nursing an elderly patient back to health, we ought to want to know more about this care that is the foundation of tort law. At the very least, one would think that we would have a better understanding of care’s antithesis, carelessness, given that our tort law jurisprudence rests primarily, if not wholly, on that very premise of fault in the wrongdoer. We should know more of what carelessness looks like, if not in its everyday expression (about which our cases and casebooks unintentionally show us much) but in its common characteristics. What is the face of carelessness so as to recognize, judge, and condemn it? To know the attributes of carelessness must indeed have tremendous value to the student and practitioner of tort 11. 12. 13. 14. 15. reasonable person standard is not immediately evident.” Id. at 590. Id. at 595. Id. at 620 (emphasis omitted). Id. at 613-14 (citing Robert P. Charrow & Veda R. Charrow, Making Legal Language Understandable: A Psycholinguistic Study of Jury Instructions, 79 COLUM. L. REV. 1306 (1979); AMIRAM ELWORK ET AL., MAKING JURY INSTRUCTIONS UNDERSTANDABLE (1982); Amiram Elwork et al., Toward Understandable Jury Instructions, in IN THE JURY BOX: CONTROVERSIES IN THE COURTROOM 161, 176 (Lawrence S. Wrightsman et al. eds., 1987)). See Kelley & Wendt, supra note 9, at 617-18. See, e.g., Osborne M. Reynolds, Jr., The Reasonable Man of Negligence Law: A Health Report on the “Odious Creature,” 23 OKLA. L. REV. 410 (1970); Anita Bernstein, Treating Sexual Harassment with Respect, 111 HARV. L. REV. 445, 453 (1997) (arguing that the reasonable care standard “cannot be salvaged”). 106756829 798 3/9/2016 2:03 AM NEW ENGLAND LAW REVIEW [Vol. 39:795 law, for such is the lifeblood of competent legal service in the broad tort law field, including wrongful death, personal injury, property damage, and even fraud and defamation. If we knew the common and essential attributes of carelessness, we might better counsel our clients, advocate their cases, teach our law students, and decide our tort cases. We ought to have made a better study of that care which lends order to our private relationships and, moreover, that carelessness which undergirds our tort law. Odd indeed is the absence of an understanding and veneration of care, because care is tort law’s essential organizing principle. Do not think that this author is ignorant of the historical and philosophical debates and trends that have led to this ignorance and even denigration of care. Surely for a time, the Social Darwinism of Wigmore and Holmes and, more recently, the positivism of Posner have hidden from us the intrinsic goodness of care—hidden from us even the indispensable role care plays in our tort law as it contributes to the ordered liberty of our society.16 It is admittedly fashionable to label universals like care, justice, and equity as “spurious”17 rather than to harness their power by exploring, understanding, and being guided by their attributes. But at least some continue to understand the great philosophies and religions on the nature, role, and inescapable value of care.18 It is certainly our obligation and opportunity in the law to do likewise. Care needs no savior, because it takes the measure of us and our age more than we take its measure. The extent to which our tort laws recognize, appreciate, invoke, and promote care will be the measure of this generation, as it has been the measure of any generation. This writing is not in other words a polemic or plea. It only seeks for its writer and readers to do that which ought to be done in all societies and circumstances: to turn our attention to the sweet dictates and liberties of care, that doing so might restore and benefit every one of us. Tort law, however, deals with the practical. It comes into play only 16. 17. 18. See, e.g., George P. Fletcher, Fairness and Utility in Tort Theory, 85 HARV. L. REV. 537, 539-40 (1972) (“ubiquitously held” “beliefs about tort history . . . are all false or at best superficial”); 10 BERNARD S. JACKSON, STUDIES IN JUDAISM IN LATE ANTIQUITY: ESSAYS IN JEWISH AND COMPARATIVE LEGAL HISTORY 8 (Jacob Neusner ed., 1975) (“A combination of nineteenth century evolutionism and twentieth century pragmatism produces an attitude which views the ancient texts as manifestations of primitive or archaic minds, and therefore of no contemporary interest.”). See, e.g., John Mikhail, Law, Science, and Morality: A Review of Richard Posner’s The Problematics of Moral and Legal Theory, 54 STAN. L. REV. 1057, 1086-87 (2002). See MORTIMER D. SCHWARTZ ET AL., PROBLEMS IN LEGAL ETHICS 17-19 (5th ed. 2001) (citing H.T.D. ROST, THE GOLDEN RULE: A UNIVERSAL ETHIC 28, 39, 43, 49, 103, 114 (1986); BENJAMIN CAMFIELD, THE COMPREHENSIVE RULE OF RIGHTEOUSNESS: DO AS YOU WOULD BE DONE BY 54-55 (1679)). 106756829 2005] 3/9/2016 2:03 AM THE ATTRIBUTES OF CARE AND CARELESSNESS 799 when a real injury has occurred under real circumstances. Perhaps the practical nature of tort law is why there may be only a relatively small number of scholarly journals devoted to its discussion.19 Tort law’s practical, discrete, and concrete nature makes it a difficult subject to cover in broad strokes and terms, for its breadth must cover the sum total of human social activity. In every instance in which a person takes an action having some consequence for another—whether it be the design of a product, the manufacture of a drug, or the swing of a bat in a crowded baseball stadium—tort law’s duty of care lies latent, waiting only for an injury. Think for a moment of the ancient negligence liability provisions having to do with the construction and navigation of a boat,20 the construction and maintenance of a home or wall,21 the ownership and maintenance of open lands,22 and the ownership and control of an ox.23 Those categories probably included the primary social and economic activities of that ancient day, out of which personal injury could be expected to arise. Yet the universal historical imperative that we voluntarily act toward one another in care—with peace, proportion, self-control, kindness, patience, and understanding, among other things—required then, and still requires today, that there be a remedy for a careless wrong. Today the activities would be somewhat different. Driving and industrial employment come readily to mind as the modern activities most likely to cause harm. But the attributes of care and carelessness have probably remained much the same, even as there has been great change in 19. 20. 21. 22. 23. Examples include the American Bar Association’s Tort Trial and Insurance Practice Section’s Tort & Insurance Law Journal and the Australian Torts Law Journal. See, e.g., REUVEN YARON, THE LAWS OF ESHNUNNA 47 (2d rev. ed. 1988) (“If a boatman was negligent and caused the boat to sink—whatever he caused to sink, he shall pay in full.” (quoting Laws of Eshnunna, 18th century B.C.)). See, e.g., Reuven Yaron, The Goring Ox in Near Eastern Laws, in JEWISH LAW IN ANCIENT AND MODERN ISRAEL: SELECTED ESSAYS 50, 56 (Haim H. Cohn ed., 1971) (“If a wall was threatening to fall and the ward [authorities] have had [it] made known to the owner of the wall, but he did not strengthen his wall and the wall fell down and caused a son of a man to die, [it is a case concerning] life: decree of the king.” (quoting Laws of Eshnunna, 18th century B.C.)). See, e.g., J. Weingreen, Concepts in Ancient Biblical Civil and Criminal Law, 14 IRISH JURIST 113, 133 (1989) (“When a man leaves a pit (a cistern or a well) uncovered, or when he digs one but does not cover it, should an ox fall into it (and die), then the owner of the pit (well, or cistern) shall make good the loss.” (quoting Exodus 21:33-34)). See, e.g., J.J. Finkelstein, The Ox that Gored, in 71 TRANSACTIONS OF THE AMERICAN PHILOSOPHICAL SOCIETY pt. 2, at 20 (1981) (“[I]f the ox was previously reputed to have had the propensity to gore, and its owner had not kept it under control, he shall make good ox for ox, but will keep the dead one for himself.” (quoting Exodus 21:36)). 106756829 800 3/9/2016 2:03 AM NEW ENGLAND LAW REVIEW [Vol. 39:795 humankind’s social activities. The attributes of care and carelessness not only inform but also can to some degree organize our understanding of tort law. Those attributes are in essence what any tort law text teaches, judge judges, and practitioner practices, although only implicitly. Tort law tends to be conceived of as a disjointed body of rules without organizing principles, when to the contrary it has within care a clear organizing principle inadequately expressed and studied. It is obvious that manufacturing, publishing, professional service, and other forms of human social conduct, taken in part or as enterprises, generate products liability, defamation, professional malpractice, vicarious liability, and other tort law rules and doctrines. But the fact that they do so because of the latent dictates of care is little understood or acknowledged. This Article begins then with two summary tables. The first table lists side-by-side the attributes of care and carelessness, first in their commonality, then in their distinction. The second table groups various tort law doctrines under the attributes of care and carelessness which those doctrines most reflect. Part I of this Article elaborates upon and individually explores those attributes of care. Part II explores the attributes of carelessness, as they are reflected in those tort law doctrines. The reader is encouraged to note at the outset that care and carelessness share many of the same attributes. Our interest should lie not merely in where care and carelessness depart from one another. We should just as well recognize the common attributes of care and fault, if only to further highlight their distinctions. Part III then shows how the attributes of care and carelessness can be used in a practical manner, in a proposed negligence jury instruction. 106756829 2005] 3/9/2016 2:03 AM THE ATTRIBUTES OF CARE AND CARELESSNESS 801 Table I ATTRIBUTES OF CARE Willing or Volition Perception or Intelligence Effectiveness or Efficacy Liberty Impartiality Humility or Condescension Mercy or Leniency Judgment or Justice Truth or Authenticity Unselfishness Discipline or Self-Control Reason or Rationality Virtue Compassion Proportionality ATTRIBUTES OF CARELESSNESS SHARED Willing or Volition Perception or Intelligence Effectiveness or Efficacy Liberty OPPOSING Partiality or Prejudice Pride Vengeance Arbitrariness or Injustice Falsity or Disingenuousness Selfishness Indulgence or Intemperance Irrationality Opposition to Good Cruelty Disproportionality 106756829 802 3/9/2016 2:03 AM NEW ENGLAND LAW REVIEW [Vol. 39:795 Table II SHARED ATTRIBUTES OF CARE AND CARELESSNESS Willing or Volition Perception or Intelligence Effectiveness or Efficacy Liberty ASSOCIATED TORT LAW DOCTRINES Intent as an element of assault, battery, and other torts Mistake negating intent as an element Modified standard of care for children Jury instructions to anticipate children’s conduct Modified standard of care for physical disability Act of God/unforeseen catastrophic events rules Epilepsy, faints, and other physical reaction cases Professional negligence/malpractice standard of care Learned intermediary doctrine Sophisticated user rule Incidental, one-time product seller rule Special knowledge or expertise rules Transferred intent doctrine Deliberation required of fiduciary Impossibility cases Unavoidably unsafe products doctrine State of the art defense Impact and physical manifestation rules “But for” and substantial factor causation tests Apprehension as element of assault and imprisonment Remedial rather than injunctive or anticipatory relief Statutes of limitation Statutes of repose Notice of claim statutes Notice of intent statutes Open and obvious hazard doctrine Assumption of the risk defense Unavoidably unsafe products doctrine Unavoidable accident jury instructions Proximate cause rules No extraordinary precaution jury instructions Self-defense and defense of others Privileges to enter the land of another 106756829 2005] 3/9/2016 2:03 AM THE ATTRIBUTES OF CARE AND CARELESSNESS ATTRIBUTES OF CARE Humility or Condescension Mercy or Leniency Judgment or Justice Truth or Authenticity Compassion Impartiality Unselfishness or Self-Control Proportionality 803 ASSOCIATED TORT LAW DOCTRINES Higher duty of care to the young, old, and disabled Res ipsa loquitor for the comatose or unknowing Liability to unborn children rules Eggshell skull rule Incremental harm defamation doctrine Significant minority defamation rule Private, voluntary waiver of claims Private, voluntary settlement and release of claims Duty or immunity waiver based on available insurance Private and public necessity as defense Judgment and satisfaction of judgment Single, full, and partial satisfaction rules Contribution and indemnity rules Sudden emergency and rescue doctrines Permissive use of force in discipline and confinement Objective standards of care Informed consent malpractice rules Make whole remedy doctrine All provable damages rules Loss of consortium recovery Collateral source rule Vicarious liability rules Contributory and comparative negligence doctrines Common law indemnity Others-will-act-properly jury instructions Immunity based on relationship rather than person Fiduciary duties against self-interest and selfseeking Manifestation of consent Allocation of fault and apportionment of damages rules 106756829 3/9/2016 2:03 AM 804 NEW ENGLAND LAW REVIEW ATTRIBUTES OF CARELESSNESS Cruelty Injustice Falsehood Partiality Pride or Prejudice Selfishness Opposition to Good Indulgence or Intemperance Unreasonableness or Irrationality Disproportion [Vol. 39:795 ASSOCIATED TORT LAW DOCTRINES Waivers of family and governmental immunity Continuing tort and constitutional tort doctrines Malice as standard for punitive damages Actual malice constitutional standard for defamation Risk/utility products liability tests Strict liability for abnormally dangerous activities Fraudulent and negligent misrepresentation claims Breach of warranty liability False imprisonment and conversion claims Defamation and false light claims Fraudulent misrepresentation claims Conversion claims Expert testimony and professional standards rules Objective standards of care Assault, trespass, and other intentional torts Reckless, willful, and wanton misconduct distinctions Punitive damages Intoxication and sexual harassment torts Profits as a measure of punitive damages Negligence, products, and premises liability standards Custom, regulations, and standards evidence Professional malpractice and fiduciary duty standards Risk/utility products liability balancing tests I. THE ATTRIBUTES OF CARE Willing or Volition. The care which tort law requires of us must first of all be voluntary or volitional. It would be nonsense to require something of someone which is not within that person’s capability to choose or not choose. The law does not operate upon automatons. It is not the wind that the law governs; it is human intentions, and tort law is certainly no exception. Thus, surely willing or volition (“voluntariness” might be an unattractive legal word) is a cardinal attribute of tort law’s care. “There cannot be an act without volition,” is the manner in which the paradigmatic 106756829 2005] 3/9/2016 2:03 AM THE ATTRIBUTES OF CARE AND CARELESSNESS 805 Restatement (Second) of Torts puts it.24 One cannot be considered “careful” without considering the quality of the choices one has made. To consider as “careful” one who has no capacity to choose and so no will or volition, simply because they happened to cause no injury, would be nonsense. Care implies choosing. Choice, indeed, is the great tool of the litigator—whether for plaintiff or defendant, depending on the facts. Choice often defines the case like no other attribute. When defense counsel can legitimately ask, “But what could my client have done?” and there is no answer suitable to demonstrate the defendant’s lack of care, then there has been adequate care, and there is no liability. When, by contrast, the plaintiff’s counsel can demonstrate the reasonably careful, known alternative not chosen by the defendant that would have prevented or substantially reduced the likelihood of the plaintiff’s injury, then once again care has been demonstrated even by its absence on the part of the defendant. If volition is an attribute of care, then it should be expressed in tort law rules and doctrines, and indeed it is. One thinks first of those cases where volition might well be absent, as for instance, in the case of the instinctive and unconsidered actions of a very young child. There one correctly finds the absence of any duty of care—a very young child is incapable of the lack of care or negligence.25 And so it should be for one who is too young to form the will and exercise the volition to regard the well-being of others. Although we are perhaps less willing to admit that the same incapacity may return at the end of life, tort law reluctantly admits a similar non-liability rule in some cases where the very aged and infirm may also lack the capacity to act voluntarily, at least with respect to their own safety.26 We find similar rules for non-liability in the absence of volition, where injury has resulted from a lack of ordinary physical capacity such as 24. 25. 26. RESTATEMENT (SECOND) OF TORTS § 2 cmt. a (1965). See, e.g., Mastland, Inc. v. Evans Furniture, Inc., 498 N.W.2d 682 (Iowa 1993) (holding that a two-year-old child who started a house fire while playing with a cigarette lighter was not capable of negligence); Price v. Kitsap Transit, 886 P.2d 556 (Wash. 1994) (holding that a four-year-old child who engaged a bus emergency brake was not capable of fault and was not an “entity” to which fault could be apportioned). See, e.g., Kitsap County Transp. Co. v. Harvey, 15 F.2d 166 (9th Cir. 1926) (holding that a carrier failed to exercise the requisite duty of care owed to an elderly woman in maintaining seats in a steamship cabin ten inches above the aisle); LaCava v. New Orleans, 159 So. 2d 362 (La. Ct. App. 1964) (holding that a seventy-year-old man who tripped on a sidewalk was contributorily negligent); Johnson v. St. Paul City Ry. Co., 69 N.W. 900 (Minn. 1897) (holding that the decision not to submit to the jury the issue of whether or not a seventy-five-year-old woman was contributorily negligent was not in error); Tobia v. Cooper Hosp. Univ. Med. Ctr., 643 A.2d 1 (N.J. 1994) (holding that a healthcare provider could not raise the issue of contributory negligence in a case involving an elderly patient’s self-inflicted injury). 106756829 806 3/9/2016 2:03 AM NEW ENGLAND LAW REVIEW [Vol. 39:795 blindness,27 deafness,28 and paralysis.29 The “act of God” cases, excusing liability for unforeseen harm relating to catastrophic natural events,30 may well fall under the same attribute of care that the party’s conduct must above all be volitional. Even involuntary intoxication,31 epileptic seizures,32 and other similarly unwilling physical reactions33 are excused in the absence of volition, at least where anticipatory precautions need not have been taken. The insanity cases34 are problematic in tort law precisely because care ordinarily requires such volition. We do not require care from one who cannot exercise it, because the care we expect of one another has volition as its first attribute. Perception or Intelligence. Care certainly implies intelligence sufficient to perceive the needs of and risks to one another attendant on our various social activities. Care implies not only the will or volition 27. 28. 29. 30. 31. 32. 33. Roberts v. State, 396 So. 2d 566 (La. Ct. App. 1981) (holding that a blind man, who was familiar with his surroundings, was not negligent in going to the restroom without his cane). Otterbeck v. Lamb, 456 P.2d 855 (Nev. 1969) (holding that a bus driver owed a duty of care to a deaf passenger). Hodges v. Jewel Cos., 390 N.E.2d 930 (Ill. App. Ct. 1979) (holding that entranceways to public buildings must be considered from the standpoint of the handicapped as well as from the standpoint of the able-bodied). See RESTATEMENT (THIRD) OF TORTS: LIAB. FOR PHYSICAL HARM § 3 cmt. l (Tentative Draft No. 1, 2001) (act of God is an affirmative defense); see, e.g., Ark. Valley Elec. Coop. Corp. v. Davis, 800 S.W.2d 420, 423 (Ark. 1990) (“A person is not liable to another whose damages were caused solely by an act of God.”). See RESTATEMENT (THIRD) OF TORTS: LIAB. FOR PHYSICAL HARM § 12 cmt. c. (Tentative Draft No. 1, 2001) (noting involuntary intoxication may excuse tortious conduct); cf. Janelsins v. Button, 648 A.2d 1039 (Md. Ct. Spec. App. 1994) (holding voluntary intoxication no excuse to civil battery). See Moore v. Capital Transit Co., 226 F.2d 57 (D.C. Cir. 1955), cert. denied, 350 U.S. 966 (1956); Storjohn v. Fay, 519 N.W.2d 521 (Neb. 1994). See, e.g., House v. Kellerman, 519 S.W.2d 380, 383 (Ky. Ct. App. 1974) (reflex action of one suddenly awakened); Ballew v. Aiello, 422 S.W.2d 396, 399 (Mo. Ct. App. 1967) (partially unconscious, non-volitional act of grabbing steering wheel); see also RESTATEMENT (FIRST) OF TORTS § 14 cmt. a (1934): [A] muscular movement which is purely reflexive or the convulsive movements of an epileptic, are not acts in the sense in which that word is used in the Restatement. So too, movements of the body during sleep or while the will is otherwise in abeyance are not acts. An external manifestation of the will is necessary to constitute an act and an act is necessary to make one liable . . . . 34. Id. See, e.g., McGuire v. Almy, 8 N.E.2d 760 (Mass. 1937) (holding that an insane person is liable for intentional harm). 106756829 2005] 3/9/2016 2:03 AM THE ATTRIBUTES OF CARE AND CARELESSNESS 807 connected with choosing, but also the knowledge or perception of what is chosen. One can choose to act in a certain fashion without yet knowing the nature or extent of the risks so faced in choosing. People often do undertake to act while unaware of the risks they are creating. Intelligence and perception are necessary attributes of care, for the responsibility of care cannot arise without first some knowledge of the circumstances. It is in this respect inescapable (if anyone could honestly wish to escape it) that care has an aspect of virtue. It is not mere intelligence sufficient to perceive the risks which care requires of us. It is moreover a desire to conform one’s conduct so as to attempt to minimize or eliminate those risks—that which we ought to frankly call virtue. After one understands the risks, the conscience ought then to encourage one in the pursuit of risk-reducing conduct. Care requires that the rightness or fitness of so conforming one’s conduct be understood in the conscience. It is a particular kind of intelligence which care requires of us: that of the appreciation of the risk of our conduct toward ourselves and one another. Intelligence in the law of torts exists not for the purpose of self-expression but to promote the wellbeing of ourselves and one another. The intelligence of care does not author a brilliant treatise, craft a profound poem, or interpret an esoteric melody, purely for the display of that intelligence. Rather it regards the pursuit of orderly well-being as the inherent good and so acts accordingly. The result may indeed be a brilliant treatise, profound poem, or interpreted melody, but its purpose would be to promote well-being, not to express intelligence itself at the hazard of its author or of another. Nietzsche was intelligent yet died absurdly insane and likely caused others much grief in expressing such a distorted and hazardous brilliance.35 Jonas Salk employed intelligence to quite different ends, as indeed did the artist Michelangelo and the author Solzhenitsyn.36 But all brilliance aside, an ordinary understanding or perception is quite clearly a cardinal aspect of care, for without at least some rudimentary knowledge of the risks we face and create, we would certainly all perish. And so is care’s intelligence found to be a doctrinal consideration and rule-maker throughout tort law. Over and over again in tort law, the duty imposed depends on the knowledge and sophistication expected of the actors. In healing others, hospital interns are expected to exercise a physician’s skill, knowledge, and training—not those of a just-graduated 35. 36. See RUDIGER SAFRANSKI, NIETZSCHE: A PHILOSOPHICAL BIOGRAPHY 370-71 (Shelley Frisch trans., 2002) (describing Nietzsche’s ultimate demise). See RICHARD CARTER, BREAKTHROUGH: THE SAGA OF JONAS SALK 1-7 (1966) (describing Salk’s “saintly” brilliance); GEORGE BULL, MICHELANGELO: A BIOGRAPHY 3-4 (1995) (noting Michelangelo’s successes); see also generally D.M. THOMAS, ALEXANDER SOLZHENITSYN: A CENTURY IN HIS LIFE (1998). 106756829 808 3/9/2016 2:03 AM NEW ENGLAND LAW REVIEW [Vol. 39:795 medical student.37 In transporting others, pilots are required to exercise the skill, knowledge, and training of reasonably prudent pilots, not of just anyone who may happen to fly an airplane.38 In providing products for others, manufacturers and sellers are held to a manufacturer’s standard, so long as they are in the relevant business.39 It is common tort law doctrine that the knowledge of learned intermediaries and sophisticated users can cut off a manufacturer’s liability for a defective product.40 Tort law even excuses the ignorance of those who only incidentally sell a defective product.41 Section 289(a) of the Restatement (Second) of Torts generalizes our consideration of the actor’s knowledge with the admonition that we must exercise “such attention, perception of the circumstances, memory, knowledge of other pertinent matters, intelligence, and judgment as a reasonable man would have . . . .”42 Indeed Section 289(b) of the Restatement (Second) of Torts states that where the reasonable person who possesses them would exercise knowledge or skills beyond the knowledge or skills held by the rest of us, then care requires that the person do so.43 In making such determinations, jurors are to consider the foreseeability of the untoward consequences of human conduct.44 Similarly, process and deliberation are key aspects of the 37. 38. 39. 40. 41. 42. 43. 44. Centman v. Cobb, 581 N.E.2d 1286, 1288 (Ind. Ct. App. 1991) (“[A]n intern is a practitioner of medicine required to exercise the same standard of skill as a physician with an unlimited license to practice medicine.”). See, e.g., Heath v. Swift Wings, Inc., 252 S.E.2d 526, 529 (N.C. Ct. App. 1979) (rejecting a subjective standard in favor of an objective standard of care in cases involving professionals requiring specialized skills). See RESTATEMENT (SECOND) OF TORTS § 402A (1965); RESTATEMENT (THIRD) OF TORTS: PRODUCTS LIAB. § 1 cmt. c, n.1 (1998) (“American courts universally hold that only sellers who are in the business of selling products are strictly liable.”). See, e.g., Smith v. Walter C. Best, Inc., 927 F.2d 736, 741-42 (3d Cir. 1990) (holding that the commercial sale of a product to a company knowledgeable of the risks cuts off company employee’s right to sue for failure to warn); Lacy v. G.D. Searle & Co., 567 A.2d 398 (Del. 1989) (holding that a physician had acted as learned intermediary with respect to patient warnings regarding IUD). See, e.g., Tauber-Arons Auctioneer Co. v. Superior Court, 161 Cal. Rptr. 789, 794-95 (Cal. Ct. App. 1980) (holding that an auctioneer was not strictly liable for one-time sale of defective used product); see also RESTATEMENT (THIRD) OF TORTS: PRODUCTS LIAB. § 8 (1998) (limiting liability of commercial seller of used product). RESTATEMENT (SECOND) OF TORTS § 289(a) (1965). Id. § 289(b) (“[S]uch superior attention, perception, memory, knowledge, intelligence, and judgment as the actor himself has.”); see also RESTATEMENT (THIRD) OF TORTS: LIAB. FOR PHYSICAL HARM § 12 (Tentative Draft No. 1, 2001) (“If an actor has skills or knowledge that exceed those possessed by most others, these skills or knowledge are circumstances to be taken into account . . . .”). See RESTATEMENT (SECOND) OF TORTS § 388 (1965) (“knows or has reason to know 106756829 2005] 3/9/2016 2:03 AM THE ATTRIBUTES OF CARE AND CARELESSNESS 809 fiduciary’s duty of care to arrive at a properly considered and intelligent decision.45 In so many respects knowledge and perception are key considerations in fashioning tort law rules, because they are such necessary corollaries to the care which underpins tort law. Effectiveness or Efficacy. To care though, knowledge and intention are not enough. The road to hell (after all) is paved with such intention. To be properly careful, one must intend that which can be accomplished—that is, to choose that which one has the capacity to perform so as to bring about the intended result. Care most certainly implies effectiveness or efficacy as a necessary attribute or characteristic. Care without effectiveness would be sentimentality or indeed (still worse) hypocrisy. It is perhaps the equivalent of the misunderstood distinction between sympathy and compassion—the former wholly ineffective but the latter entirely useful in bringing about a remedy. To put it another way, care must produce action of the sort that will make a difference, or it is not care. It is somewhat like the parent who repeatedly tells the child that the parent loves the child—but never does more to feed and clothe it. Such inaction would not be love, for love is something expressed not by words (in such a situation of need) but by action. Nor is it care to have the will, knowledge, and intention to avoid harm, but not to choose means to do so. Effectiveness or efficacy as an aspect of care is indeed found in tort laws and doctrines, wherever the odd and various social activities of humans would require it. Foremost, tort law does not require the impossible from us.46 Efficacy, capacity, and capability are the most basic measures of tort law. Rudimentarily, the one whose conduct is under consideration is judged by the physical characteristics (as, for instance, short stature47) which that one—and that one only—possesses. To judge a person based on other than those physical capacities the person possesses—to require that they run faster or jump higher so as to avoid harm—would deny care any true efficacy. Similarly, tort doctrine excuses injury due to unavoidably 45. 46. 47. that the chattel is . . . dangerous”). See, e.g., Smith v. Van Gorkom, 488 A.2d 858, 872 (Del. 1985) (holding that a corporate director has a duty, arising from the fiduciary capacity, to inform himself prior to making business decisions). See, e.g., Parlato v. Equitable Life Assurance Soc’y, 749 N.Y.S.2d 216, 223 (N.Y. App. Div. 2002) leave denied, 787 N.E.2d 1164 (N.Y. 2003) (quoting Matter of Sloat v. Board of Examiners, 9 N.E.2d 12, 15 (N.Y. 1937)) (“The law, of course, ‘does not require the impossible.’”). Mahan v. State, 191 A. 575 (Md. 1937) (noting a defendant’s peculiar inability to see over vehicle’s hood due to short stature); see also cases on blindness and deafness, supra notes 27-28; DOBBS, supra note 8, § 118 (noting that as to physical characteristics, the reasonably prudent person adopts those of the person whose conduct is at issue). 106756829 810 3/9/2016 2:03 AM NEW ENGLAND LAW REVIEW [Vol. 39:795 unsafe (but yet for other reasons warranted) medical drugs and devices,48 just as it excuses liability for products judged defective only by a state of the art which did not exist at the time of manufacture.49 To judge a product by that characteristic which it unavoidably possesses, or to require a product to employ technology which did not then exist, would ruin care’s effectiveness. More succinctly, it would be foolishness for the lay person to presume to perform brain surgery to save a life, and so tort law would never require it. But tort law most certainly requires brain surgery within the standard of care when performed by a trained brain surgeon.50 Indeed, care requires that one who holds oneself out as a specialist possess and exercise the skill, knowledge, and training of a specialist, even if the skill, knowledge, and training is thoroughly absent.51 The standard of care is certainly not satisfied by the claim that one is (or wishes to be) a healer. An appreciation of the risks and a desire to overcome those risks means little or nothing to tort law, in the absence of the efficacy to accomplish the desire. Efficacy as a necessary component of care is found right where one would expect to find it in tort law. Humility or Condescension. To say that care has an aspect of humility will sound strange to the legal ear, perhaps because the postmodern materialist mind thinks so little of virtue. Yet it remains inescapable that care also includes that attribute which causes and indeed requires us to condescend to those who might be judged by some to be beneath us. Care reaches down. It encourages those with power and means to give regard (and not merely some regard but equal regard) to those who are without either. Care does not prefer the rich and powerful. To care, all who exist have value—care itself being the intrinsic value. To prefer, to prejudge, or to exhibit a prejudice or bias based on the wealth, status, or accomplishment that the world values, would demonstrate an absence of care; for care is submissive, plain, and unpretentious. If care is humble, then we should find such humility in tort law. And indeed we do, just as tort law protects the young, weak, and elderly. It is “‘[t]he crowning glory of courts . . . to protect the weak and ignorant from 48. 49. 50. 51. RESTATEMENT (SECOND) OF TORTS § 402A cmt. k (1965). See, e.g., Voss v. Black & Decker Mfg. Co., 450 N.E.2d 204, 210 (N.Y. 1983) (holding that “the state of the art at the time of production is the issue”); see also RESTATEMENT (THIRD) OF TORTS: PRODUCTS LIAB. § 2 cmt. d (1998) (noting that evidence that the product design “was the safest at the time of sale” is generally admissible). See, e.g., RESTATEMENT (SECOND) OF TORTS § 299A (1965). See, e.g., Aves v. Shah, 997 F.2d 762, 765 (10th Cir. 1993) (finding a physician held herself out as an obstetric specialist); Duffey Law Office v. Tank Transport, Inc., 535 N.W.2d 91, 96 (Wis. Ct. App. 1995) (holding to a higher specialist’s standard an attorney who held himself out as a labor law specialist). 106756829 2005] 3/9/2016 2:03 AM THE ATTRIBUTES OF CARE AND CARELESSNESS 811 imposition by the strong and intelligent,’”52 or so it used to be. Where necessary under the circumstances, tort law holds us to a higher duty to the young and elderly.53 Tort law protects the unconscious during surgery.54 It protects the seaman who falls overboard by his own neglect.55 It protects the unborn child.56 Tort law so reflects care’s condescension that it does not matter whether the low status of the injured party was patent before the injury. Its eggshell skull rule even protects those who have hidden susceptibility to harm.57 Similarly, defamation’s incremental harm doctrine protects the reputation of even those who (it would seem) have none,58 and its significant minority rule protects the reputation of those who have a reputation only among those without one.59 One cannot be so low as not to be degraded even further, or so tort law in its condescension accepts and presumes. Defamation law further gives greater protection to those private figures who, lacking media access, are unable to set the record straight so 52. 53. 54. 55. 56. 57. 58. 59. Abercrombie v. Carpenter, 43 So. 746, 747 (Ala. 1907), quoted in Davidson v. Reed, 337 So. 2d 1288, 1290 (Ala. 1976). See Woodall v. Castner-Knott Dry Goods Co., 673 So. 2d 769 (Ala. Ct. App. 1995) (“[R]easonable care . . . may require greater precautions when children or the elderly are present.” (quoting F.W. Woolworth v. Kirby, 302 So. 67, 71 (Ala. 1974)). See Ybarra v. Spangard, 154 P.2d 687, 689 (Cal. 1944) (applying the doctrine of res ipsa loquitor to hold a doctor liable for neck injuries sustained by a patient while unconscious during surgery). Harris v. Pennsylvania R.R. Co., 50 F.2d 866, 868 (4th Cir. 1931) (“[A] legal obligation rests upon a ship to use due diligence to save one of the crew, who, by his own neglect, falls into the sea.”). Volk v. Baldazo, 651 P.2d 11, 12 (Idaho 1982) (involving a wrongful death claim for unborn child); Vaillancourt v. Med. Ctr. Hosp., Inc., 425 A.2d 92, 93 (Vt. 1980) (same). RESTATEMENT (SECOND) OF TORTS § 435(1) (1965) (“If the actor’s conduct is a substantial factor in bringing about harm to another, the fact that the actor neither foresaw nor should have foreseen the extent of the harm or the manner in which it occurred does not prevent him from being liable.”); see also Colonial Inn Motor Lodge v. Gay, 680 N.E.2d 407, 416 (Ill. App. Ct. 1997) (holding that the fact that a building rather than a person may have had an “eggshell skull” did not foreclose liability). Liberty Lobby, Inc. v. Anderson, 746 F.2d 1563, 1568 (D.C. Cir. 1984). In an opinion authored by Justice Antonin Scalia before his appointment to the Supreme Court, the Liberty Lobby court held that “[t]he law . . . proceeds upon the optimistic premise that there is a little bit of good in all of us—or perhaps upon the pessimistic assumption that no matter how bad someone is, he can always be worse.” Id. See, e.g., Grant v. Reader’s Digest Ass’n, Inc., 151 F.2d 733, 734 (2d Cir. 1945) (“A man may value his reputation even among those who do not embrace the prevailing moral standards; and it would seem that the jury should be allowed to appraise how far he should be indemnified for the disesteem of such persons.”). 106756829 812 3/9/2016 2:03 AM NEW ENGLAND LAW REVIEW [Vol. 39:795 as to protect themselves.60 Care in its humility certainly condescends, and tort law does as well. Mercy or Leniency. Care must include some aspect of mercy or leniency, at least when to offer it would serve to benefit both the wronged and the wrongdoer. That is, care would not in every instance dictate unrecompensed pardon. Nor would it in every case require full compensation for satisfaction of judgment. The extent to which the injurycausing wrong ought to be met with injury-healing action (whether judgment, settlement, compensation, retraction, apology, service, or other relief or remedy) depends on the circumstances, actions, attitudes, and well-being of the wronged and wrongdoer. Care of course attempts to avoid injury. But when injury has occurred, care further dictates some action. Yet it is not necessarily the full and swift compensation, deterrence, and even retribution which many associate with tort law. Care may instead include a good measure of mercy or leniency. Care includes this attribute of mercy, of course, because care is owed not only to the wronged but also to the wrongdoer. The good will that care requires of each of us is to be good, even to the wrongdoer. The talionic punishment (“eye for an eye, tooth for a tooth”) written (if not enforced) down through the ages stands as an admonishment to care, not as its attribute.61 Care implies the best for all in every situation, even where injury has already occurred. It does not absent itself once injury occurs. Tort law’s mercy or leniency, as an attribute of care, is probably best reflected in a little-heralded, but quite significant, statistic that does not appear in the case law. Study suggests that only about one in ten people injured by another make any resort to the tort system.62 That means that nine out of ten do not. That statistic suggests a very large degree of mercy. But such is the very nature of tort law: when it does come into play it does so only by the private action of a private party. There is no compulsion about it, until a plaintiff decides to make it compulsive. This writer’s experience suggests that plaintiffs’ reasons for suing are as various and peculiar as the plaintiffs who do so. It is not always money, and it is not always principle. It is not even always some combination of the two considerations. Even when a plaintiff does sue, statistics show that nineteen 60. 61. 62. See, e.g., Gertz v. Robert Welch, Inc., 418 U.S. 323, 345 (1974) (holding that private individuals are “more vulnerable to injury than public officials” and thus “more deserving of recovery”). See, e.g., Finkelstein, supra note 23, at 25 n.1. DAN B. DOBBS & PAUL T. HAYDEN, TORTS AND COMPENSATION: PERSONAL ACCOUNTABILITY AND SOCIAL RESPONSIBILITY FOR INJURY 808-09 (4th ed. 2001) (citing Marc Galanter, Real World Torts: An Antidote to Anecdote, 55 MD. L. REV. 1093, 1103 n.28 (1996)). 106756829 2005] 3/9/2016 2:03 AM THE ATTRIBUTES OF CARE AND CARELESSNESS 813 out of twenty tort cases settle voluntarily before trial, again saying volumes about mercy. Indeed statistics suggest that in those great majority of tort cases which settle before trial, the settlements may undercompensate the injured on average (and to the extent such things can be measured) by one quarter63—yet more mercy. For a moment setting aside the statistical reliability of doing so, one might take together the two statistics above to conclude that in only one out of 200 (one out of ten multiplied by one out of twenty) instances of injury is a tort judgment imposed upon the wrongdoer. Add to that inference the fact that the plaintiff prevails in not even one half of jury-tried tort cases,64 and the conclusion appears to be that judgment against the defendant is imposed in only one out of every 400 potential tort cases. That again is a vast quantity of mercy. Consider also that tort law permits (and even some would say depends upon) the payment of compensation not out of the wrongdoer’s pocket, but from liability insurance. Tort law even occasionally imposes a duty depending in part on the availability of insurance.65 This aspect of tort law permitting one (the liability insurer) to stand in the shoes of the insured wrongdoer is critical to care’s mercy, because mercy is not the mere avoidance of a penalty. It is rather the restoration of the wrongdoer to good status and account not only with the injured but with the community. And so it is that tort law doctrines deal also with the release of the wrongdoer upon payment of a negotiated settlement,66 effective even (depending on the circumstances) as to subsequent death following the initial injury for which there was negotiated compensation.67 Care’s mercy and leniency are simply present throughout tort law. Judgment or Justice. The natural balance to care’s mercy or leniency is its judgment and justice. The natural mind does not think of justice as being an aspect of care, to which the natural mind instead affords a sweet sentimentality. But care is instead something quite strong and robust. Care has the muscles that come with constant action on behalf especially of those who are in need of protection. Justice is the term best used to describe 63. 64. 65. 66. 67. Id. at 809 (citing BUREAU OF JUSTICE STATISTICS BULLETIN 1 (Sept. 1999); NATIONAL SAFETY COUNCIL, INJURY FACTS 83 (1999)). Id. (citing BUREAU OF JUSTICE STATISTICS BULLETIN 1 (Sept. 1999)). See, e.g., Natrona County v. Blake, 81 P.3d 948, 951 (Wyo. 2003) (holding that prevalence of insurance is one factor in determining whether duty is owed); Hurt v. Freeland, 589 N.W.2d 551, 555 (N.D. 1999) (citing W. PAGE KEETON ET AL., PROSSER AND KEETON ON THE LAW OF TORTS § 53, at 359 n.24 (5th ed. 1984)). See, e.g., RESTATEMENT (SECOND) OF TORTS § 885 (1979) (“Effect of Release of or Payment by or on Behalf of One of Several Tortfeasors”). See, e.g., Varelis v. N.W. Mem. Hosp., 657 N.E.2d 997, 1004 (Ill. 1995) (holding that decedent’s personal injury recovery during his lifetime precluded further recovery by decedent’s personal representative). 106756829 814 3/9/2016 2:03 AM NEW ENGLAND LAW REVIEW [Vol. 39:795 that action, at least once a careless injury has occurred and care must take some action to see its restoration. Care’s justice is not retributive. It has nothing to do with gratifying a vengeful, sensual desire to see penalty exacted. Care’s justice is not based in feelings or in their satisfaction at all. It is instead a rational and considered response to wrong. It is the disposition to treat according to merited conduct. Justice itself has public and private attributes, even when considered to be an aspect of care. Justice as an aspect of care plays a role in restoring and preserving private order, which in its aggregate quickly becomes public order. Justice as an attribute of care is closely connected to remedy, for it is that aspect of care which authorizes and requires remedy, before mercy can be extended and wrongdoers pardoned. And so it is that with judgment and justice giving to care its muscle, tort law depends at its core (both conceptually and procedurally) on judgment and satisfaction of judgment.68 Tort law carefully circumscribes the parameters of judgment to a single satisfaction69 yet just as carefully grants further recourse to those whose paper judgment is only partially satisfied.70 Tort law requires in other words that judgment be real and effectual. Cases and statutes modify and clarify the traditional release rules71 in order that judgment is satisfied even when balanced against mercy.72 Contribution, comparative negligence, allocation of fault, and apportionment of damages rules and statutes carefully balance the equities in judgment. Tort law at its core grants us the judgment of our peers as to the nature and extent of the defendant’s wrong, the degree of responsibility borne by the plaintiff, and the compensation due as a remedy. Although historically and even today that judgment is for the most part avoided in its strictest form, it nonetheless provides the foundation for the entire tort system. Those who settle may well do so because of the impending 68. 69. 70. 71. 72. See, e.g., RESTATEMENT (THIRD) OF TORTS: APPORTIONMENT OF LIAB. § 25 (2000) (“Satisfaction of Claim Through Discharge of Judgment”). See In re Miamisburg Train Derailment Litig., 725 N.E.2d 738, 746 (Ohio Ct. App. 1999) (applying common law single satisfaction rule). See RESTATEMENT (THIRD) OF TORTS: APPORTIONMENT OF LIAB. § 26 (2000). See, e.g., Abb v. N. Pac. R.R. Co., 68 P. 954 (Wash. 1902) (holding that release of one releases all). Compare Maryland Cas. Co. v. Delzer, 283 N.W.2d 244, 248 (S.D. 1979) (finding release governed by parties’ intent), with UTAH CODE ANN. § 78-27-42 (2002) (“A release given by a person seeking recovery to one or more defendants does not discharge any other defendant unless the release so provides.”), with In re Tutorship of Witt, 747 So. 2d 1142, 1150 (La. Ct. App. 1999) (holding that release of one is discharge of all unless there is an express reservation of rights), with Estate of Williams v. Vandeberg, 620 N.W.2d 187, 191 (S.D. 2000) (finding release of agent is release of principal notwithstanding express reservation of rights). 106756829 2005] 3/9/2016 2:03 AM THE ATTRIBUTES OF CARE AND CARELESSNESS 815 judgment. Those who forego making a claim may well do so just as well because of the opportunity for judgment should they choose to pursue it. Whether or not a plaintiff or defendant, or even a non-suing party, values judgment sufficiently to obtain it through the voice of the tort law jury, the potential for that judgment lends meaning to the entire tort system. Judgment as an aspect of care is not necessary in every case, nor is it necessarily warranted in a majority or even a substantial percentage of cases. But it still lends purpose and mission to care, even if it occurs in so few as a hundredth of cases. Truth or Authenticity. If truth is the reality or authenticity of affairs and circumstances, then care certainly has the character of truth all about it. The great truth of care lies in its disposition to require each of us to recognize the existence of others. So is the peculiarity of consciousness. Certainly it is true that as one knows consciousness and existence, one must equally grant consciousness and existence to others. The real or authentic state of affairs is that we share existence. Care admits no narcissistic existence, because such uncaring selfishness is based on a false impression or imagination of the universe of being. Care requires us to conform our will to the reality that others have an equal value in existence. Care confronts us with the truth of others, requiring and disposing us to give others their due consideration. Care requires that we recognize the external and (in a sense) the eternal—that the truth of conscious being has existed and will continue to exist beyond our own consciousness and comprehension. Tort law thus naturally reflects care’s truth both at its roots and in its doctrinal expression. At its roots, tort law conceives of its basic duty of care as a rule of reason or rationality, defined not by what any one actor subjectively believes (whether it be true or false), but rather, by an objective determination based on external considerations73—that is, by an external truth rather than an internal speculation. In that respect, tort law is quite true to truth—quite dependent on truth as an aspect of care. Tort law in the most fundamental of senses enforces truth (the most fundamental of truths) between private actors, that they have an equal claim to existence. But beyond that, tort law enforces particular truth between particular actors. It creates liability for false imprisonment 74 and defamation.75 It recognizes causes of action for false light invasion of privacy,76 and 73. 74. 75. 76. See, e.g., RESTATEMENT (SECOND) OF TORTS § 283 (1965) (“Conduct of a Reasonable Man: The Standard”). See id. § 35. See id. § 558. See id. § 652E. 106756829 816 3/9/2016 2:03 AM NEW ENGLAND LAW REVIEW [Vol. 39:795 fraudulent misrepresentation.77 It requires informed rather than uninformed consent to medical treatment.78 Wherever and whenever individuals speak, write, and represent to one another in contexts material to their health and finances, tort law is there, prepared to remedy the harm that may flow from untrue statements or manipulated circumstances and transactions. Indeed, tort law does not recognize a misrepresentation cause of action for falsehoods that are neither material nor actually believed and relied upon79 because tort law itself must be real and authentic rather than imagined or disingenuous. Truth as an attribute of care is a fundamental source of tort law rules and doctrines. Compassion. Care naturally has a large degree of compassion about it. Compassion is the consciousness of another’s loss or harm together with an active desire to do what is appropriate and possible to avoid or relieve it.80 Compassion is not merely a feeling of sympathy or pity. It may begin with the same disquieted feeling that leads some to sympathy, or it may lack that disquieted feeling entirely and lie instead solely in the comprehension of the senses that another suffers or may suffer followed by a willing that it not be so—a marriage of the heart and mind leading to action. Unlike sympathy or pity, compassion carries with it the will to action so as to prevent or relieve the suffering that it anticipates or witnesses. Indeed, one can be sympathetic or pitying while at the same time being the cause of the unnecessary and inappropriate loss or harm that evinces it. Villains, even negligent ones, probably often do pity their victims and feel some measure of sympathy. The Levite and the priest surely felt sympathy for the injured one whom they walked past.81 But one cannot be compassionate while deliberately causing unnecessary or inappropriate harm, or unnecessarily allowing it to continue. Compassion would lead to a willing that the harm not occur or that, once having occurred, it be promptly remedied so far as possible. Thus care must be endowed with a heart of compassion, for care is itself that watchful regard for the well-being of another. Does tort law reflect compassion as an attribute of its care? Of course the preventive and deterrent roles of tort law speak of its compassion to those who would otherwise have been injured. The refinements in our vehicles, highways, products, and medical services which have been influenced by the responsibility required by the tort system have no doubt 77. 78. 79. 80. 81. See id. § 541. See, e.g., Canterbury v. Spence, 464 F.2d 772, 780 (D.C. Cir. 1972). See RESTATEMENT (SECOND) OF TORTS § 538 (1977). See WEBSTER’S NINTH NEW COLLEGIATE DICTIONARY 268 (1987) (defining compassion as “consciousness of others’ distress together with a desire to alleviate it”). Luke 10:30-37 (the parable of the Good Samaritan). 106756829 2005] 3/9/2016 2:03 AM THE ATTRIBUTES OF CARE AND CARELESSNESS 817 saved thousands from death or injury. But moreover, at its root tort law conceives of itself as providing a “make whole” remedy to one who is harmed by another’s carelessness.82 Damages are meant foremost to compensate rather than to punish because counterbalancing or, so far as possible, neutralizing the effect of a wrong is the willing and acting nature of compassion. If the tort system were merely sympathetic, it might well declare the fact of the injury on some record but provide no compensation or other relief for its sufferer. If the tort system were merely retributive, it might well merely punish the wrongdoer. But the tort system, having care at its foundation and compassion as its corollary, must take the appropriate action with respect to the sufferer of the injury. Thus, the purpose of tort damages is to place the injured party in as close a position as possible to the preinjury status or condition.83 Tort law damages rules permit recovery for medical expense,84 wage loss,85 pain and suffering,86 mental and emotional distress,87 loss of enjoyment of life,88 loss of consortium,89 and loss of household services.90 Compassion being no fool, tort defense includes the failure to mitigate.91 Collateral source rules, rules on the aggravation of pre-existing conditions, and rules on subsequent injuries are all meant to reflect just that degree of care and assistance that is fitting and proportional to the injury brought about by the wrongdoer’s carelessness. Tort law 82. 83. 84. 85. 86. 87. 88. 89. 90. 91. See Singleton v. Northfield Ins. Co., 826 So. 2d 55, 69 (La. Ct. App. 2002) (“[T]he public policy underlying a tort action . . . is to . . . make whole a party harmed through the fault of another.”). See Head & Seemann, Inc. v. Gregg, 311 N.W.2d 667, 671 (Wis. Ct. App. 1981) (“[T]he tort system is designed to make one whole to the extent possible through a monetary award . . . [to] restore [plaintiff] to its preinjury position.”). See, e.g., Molzof v. United States, 502 U.S. 301, 312 (1992); RESTATEMENT (SECOND) OF TORTS § 924(c) (1979) (“reasonable medical and other expenses”). See, e.g., RESTATEMENT (SECOND) OF TORTS § 924(b) (1979) (“loss or impairment of earning capacity”). See, e.g., Bowers v. Sprouse, 492 S.E.2d 637 (Va. 1997) (holding that a verdict for medical expense without pain and suffering award is inadequate as a matter of law); American States Ins. Co. v. Audubon Country Club, 650 S.W.2d 252 (Ky. 1983) (same). RESTATEMENT (SECOND) OF TORTS § 652H (1976) (damages for “mental distress”); Id. § 905 (damages for “emotional distress”). See, e.g., Molzof, 502 U.S. at 312. See, e.g., American Export Lines, Inc. v. Alvez, 446 U.S. 274, 284 (1980) (“Currently, a clear majority of States permit a wife to recover damages for loss of consortium from personal injury to her husband.”) (footnote omitted). See, e.g., Gess v. United States, 991 F. Supp. 1332, 1347 (M.D. Ala. 1997) (holding that Alabama law permitted recovery for loss of daughter’s household services). See, e.g., Aisole v. Dean, 574 So. 2d 1248, 1253-54 (La. 1991) (holding that plaintiff had a duty to mitigate damages by losing weight as directed by her doctors). 106756829 818 3/9/2016 2:03 AM NEW ENGLAND LAW REVIEW [Vol. 39:795 seems founded on compassion at every such juncture with the suffering of those injured by carelessness. Impartiality. To say that care is impartial is to say much. To be impartial is to do for each as true circumstances (rather than name, class, reputation, or other immaterial and immeasurable intangibles) warrant. Those who misunderstand care often do so because they think it is something which favors one class over another—that it has as an attribute a pitying bias for those who claim to require the help or consideration of others. But care is not premised on class or on individual identity. It makes no preference for one over another. Indeed the only preference which care admits is to do as one is able for those to whom he is connected by knowledge, proximity, or other association. It matters not to care if those for whom one is able to care happen to be friends or enemies, leaders or followers, native or alien. The ability to give favor is the determinant, rather than the recipient’s identity. More particularly, although care protects the weak, it does not favor them in its administration of mercy or justice. Everyone gets their due, precisely because care has equity, objectivity, fairness, proportionality, and impartiality as attributes. Tort law certainly well reflects care’s impartiality. Indeed the entire body of tort law is so persistently evenhanded as to be remarkable for its dispassionate quality. Foremost among those doctrines are those of comparative negligence, where the recovery of the injured person is measured and reduced by the injured person’s own lack of consideration for the putative injurer.92 Right where one might think the tort system would extend (and perhaps distort) care’s compassion in order to favor and prefer the injured, tort law instead balances the care of the injured against the care of the injurer. Tort law does so because care is necessarily impartial. Indeed several states have pattern jury instructions that one party may act assuming that others will also act with reasonable care and lawfully.93 So, too, are tort law’s rules of contribution designed to bring about equity and fairness among all of the potential wrongdoers—even 92. 93. See, e.g., Consol. Rail Corp. v. Gottshall, 512 U.S. 532, 542-43 (1994) (applying comparative negligence in Federal Employers’ Liability Act (FELA) actions); The Max Morris, 137 U.S. 1, 14-15 (1890) (replacing contributory negligence with comparative negligence in maritime law); RESTATEMENT (SECOND) OF TORTS § 466 (1965) (contributory negligence). See Kelley & Wendt, supra note 9, at 611 n.91 (citing Ala. 28.16 (2d ed. 1993 & Supp. 2000); Ariz. Neg. 4 (3d ed. 1997) (limiting instruction to auto accidents); Cal. 3.13 (8th ed. 1994 & Supp. 2002); Conn. 2-25 (1998) (limiting instruction to auto accidents); Del. 5.3 (2000); Minn. 26.10 (4th ed. 1999); Miss. 15:15 (2001); Mont. 2.04 (1987 & Supp. 2001); Nev. 4.03 (1986); N.H. 6.16 (1994 & Supp. 2001); Ohio 7.30(3) (2001); Or. 20.06 (1993); S.D. 12-06, 12-06A (1995); Tenn. 3.05 (3d ed. 1997 & Supp. 2000); Utah 3.12 (1993); Wash. 12.07 (1989)). 106756829 2005] 3/9/2016 2:03 AM THE ATTRIBUTES OF CARE AND CARELESSNESS 819 when there are significant other relationships between them which might give warrant to bias or playing favorites.94 Similarly the law of indemnity allows one whose liability arises from relationship to the active wrongdoer to equitably shift the loss to that active wrongdoer.95 Status, relationship, or even deep pockets are not enough to defeat the impartial aspect of care, at least so far as abilities and circumstances are able to bring about such pure justice. The preference for individuals or classes exists in tort law immunities only so far as those immunities are judged necessary to preserve the essential role and authority of the one granted immunity.96 Indeed immunities expressly do not exist to protect the individual occupant of the position granted immunity.97 It is only in the no-fault systems (those hybrids which are so difficult to conceive of as tort systems precisely because they are not based on care), that we see and sense real or potential preferences and inequities—that the careful driver and employer should pay for the injuries and losses caused by another’s carelessness. Impartiality as an attribute of care is expressed everywhere throughout tort law. Unselfishness or Self-Control. Care naturally also includes the attributes of unselfishness, self-discipline, and self-control. Care’s very quality of impartiality or disinterestedness necessitates that there be an aspect of unselfishness, self-denial, self-abnegation, and subordination of the self, in care. Put simply, care discourages self-seeking and encourages instead the consideration and seeking of the interests of others. While selfishness would prefer the good of oneself at the unnecessary expense of others, unselfishness as an aspect of care would to the contrary require the active preference of the good of others in any instance in which that good outweighs the good which might accrue by selfish action. Surely rational choice to provide for the self is well within the dictates of care. Care does not require self-immolation or self-denial purely for its own sake. Rather, care requires a setting aside of the interests of the self when those interests 94. 95. 96. 97. See, e.g., Jones v. Barwick, 386 So. 2d 7, 8 (Fla. Dist. Ct. App. 1980) (involving defendant motorist’s claim against plaintiff’s husband for contribution); Redford v. City of Seattle, 615 P.2d 1285, 1289 (Wash. 1980) (holding that a third-party defendant is bound by an indemnity agreement between a contractor and a property owner). See, e.g., Ingram v. Nationwide Mut. Ins. Co., 129 S.E.2d 222, 225 (N.C. 1963) (shifting liability from an employer to an employee wrongdoer). See, e.g., Pierson v. Ray, 386 U.S. 547, 554 (1967) (judicial immunity); Tenney v. Brandhove, 341 U.S. 367, 377 (1951) (legislative immunity). Pierson, 386 U.S. at 554 (“[I]t ‘is not for the protection or benefit of a malicious or corrupt judge, but for the benefit of the public, whose interest it is that the judges should be at liberty to exercise their functions with independence and without fear of consequences.’”) (citations omitted). 106756829 820 3/9/2016 2:03 AM NEW ENGLAND LAW REVIEW [Vol. 39:795 are in conflict with the equal and greater interests of others. In other words, the only basis for preferring the self over others would be that the greater good would be accomplished by it—with a great caution that our innate subjectivity and self-preference makes the judging of it highly hazardous. We ought instead (as is the great and most common admonition) make judgments based on what others would want of us. That is not to say that rendering care will leave one penniless. Unselfishness is not fraught with any real hazard of the lack of adequate provision. Much to the contrary, good reputation is amassed and honest fees are earned by precisely such careful conduct, the rendering of which lends purpose and meaning. At the end, because self-control is a necessary aspect of the truth that we are each conscious (and thus conscious of one another) it is equally an aspect of care that the value of any action to the good of all beings (rather than the good of oneself) is the only basis for preferring that action over any other. If it is so that care includes a strong attribute of unselfishness and self-denial, then tort law would naturally recognize it. And so indeed it does in its fiduciary rules and doctrines against self-seeking and selfinterested transactions in the management of resources belonging to others.98 Tort law expressly prohibits and condemns injurious self-seeking and self-interest in fiduciary relationships. The hallmark of prudent management is unselfish action rendered with the sole motive of preserving and promoting the interests of another. But tort law of course roots itself in a much more fundamental unselfishness, by adopting an objective standard of reasonable care. The very conception of tort law as dependent upon an objective standard of conduct rests on unselfishness. It is unselfishness itself to remove self from the definition and determination of what conduct one person owes another. Any time a tort case jury makes that determination, and (more precisely) makes it based on an expressed standard of reasonable conduct, that jury is imposing unselfishness on the parties. Litigators understand better than most of us that care bespeaks unselfishness, invoking as they often do the evidence of the defendant’s self-control and self-denial—of actions taken by the defendant which would appear to be against the defendant’s own self-interest but which conversely tended quite clearly to promote the interest of others. There is no better defense to a jury-tried tort claim than for the defense counsel to demonstrate the client’s unselfishness, because unselfishness is a fundamental and commonly understood attribute of care. Self-control is surely expressed throughout tort law. Liberty. How, one might reasonably ask, can liberty be an attribute of 98. See, e.g., Walta v. Gallegos Law Firm, P.C., 40 P.3d 449, 460 (N.M. Ct. App. 2001) (“avoid self-seeking conduct and self-dealing”); RESTATEMENT (SECOND) OF TORTS § 874 (1977) (violation of fiduciary duty). 106756829 2005] 3/9/2016 2:03 AM THE ATTRIBUTES OF CARE AND CARELESSNESS 821 care, if care also implies self-control and self-denial? It is a fair question. But it is also a question rather easily answered by a proper definition of liberty. Most would incorrectly assume that liberty in its true sense implies a freedom from all constraint. And if it were so, then indeed liberty would be no aspect of care. But resort to the dictionary and to common wisdom teaches otherwise. Liberty in its true and useful sense is freedom from despotic or arbitrary authority—not from all authority, but from that authority which has no rationality or reason as its basis.99 That concept is rather easily recognized by lawyers trained in the meaning and jurisprudence of due process. No law is constitutional without its having a rational basis. Laws which are arbitrary or the product of whimsy or caprice are laws without authority—unconstitutional laws which cannot be enforced upon challenge.100 Yet liberty itself depends on order and thus on reasonable constraint of self-interest. No one can honestly argue that any society without law, that is, any society resting on the anarchic force and violence of the powerful, is a society at liberty. Liberty depends in truth on the existence of reasonable authority and on widespread obedience to it. Only then do we have an authentic opportunity to choose. And it is in that power of choice that liberty first and only arises. Thus one sees that care has an attribute of liberty, for it is within the generous confines of care that true liberty exists. Care requiring choice requires liberty to choose. But moreover, care, once chosen, authorizes great and true liberty. As we shall see, it is only in the absence of care (in carelessness) that we lose liberty.101 This kind of true liberty as an attribute of care is again both a fundamental as well as a peculiarly expressed aspect of tort law. Liberty is fundamentally an aspect of tort law in the pure sense that tort law exists as a solely (or nearly so) remedial law.102 Tort law does not impose prior restraint. It is not regulatory. It is not administrative. Injunctions are not available to prevent potential torts.103 It is purely remedial in its frank 99. 100. 101. 102. 103. BLACK’S LAW DICTIONARY 937 (8th ed. 2004) (defining liberty as “[f]reedom from arbitrary or undue external restraint, esp. by a government”). See McCulloch v. Maryland, 17 U.S. 316, 421 (1819) (“Let the end be legitimate, let it be within the scope of the constitution, and all means which are appropriate, which are plainly adapted to that end, which are not prohibited, but consist with the letter and spirit of the constitution, are constitutional.”); see also Marbury v. Madison, 5 U.S. 137, 176 (1803). See infra Part II notes 108-115 and accompanying text. See United States v. Burke, 504 U.S. 229, 234-35 (1992) (“Remedial principles . . . figure prominently in the definition and conceptualization of torts.”) (citing R. HEUSTON, SALMOND ON THE LAW OF TORTS 9 (12th ed. 1957) (“[A]n action for damages . . . [is] . . . an essential characteristic of every true tort.”)). See Lawson v. Murray, 515 U.S. 1110, 1111-13 (1995) (Scalia, J., concurring) (noting that injunctions are remedies for violation of judicial or legislative decrees, not to 106756829 822 3/9/2016 2:03 AM NEW ENGLAND LAW REVIEW [Vol. 39:795 operation. Wrongdoers remain free not only to choose wrongs but to continue in them—even after an injury. A product manufacturer may go right on placing a product in the stream of commerce long after a claims history demonstrates the product’s defectiveness. Product recall is no part of traditional tort law.104 Those who expose others even to significant and unavoidable risks of injury may under tort law go right on doing so, so long as they recognize that tort law may hold them liable for resultant injury.105 Tort law certainly condemns no reasonably careful conduct, whether before or after an injury. Statutes of limitation and of repose even grant a deserved liberty from claims made after a plaintiff’s unreasonable delay. Tort law’s liberty extends likewise to the plaintiff, to encounter open and obvious hazards106 as well as to voluntarily assume known risks.107 In each instance plaintiff and defendant are both free from the constraints of tort law to engage in that conduct which they prefer. Tort law most certainly includes care’s necessary attribute of liberty. II. THE ATTRIBUTES OF CARELESSNESS Liberty. What are the attributes of fault, negligence, or carelessness? Care and carelessness are assumed to be opposed to one another in all respects. Yet (it has already been stated) they do share attributes,108 and the attribute liberty, at which the above consideration of care concluded, is clearly only one of them. Liberty in this sense is meant as the unconstrained ability to choose one or another course of conduct. If there were no liberty, then there would be no wrong. The law cannot condemn one who acts under true compulsion—or who has no liberty at all to act. Fault depends upon liberty as much as it depends upon its errant exercise. Liberty may be exercised expressly to accomplish the most cruel and inhumane of ends, it may be exercised with indifference toward those same cruel results, it may be exercised carelessly as to whether injury may result, prevent potential torts). 104. See, e.g., Gregory v. Cincinnati, Inc., 538 N.W.2d 325, 326 (Mich. 1995) (holding 105. 106. 107. 108. that there is no duty to recall a product adjudged to be negligently designed); Patton v. Hutchinson Wil-Rich Mfg. Co., 861 P.2d 1299, 1303-04 (Kan. 1993) (holding that while there may be a duty to warn consumers about a negligent design, there is no duty to recall or retrofit defective products). See, e.g., Spano v. Perini Corp., 250 N.E.2d 31, 34 (N.Y. 1969) (involving plaintiffs in blasting cases seeking not to restrain freedom to blast but to recover compensation for damaged property). See, e.g., Howlett v. Birkdale Shipping Co., S.A., 512 U.S. 92 (1994) (holding that there is a duty to warn of a hazard only if it is not obvious or would not be anticipated by a skilled person in the usual performance of his work). See RESTATEMENT (SECOND) OF TORTS §§ 496F-496G (1965 & Supp. 2004). See supra Table I. 106756829 2005] 3/9/2016 2:03 AM THE ATTRIBUTES OF CARE AND CARELESSNESS 823 or it may be exercised with due regard for the safety and general well-being of others, or it may be exercised precisely to promote that safety and wellbeing. Liberty is a neutral attribute. It alone tells us nothing of the quality of the liberated act. Indeed carelessness is readily recognized as the sum and substance of a certain kind of (disordered) liberty. Carelessness certainly has liberty as a necessary attendant to its every act. And so the tort law practitioner knows that among the first of steps in diagnosing the wrong is to determine whether the alleged wrongdoer had liberty to act. Whether there were alternatives is certainly an expressed element of (for instance) products liability law.109 Products liability law judges defectiveness—carelessness, unreasonableness, or fault in design— by whether the defendant manufacturer had the liberty to do otherwise. But it is certainly not only in products liability law that liberty is an attribute of unreasonableness or carelessness. The same is true for every run-of-themill motor vehicle accident: what other, distinctively-safe course could the party have taken to avoid the accident? Every doctrine of unavoidable harm—whether sudden emergency,110 unavoidably unsafe products,111 or state-of-the-art design112—has its basis in the presumption that carelessness depends upon some liberty of the putative wrongdoer to act. Beyond that point, at the most extreme limits of human misconduct, we naturally see carelessness’s attribute liberty as something for which tort law provides accountability. Tort law was prepared, for instance, to provide a remedy against one whose negligence contributed to the murders committed by Jeffrey Dahmer in his exercise of a demonic liberty.113 Similarly tort law has recognized liability for serious injury which was the foreseeable result of the defendant’s licentious pursuit of a grossly malformed sexual desire.114 But more mundanely, tort law would hold liable the vehicle driver 109. RESTATEMENT (THIRD) OF TORTS: PRODUCTS LIAB. § 2(b) (1998) (“A product . . . is 110. 111. 112. 113. 114. defective in design when the foreseeable risks of harm posed by the product could have been reduced or avoided by the adoption of a reasonable alternative design.”). See, e.g., Lockhart v. List, 665 A.2d 1176, 1182 (Pa. 1995) (holding it proper to instruct jury separately on sudden emergency doctrine). See supra text accompanying notes 48-49. See, e.g., Beech v. Outboard Marine Corp., 584 So. 2d 447, 450 (Ala. 1991) (holding that in order to prove defective design, the plaintiff must show a “safer, practical alternative design was available to the manufacturer at the time” of production); MICH. COMP. LAWS ANN. § 600.2946 (West 2000). Estate of Sinthasomphone v. City of Milwaukee, 785 F. Supp. 1343, 1349 (E.D. Wis. 1992) (denying defendant city’s motion to dismiss plaintiffs’ constitutional tort claim arising from police officer’s negligence in returning decedent to the custody of his killer). See, e.g., Saret-Cook v. Gilbert, Kelly, Crowley & Jennett, 88 Cal. Rptr. 2d 732, 746 (Cal. Ct. App. 1999) (affirming damage award in a case arising out of harassment by 106756829 824 3/9/2016 2:03 AM NEW ENGLAND LAW REVIEW [Vol. 39:795 who recklessly races past a school for the sheer pleasure of speed, notwithstanding the considerable risk of injury to the school children.115 Liberty can obviously be exercised for the most prurient, sensual, or frivolous of pleasures. Or it can be exercised without adequate regard for the likelihood of injury. Such liberties exercised without care for the one at hazard will obviously give rise to a tort-based cause of action when the careless risk comes to fruition in injury. Liberty is a first attribute of carelessness. Indulgence or Intemperance. Unlike care’s self-control,116 carelessness often has in it an aspect of indulgence or intemperance. To indulge is to willingly pursue a sensual propensity beyond that which reason would properly dictate. Intemperance is the quality of disregarding the natural and orderly bounds to appetite.117 There is nothing wrong with appetite. Our propensities serve important purposes. It is when we choose to serve the propensity, rather than serve the purposes, that natural and appropriate pleasures become endangering indulgences. One may indulge or be intemperate as to intoxicating drink, sexual appetite, the accumulation of property (which would be avarice or greed), or as to the exercise of authority or power. But the indulgence need not be of an obviously corrupting kind in order to bespeak carelessness. One can be intemperate as to the love of one’s own children (spoiling the child) or indeed of one’s own reputation (producing a dangerous pride), or as to rest (producing laziness or idleness), or to work (hazarding one’s family and health). It is the indulgence of the propensity in each case, not the propensity itself, which marks the conduct as careless. And not every act of carelessness has indulgence or intemperance as an attribute—but many do. Carelessness can often be identified by a root or motive. Surely it makes a clearer case of carelessness when its root or motive can be identified or reasonably inferred. When the motive lies in the satisfaction of inordinate appetite, carelessness is quite clearly revealed. Perhaps it seems obvious to say that carelessness may have indulgence as an attribute, but one must keep in mind that the act alone is not always, and to the contrary is often not, a former lover). 115. See Morel v. Franklin Stores Corp., 91 So. 2d 42, 44 (La. Ct. App. 1957) (“[I]t is gross negligence to operate a motor vehicle at high speeds through a section in the city where schools are located, at least, where the motive of the operator is the sheer pleasure of speed.”). 116. See supra text accompanying note 98. 117. See WEBSTER’S THIRD NEW INTERNATIONAL DICTIONARY 1155 (1986) (defining indulgence as, among other things, “gratification of a kind [usually] forbidden or frowned on or to a degree [usually] considered excessive”); BLACK’S LAW DICTIONARY 825 (8th ed. 2004) (defining intemperance as “[a] lack of moderation or temperance; [especially] habitual or excessive drinking of alcoholic beverages). 106756829 2005] 3/9/2016 2:03 AM THE ATTRIBUTES OF CARE AND CARELESSNESS 825 sufficient to demonstrate a lack of care. The same act may be undertaken for a variety of reasons, which depending on the circumstance, may be quite prudent or not prudent at all. But an act undertaken out of intemperance is a distinctive mark of carelessness. Experienced tort law practitioners are quick to recognize and call the jury’s attention to indulgence and intemperance. The inexperienced are less so, possibly because legal training tends to divert the attention from the true attributes of carelessness toward the purportedly more scientific elements of the claim. The great trial lawyers identify and draw out our great intemperate flaws. The poor ones look askance at them for more mundane fodder. Many forms of intemperance are quite obvious in tort cases. The drunken driver has done much to keep tort lawyers employed. Notice, however, that in even such obvious cases it is not the drunkenness which alone establishes the lack of care (think of the involuntary intoxication cases118), but rather the consciously practiced indulgence of the appetite. The personal injury practitioner who drafts the drunken driver’s crossexamination while thinking of that reality alone, will do much to serve the injured client.119 Indeed, it takes a further indulgence of a different form than drink to get the drunken driver behind the wheel of the vehicle, which simply reveals another good area for inquiry. But it is not only the drunken driver and sex fiend120 who can injure others by careless indulgence of an appetite. So too can those who are motivated to an undue extent by the accumulation of finances, for instance in the sale of their known-to-bedefective products.121 Tort law properly recognizes such avarice as the basis not only for liability but also for an award of punitive damages.122 A sensitive understanding and exploration of indulgence as an attribute of carelessness is an important tool to the tort law judge and practitioner. Willing or Volition. Equally is intention, will, or volition an aspect of carelessness. To draw out a point made in the discussion above of indulgence, desire or propensity alone is not carelessness. To condemn desire itself would be to condemn all of us in all of our usual appetites. One cannot condemn a person who desires to scratch or sneeze. It is instead the 118. See supra note 31 and accompanying text. 119. Such a cross-examination might sound like this: “And as you took another drink, you were not thinking of how you would get home, were you? You were thinking of how you could satisfy a thirst which had already been quenched to the point of your intoxication?” 120. See, e.g., Saret-Cook v. Gilbert, Kelly, Crowley & Jennett, 88 Cal. Rptr. 2d 732 (Cal. Ct. App. 1999). 121. See, e.g., Gryc v. Dayton-Hudson Corp., 297 N.W.2d 727, 741 (Minn. 1980) (holding that a multi-million dollar corporation’s reaping substantial profits by sale of defective product supported punitive damages award). 122. See, e.g., id. 106756829 826 3/9/2016 2:03 AM NEW ENGLAND LAW REVIEW [Vol. 39:795 conscious turning of the will and intention to the fulfillment of desire, and not alone to its fulfillment, but to its fulfillment beyond its orderly bounds and requirements to the destruction of the actor. It is committing the will to gratify the appetite that draws an otherwise neutral circumstance within the peculiar scope of carelessness. Thus, willing and intention are necessary attributes of carelessness, in much the same way that they are necessary to care.123 Only their focus has changed from the will to follow the reason to the will to gratify the desire. It is a truth of our human condition that our desires are safely gratified only when incidental to some other purpose. The volitional pursuit of the gratification of desire nearly by definition commits one to carelessness, for doing so removes from our focus not only those around us who are thus placed at risk, but also our own health and wellbeing, which is so dependent upon the check and balance of those desires. Perhaps it is because desires only grow when the attention is turned toward their gratification—that desires are not gratified in the end, only further pursued. But even if the cause is set aside as mysterious or unknown, it is yet quite clear that willing or volition is an attribute of carelessness much as it is an attribute of care. Of course tort law fully reflects the volitional nature of carelessness. Nearly everywhere one turns, tort law reflects a consciousness of the state of mind of the actor whose conduct is under consideration. The entire body of tort law having to do with intentional torts—trespass, assault and battery, false arrest and imprisonment, conversion, intentional infliction of emotional distress—depends upon a consideration of the willing state of mind of the actor. In each such case there must be intent to bring about the harm, or at least the knowledge that it is substantially certain (or in the case of intentional infliction of emotional distress that it is highly probable) to occur together with a demonstrated willingness to perform the act that would nonetheless cause it. But it is not only intentional torts that include an attribute of volition in the judgment of carelessness. It is negligent torts as well, for as the above cases on involuntary reactions demonstrate, there is no liability without a willingness or volition.124 Willingness, or a consideration of the level or degree of intent, is a primary attribute of carelessness as reflected throughout tort law. Perception or Intelligence. As in the case of care, carelessness also includes an attribute of perception or intelligence125—though surely not in the positive normative sense in which we sometimes use those words. The perception exercised by carelessness is not to conform one’s conduct to what reason dictates. Here instead, perception and intelligence mean that 123. See supra text accompanying notes 24-34. 124. See supra notes 32-33 and accompanying text. 125. See supra Table I. 106756829 2005] 3/9/2016 2:03 AM THE ATTRIBUTES OF CARE AND CARELESSNESS 827 the actor recognizes the situation to be one in which there are or may be others whose interests could be affected by that action which the actor then contemplates—and that the actor chooses the unreasonably perilous course notwithstanding that intelligence or perception. There can be no carelessness when there is no known or knowable object of care. One can (and we sometimes do) engage in all kinds of wildness under circumstances where there is no one who may even potentially be brought to harm by it. Wildness under that circumstance would simply not be carelessness (except perhaps toward oneself depending on the nature of the activity), because no one would have been placed at risk. Thus, perception and intelligence are clearly attributes of carelessness—though again, neutral ones shared with care. Tort law clearly recognizes perception and intelligence as aspects of carelessness. Knowledge and perception go hand in hand with tort law’s consideration of willingness, volition, and intent, discussed immediately above. Whether the claim is one for an intentional or a merely negligent tort, the knowledge or “knowability” of the circumstances leading up to the injury are pertinent in every such case. Tort law’s doctrine of transferred intent126 gives us a curious though perfectly illustrative example of how perception and intelligence work as an aspect of carelessness. Under the doctrine, it is sufficient to establish the intentional tort that the wrongdoer has intended to strike, shoot, or otherwise cause the harmful offensive contact upon one person, even though another unknown person in proximity suffers the actual wrong. Carelessness appreciates the circumstance. Once the untoward risk is knowingly encountered, carelessness has been demonstrated whether the harm befell that one or another. If there were something mechanical about the intentional tort elements themselves, then we might have no rule for transferred intent. But because perception is an attribute of the basic carelessness which tort law attempts to judge, rather than being an extrinsic and mechanical element of the tort itself, we have such a doctrine for transferred intent. Tort law must condemn an intelligent encountering of the undue risk, because perception or knowledge is an attribute of carelessness, just as much as tort law must excuse as reasonably careful an act as to which there is no known risk. Unreasonableness or Irrationality. Here though, in unreasonableness or irrationality, lies a fundamental distinction in attributes between care and 126. See, e.g., Lopez v. Surchia, 246 P.2d 111, 113 (Cal. Ct. App. 1952) (holding defendant liable for unintentionally shooting plaintiff because the injury was the result of an illegal act); Carnes v. Thompasin, 48 S.W.2d 903, 904 (Mo. 1932) (finding liability for injury to a bystander when the intended victim dodged the defendant’s blow); William L. Prosser, Transferred Intent, 45 TEX. L. REV. 650 (1967). 106756829 828 3/9/2016 2:03 AM NEW ENGLAND LAW REVIEW [Vol. 39:795 carelessness. Reason perceives circumstances as they are. The rational mind comprehends. In care, the will conforms one’s conduct to the dictates of reason. The rational mind in that sense prevails in the will. But with carelessness, the rational mind and reason do not prevail. The will is instead exercised in pursuit of something other than what reason and rationality project. Choices are made which are inconsistent with, and often openly opposed to, what the rational mind says is fitting and true. Thus to be careless is to be without reason. Carelessness has the quality of irrationality about it. A decision or judgment is made which simply does not fit the actual circumstances. Impulses and appetites prevail over the will, despite that the reason knows better. Indeed the reason exists to declare truth to the will in order that the will may acknowledge it and pursue the course most fitting to it. Carelessness arises when the will pursues a course contrary to reason. Nearly any careless act can readily be understood and characterized as contrary to reason—that it was known and foreseeable that continued action along that careless course would lead to consequences which were less advantageous and more harmful than had the proper course been pursued. In that manner careless action is irrational—stupid, unwise, and lacking in sense. Carelessness surely has an attribute of irrationality. Tort law of course employs in so many ways carelessness’s attribute of unreasonableness. Little exposition is necessary. Unreasonableness is the liability standard no less in ordinary negligence cases127 than in products liability,128 premises liability,129 and breach of fiduciary duty.130 Professional malpractice provides a somewhat different form of this rationality standard, measured as it is by a breach of the custom or standard of practice.131 Indeed attention is given to professional standards precisely when they would seem to approve of an unreasonable custom.132 The tort 127. 128. 129. 130. See, e.g., RESTATEMENT (SECOND) OF TORTS § 291 (1965) (“unreasonableness”). See, e.g., id. § 402A (“unreasonably dangerous”). See, e.g., id. § 343(a) (“unreasonable risk of harm”). See, e.g., Fed. Deposit Ins. Corp. v. Dannen, 747 F. Supp. 1357, 1362 (W.D. Mo. 1990) (applying the reasonable director standard in a case involving bank officer misconduct). 131. See RESTATEMENT (SECOND) OF TORTS § 299A (1965). 132. See, e.g., Edward J. Imwinkelried, Expert Testimony by Ethicists: What Should Be the Norm?, 76 TEMP. L. REV. 91, 105 (2003) (“[T]here is a rebuttable presumption that the professional standard ought to govern, but the judge retains a measure of discretion to decide that from a broader social perspective, the standard practice is objectively unreasonable.”) (citing DOBBS, supra note 8, §§ 163-65); Matthew R. Giannetti, Note, Circumcision and the American Academy of Pediatrics: Should Scientific Misconduct Result in Trade Association Liability?, 85 IOWA L. REV. 1507, 1546 (2000) (“[A] customary practice is not dispositive and can become obsolete.”). 106756829 2005] 3/9/2016 2:03 AM THE ATTRIBUTES OF CARE AND CARELESSNESS 829 cases use several means to limit custom evidence (including for instance that the custom must first be found to have been universal133) whenever it appears that the custom evidence is undifferentiated as to carelessness and therefore suggests a practice that is less than reasonable. But that attention to the standard merely proves the point that tort law at its foundation relies heavily on irrationality or unreasonableness as an attribute of the carelessness which it must and does condemn. Irrationality is clearly an attribute of carelessness employed by tort law. Selfishness or Interestedness. Carelessness plainly has an aspect of selfishness about it. Yet we have such natural difficulty with the concept of selfishness—is not some self-interest healthy?—that the thought bears elaboration. Interest alone is not bad or wrong, for we are all interested. The kind of interestedness or selfishness here employed is that which rejects a fitting course of action which would properly have been chosen for the general well-being, but is not chosen because it does not relate sufficiently to some benefit to the self. What this form of interestedness does is to make an end of benefiting the self, when such self-benefit is properly only a means. In such a condition, one commits one’s will to the satisfaction of the interests only (or primarily, or in any case unduly in its objective measure) of the self. If it does not benefit the self, the course of action is not chosen, even though it has an obvious and necessary benefit to another. As in the case of indulgence or intemperance, selfishness or interestedness can make a vice of what would ordinarily have been thought to be a virtue. Rejection of otherwise warranted action because it does not gratify the self is inherently carelessness. Tort law naturally recognizes self-interested action as an attribute of carelessness. As stated above in the discussion of unselfishness as an attribute of care, tort law’s fiduciary duty frankly prohibits the obverse selfinterested action, or more accurately, leaves the self-interested trustee exposed to liability in the event of a loss to the fiduciary.134 But again, tort law employs selfishness when judging the careless in a far more comprehensive and fundamental manner than those express prohibitions, when it adopts an objective standard of unreasonableness for all fault-based torts. The fault standard which lies at the heart of negligence law, being an objective standard, rejects any justification one might claim for conduct based on the conduct’s relationship to the subject actor. Under that objective standard, the fact that an action appears beneficial to the actor under consideration has no relevance whatsoever to the determination of negligence. Indeed tort law expressly rejects that a 133. DOBBS, supra note 8, § 163 (citing Rentz v. Brown, 464 S.E.2d 617 (Ga. Ct. App. 1995)). 134. See supra notes 45, 98, and accompanying text. 106756829 830 3/9/2016 2:03 AM NEW ENGLAND LAW REVIEW [Vol. 39:795 professional, for instance, might attempt to justify the injury-causing conduct in question with testimony that it conformed to the testifying expert’s own personal standard135 or that the standard should be that of a person with the defendant’s own particular training and experience.136 Tort law must remain determinedly devoted to an objective measure of conduct, because to make the standard subjective to the needs, qualifications, and interests of the party whose conduct is in question would be to equate selfishness or benefit to the self with reasonable care, which it cannot be. Indeed in any case in which the plaintiff is properly found to have been injured by the defendant’s carelessness, the necessity of such judgment has almost by definition arisen only because of the defendant’s selfishness— the failure to conform to the external standard. Again, litigators understand the selfish aspect of carelessness better than most of us, for they recognize that jurors innately perceive and respond with appropriate condemnation to those acts which evidence self-interest at the expense of others. There is little better evidence for a jury-tried negligence claim than for plaintiff’s counsel to demonstrate the defendant’s self-interest in the unreasonably hazardous action—that the defendant was speeding because they were late to work, for instance137—because selfishness is a fundamental and commonly understood attribute of carelessness. Partiality. Partiality, prejudice, and preference are closely related to selfishness and self-interest as an aspect of carelessness. Once the personal interest of the actor in engaging in certain conduct becomes evident to that actor, carelessness arises when that interest is preferred over the interest of others. It is not merely the self-interest, but rather the actual preferring of that interest over other greater interests, which marks carelessness. Without the preferring, there is nothing to be judged as careless. For it to be careless, one must volitionally intend and will the act with a motive that the act result in some gain to oneself over that gain which might accrue to others by different, careful action. If pride is the tendency to raise oneself up to a disproportionate height regarding status, accomplishment, heritage, or other natural attribute,138 then pride must be a common incident of carelessness. For the great tendency of carelessness is to exhibit injustice, 135. See Boyce v. Brown, 77 P.2d 455, 458 (Ariz. 1938). 136. See Heath v. Swift Wings, Inc., 252 S.E.2d 526, 529 (N.C. Ct. App. 1979) (rejecting a subjective standard of care based on defendant’s own training and experience). 137. See, e.g., Patin v. State Farm Ins. Co., 395 So. 2d 466, 469 (La. Ct. App. 1981) (Foret, J., concurring) (opining that the driver, who claimed that she was late for work, was “reckless to the extent of being wanton”). 138. See WEBSTER’S THIRD NEW INTERNATIONAL DICTIONARY 1799 (1986) (defining pride as “a sense of one’s own worth and abhorrence of what is beneath or unworthy of oneself”). 106756829 2005] 3/9/2016 2:03 AM THE ATTRIBUTES OF CARE AND CARELESSNESS 831 unreasonableness, partiality, and falsehood as to the true merit and state of the careless person. Pride and preference are relational attributes, because they consist of comparison. Pride denies the value and merit of others just at the point at which it exhibits a disproportionate evaluation of one’s own value. Pride and personal preference are thus tied to carelessness in every way. Where carelessness exists, so will one find preference, partiality, and pride as its ready hallmarks. Whether it is something as simple as the speed at which we transport ourselves along the highway, or something as complex as a fraudulent transaction, tort law in every instance recognizes partiality as an aspect of carelessness. Certainly it is so for fraudulent misrepresentation, in which the intent of the wrongdoer must be to induce the wronged into a transaction in which the wronged will be deceived.139 Such action plainly displays partiality in that one will benefit by the other’s harm. But carelessness is not much less partial in the occurrence of negligence. The driver who exceeds the speed limit may in fact do so for good cause. Ambulance drivers and police officers routinely do so, without their conduct being judged as careless. They certainly intend to speed, but they do so not out of a personal preference to reach a certain destination sooner, but rather, out of a duty of care owed to the one suffering the medical emergency, or to the public at risk of the fleeing criminal’s misconduct. Think for a moment of a high speed chase in which the police and suspect’s vehicles are both moving at the same rate of speed with the drivers’ similar voluntary intention that the vehicles do so. Yet the intention of the fleeing suspect to prefer the suspect’s own freedom over the safety of those along the highway will determine the suspect’s actions highly careless, whereas the officer’s contrary intention to protect the public will be judged the opposite.140 Partiality is clearly an attribute of carelessness recognized by tort law. Effectiveness or Efficacy. As in the case of care,141 effectiveness or efficacy is an attribute of carelessness. There must be an accomplishment, in other words, of the selfish, partial, unreasonable end. There are careless thoughts, but we are not concerned here with those latent departures. Selfish, careless thoughts that one has no ability to carry out are no more 139. See, e.g., Johnson v. Univ. Health Servs., Inc., 161 F.3d 1334, 1341 (11th Cir. 1998) (denying a physician’s claim that she was fraudulently induced to relocate in order to join defendant’s medical practice because the physician failed to produce “evidence of justifiable reliance”). 140. See, e.g., Standard v. Hobbs, 589 S.E.2d 634, 638-39 (Ga. Ct. App. 2003) (holding that qualified immunity protected a police officer from liability for injuries resulting from a high-speed chase). 141. See supra text accompanying notes 46-51. 106756829 832 3/9/2016 2:03 AM NEW ENGLAND LAW REVIEW [Vol. 39:795 than the seeds of harmfulness. There must be some action produced in order for the desire or propensity to ripen into carelessness itself. It is only when the desire or propensity influences the will or intent so as to produce a choice of wrong ends, that careless action will in fact be produced. No one is condemned for their unexpressed, latent thoughts over which we often have little control in any case. It is the conscious nurturing and eventual pursuit of those selfish thoughts by the will that brings about careless action. Effectiveness or efficacy is neutral in itself. It is an aspect of both care and carelessness. But it is the choice of an opposite end (pursuit of selfish interests at the expense or to the ignorance of the interests of others) which will, given time and fruition, inevitably produce its careless harm as a result. Tort law reflects the efficacy of carelessness in large part by limiting liability to those instances where real and substantial harm results. For instance, tort law does not hold the propositioning of a woman to be an actual assault142 or offensive profanity and vulgarity to be a tort.143 The thought of the wrong, the intent to harm, or even an unaccepted invitation to the wrong is alone not enough. The willingness or volition must be effective by taking form in a damaging result. The old impact rule (still retained in some jurisdictions144) and the more recent physical manifestation of injury doctrine145 are other expressions of the efficacy tort law recognizes to be an attribute of carelessness. Indeed efficacy defines the limits and contours of liability as to which causation is an essential element. Those many and varied doctrines of causation—including especially the “but for” test146—are solid evidence that tort law recognizes 142. See, e.g., Jones v. Clinton, 990 F. Supp. 657, 677 (E.D. Ark. 1998) (holding that a 143. 144. 145. 146. “mere sexual proposition or encounter” “does not constitute sexual assault”); Reed v. Maley, 74 S.W. 1079, 1080 (Ky. 1903) (holding that a woman has no cause of action “against a man who [only] solicits her to have sexual intercourse with him”). See, e.g., Anderson v. Oklahoma Temp. Svcs., Inc., 925 P.2d 574, 576 (Okla. Civ. App. 1996) (holding that profanity and vulgar behavior are not enough to state a tort cause of action). See, e.g., Champion v. Gray, 478 So. 2d 17, 18-19 (Fla. 1985) (allowing recovery in a case where a mother collapsed and died upon seeing the dead body of her daughter at an accident scene). See, e.g., Daley v. LaCroix, 179 N.W.2d 390, 395 (Mich. 1970) (holding that recovery is possible when plaintiff’s “definite and objective physical injury is produced as a result of emotional distress proximately caused by defendant’s negligent conduct”). See, e.g., Rouleau v. Blotner, 152 A. 916, 916 (N.H. 1931) (holding that the defendant’s failure to use a turn signal was immaterial because the plaintiff saw defendant turn. “[I]f [the plaintiff] were a deaf man, the failure to sound whistle, bell or horn would be immaterial.”). 106756829 2005] 3/9/2016 2:03 AM THE ATTRIBUTES OF CARE AND CARELESSNESS 833 efficacy to be an attribute of carelessness. Tort law does not condemn the idle thought, but rather its poisonous fruit. Opposition to Good. When we consider more closely the nature of selfishness as an attribute of carelessness, it becomes evident that selfishness is not merely neutral as to what would be good, but rather it is in active opposition to it. So long as the will is committed to the self rather than to the care and love of others, it must stand opposed to that good. When the will resists the urge to consider and pursue the interests of others rather than of the self, and instead pursues the interests of the self, it must actively oppose those interests of others. One cannot serve two masters at once.147 If one serves oneself as a master, it will not only be at the expense of the other master one might better serve but in opposition to that master. Carelessness in other words may have its root in disregarding the wellbeing of another, but it has its full flower in the active opposition to that other. We see carelessness’s opposition to good displayed in many tort doctrines and cases. There is of course the entire body of intentional tort law comprised in large part of assault and battery and trespass, each distinguished by the element of intent where harm is known to be substantially certain to occur148—in active opposition to good. The intentional infliction of emotional distress tort lies just within the periphery of these other intentional tort cases, where harm is known to be highly likely to occur.149 Tort law takes pains to distinguish intentional from merely negligent torts,150 in part precisely because such intentional opposition to good is a distinct attribute of carelessness. Certainly those cases in which liability is found or even punitive damages are awarded for the recklessness, willfulness, or wantonness which the defendant’s conduct displayed for the safety of the plaintiff151 are representative of carelessness’s opposition to good. It seems precisely where the defendant intends the injury, or is so reckless with regard to it as to warrant not just deterrence but punishment, that opposition to good is most apparent, and 147. Matthew 6:24. 148. Garratt v. Dailey, 279 P.2d 1091, 1094 (Wash. 1955) (holding that a five-year-old boy would only be liable for injuries suffered by the plaintiff when the boy moved her chair if he knew with substantial certainty that she would attempt to sit down where the chair had been before he moved it). 149. See RESTATEMENT (SECOND) OF TORTS § 46 (1965). 150. See, e.g., Spivey v. Battaglia, 258 So. 2d 815, 817 (Fla. 1972), cited in DOBBS, supra note 8, at 50 (holding that whether a particular act is negligent or intentional depends upon the facts of the case). 151. See RESTATEMENT (SECOND) OF TORTS § 500 cmt. A (1965); Seeholzer v. Kellstone, Inc., 610 N.E.2d 594, 597 (Ohio Ct. App. 1992) (holding that willfulness reflects state of mind and wantonness probability of harm). 106756829 834 3/9/2016 2:03 AM NEW ENGLAND LAW REVIEW [Vol. 39:795 tort law is most willing to extend liability, multiply damages, and punish in addition to simply deterring carelessness. Tort law recognizes that opposition to good is an aspect of carelessness and accordingly seeks to discourage, defeat, and remedy it. Cruelty. Cruelty, or the perverse pleasure some take in the loss or harm of another,152 is an aspect of carelessness—never of care but often of carelessness. Unfortunately, selfishness always has one or more victims or subjects, or it would not be selfishness. Still more unfortunately, the careless person ordinarily readily identifies the subject or victim of that one’s selfishness and, in doing so, necessarily harbors and develops a hardness of the heart toward that victim or subject, which can frankly be called cruelty. You will often hear the careless jest or speak poorly of their subjects, in attempted justification of their selfishness. But such denigrating jest or speech is readily seen as evidence of the cruelty or hardness which characterizes carelessness. Often the attempted justification will clothe itself in the language of responsibility or justice. In other words, cruelty can also take the form of vengeance once a wrong has been committed. But the clothes are ill fitting. The subjectivity and hardness of the careless attitude will yet be reflected notwithstanding that the claim is made that justice requires vengeance. Cruelty is an attribute of carelessness no matter in whom it is reflected. The tort practitioner is well acquainted with cruelty as an attribute of carelessness, and has at hand tort law’s ready tools to combat it. Parental immunity from a child’s tort action is waived in some jurisdictions for cruel and inhumane treatment.153 Cruel intent waives the statutory governmental immunity in some cases,154 just as cruelty in a marriage can establish grounds for a tort action within a divorce.155 The continuing tort doctrine permitting recovery even for wrongs which have occurred outside the limitations period (so long as additional continuous wrongs are within 152. See BLACK’S LAW DICTIONARY 405 (8th ed. 2004) (defining cruelty as “the intentional and malicious infliction of mental or physical suffering”). 153. See, e.g., Renko v. McLean, 697 A.2d 468, 472 (Md. 1997) (refusing to waive parental immunity in all instances of wrongful parental conduct); Pullen v. Novak, 99 N.W.2d 16, 25 (Neb. 1959) (holding that “brutal, cruel, or inhuman treatment” must be shown before a child can recover in tort from a parent); Mahnke v. Moore, 77 A.2d 923, 926 (Md. 1951) (“Justice demands that a minor child shall have a right of action against a parent for injuries resulting from cruel and inhuman treatment or for malicious and wanton wrongs.”). 154. See, e.g., IDAHO CODE § 6-904B (Michie Supp. 2003). 155. See, e.g., Twyman v. Twyman, 855 S.W.2d 619, 621-22 (Tex. 1993) (holding that an action for intentional infliction of emotional distress was appropriate in a divorce case in which the husband “emotionally coerce[d]” the wife to engage in sadomasochistic conduct). 106756829 2005] 3/9/2016 2:03 AM THE ATTRIBUTES OF CARE AND CARELESSNESS 835 the period)156 is a particular sanction against cruelty. That constitutional tort actions are allowed for cruel and unusual punishment157 is another example of the civil sanction the law is ready to provide against such treatment. Tort law of course seeks to balance perfectly care and compensation against satisfaction and release, solely to ensure that there is no cruelty. The tort law plaintiff is just as subject to sanction for frivolous claims asserted to burden and oppress the defendant, as the defendant is for frivolous defenses.158 Tort law opposes cruelty precisely because cruelty is an attribute of the carelessness, which is tort law’s raison d’etre. Injustice. If justice is equity or fitness of one’s treatment of others according to their merit,159 injustice must be the opposite: a disproportion between treatment and merit. Justice requires that one promote the interests of one’s neighbor as much as one’s own interests, because that treatment is what is due. Injustice allows one to prefer one’s own comfort, safety, provision, and gratification over one’s neighbor’s equal interests, when that mistreatment is what is not due. The careless person by preferring self over others mistreats others at every turn, except where doing so would be against the selfish person’s own interests. Carelessness’s injustice would be patent at every turn, because preferring the self over others leads instantly to a string of unmerited wrongs, except that the careless one often perceives it to be in the self-interest not to be thought of as selfish. Selfishness as a form of carelessness regards others solely for the value they can lend to the selfish one rather than as possessing an intrinsic and equal value, and thus promotes a mistreatment of others out of accord with their merit. Injustice is thus an attribute (one of the thorns or poisons) of carelessness. Tort law in its essential conception condemns injustice, for it establishes a rule and duty of care which mandates reasoned regard for the safety and value of others. It is precisely the defendant’s failure or refusal to give such reasoned and adequate regard for the plaintiff that gives rise to a negligence cause of action. In any instance in which the defendant in a tort action can be shown to have given greater regard for the defendant’s profits, interests, merits, or safety, than that regard given for the injured plaintiff, the plaintiff will have shown liability based on unreasonable 156. See, e.g., Feltmeier v. Feltmeier, 798 N.E.2d 75, 87 (Ill. 2003); Pavlik v. Kornhaber, 761 N.E.2d 175, 187 (Ill. App. Ct. 2001); Cusseaux v. Pickett, 652 A.2d 789, 794 (N.J. Super. Ct. Law Div. 1994). 157. See, e.g., Carlson v. Green, 446 U.S. 14, 17-23 (1980) (allowing a tort claim under the Eighth Amendment in a case where a prisoner was denied medical care). 158. See, e.g., MICH. COMP. LAWS ANN. § 600.2591(1) (West 2000) (providing for sanctions for frivolous filings as part of tort reform legislation). 159. See BLACK’S LAW DICTIONARY 881 (2004) (defining justice as “[t]he fair and proper administration of laws”). 106756829 836 3/9/2016 2:03 AM NEW ENGLAND LAW REVIEW [Vol. 39:795 conduct. Such is the nature of the risk/utility balancing tests which are always found at the center of tort law.160 Tort law grants strict liability for harm caused by abnormally dangerous activities precisely when greater regard is given for the activity than for the value it contributes to the community.161 So too is the most popular test for defective products dependent upon a balancing of the interests, to determine whether the defendant gave an objectively balanced regard for the safety of those who may be injured by its product.162 Tort law grants to those who act in peculiar roles, such as emergency personnel,163 rescuers,164 or innocent passersby, peculiar regard fitting to their circumstances, where liability would arise only when their unjust conduct did not meet the merits of the situation. Tort law requires of us that our assessment of the interests and safety of others meet an objective standard fitting the merits of their lives and circumstances. When our assessment does not fit those merits, which is the nature of injustice, then tort law condemns, and provides compensation for, the resulting harm. Falsehood. Just as truth or veracity is an aspect of care,165 so is falsehood an aspect of carelessness. The careless person tells truths only when it is in that person’s self-interest. Falsehood, distortion, and lies follow the careless person like the wake of a boat, for selfishness itself is diametrically opposed to the truth of the inherent value of universal, rather than of discrete, insular, or self-existent, being. By placing the self at the center as the supreme arbiter and good, the careless person fundamentally distorts the true state of relationships, and puts everyone else at risk. The careless person’s mind may from time to time remind the careless person of the truth that others have equal value and thus ought to be equally regarded. But the careless person’s selfishness will promptly deny that truth and reestablish the fundamentally false premise on which the careless person 160. See RESTATEMENT (SECOND) OF TORTS § 293(a) (1965) (stating that negligence under 161. 162. 163. 164. 165. a risk magnitude analysis is determined in part by “the social value which the law attaches to the interests which are imperiled”). See id. § 520(f) (1977) (stating that an abnormally dangerous activity for purposes of strict liability is determined in part by the “extent to which its value to the community is outweighed by its dangerous attributes”). See id. § 402A (1965); see also Prentis v. Yale Mfg. Co., 365 N.W.2d 176, 186 (Mich. 1984) (adopting the risk/utility test for products liability cases); O’Brien v. Muskin Corp., 463 A.2d 298, 306 (N.J. 1983) (concluding that the risk/utility test is one means of establishing the existence of a defect). See, e.g., DOBBS, supra note 8, § 129 (citing RESTATEMENT (SECOND) OF TORTS § 296(1) (1965) (explaining that the emergency doctrine modifies the standard of care when the emergency was not of the party’s own making)). See, e.g., id § 317 (citing RESTATEMENT (SECOND) OF TORTS §§ 314A, 314B (1965)). See supra notes 73-79 and accompanying text. 106756829 2005] 3/9/2016 2:03 AM THE ATTRIBUTES OF CARE AND CARELESSNESS 837 acts in furtherance of self-interest rather than common and universal interest. Falsehood is an inherent aspect of carelessness. Tort law is thus found to properly condemn falsehood not only in its expression but also in its definition or being. By mandating due regard for one another, and by imposing liability for injury where that regard is not given, tort law opposes falsehood in its deepest root or conception. Tort law stands directly against falsehood by protecting and promoting the truth of sentient being. As noted above, certainly tort law condemns and provides remedy for direct falsehoods like misrepresentation and defamation,166 as well as indirect and implied falsehoods like breach of warranty and conversion.167 But beyond that liability, tort law further imposes negligence liability when a defendant injures by falsely presuming to afford himself greater regard than the regard given for the injured plaintiff.168 Tort law does not excuse any individual or group from the duty of care except in the doctrines of immunity, where such an exemption is necessary to promote truth and equality.169 Tort law in so many respects condemns the falsehood which is an attribute of tort law’s nemesis, carelessness. III. A PROPOSED NEGLIGENCE JURY INSTRUCTION These then are the obvious attributes of care and carelessness, and some of the ways in which tort cases, rules, and doctrines reflect those attributes. How can these attributes be made more patent in tort law practice? Consider as an example the somewhat circular and opaque pattern jury instructions on reasonable care, referenced above,170 which do little more than intone care as a mantra without in any degree defining it. It might be informative, wise, and refreshing to see those jury instructions supplemented with reference to the attributes of care. A more informative jury instruction based on the attributes of care might well state: In making your determination of what reasonable care required of the plaintiff and the defendant under the circumstances which you find existed at the time of injury, you should consider those 166. See RESTATEMENT (SECOND) OF TORTS §§ 525, 526, 530, 558 (2000); see also FOWLER V. HARPER ET AL., 2 THE LAW OF TORTS 24, 377-78 (2d ed. 1986). 167. See RESTATEMENT (SECOND) OF TORTS §§ 222A, 229, 402A cmt. m (2000); see also RICHARD A. EPSTEIN, TORTS 31-33, 385-86, 392-94 (discussing conversion and warranty). 168. See RESTATEMENT (SECOND) OF TORTS §§ 281, 283 (2000); see also FOWLER V. HARPER ET AL., 3 THE LAW OF TORTS 381-86 (2d ed. 1986) (discussing the theory of negligence). 169. See EPSTEIN, supra note 167, at 611-14 (discussing the principle of immunity). 170. Supra note 93. 106756829 838 3/9/2016 2:03 AM NEW ENGLAND LAW REVIEW [Vol. 39:795 qualities of care which you believe are recognized in and valued by the community, including but not limited to the extent to which the conduct was: willingly and voluntarily done; done with knowledge of or an appreciation for the likely results; likely to be effective in bringing about the result; within the bounds of that free conduct which an ordered society can permit; impartial and fair as between different persons; considerate of those who lack what is possessed by other members of society; fitting to the merits of the conduct; in accord with real and genuine circumstances rather than false, fanciful, or imagined; reflective that each person is only one among many; not unduly borne of individual interest and desire; reasoned and rational rather than arbitrary; promoting of the general health and welfare; not thoughtless or wanton but in due regard for the circumstances including the capability and vulnerability of others. You should not give undue weight to any one of these qualities but may consider all or any of them, or such other qualities of reasonable care which you believe are recognized and accepted in your community, in reaching your decision on what constituted reasonable care under the circumstances you find existed. This jury instruction lists and paraphrases the attributes of care set out in Table I. The extent to which jurors would understand and recall such an instruction among the many other instructions jurors receive is of course open to question. But such an instruction would not leave jurors largely guessing what is meant by reasonable care, and would instead encourage jurors to think about and discuss the conduct in question within the context of those community values which the attributes of care most reflect. Care is a powerful tool—among law’s most powerful. With tort law in such relative upheaval and suffering such political and popular disrespect, it may well be time to remove some of the tarnish from this powerful tool, beginning with an appropriate jury instruction.