Get - Wiley Online Library

advertisement
Engineering Ethics: What? Why? How?
And When?
CHARLES EDWIN HARRIS, JR.
Department of Philosophy
Texas A&M University
MICHAEL DAVIS
Center for the Study of Ethics in the Professions
Illinois Institute of Technology
MICHAEL S. PRITCHARD
Department of Philosophy
Western Michigan University
MICHAEL J. RABINS
Department of Mechanical Engineering
Texas A & M University
ABSTRACT
Engineering ethics is professional ethics, as opposed to personal
morality. It sets the standards for professional practice, and is only
learned in a professional school or in professional practice. It is an
essential part of professional education because it helps students
deal with issues they will face in professional practice. The best way
to teach engineering ethics is by using cases—not just the disaster
cases that make the news, but the kinds of cases that an engineer is
more likely to encounter. Many cases are available, and there are
methods for analyzing them. Engineering ethics can be taught in a
free-standing course, but there are strong arguments for introducing ethics in technical courses as well. Engineering is something
that engineers do, and what they do has profound effects on others.
If the subject of professional ethics is how members of a profession
should, or should not, affect others in the course of practicing their
profession, then engineering ethics is an essential aspect of engineering itself and education in professional responsibilities should
be part of professional education in engineering, just as it is in law
and medicine. Probably few engineering educators would disagree
with these claims; their implementation in engineering education
is another matter. We want to discuss the introduction of engineering ethics into engineering education in terms of four questions: What is engineering ethics? Why should it be emphasized in
engineering education? How should it be taught? and When
should it appear in the student’s education?
I. WHAT?
We begin with an obvious but important distinction, that between morality and professional ethics. Morality , as we shall use
April 1996
that term, refers to those standards of conduct that apply to everyone rather than only to members of a special group. Ideally, these
standards are ones that every rational person wants every other to
follow, even if everyone else’s following them would mean that he
or she had to do the same. We were all quite young when we
learned such basic moral rules as: don’t lie; don’t kill; don’t cheat;
keep your promises; don’t steal; and so on. We were still quite
young when we learned that these rules have exceptions (for example, “except in self-defense” for “don’t kill”).1 Now and then, we may
change our view on how to interpret a particular rule or exception—
for example, we may come to think that it is possible to lie without
saying anything false (for example, by omitting some fact necessary
for understanding what we do say). But, since we entered our teens,
such changes have been few and relatively marginal. Our students
are much like us. They arrive in class more or less morally mature.
We have little to teach them about ordinary morality.
Not so with professional ethics. By “professional ethics” (henceforward in this paper, just “ethics”) we refer to those special morally
permissible standards of conduct that, ideally, every member of a
profession wants every other member to follow, even if that would
mean having to do the same. Ethics applies to members of a group
simply because they are members of that group. Medical ethics applies to people in medicine (and no one else); business ethics applies
to people in business (and no one else); and engineering ethics applies to engineers (and no one else).1,2
The special standards that constitute engineering ethics are what
are to be taught. They have been formulated in different codes of
ethics, in formal interpretations of those codes, and in the less formal
practices by which engineers pass on the special ways they do things
to each new generation of engineers. So, except for those students
lucky enough to have a mother or father who is an engineer, no one
is likely to learn much about engineering ethics except at engineering school or while practicing engineering. Engineering ethics is as
much a part of what engineers in particular know as factors of safety,
testing procedures, or ways to design for reliability, durability, or
economy. Engineering ethics is part of thinking like an engineer.
Teaching engineering ethics is part of teaching engineering.
II. WHY?
Why teach engineering ethics? One possible answer is the long
and familiar list of tragedies, disasters, and scandals in which engineers have been major players. Something should be done about all
these bad things. This answer, what we can call the big news/bad
news approach to ethics education, seems to miss the mark. Although these incidents should be a matter of concern to all of us,
and especially to engineering students, who can learn from past
mistakes, they are exceptional rather than ordinary occurrences in
Journal of Engineering Education 93
engineering. Most engineers will never be involved in such newsworthy circumstances.
Big news for the media is usually bad news. This is why, when
audiences are asked to think of media coverage of ethical issues in
engineering, they come up with a familiar list of disasters: the collapse of the Hyatt-Regency walkway in Kansas City, the Challenger
disaster, the Bhopal disaster, DC-10 crashes, and so on-and on. But
an exclusive focus on big news/bad news events may encourage engineering students to think of ethics as primarily about others—those
relatively few engineers who have the misfortune of being involved
in something newsworthy. And they may take comfort in the
knowledge that, despite some bad press for a few engineers, national
surveys usually place engineers near the top of the list in regard to the
public’s confidence in the ethics of the professions.3
However, rather than relying on media coverage of disasters or
public surveys for an answer to the question, “Why teach engineering ethics?,” we suggest looking elsewhere. Some years ago the
Hastings Center, an ethics think tank in New York, brought together educators from a broad range of disciplines to talk about
what should be the common goals of ethics education in colleges
and universities.4 One goal they identified was to stimulate the ethical imagination of students. Too often, the educators agreed, young
professionals get caught by surprise when faced with an ethical
problem in their professional practice. Never having seriously
thought about such a problem, they may not handle it well.
Another, related Hastings Center goal is to help students recognize ethical issues. Although a conflict of interest may be lurking
around the corner, it may not announce itself to the involved parties
until matters have gone too far. For example, what counts as a conflict of interest in engineering practice—as well as precisely why it is
an ethical problem—may not be obvious to the uninitiated. So, a
third Hastings Center goal comes into play: to help students analyze
key ethical concepts and principles that are relevant to the particular
profession or practice. Other concepts come to mind—public health
and safety, quality, usefulness, efficiency, cost/risk/benefit analysis,
environmental harm, truthfulness, trustworthiness, loyalty.
Many of these concepts are “messy.” They resist the sort of precise definition engineering students might want. Even if there are
paradigms for, say, “safe” or “unsafe,” there are areas of vagueness
and uncertainly. Algorithms that do justice to the ethical issues are
hard to come by. So, yet another Hastings Center goal applies: to
help students deal with ethical disagreement, ambiguity, and
vagueness. The trick is to acknowledge that some disagreement and
uncertainty can be expected and should be tolerated, but to refuse to
accept the view, “Everyone’s opinion is as good as anyone else’s
when it comes to ethics.”
There is one more Hastings Center goal that merits attention:
to encourage students to take ethical responsibility seriously. In one
sense, this should not be difficult for engineering students, once
they reflect on the obvious fact that engineering is not just a technical or theoretical enterprise. Inherent in the exercise of engineering
expertise is the provision of useful, if not essential, services to
clients, employers, customers, and the public. Usefulness, quality,
safety, efficiency, and cost effectiveness are not secondary features
of this activity. They are its heart. So are reliable judgement and
trustworthiness. So, if we examine what engineers do, and not simply the technical content of engineering textbooks, it is easy to see
that ethical responsibility should be a central concern of the engineering profession and practice.
94
Journal of Engineering Education
We believe the goals elaborated by the Hastings Center provide
good reasons for teaching engineering ethics, but there are additional goals as well. Teaching ethics can increase student sensitivity
to ethical issues simply by making students aware that they, as engineers, will have to resolve certain ethical problems. Just being exposed to a few examples of a particular problem, having them identified and explained, will make it more likely than otherwise that
the students will see a problem of that sort when it arises on the job.
Why teaching ethics might have that effect is not hard to understand. The mechanism is precisely the same as for learning to see
technical problems. Practice sharpens perception.
Teaching engineering ethics can increase student knowledge of
relevant standards. A student who reads a code of engineering
ethics is more likely to know what is in it than a student who does
not read it . A student who has to answer questions about the code
is more likely to recall the relevant provisions than one who has not.
And so on. Knowledge of standards includes more than just knowing what is written in codes or handbooks. Part of knowing standards is understanding the rationale for them (especially the consequences of departing from them). For example, part of teaching
students to take operating costs into account when designing something is pointing out how uneconomical the design is if they don’t.
Teaching engineering ethics can improve ethical judgement.
Ethical judgement, like technical judgement, tends to improve with
use. If a professor of engineering gives students a chance to make
ethical judgements, explain them, and compare them with those
other students make, the student is more likely to judge well than if
she gets no such experience. The classroom and laboratory provide
a safe place to make mistakes and learn from them—ethical mistakes as well as purely technical ones.
Finally, teaching engineering ethics can increase a student’s ethical will-power. One might say, “Surely the classroom and laboratory are not the place for that.” Think again. Isn’t an engineer who
knows that he shares a particular standard of conduct with other
engineers more likely to follow it than one who believes himself
alone? One benefit of discussing ethics in the classroom is that it
shows students how much consensus there is (among engineers) on
most standards of engineering ethics. There is power in numbers.
That is one source of will-power.
III. HOW?
There is widespread agreement that the best way to teach professional ethics is by using cases. There are several modes of ethical
analysis that can be useful in treating cases. We shall discuss two of
them.(For fuller accounts, see reference 5) Both methods are based
on concepts and even expressions that we use in everyday experience when we talk about moral problems.
One of these expressions is “drawing the line.” We often ask
where we should draw the line between acceptable and unacceptable actions. Let us consider a case that illustrates this first mode of
ethical analysis, which we shall refer to as resolving a line-drawing
problem.
Engineers often face the problem of accepting gifts from vendors. On the one hand, most engineers probably believe that accepting a cheap plastic pen from a vendor is permissible. On the
other hand, all engineers believe it is not permissible to accept a
$10,000 check from a vendor to specify a product that is both infeApril 1996
rior and more expensive. But where do we draw the line between
these two extremes? Suppose a vendor offers to take us to the local
country club for golf, or to sponsor us for membership in the country club. Suppose he invites us to a seminar in Hawaii, where his
company and ours split the expenses. Suppose he invites us to a
seminar in Hawaii, all expenses paid. Where do we draw the line?
In the line-drawing method, we compare the controversial case
to noncontroversial cases, i.e. to the cases where there would be little doubt that the action is right (accepting the plastic pen) or
wrong (accepting the $10,000 bribe). By isolating the similarities
and differences between the controversial case and the noncontroversial cases, we are usually able to decide whether a controversial
action is morally acceptable.
Now let us turn to the second mode of ethical analysis. Another
term that we often use in referring to moral problems is “conflict.”
We say that we are in a conflict over an issue, meaning that we feel
pulled in two different directions by competing considerations.
Here we must engage in resolving a conflict problem.
The popular videotape “Gilbane Gold,” produced by the National Society of Professional Engineers, presents a classic conflict
problem.6 In the story, a young engineer, David Jackson, the environmental engineer at ZCORP, faces a problem. His job requires
him to sign documents certifying that the plant discharge into the
local sewer meets city regulations, when he suspects that it does not.
To make matters worse, the contaminants in the plant’s discharge
are arsenic and lead, and the sludge from the water treatment plant
is made into a fertilizer (Gilbane Gold) which is used by local farmers. Plant management does not want to spend any more money to
treat the discharge, and David believes that he could lose his job if
he presses the issue too far.
David’s situation can best be described as a conflict problem. His
major conflict is between his obligation to be a loyal employee and
his obligation to protect the health of the public. Both obligations
are legitimate. What should he do?
David needs to do some brainstorming. In fact, the importance
of imagination in resolving ethical problems cannot be overemphasized, whether they are line-drawing or conflict problems. David
should first think of what we call creative middle ways, i.e. actions
that will enable him to meet all of his apparently conflicting obligations. For example, David might try to find a technical solution to
the problem. This would enable him both to protect the citizens’
health and to protect ZCORP. Failing this, he might suggest to his
manager, Diane, that she, along with other managers of high-tech
plants in the area, approach the city with the problem in a non-confrontational way. He might encourage her to argue that the plants
and the city have a mutually beneficial relationship that should be
preserved and that the problem can be solved if they work together.
Unfortunately, creative-middle-way solutions are not always
possible. Then more difficult choices must be made, in which some
obligations must be given priority over others. David might have to
tell his superiors that he will not conceal anything from city authorities. He might even have to refuse to sign any more documents
that certify that ZCORP’S discharges are within city regulations.
As a last resort, he might have to resign and go public, if he believes
the situation is serious enough.
There is now a considerable body of cases in engineering ethics
for case analysis. The Ethics and Values in Society (EVS) Program
at the National Science Foundation, under the direction of Dr.
Rachelle Hollander, has funded several projects designed to create
April 1996
cases. One, at Western Michigan University, developed a set of 33
cases, each focused on a single issue. The cases came from the experiences of practicing and retired engineering managers and focus on
the kinds of situations a practicing engineer is likely to encounter.
Each case is followed by discussion by a board of commentators.7
Another project, at Texas A&M University, developed a set of 11
cases taken mostly from real-world situations.8 The cases are presented with student handouts, instructor’s guides and recommended transparencies for classroom use. Each case is specifically aimed
at a particular required course (or courses) in the engineering undergraduate curriculum.
The National Society of Professional Engineers has case material available under the title, “Professional Engineers in Education
(NSPE-PEE).”6 An electronic disc containing eight cases with
guidelines is available from the Murdough Center for Engineering
Professionalism and Ethics at Texas Tech University, directed by
Dr. Jimmie Smith.9 Dr. Pennington Vann, also at the Murdough
Center, has developed a bibliography on engineering ethics, including a listing of video tapes, such as “The Truesteel Affair”10 and “To
Engineer Is Human.”11 Dr. Michael S. Pritchard and others at
Western Michigan University are developing cases that deal with
the avoidance and prevention of wrongdoing in engineering.12
IV. WHEN?
We believe students should be introduced to ethics in as many
times and places inside and outside the curriculum as possible.
Guest lectures, presentations to student chapters of professional societies and many other possibilities present themselves.
Another possibility is to have a single, free-standing, non- technical elective course. At some schools, engineering departments
offer seminar courses on engineering ethics. Elsewhere, such freestanding, non-technical electives are offered by philosophy departments. At Texas A&M, the course is taught by both an engineer
and a philosopher. The course consists of one-hour lectures on
Monday and Wednesday and a two-hour recitation section on Friday, which is devoted to case analysis. The usual format for the Friday session is to have a student act as a scribe to summarize the results of the class discussion on the blackboard. The instructor is
then free to move around the room and encourage student discussion, in accordance with the line-drawing, conflict-resolution and
other methods of case analysis.
Another approach is to introduce engineering ethics into required
engineering courses. This approach has the advantage of teaching engineering ethics in a way that brings home how integral engineering
ethics is to engineering practice. One way is to use videotapes or
cases, such as the ones mentioned in the previous section.
Still another way is simply to enhance student awareness of ethical issues. (See reference 13.) For example, in a course on electrical
circuits, an instructor might take a moment now and then to point
out the practical effect of getting a problem wrong: “These circuits
are typically used in aircraft navigation systems; a small error here,
combined with two common errors of pilots, could cause a crash. In
practice, your calculations will be checked many times, but some errors slip through. The easiest way to prevent disaster is to get the
problem right the first time. Next problem.” Even a few such comments in the course of a semester can help engineering students see
the practical context of highly abstract calculations: both the relaJournal of Engineering Education 95
tion of those calculations to such ethical concerns as safety and the
relation of their education to what they want to do after graduation.
Another easy way to provide information about ethics is to pass
out a code of ethics at the beginning of the term and refer to it often
enough during the term so that students get the idea it would be
good to read it. An instructor can mention that such-and-such a
provision makes engineers responsible for the safety of what they
help to make. It is surprising how many engineering faculty have
not read a code of engineering ethics. Needless to say, their students
are even less likely to have read a code. Just exposing students to a
code is therefore a significant contribution to their ethics education.
V. CONCLUSION
Engineering ethics appears to be emerging as a distinct discipline, taking its place with medical, legal and business ethics. We
believe the time is approaching when most if not all engineering
schools will have some program for introducing students to engineering professionalism and ethics. The time for thinking about
implementing such programs has arrived.
REFERENCES
1. Michael Davis, “The Moral Authority of a Professional Code,”
NOMOS 29 (1987), pp. 302-337
2. Michael Davis, “Thinking Like an Engineer: the Place of a Code of
Ethics in the Practice of a Professional,” Philosophy and Public Affairs 20,
Spring 1991, pp. 150-167.
3. The Gallup Poll Monthly, July, 1992, p. 3.
4. Daniel Calhoun, “Goals in the Teaching of Ethics,” in Ethics Teaching in Higher Education. ed. by Daniel Callahan and Sissela Bok (New
York: Plenum 1980).
5. C.E. Harris, M.S. Pritchard, and M.R. Rabins, Ethics in Engineering: Concepts and Cases, Belmont, CA: Wadsworth, 1955, pp. 127-143.
6. National Society of Professional Engineers, 1420 King Street,
Alexandria, VA 22314. Tel: 703-684-2882.
7. Michael S. Pritchard, ed., “Teaching Engineering Ethics: A Case
Study Approach,” NSF Grant No. DIR - 8820837. Available through the
Center for the Study of Ethics in Society, Western Michigan University,
Kalamazoo, MI 49008-5022. Tel: 616-387-4380.
8. R.W. Flumerfelt, C.E. Harris, Jr., M.J. Rabins, and Charles H.
Samson, Jr., “Introducing Ethics Case Studies Into Required Undergraduate Engineering Courses,” NSF Grant No. DIR 9012252. Available from
M.J. Rabins, Department of Mechanical Engineering, Texas A&M University, College Station, TX 77843. Tel: 409-845-2615.
9. The Murdough Center for Engineering Professionalism, College of
Engineering, Texas Tech University, Box 41023, Lubbock, TX 794091023. Tel: 806-742-3525.
10. Fonlight Productions, 47 Halifax Street, Boston, MA 02130.
11. Films Inc. Video, Education Department, 5547 N. Ravenwood
Ave., Chicago, IL 60640. Tel: 800-323-4222, ext. 323
12. M.S. Pritchard, “Ethics in Engineering: Good Works.” NSF Grant
No. SBR-9320257.
13. Michael Davis, “Ethics Across the Curriculum: Teaching Professional Responsibility in Technical Courses,” Teaching Philosophy 16, September 1993, pp.205-235.
96
Journal of Engineering Education
April 1996
Download