Faculty of Environmental Studies Amy Lavender Harris York University January 1999 ENVS 6101P Representing Nature Course Paper Please do not use this paper without permission and attribution. Comments welcomed. Amy Lavender Harris may be contacted at alharris@yorku.ca . Death by Another Name/ Nature Naming Death: Representing Death as Phenomenological Experience Yet the so-called “problem of man’s immortality” – which includes the “problem of man’s survival” – cannot be dismissed with a stroke of the pen. To begin with, man’s longing for survival and/or immortality is not a mere whim of his, or, if it is, it is such an obdurate whim that it has all the appearance of an obsession. (Mora, 1965: 204) 1. Introduction Death is the second question. Existence is the first only because it is easier. Existence is the sum of being: cogito ergo sum. Being is thinking; existence is conscious of itself. Death is the stumbling block, because death is the sum of not being. If all consciousness is being, death is not conscious. Therefore, we say death is not. What is not? Existence is a thing; perhaps death is also a thing. At least, we name it as a thing which is not: nothing. Existence is not everything: only consciousness is existence. Is death everything which is not existence? This is the problem of exclusive absolutes: you have to add them up to get something. Western culture is nothing if not meticulously actuarial. It is a truly curious thing that phenomenologists, among others, place so much emphasis on death, particularly given the problem of experiencing ‘being dead’, if ‘dead’ is also the opposite of being. But, ‘dead’ is a thing, and perhaps also a condition. We exclude death from existence because it appears to fail the test of consciousness: certainly, any consciousness it might have is not meaningfully conveyed. Scholars (ranging from Heidegger and Freud to contemporary thanatologists and religious theorists) typically deal with the problem of 1 experience by broadening the experience of death beyond that of “being dead”: death is also the experience of dying, and experience of the deaths of others; it can also be the anticipation, awareness, and anxiety of one’s own impending death. Thomas Nagel declares simply that the “subjective character of existence” (what it is like to be something) is absent in things that are genuinely inanimate: this includes baseballs and the dead (1974; 1981). Warren Shibles obviates the question by stating that since no communicated experience of “being dead” exists, we cannot say one way or the other, and accordingly should focus our attention on questions other than death and being (1974). Notwithstanding the above, in cultural practice we are very curious about what the condition of death is like. Myths, stories, beliefs about what happens after life ends abound in number and variety: tremendous contradictions characterize western beliefs about death, even in the same times and places. They include that death is the opposite of life; death is an end; death is a beginning; death is simply change; the dead “pass away” from us; the dead walk among us; we will all die; we need never die. Death scholarship typically seeks to rationalize these contradictions by eliminating those most fanciful, or lacking in substantive evidence. This is an important academic problem, because scholars dealing with death seem almost invariably to begin and end with western philosophy and/or psychoanalytic theory. The problem with using these (and their derivatives) is that western philosophy demands proofs; and psychoanalysis requires experience. Western alternative death scholarship that is dedicated to exploring the ‘near death’ and ‘after death’ experiences as real phenomena (Kubler-Ross, 1975; Moodie, 1978; Kastenbaum, 1979; Ring, 1980; Wilson, 1989; Harpur, 1991; Miller, 1997) does not usually enjoy the same credibility in the thanatology community. Given the preponderance of speculation on the question of “being dead”, though, it is not enough to say that death is or is not; and that certain cultural beliefs are or are not logical (or, at least, can or cannot be traced to psychic childhood trauma). Beliefs about death are, just as death is (or is not, vis above). An alternative is needed: in commencing works with the observation that the reader might not live to finish the book, and ending with an analogous statement about the 2 profound un-knowable nature of death, even orthodox death scholars suggest the limitations of their own structured questions, and pay tacit homage to the importance of considering cultural practices of learning and representing death as belief. In cultural practice, death is much more than it is or is not (in the realm of fiscal accounting and forensic evidence and hypnotic regression): death is what it is believed to be, and what it is represented as, and the processes and conceptions underlying these beliefs and representations are more interesting and revealing than the possibly unanswerable questions of evidence and experience. All this, of course, begs the question: “what do we believe death to be?”, and “how do we represent death?”, ‘we’ being, for the moment, contemporary North Americans. A short answer is that we don’t know, or at least, we are especially unsure right now. It is important to emphasize our current unknowing, because it is a central feature of our current representations of death. This new ‘unknowing’ is emerging paradoxically from nearly a century’s effort to define death with all the tools of science and law, which itself contrasts sharply with the past, when what followed death (heaven, hell, or any other of a variety of ‘locations’ and conditions) was considered far more important than defining death itself. Chief among a variety of reasons for this current “crisis” of death is the conflict among definitions of death: experience and evidence (on which we have relied, and of which science, technology and medicine are the main symptoms) are clashing with broader phenomenological interpretations (which themselves are struggling with their own rules of what constitutes ontological reality); science is clashing with nature. As a result, we are struggling to establish new definitional frameworks for death that do not necessarily rely on science or narrow appreciations of theory, and which are based on what we represent as more stable frameworks, such as the natural world. This paper builds on earlier work I have undertaken on death and problems of experience and representation. Previously I have examined the phenomenology of death, primarily as articulated by Heidegger and subsequent writers in a similar vein, and considered how western culture deals with the dead (by constructing death as other, separate, inevitable, and unknown: Harris, 1998). In this paper I intend to leave the firm ground I have previously trod, and approach 3 the phenomenology of death from a different perspective. I try to broaden the notion of “experience” in a very preliminary way, by considering two aspects of phenomenological experience which have not normally been focused on in death scholarship: (1) conceiving of death experiences as processes rather than fixed moments (or fixed objects): death as change, with the possibility of representing experiences on both sides of the ‘moment’; and (2) the use of proxy-experiences to explain what cannot be directly experienced or meaningfully articulated: death understood as/in Nature. In doing so, I hope to broaden understandings of how representations of death are formulated and re-formulated in contemporary western culture, and begin to evaluate the contemporary “crisis” of death in North America, which is predicated on contested definitions of death, underscored by emerging representations of death as natural process (in a number of ways) competing with an unravelling association of (static) death with ‘science’ (dependent upon medicine and technology). 2. Changing the Definition: Death as Object/ Death as Process In addressing experience, phenomenology is fundamentally about process. It is odd, then, that the substantial body of death literature which assumes, at least in part, a phenomenological guise considers the moment and condition of death somehow separate from time, process, and change. This seems very clearly to be related to how death is defined in the west: an absolute dichotomy of life/death is established, the irrevocable separateness of life and death given authority by medical science and underscored in law and ethics. In this section, I evaluate contemporary definitions of death, and consider some problems with the life/death dichotomy. I then discuss how phenomenology might go about unifying experience before and after the moment of death. This serves as a prelude to the third section of this paper, in which I move beyond first person-focused experience, and consider the utility of proxies in representing experience. At this point, I move beyond a true experiential phenomenology, but address more directly the concerns of what might be called a phenomenology of representation. In the third section of this paper, I look at how death is represented in/ as nature. I argue that, where death is 4 concerned, in the absence of direct and communicable experience (and in the presumed absence of the possibility of direct communicable experience), death in nature (beyond the realm of the human) is represented as if it were human experience. (a) Defining Death: Establishing a Life/Death Dichotomy: At some point during the past century, life and death in the west were dissected apart by scalpel. This cleavage imposed on the practising world a separation long argued in the abstract by theorists and philosophers, but which previously had not strongly influenced cultural death beliefs and practices. Conceptions of life and death were governed principally by religious and poetic concepts of mortality and immortality, which also had dominated how the public understood scientific and medical research even long after the renaissance. For the first time in western history, though, science began to eclipse these heretofore parallel approaches to death. As ‘crypto-religious’ death was absorbed into ‘scientific’ death, the separation of life and death was soon reinforced by institutionalized medical, legal, and moral convictions. Medical death necessarily fixates on the individual: the possibility of shared ontological experiences (at a physical or metaphysical level) is ignored. In addition, ‘scientific’ death seemed also to cleave humans from nature, with its emphasis on the possession and loss of the unique ‘privilege’ which defines the living. Subsequently, this dichotomous separation has experienced difficulties, stemming from the difficulty of pinpointing the exact moment when life ends (a medical and legal preoccupation), the dilemma of incorporating beliefs about the soul’s possible immortality (and the immortality of human culture, by extension), the problem of representing death as a somehow meaningful experience, and the (old) problem of whether humans are distinct from the ‘natural’ world, and whether such a distinction can be maintained following death. Prior to the American Civil War (to choose a not entirely arbitrary date, see below), distinctions between life and death were important primarily insofar as they related to the separation of the body and soul (a feature of religion, philosophy, science and politics since before Plato’s time, but of greater preoccupation since Descartes). The death of the physical 5 body was of interest as a setting for the transfer of the soul to an existence beyond human life: the soul’s condition was of far greater importance than that of the body. From the medieval period through the Victorian age, readiness for divine judgement was articulated as a ‘good’ or ‘bad’ death (Boase, 1972; Dinn, 1992; Jalland, 1996): the moment of death was clearly secondary to the type of death (and hereafter) experienced. This is not to say that defining the point of death was not important during these periods; for example, the legitimate fear of burial alive in the absence of vital monitoring equipment encouraged the invention of ingenious devices to alert graveside visitors of one’s situation, or to dispatch oneself if so trapped (Jones, 1967; Quigley, 1996). However, individual death was seen as part of a larger and more profound process of transcendence (Crouch and Hüppauf, 1985), which manifested important symbolic meanings for the collective society. Even those who did not accept a conventional Judeo-Christian vision of the soul’s immortal life allowed for at least a general reabsorption into the (natural) world, which was also a sort of transcendence: this was a prime feature of the romantic period’s treatment of idealized pastoral death (N. Harris, 1977; Schuyler, 1986), and will be important later, in the third section of this paper. The practical necessity of returning thousands of dead soldiers to their families during and following the American Civil War prompted a revolution in the treatment of death, and is credited with helping to establish medical-technological control over it (Bowman, 1959). Methods of embalming were known but not popularly practised until after the Civil War, when morticians were successful in convincing the public that embalming was an aesthetic, medical, and sanitary necessity (ibid.; Farrell, 1980). At the same time, medical advances, paired with urbanization, industrialization and related events, removed care and treatment from the home: medicine became institutionalized, and quickly attained the characteristics it exemplifies today, which can be expressed as the separation of the living from the dead; the “war” against death waged by the medical profession; and research efforts to identify more precisely the causes, exact moment, and possible prevention of death. Spiro et al (1996) have written on how institutions should respond to death; more often, writing on this subject deals with how death is 6 actually treated: the dying are separated from other patients; their condition is kept from them; hospital staff emotionally and sometimes medically distance themselves; dead bodies are concealed on the trip to the hospital morgue (Sudnow, 1967; Aries, 1980; Palmer, 1993; Moller, 1996; others). “Heroic” efforts are made to prevent death: when a patient dies, it is considered a defeat (this militaristic language is interpreted by psychoanalysts like Becker, 1973, as being associated with an innate or learned “terror” of death, and “heroic” impulses directed at denying death). Research on the abstract causes of death draw controversy and curiosity: scientists debate whether humans (and other biological forms) have the capacity for immortality; other researchers identify ‘causes’ of aging (with an aim toward someday circumventing it: these include “wear and tear”; genetic mutation; free radicals; “error catastrophe”; cellular clocks; waste accumulation; the immune system; and others (Jones, 1997, 35-36). In modern medical-scientific discourse, death is opposed to life: science does not concern itself with non-physical aspects of the body. The real issue in medical research, arguably as important as delaying and preventing death, though, is defining what constitutes death. This question has important legal and moral implications: the living have rights; the dead usually do not. Prior to this century, a person was considered dead when they did not have a pulse, or did not appear to breathe. These, of course, were fallible criteria, and people occasionally awakened at their wakes, or after they had already been buried (see above discussion). There are stories, from more recent dates, of people stirring while being embalmed (although the injections themselves are lethal, not to mention the removal of blood and certain organs). In practice, though, a person is dead when their heart cannot be restarted (technically, heart failure is the ultimate cause of every death). Life support systems, however, have the ability to keep a body biologically alive indefinitely; this has forced a broader definition of what constitutes death. Legal precedent in the United States has determined that ‘brain death’ (itself subject to varying criteria, ranging from inactivity in the brain stem to the loss of all function) may be considered analogous to biological death (Webb, 1997): this has been encouraged, in part, by the ability to harvest and transplant organs, which need to be as 7 ‘fresh’ as possible. It is instructive that the legal distinction between ‘alive’ and ‘dead’ is about rights - of care, ownership, ‘personhood’: when one is dead, one no longer has any but residual rights; legally and medically, once a person is dead, they have ceased to exist. Death, now, is defined as the moment when a person ceases not only to be, but ceases to be a person. Writers including Elisabeth Kübler-Ross (prior to directing her research to after-death experiences) identified this attitude (which treats the dying as persons un-becoming) as a source of anguish and terror of death (1969). It should be clear from the above discussion that there are several difficulties with attempting to define death as a precise condition happening at a specific instant, with absolute life on one side and irreversible death on the other (the absolute dichotomy of life/death). These difficulties, or slippage points, stem in part from disjunctures with other scientific and non-scientific narratives of death, which continually re-assert themselves despite the efforts to define death as an absolute. I would like to mention three, which will enter into the discussion about the phenomenology of death in the following section. The first is more a framing difficulty: medicine and science, perhaps by necessity (and certainly aided by philosophical and theoretical models), identify death as the loss or absence of the things which define us as human, or at least as biologically sentient beings. This conception clashes with resilient narratives of existence (of some sort, even unknown) following death. Secondly, the dichotomy is based on an assumption that humans are unique, individual, and separate from nature, which is narrated as continuous and collective (in other words, the death of an individual person is an end, but the death of a plant or animal is considered part of a cyclical process). Third, the dichotomy assumes the inseparability of the body and soul (or ascribes mortality to the soul). Not only does this collide with a form-matter distinction that dates back to Aristotle, but it also poses additional questions about what constitutes life and consciousness, and appears to suggest an additional contradiction to the second problem: whether we are unlike nature while alive and like nature when dead, and whether this is a contradiction in terms. The life/death dichotomy appears to raise a persistent question in yet another form: are humans like or unlike nature, and to what 8 degree, and to what extent can we consider the natural world analogous to our own experience? (b) Experience beyond Death: Before and After the Moment In the preceding section I examined some conditions contributing to the establishment of a life/death dichotomy in the west. Theorists have long used such a distinction in an abstract manner, but the influences of science and medicine entrenched the polarity and superimposed it over other explanations. While separating life and death has simplified moral, medical, and legal decision-making, it has failed to incorporate narratives beyond the dichotomy, particularly resilient narratives of continuity and immortality, based variously on the separation of soul and physical body and observations of the natural world. In this section I discuss phenomenological approaches to death, and suggest that there has been an untoward reliance on the life/death dichotomy. I argue that an unnecessarily limited understanding of experience has been applied in phenomenological approaches to death, and that ‘authenticity’ (as understood in such analyses) is not always possible nor necessary to satisfy the requirements of experience. It is significant that phenomenologists’ enquiries into the death experience, beginning formally with Heidegger (although crediting Husserl for earlier phenomenology writing, and Kierkegaard’s theories of anxiety and dread), coincide with the establishment of the life/death dichotomy. In psychoanalysis, too, Freudian, Lacanian, and other analyses of death and death-anticipation have also relied on an assumed, but not well considered, absolute divide between life and death. These frameworks also coincided with a growing chasm between the ‘real’ and the abstract, resulting in poorly matched theories of individual and shared experiences. Phenomenological approaches to death share a variety of attributes, which I discuss below. It is my intention to show (at least in a preliminary way, given the limitations of this paper) that these attributes are not entirely satisfactory in examining the death experience, “being dead”, or any of the other major enquiries of the approach. A criticism of this effort is that rather than attempting to correct or broaden phenomenology, I should argue that another approach entirely is preferable, perhaps a strict Freudian, Lacanian, or Rank-style psychoanalytic study, or 9 any of a number of different philosophical approaches on which much has been written. My response is that the focus of a phenomenological enquiry - experience - can address very well the chief questions about death floating consistently through religion, ethics, science, and belief. We are curious about death because we want to know what it is like. It is very hard for us to accept explanations that do not address this question. Despite millennia of ‘rational’ explanations, a belief persists that there is something like what it is like to be dead. Phenomenology purports to address the subjectivity and inter-subjectivity of experience (one’s own and others’), and while phenomenology does not, as a rule, consider experience that contradicts known facts, it is an approach that should be sensitive to the vagaries of theory. The bottom line on theories of death is that we do not know what it is like or not like to be dead: no theory is adequate in that regard. Yet, there is a compelling body of belief and curiosity based on that same uncertainty, that ultimately rejects the oversimplicity of the life/death dichotomy (and its mathematical relation to the obviously problematic “everything = something + nothing” accounting), because of a sense that there may be yet something deserving of attention on the “nothing” side of existence. It is my argument that a phenomenology of death should consider the possibility of some kind of experience in light of these representations, and should not privilege unduly those experiences that can be articulated or established by the usual rules of evidence. Establishing certainty of experience after death is not the real question here, and phenomenological studies that focus on certainty (or, evidence that an experience is ontologically verifiable) are perhaps failing to discern the subtle nature of some experiences, and demean the value of a phenomenological approach. A phenomenology of death is not the same as any other phenomenological enquiry: this is accepted by those who study it. Yet, it seems odd that this approach is used so often to study a phenomenon which does not seem to meet many of the basic features of the phenomenological approach, such as observability; what Husserl called evidenz; and ‘encountering’ (the correlative of “eidetic” description that precedes causal explanation) (after Embree et al, 1997; also Farber 1967; Mohanty, 1997; others). To add more layers of contradiction, such writers 10 seem almost always to begin with Lucretius’ well-known statement that death is nothing to us, since while we exist, death is not, and when death comes, we are not (Bryson, 1995: 180): this statement seems irresolutely to justify the life/death dichotomy which I have already attempted to set partially aside. Further, an acceptance of Lucretius’ declaration seems to be a statement that a phenomenology of death is not possible (if death and existence are mutually exclusive), which is paradoxical given the rather large interest in the phenomenology of death. Some death writers, such as Feldman (1992) use these statements to disallow a phenomenological study of death (as itself), but more often they are not considered to contradict the approach, through various manipulations of the ‘experience’ of death-before-itself. (i) A Conventional Phenomenological Approach to Death In Being and Time (1927; 1996 translated edition referenced herein), Heidegger commences with the understanding that an opposition of ‘being’ and ‘death’ is necessary to the study of either. Das Sein (‘being-there’) is the essential condition for any authentic experience. He asserts that ‘care’ (the potentiality-of-being coexistent with the need to accomplish further, or “a constant unfinished quality” [219]) is a stipulation of da-sein, and that if nothing remains to accomplish, da-sein, as such, is no longer possible: “eliminating what is outstanding in its being is equivalent to annihilating its being” (220). These statements establish the two fundamental tenets of Heidegger’s phenomenology of death: (1) death is seen as a limit (the fulfilment and simultaneous elimination of da-sein) ; and (2) driven by ‘care’, we are thus “beings-toward-death”. These statements are not at odds with Freud or Lacan’s theories of the “death drive” (Ragland, 1995), nor do they conflict with a common assertion that humans are the only creatures with foreknowledge of our own death. Heidegger used the concept of the limits of da-sein to approach (and limit) existence itself: being-toward-death reveals the “authentic temporal roots of man [humanity] as essentially finite” (Leman-Stefanovic, 1987: xii). Of course, setting a limit to da-sein presents difficulties to a phenomenology of death: Heidegger’s efforts to get around this are summed up by 11 Leman-Stefanovic thusly; that “some kind of phenomenological inference or “extrapolation” may provide a “unique and privileged revelation of what it is like to be dead” (ibid.: 3); and that “insofar as I am aware that death will necessarily be present for me at some indeterminate time as a factical event”, death will be meaningful to me (4). However, Heidegger firmly places these understandings on the da-sein side of the limit: he very clearly is not suggesting the existence of an authentic first-person experience of “being dead”. He also warns against incorporating the experience of the deaths of others, noting that we must guard against “any ontic re-presentation and unauthentic objectification of the factical event of the death of the Other” (7). Heidegger argues, in a vaguely Freudian sense, that being-toward-death inheres in da-sen; our existence is oriented toward the limit/ achievement of not-being. However, he doesn’t clearly set out (and Freud, and subsequent theorists of an innate ‘death drive’ also fail in this regard) how our knowledge of death comes about, if not from the experiences of the deaths of others, except in the most abstract terms. Other writers who assert that our knowledge of death comes from the deaths of others (Kaufmann, 1959; Mora, 1965; Shibles, 1974; Bowker, 1991; others) seem to have less difficulty integrating the experiences of others into a phenomenology of being-toward-death: obviously, a particular sort of ‘nature-nurture’ debate exists in discussions of how we achieve an awareness of our own death (this is well documented in Becker, 1973, who, incidentally, argues in favour of an innate heroic urge against death). Given the above, a phenomenology of death, in the Heideggerian tradition, must concern itself with being-toward-death (but not being dead), and must adhere to strict rules about how the experiences of others are used. (ii) Some Problems and an Alternative Phenomenological Approach It is important at this point to state again the primary purpose of this paper: to consider how phenomenology can enlighten persistent representations of the condition of death. In this section I present several tenets of a phenomenological approach to death in a slightly new way, in order to demonstrate (1) that death is better conceived as change rather than a limit (offering 12 possibilities for phenomenological consideration beyond the life/death dichotomy; and (2) to ‘make room’ for indirect experiences (represented as analogous to first-person experiences - a modification of others’ experiences) in a phenomenological enquiry. The ‘tenets’ I consider include: completion (the fulfilment of ‘care’ that Heidegger considers); the ontological basis for being-toward; uncertainty as a formulating aspect of subjectivity; the shared character of experience; and the dynamic nature of experience. I have indicated earlier that phenomenological approaches to death generally begin with an explicit or implied acceptance of Lucretius’ comment that existence and death are mutually exclusive and mutually obliterating. This is a main basis for the life/death dichotomy discussed above, which has been perhaps somewhat naively accepted in the phenomenology of death. Heidegger assumes that consciousness ceases with death; the absence of any verifiable conveyed experience is taken as evidence of this. Shibles (1974) is particularly vocal in arguing the fallacy of this assumption: the absence of any direct experiential knowledge on what follows death means that we cannot say what death is like; the failure of the dead to convey any experience of death does not mean that they have necessarily ceased to exist (the above raises an issue in phenomenology beyond the scope of this paper which deserves further attention: whether individuals may be said to exist at all independently of a social context, and whether something not conveyed may exist). Given the above, death cannot truly be considered a limit: from the outside, we can suggest that it may be different from life, but is not necessarily an absolute. Heidegger’s concept of ‘care’ adds an additional complication. Da-sein (being there) is always incomplete; ‘existence’ is constantly striving toward the fulfilment of itself, but ceases to exist if it is completed (1996: 220). In addition to the seeming paradox, experientially this is difficult to accept: if death is completion (loosely), then the dying (or living) must have some consciousness of moving toward fulfilment. Ontologically, there may be a sense of movement and change, but being is not usually self-consciously arrayed toward the completion of death. In other words, death-as-completion (=non-being) is an inadequate proof of death-as-limit. Huertas-Jourdas (1978) offers as an alternative his “Law of Partial Actualization” which allows an abstraction 13 from direct experience: experience is made up of both the ‘real’ (as ontologically experienced) and the ‘ideal’, as the “haunting” aspect lived as “represented” by the real but as not being really there (123); neither has precedence in constructing awareness, although only one may be actualized at any one time. He describes this as the “passage of the ideal into actual presentation” (123). The point of death-as-limit is that it obviates the possibility of ‘authentic’ experience after death. I have shown above that adequate grounds do not exist to describe death as a limit; indeed, we cannot knowledgeably assert with conviction anything about death: we can only consider what is possible, and does not contradict what we do know. Lund (1985) argues that disembodied experience is possible, even if it is not conveyed to the living: he describes this possible existence as somewhat analogous to dreams and other thoughts we have that are not necessarily related to our corporeal existence. Lund’s assertions might be used to re-articulate Huertas-Jourdas’ ‘Law of Partial Actualization’ as the passage of the actual into ideal presentation: certainly this is a central feature of representation (Lund addresses this as well, noting as others have that the ‘real’ is never presented to us as it actually is). I should mention here as well Heidegger’s concept of ‘transcendence’ as part of a triad consisting also of individuation and temporality: Leman-Stefanovic describes this formation as “holding open .. the horizon within which the Being of the essent is perceptible in advance” (21-22). Is foreknowledge a feature of being-toward (-death)? On what basis is this foreknowledge established? Neither Leman-Stefanovic nor Heidegger clarify, except in the abstract. What I have been alluding to is death-as-change, which is a less-dogmatic conception of death which avoids contradiction, begins to address persistent myths of continuity; and possibly allows a phenomenological approach to death itself. ‘Change’ suggests a more incremental approach than the life/death dichotomy; it does not become trapped in the justification of opposites, but it also does not deny that life and death are likely very different. Death-as-change seems to more genuinely reflect the concerns of a phenomenological approach to death, in that it does not posit the same sort of absolute end to experience that Heidegger’s approach does 14 (raising question such as whether dreams may be considered experiences, not unlike those Locke addressed in his Essay Concerning Humane Understanding [1690]). We experience life as a series of changes, not all which are immediately (or ever) comprehensible to us; it seems therefore more logical to consider death as a process, different from, but not entirely distinct from life. Finally, death-as-change is sensitive to beliefs about continued existence after death: phenomenology is obligated to consider these beliefs, and at least their potential reliability, given that they are more plausible, rationally, than death-as-limit is. Like Lund, Mora gives equal consideration to myths and beliefs of continuity after death: he contemplates the following view (formulated by Fechner), which seeks to co-join spiritual belief with empirical ‘proofs’: [that] sensation is not the foundation of psychic activity; it is often a screen that comes between consciousness and reality. If we pierce this screen we come up with a vision of reality which is not dependent upon sensation. From the new point of view thus gained, what is called “death” is only the cessation of sensory perception but not, or not necessarily, that of psychical-spiritual activity. (232) Again, this assertion cannot be established with current knowledge, but it satisfies, at least in part, the possibility that underlies beliefs that there may be experience beyond death. Returning to the phenomenological method, the problem remains of how one may go about accessing the possible ontological reality of experience after death. Arguing that death is better conceived as change, or a process, may be accepted into phenomenology (Heidegger’s insistence on death-as-limit was after all, a book-end to his considerations of existence, and does not necessarily rewrite the larger field of phenomenology), but altering how experience is understood and interpreted might make claims that the approach remains phenomenological seem rather misguided. In an initial effort to make a case that a broader interpretation of experience is amenable, and indeed necessary, to the phenomenology of death, I return to the articulation of experience. I noted earlier that basic features of phenomenology include observability, evidenz, and ‘encountering’(among others); the first two features are very much concerned with the ability to meaningfully convey (or articulate) an experience. It is my 15 argument that the privileging of that which is articulable is a shortcoming of Heideggerian phenomenology, and that further study of phenomenology as originally devised by Husserl will reveal that pre-articulated experience is what phenomenology is trying to get at, which the third feature I have listed above suggests (unfortunately such study is beyond the limits of this present work, as it was Heidegger who devised the phenomenology of death, and there is a considerable separation between the two writers). The phenomenology of death is different from other phenomenological enquiries: the subject is one which cannot be approached through conventional ontological representations. I stated earlier that it was my intention to argue that where death is concerned, in the absence of direct and communicable experience (and in the presumed absence of the possibility of direct communicable experience), death beyond the realm of the human is represented as if it were human experience. I have discussed, briefly, the question of how it is we come to have an awareness of our own (future) death; both Heidegger and Shibles make use of Tolstoy’s “The Death of Ivan Illych” for different purposes, but both demonstrate the role of others in influencing our own understandings of death. It is important to note that these are understandings of death ‘before the fact’, and do not elucidate ‘being dead’ (or, in other words, they refer to the death of the other, and only help us consider the concept of mortality). Yet, our experiences of the deaths of others form an important part of our representations of death: this is clear from the literature that takes its assumptions from our observations of the deaths of others: they stop ‘being’ responsive and lose their biologically ‘human’ form. To us, they appear to end. But this is only part of the story. What of the deaths of non-human elements of our environment. Here I speak of plants and animals (which are not considered widely to have any consciousness of their own deaths), who die but are not considered to end. In the next section I attempt to show just how substantial an effect these ‘others’ have had on our own representations of death, but at the moment, I want to reconsider the persistent representations of some sort of continuity after death of what makes us unique as individuals. These representations exist independently of philosophical or religious arguments, and are not convinced nor dissuaded by them; they exist at 16 the level of what Mora calls ‘instinctive’ proofs. It seems that perhaps observations of what happens in nature are translated, at a metaphorical or mythical level, as though they were our own experience (or destiny). What we are presented with, then, is a phenomenology based on what is possibly, at root, an ‘inauthentic’ experience of being-toward, but which is impossible to separate from our own ontological reality. 3. ‘Experiencing’ Death: Using Nature as a Proxy Anthropologists examining non-western or ‘primitive’ societies often mention their explanations of death. One that stands out as somewhat representative is a fable attributed to the Malagash people of Madagascar, which explains death as the result of a decision made by the first people: offered the opportunity of continual death and rebirth, like the moon, or death like a tree, which lives on through its seeds, they chose immortality through their children (Palmer, 1993). This myth resonates because it takes knowledge of human mortality and genealogy and constructs an explanation based on observable processes in the natural world. Explanations of this sort persist because they do not contradict specific knowledge that may be acquired subsequently. For example, we can observe empirically that the moon reappearing throughout the month is the same moon each time, although it is ‘dead’ to us after it has waned. We also know, through the wonders of medical science, that parents reproduce themselves, and that some genetic material is reborn, or continues, in our children. This sort of continuity is comforting to us, whether we base it on tradition or myths of science. Having addressed in the context of a rational enquiry some problems and potential explanations of death in the earlier sections of this paper, in this section I attempt to demonstrate how a phenomenology of ‘being-dead’ is made possible by accepting that observances of the natural world are represented as if they were our own experiences, and that these representations form an important part of our ontological reality. In doing so, I consider the basis for myths/ beliefs about death; and representations of nature as infinite and continuous; and their connections to this reality. The persistence of representations of existence following death 17 necessitates an evaluation of their source, given that they can neither be verified nor dismissed by normal empirical or rational methods; an alternative approach is required that accommodates their subjective character. A phenomenological enquiry (even an unorthodox one) helps get at their relation to individual human understandings of death. The allegories of the moon and trees mentioned above are suggestive of some characteristics of nature we hold as essential: nature changes, but continues always; it is never ‘fulfilled’ (in the Heideggerian sense): it is always becoming. These characteristics of nature form the basis of our myths and beliefs of immortality and continuity. Human death is linked with the seasons (e.g., “To everything there is a season, and a time to every purpose under the heaven: a time to be born and a time to die”, Ecclesiastes). Autumn (the fall) is associated with death; birth with springtime; and summer with youth. In a treatise on death and animal-myths, Herzog alludes to the life- (and potentially death-) giving powers of the natural world: “dead life transforms itself into food, and food is transformed back into life ... life itself means transformation” (1983: 16). Henderson traces numerous other myths of death and regeneration to their natural sources: he notes that the cycles of nature never fail in these myths; the dead are invariably restored to life. Henderson lists the most common natural subjects of death-resurrection myths: the phases of the moon; the agricultural or seasonal cycle; particular insects (such as the scarab) which lead a ‘ritually’ cyclic existence; sacred and ordinary trees; the sun; and the nurturing woman-earth (1963: 99-100). The connection of these myths with our contemporary representations and understandings of death must be considered, particularly given that our present urban culture is removed from direct experience with nature in the forms one would expect to have such an impact. Herzog (a Jungian scholar) examines these myths as archetypes underpinning our psychological makeup; Henderson concurs: “analytical psychology has shown that what is true of myths in the collective sense is also true in the individual sense. A single person may step out of his culture pattern at any time, producing dreams or acts which bring again to life myths which might have been thought to be dead or outgrown” (15). Other writers, on the psychology of death (Cappon, 1983; 18 Kastenbaum, 1992) indicate that our first experiences of death are often based in the natural world (as banal as leaves falling from a tree; or witnessing a dead animal), which may be related to broader understandings of cycles. Whether we remember these incidents as adults, they have become indistinguishable from our understanding. The point of the above illustrations is that our experiences always refer to an already existing framing mechanism, which provides a context for our understanding of them. Thus, our ontic reality is never ‘purely’ authentic or in-the-moment. This provides an additional insight into Huertas-Jourdas’ description of the “haunting” aspect of the ideal, represented by the real but never being quite in it (123): all experiences are ‘partially actualized’ by a combination of their “real” and “ideal” parts. In this way, a phenomenology of death may arguably incorporate non-direct (partially authentic?) experiences, as long as they inhere in the experience itself. Certainly, it is impossible to entirely separate an experience from the layers of its innate meaning or significance, even before we consciously attempt to impose meaning on it. This is, in part, what makes a phenomenological interpretation of death (becoming or being) somewhat unique: such a fundamental part of our understandings of death (as an abstract or personal concept) is necessarily derived from pre-existing, and proxy, interpretations and experiences, because of the apparent impossibility of meaningfully conveying an experience of being dead. Representations of “being dead” recur in our culture; they are an important component in a phenomenological enquiry, which is enlightened by an understanding of how we represent proxy experiences when direct experiences are impossible. 4. Conclusion In this paper it has been my intention to explore the concept of death beyond assumptions of ‘mere’ physical mortality and the terminality of experience, upon which most conventional death scholarship is based. I am not trying to demonstrate the existence of some sort of immortality, because there does not appear to be adequate proof that this is the case. However, myths and representations of continued existence are a persistent (although not necessarily 19 universal) feature of human belief, which cannot be easily explained away in biological nor psychological terms, and this justifies some sort of consideration. I have considered the development and limitations of a western twentieth century life/death dichotomy, which I argue has influenced theoretical approaches to death, in particular phenomenological enquiries (which have been a recurring approach in death scholarship). I show that an acceptance of the life/death dichotomy should , by definition, rule out a phenomenological approach, but note that it has not dissuaded such scholars. I indicate that a phenomenological approach is potentially well situated to consider the possibility of some kind of experience after death in light of recurrent representations of the same, and therefore attempt to broaden the phenomenology of death beyond the most orthodox rules of phenomenology by first revising the distinctions between life and death from opposition to change, and secondly arguing that a phenomenology of death must be open to considering the subjective character of this change, and its affect on ontological experience. I suggest that in the absence of easily accessible knowledge of such experience, phenomenology should consider proxy-experiences, in cases, such as death, where they are represented in such a way that they are indistinguishable from direct experience. I argue that processes of death and regeneration/ continuity in the natural world are analogous in this manner to human experience, and therefore should be considered in a ([n] admittedly unorthodox) phenomenological enquiry. Broadening a phenomenology of death to include proxy experiences that are represented as indistinguishable from direct experiences permits the study of persistent myths of continuity (personal or otherwise) which are otherwise rationally inaccessible in conventional scholarly approaches. Obviously, questions remain about the utility of the approach I have suggested. Bound by the length of this paper, I have offered a fairly general set of ‘proofs’ for my position, including alternatives to the life/death dichotomy, and the degree to which death-in-nature is actually represented as truly analogous to direct human experience. I have also not really established whether my proposed approach may be reconciled in practice with conventional phenomenology. Notwithstanding these present inadequacies, I hope this preliminary interpretation does offer at 20 least a glimpse of a solution to the dilemma of representation/ persistent myth vs. ontological evidence, where the experience of ‘being dead’ is concerned. SOURCES Ariès, Philip, 1980. The Hour of Our Death. New York: Alfred A. Knopf. Becker, Ernest, 1973. The Denial of Death. New York: The Free Press. Boase, T.S.R., 1972. Death in the Middle Ages: Mortality, Judgement, and Remembrance. London: Thames and Hudson. Bowker, John, 1991. The Meanings of Death. Cambridge; New York: Cambridge University Press. Bowman, Leroy, 1959. The American Funeral: A Study in Guilt, Extravagance, and Sublimity. Washingotn, DC: Public Affairs Press. Brockman, John, 1973.Afterwords. Garden City, NY: Anchor/ Doubleday. Bryson, Ken, 1995. Flowers and Death. 3rd. Ed. Toronto: Cactus Press. Cappon, Daniel, 1983. The Psychology of Dying. In Ruitenbeek, Hendrik M, ed.. The Interpretation of Death. New York: Jason Aronson. Crouch, Mira and Bernd Hüppauf, eds., 1985. Essays on Mortality. Kensington, SW Australia: The University of New South Wales, Faculty of Arts. Dinn, Robert, 1992. Death and Rebirth in Late Medieval Bury St. Edmunds. In Basset, Steven, 1992. Death in Towns: Urban Responses to the Dying and the Dead, 100-1600. Leicester, UK: Leicester University Press. Embree, Lester, et al, eds., 1997. The Encyclopedia of Phenomenology. Boston: Kluwer Academic Publishers. Farber, Marvin, 1967. Phenomenology and Existence: Toward a Phenomenology Within Nature. New York: Harper & Row. Farrell, James J., 1980: Inventing the American Way of Death, 1830-1920. 21 Philadelphia: Temple University Press. Harpur, Tom, 1991. Life After Death. Toronto: McClelland & Stewart. Harris, Amy Lavender, 1998 (unpublished paper). Being Dead: A Phenomenological Grave-Side Enquiry. Course paper for ENVS 6149 Culture and Environment Course, Faculty of Environmental Studies, York University (Toronto). Harris, Neil, 1977. The Cemetery Beautiful. In Jackson, Charles O., ed., 1977. Passing: The Vision of Death in America. Westport, Conn: Greenwood Press. Heidegger, Martin, 1996. Being and Time. (A Translation of Sein und Zeit by Joan Stambaugh). New York: State University of New York Press. Henderson, Joseph and Maud Oakes, 1963. The Wisdom of the Serpent: The Myths of Death, Rebirth, and Resurrection. New York: George Braziller. Herzog, Edgar, 1983. Psyche and Death. Dallas, Tex: Spring Publications. Huertas-Jourdas, José, 1978. Is a Husserlian Phenomenology of Death Possible? In Hetzler, Florence M. and Austin H. Kutscher, 1978. Philosophical Aspects of Thanatology. New York: MSS Information Corporation/ Arno Press. Jalland, Pat, 1996. Death in the Victorian Family. New York: Oxford University Press. Jones, Barbara, 1967. Design for Death. London: Andre Deutsch. Jones, Constance, 1997. RIP: The Complete Book of Death and Dying. New York: Harper Collins. Kastenbaum, Robert, ed., 1979. Between Life and Death. New York: Springer Publishing Company. Kaufmann, Walter, 1959. Existentialism and Death. In Feifel, Herman, ed., 1959. The Meaning of Death. New York; Toronto: McGraw-Hill Book Company. Kastenbaum, Robert, 1992. The Psychology of Death. New York: Springer Publishing Company. xxvi Kübler-Ross, Elisabeth, 1969. On Death and Dying. New York: McMillan. Kübler-Ross, Elisabeth, 1975. Death: The Final Stage of Growth. Englewood Cliffs, NJ: Prentice-Hall. Leman-Stefanovic, Ingrid, 1987. The Event of Death: A Phenomenological Enquiry. Dordrecht, Netherlands: Martinus Nijhoff Publishers. Miller, Sukie, 1997. After Death. New York: Touchstone (Simon & Schuster). Mohanty, Jitendranath, 1997. Phenomenology: Between Essentialism and Transcendental Philosophy. Evanston, Ill: Northwestern University Press. Moller, David Wendell, 1996. Confronting Death: Values, Institutions, and Human Mortality. New York: Oxfird University Press. Moody, Raymond A. Jr., 1978. Life After Life. New York: Bantam. Mora, José Ferrater, 1965. Being and Death: An Outline of Integrationist Philosophy. Berkeley and Los Angeles: University of California Press. Nagel, Thomas, 1974. “What is it Like to be a Bat?”, in Kolak, Martin and Raymond Martin, eds., 1990. The Experience of Philosophy. Belmont, CA: Belmont Publishing Company. pp. 297-306. Nagel, Thomas, 1981. “Death”, in Kolak, Martin and Raymond Martin, eds., 1990. The Experience of Philosophy. Belmont, CA: Belmont Publishing Company. pp. 369-375. Palmer, Greg, 1993. Death: The Trip of a Lifetime. San Francisco: Harper San Francisco. Quigley, Christine, 1996. The Corpse: A History. Jefferson, NC.: McFarland & Company. Ragland, Ellie, 1995. Essays on the Pleasures of Death: From Freud to Lacan. New York; London: Routledge. Ring, Kenneth, 1984. Heading Toward Omega: In Search of the Meaning of the N.D.E.. New York: William Morrow. Schuyler, David, 1986. The New Urban Landscape: The Redefinition of City Form in xxvii NineteenthCentury America. Baltimore: Johns Hopkins University Press. Shibles, Warren, 1974. Death: An Interdisciplinary Analysis. Whitewater, Wisconsin: The Language Press. Spiro, Howard M., Mary G. McCrea Curren, and Lee Palmer Wandel, eds., 1996. Facing Death: Where Culture, Religion, and Medicine Meet. New Haven and London: Yale University Press. Sudnow, David, 1967. Passing On: The Social Organization of Dying. Englewood Cliffs, NJ: Prentice-Hall. Webb, Marilyn, 1997. The Good Death: The New American Search to Reshape the End of Life. New York: Bantam. Wilson, Ian, 1989. The After Death Experience. London: Corgi. xxviii