EUROSPHERE Research Notes Research Note No.16, 2008 Reflections on Social Movement Actors Ahmet Öncü Reflections on Social Movement Actors Ahmet Öncü In his highly abstract yet compelling portrayal of the last 200 years of politics Craig Calhoun (2000:147) suggests that “under one label or another, the public has been opposed to the private; the economic to the aesthetic; the rationalist to the romantic; secularization to revival; and institutionalization to nascent movements intent on breaking free”. I would like to offer Calhoun’s reminder as a point of departure for our inquiry into social movement actors. We may approach social movement actors -in distinction with other social and political actors included in our research framework- by seeing them as “nascent” mobilizations “intent of breaking free” from the constraints of a political regime perceived as ignorant of certain forms of “life” in its abstraction of “sociation”, to use a concept introduced to sociology by Simmel. The notions of “being nascent” and “having the intention of breaking free” from the limitations of established social and political life are not only central for framing various types of collective action as social movement but also critical for locating them in the politics of diversity. Needless to say, it is the latter that is most relevant and interesting for our purposes. Let me begin with a disclaimer. The following discussion does not aim at coming up with a well-written scholarly paper. It does not offer a comprehensive synopsis of the stock of knowledge and its discontents in what is known as “the social movement literature”. It rather aims to initiate a dialogue within our team in regard to the conceptualization of social movement actors. This brief document has four parts. First, I suggest a provisional working definition of social movement. Second, I use a particular categorization of contentious politics in order to be able to differentiate forms of social movement. Then I hint at how we may try to conceptualize organizational features of social movements. Finally, I offer a list of questions that partners may find useful in selecting as well as examining the selected social movements before they go out to do the interviews. 1- A Provisional Working Definition The definition of social movement is always a controversial issue because of the multiparadigmatic nature of the field. In his succinct overview of the state of the art in the literature, Diani (2000: 157) identifies four main paradigms: 1) “Collective Behavior” perspective developed by Turner and Killian; 2) “Resource Mobilization Theory” formulated by Zald and McCarthy; 3) “Political Process” perspective represented primarily by Tilly; and 4) “The New Social Movements” approach introduced by Touraine and Melucci. Diani draws the following conclusion from his overview: “Different approaches to the field share, in their definitions of ‘social movement’, the emphasis on some specific dynamics. In particular, three basic components of social movements have been identified: networks of relations between a plurality of actors; collective identity; conflictual issues.” Diani goes onto tell us that “anti-institutional styles of political participation” and “antisystemic attitudes” are not conceived as distinctive characteristics of the concept of social movements. Agreeing strongly with the first part of Diani’s reading, I would like to emphasize one of the practical implications of it for our purposes: If we want to designate “a EUROSPHERE RESEARCH NOTES No.16 ÖNCÜ social and political actor” “social movement” we must be able to show that this “actor” is constituted as a “network of relations” among a set of collective as well as individual actors who share an identity constructed for taking a position on a conflictual issue. The second part of Diani’s conclusion is more exigent than the first one, and unfortunately a far cry from offering us an apparent rule of thumb because it is not clear at all what “anti-institutional style of participation” means and how it differs from “an institutional style of participation”. The conceptual fuzziness here derives from the difficulty in distinguishing non-institutional acts from anti-institutional acts. An act can be noninstitutional yet at the same time be lacking the feature of being anti-institutional. This is simply because the realm of politics is always dynamic and political acts are constantly being transformed as a result of ongoing political and social interactions. In other words, noninstitutional political acts can be taken within the framework of institutional politics without changing the core of this framework, and thus go unnoticed, ignored or permitted by the powerful actors occupying the commanding positions of the establishment. I can give a funny yet hopefully an illuminating example: can anybody argue against the fact that drinking a bottle of fine French wine in a Turkish kebap restaurant is a non-institutional act? I guess nobody with a sober mind can do this because one habitually drinks raki at a kebap restaurant. Nevertheless, does this show us that this very non-institutional act is also an antiinstitutional act? Unlike the first question, there seems to be no clear cut answer here. The best we can say is this: “It all depends on the intention of the “contender”, how this noninstitutional act is perceived by the “defender” as well as how the intention of the contender interacts with the perception of the defender. In other words, a non-institutional act can become an anti-institutional act if the “conflictual issue” between the non-institutional actor and the authority in charge of securing the status quo moves them –either actually or perceptually- beyond the limits of acceptable political forms of contention. What if the kebap restaurant owner bans drinking French wine in his/her premises! Will the drinker keep silent and order raki now or make claims that may shake the very foundations of kebap restaurant? What if the wine drinker, after obtaining the opportunity to drink wine first, now says: “Vous nous aveza apporte la mauvaise commande. J’avais voulu un le plateau de fromages”. The moral of the story is this: There must be a threshold up to which non-institutional acts can be accommodated within the boundaries of institutional politics. But once this threshold, however it is defined, is left behind, all non-institutional political acts can be potentially framed as anti-institutional. That means that we are in an ambivalent field of politics when it comes to social movements. After this clarification we can now move on to one of the most up-to-date attempts that aims at providing an all-inclusive definition of social movement – (please note the emphasis on the notion of institution and compare it with Diani’s suggestion). The Blackwell Companion on Social Movements gives us the following definition: Social movements can be thought of as collectivities acting with some degree of organization and continuity outside institutional or organizational channels for the purpose of challenging or defending extant authority, whether it is institutionally or culturally based, in the group, organization, society, culture or world order of which they are a part. (Snow, et.al., 2004:11) Given the definition, it is evident that we are interested in a collective actor somewhat excluded from “institutional” channels and hence acts unconventionally. The institutional channels are under the control of an “authority” appearing to be based not only institutionally but also culturally, i.e. as a life world. The contending actor is factually non-existent in the regular politics. Yet the same actor all of a sudden shows up “with the purpose of challenging or defending extant authority”. It is the notion of challenge that is central in the identification of a collective actor as a social movement. Whether the challenge takes on an offensive or 2 EUROSPHERE RESEARCH NOTES No.16 ÖNCÜ defensive mode seems not to be the crucial question. Another point to emphasize is that our collective actor challenges the authority together with the ones who share in that authority even if they are not directly participating in the actions of that authority (i.e., the authority is also culturally based). So, to conceive our collective actor “with some degree of organization” as a “social movement” or “a citizen initiative”, we must be in a position to show that the contending actor is a contestant in the realm of routine institutional and routine cultural politics for it collides with the establishment in one way or another. This form of political acts raises issues that challenge directly or indirectly the limits of the authority. Therefore in order to differentiate social movements from other social and political actors we need to specify the relation of the collective actors to the authority with respect to the issue of the legitimacy of that authority (I will return to this point below). So I continue with the following hypothesis: Social movements make controversial claims that cannot be easily resolved by the authority because they are outside the routine political functions and political traditions of that authority. Because of this, such political claims are almost always linked to ideological cleavages as well as clashes of moral values – which are often related to the foundations of the state. In this sense it is not off-the-wall to say that “social movements” are critical actors because they are critiquing actors. They are present in the absence or rather the glossed over regions of public politics. Here comes the troubling question. If social movements are not part of the politics of establishment but they are implicated in it, how will we be sure about the “social movementness” of a political mobilization? Indeed this a question Tilly (1999:257) poses to us and then he answers: How, then, will we recognize a social movement when we see one? It consists of a sustained challenge to power holders in the name of a population living under the jurisdiction of those power holders by means of repeated public displays of that population’s worthiness, unity, numbers, and commitment. It is not too difficult to see that Tilly conceptualizes social movements as “contentious displays”. Thus, for him (Tilly, 1999:261), worthiness, unity, numbers, and commitment (as performances displayed by the multiple actors involved in the mobilization) make up the sources of strength of social movements and keep them effective and salient in the public sphere. He suggests the following formula: “Strength = worthiness x unity x numbers x commitment If any of these values falls to zero, strength likewise falls to zero; the challenge loses credibility”. Through contentious performances social movements involve continuous interaction between challengers and power holders. To see why social movements are not only continuous interactions but also contentious performances, we may make use of “the simple static model of polity” that consists of the following elements (McAdam, Tarrow, and Tilly, 2001: 11-12): • • • • • Agents of government Polity members (constituted political actors enjoying routine access to government agents and resources) Challengers (constituted political actors lacking that routine access) Subjects (persons and groups not currently organized into constituted political actors Outside political actors, including other governments 3 EUROSPHERE RESEARCH NOTES No.16 ÖNCÜ According to this model, social movements act as constellations of collective as well as individual actors from within the set of challengers who come to assume an identity that may help to turn an episodic contention into a continuous contention. Given that social movements are not the only sites of contentious performances in the public sphere, the question becomes what differentiates them, say, from political parties, “think tanks”, and media. The answer must lie in the phrase: “the lack of routine access to public politics”. Social movements come to fill the lack of formal political channels that allow dealing with actual or perceived contentions, either because these channels are not instituted yet or even if they are, technically speaking, available not used by some challengers yet. Having said all this, in terms of the practicalities of our research, we finally need to differentiate social movements from other similar collective actors. There are two such collective actors: advocacy networks and coalitions of actors (Khagram, Riker and Sikkink, 2002: 3-24) . Briefly defined, advocacy networks are actors linked within the boundaries of a given social and political space, bound together by shared values, dense exchanges of information and services, and common discourses. Coalitions of actors involve a greater level of coordination than present in advocacy networks. Coalitions coordinate shared strategies or sets of tactics to publicly influence social and political change. These mostly take on the form of “campaigns”. Unlike these two forms of collective action, social movements are sets of actors with claims to solidarity and common purposes and have the capacity to generate coordinated and sustained social mobilization that involves the use of protest or disruptive action in order for bringing social and political change. So the differentia specifica of social movements is the “disruptive action” that threatens a social-political establishment. 2- Forms of contention and different forms of social movements McAdam, Tarrow, and Tilly (2001) have recently elaborated on the meaning of “contentious politics”, a concept that has been at the center of their research orientation for some time. Tilly (2004) summarizes the essence of their approach by saying that the objective is not the explanation of social movements per se but rather the definition of the problem as the explanation of contentious politics, “including both a) differences in the operation of contrasting forms of contentious politics within the same regimes, and b) differences in the operation of contentious politics within contrasting regimes” (Tilly, 2004: 36). It is critical here to note first that the notion of “political regime” occupies a central place in the explanation of emergence of different forms of “disruptive actions” (such as institutionally acceptable actions or upfront anti-institutional actions; actions tolerable in terms of the ideological pillars of the routine politics or actions appearing to be instigated by “antisystemic attitudes” or irrefutably antagonistic, etc.). Secondly, it is crucial to stress that all political regimes have various mechanisms to deal with both “permissible” and “nonpermissible” contentions and hence disruptive actions. The activation of the use of these mechanisms depends on the form of actions that collective actors take. McAdams, Tarrow, and Tilly’s (2001:7-8)) suggestion of the two forms of contention as “contained” and “transgressive” contentions may help us to differentiate forms of social movements and how these might be perceived from the point of view of a political regime. 1. Contained contention: parties are previously established actors employing well established means of claim making. It consists of episodic, public, collective interaction among makers of claims and their objects when (a) at least one government is a claimant, an object of claims, or a party to the claims, (b) the claims, if realized, affect the interests of at least one of the claimants, and (c) all parties to the conflict were previously established as constituted actors. 4 EUROSPHERE RESEARCH NOTES No.16 ÖNCÜ 2. Transgressive contention: consists of episodic, public, collective interaction among makers of claims and their objects when at least one government is claimant, and object of claims, or a party to claims, (b) the claims would, if realized, affect the interests of at least one of the claimants, (c) at least some parties to the conflict are newly self-identified political actors, and/or (d) at least some parties employ innovative collective action. (Action qualifies as innovative if it incorporates claims, selects objects of claims, includes collective self-representations, and/or adopts means that are either unprecedented or forbidden within the regime in question.” Based on these categories and principles, I would suggest that in our research we must be specific in regard to the forms of contention with which our selected social movements are involved. In other words, each partner team after selecting the social movements from their national political “regime” context should make an assessment of the forms of contentious politics that these movements are a part. Thus the question is not only spelling out the “network of relations” among a set of actors who share a common identity constructed for expressing a contention but also specifying the contention as either contained or transgrassive. Needless to say, there are many possibilities. We may have a national context or contexts where “transgrassive” contentions do not exist at all (a Disneyland type of democracy!) or rarely emerge either because the regime has been too flexible to accommodate all forms of contentions so that actors could express their contentions via well-established identities within the boundaries of routine politics, or because collective actors are less prone to challenge the status quo for the authority has been very much unwilling to be receptive to new identities. From this viewpoint, social movements are historically formed “collective and mutual claim making” with the purpose of bringing a novelty to the configurations of routine public politics. That is why social movement research is inherently linked to “processes of democratization” and theories of democracy because independently from their outcomes social movements are performances by a section of demos whose voices are yet to be heard politically (Burnstein, 1999). Whether this voice would be uttered in the routine politics or outside the scope of the routine politics is contingent on the “political opportunity structure”. 3- How to conceive organizational features of social movements At this point, before moving any further, we must recall Tilly’s (1999:256) warning regarding the two most common mistaken views about social movements conceived as “collective and mutual claim making” inherently linked to “processes of democratization”. The first erroneous assumption is that social movements are coherent groups rather than clusters of performances. The second fallacy is that social movements have continuous, self contained life histories reminiscent of individuals and formal organizations. Suffice to say, social movements are neither individuals who are supposed to exist as coherent entities (i.e. cogito ergo sum) nor formal organizations with official objectives as well as rule making capacities constraining the actions of their members by forcing them to stay within the boundaries established for separating them from the outside. Social movements, although they are somewhat bounded, involve “contingent, interactive performances by multiple and changing actors”. In other words, life histories of social movements do not look like linear paths but rather non-linear, multi-directional ebbs and flows. To proceed in this direction leads us to focus on the dynamic and changing nature of actors, identities, and actions associated with social movements. Thus, at any particular stage in the history of movements we must stop and ask questions again and again regarding actors, identities and actions. As to the actors, the key question becomes the “who” of the claim making, as well as the “why” of “their” claim making. As to the identities, the question turns out to be what the claim makers and others say who the claim makers are and why they say 5 EUROSPHERE RESEARCH NOTES No.16 ÖNCÜ so. Finally, as to the actions, the begging issue is to investigate forms of claim making that challengers take and what reasons they provide for their choice of particular forms of claim making (McAdam, Tarrow, and Tilly, 2001: 126). As a general rule the identities that actors take on consist of social relations and their representations. They are not stable or all-inclusive characteristics of individual or collective actors. Most of them function as social categories regulating social relations within and between categories. Thus, they do not exist only as boundaries separating one group of actors from another but also function as bases of social dynamics in a particular polity. Social movements are those actors who make claims on the bases of such categories, and hence provide social relations with a political twist. This they do through challenging “the authority” on the basis of a collective identity. According to Tilly (1999:262), “construction of shared identities often does attract and commit individuals to social movements”. But the successful construction of a shared identity does not suffice for the persistence of social movements. What is needed, as already emphasized, is to give a contentious political meaning to that identity by challenging the authority and the “members” of the routine politics of the regime where this movement erupts. Thus, we arrive at another significant conceptualization of social movements that we can use in operationalizing social movement actors in our research: “Social movements couple the making of public claims with the creation, assertion, and political deployment of collective identities”. (Tilly, 1999: 262). Tilly talks about two sorts of identities utilized by movement organizers in “patching together provisional coalitions, suppressing risky tactics, negotiating which of the multiple agendas that participants bring with them will find public voice in their collective action, and, above all, hiding backstage struggle from public view”. (Tilly, 1999: 263). The first of these identities is called embedded identities, which refer to those that inform about what governs everyday life of individuals – race, gender, class, ethnicity, locality, kinship and so on. The second set of identities is called detached identities and refers to the ones that rarely or never govern everyday social relations. These include associational membership and legal categories such as “minority”, “party member”, “union representative” or “handicapped persons”. According to Tilly, the collective identity “citizen” falls somewhere in between embedded and detached identities. The interesting point for us is that as we move in the continuum away from embedded to detached identities, collective identities “resemble linguistic genres in entailing coherent interpersonal collaboration but varying contingently in content, form, and applicability from setting to setting”. It seems that, putting the issue of forms of contention aside, differentiation of one social movement from another rests almost always on the type collective identity picked up or constructed and utilized for mobilization. The ones that utilize detached identities involve universalistic (as opposed to particularistic) forms of claim-making, large scale coordination, and reliance on specialized representatives or political entrepreneurs (McAdams, Tarrow, and Tilly, 2001:141). Thus, specification of the kind of collective identity utilized by the movement is especially crucial for understanding the organizational logic of the movement, and hence its choice of structures for mobilization. 4- A tentative list of questions for guiding the selection/examination of SMOs In the literature we come across six broad social movement types. These are: 1. Labor movement 2. Women’s movement 3. Ecological movement 4. Antiwar/peace movement 5. Ethnic/nationalist movement 6. Religious movement 6 EUROSPHERE RESEARCH NOTES No.16 ÖNCÜ Given these broadly defined social movement types and what has been said above, I would like to suggest the following list of questions in regard to the social movement actors to be considered by the partners. 1. What are the broad social movement types that the particular movements selected are associated with (i.e., labor movement, women’s movement, etc.)? 2. What are the specific political demands and challenges that the movements pose to the authority? (Say we take an ethnic movement; what are the stated demands and political goals of the movement? Example: Legislation of new codes or transformations in the existing policies regulating the rights extended to the ethnic community, such rights as education in the native language, freedom of forming political and cultural associations on the basis of ethnic identity, freely and openly electing political representatives whose mandate is to speak for the interests of the ethnic community, etc.) 3. Who are the collective as well as individual actors that constitute the movements? In other words, who are involved in the networks of relations of the movements, i.e., the leading social movement organizations (SMOs) and prominent individuals? (We need to come up with a list of organizational titles and names of prominent individuals such as professors, artists, lawyers, politicians, etc. for each movement we intend to examine). 4. Who are the leaders of the networks? To is to say, who own “the sustained challenges” of the movements both as organizations and individuals? 5. What are the framing strategies and protest tactics that these leaders use in mobilizing the participants of the movements? (Example: Do the leaders frame the movement participants as “concerned citizens” or “heroes” and “heroines”? Do they ask participants to go out and “strike”, “block roads”, “occupy public buildings”, “hunger strike” or make some procedural complaints to the authorities, or both depending on the particular contention around and for which they mobilize the participants? 6. Does each and every political demand and goal publicized by the movements in order to set an agenda in the public sphere gain the backing of each and every participant of the networks of the movements? In other words, is there any ideological and/or political division within the networks? Do you find any such confrontation in the history of the movements? If yes, what appears to be the dividing political and ideological lines or cracks within the internal (backstage) politics of the movements? 7. What are the main resources of the movements such as physical premises (buildings, offices), other available facilities and technological infrastructures such as web sites, journals, newsletters etc. that can be used for the political causes of the movements, the number of participants and supporters, the range of the reach of the movements in the wider society i.e., whether there is a large population of sympathizers not directly involved in the movements yet show solidarity of some sort with the movements, e.g., extending support through donations, protecting the participants from the authorities’ oppressions, cheering up when they meet or come across with the participants in the protest environments etc., or acting very hostile towards the participants in various forms, e.g. is there intimidating representations of the movements in the nongovernmental print, visual and electronic media? 8. Which channels and ways of influence are made possible for the movements by the general political opportunity structure? 7 EUROSPHERE RESEARCH NOTES No.16 ÖNCÜ 9. Does the general political opportunity structure involve freedom of organization for all, or only for some social movements? Which ones? 10. Which strategies and methods does the authority use to keep some movements outside the facilities that the general opportunity structure makes available for others? 11. What sort of international/EU and national norms, discourses, conditionalities and support exist that the movements can deploy to legitimize/back up their claims? 12. What are the mechanisms, processes and identities that the movements construct for mobilization at the local, national and transnational/EU levels? 13. Do the movements take an active part in any kind of transnational network? Can any of these networks be characterized as a transnational social movement? If so, how are the interactions within this network organized and managed? 8 EUROSPHERE RESEARCH NOTES No.16 ÖNCÜ References Burstein, P. 1999. “Social Movements and Public Policy”. In How Social Movements Matter, edited by Marco Giugni, Doug McAdam, and Charles Tilly. Minneapolis, London: University of Minnesota. Calhoun, C. 2000. “‘New Soocial Movements’ of the Early Nineteenth Century”. In Political Sociology, edited by Kate Nash. Oxford: Blackwell. Diani, M. 2000. “The Concept of Social Movement”. In Political Sociology, edited by Kate Nash. Oxford: Blackwell. Khagram, S., Riker, V. J., and Sikkink, K. 2002. Restructuring World Politics: Transnational Social Movements, Networks and Norms. Minneapolis, London: University of Minnesota. McAdam, D., Tarrow, S., and Tilly, C. 2001. Dynamics of Contention. Cambridge: CambridgeUniversity Press. Tilly, C. 1999. “From Interactions to Outcomes in Social Movements”. In How Social Movements Matter, edited by Marco Giugni, Doug McAdam, and Charles Tilly. Minneapolis, London: University of Minnesota. Tilly, C. 2004. “Wise Quacks”. In Rethinking Social Movements, edited by Jeff Goodwinand James M. Jasper. New York, Toronto, Oxford: Rowan and Littlefield. 9