INTERNATIONAL JOURNAL BEHAVIOR, 6(3), 442-460 OF ORGANIZATION THEORY AND FALL 2003 DYNAMIC INTERPRETATIONS OF CIVIC DUTY: IMPLICATIONS FOR GOVERNANCE Vera Vogelsang-Coombs and Larry Bakken* ABSTRACT. This essay explores the norms of civic duty, based on the legal, ethical, and practical interpretations of democratic citizenship. The authors find that interpretations of civic duty are dynamic and touch on a fundamental political question: What is the proper balance between elected officials and the professional civil service in a liberal democracy? They conclude that the norms of civic duty are political interpretations concerning an institutional struggle over governance as much as they are matters of law, ethics, and best practice. Successive interpretations of civic provide an opportunity for the renewal of citizenship while channeling political conflict into liberal democracy’s established institutions. INTRODUCTION This essay explores the norms of civic duty, based on legal, ethical, and practical interpretations of democratic citizenship. Civic duty refers to the rights, obligations, feelings, and habits of a citizen. A citizen has membership in a democratic state. A state is an independent country with defined territory. A state compels obedience from all who reside in its geographic domain because its sovereign commands absolute power internally. The sovereign’s institutions promote a country’s permanent -------------------------------* Vera Vogelsang-Coombs, Ph.D., is Director, Leadership Programs, and Director, Master of Public Administration Program, Maxine Goodman Levin College of Urban Studies, Cleveland State University. Her research interests are in local government leadership, ethics in government, and public management. Larry Bakken, J.D., LL.M., is a professor in the Hamline University Law School and the Graduate School of Public Administration and Management. His research interests are in administrative law, ethics in government, government regulation, and public conflict resolution. Copyright © 2003 by PrAcademics Press DYNAMIC INTERPRETATIONS OF CIVIC DUTY: IMPLICATIONS FOR GOVERNANCE 443 interests--law and order, social stability, long-term economic prosperity, and national security. The relationship between a state and citizens is two-way. The state provides protection to citizens. In exchange, citizens accept the duty to obey the sovereign, to fulfill the requirements of citizenship, and to defend the state from external aggression. Adult residents who are not citizens do not enjoy the full protection or the rights therein of a state. A democratic state is one in which the “demos”--the people collectively--are the sovereign; its defining characteristic is selfgovernment. In America, the founders vested the new country’s sovereignty in the citizenry. The founders believed that citizens, as differentiated from a king’s subjects, could govern themselves because they could regulate themselves (Eberly, 1994). Citizens regulate themselves when they are faithful to the duties associated with the status of citizenship. Citizenship takes two forms: legal citizenship and ethical citizenship; ethical citizenship has two subclasses -- national citizenship and democratic citizenship. The meaning of civic duty is dynamic because the American state embeds the norms of citizenship in changing political institutions, legal rules, and democratic culture. American democracy involves citizens in the roles of private individual, political participant, and officeholders. Officeholders can have three identities: (1) political representatives, i.e., popularly elected officials or lawmakers; (2) public administrators, i.e., bureaucrats or the civil service; and (3) and independent judges. Excluded from this analysis is a discussion of independent judges’ civic duty. The following sections describe each row of Table 1 in turn. LEGAL CITIZENSHIP AND LIMITED GOVERNMENT Democratic government sets the foundation for legal citizenship. American government is a form of liberal democracy. Liberal democracy rests on the principle of limited government. This principle assumes that the citizens voluntarily surrender part of their absolute power as sovereign to government so that government can make decisions for the state. In exchange for the people’s grant of some sovereign power, liberal democracy functions according to a constitution or charter. In America, the Constitution is written. This written document expresses the reciprocal relationship between individual 444 VOGELSANG-COOMBS & BAKKEN citizens and democratic government. Besides enumerating the powers 444 VOGELSANG-COOMBS & BAKKEN TABLE 1 Citizenship, Liberal Democracy, and Civic Duty Types of Citizenship Legal Citizenship National Citizenship (Ethical Citizenship) Democratic Citizenship (Ethical Citizenship) Characteristics of Liberal Democracy Limited Government Good Government Potential Responsiveness Norms for Citizenship The Civic Duty of Public Administrators Personal The Higher Standard Responsibility of Conduct Caring for Office as Public Public Service Interests The Civic Citizenship as Culture Office that the people have surrendered to government, the Constitution also lists the restraints on government. Its significance is that it is the supreme law of the land. All who reside in America are subject to it, including the popularly elected president, the head of state. The U.S. Constitution uses three other legal devices to protect citizens from government. First, it establishes a federal republic with dual sovereigns. Federalism means that two distinct governments exist that derive their powers directly and independently from the sovereign people: The national government and states. The Constitution assures a republican form of government in every state and at the national level. Citizens of one state enjoy the privileges of citizenship in every other state. It also guarantees to protect states in the American union from external invasions and domestic violence. Second, the Constitution secures citizens’ civil rights and liberties. The U.S. Bill of Rights, constitutional amendments, and federal laws express these protections. Liberties, such as free speech, are inalienable and are immune from the arbitrary exercise of governmental power. Neither government nor a citizen can repudiate them or transfer them to another person. Third, the Constitution authorizes the principle of reserved powers. Amendment X gives to the states or the people the powers that the Constitution has not explicitly granted to the national government or withheld from the states. Pluralism and Civil Society Liberal democracy presupposes the existence of a pluralist civil society. A pluralistic society divides a democratic state’s power into DYNAMIC INTERPRETATIONS OF CIVIC DUTY: IMPLICATIONS FOR GOVERNANCE 445 open and competing groups instead of concentrating it in a ruling elite. Pluralism creates a civil society. Civil society is broader than government, giving citizens a private (social) life and a political life. Citizens get a unique identity by pursuing personal interests, including family life, in private (non governmental) associations. The premise is that only citizens can define their interests. Citizens advance their own interests by joining groups of similarly minded individuals. Pluralism assumes that a check on group power occurs as self-interested individuals shift their allegiances from group to group in response to changing perceptions of their own interests (Shafritz, 1993a, pp. 354355). Citizens’ groups align with others in the political arena to advocate for their policy preferences and to achieve favorable outcomes. Politics is the mechanism for aggregating and converting individual preferences into collective decisions. In theory, this conversion takes place in the competitive processes of responsible parties and within a set of legal rights and political rules. Backed by political authority, these collective choices compel obedience. For a critique of this view, see Lowi (1979). Civic Duty and Personal Responsibility Citizens in liberal democracy can assume the identity of a private citizen, a political participant, or an officeholder. All have a duty to be responsible. Personal responsibility for private citizens means that individuals voluntarily restrain their behavior. They choose to restrict themselves not to interfere with others’ private lives, liberties, and interests. In exchange, responsible citizens have the right to expect others to do the same. Furthermore, citizens’ private lives have legal protections. Democratic government has a duty to avoid arbitrary intrusions into the citizenry’s private affairs and can only do so reluctantly after following due process. Personal responsibility also means that citizens have a civic duty to participate in democratic political processes. Political participation is necessary because the legitimacy of democratic government depends on it. It allows the citizenry to show consent. Showing consent legitimates democratic government’s use of the sovereign state’s power. Citizens show consent indirectly by voting for political representatives who, in turn, conduct the “people’s business.” Voting depends on three principles. First, citizens stand as political equals. Second, liberal democracy holds open and free elections at regularly scheduled intervals. Third, democratic government has an obligation to count each citizen’s vote. Personal responsibility for 446 VOGELSANG-COOMBS & BAKKEN elected officials means that they encourage pluralistic participation, grant access to citizen groups, broker exchanges among competing interests, and enforce contracts. Political representatives grant the right to exercise limited discretion to public administrators so that democratic government can listen and respond to legitimate group interests. Elected officials control administrative discretion by organizing government agencies into hierarchies and through legislative oversight. The electorate has the power to replace democratic government or even to change the Constitution if the voters perceive officeholders as unresponsive. The Higher Standard of Conduct In democratic theory, the position of a free and autonomous citizen is the most esteemed identity. Citizens who serve in government must surrender more rights and democratic freedoms to government. The democratic sovereign restricts the conduct of officeholders because of its distrust of concentrated political authority. Therefore, some actions of private citizens are illegal if done by political representatives or public administrators. The restrictions of office translate into a higher standard of conduct. Legislative codes, conflict of interest statutes, and criminal sanctions operationalize this higher standard. In exchange for discretionary authority, public administrators must follow the rules of their office. Legal requirements exist for public administrators to carry out their office with political impartiality and professionalism. They have a duty to respect election outcomes, to support democratic processes, and to act as rule-abiding trustees (March & Olsen, 1995). Administrators must submit to sanctions if a legislative review finds that they have failed to discharge these duties properly. Impartiality and professionalism counteract the partisanship and ideologies of popularly elected officials. One school of thought frees public administrators from legal restraints, obliging them to disobey evil-minded elected officials in times of crises. If nefarious elected officials capture the state’s absolute power and present their unconstitutional activities as those of the democratic sovereign, then dictatorship happens, as in Nazi Germany. According to March and Olsen, public administrators must actively thwart the methods and goals of iniquitous political officials. NATIONAL CITIZENSHIP AND GOOD GOVERNMENT The legal foundations of citizenship are incomplete. Citizens who possess legal and civil rights in a pluralist society do not automatically DYNAMIC INTERPRETATIONS OF CIVIC DUTY: IMPLICATIONS FOR GOVERNANCE 447 feel political allegiance to their country (Heywood, 1994). To stimulate national citizenship, the American founders vested the sovereignty of the new country in the political community, not the electorate. This political community encompasses the nationwide body of citizens as they interact informally and formally in social, religious, economic, cultural, and community associations in their localities (Hult & Walcott, 1990). By vesting sovereignty in the national political community, the founders broadened the idea of citizenship to include an ethical dimension. Ethical citizenship refers to the moral beliefs, values, fraternal feelings, habits, and reciprocal commitments of individuals that guide their lives. Whereas legal citizenship is expressed in law and rules, ethical citizenship is in standards that most people acknowledge but are not codified. Ethical citizenship is always a matter of voluntary behavior and is subject to different interpretations by different people. The founders rooted the political community in a culture of “good government.” Political culture refers to the citizenry’s attitudes about the style of democratic governmental operations (Shafritz, 1993b, p. 362). Good government, as opposed to perfect government, is based on legitimacy that extends beyond electoral popularity. This means that democratic government must defend its legitimacy on higher (normative) values. It is not enough for government to appear good; its actions must be good. To make government’s actions “good,” officeholders are bound to justify publicly and receive approval from the democratic sovereign (not just the electorate) (Madison, 1788/1961). In obtaining prior approval, officeholders determine whether their proposed actions are ethically appropriate, i.e., have wide community support. For March and Olsen, the ethic of appropriateness means that government acts consistently with cultural and political norms. This ethic reassures the democratic political community that officeholders will not act arbitrarily nor for purely private interests. The actions of good government strengthen the democratic sovereign’s confidence in those to whom it has entrusted the state’s power. Civic Duty and Caring for Public Interests Membership in the political community gives citizens a public life besides a private life. In public life, citizens actively maintain public purposes, based on a perception of national solidarity and a sense of a common destiny. For Norton Long (1962b, p. 184), a precondition of 448 VOGELSANG-COOMBS & BAKKEN legal citizenship is that citizens have a sense of “moi commun.” Communal feelings stir in citizens, he says, if “a public thing” quite literally exists for which they feel responsible. For John Dewey (1927), this public thing emerges when citizens rediscover the “public and its interests.” A political community of citizens, he says, cares for public interests. To care for public interests, citizens must engage each other to discern common needs. This task requires citizens to reflect and to distinguish between the special case (their own interests) and the general case (the interests of others). In other words, citizens use moral reasoning to perceive the difference between public interests and private interests. According to Dewey, people create private interests when they join voluntarily, and only those people involved in a transaction experience the direct or indirect consequences of those interactions. Public interests are not fixed. They emerge when individuals as a group are seriously and indirectly harmed by the consequences of transactions in which they have not engaged. Although reasonable citizens may disagree, their open discussions allow the political community to search for remedies for public interest causes. Caring for the public gives diverse citizens a common ethical identity. Public spirit awakens this identity in citizens. The civic virtue of private citizens is the source of public spirit. Public-spirited citizens participate in public life when they perceive that the personal advantage of each member of the community is consistent with working for the good of all. Alexis de Tocqueville (1838/1945: Vol. II, p. 129-132) calls this disposition of American citizens “the principle of self interest rightly understood.” Citizens live this principle daily in small acts of self restraint, not through great sacrifices. Such daily actions, says de Tocqueville, gradually draw individuals through their habits in the direction of the national political community. Virtuous citizens, acting on this principle, voluntarily help others. In place of doing it themselves, they willingly give up additional personal resources to sponsor community programs aimed at serving the poor and at improving society. De Tocqueville says that this public role for private citizens is based on custom, not law. This custom binds together the nation, allowing diverse citizens in the political community to lead a good life. For Dewey, public life is a good life. A good or high-quality common life emerges only if a democratic state is a good state. A good state comes into existence when trustees of the public (lawmakers and public administrators) systematically care for public interests. In Dewey’s good state, citizens have greater liberty and security in their private affairs DYNAMIC INTERPRETATIONS OF CIVIC DUTY: IMPLICATIONS FOR GOVERNANCE 449 because they are relieved from the waste of negative struggle and needless conflict. The community-based processes of the good state, by promoting reflection, moral reasoning, and open discourse, civilize humanity, allowing citizens to show empathy, tolerance, and generosity (March & Olsen, 1995: 60). Office as Public Service For Dewey, the public is vital to the creation of government. Government is the public organized to carry out the functions of the state in a way that strengthens ethical bonds among citizens. The sovereign political community connects the power of the democratic state to care for public interests through government officials. It gives them the use of the democratic state’s power to regulate the conjoint actions of individuals and groups that cause a public interest to emerge. Different issues create different public interests. As trustees of the public and its interests, public administrators hold the office of a public servant. The duty of public servants is to recognize the dynamics and the consequences of individuals “acting as a public.” According to March and Olsen, the political community’s discussions about public interests should guide and restrain public servants’ actions. By listening to these discussions, public servants will get an idea about what governmental actions are acceptable to the larger political community on moral grounds. These discussions reveal the issues that government should avoid or remove from the policy agenda temporarily because of a lack of wide acceptance. By withdrawing these issues, public servants help to prevent the polarization of the community. Such actions displace conflicts, producing new majorities and new allocations of governmental power. In effect, the influence of community discussions on public servants allows the democratic sovereign to civilize its government. Ethical Maturity This task of public service requires ethically mature officeholders. Ethically mature public servants, says Stephen K. Bailey, appreciate the reality of self-interest and its impact on motivating behavior, both public and private. ... Public service is the capacity to harness private and personal interests to public interest causes. Those who will not traffic in personal and private interests (if such interests are within the 450 VOGELSANG-COOMBS & BAKKEN law) to the point of engaging their support on behalf of causes in which both public and private interests are served are, in terms of moral temperament, unfit for public responsibility (Bailey, 1964/1990. p. 47). Ethically mature public servants, says Bailey, possess three moral qualities: optimism, courage, and fairness tempered by charity. Optimism allows public servants to see possibilities in shifting political priorities so that they can perform the political function of government without becoming cynical. Optimistic public servants are motivated to better society and to improve the quality of human life. Cynical officials who perceive humankind as unworthy of such efforts are a source of corruption in a free society. Courage overcomes the forces of private relations, especially friendship, and provides a degree of neutrality to override requests for special favors. Ethical courage means that public servants are willing to decide even with inadequate information. Ethical courage is meaningless unless it enables public servants to act justly. Fairness tempered by the virtue of charity promotes justice. Charitable public servants discipline themselves by controlling persistent inner claims for personal recognition, power, and status. Charity is also a source of visions for the “good society” without which government, says Bailey (1964/1990, p. 52), becomes “a sullen defense of existing patterns of privilege.” Fairness compensates for the subjective nature of all decision making. Fairness is necessary because of administrative discretion. Fair-minded public servants control that discretion by balancing flexibility and consistency in their decisions. As Bailey points out, public administrators who never deviate are rigid and lack compassion; those who deviate too much are subversive. The ethical compromises of mature administrators allow them to act with enough consistency and flexibility to survive and succeed in public service. CHALLENGES TO NATIONAL CITIZENSHIP At the end of the twentieth century, scholars have identified at least five challenges to national citizenship in America. First, Robert Putnam (1995) argues that American life lacks communal solidarity. Instead of finding de Tocqueville’s “nation of joiners” with a vibrant public life, Putnam observes that Americans are “bowling alone,” and their civic life has all but disappeared. Second, scholars have identified a societal malaise: widespread alienation of citizens from government. For example, Evan Berman’s (1997) national survey identifies three sources DYNAMIC INTERPRETATIONS OF CIVIC DUTY: IMPLICATIONS FOR GOVERNANCE 451 of citizen discontent: (1) government officials whom citizens perceive as indifferent or hostile to their needs; (2) poor service delivery; and (3) governmental processes that exclude citizens. Third, the emergence of the welfare state has significantly undermined the citizen-government relationship. Specifically, Eberly says that Americans have assumed problematic identities as clients, customers, consumers, and claimants of government. The provision of public assistance to tens of millions of Americans is often accompanied by the subtle message that recipients are hopelessly trapped in conditions that require the permanent help of advocates, interest groups and government workers. It produces a mindset that dwarfs citizenship for the poor and the non-poor alike. It leaves the poor feeling justified in doing little to reclaim control of their lives and the non-poor feeling no obligation to intervene with neighborly aid (Eberly, 1994, p. xxix). Fourth, in a comprehensive study of citizenship, Rogers Smith (1997) finds that liberal democracy is not the core meaning of the American civic identity. Clashing traditions and popular politics have excluded most Americans from enjoying full citizenship. Fifth, Chester Newland (1987) argues that a pervasive system of spoils at the national level excludes most of the public administration community from important matters of governance. This exclusion undermines the capacity of American democracy to function adequately or to achieve social change. Some fixes to these problems of national citizenship, such as Benjamin Barber’s (1984) “strong (grassroots) democracy,” aim at weakening liberal democratic institutions and basic protections. A more constructive approach is not to deny democratic liberal traditions. It draws the norms of ethical citizenship from the operations of successful liberal democracies. If democracy is to endure, then pragmatic realism, says Hanson Baldwin (1960), must temper the idealistic notions of citizenship. DEMOCRATIC CITIZENSHIP AND POTENTIAL RESPONSIVENESS E. E. Schattschneider provides a realist’s view of democratic citizenship. The most damage to the democratic cause, he says 452 VOGELSANG-COOMBS & BAKKEN (1975:135-136), comes from idealists who attribute a “mystical, magical omnipotence” to the people. 454 VOGELSANG-COOMBS & BAKKEN This attribution takes no heed of what the democratic system can do. Involving 280 million people directly in all aspects of governance is physically impossible. Instead, he assumes that democratic citizens are moral equals: Each person is a precious and unique human. Morally equal citizens have potential involvement. Potentially involved citizens become active in public affairs because of a democratic dynamic: conflict is contagious. Different public issues activate different citizens. If only 0.10 percent of the citizenry mobilizes around an issue, then the latent force of the remaining citizens is 999 greater than that of the activists. Schattschneider’s point is that any estimate of citizen participation based on the number of original activists is fatuous. Potentially involved citizens are not neutral spectators. Public issues succeed or fail because the original activists mobilize or exclude the spectators. For Schattschneider (1975, pp. 4-5), the balance of citizen involvement in any public issue, he says emphatically, is not fixed until everyone is involved. From this analysis, Schattschneider recasts the meaning of ethical citizenship to include a practical dimension. He adapts Aristotle’s (trans. 1962) concept of practical knowledge. Aristotle argues that humans use knowledge derived from direct experience, experimental learning, and practice in taking action (personal discipline) in matters of ethics and politics. For Schattschneider, democratic citizens use practical knowledge in democratic governance. They adjust their role so that it is consistent with what most people can and are willing to do in public life. The behavior of practical-minded citizens is the same as in private relationships: People take advantage of what other people know and judge results. In public affairs, citizens rely on government leaders and organizations, or their responsible opposition, to give them choices about policy alternatives. These choices must allow citizens the potential to participate in meaningful ways. In this democratic system, the sovereign people “act through the government.” This system satisfies citizens only if it meets the condition of “potential responsiveness.” Potential responsiveness in a democracy, says Hanna Pitkin, requires citizens to have: “. . .Access to power rather than its actual exercise . . . There need not be a constant activity of responding, but there must be a constant condition of responsiveness, of potential readiness [of government] to respond” (Pitkin, 1972, p. 233). If citizens perceive potential responsiveness in the democratic system, then they feel that they can initiate action or trust leaders to do the right thing. Citizens accept governmental authority despite their lack of awareness of what DYNAMIC INTERPRETATIONS OF CIVIC DUTY: IMPLICATIONS FOR GOVERNANCE 455 government is doing most of the time. These beliefs are a part of the democratic civic culture. The Civic Culture According to Gabriel Almond and Sidney Verba (1963), the civic culture shapes the norms for citizens, their relationship to each other and to their democratic government. Their comparative analysis of five democracies, though drawn in 1963, remains the classical formulation. It shows that stable democracies have democratic civic cultures. They describe the American civic culture as mixed. American citizens’ activity in public life combines involvement and activity with passivity and noninvolvement. They take on and balance the duties of three identities: The influential activist, the passive governmental subject, and the parochial (family-oriented, private) person. Almond and Verba find that the norms of trust and confidence from citizens’ social interactions transfer to their political relationships and temper them. They also find that the interactions of citizens and government show a cyclical pattern. In normal times, most citizens are quiescent. They are uninterested in what decision makers do, but officeholders can act only within legal and ethical bounds. If an issue becomes salient, then citizens will increase their involvement with government, making demands on elected officials and public administrators. If government officials make appropriate adjustments, then the importance of politics will lose saliency for mobilized citizens, and they will withdraw from active participation. This cycle allows a democratic system to change slowly and humanely. If issues become and remain intense, then they destabilize a democracy. Almond and Verba’s research shows that the cycle of political participation strains neither people nor stable democracies. The reason is that the civic culture controls decision makers without checking them so tightly as to render democratic government ineffective. The check and balance occur for four reasons. First, democratic government officials subscribe to the belief in the influence potential of citizens. Second, government decision makers anticipate citizens’ reactions even if citizens are not active or making demands on them. Third, government officials and citizens are part of the same political community. They share the same civic culture that exposes them to the same democratic values. Fourth, public and private life is not opposites in the civic culture. The democratic culture mixes the personal, social, and political identities of 456 VOGELSANG-COOMBS & BAKKEN citizens. It socializes government officials to uphold a continuum of public-private relationships that flourish legitimately in the political community. Citizenship as Office Terry Cooper (1991) formulates an ethic of citizenship for democratic public administration. He assumes that citizenship underpins all normative relationships in the political community. Citizenship, in his conceptualization, is the public office of virtuous individuals in the political community. Public administrators are citizens first. They are virtuous citizens “employed as one of us to work for us” (Cooper, 1971, p. 139). In office, they are fiduciary citizens. As trustees for the political community, virtuous administrators make citizens part of the administrative role. Efficient service delivery and law enforcement are their penultimate obligations. Their ultimate duty is to build and contribute to community life by sharing the sovereign’s power, upholding civic values, and pursuing long-term interests. The authority relationships of virtuous administrators are both vertical and horizontal. They look at popularly elected politicians and to the citizenry for direction. For Cooper, the ultimate loyalty of virtuous administrators belongs to the citizenry because the citizenry’s authority is that of the sovereign. The sovereign’s authority transcends loyalty to specific elected officials or particular governmental agencies. Virtuous administrators, says Newland (1987), use transformational leadership practices to awaken and broaden the involvement of citizens in public affairs. They combine their professional expertise and civic values in a way that gives citizens new and meaningful opportunities to participate in governance and for self reflection. These practices stimulate positive changes in individuals, institutions, and the community. “Coproduction,” “indirect administration,” and “transparent decision making” are three examples of such practices. For Charles Levine (1984/2001), “coproduction” means that virtuous administrators involve active citizens as partners in allocation decisions regarding service delivery. For Cooper, virtuous administrators engage in indirect administration by subordinating their technical expertise to active community leaders. They engage in policy deliberations by working through and respecting existing communities, their associations and authorities. Cooper says that virtuous administrators are justified to shed their neutrality and to act as policy advocates if their judgments are DYNAMIC INTERPRETATIONS OF CIVIC DUTY: IMPLICATIONS FOR GOVERNANCE 457 consistent with their role as fiduciary citizens. Transparent decisionmaking, says Carol Lewis (1991, p. 58), establishes the ethical credibility of public administrators. It is necessary because most administrative decisions take place without the physical presence of citizens. Credible administrators, she says, “go on record.” By going on record, they justify publicly their decisions. Dennis Thompson (1987) finds that this practice socializes them to account for their decisions even if citizens will not judge the results for years. Besides enhancing governance and enriching community life, these practices develop the virtuous character of democratic citizens. Political Socialization The development of democratic citizenship is a task of political socialization. Political socialization is concerned with the “personal and social origins of political outlooks” (Dawson, Prewitt, & Dawson, 1977, p. 1). It is the process through which citizens orient themselves to the political community, democratic government, and the civic culture. Political socialization begins early and is lifelong. It takes place in the family, peer groups, public schools, work places, and in political processes, although the quality of these experiences will vary. A liberal education is a vehicle for building citizenship in young adults. For Hanna Gray (1987/1997), this broad education allows young people to reflect carefully about the human condition while encouraging them to use this learning to shape their lives as moral citizens and civilized human beings. Socialization also takes place in university-based MPA Programs and through the associations of professional administrators, such as the American Society for Public Administration (ASPA) and the International City/County Management Association (ICMA). Finally, virtuous administrators socialize citizens. Their transformational practices connect citizens and democratic government. Virtuous administrators are also educators. They teach citizenship, using the experience of the political community. IMPLICATIONS FOR DEMOCRATIC GOVERNANCE The dynamics of interpretations of citizenship and civic duty touch on a recurring question in democratic governance: What is the proper balance between popularly elected officials and public administrators in a liberal democracy? Answers to this question are political ones as much 458 VOGELSANG-COOMBS & BAKKEN as they are matters of law, ethics, and best practice. The terms associated with civic duty -- the “common good,” “the public interest,” “ethical maturity,” and “the virtuous administrator”-- are political terms. Political terms have ambiguous meanings because no consensus exists on their definitions. This definitional ambiguity accommodates multiple normative interpretations of civic duty. For example, citizen-centered norms of civic duty prevail in the literature at the end of the 20 th century. Embedded in these norms is the following proposition: The citizen is supreme in governance, despite what legitimate elected officials want public administrators to do. This is an explosive proposition. It implies that the ultimate duty of the public administrator is to enable citizens to realize their view of the public interest. This proposition makes professional administrators, through their citizenship identity, preeminent over elected officials in democratic governance. As a political proposition, one can place it at an extreme point on a definitional scale of civic duty. Given this conceptual placement, one can better understand why this is a provocative proposition. Moreover, political shifts in a changing environment are inevitable, and they will lead people to challenge the prevailing conventions. For example, before the terrorists attacked America on 9-11-01, national citizenship was a minor identity for Americans. Putnam’s “bowling alone” metaphor captures the view that civic duty was irrelevant in American society. After the attacks, national citizenship has become a primary identity for many Americans. In the catastrophe’s wake, normative interpretations of civic have tipped to the other extreme. These new norms make the preferences of elected officials pre-eminent in American governance. They contain another controversial political proposition: The ultimate duty of public administrators is to enable elected officials to realize their view of the public interest. It implies that the public interest (i.e., the national interest) is whatever the head of state, the nationally elected president, says it is. Inherent in the literature on civic duty are changing political interpretations of “who should govern.” The extreme interpretations clarify that norms of civic duty are part of an ongoing institutional struggle. To accept either extreme interpretation of civic duty literally is to invite “revolution from the left” or “revolution from the right” (Vogelsang-Coombs, 1985, pp. 406-407). Revolution from the left assumes devolution, and devolution, ultimately, means secession. The U.K. and Canada are two democracies where public discussions of devolution divide rather than unify their political communities. DYNAMIC INTERPRETATIONS OF CIVIC DUTY: IMPLICATIONS FOR GOVERNANCE 459 Revolution from the right assumes that the discretion of public administrators places them out of the bounds of office and beyond the control of legitimate political representatives. Ultimately, this means that public administrators could seize power on their own or become a “hired gun” for groups aimed at subverting democratic government. As Herbert Kaufman (1978), Vogelsang-Coombs & Cummins (1982), among others, have pointed out, this view is empirically dubious and should be treated as an allegation of a bureaucracy problem. Given their diversity, structure, ethos, and practices, professional administrators, says Long (1962a, p. 74), are institutional mechanisms for stimulating the conditions that develop nationwide interpretations of experience. John Rohr (1986) notes that professional administrators compensate for the conspicuously undemocratic composition of representative institutions. Larry D. Terry (1995) offers evidence that administrative (bureaucratic) leaders who act as “conservators” preserve the mission, values, and stability of democratic government. Guided by constitutional principles, these conservators are an institutional check on the power of elected officials. In sum, by clarifying different types of citizenship, we have sought to deepen an understanding of civic duty. By uncovering extreme interpretations of civic duty, we have related interpretations of civic duty to an institutional tension between elected officials and public administrators. This tension arises from a fundamental political question in democratic governance. Changes in the normative interpretations of civic duty ease this tension temporarily, but each change, argues Harold Lasswell (1962), serves liberal democracy by channeling social energy into established political institutions. A change in an institutional venue produces a change in the scope of political conflict. However, political institutions do not channel conflict impartially; they elicit reactions and counter reactions. Interpretations of civic duty are dynamic because they are answers to a political question. As answers to a political question, they can never resolve the matter of who should govern a liberal democracy once and for all. In this light, changes in the norms of civic duty take on new significance-- they are institutional expressions associated with the management of an ongoing political conflict. Whether or not citizens’ behaviors literally match the changing prescriptions is secondary to their role in what Lasswell (1962, chap. X) calls “preventive politics.” The political dynamic of changing normative interpretations absorbs social energy, protecting the democratic 460 VOGELSANG-COOMBS & BAKKEN sovereign from the destabilizing effects of an uncontrollable conflict. The accumulation of normative meanings and shared practices allows the political community to change institutional controls over the powers of democratic government without jeopardizing national unity. Within the experience of its political institutions, the democratic sovereign forms and reforms the legal and ethical bonds between citizens and the state. Each time the political community reinterprets these ties, it accommodates changing human conditions while preserving self government. The renewal of citizenship, as expressed in dynamic interpretations of civic duty, intensifies political allegiance to the liberal democratic state. REFERENCES Almond, G. A., & Verba, S. (1963). The civic culture: political attitudes and democracy in five nations. Princeton: Princeton University Press. Aristotle. (1962). The Nichomachean ethics (M. Ostwald, Trans.) Indianapolis, MD: Bobbs-Merrill Company. Bailey, S. K. (1964/1990). Ethics and the public service. In Richter, W. L., Burke, F. & Doig, J. W. (Eds.), Combating corruption/encouraging ethics (pp. 45-53). Washington, DC: American Society for Public Administration. Baldwin, H. W. (1960). Warfare and civilization: An introductory essay. In Thucydides, The Peloponnesian War (4th Printing, H. W. Baldwin, Trans., pp. 1-8). New York: Bantam Books. Barber, B. (1984). Strong democracy: participatory politics for a new age. Berkeley, CA: University of California Press. Berman, E. (1997). Dealing with cynical citizens. Public Administration Review, 57 (2), 105-112. Cooper, T. L. (1991). An ethic of citizenship for public administration. Englewood Cliffs, NJ: Prentice-Hall. Dawson, R. E., Prewitt, K., & Dawson, K. S. (1977). Political socialization (2nd ed.). Boston: Little, Brown and Co. Dewey, J. (1927). The public and its problems. Chicago: Swallow Press: Chicago. DYNAMIC INTERPRETATIONS OF CIVIC DUTY: IMPLICATIONS FOR GOVERNANCE 461 Eberly, D. E. (1994). The quest for a civil society. In Eberly, D. E. (Ed.), Building a community of citizens: Civil society in the 21st century (pp. xvii-xlviii). Lanham, MD: University Press of America. Gray, H. H. (1987/1997). The aims of education. In Boyer, J. W. (Ed.), The aims of education (pp. 63-79). Chicago: The University of Chicago Press. Heywood, A. (1994). Political ideas and concepts: An introduction. New York: St. Martin’s Press. Hult, K.M., & Walcott, C. (1990). Governing public organization: Politics, structures, and institutional design. Pacific Grove, CA: Brooks/Cole Publishing. Kaufman, H. (1978). Fear of bureaucracy: A raging pandemic. Paper presented at the Edmund James Lecture at the Department of Political Science at the University of Illinois. Lasswell, H. D. (1962). Psychopathology and politics (2nd ed). New York: Viking Press. Levine, C.H. (1984/2001). Citizenship and service delivery: the promise of coproduction. In C. Stivers (Ed.), Democracy, bureaucracy, and the study of administration (pp. 280-300). Boulder, CO: Westview Press. Lewis, C. W. (1991). The ethics challenge in public service: A problemsolving guide. San Francisco: Jossey-Bass Publishers. Long, N. (1962a). Bureaucracy and constitutionalism. In C. Press (Ed.), The Polity (pp. 64-76). Chicago: Rand McNally. Long, N. E. (1962b). An institutional framework for the development of responsible citizenship. In Press, C. (Ed.), The polity. Chicago: Rand-McNally. Lowi, T. J. (1979). The end of liberalism. New York: W.W. Norton. Madison, J. (1788/1961). Federalist paper #49. In The Federalist papers (pp. 313-317). New York: New American Library, Mentor Book. March, J. G., & Olsen, J. P. (1995). Democratic governance. The Free Press: New York. 462 VOGELSANG-COOMBS & BAKKEN Newland, C. A. (1987). Public executives: Imperium, sacerdotium, collegium? Bicentennial leadership challenges. Public Administration Review, 47 (1), 45-56. Pitkin, H. F. (1972). The concept of representation (First Paperback ed.). Berkeley, CA: UCLA Press. Putnam, R. (1995). Bowling alone: America’s declining social capital. Journal of Democracy, 6 (1), 65-78. Rohr, J. (1986). To run a constitution. Lawrence, KS: University of Kansas Press. Schattschneider, E. E. (1975). The semi-sovereign people: A realist’s view of democracy in America (Reissued ed.). Hinsdale, IL: The Dryden Press. Shafritz, J. M. (1993a). Pluralism. In Shafritz, J. M. (Ed.), The HarperCollins Dictionary of American government & politics (1st ed. (pp. 354-355). New York: Harper Collins Publishers. Shafritz, J. M. (1993b). Political culture. In Shafritz, J. M. (Ed.), The HarperCollins Dictionary of American government & politics (1st ed., p. 362). New York: Harper Collins Publishers. Smith, R. M. (1997). Civic ideals: conflicting visions of citizenship in U.S. history. New Haven: Yale University Press. Terry, L. D. (1995). Leadership of public bureaucracies: The administrator as conservator. Thousand Oaks, CA: Sage Publications. Thompson, D. F. (1987). Political ethics and public office. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press. Tocqueville, A. de. (1835/1945). Democracy in America (Vol. 2, P. Bradley, Ed.). New York: Vintage Books-Random House. Vogelsang-Coombs, V. (1985). The dialogues of executive reorganization. Unpublished doctoral dissertation. Washington University, St. Louis, MN. Vogelsang-Coombs, V., & Cummins, M. J. (1982). Reorganizations and reforms: Promises, promises. Review of Public Personnel Administration, 2 (2), 21-34.