Justice Antonin Scalia vs. Justice Clarence Thomas: The “Originalist Bloc” Divided Andrea Waters Honors Thesis “Theoretical debates about Constitutional adjudication are as old as the Constitution itself” (Gerber pg. 38). There are advocates for almost every type of interpretative method that they believe the Supreme Court “should and ought” to use to make its judicial decisions. The question over how the United States Supreme Court justices should best interpret the Constitution is a raging debate across the country. The debate began in the 1970’s on a small scale but it was brought to the public forefront during the Reagan administration. Originalism is one of the dominating methods in America today and one, which has been embraced by two of the current United States Supreme Court justices, Justice Antonin Scalia and Justice Clarence Thomas. Originalism, also referred to as original intent, is the belief that “text should be construed strictly and should not be construed leniently” (Scalia pg. 23). That the text is to be read exactly as it would have been understood when it was ratified. In the following pages I will be examining the theory of Originalism as well as looking deeper at the jurisprudence of Justice Thomas and Justice Scalia who subscribe to the Originalist interpretive method. In the first part I will be investigating Originalism as well as other popular interpretative methods. The next section will concentrate on Justice Scalia and Justice Thomas and what it is in their past that could have influenced them to become Originalists. The third section of the paper will look at the similarities in jurisprudence between the Justices by analyzing cases in which they join together and agree in an opinion. The last section, the true focus of the paper, concentrates on how it is that these two Justices disagree in many cases and what leads them to do so. I. The Theory of Originalism and Other Interpretive Methods Originalists argue that strict reading is found by interpreting the Constitutional text in a way that fits the intended meaning of the Framers (or authors) of the Constitution. Those who argue for this interpretive method believe the meaning of the Constitution does not change with 1 the times and should not be seen as “evolving”. They argue that the Framers made the Constitution flexible by allowing for an orderly process for achieving evolution. The advocates for Originalism state that if there is a change that needs to be made to the Constitution in order to best resolve or attack a contemporary problem the only way is to follow the amendment process laid out in the Constitution. Keith Whittington, in Constitutional Interpretation, argues that the Constitution will be “seriously undermined if political participants could cynically offer up as constructions, meanings that are recognizably at variance with the text simply in order to avoid the more arduous process of a formal amendment” (Whittington pg. 11). Originalists also claim that if the Court is allowed to interpret the Constitution in a lenient way then this will compromise the neutrality of the Court and will bring political aims into consideration and Justices will be able to “create” law. Many Originalists point to the “right of privacy” used in Griswold v. Connecticut (1965), which was found in the “penumbras” of various amendments in the Bill of Rights, as an example of how the Court has become a place of Judicial Activists. In the case of Griswold, the Court concluded that the Constitution does protect the right of privacy, referencing the “penumbras” of other Constitutional protections. Originalists argue that if the Court is able to cite rights they find in the “penumbras” of enumerated rights it will give judges too much power. Lackland Bloom finds in his research on the history of Supreme Court Constitutional interpretation that the Marshall Court was able to approach the text largely free of precedent but that “subsequent courts were faced with an accumulation of precedent and doctrine, greater access to evidence of the original understanding as more historical evidence became available and significant changes in the social and economic conditions, all this is seen in the evolving work product of the justices” (Bloom pg. 61). 2 Originalists do not agree that there should be the possibility of an evolving work product, but one that stays consistent with the original text. There are, however, many scholars who question whether there is only one type of Originalist. Dennis Goldford, in The American Constitution and the Debate over Originalism, argues that there are two different kinds of Originalists; those whom he says subscribe to “hard Originalism”, the belief that the original meaning of the law is grounded in the intentions of the authors of the Constitution. There are also those who follow “soft Originalism”, that the original intent is grounded in the understanding of those who ratified it as well as the general public at the time of its completion (Goldford pg. 122). Both kinds of Originalists look back to the founding of the Constitution for the answer to a contemporary problem. They differ, however, in if they are looking at the writers or the readers at the time. Justice Scalia subscribes to a type of soft Originalism theory, that the law should be based on what the public at the time of the adoption of the Constitution would have declared the law to be. Scalia believes this to be stricter than allowing Justices to attempt to decipher “intent” of either the authors or of the ratifiers. Others argue that there is a difference between the intent of the authors and the understanding of those who ratified and that it is important which group you look at for their intent. Some scholars argue that the disparity between the ratifiers and the framers is not the main issue because they are both equally difficult to find. Lawrence Sollum states, “all of the problems that attended the equation of constitutional meaning with Framers’ intent seem to attach to ratifiers’ intent. Moreover, evidence may be even more difficult to obtain and the problems of group intention of multiple conventions with multiple members even more confounding with respect to ratifiers’ intent” (Sollum pg. 930). 3 There are other scholars who write of different versions of Originalism; Tara Smith argues in her criticism of Originalism that there are three species of Originalism, “Original Intent, Public Understanding and Textualism” (Smith pg. 162). Though in most cases Originalism is believed to be the same thing as original intent, according to Smith, original intent is the view that a judge is to apply the Constitution as intended by the framers. The “public understanding” view is that it is not the lawmaker’s intent that matters but the ordinary or commonplace understanding of the words’ meaning. Textualism, the one of the three that Justice Scalia advocates, differentiates between the framer’s intent and the words explicitly written (Smith pg.163). Justice Scalia advocates for textualism because believes ruling by intent is just as ambiguous as “living constitution” and allows the interpreter too much discretion. Scalia looks directly at the words that were written and what they meant to the public in the late 18th century. Other individuals who study Originalists who have served on Federal Courts concluded that there are only two different types of Originalists, “conservative originalists” and “liberal originalists”. “Conservative originalists” believe that rights are those created through the democratic process and explicitly written in the Constitution and its amendments; only those rights are to be protected by the Constitution. “Liberal originalists” aim toward the protection of the Jeffersonian principles of individual liberty articulated in the Declaration of Independence”, those endowed by “our Creator” (Sandefur pg. 554). Liberal originalists, such as Justice Clarence Thomas, believe the “Declaration is part of the organic law of the United States and ought to guide our understanding of the Constitution” (Sandefur pg. 490). Conservative originalists disagree, arguing that the Declaration is a world apart from the Constitution and should not be considered when interpreting the Constitution. Justice Scalia is speculated to be a conservative originalist according to many scholars because of his disagreement with using the Declaration as 4 a source of law. As exemplified above, even though Originalism is only one of many theories of interpretation it can also be broken down into different categories. Many believe that Originalism has a strong intuitive appeal because it is an objective reading of Constitutional text, in contrast to the unpredictable decision-making and subjective reading associated with the “living constitution” (Sandefur pg. 555). There have been questions, however, about how the goals of Originalists can be reconciled with the existence of precedents with which they may not agree. Precedent exists to give the Court a rule or principle that it can use when deciding succeeding cases with similar issues. Keith Whittington, a proponent of Originalism, states that “two difficulties emerge: the fact that the use of precedent is one of the tools of legal interpretation itself, and the transition to correct interpretation” (Goldford pg. 169). Many critics of Originalism state that its reputation for not following stare decisis makes it unstable and could cause harm to the judiciary. Even Justice Scalia, a strong advocate of Originalism, has spoken out against those who argue for extensive change to precedent if it is seen as different from the original intent of the statute. An Originalist, Whittington, argues for a gradual transition from non-originalist to originalist law. The argument is that the Originalist Court will only need to gradually change the way in which it interprets different statutes and laws whose previous reading had been inconsistent with the Founder’s design, not every government action that cannot be justified in Originalist terms. For example, one belief is that the Court has strayed from the Original reading of the Commerce Clause and Whittington advocates gradually declaring different laws unconstitutional that are upheld by the past reading of the Commerce Clause. Originalism is a popular interpretive method, but it is not the only one that has many supporters. There are those at the opposite side of the spectrum who believe in a “living 5 constitution”. This is the belief that the Constitution is “a body of law that changes from age to age, in order to meet the needs of a changing society” (Scalia pg. 38). According to the people who subscribe to this view, the Constitution is an evolving document that needs to keep up with the changing values of our nation. “In theory Originalists look at the text, the framers’ intent, and the underlying purpose at the time of the Constitution’s adoption. Nonoriginalists on the other hand, assert that the Constitution is a living document meant to deal with conditions unforeseen at the time of its adoption” (Goldford pg. 60). Living Constitutionalists believe that the Constitution is a dynamic document that should respond to the changing needs of America. They believe that interpreting the Constitution in accordance with the outdated views of the past is not an acceptable policy matter. They argue that the Supreme Court cannot possibly adequately decide what the Framers would have done in many of the current cases which deal with today’s technology and the modern state. They dispute that the framers intention cannot control the resolution of current problems. Promoters of the “living constitution” method of interpretation argue that the court should interpret the Constitution’s broad guarantees taking into account the changing needs and values of the modern society. These advocates state that the living constitution “is a constitution with provisions suggesting restraints on the government in the name of basic rights, yet sufficiently unspecific to permit the judiciary to elucidate the development and change in the content of those rights over time” (Goldford pg. 57). They argue that the Constitution cannot survive if it is not evolving and malleable; if it is rigid it will not be able to accommodate the needs of the people. Advocates of a “living constitution” also counter the popular accusation that they are more subjective than Originalists by stating that Originalists evaluating the “intent” or motive of the Framers depends just as much on what the Justice believes to be true. Another criticism that 6 advocates of the evolving document level at Originalism is that any sequence of words can communicate more than one meaning and to conclude that their one interpretation is the only correct solution is difficult. The debate over the correct constitutional interpretative method makes it clear that there is tension between constraint and flexibility when it comes to reading the words the Framers wrote. From Originalists’ perspective, “to accept constitutionalism is necessarily to accept Originalism; to reject Originalism is necessarily to reject constitutionalism itself” (Goldford pg. 62). Many cite James Madison writings to Henry Lee in 1824 stating, “It is the legitimizing Constitution. And if that be not the guide in expounding it, there can be no security for a consistent and stable, more than for a faithful exercise of its powers” (Madison 1824 pg. 63). Interpreting the Constitution is a very difficult task and both sides of the debate acknowledge this, but disagree on the way forward for the United States Supreme Court. There are also popular alternative theories that have been presented in addition to Originalism and the notion of a “living constitution”. There is the belief that the Constitution should be read in light of the popular will; must regard the will of the people as all important and that the Court needs to take the activist role in leading public sentiment. Supporters of this theory are John Ely, Bruce Ackerman and to some extent Justice Stephen Breyer. This theory centers on the belief that the “Constitution regards the people as sovereign, above even the Constitution itself, which is why judges should be guided by the people’s wishes” (Smith pg. 171). This theory, however, is recognized as an obvious threat to objectivity because the justices are attempting to read the will of all Americans. Another theory seen as very similar to the idea of an evolving document is the interpretive method advocated for by Ronald Dworkin. Dworkin writes that there are values in the law and that each decision is part of an ongoing story. This is criticized also for giving too much power to the individual judges on the Court. Another method, 7 which many times aligns with Originalists, is the idea of “minimalism” and judicial restraint. Supreme Court Justice Sandra Day O’Connor Justice Anthony Kennedy are associated with this theory, which promotes saying no more than necessary to justify the decision in a case and to leave as much as possible undecided (Smith pg. 180). Justice Scalia is also often associated with judicial minimalism along with his originalist beliefs. From the debate above it is easy to see that there are many different interpretive methods. The focus of this thesis, however, is on Originalism and in particular, on analyzing the interpretive methods of the two justices who adamantly subscribe to its methods, Justice Scalia and Justice Thomas. They have both served on the Supreme Court for a number of years and have written many opinions together as the so-called “Originalist bloc”. There are times, however, when they do not agree as to what is the correct Originalist reading of the Constitution and they come to difference conclusions in a case. There are also times when they agree as to the result of the case but their conclusions come from different parts of the text or one Justice believes the other did not go far enough in their interpretation. These occurrences, when there is a disagreement over the correct Originalist perspective are the subject of my analysis. But before delving into the analysis of their differing opinions, we must look at the background of these two Justices and look at what scholars and critics have to say about them. II. Background and Influences of Justice Scalia and Justice Thomas Justice Antonin Scalia was born into an academic family in 1936 in New Jersey. Justice Scalia attended military prep school in Manhattan; he then proceeded to study at Georgetown and Harvard law. He graduated at the top of his class and then began to follow in his father’s footsteps and became an academic and a professor himself. He taught for many years at the University of Chicago but then became active in politics and served in administrative agencies 8 and also as Assistant Attorney General for the Ford Administration. President Ronald Reagan appointed him to the Court of Appeals in 1982. He only served on the Court of Appeals for four years before President Reagan appointed him to the Supreme Court of the United States but he still had enough time to gain a reputation for judicial restraint. While on the Court he became known for his advocacy of judicial restraint and limited interpretation of Constitutional text. When nominated for the Supreme Court, Justice Scalia faced no opposition and gained the seat with a vote of 98-0. At his confirmation hearing, Scalia gave an insight into the type of judge he was about to be; “in any case, I start from the original meaning” (Rossum pg. 21). Scalia writes many articles and books and has become the champion for those who agree with his interpretive method, Originalism. One of his books that is cited the most is A Matter Of Interpretation, a work in which Justice Scalia argues for Originalism and responds to critiques by other scholars. In this writing, Justice Scalia criticizes the judicial decision-making that follows subjective intent and judicial creation of a living Constitution. Supporters of Justice Scalia agree that all Justices should follow this same interpretive method and look to the text, as it would be understood at the time of its inception and ratification. Taking into account the background of Justice Scalia is important when attempting to evaluate how it is that he became the main advocate for Originalism. What in his life has influenced him to become the textualist Supreme Court Justice he is? When asked, “when did you first become an originalist?” he treats the question with much skepticism, stating that he has always been and that it is a popular and universal belief. One significant part of Justice Scalia’s identity, which could have had an influence on his textualism belief, is his religious views. He was raised from a young age to be a devout Roman Catholic. He has even described himself as “old fashioned” Roman Catholic, saying that he preferred the beliefs of the old Vatican of the 9 mid 1900’s. He believes that people should still be praying the rosary everyday as well as observing all of the holy days if they are to be true Catholics. (Lehrer). This is an important fact to know about Justice Scalia because this can give an insight into his Originalist Court opinions. Justice Scalia is an Originalist when it comes to his own religion and the way in which he believes Catholics should observe their faith. He closely reads the rules they are to follow and does not follow the modern phenomenon of a more lenient Catholic Church, but argues that the rules should be followed as they were written. Another reason that Justice Scalia’s religion is of interest is that Catholicism is a more textually based faith than many others. This can contribute to his deeply held belief that text should be read literally. Brisbin, a Professor, contends that Scalia’s Catholic education fostered a textualist methodology of legal interpretation (Brisbin pg. 12). Brisbin refers to testimony by other Catholics raised during World War II, a time Justice Scalia was attending Catholic school, that their education was filled with the “inculcation of a ‘linguistic essentialism’ and ‘obsessed textualism’, or the special pre-Vatican II attention of Catholic education to the use of words to define rules of moral conduct” (Brisbin pg. 13). The argument by Brisbin is that Scalia’s “cultural identity as a person became fused into his constitutional theory” (Brisbin pg. 12). Besides his religion, it is suspected by many scholars that the beliefs of the elder Scalia had a large influence on his son. S. Eugene Scalia was a Professor of Romance Languages at Columbia University. Eugene Scalia translated many texts from their original language into English, a fact that is important when looking at Justice Scalia’s belief that all texts should be read exactly as written. The elder Scalia wrote an excerpt in Carducci: His Critics and Translators explaining his beliefs in the interpretation of text. He states “literalness prevents the translator from yielding to the temptation of following the line of least resistance, that is, the 10 temptation of translating what is unique in the poet of another language by the poetically conventional and stereotyped of his own language” (Brisbin pg. 13). By referring to the writings of his father, scholars like Brisbin infer that the elder Scalia passed on his ideas of the importance of literalness when reading a text on to his son. It is difficult to pinpoint exactly what it is that influences Supreme Court Justices to hold the beliefs they do and the interpretive method they practice. When looking at Justice Scalia, however, one can perhaps see the influence of his early Catholic education as well as his current beliefs about his religion as well as his early family life as the son of a Professor and translator of texts. The background for Justice Clarence Thomas begins rather differently than Justice Scalia though with some of the same steps along the way in their ascension to the Supreme Court. Clarence Thomas was born in Pinpoint, Georgia in 1948. He was born in extreme poverty and very early in life he was sent to live with his grandfather whom he calls “Dad”. He was raised as a Catholic and attended College of the Holy Cross and later attended Yale Law School. He originally began attending seminary with the intent of becoming a Priest but, when he experienced racism, he lost respect for the church because he did not believe it did enough to combat racism. After practicing law for a short period of time in the private sector he eventually was appointed as Assistant Secretary for Civil Rights at the U.S. Department of Education. He was then the Chairman of The Equal Employment Opportunity Commission under President Ronald Reagan. He was then appointed to the Court of Appeals for the District of Columbia Circuit. Justice Thomas writes in his memoir My Grandfather’s Son, that when the rumors began circulating that he would be the next nominee for the Supreme Court he wanted to “avoid going through a confirmation for a job I didn’t want” (Thomas pg. 202). Despite his hesitance, after 11 being on the Court of Appeals for one year and four months Justice Thomas was nominated to the Supreme Court. During his time on the Court he has followed very closely his belief in reading the Constitution in an Originalist way. It is harder to pinpoint the reason Clarence Thomas became an adamant supporter of this school of interpretation. He, like Justice Scalia, grew up as a Catholic and for the same reasons as above he may have been affected by the Catholic belief in reading the text as literally as possible when looking at the moral rules laid down by his faith. Many have referred to Justice Thomas as an example of a libertarian originalist, an originalist who stresses individual liberty and limited government. When looking for the reason for his libertarian beliefs as well as political leanings, he himself cites a few authors who have influenced him. Justice Thomas cited Richard Wright’s novel, Native Son as a book that was very influential in his life. Growing up, Justice Thomas experienced extensive racism and he himself states that he was a very angry person and was disgusted at the way blacks were treated in society. He placed a fifteen-cent stamp on his Yale degree because he believed that is all it was worth. The novel, Native Son, is described as an angry novel in which the main character experiences both white understanding as well as white insensitivity. This could give us an idea as to why he is a libertarian, because he believes that because of the involvement of the government in affirmative action they have made his diploma worth nothing because no one respects his degree. The anger within the novel is said to reflect how Justice Thomas felt during his youth and this anger led to his current distrust of government. Another book Justice Thomas cites as influential in his life is Race and Economics by Thomas Sowell. This book analyzes the relationship between race and wealth within the United States. Within the book, Sowell argues about the comparisons made between “whites” and 12 “blacks” as well as against governmental policies that have been put into place in the United States, discussing the effects of policies such as rent controls and minimum wage laws affect on minorities. This again could have led to Justice Thomas’s disapproval of affirmative action and extensive government involvement in society. In addition, he cites Ayn Rand’s, The Fountainhead as a novel that has influenced him. Ayn Rand is a libertarian whose books stress the need for individuals to be free of regulation and intervention by the government. Justice Thomas requires his incoming law clerks to watch the movie version of the novel before they begin to work for him. This book was said to have influenced his libertarian leanings and his firm belief that the power of the federal government needs to be limited (Bates). In “Clarence Thomas and Native Son” the author argues that “Wright and Rand capture Thomas’ openness to sharp breaks with rule and precedent and readiness to rule in favor of those individuals and corporations that challenge a social welfare state” (Bates). This is an interesting way to look at Justice Thomas’ past and is a way in which some scholars have explained why he holds the beliefs he does. Through his experience as an African-American he has developed hardness against the government and its attempt to make up for slavery and the wrongs done through affirmative action. He states that because of this program, his degree means nothing to the whites that look at it. This argument, however, is very unpopular with the general African-American public and many believe Justice Thomas has parted with those he represents. Though Justice Scalia and Justice Thomas are said to represent the Originalist bloc on the Supreme Court, they came to this position through very different routes. Their reasons for holding the belief system they now do is hard to place, but it can be hypothesized that their upbringing as youth and philosophical and religious beliefs led them to the textualist approach they take today. The belief they share is that the text should be read literally and with originalist 13 jurisprudence. When Justice Thomas was first appointed to the Supreme Court it was widely believed that he would be the understudy of Scalia. It has become clear, however, that “Justice Thomas is not simply Justice Antonin Scalia’s loyal apprentice, no matter how vociferously some seek to establish and maintain this myth. Careful students of the Supreme Court have become increasingly aware in recent years of the distinctions between Justice Thomas’s jurisprudence and Justice Scalia’s” (Gerber pg. 193). III. Supreme Court Cases in Which Justice Thomas and Justice Scalia Agree Before delving into their differences, however, it is important to point out the judicial philosophies they both agree or disagree with. This can be found by looking at cases in which they come to the same conclusion. There are many cases where Scalia or Thomas writes the opinion and the other joins or concurs in the opinion. Justice Thomas and Scalia can be found on the same side if it is a situation where the majority finds justification in the “right to privacy” found in the Bill of Rights. They also do not agree with any mentions of the “living constitution” or any opinions hinting at an evolving state within the United States. A few notable cases in which these Justices agree are Lawrence v. Texas, Roper v. Simmons, McCreary County v. ACLU, Van Orden v. Perry and District of Columbia v. Heller. Lawrence v. Texas (2003) was a case involving the right to privacy found in Griswold v. Connecticut (1965). In this case, individuals Lawrence and Garner are two homosexuals who are arrested for engaging in sodomy, an act that was in violation of Texas law. In a 6-3 decision, the Supreme Court struck down the Sodomy Law in Texas. Lawrence was an important case because the Court overruled Bowers v. Hardwick (1986), a case were the Supreme Court had upheld the constitutionality of a Georgia sodomy law. The majority argued that the law was not right when originally decided. Kennedy, the author of the majority opinion, held that intimate consensual 14 sexual conduct was part of the liberty protected by substantive due process under the 14th amendment. Both Justice Thomas and Justice Scalia were on the dissenting side of this case. Scalia wrote a dissenting opinion that was joined by Thomas and Rehnquist with Thomas writing his own concurring opinion as well. In Scalia’s dissenting opinion he argued that the Court is not respecting the precedent put forth in Bowers and stresses that if they do not respect this precedent, then he wants them to rethink Roe v. Wade (1973). In the case of Roe the Court concluded that a right to privacy under the due process clause of the Fourteenth Amendment extends to a woman’s right to have an abortion. Scalia points to Griswold v. Connecticut; where this “so-called ‘right to privacy’” was established by “pointing to the penumbras of constitutional provisions” and he does not agree that this right exists (2003). This “right to privacy” is also brought up in Justice Thomas’s own dissent. Thomas, in his dissent, argued that the Texas sodomy law is “uncommonly silly” and that if he “were a member of the Texas legislature, I would vote to repeal it” (2003). However, he stated that he cannot vote with the majority because of their use of the “right to privacy”, which he, like Scalia, does not believe exits. The term “uncommonly silly” was first used by Justice Stewart in the case of Griswold when describing laws that forbid the use of contraceptives by anyone (1965). Both Justice Thomas and Scalia align themselves on the dissent side of this opinion because they, as originalists, do not agree with the conclusion by the Supreme Court in 1965 that there exists a right to privacy. As Originalists, they argue that if the Framers of the Bill of Rights did not explicitly state it, it is not a fundamental right protected by the Constitution. Originalists are “kept from joining opinions that rely on legislative history or that expand the words of the Constitution beyond what they meant to those who drafted and ratified it” 15 (Rossum pg. 199). This is evident in the dissents written by Justice Thomas and Justice Scalia, both of whom state their disagreement with the “right to privacy”. Originalists look at the direct text and do not agree with creating a “fundamental right” by looking at other explicitly written rights in the Constitution. Originalists believe that this practice will undermine the authority of the Constitution altogether. In Lawrence, Justice Scalia also refers to the Court’s conclusion that there is “an emerging awareness that liberty gives substantial protection to adult persons”. However, he argues in opposition that “an ‘emerging awareness’ does not establish a fundamental right (2003). As originalists, both Justice Thomas and Justice Scalia do not believe that you can read a law more leniently because you know that it will be better received by a more modern society. Justice Scalia writes in his book, A Matter of Interpretation, “the ‘living constitution’ is a body of law that changes from age to age, in order to meet the needs of a changing society” (Scalia pg. 38). Justice Scalia does not believe that a body of law should be deemed able to “change from age to age” because that would create a sort of “judicial tyranny” giving the Courts the right to take away rights as well as create them depending on the decision they are making. Because the majority in Lawrence is citing the “emerging needs” of a society, the Court is making a ruling according to an interpretive philosophy they, the Originalists, do not agree with. Another case where Justice Scalia and Justice Thomas wrote dissenting opinions arguing against the “living constitution” philosophy is Roper v. Simmons (2005). Roper was a landmark Supreme Court case in which the Court was deciding whether the Eighth Amendment’s “cruel and unusual” punishment clause prohibits the execution of criminals who are under the age of eighteen at the time of the crime. The Supreme Court, in a 5-4 decision, ruled that such executions are unconstitutional. Kennedy writes the opinion for the Court and cites that the 16 “evolving standards of decency” in America make the execution of juveniles unconstitutional. Kennedy also cites the amount of states who still have the death penalty in place for perpetrators under the age of 18 and concludes that the “national consensus against the death penalty for juveniles is similar” and because many states within the United States have abolished the death penalty for minors it is then unconstitutional (2005). Justice Scalia cites his originalist beliefs in his dissenting opinion where he appears to be appalled by the ruling of the Court. He references Alexander Hamilton in Federalist No. 78, in which Hamilton assured New York that “the judiciary… has neither force nor will but merely judgment”. Scalia argues, “what a mockery today’s opinion makes of Hamilton’s expectation” (2005). Thomas joins in Scalia’s heated dissent where he argues that the Court is taking too active of a role in making policy. Originalists disagree vehemently with what Justice Scalia calls judicial activism and this is what he states is happening here. Originalists, such as Thomas and Scalia, also disagree with the Court ever referencing other countries judicial decision-making as evidence for their own opinion. Justice Kennedy, in his majority opinion, looks to “the laws of other countries and to international authorities as instructive for its interpretation of the Eighth Amendment” (2005). Scalia responds that, “the basic premise of the Courts argument- that American law should conform to the laws of the rest of the world- ought to be rejected” (2005). Justices Thomas and Scalia are on the same side in this opinion because, as Originalists, they disagree with any allusion to foreign citations within United States Supreme Court opinions because they, like their stance in the “penumbra” of privacy, believe it undermines the American principles founded in the Constitution. Another area in which you can find Justice Scalia and Justice Thomas in agreement is cases involving the Establishment Clause of the Constitution. The cases where this is most 17 notable is in the cases of McCreary County v. ACLU (2005) and Van Orden v. Perry (2005). In these cases the Court is determining whether it is in violation of the Establishment Clause for public property to display the Ten Commandments. In the case of McCreary County v. ACLU the Supreme Court ruled in a 5-4 decision that the display of the Ten Commandments inside the Courthouse was unconstitutional. The majority, led by Justice Souter, concluded that the purpose had been to advance religion and that to an observer it would appear the government was endorsing religion, which is in violation of the Establishment Clause. Scalia wrote the dissent and was joined by Justices Rehnquist, Thomas and Kennedy (in part). In Scalia’s dissent he cites many of his originalist beliefs on how the Establishment Clause is to be read when looking to American history and the culture of the framers and the importance of religion in their life. Thomas joins Scalia in his dissent that stresses more similarities in their foundation as originalists, the need to look back at the founding of the Constitution to come to an accurate conclusion as to the meaning of a provision of the Bill of Rights. Justice Scalia begins by stating “the fact that the Founding Fathers believed devotedly that there was a God and that the unalienable rights of man were rooted in Him is clearly evident in their writings, from the Mayflower Compact to the Constitution itself” (2005). He then moves on to cite the actions of many members of the founding fathers as evidence of their use of religion in the public forum. He points to President Washington opening his Presidency with a prayer as well as John Adams addressing his Massachusetts Militia; “our Constitution was made only for a moral and religious people. It is wholly inadequate to the government of any other” (2005). Justice Scalia continues his dissent against the majority’s conclusion that the display of the Ten Commandments was moving to advance the religion. He cites James Madison and again 18 stresses, “I have relied upon statements of Founders who occupied federal office, and spoke in at least a quasi-official policy” (2005). Another case that was heard at the same time as McCreary is the case of Van Orden v. Perry (2005) where the plurality of the Court came to the opposite conclusion than in McCreary by ruling that a display of a Ten Commandments monument on state capitol grounds did not violate the Establishment Clause. This ruling was opposite of McCreary because the display was outside on capitol grounds in contrast to being inside the Courthouse. It is obvious Justice Thomas and Justice Scalia’s agreement as Originalists on the matter of the proper reading of the Establishment Clause when looking at Thomas’ concurring opinion in Van Orden. The plurality opinion was written by Justice Rehnquist and joined by Justices Scalia, Kennedy and Thomas. Justice Thomas argues, “The Ten Commandments display at issue here is constitutional. In no sense does Texas compel the petitioner” (2005). He exams the word, “compel” and concludes that “if the Court would return to the views of the Framers” then the Court would not face as many Establishment claims as it does today (2005). In these twin Ten Commandment cases it becomes even more apparent the similarities in the beliefs of Justices Thomas and Scalia. Both argue that in order to make accurate decisions regarding the Establishment Clause, the Court needs to look at the framers of the Constitution. As originalists they believe historical material is “not merely relevant to” but required in the search for textual meaning (Whittington pg. 179). By using the acts of the first Presidents of the United States as well as many actions of the early Supreme Court, Justice Thomas and Scalia call on examples from America’s founding to prove their point that the current Supreme Court is making wrong decision regarding the true meaning of the Establishment Clause. 19 Another landmark case that found Justice Thomas and Justice Scalia in agreement was in District of Columbia v. Heller (2008). In this case, the Supreme Court held that the Second Amendment protects an individual’s right to possess a firearm for private use within the home in federal enclaves. Justice Scalia wrote the opinion for the Court in the first Supreme Court case in history to decide that the Second Amendment protects an individual’s right to bear and keep arms for self-defense. The case originated when a lawsuit was brought in D.C. challenging the Firearms Control Regulations Act of 1975. This Act restricted residents of D.C. from owning handguns, semi-automatic firearms and semi-automatic firearms, but stated that guns owned by police officers or guns registered before 1976 were allowed. Any guns kept at home, however, must be unloaded and disassembled. The Court of Appeals had struck down provisions of the Firearms Control Regulations Act as unconstitutional, and the Supreme Court followed by striking out many remaining provisions as Justice Scalia solidified the position of the Court that individuals who are not affiliated with any state militia can keep handguns for private use. This opinion was written by Scalia and joined by Justices Roberts, Kennedy, Alito and Thomas. Many saw Scalia’s majority opinion codifying an individual’s right to self-defense as a “triumph of Originalism”. This is a significant case wherein Justice Thomas and Justice Scalia are in the majority opinion, Justice Scalia using historical material to support his conclusion. This is another example of the commonality between Thomas and Scalia; both rely on historical evidence from the Founding period to support their opinion. In this case Justice Scalia rules that there is a distinction between the ownership of machine guns and the ownership of handguns for self-defense and private use. The distinction is that the militia at the time of the Second Amendment’s ratification was any group of citizens who were able to be in the military service and that they would bring the sorts of lawful weapons that they owned. 20 Overall, by looking at cases such as Lawrence, Roper, McCreary, Van Orden and Heller, it is clear that both Justice Thomas and Justice Scalia agree on many fronts when it comes to how to read the Constitution in an Originalist way. Both Justices cite many historical examples to support their opinions in their attempt to find the intention of the Founding fathers of the Constitution. They agree that in order to find the intention of the Framers they can look at what was happening in the late 18th century and look at the laws that were passed and the actions immediately following the adoption of the Constitution. It is also apparent by looking at these few cases that both Justices are vehemently opposed to the use of the word “evolving” or “changing standards” to justify the conclusion of the Court. Both originalists believe that the Constitution is not an evolving or “living” document, but a contract that does not change. In cases in which the majority relies on foreign court’s actions or cites any new changes in society these two Justices will be on the dissenting side of the opinion. In cases of the Establishment Clause it is also evident that both Justices believe that the Framers’ intent was for a limited government and that they were not advocating for a government devoid of any religion. They come to this conclusion in many of their opinions by citing the actions of the early government of the United States. On all of these fronts, Justice Thomas and Justice Scalia can be found in agreement. IV. The Differing Jurisprudence of Justice Thomas and Justice Scalia There are, however, many times when these two justices do not agree as to the correct way to rule on a case, or the best way to read a statute or a constitutional precedent. The subject of the cases in which these Justices disagree vary but they center on a few dividing lines. Justice Scalia is much more likely to respect stare decisis than is Justice Thomas. A source of dispute between them is where to look in history to find support in the current case. Justice Thomas will 21 always look back and refer to the founding era of the United States to rule if a law is constitutional or not, Justice Scalia is much more likely to look to the precedent attached to a case and not urge a reassessment. A section of the Constitution that they have disagreed upon as well is the Commerce Clause. Justice Thomas adamantly believes the Court does not read the Commerce Clause as the Framers intended it. Many times Scalia agrees with Thomas that the Clause has become too broad, however, in a few cases he is in support of a broader Commerce Clause reading. Another distinction noted by Rossum in Antonin Scalia’s Jurisprudence is that ‘Scalia’s voting is most closely aligned with that of Justice Thomas- despite the fact that Scalia, operating on logical positivist assumption, rejects Thomas’ natural-rights premises” (Rossum pg. 158). Justice Thomas, unlike Justice Scalia, believes that you can look to the Declaration of Independence to see the rights intended for the citizens of the United States. Justice Scalia argues that rights only exist when they are written in the Constitution or added as an amendment. There are other cases when these Justices simply ask different questions within a case and this leads to differing conclusions. The remainder of the thesis will center on how these two originalists, who are looking to find the exact intention and meaning within the Constitution set forth by the framers, can come to different conclusions in a case? How can two individuals, wanting to look directly at the text for it’s meaning, differ so radically in some of their beliefs? a. In Some Instances, the Justices ask Different Questions of a Case Bradley Jacob, author of “Will The Real Constitutional Originalist Please Stand Up” argues, “even those who agree that the proper interpretive task is not to let the document’s meaning “live” and evolve…may not always agree on the content of that original meaning” (Jacob pg. 630). Jacob is describing the situation that occurred in Hamdi v. Rumsfeld (2004) and 22 the differing opinions of Justice Thomas and Justice Scalia. This case is a good example of one of the ways they can come to different conclusions in a case, if they ask unique questions. In the case of Hamdi v. Rumsfeld the majority concluded that Yaser Hamdi, a U.S. citizen captured as an enemy combatant, cannot be detained indefinitely but must have the ability to challenge his detainment. The case did not have a single opinion that had a majority of justices concurring, but all justices, in some form, agreed that a U.S. citizen couldn’t be denied habeas corpus. Justice O’Connor wrote the opinion for the Court and was joined by Justices Rehnquist, Breyer and Kennedy. Justice Scalia’s dissenting opinion argued for the most restrictions on the Executive Office’s power of detention. Justice Thomas was the lone dissenting opinion, he did not agree that the detainee deserved due process rights but argued that the Executive Branch had very broad powers and could restrict even a U.S. citizen from habeas corpus. This disagreement between the two originalist judges is an interesting phenomenon. Justice Scalia, in his dissent, uses Originalist understanding of the Constitution to argue the Hamdi should be entitled to the full protection of a U.S. criminal defendant. He cited Laws of England from 1765 that promised citizens detained as a prisoner the right of due process. He also states that “these words were well known to the Founders; Hamilton quotes this very passage in the Federalist No. 84” (2004). Justice Scalia is concentrating on the question of “whether there is a different, special procedure for the imprisonment of a citizen wrongly accused of wrongdoing by aiding the enemy in wartime” (2004). He then explores what the original meaning of the Bill of Rights would lead us to believe about what the acceptable practice would be in the Founding era when it came to someone in Hamdi’s position. Justice Scalia cites Court decisions after the War of 1812 to create a parallel with the situation of Hamdi as well as the situation of citizens during the era of the Civil War and President Lincoln’s work to suspend habeas corpus without 23 congressional authorization. Scalia’s conclusion is that “the proposition that the Executive lacks indefinite wartime detention authority over citizens is consistent with the Founder’s general mistrust of military power permanently at the Executive’s disposal” (2004). Justice Thomas, who throughout his opinion cites the works of the Framers and the historical understanding of the Framer’s view of Executive power, takes the opposite position from that of Justice Scalia. For Thomas, the key question is whether the President has the power, according to the war powers under the Constitution during a time of military conflict, to authorize the incarceration of a citizen in Hamdi’s position. Thomas, like Scalia, cites the Founders and the original meaning of the Constitutional text. Like Justice Scalia, he also cites the Federalist papers in order to provide historical evidence. He argues, “See also The Federalist Nos. 34 and 41. The Founders intended the President to have primary responsibility- along with the necessary power- to protect the national security and to conduct the Nation’s foreign relations” (2004). Justice Thomas concludes that the President has extremely broad wartime powers. He cites a case in 1795 in which the Court sided with the President’s broad powers to detain, if necessary, citizens indefinitely. He then argues, “almost 140 years later…the Court explained that the Due Process Clause ‘lays down no categorical imperative’” (2004). This is an important case to examine when comparing Justice Thomas and Justice Scalia as Originalist judges because it is a case in which they distinctly disagree on the outcome of the case while both have Originalist underpinnings to their arguments. Both cite the Founders as well as look to the Federalist Papers. Both Originalists are attempting to find the original meaning of the text to determine who is correct when determining if a citizen in Hamdi’s position deserves habeas corpus. Justice Thomas disagrees strongly, however, with Scalia, stating that he does not “believe that Justice Scalia’s evidence leads to the necessary ‘clear 24 conviction that [the detention is] in conflict with the Constitution or laws of Congress constitutionally enacted’” (2004). In this case, two leading originalists come to opposite conclusions on what the Framers would say about the incarceration of U.S. citizens in time of war. This case is an example of how Justice Scalia and Justice Thomas can disagree. In some cases they ask different questions of a case, and even if they are both referencing the Framers of the United States, they can still come to differing conclusions. Another important case to consider when examining the differences between Justice Thomas and Justice Scalia is the case of Gonzales v. Raich (2005). This is a case, which finds Justice Scalia concurring with the majority opinion and Justice Thomas writing a dissent. This case centers on the power struggle between state and federal power and the question of how to best apply the Commerce Clause, and if the Clause even applies to the growing of marijuana for medicinal use. In this case the majority concludes that Congress has the power to ban marijuana for non-medical uses, and this leads the Court to conclude that banning growing marijuana for medicinal use is a way to stop others from gaining access to the drug. The majority opinion is written by Stevens and is joined by Kennedy, Souter, Ginsburg, and Breyer with a concurrence by Justice Scalia. Justice Scalia in his separate concurrence writes that he voted for limits on the Commerce Clause in previous cases but that his reading of the Necessary and Proper Clause causes him to vote the way he does. Justice Thomas writes a dissent where he states “certainly no evidence from the founding suggests that “commerce” included the mere possession of a good or some purely personal activity that did not involve trade or exchange for value” (2005). Justice Thomas cites founding principles from the beginning of the United States in order to support his conclusion that Raich should be constitutionally able to grow medical marijuana. Thomas looks 25 to his dictionaries and historical texts to find support; “throughout founding-era dictionaries, Madison’s notes from the Constitutional Convention, the Federalist Papers and the ratification debates, the term commerce”, he writes, meant trade or exchange, not any activity that could somehow be construed to be commerce. Justice Thomas finds his conclusions by looking at the framers and his perception of their understanding of the Commerce Clause. Justice Scalia goes a different route in a concurring opinion with no mention of the founders but to past cases and the “pattern” put forth by the Court in their past decisions. This is an important part to note in this analysis of how these two Justices come to different conclusions in this case. Justice Scalia appears to deviate from his Originalist stances in order to cite past cases and precedent and not only Constitutional history. Eric Claeys conducts an analysis of the Gonzales decision in his article “Raich And Judicial Conservatism at the Close of the Rehnquist Court”. Claeys writes that this case is a perfect example of the struggle Justice Scalia and Justice Thomas have to both fulfill their role as Originalists. Claeys writes that Scalia “sparred with Justice Thomas about how to apply the principles of constitutional interpretation they are supposed to share” (Claeys pg. 793). Claeys writes that though both Justices are committed to Originalism there are tensions between Originalism and minimalism. “Justice Thomas and Justice Scalia both favor Originalism and judicial minimalism, but Justice Thomas stresses the former over the latter, and Justice Scalia the latter over the former” (Claeys pg. 793). It is evident in this case that Justice Scalia is siding with minimalism because he is voting with a majority that is supporting a broad reading of the Commerce Clause. In most cases, Scalia is opposed to a broad reading of the Commerce Clause but in this case instead of advocating for change, he follows his beliefs of judicial restraint and votes with precedent. This is an example of minimalism because Justice Scalia wants Justices to 26 do as little as possible. Justice Thomas is willing to question the current reading of the Commerce Clause and recommend a return to a narrower reading. Justice Scalia is willing to side with precedent even if it goes against the Constitution’s original meaning. Justice Scalia argues for restraint in judicial discretion. In most cases this will put him beside Justice Thomas and the Originalists but in this case, when citing the current precedent of reading the Commerce Clause it became apparent Scalia would rather have minimalism than Originalism. In Originalism: The Lesser Evil Scalia admitted he was “ready to “adulterate it [Originalism] with the doctrine of stare decisis” (Claeys pg. 800). The Gonzales case is important because it is a case in which Justice Scalia is concurring with the majority that is citing a precedent he does not agree with. Justice Thomas, on the other hand, writes a dissent in which it is very apparent that he is much more opposed to encroachment of the federal government on state sovereignty. Some analysts cite the Gonzales case as an example of why Justice Scalia is a “faint-hearted Originalist”, because he was siding with the Justices who argue for an “evolving” Constitution and refused to confront and refute the originalist analysis that Justice Thomas puts forth. This is an important case to scrutinize when looking at the differences between Justice Thomas and Justice Scalia because it is further evidence that they do differ on the way that they implement their judicial beliefs. Both may be looking for Originalist meaning in the text but Justice Scalia is much more likely to not rule for that reading because it would involve major changes to past precedents put forth by the Court. b. Justice Scalia Minimalism v. Justice Thomas Questioning of Precedent How can these Justices come to different conclusions if they are both advocates of looking at the direct text? The question of precedent is a very important subject when looking at how these two Justices can differ in the way in which they rule. One of the major reasons Scalia 27 and Thomas can disagree in some cases is because of their differing understandings of the force of precedent. The following cases are those in which Justice Thomas is either in a separate concurring or dissenting opinion than Justice Scalia because he is stressing the need to change a precedent. In these cases, Justice Scalia is not found forming the “bloc” that many cite when looking at Scalia and Thomas. According to Justice Scalia, "Clarence Thomas doesn't believe in stare decisis, period. If a constitutional line of authority is wrong, he would say, let’s get it right. I would not do that” (Foskett). It is important to dissect cases in which Thomas and Scalia differ to see if this statement by Scalia proves correct. Looking at cases such as U.S. v. Lopez give a good example of Justice Scalia and Thomas agreeing on an outcome but with Justice Thomas separating himself from Scalia in order to promote change to a precedent. Lopez was the first Supreme Court case since the New Deal to determine that Congress had gone too far in exercising its powers under the Commerce Clause. In the majority opinion, written by Chief Justice Rehnquist, the Court ruled that Alfonso Lopez, a student who had been caught in his High School with a weapon, could not be charged in violation of the federal GunFree School Zones Act of 1990. The Court concluded that it would be a very slippery slope in which the Federal Government had too much power if they were allowed to regulate almost any activity regardless of its connection to “commerce”. Rehnquist states in his opinion that if they ruled in favor of the government they would be “hard pressed to posit any activity by an individual that Congress is without power to regulate” (1995). In Justice Thomas’s concurrence in U.S. v. Lopez (1995) he argues, “in future cases, we ought to temper our commerce clause jurisprudence…more faithful to the original understanding” (1995). Justice Thomas, though he agreed with the majority (which was joined 28 by Justice Scalia), wrote a separate concurrence in order to stress that the Court needs to narrow the Commerce Clause reading they have had in the past. In this case “Thomas made one of his most powerful appeals to original meaning textualism…Courts entire Commerce Clause jurisprudence since the New Deal has strayed” from the Original meaning of the text (Jacob pg. 609). In his opinion Justice Thomas refers to the Founders and how the word “commerce” was used and discussed at the time of the writing and ratification of the Constitution. This concurring opinion is important when looking at the relation between Justice Thomas and Justice Scalia because of Scalia’s failure to join Thomas’ concurrence. Scholars who have analyzed this case and these two justices argue that Justice Thomas “disturbed all Court precedent that conferred on Congress power to regulate interior trade or the productive activities that generate good or service for trade” (Claeys pg. 801). Claeys argues that Scalia did not sign on to Thomas’s concurrence because he is not as committed to the original reading of the text as he is to past precedent. In the case of McIntyre v. Ohio Elections Commission (1995) Justice Thomas states, “while, like Justice Scalia, I am loath to overturn a century of practice shared by almost all of the states, I believe the historical evidence from the framing outweighs recent tradition” (2005). Another case in which Thomas and Scalia disagree on the appropriate reading of the Commerce Clause is the case of Printz v. U.S (2007). In this case, Scalia writes the majority opinion and Justice Thomas writes a separate concurrence. Justice Scalia, the majority opinion writer, rules that provisions of the Brady Handgun Violence Prevention Act are unconstitutional. This Act worked to establish a national background check system individuals would be run through in order to own a handgun with the intent of preventing the sale of a firearm to a forbidden person. This is an interesting case when looking at the jurisprudence of Justice Scalia and Justice Thomas because Scalia does conduct textual analysis but some scholars have called it 29 “lesser” textual analysis. Justice Scalia refers to the Founders who wrote the Constitution and argues that the Constitution was designed to allow federal regulation of interstate dealings but not internal matters that are strictly within the state. This reasoning leads Scalia to conclude that it would be unconstitutional for the Act to compel a state official to administer a federal program. It is obvious within Justice Thomas’ concurrence that he does not believe that Justice Scalia went far enough in limiting the expansion of federal power in the future. Thomas proposes deciding the case of Printz on either of two separate grounds, lack of power under the Commerce Clause, or by relying on Justice O’Connor’s Tenth amendment reading from a past case. Justice Thomas’ concurring opinion is another excellent example of the differences between the two originalist judges. Both look to the Founders to find the reasons this Act is unconstitutional but Justice Scalia leaves the question much more open than Thomas wants. According to Claeys, “Scalia sought doctrine that would leave courts to enforce clear and manageable rules. Justice Thomas’ concurrence suggested that he would at least consider federalism theories that might force the Court to butt heads with Congress” (Claeys pg. 809). This case is another example of the tension between minimalism and Originalism. In this case, Scalia sides with minimalism, whereas Justice Thomas calls for a majority opinion that would bring Commerce Clause jurisprudence closer to what he believes the Founders had intended. The belief in judicial minimalism is the belief that “judges have policy-making discretion in the course of interpretation, but then seek to minimize that discretion as much as possible” (Clays pg. 793). This is a good case to analyze when looking further at the contrast between the Originalism jurisprudence of Scalia and that of Thomas. Justice Thomas, in this case, continues to “believe that we must temper our Commerce Clause jurisprudence and return to an interpretation better 30 rooted in the Clause’s original meaning” (2007). Justice Scalia, in contrast, declared this specific Act unconstitutional but did not make a move to limit federal power even though he has been on record for supporting a narrower Commerce Clause, much like what Justice Thomas is supporting in his opinion. Minimalism trumps the move back to “original meaning” in this case for Scalia, another important note when looking at how these two Justices differ in their opinion. Most members of the public who refer to themselves as Originalists argue that looking to the Framers of the Constitution and the text itself is the best way to make the “correct” judicial decision. But even when vehemently arguing for a return to a narrow reading of the text, most do not argue for the reexamination of some of the first precedents set by the Supreme Court of the United States. In the case of Eastern Enterprises v. Apfel (1998) Justice Thomas does just this. In his concurring opinion he signals a willingness to reconsider the case of Calder v. Bull, a case decided in 1798. In the case of Eastern Enterprises, the plurality opinion of the Court finds the Coal Act passed by Congress, which required coal operators to pay pension for past employees, unconstitutional. Justice O’Connor, author of the opinion, argues that the Coal Act is an unconstitutional regulatory taking of property even with compensation, which required the Act to be invalidated. The importance of this case, however, is Thomas’ short concurring opinion. In his opinion he writes that the reading of the Ex Post Facto Clause of the Constitution by the Court should be under review. He also concludes “in an appropriate case, therefore, I would be willing to reconsider Calder and its progeny” to the reading of the Ex Post Facto Clause. The conclusion of Calder was that Ex Post Facto only applies to criminal cases; Justice Thomas argues that it should not be so limited. This is a notable opinion because though Justice Scalia joins the plurality opinion he does not join Thomas’ concurring opinion. This opinion is unique because it 31 shows that Justice Thomas has committed himself to what he believes is the original way to read the Constitution and he is willing to overturn very old precedent to accomplish these aims. This case again shows Justice Scalia not signing on to this version of Originalism. c. Justice Thomas the Libertarian vs. Justice Scalia the Social Conservative Besides appearing to hold different views of precedent, some also point out that Justice Thomas is a libertarian whereas Justice Scalia is more of a social conservative. Those who adhere to the political philosophy of libertarianism uphold individual liberty and freedom. Social conservatism is the belief that the government’s role is to protect and encourage traditional values and behaviors. Scholars analyze times that Thomas’ libertarian streak clashes with the social conservative views of Justice Scalia. Examples of this lie in the differing opinions of Justice Scalia and Justice Thomas in the First Amendment case of McIntyre v. Ohio Elections Commission (1995) as well as the separate dissenting opinions of Thomas and Scalia in Kelo v. City of new London (2005). In the McIntyre case, the majority ruled that an Ohio statute that outlawed anonymous leaflets was unconstitutional. Justice Thomas writes a concurring opinion while Justice Scalia dissents. Justice Thomas concurs with the opinion but writes separately because he does not agree with Stevens’ taking into consideration the “expressive value” of the anonymous speech to the speaker and society (1995). Thomas wants the majority to conclude that there is an absolute right to anonymous leafleting, not just because the society agrees with it right now. In his concurring opinion Justice Thomas refers to The Federalist Papers written by Hamilton under the pseudonym “Publius” as an example of anonymous leafleting happening at the time of the Constitution’s framing. Despite his originalist argument and mention of the framers and the origins of the Constitution, Justice Scalia is not on the concurring side of the opinion, but a part of the dissent. 32 He begins his dissent by admitting “the question posed by the present case is not the easiest sort to answer for those who adhere to the Court’s (and society’s) traditional view that the Constitution bears its original meaning and is unchanging” (1995). His dissent, like Thomas’ concurrence, cites United States founding history extensively as well as the time of Constitutional framing. But his dissent is different than Justice Thomas’ because he cites something other than original meaning, “the widespread and longstanding traditions of our people” (1995). This is interesting to note because when looking at the expressed beliefs of Justice Thomas and Scalia they do not agree with looking at the “evolving” society when making decisions on the Court. In this case these two Justices fall on the opposite sides because Justice Scalia writes that he would have agreed with Thomas had it not been that many states had been outlawing anonymous leafleting for years. This is a fascinating twist to the analysis of this “Originalist bloc” made up of these two Justices. When one justice refers to a changing standard of society, the other disagrees passionately. This is also an example of the tension between Thomas’ liberal Originalism and Scalia’s social conservative Originalism. This case is cited as such because Justice Thomas wants the government to be more hands-off when it comes to the right to free speech whereas Justice Scalia is advocating for states rights; their right to make their own laws. Justice Scalia makes a conservative argument when supporting that certain public values are promoted if there are limitations on free speech whereas Thomas does not support any limitations if they will in any way limit an individual’s right to free speech. Justice Thomas, following libertarian beliefs, aims to protect individual liberty rather than “upholding the authority of government to prevent social disruption” (Sandefur pg. 554). Justice Scalia agrees that some limitations may be acceptable, whereas Thomas argues vehemently that there are no exceptions. This is another example of 33 Justice Thomas’ absolutist version of Originalism, that people have the absolute right to free speech, Scalia is more of a moderate if there are social values to be found in these limitations they may be justified. This is a disparity between Justice Thomas and Justice Scalia that needs to be noted. O’Neil argues that the McIntyre case is a time when “Scalia specifically disagreed with Thomas’ originalist concurrence” and the fact that “the Court originalists did not march in lockstep” is an interesting occurrence to note (O’Neil pg. 208). Kelo v. City of New London is another case scholars cite when arguing that sometimes Justice Scalia and Thomas part ways when it comes to a question of a libertarian or conservative reading of the text. In this case both Thomas and Scalia are on the dissenting side of the opinion. Justice Thomas, however, signs on to the dissent but also provides his own, which Justice Scalia does not sign on to. This case is cited in Randy Barnett’s critique of Justice Scalia as a representative of Originalism. Barnett calls him “faint-hearted” and cites this case as an example because he states that in Kelo, Scalia fails to endorse the originalist justification for a result he agrees with (Barnett). But when reading the dissenting opinion of Justice Thomas it become obvious that these two justices disagree not because of the justification given but because of a differing opinion on the best way to read the “public use” part of the takings clause. Kelo centered around the question of whether the government can constitutionally claim homes and other private property for “public use” even if the government itself will not be using the property. The majority opinion, written by Justice Stevens, concludes that yes, the city may claim private property under the Fifth Amendment as long as the development intends to benefit the community. The dissenters, made up of Justices O’Connor, Thomas, Scalia and Rehnquist, were shocked by the majority’s conclusion and wrote scathing dissents from the opinion. In 34 Justice O’Connor’s dissent, which Justice Scalia joins, she argues that the “Founders could not have intended so perverse a result” (2005). O’Connor’s dissent argues against this “reverse Robin Hood” conclusion that would allow the government to take property for other private parties. The dissent counters the majority opinion by stating that “public use” must mean a public project not an indirect land grab by investors. The majority, however, cites the evolution of the term “public use” to the term “public purpose.” Justice Stevens justifies that “public purpose” is a “broader and more natural interpretation of public use” (2005). In this case Originalists Scalia and Thomas agree that the framers of the Constitution would not have wanted the takings clause to be read so broadly. But Justice Thomas writes a dissent that goes further than O’Connor’s dissent that Scalia joined. Justice O’Connor’s definition of public use could technically include private ownership such as taking land for the creation of a privately owned hospital. Justice Thomas, in his dissent where he cites the meaning of public use at the time of the framing as well as other citations to early Takings Clause jurisdiction, argues that any plan to take property from one private party in order to give it to another violates “public use” under eminent domain. The fact that Justice Scalia does not sign on to Justice Thomas’ dissent is important. This signals that he does not agree with the approach that Thomas takes, which is to embrace a full limitation on the government from taking private property not exclusively for public use. This could be a reason that some scholars cite this case as an example of Justice Scalia, the conservative, vs. Justice Thomas the libertarian. A conservative would most likely leave some room for interpretation of the takings clause that would possibly allow the government to transfer property from one private owner to another. A libertarian, however, would make much of the argument that Justice Thomas does. The government needs to be limited extensively and not 35 given the power to take property for “public purpose”. Liberal Originalism supports the Jeffersonian principles of individual liberty expressed in the Declaration of Independence. Again, as in McIntyre, an individual has the absolute free right to not have their property taken from a private entity, Justice Scalia sides with O’Connor that though it should not happen, there are specific times when it may be allowed. This is another example of Justice Thomas, the absolutist and libertarian, in opposition to Scalia’s conservative Originalism. For this reason, many scholars cite these differing social beliefs as reasons that these two Justices disagree on some constitutional reading questions. Outside parties, however, have assigned these social beliefs to the Justices; Justice Scalia and Thomas have not confirmed them themselves. A case that is interesting to note is the case of U.S. v. Bajakajian (1998). In this case Justice Thomas writes the majority opinion while Justice Scalia joins the dissenters. This case is notable because in this case Justice Thomas parts from the conservative bloc of the Court to vote with Justices Stevens, Souter, Ginsburg and Breyer, those seen as members of the liberal bloc. This case is the only time in history that the Supreme Court has held that a fine imposed on an individual was in violation of the Excessive Fines Clause of the Eighth Amendment. Hosep Bajakajian had attempted to leave the United States with $357,144, which he failed to report to the United States customs. The government required that he forfeit the entirety of the money. The interesting part of the case is that all of the Justices agreed that if a fine is grossly disproportionate to the offense then it is excessive. The case, however, was a divided court of 5-4 in the end. This case is beneficial to look at when comparing Justice Thomas and Justice Scalia because both Justices agreed that a fine can be disproportionate, but Justice Scalia does not agree on how to apply that general standard to the facts of the Bajakajian case. This is an example of 36 both justices agreeing on the reading of the Constitution and the fact that a fine can be too excessive but they do not agree on how to apply it to the case before them. In this case Thomas and the majority, held that a “punitive” forfeiture violates the Excessive Fines Clause of the Eighth Amendment if it is grossly disproportional to the offense it is designed to punish. The dissenters, which Justice Scalia joined, accused the majority of not showing deference to the judgment of Congress that the crime of failing to report money leaving the country is a serious one. David Smith, in his article examining the Bajakajian case writes that Justice Thomas breaking from the conservative ranks was not very surprising in this case. He writes that Thomas “has repeatedly expressed his strong misgivings about the government’s overzealous pursuit of harsh forfeitures” but had never voted against one because he had not had a good reason as to why it was unconstitutional” (Smith). Thomas argues that the Constitutional provision has been breached and that the government has taken their right to fine too far. This case is an example of Thomas’s belief that the Constitution is meant to limit the government and that the modern era has allowed the Government too much leniency in exercising its power. This is another case in which it appears that Justice Thomas opposes government power more fervently than Justice Scalia. Justice Scalia is protecting Congress’s right to apply the fine because it promotes the social value to prevent drug use. Justice Thomas, as a libertarian, argues that if taking the entire money amount being taken out of the country is not excessive than what is excessive? Libertarians are also known for not being in support of Congress’s role in the drug war. Also to be noted is that the application of the Originalist theory is sometimes a reason for the disparity between the justices. They both agreed in this case on the basic fact that the fine is extremely high, but Justice Scalia did not agree with Justice Thomas that the method he put forth was the 37 best. This is important because these Originalist justices are seen as a solid force, which always agrees, but this case is another example proving that this is not always true. d. Differing Views on the Declaration of Independence and Natural Rights One of the largest differences in jurisprudence between Justice Thomas and Justice Scalia, besides precedent and the possible social differences that guide them to differing conclusions, is the way in which they view the role of natural rights and their application to Supreme Court decisions. They “disagree about whether Originalism is limited to an interpretation of the Constitution’s language only or whether the political- philosophical context of the Constitution’s framing should factor into the analysis” (Sandefur pg. 553). Timothy Sandefur argues that “Scalia’s greater reliance on stare decisis is not the only or even the most interesting source of dispute between the Justices, their differences center largely on their different views of the proper role of natural rights in an originalist interpretation”(Sandefur pg. 553). Justice Thomas has expressed his belief that “American politics and the American Constitution are unintelligible without the Declaration of Independence” and the expressed beliefs within it that there are certain un-enumerated rights endowed by “our Creator” (Epstein). Justice Scalia does not reject the doctrine of natural rights but “believes that natural rights are political concepts that should be relied upon by political branches not by Courts” (Sandefur pg. 553). Justice Scalia has argued that if the Court is to protect a right that you believe exists then a law needs to be enacted. He has made it apparent that he does not believe in justifying a ruling based upon unwritten rights. This difference in approach to natural rights in apparent in the case of Troxel v. Granville (2000). In this case the Supreme Court strikes down a Washington State law that allowed any third party to petition the state court for child visitation rights against the wishes of the parent. This case was brought by grandparents of two young girls who petitioned 38 for the right to visit the daughters of their son who had died. The mother objected to the amount of time the grandparents sought to spend with the girls. The Supreme Court ruled that the Fourteenth Amendment protects the fundamental right of parents to make decisions concerning their children. Justice Thomas concurred with the majority and its use of this fundamental right as the basis of their decision. Thomas hints that un-enumerated parental rights should be protected when he states, “neither party has argued that our substantive due process cases were wrongly decided and that the original understanding of the Due Process Clause precludes judicial enforcement of un-enumerated rights under that constitutional provision” (2000). This case is a perfect example of the differences between the two Justices and their willingness to apply natural rights to their court opinions. This case is also an explicit example of Justice Scalia’s disinclination to use the Declaration of Independence as a source of Constitutional construction. In his dissenting opinion he argues, “the Declaration of Independence, however, is not a legal prescription conferring powers upon the courts” (2000). Justice Scalia expresses his agreement with the conclusion the Court reaches but that he does not agree with their use of “what is (in my view) that un-enumerated right” (2000). Thomas Standefur argues, “on matter of un-enumerated rights, federalism, and the nature of Originalism, Justice Thomas’ liberal Originalism differs significantly from Scalia’s conservative Originalism” (Sandefur pg. 554). Because Justice Thomas is looking to natural rights referred to in the Declaration of Independence as a source of Constitutional Interpretation, and Justice Scalia believes justices can only support their opinion with an enumerated right, Thomas continues to be referred to as the more liberal justice of the two. Some scholars argue that Thomas’s natural rights approach is far truer to the Constitution as a natural right document. 39 He is seen as a “liberal originalist”, however, because his “aim is more to the protection of individual liberty rather than upholding the authority of the government to prevent social disruption” (Sandefur pg. 560). Both justices are looking to the Constitution and the framing of the document for the justification for their opinions but they disagree about what documents from the framing can be applied and used. This is one of the most interesting examples of how two judges committed to the same textual answer to a Constitutional inquiry can come to very different conclusions and end up on opposite sides of an opinion. Troxel is a good example of this. Both Scalia and Thomas agree on the conclusion, but Scalia does not believe that you can refer to the Declaration of Independence and “fundamental rights” not specifically expressed in the Constitution. Scalia says Courts can only protect rights that are specifically mentioned, not endowed by “our Creator”. For this reason, Justice Thomas is in the majority and Justice Scalia is in the dissent. V. Conclusion Scholars do admit, “There are disputes as to the meaning of Originalism itself (Sandefur pg. 555). There are distinct differences in the Originalist jurisprudence of Justice Thomas and Justice Scalia. Both have expressed their following of the philosophy of “Originalism…the original meaning of the text-applies to present circumstances that should govern judicial interpretation of statutes and the Constitution” (Scalia pg. vii). Many times they do agree as to the way to rule on the cases that come before them. As seen in the Supreme Court cases from above both of these Justices disagree with the use of foreign country’s courts jurisprudence as justification for a majority opinion, as in the case of Roper. If there is a mention of the practice of a different country, these Justices will be on the dissenting side together. Both also are adamantly against the use of the terms “evolving” Constitution or “changing society” as reasons 40 for a Court decision. If the majority concludes a decision based on the needs of a changing America or on “penumbras” found in the Constitution, both Justices will be found together in the opposition. For these reasons, Justices Thomas and Scalia are many times found on the same side of the bench. The voting alignment in non-anonymous cases finds Justice Thomas and Scalia agreeing 75% of the time. When looking at the number of cases Thomas and Scalia join the majority; Thomas joins 57.8% of the time, Scalia 56.7% of the time. Ralph Rossum concludes that Scalia has come to this percentage as a “direct result of his textualism, which keeps him from joining opinions that rely on legislative history or that expanded the words of the Constitution beyond what they meant to those who drafter and ratified it” (Rommus pg. 199). This way of voting in cases is consistent with both Justices. Both are attempting to decipher what it is the framers were intending with the words they used in the Constitution. However, despite voting in alignment on many cases, Justices Thomas and Scalia “did not understand or practice Originalism in precisely that same way” (O’Neil pg. 210). Both Justices Thomas and Scalia are looking to find the Original meaning of the text but it is not always true that they come to the same conclusion. As can be seen from the cases cited above there are many differences in jurisprudence that keep Justice Thomas and Justice Scalia from agreeing 100% of the time. Justice Thomas is much more likely than Justice Scalia to be willing to overturn Court precedent to get back to what he believes to be the original meaning of the text and the correct way to rule in a certain case. Justice Scalia values judicial minimalism as more of a priority than overturning precedent in order to get back to an original meaning he may even agree with. For this reason, there are many cases in which Justice Scalia will not be found joining Justice Thomas’s concurrences or dissenting opinions because Thomas is calling for much more dramatic action than Justice Scalia agrees with. 41 Another substantial reason that these two Originalists fail to come to the same conclusion on all of the cases that come before them is because they do not agree about the use of natural rights when making decisions. Justice Thomas is much more likely to cite the Declaration of Independence as a source of justification for a decision while Justice Scalia does not agree that it is an adequate source of inquiry. Another reason that these two justices are not always on the same side is because of a simple difference in the reading of the question being asked the Court or simply when they look to different sources when making their decisions. For all of the reasons listed above these two justices do not always agree in every case that comes before them. The cases referenced above are only a few of the cases in which the jurisprudential differences of the two justices are very apparent. When looking at the differences mentioned above between these two Justices, it is clear that it is a very difficult challenge to attempt to find the original meaning of the Constitution. Also, this is only the analysis of two Supreme Court justices; there are many more judges on Courts throughout America as well as members of the public who are considered to be Originalists. Originalism is a difficult interpretive method to uphold because it is hard to agree on what the sole original meaning is. This is true for interpretive methods as a whole. No one would tell you that they are making decision without basing any of their reasoning on the Constitution of the United States. Even those who subscribe to the “living Constitution” would tell you that they are looking to the text to find the conclusion to the case before them. For this reason, interpreting the Constitution with the attempt to make the “correct” decision is difficult. For this reason, it is not surprising that when comparing two justices who agree as to how to best interpret the text, it becomes obvious that they do not come to the same conclusions every time. 42 But even with an inquiry into why it is that these two Justices can disagree, it is obvious why it is that they are seen as a solid block to most of the public. When looking at the Court today these two are trying their best to find the textual answer to whatever question is asked. And many times, because some of the Court’s members are followers of a more “living” constitution, these two are found side by side on many decisions. Justice Scalia is the more expressive of the two Justices by far. He has written many articles and one book as well as given many speeches about his method of interpreting the Constitution and attempting to convince people that it is the best way to do so. Justice Thomas is much less likely to speak about his philosophy on voting. He speaks of natural rights and original meaning in what interviews and articles he has been a part of but he is the much more aloof of the two. In the end however, many members of the public still look at them as the “Originalist bloc” on the Supreme Court. And until more people look into their individual jurisprudence and personal history this is the legacy that will stay with these two Justices for the many years to come. 43 Works Cited Barnett, Randy. Scalia’s Infidelity: A Critique of Faint-Hearted Originalism. University of Cincinnati Law Review, Vol. 75, No 7. 2006. Bates, Robin. Native Son. 9 June 2009. Harper Collins Publishers. Bloom, Lackland. Methods of Interpretation: How the Supreme Court Reads the Constitution. The Quad Vol 41, No. 1. Fall 2010. SMU Dedman Law. Bowers v. Hardwick (478 U.S. 186 (1986)). Brisbin, Richard. Justice Antonin Scalia & The Conservative Revival. 28 September 1998. Johns Hopkins University Press. Calder v. Bull (3 U.S. 386 (1798)). Claeys, Eric. Raich and Judicial Conservatism at the Close of the Rehnquist Court. 23 November 2005. Lewis & Clark Law Review Vol. 9, Num. 4. District of Columbia v. Heller (554 U.S. 570 (2008)). Eastern Enterprise v. Apfel (524 U.S. 498 (1998)). Epstein, Aaron. The Supreme Court: Natural Law According to Clarence Thomas. The Seattle Times. 30 August 1991. Foskett, Ken. Judging Thomas: The Life and Times of Clarence Thomas. Harper Collins Publishers. 2005. New York, New York. Gerber, Scott.First Principles: the Jurisprudence of Clarence Thomas. 1999. New York. University Press. Goldford, Dennis. The American Constitution and the Debate Over Originalism. Cambridge University Press. 2005. New York, New York. Gonzales v. Raich (545 U.S. 1 (2005)). 44 Griswold v. Connecticut (381 U.S. 479 (1965)). Hamdi v. Rumsfeld (542 U.S. 507 (2004)). Holzer, Henry Mark. The Supreme Court Opinions of Clarence Thomas, 1991-2006. 2007. McFarland & Company , Inc., Publishers. Jefferson, North Carolina. Jacob, Bradley. Will the Real Constitutional Originalist Please Stand Up? April 2007. Creighton Law Review. Kelo v. City of New London (545 U.S. 469 (2005)). Kroft, Steve. “The Private Clarence Thomas”. 12 October 2007. 60 Minutes. cbsnews.com Lawrence v. Texas (539 U.S. 588 (2003)). McCreary County v. ACLU (545 U.S. 844 (2005)). McIntyre v. Ohio (514 U.S. 334 (1995)). Lehrer, Jim. Ifill, Gwen. “Examining the ‘Life and Constitution” of Antonin Scalia”. 7 January 2010. PBS Newshour. pbs.org O’Neil, Johnathan. Originalism in American Law and Politics: A Constitutional History. 2005. The Johns Hopkins University Press. Printz v. U.S. (521 U.S. 898 (1997)). Roe v. Wade (410 U.S. 113 (1973)). Roper v. Simmons (543 U.S. 551 (2005)). Rossum, Ralph. Antonin Scalia’s Jurisprudence. 28 March 2006. University Press of Kansas. Sandefur, Timothy. Clarence Thomas’s Jurisprudence Unexplianed. New York University Journal of Law & Liberty Vol. 4.No. 535. Sandefur, Timothy. Liberal Originalism: A Past for a Future. Spring 2004. Harvard Journal of Law & Public Policy. 45 Scalia, Antonin. A Matter of Interpretation: Federal Courts and the Law. 1997. Princeton University Press. Princeton, New Jersey. Smith, David. Forfeiture. The Champion: National Association of Criminal Defense Lawyers. Aug 1998. www.nacdl.org Smith, Tara. Why Originalism Won’t Die- Common Mistakes in Competing Theories of Judicial Interpretation. 2007. Duke Journal of Constitutional law & Public Policy. Sollum, Lawrence. District of Columbia v. Heller & Originalism. 2009 Northwestern University Law Review. USA Vol. 103: No. 2). Thomas, Clarence. My Grandfather’s Son: A Memoir. 2007. Harper Collins Publishers. Troxel v. Granville (530 U.S. 57 (2000)). U.S. v. Bajakajain (524 U.S. 321 (1998)). U.S. v. Lopez (514 U.S. 549 (1995)). Van Orden v. Perry (545 U.S. 677 (2005)). Whittington, Keith. Constitutional Interpretation. 1 September 1999. University Press of Kansas. 46