Price-Taking Behavior

advertisement
Price-Taking Behavior
Author(s): Leif Johansen
Source: Econometrica, Vol. 45, No. 7 (Oct., 1977), pp. 1651-1656
Published by: The Econometric Society
Stable URL: http://www.jstor.org/stable/1913957
Accessed: 16/12/2009 23:41
Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of JSTOR's Terms and Conditions of Use, available at
http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp. JSTOR's Terms and Conditions of Use provides, in part, that unless
you have obtained prior permission, you may not download an entire issue of a journal or multiple copies of articles, and you
may use content in the JSTOR archive only for your personal, non-commercial use.
Please contact the publisher regarding any further use of this work. Publisher contact information may be obtained at
http://www.jstor.org/action/showPublisher?publisherCode=econosoc.
Each copy of any part of a JSTOR transmission must contain the same copyright notice that appears on the screen or printed
page of such transmission.
JSTOR is a not-for-profit service that helps scholars, researchers, and students discover, use, and build upon a wide range of
content in a trusted digital archive. We use information technology and tools to increase productivity and facilitate new forms
of scholarship. For more information about JSTOR, please contact support@jstor.org.
The Econometric Society is collaborating with JSTOR to digitize, preserve and extend access to Econometrica.
http://www.jstor.org
Econometrica, Vol. 45, No. 7 (October, 1977)
PRICE-TAKING BEHAVIOR
BY LEIF
JOHANSENI
A recent paper by D. J. Roberts and A. Postlewaite [1] shows a possible justification for
the assumption that participants in a market behave as price-takers when the number of
participants becomes large. The present note compares this justification with other
approaches to the same question and argues that the various approaches are complementary rather than alternative since, in order to demonstrate the viability of a system with
price-taking behavior, all types of feasible deviations from such behavior must be
explored. The note introduces a taxonomy for such deviations which may be useful in
comparing various approaches and contributions found in the literature.
of price-taking behavior has not been convincingly made in standard economic theory. This is now generally recognized, and
several contributions from the last 10 to 15 years have tried to fill the gap by
studying how incentives for price-taking behavior increase with the size of the
economy, somehow defined in proportion to the transactions of the individual
decision unit. D. J. Roberts' and A. Postlewaite's recent contribution [1] is an
interesting and important addition to this literature. In this note I shall not take
exception to the main part of their analysis. I would like, however, to comment on
their concluding section where they evaluate their results and put them in
perspective by comparing with other approaches.
Roberts and Postlewaite observe, in the introduction as well as in the concluding section, that their results "provide one justification of the competitive
assumption." They compare this with the literature on the core of an economy and
competitive equilibria, more specifically with the analyses which show that the
core shrinks to the set of competitive equilibria when the size of the economy
increases, and they observe that this branch of literature "points to another
possible justification."
In my view these approaches should not be considered as alternative, but rather
as complementary approaches. There is no need to take a stand as to which one is
the more fruitful or realistic; both approaches are needed. The reason for this can
be briefly sketched as follows.
Consider an economy for which a competitive equilibrium exists. We want to
find out whether this is a stable situation, not from a dynamic point of view, but
from the point of view of incentives for deviating from the price-taking behavior
assumed in the definition of the competitive equilibrium. In order to reach a
positive conclusion about such stability it is necessary to explore in principle all
types of deviations from price-taking behavior which are open to the participants.
The various possible actions which might be considered by the decision-makers
can be classified according to the following criteria: In the first place, we may
distinguish between actions which can be taken on an individual basis, and actions
which require the coordinated decisions by more than one agent. In the second
THE CASE FOR THE ASSUMPTION
I am grateful to D. J. Roberts, A. Postlewaite and a referee for interesting communications.
1651
1652
LEIF JOHANSEN
place, we may distinguish between actions which are confined within the rules of
prices and markets, and actions which are not so confined. According to this
classification we have four possibilities out of which only three are relevant, as
indicated in Table I. (Each class could of course be further sudivided according to
other more detailed criteria.)
TABLE I
Actions under
the price and
market regime
Actions not
restricted by
the price and
market regime
Actions taken
on the basis
of individual
decisions
(1)
Studied by
Roberts and
Postlewaite
(2)
(Irrelevant)
Actions taken
by coordinated
decisions by two
or more agents
(3)
Various forms
of collusive
market behavior
(4)
The theory of
the core of an
economy
I shall comment briefly on the various cases represented in the table.
Case (1) represents actions taken on the basis of individual decisions, within the
framework of the price and market regime. This is the case studied by Roberts and
Postlewaite. They show how incentives for actions deviating from price-taking
behavior within this class vanish as the size of the economnyincreases in some
sense. In general one might question the way of posing the problem in this class.
The problem refers to the possibility of taking individual actions. Models permitting the study of such possibilities somehow neglect the fact that there is a buyer
involved in every sales action, and vice versa. Thus purely individual actions are
not possible. A sort of impersonal market pool where all sellers dispose of
commodities supplied, or a market administrator with no objective of his own, is
introduced implicity or explicitly to resolve this problem. However, this problem
is not specific to Roberts' and Postlewaite's study (the fact is that most of standard
micro-economic theory, which forms the basis for general equilibrium theory,
considers only individual decisions),-and we shall not dwell upon it here.2
Case (2) represents actions not restricted by the price regime which will be
actions involving direct exchange of goods. A sort of cooperation or coordination
between two or more agents is necessary; accordingly case (2) in the table is ruled
out as irrelevant (disregarding gifts in kind).
Case (3) refers to actions taken by coordinated decisions by two or more agents
within the framework of the price and market regime. This case is not treated by
2
Recent work by L. S. Shapley and others on "non-cooperative general exchange" could also be
referred to this class (1). It would, however, be beyond the purpose of this brief note to try to survey the
literature.
PRICE-TAKING
BEHAVIOR
1653
Roberts and Postlewaite apart from some elements which are implicit in their
Theorem 2.3 The main problem in class (3) would seem to be the classical problem
of tendencies towards collusive behavior by resource owners and producers (if we
broaden the view so as to consider not only exchange economies). This problem is
of course well known in economic theory at least from Adam Smith's reference to
conspiracies against the consumers. At this point there is hardly any doubt about
the existence of incentives for deviating from price-taking behavior, and there is
of course also ample evidence of the empirical relevance of the problem. The
chances of successful deviation from price-taking behavior are best if one group of
agents can coordinate their actions while other groups remain as individual
price-takers within the framework of the market regime, i.e., other groups are not
able to establish "countervailing power."
Under class (4) come the theory of the shrinking core and other cooperative
game approaches using various solution concepts. In this case it is not assumed
that the agents are restricted in their actions by any price and market regime. The
only restrictions imposed are the ownership restrictions that nothing can be taken
away from any agent without his consent, and the physical restrictions that no
more can be allocated and distributed than what is available initially or produced.
Within the limits set by these restrictions all sorts of coordinated actions are
permitted. In the context of the present note the central result in this field can be
interpreted as saying that no group can gain by breaking away from the rest of the
agents and managing their own resources differently from that which is effected
under the competitive market equilibrium; and, as the number of agents increases
beyond any limit, the competitive equilibrium, with price-taking behavior all
around, is the only solution which possesses this kind of robustness against
formation of coalitions.
Referring back to case (3) an equilibrium with monopolistic behavior in some
branches might appear to be a stable situation under a price and market regime.
TIheresult referred to concerning case (4) implies that such a situation would not
be robust against the formation of coalitions of the type treated under case (4).
This is evident for instance from the fact that a monopolistic equilibrium is not
Pareto optimal with reference to all agents: in such a situation the coalition of all
agents, including resource owners or producers and consumers, would be able to
improve on the situation for all agents involved when they are restricted only by
ownership and physical constraints, i.e., they would "block" the monopolistic
equilibrium.
Summarizing the incentive test for the price-taking equilibrium, Roberts
and Postlewaite cover up case (1)-or at least a quite wide range of cases which
can be classified under (1), and the core theory covers up case (4), while there is no
theory (and can hardly be any) which shows that the incentives for deviating from
price-taking behavior by collusion under case (3) vanish when the number of
agents increases. For case (3) it should however be added that there are, so to
3 See the closing remark by Roberts and Postlewaite referring to the possibility that "choices of
responses may be coordinated."
1654
LEIF JOHANSEN
speak, more dimensions to the incentives issue. If for instance a cartel is formed,
then there will obviously be individual incentives for each member to break out
and supply more than permitted by the cartel if he believes a sufficient number of
the other members will remain in the cartel and contribute to keeping the price
high. This points to an inherent stability problem: In a competitive equilibrium
situation there are common incentives towards collusive behavior; in a market
situation thus established there are again individual incentives to break out.
I think practical experiences bear out these conclusions quite well. In free
markets with many sellers of homogeneous goods there is not much to be seen of
significant deviations from price-taking behavior based on individual decisions,
thus confirming the results for case (1). There is also not much to be seen in market
economies of groups breaking away from the price and market regime, trying to
manage on the basis of their own resources (at least as long as we disregard the
effects of high tax rates, which is another problem than the one considered here).
On the other hand, as already observed, there is ample evidence of attempts at
deviating from price-taking behavior by collusions as under case (3) (as well as
evidence of the inherent instability of this situation as pointed out above).
Accordingly, both from the theoretical point of view and on empirical grounds the
assumption of price-taking behavior seems to be most vulnerable on account of
case (3) in the table.
In a more complete investigation of the likelihood of deviations from pricetaking behavior the consideration of incentivesis however only one side of the
issue. The other side is the practicalpossibilityof deviating behavior. If considerations of incentives fail to produce definitive results, one might add considerations
referring to the practical possibilities to see if more definitive results can then be
established. In case (1) above there is no problem about the practical possibilities
since the actions explored are reasonably simple and based on individual actions
so that there is no organizational problem. Furthermore, in this case no practical
difficulties are "needed" since a definite result is obtained regarding the incentives.
In case (4) the core theory disregards all practical difficulties regarding communication and formation of coalitions. Suppose (hypothetically) that the competitive equilibrium, based on price-taking behavior, did not possess the robustness property so that some coalition might block the competitive equilibrium
solution. Then there would be a need for considerations regarding the practical
possibilities of forming such coalitions. However, since the theorem says that no
coalitions can make a gain for all their members by blocking the competitive
equilibrium, there is no need for further considerations of practical difficulties of
communication and formation of coalitions in order to "save" the competitive
equilibrium on this score.
One might however raise an issue concerning the interaction between the
considerations referring to case (4) and case (3). According to the theory referred
to under (4) only Pareto-optimal solutions are viable (and this holds regardless of
the number of agents). Nevertheless, we observe behavior deviating from pricetaking, and accordingly violating Pareto optimality, as under case (3). It seems
PRICE-TAKING
BEHAVIOR
1655
therefore that, while the theory treating the problems under (4) shows convincingly that incentives for blocking the competitive equilibrium by actions permitted
under class (4) are absent, we observe in practice that other solutions which should
be blocked according to the same theory do survive. For the explanation of this
fact considerations of incentives are not sufficient, i.e., considerations of practical
possibilities of forming coalitions must also be invoked.
For case (3) we have, as already remarked, no theory which shows that the
incentives for deviating behavior vanish even when the number of agents
increases (although the relative strength of the common incentive in favor of
collusion and the individual incentives towards breaking out may change). The
competitive equilibrium can be protected against such behavior to the extent that
there are other factors which prevent deviations from price-taking behavior. The
obvious elements here are of course practical problems of forming groups so as to
counteract the individual incentives towards breaking out, and there are wellknown reasons to believe that these problems increase with the number of agents.
Roughly we might imagine a theorem of convergence towards price-taking
behavior under class (3) which stems not mainly from incentive considerations,
but rather from difficulties and costs involved in organizing groups and controlling
the behavior of the members of groups when the size of the economy increases.4
Anti-trust regulations and other types of interference against collusive behavior
and exploitation of strong market positions are relevant in relation to case (3)
exactly because the incentives for deviations from price-taking behavior do not
disappear, and because the practical difficulties of organization are not always
sufficiently strong to resist the incentives for collusion.
In this discussion we have referred to incentives on the one hand, and practical
possibilities on the other hand. These "practical possibilities" or "practical
difficulties" are not integrated in any analytical construct. This may be all right in
an informal discussion. However, for a more rigorous exploration the possibilities
or difficulties should not be introduced as something from the outside, but should
rather be taken into account in the form of constraints, input requirements, etc., in
the formal description of the set of possible actions and transformations describing the economy. Some recent trends in economic theory which have been
concerned mainly with monetary aspects of general equilibrium, may have
something to contribute in this sphere.
The brief discussion given above can be summarized as follows. In order to
explore the viability of competitive equilibrium, including price-taking behavior,
it is necessary to study its robustness against actions deviating from price-taking
behavior by individual decisions as well as by coordinated actions by groups of
agents, and against deviations within the confines of the price and market regime
as well as against actions not so restricted. This gives rise to the taxonomy
underlying the discussion above. Roberts and Postlewaite cover one of the
possible avenues of deviating behavior. The cooperative game theory, or more
4The necessity of control originates, of course, from individual incentives to break out of, e.g., a
cartel if one believes that the remaining cartel will nevertheless continue and keep prices high; thus
incentives in this sense play their part also in the "theorem" suggested.
1656
LEIF JOHANSEN
especially the core theory, covers another avenue. Roberts and Postlewaite
consider the latter to be an alternative to their own approach. It seems to be more
correct and interesting to consider the two approaches as complements, since all
avenues must be covered in order to demonstrate theoretically the viability of
price-taking behavior. From this point of view case (3) in Table I seems to
represent the most vulnerable point. In this case incentives for deviating behavior
will not disappear even when the number of agents increases beyond any limit.
When incentives fail to vanish, then practical problems of communication,
organization, etc., may prevent deviating behavior. To what extent these factors
work is an empirical matter, but it is evident that they are not sufficiently strong so
as to wipe out the possibilities of deviating from price-taking behavior along
avenue (3) in the classification above.
This note is not meant as a criticism of the main contribution of Roberts' and
Postlewaite's paper, apart from the reservation I have adduced against the way in
which they formulate some of their concluding observations. I have rather taken
their paper as a welcome point of departure for a modest attempt at a sort of
stock-taking to see where we are and how various trends in contemporary
literature fit together in a somewhat broader perspective.
Universityof Oslo
Manuscript
receivedMarch,1976; revisionreceivedOctober,1976.
REFERENCES
[1] ROBERTS, D. J., AND A. POSTLEWAITE:"The Incentives for Price-Taking Behavior in Large
Exchange Economies," Econometrica, 44 (1976), 115-128.
Download