BROOKLYN LAW REVIEW VOLUME 78 FALL 2012 NUMBER 1 TABLE OF CONTENTS ARTICLES Righting Others’ Wrongs: A Critical Look at Clawbacks in Madoff-Type Ponzi Schemes and Other Frauds Amy J. Sepinwall 1 Rescuing Dignitary Torts from the Constitution Cristina Carmody Tilley 65 NOTES Giving Battered Immigrant Fiancées a Way Out of Abusive Relationships: Proposed Amendments to the Immigration and Nationality Act Adam B. Horowitz 123 Softwood Lumber’s “Termite” Problem: Why the Extension of the 2006 Softwood Lumber Agreement Is Right for Softwood Lumber but Wrong for the Multilateral Trading System K. Craig Reilly 165 Count Your Chickens Before They Hatch: How Multiple Pregnancies Are Endangering the Right to Abortion Priyanka Shivakumar 201 “Only Dust Remains[?]”: The 9/11 Memorial Litigation and the Reach of Quasi-Property Rights Patrick J. Mulqueen 231 Combating Inaccuracies in Criminal Background Checks by Giving Meaning to the Fair Credit Reporting Act 271 Noam Weiss ARTICLES Righting Others’ Wrongs A CRITICAL LOOK AT CLAWBACKS IN MADOFFTYPE PONZI SCHEMES AND OTHER FRAUDS Amy J. Sepinwall† INTRODUCTION We typically expect wrongdoers to redress the victims of their transgressions.1 But do those who innocently benefit from wrongdoing owe restitution to the victims of the wrong? Irving Picard, the trustee who has been charged with recovering and distributing money to the victims of Bernie Madoff’s Ponzi scheme, obviously thinks so.2 Picard has filed over one † Assistant Professor, Department of Legal Studies and Business Ethics, The Wharton School, University of Pennsylvania. B.A., McGill University, 1997; M.A., McGill University, 1999; J.D., Yale Law School, 2004; Ph.D., Philosophy, Georgetown University, 2010. For helpful comments and suggestions, I am grateful to Dan Cahoy, David Grey, Peter Henning, Waheed Hussain, David Luban, Richard Shell, Andy Siegel, Alan Strudler, and Bill Tyson, as well as audiences at Wharton and the 2011 Law and Society Annual Meeting. This paper was selected for the 2012 Huber Hurst Research Seminar in Business Law, Legal Studies, and Ethics, and benefited greatly from feedback received there. Generous support was provided by the Dean’s Research Fund at Wharton as well as the Wharton Legal Studies Research Fund. Hilary Greenwald and Joyce Shin provided excellent research assistance. All errors that remain are my own. 1 See, e.g., 1 FRANCIS HILLIARD, THE LAW OF TORTS OR PRIVATE WRONGS 82 (1859) (“The liability to make reparation for an injury rests upon an original moral duty, enjoined upon every person, so to conduct himself or exercise his own rights as not to injure another.” (citation omitted) (emphasis omitted)); John C.P. Goldberg, The Constitutional Status of Tort Law: Due Process and the Right to a Law for the Redress of Wrongs, 115 YALE L.J. 524, 541-44 (2005) (describing the goal of tort law as seeking redress for private harm). For a searching review of the ways in which federal agencies have acted to compel disgorgement from wrongdoers and, in some cases, have then sought to return ill-gotten gains to the wrongdoers’ victims, see generally Adam S. Zimmerman, Distributing Justice, 86 N.Y.U. L. REV. 500 (2011). 2 See infra notes 119-20 and accompanying text. The Securities and Exchange Commission (SEC) defines a Ponzi scheme as “an investment fraud that involves the payment of purported returns to existing investors from funds contributed by new 1 2 BROOKLYN LAW REVIEW [Vol. 78:1 thousand clawback suits,3 seeking to recover any money “winning investors” realized in excess of their investment and to return this money to the Madoff “losers,”4—i.e., those who lost some or all of their principal when the Ponzi scheme went bust.5 Kenneth Feinberg, former Special Master for the September 11 Victims Compensation Fund,6 therefore quips that the Madoff clawback suits have Picard “taking from Peter to pay Paul.”7 Importantly, the “Peters” in these suits include entities or individuals who are believed to have been innocent of any wrongdoing—there is no allegation that they knew or should have known of the fraud.8 Thus, the Madoff case provides investors.” SEC, Ponzi Schemes—Frequently Asked Questions, http://www.sec.gov/ answers/ponzi.htm (last visited Nov. 1, 2012). 3 Times Topics: Irving H. Picard, N.Y. TIMES, http://topics.nytimes.com/topics/ reference/timestopics/people/p/irving_h_picard/index.html (last updated June 25, 2012); see also Lisa Sandler & Bob Van Voris, Madoff Trustee Defends “Clawbacks” in U.S. District Court, BLOOMBERG (Aug. 23, 2011, 9:10 AM), http://www.bloomberg.com/news/ 2011-08-23/madoff-trustee-defends-1-6-million-clawback-suit-in-u-s-district-court.html. 4 I follow the bankruptcy trustee in referring to those who had withdrawn amounts equal to or greater than their principal investment as “winners,” and to those who had not yet recovered all—or perhaps even any—of their principal when the scheme collapsed as “losers.” Nonetheless, I note that this is a tendentious way of describing the two categories of investors, since it implies that there is something undeserved about the money the “winners” obtained. See Clarence L. Pozza, Jr. et al., A Review of Recent Investor Issues in the Madoff, Stanford and Forte Ponzi Scheme Cases, 10 J. BUS. & SEC. L. 113, 117 (2010) (“Ponzi scheme investors . . . are often regrettably characterized as ‘winners’ and ‘losers.’ This dichotomy tends to prejudge the equitable collection of funds and distribution to Ponzi victims.” (footnote omitted)). 5 See, e.g., David Ellis, Madoff Investors May Have to Cough Up Profits, CNNMONEY (July 26, 2010, 10:52 AM), http://money.cnn.com/2010/07/26/news/ companies/madoff_investors/index.htm; Ashby Jones, Madoff “Winners” Beware: Irv Picard Hasn’t Gone Away, WSJ LAW BLOG (July 26, 2010, 9:14 AM), http://blogs.wsj.com/ law/2010/07/26/madoff-winners-youre-forewarned-irv-picard-hasnt-gone-away/. 6 See, e.g., Margaret L. Shaw, Madoff Victim Compensation: Interview with Ken Feinberg, 16 DISP. RESOL. MAG., Winter 2010, at 11. Kenneth Feinberg has also overseen compensation funds for victims of the Virginia Tech shootings, the BP oil spill, and Holocaust reparations. See generally FEINBERG ROZEN, LLP, http://www.feinbergrozen.com/ (last visited Oct. 1, 2012). 7 See Shaw, supra note 6, at 11. 8 I rely here on a standard definition of fraud. See, e.g., BLACK’S LAW DICTIONARY FREE ONLINE (2d ed.), http://thelawdictionary.org/fraud/ (last visited Sept. 7, 2012) (“Fraud consists of some deceitful practice or willful device, resorted to with intent to deprive another of his right, or in some manner to do him an injury.”). While many of those who have been targeted for clawbacks are innocent of the fraud, see, e.g., Richard Sandomir, Actions of Madoff Victims’ Trustee Will Be Reviewed, N.Y. TIMES, July 28, 2011, at B15, Picard alleges that many others knew or should have known. Most prominent among those whom the trustee accuses of having known about, or else been willfully blind to, the scheme, are Fred Wilpon and Saul Katz, real estate moguls and part owners of the New York Mets, who had invested their company’s revenues with Madoff. See, e.g., Jeffrey Toobin, Madoff’s Curveball: Will Fred Wilpon Be Forced to Sell the Mets? NEW YORKER (May 30, 2011), http://www.newyorker.com/reporting/ 2011/05/30/110530fa_fact_toobin?printable=true&currentPage=all; Bob Van Voris, Madoff Trustee May Do What Bernie Didn’t: Give Victims Profit, BLOOMBERG (Feb. 11, 2011, 12:01 AM), http:// www.bloomberg.com/news/2011-02-11/madoff-trustee-may-do- 2012] RIGHTING OTHERS’ WRONGS 3 an opportunity to explore the grounds and bounds of restitution as between the innocent beneficiaries and victims of a wrong. We shall see that the questions of whether, when, and why innocent winners in a financial fraud should be compelled to restitute the fraud’s losers are both underserved by existing doctrine9 and understudied by scholars.10 Perhaps nowhere is something-bernie-never-did-give-victims-real-profit.html. The company used its Madoff accounts as a kind of bank, depositing money until it was needed for payroll or other expenses, withdrawing the needed funds, and then beginning the cycle anew. Toobin, supra; see also Richard Sandomir, Trustee Says Mets Saw Madoff as House Money, N.Y. TIMES, Feb. 21, 2012, at B11. Over the years, Wilpon’s company deposited roughly $700 million, and withdrew roughly $1 billion (the $300 million in excess of the company’s deposits was taken to constitute profits on the investment). See, e.g., Holman W. Jenkins, Jr., Madoff and the Mets: How the “Extremely Wealthy” Allowed the Madoff Fraud to Endure, WALL ST. J. (BUSINESS WORLD) (Feb. 8, 2011, 9:12 PM), http://online.wsj.com/ article/SB10001424052748704364004576132201926195.html. Picard filed a lawsuit against Wilpon and his partners, seeking to claw back the $1 billion in withdrawals the firm had made from its Madoff accounts over the years. See, e.g., Michael O’Keefe, Feds To Investigate Irving Picard’s “Clawback” Suits to See if Madoff Ponzi Scheme Victims Are Hurt, N.Y. DAILY NEWS (July 28, 2011, 4:00 AM), http://articles.nydailynews.com/2011-07-28/sports/29840581_1_madoff-trusteewilpon-and-katz-amanda-remus. The trustee maintains that the defendants did know, or should have known, about the Ponzi scheme, while the defendants vehemently contest these allegations, calling the claims against them “abusive, unfair[,] and untrue.” Van Voris, supra. Madoff himself insists upon Wilpon and Katz’s innocence: “Fred was not at all stock market savvy and Saul was not really either. They were strictly Real Estate people. Although I explained the Strategy to them they were not sophisticated enough to evaluate it properly.” See Toobin, supra, at 15 (internal quotation marks omitted). In a series of rulings, Judge Jed Rakoff reduced the maximum amount of recovery from the defendants to $384 million. See, e.g., Adam Rubin, Mets Owners Must Pay, Go to Trial, ESPNNEWYORK.COM (Mar. 6, 2012), http://espn.go.com/new-york/mlb/story/_/id/7647107/judge-new-york-mets-owners-paymuch-83m-trial-decide-303m. On March 16, 2012, Wilpon and partners entered into a settlement agreement with Picard under which they agreed to pay $162 million to the trustee. See Richard Sandomir & Ken Belson, Mets’ Owners Agree to Settle Madoff Suit for $162 Million, N.Y. TIMES, Mar. 19, 2012, at A1, available at http://www.nytimes.com/2012/03/20/sports/baseball/mets-owners-pay-162-million-tosettle-madoff-suit.html?_r=1&pagewanted=print. 9 General restitutionary doctrine has long been charged with inattention and incoherence. See, e.g., Andrew Kull, Restitution in Bankruptcy: Reclamation and Constructive Trust, 72 AM. BANKR. L.J. 265, 267 (1998) (“Most law schools gave up teaching restitution a generation ago, and many judges and practitioners are not familiar with its general principles. Lack of familiarity with the restitutionary elements of the background rules results in a predictable distortion of commercial law.”); Chaim Saiman, Restitution and the Production of Legal Doctrine, 65 WASH. & LEE L. REV. 993, 994 (2008) (“[I]n American legal discourse restitution sits at the backwaters of the academic and judicial consciousness . . . .”). Cf. PETER BIRKS, UNJUST ENRICHMENT 40 (2d ed. 2005) (noting that novel fact patterns pose problems for the doctrine of unjust enrichment, since there isn’t a general, one-size-fits-all principle for determining when one party has innocently benefitted at the expense of another). See generally Mallory A. Sullivan, Note, When the Bezzle Bursts: Restitutionary Distribution of Assets After Ponzi Schemes Enter Bankruptcy, 68 WASH. & LEE L. REV. 1589, 1598-99 (2011) (describing the general confusion around restitution, especially in the context of a bankruptcy). 10 Cf. BIRKS, supra note 9, at 3 (“Of the subjects which form the indispensable foundation of private law, unjust enrichment is the only one to have evaded the great 4 BROOKLYN LAW REVIEW [Vol. 78:1 this inattention more apparent, and potentially disquieting, than in the efforts to require innocent Ponzi scheme winners to defray the losses of the scheme’s losers. As courts have noted, the provisions governing the efforts to recover money for investors in a Ponzi scheme stand “at the intersection of two important national legislative policies on a collision course— the policies of bankruptcy and securities law.”11 Neither of these bodies of law was designed with the other in mind,12 and there is much that remains unsettled in determining the appropriate interaction between the two.13 rationalization achieved since the middle of the 19th century in both England and America by the writers of the textbooks.”). 11 Picard v. Katz, 462 B.R. 447, 451 (S.D.N.Y. 2011) (quoting In re Enron Creditors Recovery Corp., 651 F.3d 329, 334 (2d Cir. 2011) (citation omitted)); see also id. at 450 (noting that the clawback lawsuit against Wilpon and his partners “raises important and in some respects unsettled issues of the interaction of securities law with bankruptcy law”). Cf. Hanoch Dagan, Restitution in Bankruptcy: Why All Involuntary Creditors Should Be Preferred, 78 AM. BANKR. L.J. 247, 247-48 (2004) (discussing the untoward interaction of restitution and bankruptcy law). 12 See, e.g., Pozza, Jr. et al., supra note 4, at 131 (“The legal principles often utilized in the Ponzi scheme cases were not originally developed to address Ponzi scheme victim fairness issues and create somewhat extreme arguments and results.”). Cf. Kull, supra note 9, at 265-66 (“The contemporary treatment of restitution in bankruptcy has become confused and haphazard because the subject is not addressed by the Bankruptcy Code.”); Peter J. Henning, The Roller Coaster Ride Continues for Madoff Investors, N.Y. TIMES (DEALBOOK) (Oct. 3, 2011, 3:26 PM), http://dealbook.nytimes.com/2011/10/03/the-roller-coaster-ride-for-madoff-investorscontinues/ (“Investors in Mr. Madoff’s Ponzi scheme have been whipped back and forth as the courts try to apply the law to a case that is unprecedented in many ways.”). 13 See, e.g., Kathy Bazoian Phelps, Partner, Danning, Gill, Diamond & Kollitz L.L.P., Fraudulent Transfer Claims and Defenses in Ponzi Schemes, Address Before the Southwest Bankruptcy Conference (2009), available at http://www.abiworld.org/committees/ newsletters/litigation/vol6num5/ponzi.pdf (last visited on Sept. 24, 2012) (“[C]ourts are continuing to refine the rules which arise in unwinding these tangled financial webs. In particular, the law regarding fraudulent transfer claims to recover funds paid by the Ponzi debtor to investors as a return of principal or payment of fictitious profits and defenses which can be asserted to those claims continue to evolve.”); Joshua Marcus & Jake Greenberg, Ponzi Schemes: Washed Ashore by Recession’s Low Tide, Reveal Controversial Issues, 29 AM. BANKR. INST. J., Oct. 2010, at 48, 107 (“Ponzi schemes— one of the horrible byproducts unearthed by the financial crisis—have raised noteworthy and contentious bankruptcy issues.”). Cf. Paul Sinclair, The Sad Tale of Fraudulent Transfers: The Unscrupulous Are Rewarded and the Diligent Are Punished, 28 AM. BANKR. INST. J., Apr. 2009, at 16, 80 (“[P]ursuing investors who lacked diligence in Madoff will unnecessarily cost hundreds of millions.”); Jeff Benjamin, Madoff Investors May Face Clawbacks, INVESTMENT NEWS (Feb. 10, 2009), http://www.investmentnews.com/ article20090210/REG/902109979 (quoting an attorney involved in the Madoff clawback cases, who predicts that, given the unsettled questions of law, “[t]he [civil litigation] will spawn a whole industry for the next decade.”). It may be worth noting that there is a prior question as to whether bankruptcy law should apply at all in the wake of a Ponzi scheme, given that criminal forfeiture exists as a viable alternative. Supporters of criminal forfeiture argue that it would be less costly, thereby leaving more money to be distributed to the fraud’s victims, and more compelling, given its retributive rationale. See generally Marcus & Greenberg, supra. Bankruptcy looks nonetheless to remain a preferred avenue for 2012] RIGHTING OTHERS’ WRONGS 5 Even more concerning, few commentators have given thought to whether the recovery provisions of bankruptcy law ought to extend to the innocent beneficiaries of a financial fraud. This is especially troubling because no legal mechanism exists to permit recovery from investors who innocently profited from a financial fraud where the fraud does not result in the entity’s bankruptcy. In this way, Ponzi scheme winners incur harsher treatment than those who innocently profit from other kinds of financial fraud, although case law and commentaries do not offer a justification for this inconsistent treatment. In particular, outside of the doctrine of unjust enrichment—which, I argue, is inapposite here—we lack a theory that elucidates why, and if so when, innocent beneficiaries of a transgression owe restitution to the transgression’s victims. A central task of this article is to provide such a theory, which can usefully be applied not just to Ponzi scheme cases but to other cases of financial wrongdoing as well—a prospect made all the more pressing in the wake of the financial meltdown. More specifically, I examine attempts to extend the recovery provisions of bankruptcy law to the innocent beneficiaries of a Ponzi scheme and, after an analysis of the history and structure of the relevant statutes, I argue that these attempts problematically deviate from the recovery provisions’ purpose. I then seek to establish that innocent winners in a Ponzi scheme are unlike the innocent beneficiaries of ill-gotten gains or good faith purchasers of stolen goods, and instead are more akin to investors who innocently profit from corporate or financial wrongdoing. Yet, so long as the offending corporations or brokerage firms do not end up bankrupt, the innocent investors who earned profits as a result of the wrongful conduct will be permitted to retain their “winnings.” I contend that if we do not seek to claw back profits from these innocent investors, then we should not seek to claw back profits from the innocent Ponzi scheme winners, either.14 That contention, of restituting the victims of a financial fraud, not least of all because it allows the estate to recover assets beyond those of the fraud’s perpetrator—of particular relevance here, those of innocent winning investors. Cf. Paul W. Bonapfel et al., Ponzi Schemes— Bankruptcy Court v. Federal Equity Receivership, 26 EMORY BANKR. DEV. J. 207, 21213 (2010). 14 The migration of the noun “clawback” to the verb form “claw back,” appears to have gained currency in the 1980s, in light of efforts to enforce anti-trust provisions extraterritorially, and a resulting response permitting the defendant to recoup—i.e., claw back—damages imposed on him. See, e.g., Note, Extraterritorial Application of the Export Administration Act of 1979 Under International and American Law, 81 MICH. L. REV. 1308, 1318 n.58 (1983) (“[A] number of foreign states have enacted ‘blocking’ or ‘claw- 6 BROOKLYN LAW REVIEW [Vol. 78:1 course, could cut in two diametrically opposed directions—one could argue that we should allow the losses to lie where they fell or, by contrast, that we should implement restitution on a far wider scale than the law currently allows. I end by seeking to defend the latter alternative and by suggesting measures through which it could be implemented. It is surprising that scholars have largely overlooked clawback suits in the context of a Ponzi scheme, given the troubling uncertainty and evident tensions they involve,15 as well as the dramatic rise in their use. While the first set of clawback cases eventuating from a Ponzi scheme arose in the wake of Charles Ponzi’s now infamous fraud16 during the 1920s,17 it was only in the 1980s that the use of a clawback suit to recover money from an innocent investor became widespread; in fact, 149 of the 190 published state and federal cases were decided in or after the year 2000.18 Further, commentators predict that these suits will become even more common in the coming years.19 To be sure, the Madoff scandal itself has garnered significant media and scholarly attention. Much of this has focused on the factors that facilitated the scheme—Madoff’s exploitation of the affinity bonds he shared with many of his back’ statutes designed to protect their citizens from assertions of extraterritorial jurisdiction by the United States.”); Note, Predictability and Comity: Toward Common Principles of Extraterritorial Jurisdiction, 98 HARV. L. REV. 1310, 1311 n.6 (1985) (“Clawback statutes, such as § 6 of the British Protection of Trading Interests Act, 1980, ch. 11, follow from the premise that certain foreign judgments will not be given extraterritorial effect. . . . Once such a statute is invoked, the foreign defendant will be allowed to ‘claw back’ the punitive portion of the judgment (for example, two-thirds of a treble-damages antitrust award).” (citations omitted)). 15 Cf. Miriam A. Cherry & Jarrod Wong, Clawbacks: Prospective Contract Measures in an Era of Excessive Executive Compensation and Ponzi Schemes, 94 MINN. L. REV. 368, 411 (2009) (noting that the term clawback “has been subject to neither rigorous analytical scrutiny nor definition and exposition”); Robert A. Prentice & Dain C. Donelson, Insider Trading as a Signaling Device, 47 AM. BUS. L.J. 1, 15 (2010) (observing that clawback provisions were “essentially unknown” before Sarbanes-Oxley). 16 Cunningham v. Brown, 265 U.S. 1, 7-9 (1924) (discussing the collapse of Charles Ponzi’s fraudulent investment program). 17 Ponzi’s scheme gave rise to eleven published opinions, two in state courts and the remainder in federal court, including two that went to the Supreme Court: Ponzi v. Fessenden, 258 U.S. 254 (1922), and Cunningham, 265 U.S. 1. 18 See infra notes 86 and 87 and accompanying text (describing the evolution of the law on this score). 19 See, e.g., Michael C. Macchiarola, In the Shadow of the Omnipresent Claw: A Response to Professors Cherry and Wong, MINN. L. REV. HEADNOTES (2011), http://www.minnesotalawreview.org/headnotes/in-the-shadow-of-the-omnipresent-claw-inresponse-to-professors-cherry-wong-2/#_ftn9 (“As the American economy continues to totter against an ever-growing populist momentum, it seems likely that clawback mechanisms of various sorts will be put to increasing use in the coming months and years.”). 2012] RIGHTING OTHERS’ WRONGS 7 victims,20 his proclaimed split-strike strategy,21 and the SEC’s failure to detect the fraud.22 Other work has either addressed alternative enforcement regimes in the case of a Madoff-type fraud23 or revisited white-collar crime sentencing policies24 in light of Madoff’s 150-year prison sentence,25 which is likely to be the longest sentence ever imposed for a violation of an antifraud law.26 The handful of scholars who have addressed the use of clawback suits against innocent investors in Ponzi scheme cases have largely agreed that the suits are permissible in principle, and possibly even worthwhile.27 Existing critical commentary tends to take issue only with the ways the suits are wielded in practice. Thus, scholars have objected to judicial interpretations of the doctrine;28 the ad hoc development of the law, which threatens uniformity and predictability;29 the opportunity for abuse of discretion that the suits allegedly afford;30 or the negative consequences that the suits are 20 See, e.g., Christine Hurt, Evil Has a New Name (and a New Narrative): Bernard Madoff, 2009 MICH. ST. L. REV. 947, 957 (2009); Paul Krugman, Madoff Explains Everything, N.Y. TIMES (Nov. 17, 2011, 4:24 PM), http://krugman.blogs.nytimes.com/ 2011/11/17/madoff-explains-everything (“The Madoff affair, as you may know, was a classic case of ‘affinity fraud.’”). 21 See, e.g., Carole Bernard & Phelim Boyle, Mr. Madoff’s Amazing Returns: An Analysis of the Split-Strike Conversion Strategy, 17 J. DERIVATIVES 62, 62 (2009). 22 See, e.g., Donald Langevoort, The SEC and the Madoff Scandal: Three Narratives in Search of a Story, 2009 MICH. ST. L. REV. 899, 900 (2009). 23 See, e.g., Jennifer J. Johnson, Secondary Liability for Securities Fraud: Gatekeepers in State Court, 36 DEL. J. CORP. L. 463, 467 (2011); Amanda M. Rose, The Multienforcer Approach to Securities Fraud Deterrence: A Critical Analysis, 158 U. PA. L. REV. 2173, 2176 (2010). 24 See, e.g., Daniel V. Dooley, Sr. & Mark Radke, Does Severe Punishment Deter Financial Crimes?, 4 CHARLESTON L. REV. 619, 622 (2010); Derick R. Vollrath, Note, Losing the Loss Calculation: Toward a More Just Sentencing Regime in WhiteCollar Criminal Cases, 59 DUKE L.J. 1001, 1004 (2010). 25 Transcript of Sentencing Hearing at 49, United States v. Madoff, 626 F. Supp. 2d. 420 (S.D.N.Y. June 17, 2009) (No. 09 Crim. 213 (DC)). 26 Peter J. Henning, The Limits of Bigger Penalties in Fighting Financial Crime, N.Y. TIMES (DEALBOOK) (Dec. 12, 2011, 4:03 PM), http://dealbook.nytimes.com/ 2011/12/12/the-limits-of-bigger-penalties-in-fighting-financial-crime. 27 See, e.g., Cherry & Wong, supra note 15, at 397. 28 The most common line of criticism on this score takes issue with what is taken to be an overly demanding standard of good faith, and an overly draconian set of consequences if one is shown to have lacked good faith, including compelled return of any money one withdrew from the scheme, whether as “profits” or principal. See, e.g., Sullivan, supra note 9, at 1615-23. 29 See, e.g., Pozza, Jr. et al., supra note 4, at 131 (“The current case-by-case approach does not appear to yield fair uniform results. A new comprehensive approach designed for overall victim fairness should be considered.”); Macchiarola, supra note 19, Conclusion (text accompanying nn.67-68); Sullivan, supra note 9, at 1632. 30 Of particular note here is a concern that the trustee can use the threat of protracted, costly litigation to leverage settlements from investors who may have been wholly innocent of the fraud. See, e.g., Sullivan, supra note 9, at 1629-30. Cf. Van Voris, supra note 8 (quoting Wilpon and Katz’s complaint that the lawsuit against them is 8 BROOKLYN LAW REVIEW [Vol. 78:1 believed to produce among investors.31 But there has been no sustained inquiry into the foundational normative question— namely, whether innocent winning investors should be required to help defray losing investors’ losses in the first place.32 This article addresses that question and concludes that clawback suits targeting blameless winners lack a compelling legal or equitable basis. The article first proceeds, in Part I, by offering some of the factual and legal background to the Madoff case. In Part II, I turn to the legislative history and statutory structure of the Bankruptcy Code’s recovery provisions, and I argue that there is only a weak doctrinal basis for the bankruptcy trustee’s clawback efforts. Nonetheless, analogies to widely embraced rules surrounding unjust enrichment and stolen goods provide considerable intuitive support for the notion that Ponzi scheme winners should return some of their gains to the scheme’s losers. For example, where an individual gains as a result of a wrong perpetrated against another—at that victim’s expense— the individual may be compelled to return these ill-gotten gains. Similarly, where an individual purchases an item without knowledge that it is stolen, she must return the stolen item to its original owner, even if that means the innocent nothing more than “an outrageous strong-arm effort to try to force a settlement by threatening to ruin our reputations and businesses” (internal quotation marks omitted)). 31 Thus, for example, Karen Nelson argues that the clawback suits create infighting between the scheme’s investors, and encourage attorneys, in contravention of legal ethics, to advise their Madoff-investing clients to secret away their assets. See Karen E. Nelson, Note, Turning Winners into Losers: Ponzi Scheme Avoidance Law and the Inequity of Clawbacks, 95 MINN. L. REV. 1456, 1473, 1457-58 (2011). Nelson also argues that clawing back money from innocent investors “strays from America’s fundamental tenets of capitalism.” Id. at 1458. I set this last concern aside because our political and economic culture is replete with instances in which individuals or entities help to defray losses that they have neither culpably caused, nor caused at all. Take, for example, the September 11th compensation fund, or our progressive system of taxation, for that matter. I go on to argue for a compensation program more expansive than the one entailed by the clawback suits, on the thought that there is usually nothing but luck that distinguishes those who profit from the stock market from those who do not. Luck should not play so great a role in determining whether one ends up on the losing end of a wrong. If capitalism cannot accommodate that thought, so much the worse for capitalism. Mallory Sullivan complains that the clawback suits are unfair because they target investors who may have relied reasonably on the legitimacy of their withdrawals, and so no longer have the money now sought to be clawed back. See Sullivan, supra note 9, at 1633-34. Reasonable reliance seems to be the rationale underlying legislative proposals to limit, if not eliminate, clawback suits against innocent Ponzi scheme investors. See id. 32 But cf. O’Keefe, supra note 8 (describing a pending GAO investigation into Picard’s recovery efforts, including his clawback suits, in response to a letter from several Congresspersons expressing concern about the trustee’s “punishing the Ponzi scheme scammer’s victims by filing ‘clawback’ lawsuits”) (quoting Rep. Scott Garret (R-N.J.)). 2012] RIGHTING OTHERS’ WRONGS 9 purchaser will forfeit the money she paid to the seller. Pursuant to this reasoning, the Madoff bankruptcy trustee has sought to defend the clawback actions by analogizing them to cases seeking the disgorgement of ill-gotten gains or the return of stolen goods. In Part III, I argue that these analogies are mistaken, because the Madoff winners are neither the beneficiaries of a windfall—as is typically true in cases of unjust enrichment—nor the recipients of a unique, non-fungible good— as is typically true in cases of stolen goods. In Part IV, I examine other doctrines that appear to impose pecuniary penalties on investors who innocently profit from corporate or financial wrongdoing, but I argue that their apparent resemblance is deceiving. These doctrines either extend only to investors who are not wholly innocent of the wrongdoing, or they do not in fact require the innocent investor to return money as a means of offering restitution. Together, Parts II, III, and IV seek to establish that we cannot find support for the Ponzi scheme clawback actions in the bankruptcy code, or within other equitable or legal doctrines. Nevertheless, rather than abandoning the prospect of restitution altogether, I seek, in Part V, to defend a restitutionary scheme that would have all those who profit in the market defray the losses that fraudulent schemes produce. In other words, I argue that “winning” investors bear restitutionary obligations whether their profits derive from a legitimate or fraudulent investment vehicle. I thus end by urging a far more expansive restitutionary program than clawback suits currently afford. I. FACTUAL AND LEGAL BACKGROUND The Madoff scandal is a good place to begin an investigation into Ponzi scheme clawback cases—not only because it is the largest fraud in recorded history, but also because it provides an entrée to the legal framework governing clawback suits and the murky, ad hoc, and oftentimes flawed judicial reasoning that these suits invite. In Part I.A, I provide a brief overview of the relevant facts leading up to Madoff’s arrest and the commencement of the recovery actions. Part I.B engages critically with the Second Circuit opinion that set the stage for the clawback suits by denying the Madoff winners’ claims to recover what they believed they were owed based on their last investment account statements. 10 A. BROOKLYN LAW REVIEW [Vol. 78:1 History and Revelation of a Fraud Madoff created Bernard L. Madoff Investment Securities (BLMIS) in the early 1960s,33 originally functioning as a market-maker and broker-dealer.34 Later, Madoff added an investment advisory arm to the business, which Madoff used to recruit investors for his eventual Ponzi scheme.35 Although Madoff, in the course of his confession, reported that the Ponzi scheme began in the early 1990s,36 one of his associates has since revealed that the scheme in fact dated back to the early 1970s.37 It is not clear how much of Madoff’s business was fraudulent in the period between the 1970s and the 1990s. But we do know that beginning in the 1990s, Madoff did not buy or sell a single share on behalf of his customers, despite sending investors regular statements that reported market transactions and indicated an average growth of 12 percent.38 Madoff claimed that his consistent positive returns resulted from a unique split-strike conversion strategy that he had pioneered.39 Because Madoff made no investments, customer redemptions were funded with money that other customers had deposited with him. Thus, when a customer sought to withdraw money from her account in an amount listed on her most recent statement, Madoff made up the difference between the amount the customer had invested and the amount she sought to withdraw with money other customers had “invested” with him.40 Importantly, many of those who withdrew more money from their Madoff accounts than their principal investments were genuinely in the dark about his fraud. For one thing, we 33 Complaint at 4, SEC v. Madoff, 2009 WL 980288 (S.D.N.Y. Apr. 10, 2009) (No. 08-CV-10791). 34 See, e.g., Martin P. Randisi & Joseph Koletar, Holtz Rubenstein Reminick LLP, A CAT Scan of the Madoff Scandal: Diagnosing Fraud Inside the Black Box, at 4, available at http://www.hrcpa.com/Catscan.pdf (last visited Sept. 24, 2012). 35 See, e.g., Plea Allocution of Bernard L. Madoff, at *2, *4, available at http://online.wsj.com/public/resources/documents/20090315madoffall.pdf (last visited Sept. 24, 2012). 36 Id. at *2. 37 See Madoff Associate Says Fraud Went Back to ‘70s, N.Y. TIMES, Nov. 21, 2011, at B4. 38 See Robert J. Rhee, The Madoff Scandal, Market Regulatory Failure and the Business Education of Lawyers, 35 J. CORP. L. 363, 371-72 (2009). Rhee here describes the difficulty that a typical investor would have faced in seeking to establish that these returns were impossible. 39 “The split-strike conversion strategy supposedly involved buying a basket of stocks listed on the Standard & Poor’s 100 Index and hedging through the use of options.” In re Bernard L. Madoff Inv. Sec. LLC, 654 F.3d 229, 231 (2d Cir. 2011). 40 See Plea Allocution of Bernard L. Madoff, supra note 35, at *1. 2012] RIGHTING OTHERS’ WRONGS 11 now know that Madoff was masterful when it came to hiding his fraud. He maintained an aloof posture, often refusing a prospective investor before “accepting” her business;41 his returns were consistent but also relatively modest so as not to arouse suspicion;42 and the purported split-strike conversion strategy was a seemingly plausible vehicle for generating these steady, yet unspectacular returns.43 Further, a securities investor has no duty to inquire about his stockbroker, even if confronted with suspicious circumstances.44 In any event, Madoff’s investors may have had some cause for assurance. In particular, many of them knew that the SEC had investigated Madoff and never uncovered any financial wrongdoing.45 They may even have reasonably relied on the fact that financial regulators believed Madoff’s business to be clean.46 Indeed, if the SEC proved incapable of detecting the fraud, it is not reasonable to suppose that the average investor should have done so. Thus, we may 41 See, e.g., DAVID E.Y. SARNA, HISTORY OF GREED: FINANCIAL FRAUD FROM TULIP MANIA TO BERNIE MADOFF, ch. 21 (2010); Robert Chew, A Madoff Whistle-Blower Tells His Story, TIME (Feb. 4, 2009), http://www.time.com/time/business/article/ 0,8599,1877181,00.html (“Madoff’s greatest talent, the witness indicated, was his use of a ‘hook’ or lure to play ‘hard to get’ and the false security of exclusivity, a hallmark of a Ponzi scheme.”). 42 See, e.g., Sullivan, supra note 9, at 1622-23. 43 See Assessing the Madoff Ponzi Scheme and Regulatory Failures: Hearing Before the Subcomm. on Capital Mkts., Ins., and Gov’t Sponsored Enters. of the H. Comm. on Fin. Servs., 111th Cong. 31 (2009) (testimony of Harry Markopolos, Chartered Financial Analyst, Certified Fraud Examiner) [hereinafter Hearings], available at http://www.gpo.gov/fdsys/pkg/CHRG-111hhrg48673/pdf/CHRG111hhrg48673.pdf (last visited Nov. 5, 2012). See generally Richard Posner, Bernard Madoff and Ponzi Schemes—Posner’s Comment, BECKER-POSNER BLOG (Dec. 21, 2008, 3:45 PM), http://www.becker-posner-blog.com/2008/12/bernard-madoff-and-ponzischemes--posners-comment.html (“The strategy . . . attributed to Madoff is the opposite of that of the typical Ponzi schemer: it [wa]s to obtain investments from well-off people far more financially sophisticated than the average Ponzi victim, including genuine financial experts such as hedge fund managers and bank officials. And therefore it require[d] different tactics from that of the ordinary Ponzi scheme, such as offering returns only moderately above average, satisfying redemption requests promptly, turning down some would-be investors . . . , and trading on a reputation earned in a legitimate business (Madoff’s business of market making).”). 44 See, e.g., Picard v. Katz, 462 B.R. 447, 455 (S.D.N.Y. 2011) (citing In re New Times Sec. Servs., 371 F.3d 68, 87 (2d Cir. 2004)). On the other hand, an investor will undercut his claim to have proceeded in good faith if he has willfully blinded himself to red flags. See id. 45 See, e.g., Zachary A. Goldfarb, SEC Lawyer Raised Madoff Concerns but Was Rebuffed, L.A. TIMES, July 2, 2009, at B3, available at http://articles.latimes.com/ 2009/jul/02/business/fi-sec-madoff2. 46 See, e.g., Herve Stolowy et al., Information, Trust and the Limits of “Intelligent Accountability” in Investment Decision Making: Insights from the Madoff Case 15-17 (Sept. 17, 2011) (unpublished manuscript), available at http://papers.ssrn.com/sol3/ papers.cfm?abstract_id=1930128 (collecting quotes from Madoff investors who stated that they were reassured that the investment scheme was legitimate as a result of the SEC’s failure to uncover any fraud). 12 BROOKLYN LAW REVIEW [Vol. 78:1 assume that many investors in Madoff’s scheme were blamelessly ignorant of his wrongdoing.47 Many investors profited from the fraud, but they did so innocently; they did not know, and had no reason to know, that Madoff was operating a Ponzi scheme.48 With markets crashing in the fall of 2008, an unexpected number of Madoff customers sought to liquidate their accounts. Because Madoff could not possibly satisfy all of the claims, the scheme went bust.49 After Madoff confessed to his family on December 10, 2008, his sons consulted with their lawyer and tipped the police off to the fraud. Madoff was arrested the next day.50 At the time, Madoff had 4800 customers with open accounts, who had invested a total of $20 billion in principal and accumulated an aggregate (fictitious) sum of $65 billion, according to their last statements on November 30, 2008.51 It was clear that Madoff did not have $20 billion in assets to return to his customers, let alone the $65 billion they thought they were owed.52 The company officially went into bankruptcy on the day of Madoff’s arrest.53 47 See generally Felicia Smith, Madoff Ponzi Scheme Exposes “The Myth of the Sophisticated Investor,” 40 U. BALT. L. REV. 215, 273 & n.305 (2010) (citing arguments that regulations concerning who counts as a sophisticated investor are too broad as, for example, where a high net wealth is sufficient to qualify the investor as “sophisticated”). 48 Picard acknowledges this when he states, on the webpage summarizing his efforts, that “[s]ome BLMIS customers unwittingly withdrew funds that were, in reality, money stolen by Madoff from other BLMIS customers.” A Message from SIPA Trustee Irving H. Picard, MADOFF RECOVERY INITIATIVE, http://madoff.com/trusteemessage-24.html (last visited Mar. 6, 2012) (emphasis added). 49 See, e.g., David A. Gradwohl & Karin Corbett, Equity Receiverships for Ponzi Schemes, 34 SETON HALL LEGIS. J. 181, 189 (2010) (“With Madoff, the engine of fraud churned on until the collapse of the securities markets caused new investors to stop feeding the scheme and made it impossible for Madoff to continue.”). 50 See, e.g., The Madoff Case: A Timeline, WALL ST. J. (Mar. 12, 2009), http://online.wsj.com/article/SB112966954231272304.html?mod=googlenews_wsj; Diana B. Henriques, New Description of Timing on Madoff’s Confession, N.Y. TIMES, Jan. 9, 2009, at B1, available at http://www.nytimes.com/2009/01/10/business/10madoff.html?_r=1; Ellen S. Podgor, Madoff, WHITE COLLAR CRIME PROF. BLOG (Dec. 16, 2008), http://lawprofessors.typepad.com/whitecollarcrime_blog/2008/12/the-madoff-case.html (listing a variety of media reports on the Madoff Ponzi scheme). 51 See, e.g., Allison Hoffman, Prosecutors Submit Scam E-mail with Madoff Victim Letters, JERUSALEM POST, Mar. 24, 2009, available at http://www.jpost.com/ International/Article.aspx?id=136942. 52 See, e.g., Linda Sandler, Madoff Brokerage, Homes, Boats Valued at $1 Billion (Update2), BLOOMBERG (Jan. 9, 2009, 11:43 AM), http://www.bloomberg.com/ apps/news?pid=newsarchive&sid=aZP0jyjuTdTI. 53 See Sec. Investor Prot. Corp. v. Bernard L. Madoff Inv. Sec. LLC (In re Bernard L. Madoff Inv. Sec. LLC) (In re Madoff II), 429 B.R. 423 (Bankr. S.D.N.Y. 2010), aff’d, 848 F. Supp. 2d 469 (S.D.N.Y. 2012); Sec. Investor Prot. Corp. v. Bernard L. Madoff Inv. Sec. LLC (In re Bernard L. Madoff Inv. Sec. LLC) (In re Madoff I), 424 B.R. 122, 124 & n.3 (Bankr. S.D.N.Y. 2010), aff’d, 654 F.3d 229 (2d Cir. 2011). 2012] RIGHTING OTHERS’ WRONGS 13 Pursuant to the Securities Investor Protection Act (SIPA), Irving Picard was appointed as a trustee to recover money and redistribute it to creditors of the estate.54 SIPA instructs the trustee “to distribute customer property and . . . otherwise satisfy net equity claims,”55 and “to liquidate the business of the debtor.”56 For the latter, the trustee must proceed in accordance with the bankruptcy code under Title 11.57 In structuring his recovery efforts, the trustee has been required to address two broad questions: first, who is entitled to restitution, and second, who should provide restitution to those entitled to it? The clawback suits against innocent investors provide a partial response to the second question, and their justifiability is the major focus of this article. Nonetheless, an examination of the trustee’s response to the first question is also useful, since it demonstrates the legal uncertainty in this area and sets the stage for the clawback suits. B. Defining “Net Equity” The Securities Investor Protection Act (SIPA) provides that, in the event a broker-dealer fails and is unable to cover its obligations, the trustee shall “distribute customer property and otherwise satisfy net equity claims of customers.”58 Among the first questions for Picard to resolve were who would count as a customer entitled to “customer property,” and what net equity these customers were due. In Madoff’s case, delineating the set of customers was rather complicated. While some of those who lost money as a result of Madoff’s fraud had invested directly with Madoff, others had invested in Madoff “feeder funds.” Sixteen feeder funds brought suit, seeking to have their status as SIPA investors recognized. Judge Burton Lifland, the bankruptcy judge handling the Madoff SIPA liquidation, denied them relief and held that they do not count as 54 See, e.g., A Message from SIPA Trustee, Irving H. Picard, MADOFF RECOVERY INITIATIVE, http://www.madoff.com/trustee-message-02.html (last visited Mar. 6, 2012). This is the trustee home page for the website the Madoff SIPA trustee has established to report on the progress of the case and provide interested parties with relevant information. On this page, Picard explains that “On the day the news [of Madoff’s fraud] broke, I received a call from the Securities Investor Protection Corporation (‘SIPC’) and was asked to serve as SIPA Trustee for the liquidation of Bernard L. Madoff Investment Securities LLC (‘BLMIS’) under the Securities Investor Protection Act (‘SIPA’).” 55 Securities Investor Protection Act of 1970, 15 U.S.C. § 78fff(a)(1)(B) (2006). 56 Id. § 78fff(a)(4). 57 Id. § 78fff-4(e). 58 Id. § 78fff(a)(1)(B). 14 BROOKLYN LAW REVIEW [Vol. 78:1 “customers” under the SIPA statute.59 The feeder funds appealed, but Judge Lifland’s decision was affirmed by the District Court for the Southern District of New York in an opinion issued in January of this year.60 When it came to determining the customers’ “net equity”—i.e., the money they were entitled to recover—there arose a “controversy of staggering proportions involving statutory interpretation, statutory purpose, the relationship of multiple SIPA and bankruptcy law provisions, and fundamental bankruptcy law philosophy.”61 Using the “Last Statement” method of calculating net equity, investors in Madoff’s scheme asserted claims in the amounts listed on the last statements they had received before the fund’s collapse.62 On the other hand, relying on the “Net Investment” or “Cash-In-Cash-Out” method, Picard, along with the SEC and SIPC, believed that the Madoff investors should be entitled only to the amounts they had deposited, minus any money withdrawn.63 In a March 1, 2010 opinion, Judge Lifland adopted the “Net Investment” method: customers would be entitled to recover only their principal, minus any withdrawals they had 59 See Sec. Investor Prot. Corp. v. Bernard L. Madoff Inv. Sec. (In re Bernard L. Madoff) (In re Madoff III), 454 B.R. 285 (Bankr. S.D.N.Y. 2011), aff’d sub nom. Aozora Bank Ltd. v. Sec. Investor Prot. Corp., No. 1:11-CV-05683-DLC, 2012 BL 54585 (S.D.N.Y. Jan. 4, 2012). 60 See generally Aozora Bank, 2012 BL 54585. 61 Paul Sinclair & Brendan McPherson, The Sad Tale of Multiple Overlapping Fraudulent Transfers: Part IV, 29 AM. BANKR. INST. J., May 2010, at 18. 62 See, e.g., In re Bernard L. Madoff Inv. Sec. LLC, 654 F.3d 229, 233 (2d Cir. 2011); Peter J. Henning, The Next Test for the Madoff Trustee, N.Y. TIMES (DEALBOOK) (Mar. 2, 2011, 8:50 AM), http://dealbook.nytimes.com/2011/03/02/the-next-test-for-themadoff-trustee/. 63 See In re Bernard L. Madoff Inv. Sec., 654 F.3d at 233; Henning, supra note 62. It may be worth noting in this context that SIPC pays Picard’s salary for the Madoff litigation (though SIPC will recover the payments it makes to Picard through whatever funds he is able to recoup). See, e.g., Gretchen Morgenson, Many Holes Weaken Safety Net for Victims of Failed Brokerages, N.Y. TIMES, Sept. 25, 2000, at A1, A24. This arrangement can prompt the trustee in a SIPA proceeding, who likely wants to become or remain a repeat player in this game, to be chary with claims and aggressive with recovery efforts. Id. An uncharitable take on Picard would find evidence for this motivation in his narrow reading of “net equity.” Cf. Paul Sinclair & Brendan McPherson, Does SIPC Protect Customers in Ponzi Scheme Cases? Sad Tales of Multiple Overlapping Fraudulent Transfers IV, 7 AM. BANKR. INST.: COMMERCIAL FRAUD COMM. NEWS, Sept. 2010, at 267-68, available at http://www.abiworld.org/committees/ newsletters/CFTF/vol7num3/sipc.pdf (commenting on the “net equity” decision in the Madoff case, and contending that “[t]his SIPC controversy . . . is further infected by the SIPC’s position as an industry body, rather than a governmental agency charged to protect investors, and thus its alleged effort to simply reduce its losses to the most limited amounts”). 2012] RIGHTING OTHERS’ WRONGS 15 made over the life of their investments.64 The Second Circuit affirmed this decision in an opinion issued on August 16, 2011,65 adducing three grounds in support of its decision. Specifically, the court argued that allowing the net winners to recover any of the money they believed resided in their accounts would (1) place the trustee in the impossible position of having to invent recovery entitlements, given that Madoff’s records were completely fictitious and could not provide any basis for ascertaining how much “profit” any investor was due; (2) unjustly enrich the winners at the expense of the losers; and (3) problematically legitimate Madoff’s fraud by recognizing and upholding the fiction he had perpetrated. I address each of these in turn, and I argue that none is convincing on its own or in combination with the others. 1. Unascertainable Holdings The court’s first set of arguments relates to administrative convenience. The SIPA statute requires the trustee “to make payments to customers based on ‘net equity’ insofar as the amount owed to the customer is ‘ascertainable from the books and records of the debtor or [is] otherwise established to the satisfaction of the trustee.’”66 Because Madoff’s books and records were “after-the-fact constructs that were based on stock movements that had already taken place,” the Second Circuit found that net equity could not be ascertained by reference to them.67 However, it is worth noting that the plain text of the SIPA statute does not restrict net equity calculations to those ascertainable from the debtors’ books and records, but instead explicitly allows alternative methods that are “to the satisfaction of the trustee.”68 Elsewhere, the court acknowledged the considerable discretion a SIPA trustee possesses in determining net equity,69 thereby 64 See In re Madoff I, 424 B.R. 122 (Bankr. S.D.N.Y. 2010), aff’d, 654 F.3d 229 (2d Cir. 2011). 65 See generally In re Bernard L. Madoff Inv. Sec., 654 F.3d 229. A group of investors who would be ineligible for net equity under the decision filed an appeal with the Supreme Court, which denied certiorari on June 25, 2012. See Velvel v. Picard, No. 11-986, 2012 WL 435188, at *1 (U.S. June 25, 2012); Ryan v. Picard, No. 11-969, 2012 WL 396489, at *1 (U.S. June 25, 2012). 66 In re Bernard L. Madoff Inv. Sec., 654 F.3d at 237 (quoting 15 U.S.C. § 78fff-2(b) (2006)) (alteration in original). 67 Id. at 238. 68 15 U.S.C. § 78fff-2(b)(2). 69 “[I]n many circumstances a SIPA trustee may, and should, exercise some discretion in determining what method, or combination of methods, will best measure 16 BROOKLYN LAW REVIEW [Vol. 78:1 refusing to endorse the Cash-In-Cash-Out method as the strategy to be pursued in each and every case.70 Thus, it is possible that an alternative to both the Last Statement and Net Investment methods exists, that this alternative is preferable as a matter of fairness to either of these methods, and that the trustee would be acting within his authority were he to pursue it.71 As the court itself acknowledged, it would be compelled to “accord a degree of deference to [the trustee’s] exercise of discretion so long as the method chosen by the trustee allocates ‘net equity’ among the competing claimants in a manner that is not clearly inferior to other methods under consideration.”72 With that said, since the pool of accumulated funds would be divided among a greater number of claimants, an alternative definition of net equity that enlarges the set of investors entitled to recovery would entail, all else being equal, a smaller recovery for each. This would mean that investors who had not recovered their principal at the time of the scheme’s collapse would be made less whole under this alternative than under the Cash-In-Cash-Out method—a problematic outcome if one believes that all of the investors should be restored to their pre-Madoff positions before any of them is entitled to profit from the scheme. Indeed, this concern appears to animate the court’s second and third lines of argument. ‘net equity.’” In re Bernard L. Madoff Inv. Sec., 654 F.3d at 238 n.7. Cf. Sullivan, supra note 9, at 1600 (noting, in the context of a bankruptcy trustee’s efforts to recover money for defrauded investors in a Ponzi scheme that “the court is given broad powers to rule on a plan of distribution, subject only to the requirement that the court use its discretion in a logical way to divide the money.” (citations omitted)); Spencer C. Barasch & Sara J. Chesnut, Controversial Uses of the “Clawback” Remedy in the Current Financial Crisis, 72 TEX. B.J. 922, 926 (2009) (“The trustee or receiver in a Ponzi scheme has a fair amount of discretion in whether to pursue claims against investors and other transferees.”). 70 Thus the court made clear that its approach here was determined by the unique circumstances of the case: In holding that it was proper for Mr. Picard to reject the Last Statement Method, we expressly do not hold that such a method of calculating “net equity” is inherently impermissible. To the contrary, a customer’s last account statement will likely be the most appropriate means of calculating “net equity” in more conventional cases . . . . The extraordinary facts of this case make the Net Investment Method appropriate, whereas in many instances, it would not be. In re Bernard L. Madoff Inv. Sec., 654 F.3d at 238. 71 For example, the trustee might have determined what each Madoff investor would have been owed had Madoff invested all of the money he received in an S&P 500 index for the duration of the investment; the trustee could then have taken this sum as the basis for determining each investor’s pro rata share, with deductions for money already withdrawn. 72 Id. at 238 n.7. 2012] RIGHTING OTHERS’ WRONGS 17 2. Unjust Enrichment In a second set of arguments, the court expressed concern that crediting investors with any amount of “interest” would leave less money in the pot with which to make losing investors whole.73 As an initial matter, it is certainly true that permitting principal plus some post hoc assignment of profits as the basis of recovery—rather than principal alone—would create a larger outstanding sum owed to investors, such that each losing investor would receive less than under the Net Investment method. But this outcome represents an “inequitable consequence” only if we have reason to privilege lost principal over lost (purported) earnings. Under a legitimate investment, winning customers who had not yet cashed out would be owed the amounts on their last statements, even though they had already recovered the amounts of their deposits and even if, because of the estate’s insolvency, seeking to pay the winners their outstanding profits would entail that losing customers would receive less than the full amount of their deposits in return. In other words, where there has been legitimate investment activity, bankruptcy law does not require that each investor receive his out-of-pocket investment amount before any investor can receive earnings on top of that investment. Yet, in such a case, winning investors do receive an “additional benefit at the expense of” losing investors.74 The question then arises: If the disparity isn’t unfair in the case of genuine investments, why does the fictitious nature of the investments render it unfair? The court, in its third argument, offers what appears to be a response. 3. Legitimating Fraud In endorsing the trustee’s interpretation of net equity, the court stated that the “[t]rustee properly declined to calculate ‘net equity’ by reference to impossible transactions. Indeed, if the [t]rustee had done otherwise, the whim of the 73 “The inequitable consequence of such a scheme would be that those who had already withdrawn cash deriving from imaginary profits in excess of their initial investment would derive additional benefit at the expense of those customers who had not withdrawn funds before the fraud was exposed.” Id. at 238; see also id. at 235 (quoting approvingly from the bankruptcy court’s underlying opinion, in which Judge Lifland argued that “[a]ny dollar paid to reimburse a fictitious profit is a dollar no longer available to pay claims for money actually invested.” In re Madoff I, 424 B.R. 122, 141 (Bankr. S.D.N.Y. 2010)). 74 In re Bernard L. Madoff Inv. Sec., 654 F.3d at 238. 18 BROOKLYN LAW REVIEW [Vol. 78:1 defrauder would have controlled the process that is supposed to unwind the fraud.”75 Part of the court’s concern arose from the fact that the “profits” Madoff recorded “were arbitrarily and unequally distributed among customers.”76 For instance, Madoff accorded significantly higher returns to his preferred clientele; the disparity in return rates had nothing to do with market performance and everything to do with Madoff’s whims. The court correctly agreed with the trustee in declining to countenance this aspect of the fraud. As the bankruptcy judge had stated—and the Second Circuit quoted approvingly— the trustee rightly “refuse[d] to permit Madoff to arbitrarily decide who wins and who loses.”77 This refusal correctly impugns the Last Statement method, at least as it applies to those whose account statements were whimsically inflated by Madoff. But again, it does not compel the Net Investment method. The trustee might instead have found an objective measure to project the amount investors would have been owed had Madoff invested their money in a legitimate vehicle. In this way, he would not have had to rely on, let alone credit, the disparate ways in which Madoff treated his investors. Further, contrary to the suggestion of the bankruptcy court and Second Circuit, there is no basis for the notion that recognizing a recovery amount that allows interest on investors’ deposits involves a kind of complicity in, or affirmation of, the fraud.78 Indeed, one might wonder how seeking to make all investors whole, or fulfilling their “legitimate expectations,” legitimizes Madoff’s fraud, rather than undercuts it. After all, in a Ponzi scheme, it is presumed that the scheme’s operator intends to defraud or otherwise hinder his investors’ ability to recover their investment.79 A recovery program more expansive than Picard’s would then thwart, rather than serve, this presumed intention. In sum, the Last Statement method may well be flawed. But it is not at all clear that the Net Investment method is more justifiable, either as a matter of law or fairness. Indeed, the Net 75 76 77 Id. at 241. Id. at 238. Id. (quoting In re Madoff I, 424 B.R. at 140) (internal quotation marks omitted). 78 See In re Bernard L. Madoff Inv. Sec., 654 F.3d at 238; In re Madoff I, 424 B.R. at 136 (stating that the Net Investment method allowed Picard to “unwind[], rather than legitimiz[e], the fraudulent scheme”). 79 See infra note 90 and accompanying text (describing the Ponzi scheme presumption). 2012] RIGHTING OTHERS’ WRONGS 19 Investment method generates fairness concerns that extend well beyond the denial of the winners’ claims to any recovery.80 C. Setting the Stage for the Clawback Actions To grasp the implications of the net equity decision for the clawback actions, it will be helpful to consider a hypothetical Madoff investor. Suppose, for example, that investor Smith opened an account with Madoff in 1980 with a one-time deposit of $1 million, and that he withdrew money from his account only once, in 2004, when he retrieved $2 million; then, on November 30, 2008, Smith received a statement from BLMIS indicating that he had $8 million left in his Madoff account. How would Smith fare in light of the net equity decision? First, that decision allowed Madoff’s customers to be divided into two groups—“winners” and “losers.” “Winners” were those investors who had withdrawn more money from their accounts than they had deposited. “Losers,” on the other hand, still had some or all of their principal invested with Madoff at the time of the fund’s collapse, and they would sustain a net loss if that money were not returned to them. Because the amount of Smith’s 2004 withdrawal ($2 million) was greater than the amount of his total deposit ($1 million), he would be counted among the Madoff “winners.” Second, the decision entailed that only the Madoff “losers” would count as “customers” for purposes of recovering net equity. Net “winners,” on the other hand, would join the ranks of other creditors of the estate, recovering the fictitious amounts they thought they were owed only if the “losers” were first made whole.81 Thus, even though Smith reasonably relied upon the veracity of his BLMIS statements, including the last statement indicating an $8 million balance in his Madoff account, he would not be entitled to recover any more than $1 million under the Bankruptcy Court’s interpretation of net equity. Third, the problem is not simply that “winners” with open accounts would be barred from recovering any money as customers of the estate. They might also be required to return their “winnings”—i.e., all money withdrawn in excess of that 80 See supra notes 61-74 and accompanying text (discussing the fairness implications of the Net Investment method). 81 See, e.g., What Is the Difference Between the Customer Fund and the General Estate?, MADOFF RECOVERY INITIATIVE, http://www.madoff.com/facts-08.html (last visited Aug. 15, 2012). 20 BROOKLYN LAW REVIEW [Vol. 78:1 which they had invested. Thus, Smith could be subject to a clawback action for the $1 million he withdrew in excess of his $1 million investment. Indeed, we now know that many reallife “winners” in Madoff’s Ponzi scheme, including some whom Picard believes to have been innocently ignorant of the fraud, have been named as defendants in his clawback suits. Finally, if the bankruptcy trustee could establish that Smith evinced a lack of good faith at the time that he received the $2 million, matters would be even worse for Smith in light of the bankruptcy code provision described below, which allows the trustee to void a transfer if the transferee knew or had reason to know of the fraud at the time of the transfer. In that case, the trustee could seek return of not just the $1 million in “profits” that Smith withdrew, but also the $1 million that represented Smith’s principal. In other words, if it were shown that Smith knew or had reason to know of the fraud, the entire $2 million transfer could be voided, leaving Smith with a net loss of one million real dollars.82 Here, too, there are real-world examples, including the clawback suit Picard filed against the owners of the New York Mets, whom he has accused of willful ignorance, and against whom he sought return of both principal and “profits.”83 Critically, the net equity decision did not, as a matter of law or logic, compel the trustee’s clawback suits. One could consistently hold both that Madoff investors with outstanding account balances were not eligible to recover more money than they had deposited and that those investors who had already withdrawn more than they had deposited would nonetheless get to keep the withdrawn “profits.” Put another way, the fact that “winners” would not be entitled to recovery in the bankruptcy proceedings need not have entailed that they would have an additional obligation to return the “winnings” they received before the bankruptcy. Thus, to return to our hypothetical example, Smith could have been foreclosed from seeking to 82 In Picard v. HSBC Bank PLC, Judge Jed Rakoff dismissed the bankruptcy trustee’s common law aiding and abetting claims against HSBC, which is accused of having funneled investors to Madoff, in part on the basis of the doctrine of in pari delicto, or “unclean hands.” 454 B.R. 25, 37 (S.D.N.Y. 2011). That doctrine prevents one wrongdoer from suing one of her fellow wrongdoers for damages arising from their shared wrongdoing. Id. With the HSBC decision as support, it may be that investors accused of bad faith will raise an in pari delicto defense. See Peter J. Henning, Madoff Trustee’s Job Just Became Much Tougher, N.Y. TIMES (DEALBOOK) (July 29, 2011), http://dealbook.nytimes.com/2011/07/29/madoff-trustees-job-just-became-much-tougher/. 83 See, e.g., Toobin, supra note 8. 2012] RIGHTING OTHERS’ WRONGS 21 recover the $8 million he thought he had in his Madoff account but permitted to keep the $2 million he had withdrawn.84 Nonetheless, as of December 10, 2010, Picard had filed complaints against over one thousand investors seeking return of their “fictitious profits,” and in some cases their withdrawn principal,85 for a total possible recovery of more than $100 billion.86 I turn now to an analysis of the doctrinal foundations for these suits. II. THE DOCTRINE OF FRAUDULENT CONVEYANCE The term “Ponzi scheme” dates back to the infamous scheme perpetrated by Charles Ponzi in the early 1920s.87 Yet it was only in the mid-1980s that bankruptcy trustees in Ponzi scheme cases began to pursue clawback actions against innocent investors who withdrew more than they had invested in the scheme.88 The clawback suits rely upon a provision of the 84 One might worry that, given that the estate was bankrupt, there would have been no money with which to make the losers whole unless Picard pursued clawbacks against innocent winners. But as I describe infra, Picard ended up filing clawback suits seeking a total of more than $100 billion, even though the outstanding principle did not amount to more than $20 billion. See infra note 85 and accompanying text. The $100 billion figure stemmed from claims of punitive damages in those cases where the trustee alleged that the transferee had known of, or been willfully blind to, the fraud, and so would not be permitted to keep either the principal or profits. See, e.g., Complaint at ¶ 8, Picard v. JPMorgan Chase & Co., 460 B.R. 84 (S.D.N.Y. 2010) (seeking $19 billion, comprised of money the bank earned from Madoff’s account as well as punitive damages). In short, there might well have been enough money to fund the recovery even if the innocent winners were not made to contribute to the customer fund. And, even if there wouldn’t have been enough money, it is not at all clear that that outcome would be unfair to the losers—indeed, that is just the issue I seek to settle here. 85 See, e.g., Joe Palazzolo, Picard Dealt Another Blow, WALL ST. J.L. BLOG (Nov. 2, 2011, 11:34 AM), http://blogs.wsj.com/law/2011/11/02/picard-dealt-anotherblow-by-sdny/. 86 See, e.g., id. 87 See Cunningham v. Brown, 265 U.S. 1, 7-9 (1924) (discussing the collapse of Charles Ponzi’s fraudulent investment program); Mark A. McDermott, Ponzi Schemes and the Law of Fraudulent and Preferential Transfers, 72 AM. BANKR. L.J. 157, 158 (1998). Ponzi was not the first to perpetrate the kind of fraud that now bears his name. In 1880, for example, Ferdinand Ward orchestrated just this kind of fraud, ensnaring, among others, Ulysses S. Grant. See generally GEOFFREY C. WARD, A DISPOSITION TO BE RICH (2012) (a recounting of Ferdinand Ward’s fraud written by a renowned historical writer, who happens to be the fraudster’s great-grandson). 88 A Westlaw search for all federal and state cases containing the terms “Ponzi” and “fraudulent conveyance” or “fraudulent transfer” turns up 190 cases. Only four of these arose before 1984. The first three stem from Charles Ponzi’s scheme itself, and only one of these was successful. More specifically, in Engstrom v. Lowell, the trustee lost because the law in question required the trustee to establish that the defendant—i.e., the target of the clawback suit—had actual knowledge of the fraud, and this the trustee failed to do. 281 F. 973, 976 (1st Cir. 1922). The trustee lost a second case arising from Ponzi’s fraud on similar grounds. See Cunningham v. Merchs.’ 22 BROOKLYN LAW REVIEW [Vol. 78:1 bankruptcy code that SIPA borrows from,89 allowing a SIPA trustee to void (or, to use the technical term, “avoid”) any transfer from the debtor’s estate that was conveyed fraudulently.90 More specifically, 11 U.S.C. § 548 provides that a bankruptcy trustee: may avoid any transfer . . . if the debtor voluntarily or involuntarily (A) made such transfer with actual intent to hinder, delay, or defraud any entity to which the debtor was or became, on or after the date that such transfer was made . . . , indebted; or (B)(i) received less than a reasonably equivalent value in exchange for such transfer . . . ; and (ii) [the debtor was insolvent, undercapitalized, or overextended at the time of the transfer, or he became so as a result of the transfer].91 Subsection (A) of the provision pertains to cases of actual fraud,92 while subsection (B) pertains to cases of constructive fraud.93 Nat’l Bank of Manchester, N.H., 4 F.2d 25 (1st Cir. 1925). In a 1924 opinion, the Supreme Court did approve the trustee’s efforts to void the withdrawals investors in Ponzi’s fraud made after the Boston Post exposed the fraud, Cunningham, 265 U.S. at 9-14, but the clawbacks in that case derived not from the Bankruptcy Code’s fraudulent transfer provision—as Picard’s clawback suits do—but instead from its preference avoidance provision. I elaborate on the distinction between these two provisions below. See infra notes 107-09 and accompanying text. The next published opinion involving clawbacks from investors in a Ponzi scheme was issued in a 1966 case where the Sixth Circuit affirmed the District Court’s decision allowing the bankruptcy trustee to reclaim money received by an associate of the Ponzi schemer who was held to have had reason to know, if not actual knowledge of the fraud. See Conroy v. Shott (In re Cohen), 363 F.2d 90, 92-93 (6th Cir. 1966). That case, thus, did not involve an innocent investor. The first published case involving a successful avoidance action against an innocent investor on fraudulent conveyance grounds was decided in 1989. See Wootton v. Barge, 875 F.2d 508, 510-11 (5th Cir. 1989). Federal bankruptcy law was overhauled in 1979, with the Bankruptcy Reform Act of 1979 replacing the Bankruptcy Act of 1898. See, e.g., Robert J. White, Leveraged Buyouts and Fraudulent Conveyance Laws Under the Bankruptcy Code—Like Oil and Water, They Just Don’t Mix, 1991 ANN. SURV. AM. L. 357, 358 (1991). Nonetheless, fraudulent conveyances provisions can be found in both Acts, see id., and Ponzi scheme cases date back to the 1920s, so the upswing in Ponzi scheme clawback cases cannot be attributed to the statutory change. 89 See 15 U.S.C. § 78fff-4(e) (2006). 90 Excellent overviews of the doctrine governing clawbacks in the wake of a Ponzi scheme can be found in Mark A. McDermott, Ponzi Schemes and the Law of Fraudulent and Preferential Transfers, 72 AM. BANKR. L.J. 157, 223-25 (1998); see also Tally M. Wiener, On the Clawbacks in the Madoff Liquidation Proceeding, 15 FORDHAM J. CORP. & FIN. L. 221, 223 n.7 (2009). 91 11 U.S.C. § 548(a)(1)(A)-(B) (2006). 92 Courts proceed as if there is a presumption of actual fraud in every Ponzi scheme case, since there will never be enough money in the scheme to provide all investors with a return of their principal along with the promised returns, and “since a failure to redeem in accordance with the investor’s expectation based on inflated account statements would . . . result[] in the investigation and discovery of the fraud.” Barasch & Chesnut, supra note 69, at 926 (citing In re Bayou Grp., 396 B.R. 810, 843 (S.D.N.Y. 2008)). See, e.g., SEC v. Res. Dev. Int’l, 487 F.3d 295, 301 (5th Cir. 2007) (“In this circuit, proving that IERC (International Education Research Corporation) operated as a Ponzi scheme establishes the fraudulent intent behind the transfers it 2012] RIGHTING OTHERS’ WRONGS 23 On its face, the text of this provision permits two different interpretations of the provision’s rationale. According to the first, the purpose of the fraudulent transfer provision is to prevent the debtor from secreting away his assets, typically for his own benefit, such that they are beyond the reach of his creditors. I refer to this as the anti-fraud reading (AF) of § 548. According to the second, the even distribution reading (ED), the purpose of the fraudulent transfer provision is to ensure the most even distribution of assets as possible by conferring upon each creditor his pro-rata share of the recovered resources.94 made.” (citation omitted)); In re Manhattan Inv. Fund Ltd., 397 B.R. 1, 8 (S.D.N.Y. 2007) (“There is a general rule—known as the ‘Ponzi scheme presumption’—that such a scheme demonstrates ‘actual intent’ as matter of law because ‘transfers made in the course of a Ponzi scheme could have been made for no purpose other than to hinder, delay or defraud creditors.’” (citation omitted)). See generally McDermott, supra note 87, at 173-74 & n.66 (collecting cases). Nonetheless, a lawyer representing a defendant in a clawback suit might want to argue that the presumption is unwarranted. The actual fraud provision refers not to the Ponzi scheme operator’s global or over-arching intention with respect to the scheme, but rather to the operator’s intentions relative to the transfers that are the subject of the clawback suit. It may be that the operator had no intention to defraud anyone when he made those transfers. Indeed, this would seem to be especially true for those transfers made early in the scheme, when the operator might well have believed that the scheme was a temporary measure, and that subsequent legitimate investments would allow him to recover the money that he had diverted from one investor to another, thereby restoring the investor whose investment had been diverted. 93 It is worth noting that there is a disagreement among courts as to whether the investor’s deposits constitute “reasonably equivalent value” for any profits she receives over and above the amount deposited. See, e.g., McDermott, supra note 90, at 164-65 & n.36 (collecting cases). Judge Posner has argued that the fictitious profits should be subject to clawback even if one grants that the investor’s principal constituted fair consideration: We said that [the clawback target’s] profit was supported by consideration. But what was the source of the profit? A theft by [the Ponzi scheme operator] from other investors. What then is [the clawback target’s] moral claim to keep his profit? None, even if the intent in paying him his profit was not fraudulent. Scholes v. Lehmann, 56 F.3d 750, 757 (7th Cir. 1995). Posner’s argument begs the question insofar as it privileges the “theft” that the scheme perpetrates against the losing investor over the fraud that the scheme perpetrates against the winning investor: Suppose that the debtor genuinely owed W money, and that the debtor could obtain the money owed only by stealing from L, and so the debtor proceeded to steal from L. We would think that W was required to return the money to L only if we discounted W’s claim to the money. But why should the debtor’s obligation to give money to W count for less than L’s entitlement to the stolen money? To be sure, the situation looks like the classic case of stolen goods, where the bona fide recipient must return the stolen good even if she had no reason to know it was stolen when she acquired it; Posner’s rhetoric— referring to the Ponzi scheme as a theft—certainly underscores the force of the analogy. Nonetheless, I go on to discuss both the ways in which the law of stolen goods is both inapposite and inadequately justified. See infra Part III.B. 94 Robert Clark uses the term “evenhandedness” to refer to one of the objectives of the avoidance provisions in bankruptcy law. Robert Charles Clark, The Duties of the Corporate Debtor to Its Creditors, 90 HARV. L. REV. 505, 511-12 (1977). As 24 BROOKLYN LAW REVIEW [Vol. 78:1 Put differently, AF attends to the value of the estate, while ED attends to its distribution among creditors. In this Part, I argue that Picard’s clawback actions find support only in the ED reading of § 548, but that the history and text of § 548 strongly favor the AF reading. A. The Even Distribution (ED) Reading One could argue that the letter of the law is compatible with the ED reading and therefore supports the clawback actions. For example, subsection (B) under § 548, which is intended to cover instances of constructive fraud, allows for avoidance of a transfer “if the debtor voluntarily or involuntarily . . . (i) received less than a reasonably equivalent value in exchange for such transfer,” and (ii) the debtor was insolvent, undercapitalized, or overextended at the time of the transfer, or he became so as a result of the transfer.95 In defending the propriety of the Madoff clawback suits against this provision, one could contend that any “profits” that a Madoff customer withdrew were profits for which the fund received less than a “reasonably equivalent value.” This money exceeds the amount the customer had invested. Further, since Madoff had promised customers returns that he could not possibly produce—again, he hadn’t invested their deposits at all, so there was no way for the deposits to appreciate in value—he was necessarily insolvent at the time of any customer’s withdrawal. Thus, the winners’ “winnings” appear to satisfy § 548’s criteria for a constructively fraudulent transfer and accordingly appear subject to avoidance. The problem with this reasoning is that the clawback actions deviate from the spirit of the fraudulent transfer provision. More specifically, if we look at the history of the fraudulent transfer provision, as well as other elements of the statutory scheme, it becomes clear that the intent of the fraudulent transfer provision is not to recoup money from transferees like the Madoff “winners.” he explains, “the ideal of Evenhandedness toward creditors . . . connot[es] . . . equality of treatment of legal obligations in connection with liquidation proceedings.” Id. 95 11 U.S.C. § 548(a)(1)(B). 2012] B. RIGHTING OTHERS’ WRONGS 25 The Anti-Fraud (AF) Reading The bankruptcy code’s fraudulent transfer provision has its genesis in the 1571 Statute of Elizabeth,96 which is virtually identical in its language to subsection (A) of the current fraudulent transfer provision. That 1571 law provided that creditors may avoid “fraudulent . . . Conveyaunces,” which were made with the “Intent to delaye[,] hynder[,] or defraude Creditors . . . .”97 By comparison, 11 U.S.C. § 548(a)(1) provides: “The trustee may avoid any transfer . . . if the debtor voluntarily or involuntarily—(A) made such transfer . . . with actual intent to hinder, delay, or defraud any entity to which the debtor was or became, on or after the date that such transfer was made or such obligation was incurred, indebted . . . .”98 The basic idea behind the Statute of Elizabeth was to counteract certain kinds of mischief. For example, at the time, there were certain sanctuaries into which the king’s writ could not enter. As a result, debtors would take refuge in these sanctuaries, but before doing so, they would sell their assets to friends and family members for a nominal sum in order to prevent creditors from reaching them. Then, when their creditors finally gave up or the statute of limitations expired, the debtor would buy back the assets from his friends and family and, presumably, live happily ever after.99 To prevent this practice, the Statute of Elizabeth was passed. For example, under the statute, if the debtor sold his flock of sheep for a pittance, creditors could avoid the transfer and undo it, thereby returning the sheep to the estate so that creditors could access their value.100 The untoward act that the Statute of Elizabeth contemplated was not one where the debtor gives money to creditor A and thereby leaves less in the pot for creditor B. It was instead the situation in which the debtor seeks to frustrate recovery on the part of all of his creditors, by transferring title of his assets to another with the express purpose of reclaiming them once the debtor was beyond the reach of his creditors. In other words, the Statute of Elizabeth did not seek an even 96 See Douglas G. Baird & Thomas H. Jackson, Fraudulent Conveyance Law and its Proper Domain, 38 VAND. L. REV. 829, 829-30 (1985). 97 13 Eliz. I, ch. 5 (1571) (Eng.), DURHAM UNIV. (UK), available at http://familyrecords.dur.ac.uk/nei/NEI_13Elizabeth1c5.htm (last visited Nov. 5, 2012). 98 11 U.S.C. § 548(a)(1)(A). 99 See Baird & Jackson, supra note 96, at 829. 100 The example is Baird and Jackson’s. See id. at 852. 26 BROOKLYN LAW REVIEW [Vol. 78:1 distribution among all creditors. It merely sought to prevent situations where the debtor attempted to safeguard assets for his own enjoyment of them. The rationale behind the Statute of Elizabeth is enshrined in current law, as can be gleaned from various elements in today’s bankruptcy code. Consider, for example, the provision permitting avoidance of a transfer just so long as it was made with fraudulent intent.101 If the objective of the fraudulent transfer provision were to ensure an even distribution among creditors, it would make no sense to permit avoidance only where the debtor transferred assets with an actual or constructive fraudulent intent. For example, suppose that the year before our “Elizabethan deadbeat”102 became insolvent,103 he gave his flock of sheep to his doctor in exchange for medical services rendered, with no expectation of having the sheep returned. The transfer would not be fraudulent, and yet the value of the estate would be diminished to the same extent as in the case where the debtor has given his brother the flock of sheep for the sake of putting them out of his creditors’ reach. If we really were concerned about ensuring that all creditors share equally in the losses, we would require the doctor to return the sheep and line up with the other creditors for his pro rata share of the estate. Allowing the doctor to retain the sheep simply because they were not conveyed with a fraudulent intent suggests that we are not concerned with ensuring an even distribution.104 A second piece of evidence supporting the AF reading over the ED reading emerges from a provision in the bankruptcy code that allows the target of a clawback action to marshal a good faith defense. In particular, 11 U.S.C. § 548(c) provides that “a transferee . . . that takes for value and in good 101 11 U.S.C. § 548(a). Baird & Jackson, supra note 96, at 852. 103 The hypothetical has the transfer occur a year before insolvency so that the transfer of the sheep cannot be avoided as a form of preference avoidance, the reach back period for which is less than one year. 104 One might argue that the doctor is entitled to keep his sheep not because they were conveyed without fraudulent intent but because he qualifies for the “ordinary course of business” defense, as captured in contemporary law by 11 U.S.C. § 547. But this is just to beg the question, for why should paying for medical services count as part of the fraudster’s “ordinary” business while returning money to investors does not? A purported distinction between the two seems to rest on the intuition that the doctor has provided a legitimate service to the fraudster; but the investors had no less reason than the doctor to believe that the transaction in which they engaged with the fraudster was legitimate. So, again, the question of the grounds for the disparity in treatment arises. 102 2012] RIGHTING OTHERS’ WRONGS 27 faith has a lien on or may retain any interest transferred . . . to the extent that such transferee . . . gave value to the debtor in exchange for such transfer . . . .”105 Thus, for example, consider a Ponzi scheme with two customers—Smith and Jones. Smith and Jones both invest the same amount of money at the same time. Neither has any idea that they are investing in a Ponzi scheme, nor are there any red flags that should have put them on notice. Six months before the Ponzi scheme is exposed, Smith withdraws an amount equal to his principal. Because Smith will have taken “for value and in good faith,” he will get to keep 100 percent of the money he has withdrawn. If the Ponzi scheme operator is completely insolvent at the time the scheme collapses, Jones will end up with nothing. Again, in the case between Smith and Jones, if the purpose of § 548 were to ensure an even distribution between creditors, the fact that Smith had taken in good faith would be irrelevant. Smith would instead be required to give back 50 percent of the money he had withdrawn in order to offset Jones’s losses. The law, instead, provides that Smith gets to keep the full amount of his withdrawal, and Jones gets nothing.106 Moreover, the distinction between “net winners” and “net losers” lends further support to the AF reading. Where an investor has received no more than the amount she deposited, a court could consider her withdrawals to represent (fictitious) interest payments, rather than return of principal, in which case the money withdrawn would not have been offset by the “reasonably equivalent value” that § 548(a)(1)(B) requires. This would be an especially plausible way to proceed where the Ponzi scheme operator specifically designated the withdrawals 105 11 U.S.C. § 548(c) (emphasis added). In recent years, courts have narrowed the scope of the good faith defense, adopting a demanding objective standard. See, e.g., In re Bayou Grp., 439 B.R. 284, 31012 (S.D.N.Y. 2010) (describing the relevant test thusly: “The first question . . . is whether the transferee had information that put it on inquiry notice that the transferor was insolvent or that the transfer might be made with a fraudulent purpose . . . these two elements are consistently identified as the triggers for inquiry notice . . . . Once a transferee has been put on inquiry notice of either the transferor’s possible insolvency or of the possibly fraudulent purpose of the transfer, the transferee must satisfy a ‘diligent investigation’ requirement . . . . The test is most commonly phrased . . . as whether ‘diligent inquiry would have discovered the fraudulent purpose’ of the transfer.”). 106 Some commentators suggest that the narrow reading of the good faith defense is an intentional effort by courts to reach all payments, not just profits, so that early and late investors are at parity. This view is also shared by some judges, who view the narrow reading as judicial activism . . . . Sullivan, supra note 9, at 1618 (citations omitted). 28 BROOKLYN LAW REVIEW [Vol. 78:1 as payments of interest, rather than return of principal. Nevertheless, courts tend to credit payments first toward principal and then, only after the amount deposited has been fully withdrawn, toward interest. Thus one court stated that “[i]f a given defendant received less than his [investment], the amounts received should be considered return of principal, regardless of how the parties may have designated them.”107 It is this treatment that allows us to consider the person who withdrew some money from her account—but less than she had invested—to be a net loser, rather than an investor who earned some profits from the Ponzi scheme. Yet again, if courts sought to achieve an even distribution among customers, it would make little sense to credit all payments up to the amount of the deposit as principal. This approach puts those payments beyond the bankruptcy trustee’s reach—because the investor has given reasonably equivalent value for these withdrawals under § 548(B)(i)—thereby leaving less money in the pot for redistribution. The fact that the doctrinal understanding of constructive fraud allows an innocent investor to keep the full amount of her principal again suggests that it does not seek an even distribution in the first instance. A final argument against the ED reading is evident from the fact that the bankruptcy code contains a separate provision that straightforwardly seeks to accomplish the goal of even distribution among creditors. The preference avoidance provisions of 11 U.S.C. § 547 state that “the trustee may avoid any transfer of an interest of the debtor in property” made “on or within 90 days before the date of the filing of the petition.” The underlying idea is that a debtor should not be permitted to play favorites in determining which creditors should have their debts repaid.108 Instead, all creditors of the same class should receive a distribution of the estate proportionate to what they are owed. Section 547 thus negates preferences among creditors and, in so doing, ensures an equitable distribution among them. Indeed, as one of the foremost treatises on 107 Merrill v. Abbott (In re Indep. Clearing House Co.), 77 B.R. 843, 852 n.14 (D. Utah 1987). 108 For a classic case that seems to involve a transfer that was both fraudulent and preferential, see Twyne’s Case, 76 Eng. Rep. 809, 810-13 (Star Chamber 1601). There, the debtor owed debts to both Twyne and C. but did not have sufficient assets to cover both debts. He secretly gifted the assets he possessed to Twyne, who allowed the debtor to continue using the assets in question. This transaction reflected both an unfair preference for Twyne and a fraudulent conveyance, insofar as it was conducted in secret with the intention of hindering C.’s recovery. 2012] RIGHTING OTHERS’ WRONGS 29 bankruptcy law explains, “preference law . . . restructures transactions so as to level out the overall treatment received by similar creditors.”109 If the purpose of § 547 is to ensure an even distribution, it could not be the purpose of § 548, the fraudulent transfer provision, to do so as well.110 Leveraging the fraudulent transfer provision for purposes of seeking equity among 109 4 WILLIAM L. NORTON, JR. & WILLIAM L. NORTON, III, NORTON BANKRUPTCY LAW AND PRACTICE § 66:1 (3d ed. 2009) (emphasis added). 110 But see In re Bayou Grp., 396 B.R. 810, 827 (Bankr. S.D.N.Y. 2008), aff’d in part, rev’d in part, 439 B.R. 284, 303, 338-39 (S.D.N.Y. 2010) (“Section 548 serves the same policy function as Section 547, which allows the trustee to avoid preferential payments made within ninety days of the bankruptcy to perfectly innocent creditors who were legally entitled to be paid. Both sections represent an equitable determination by Congress that under limited circumstances creditors must share equally in the insolvency, or, in the case of Section 548, the fraud. Section 548 is not a punitive provision designed to punish the transferee, but is instead an equitable provision that places the transferee in the same position as other similarly situated creditors who did not receive fraudulent conveyances.”). Commentators have decried the Bayou decision, because it articulates an overly demanding test for establishing good faith. See, e.g., Sullivan, supra note 9, at 1623 (“[Bayou’s] objective good faith standard contravenes congressional intent, confuses the goals of fraudulent and preferential transfer law, unfairly penalizes savvier investors with actual good faith based on their status alone, demands investors to be more diligent than the SEC itself, and assumes (with the benefit of hindsight) that investors saw the ‘red flags.’”). Thus, two other opinions from the Southern District of New York—Picard v. Katz, 462 B.R. 447, 453-57 (S.D.N.Y. 2011) (Rakoff, J.), the Madoff trustee’s billion-dollar fraudulenttransfer suit against the Mets’ owners, and Gowan v. The Patriot Grp. (In re Dreier LLP), 452 B.R. 391 (Bankr. S.D.N.Y. 2011) (Glenn, J.)—have explicitly disagreed with, and so declined to follow, Bayou’s determination of the meaning of “good faith.” See generally Paul D. Sinclair & Monika Machen, Katz, Dreier Cut into Aggressive Trustees’ Positions, 31 AM. BANKR. INST. J., Feb. 2012, at 48. More relevant here, the Bayou court’s assertion that both § 547 and § 548 have equity as their rationale is problematic for two reasons. First, if it were true, it would render mysterious the different reach-back periods in §§ 547 (ninety days) and 548 (two years); surely the fact of the bankrupt’s wrong cannot justify exposing his transferees to a longer reach-back period, which is to say exposing them to an obligation to share more in the losses. Second, if the court is correct as to the rationale for § 548, then its application to Ponzi scheme winners would undercut the reading of “net equity” advanced by the SEC, adopted by Judge Lifland and affirmed by the Second Circuit, see supra Part I.B. The Bayou court intends that “the transferee [be placed] in the same position as other similarly situated creditors who did not receive fraudulent conveyances.” In re Bayou Grp., 396 B.R. at 827. As applied to the Madoff winners and losers, then, the winners should have no more entitlement, but also no less, to Madoff’s estate. This would be the result if, say, all Madoff investors returned all of the money they had withdrawn from their Madoff accounts, and it was then divided among them in proportion to the amount of their investment. But the effect of the net equity decision is to deny winners the status of customers with valid net equity claims; at the same time, winners who can establish their good faith will have only their withdrawn profits clawed back. So, winners who cannot establish their good faith will come out behind the Madoff losers, while winners who proceeded in good faith will come out ahead. And, there is no mechanism for excluding from recovery those losers who did know of the fraud and, perhaps out of an excess of greed, chose to continue riding the Ponzi scheme wave thinking that they could get out before the scheme collapsed. In short, if the avoidance provisions really do seek an equitable distribution of the bankrupt’s assets, then the law in this area is in even more disarray than the text accompanying this note suggests. 30 BROOKLYN LAW REVIEW [Vol. 78:1 Madoff’s customers, then, renders the preference avoidance provisions superfluous.111 Or, put less charitably, it is possible to see Picard’s efforts to use the fraudulent transfer provision to pursue clawbacks as an end-run around the shorter reachback period of a mere ninety days in the preference avoidance provision,112 in favor of the longer reach-back period of up to six years in the fraudulent transfer provision.113 111 But cf. Clark, supra note 94, at 510-13. Clark describes the general rationale for both fraudulent conveyance and preference avoidance as “that of Nonhindrance of the enforcement of valid legal obligations against oneself, in connection with transfers of one’s property. In summary, then, fraudulent conveyance law embodies a general ideal, in connection with a debtor’s transfers of property rights and incurrences of new obligations, of Nonhindrance of creditors.” In this way, Clark would seem to interpret both §§ 547 and 548 along the lines of what I have called the AF reading. Nonetheless, Clark subsequently acknowledges that the ideal of Evenhandedness, which underpins preference avoidance, is indeed distinct from the other specifications of the general commitment to Nonhindrance: It is also possible, however, to view Evenhandedness as a policy independent of, and on a par with, a general ideal of Nonhindrance, and this aspect of the policy has led to its development as a separate topic. While like the other two ideals Evenhandedness specifies the moral duties of a debtor to his creditor, Evenhandedness is also the ideal behind what is referred to as the law of voidable preferences and many cases assume or state explicitly that a preference is not a fraudulent conveyance. Id. at 513. 112 11 U.S.C. § 547(b)(4)(A). At least one court has decried § 547’s short statute of limitations when it comes to Ponzi schemes: For a Ponzi scheme that lasts more than three months, the statute[] . . . does not go far enough. By definition, an enterprise engaged in a Ponzi scheme is insolvent from day one. Thus, all transfers to investors in a Ponzi scheme are preferential, not just those made within the three months before bankruptcy. Every transfer prefers the transferee to those investors at the end of the line. The evil of a preferential transfer is that it “unfairly permit[s] a particular creditor to be treated more favorably than other creditors of the same class.” All investors in a Ponzi scheme are creditors of the same class, so in theory all should be treated equally. In effect, though, applying section 547 to a Ponzi scheme . . . favors some creditors over others. Under section 547 the creditors who are most preferred are allowed to keep their preferential payments because the transfers were made outside the statutory period . . . . The statute simply does not reach the early investors. Thus, applying the statute as written, the court is “compelled to take part in a farce whose result is . . . to take away from those who have little, the little that they have.” The equitable solution would be either to apply the statute to all transfers to investors in a Ponzi scheme— without regard to when the transfers were made—or to apply the statute to none of the transfers. In re Indep. Clearing House Co., 77 B.R. 843, 871 (D. Utah 1987) (citations omitted). Other commentators have noted that the short reach-back period of the preference avoidance provision might have impelled courts to adopt expansive understandings of the circumstances under which a fraudulent transfer has arisen. See, e.g., Cherry & Wong, supra note 15, at 404 (“[B]ecause the typical losing investor nonetheless remains at an unfair disadvantage, courts have sought to rectify the balance . . . . [C]ourts have begun to adopt a narrower reading of the good faith defense so as to potentially reach all payments received by an investor from the scheme . . . not 2012] RIGHTING OTHERS’ WRONGS 31 All of this shows that the AF reading is on far firmer ground than is the ED reading. Treatise writers and distinguished jurists seem to agree. Thus, one of the classic bankruptcy law treatises states that “the intent of [fraudulent conveyance statutes] . . . is not to provide equal distribution of the estates of debtors among their creditors; there are other statutes [in bankruptcy] which have that effect.”114 A leading bankruptcy law casebook states that the “purpose of fraudulent conveyance law, whatever its form, is simple: it protects a debtor’s unsecured creditors from reductions in the debtor’s just . . . fictitious profits.” (citation omitted)). At least some of these commentators welcome this expansive reading. See id. Those who have decried the expansion do so on separation of powers grounds, and not on the fairness-based grounds I adduce here. See, e.g., Lustig v. Weisz (In re Unified Commercial Capital, Inc.), 260 B.R. 343, 349-50 (Bankr. W.D.N.Y. 2001) aff’d sub nom. In re Unified Commercial Capital, No. 01-MBK6004L, 2002 WL 32500567 (W.D.N.Y. June 21, 2002); Sullivan, supra note 9, at 1634-35. [Some c]ourts . . . appear to believe that a “just” solution to the losses suffered by the innocent investors in a “Ponzi” scheme requires some reallocation of the risks and redistribution of the losses beyond that provided for by Congress in Section 547(b) . . . . [T]he fraudulent conveyance statutes cannot and should not be utilized by courts as a super preference statute to effect a further reallocation and redistribution that should be specifically provided for in a statute enacted by Congress. The Section 548(a) and state law fraudulent conveyance statutes implement a policy of preventing the diminution of a debtor’s estate. The Section 547(b) preference statute implements a principal policy of equality of distribution. By forcing the square peg facts of a “Ponzi” scheme into the round holes of the fraudulent conveyance statutes in order to accomplish a further reallocation and redistribution to implement a policy of equality of distribution in the name of equity, I believe that many courts have done a substantial injustice to those statutes and have made policy decisions that should be made by Congress. In re Unified Commercial Capital, Inc., 260 B.R. at 349-50. 113 Section 548 authorizes avoidance of transfers made only in the two years prior to the declaration of bankruptcy. See 11 U.S.C. § 548. However, § 544(b) of the Code allows the trustee to avoid fraudulent conveyances based on state law, id. § 544(b), and the New York fraudulent transfer provision allows for a six year reach-back period, N.Y. C.P.L.R. § 213 (McKinney 2012). In the case against the Mets owners, Judge Rakoff held that the bankruptcy trustee could proceed against the defendants only upon a theory of actual fraud, as articulated in 11 U.S.C. § 548(a)(1)(A), which limited the reach back period to two years (and the recovery amount to $384 million, rather than the $1 billion the trustee had sought). See Katz, 462 B.R. at 451. It is not yet clear what effect, if any, this ruling will have on the other Madoff claw back suits and, in particular, on the allowable reach-back period. 114 1 GARRARD GLENN, FRAUDULENT CONVEYANCES AND PREFERENCES § 289 (rev. ed. 1940) (quoting In re Johnson, 20 Del. Ch. 389 (1881)) (internal quotation marks omitted); see also Peter L. Borowitz & Richard F. Hahn, The Troubled Leveraged Buyout: Risks (and Opportunities) Under Fraudulent Conveyance and Other Creditors’ Rights Laws, in 694 PRACTISING LAW INSTITUTE: CORPORATE LAW AND PRACTICE COURSE HANDBOOK SERIES 51, 53-54 (“In its original form fraudulent conveyance law focused exclusively on transfers of a debtor’s property where there was actual evidence of the debtor’s intent to harm its creditors by hiding assets from imminent levy.”). 32 BROOKLYN LAW REVIEW [Vol. 78:1 estate to which they look, generally, for their security.”115 In a First Circuit Court of Appeals decision, then-Judge Stephen Breyer stated that one of the “basic functions” of fraudulent conveyance law is “to see that an insolvent debtor’s limited funds are used to pay some worthy creditor,” and not to “determin[e] which creditor is the more worthy.”116 Breyer’s conception has subsequently been endorsed by the Second Circuit Court of Appeals,117 as well as numerous federal district and bankruptcy courts.118 In short, according to all of these sources, contemporary law allows fraudulent conveyances to be avoided because they are fraudulent, not because they risk creating a disparity between creditors of the same class. But even if the bankruptcy code was not intended to be used to take money from some innocent Ponzi scheme investors and provide it to others, perhaps we should nonetheless refrain from opposing the clawback actions. After all, any money that a Madoff customer withdrew over and above that which she invested was money that another Madoff customer had deposited. In many cases, sheer luck will have allowed some Madoff investors to come out ahead, while others come out with little or nothing. Why should luck be so decisive, especially if the winners’ “winnings” come directly from the losers’ pockets? Indeed, Picard has relied on precisely this logic in defending the clawback suits to the general public. Yet despite its intuitive appeal, this rationale turns out to be quite problematic. III. UNJUST ENRICHMENT AND STOLEN GOODS In seeking to justify avoidance actions filed against innocent and (allegedly) knowing investors alike, Picard has been quite savvy in his choice of language. In a quote to the Wall Street Journal, Picard exclaimed that “the people who made money, who got more, have made money at the expense 115 MARK S. SCARBERRY ET AL., BUSINESS REORGANIZATION IN BANKRUPTCY: CASES AND MATERIALS 387 (3d ed. 2006). 116 Boston Trading Grp. v. Burnazos, 835 F.2d 1504, 1511 (1st Cir. 1987); see also id. at 1509 (“[T]he basic object of fraudulent conveyance law is to see that the debtor uses his limited assets to satisfy some of his creditors; it normally does not try to choose among them.”). 117 See, e.g., Sharp Int’l Corp. v. State St. Bank & Trust Co. (In re Sharp Int’l Corp.), 403 F.3d 43, 54 (2d Cir. 2005); HBE Leasing Corp. v. Frank, 48 F.3d 623, 634 (2d Cir. 1995). 118 See, e.g., In re Jeffrey Bigelow Design Grp., 956 F.2d 479, 484 (4th Cir. 1992); Kapila v. TD Bank, N.A. (In re Pearlman), 460 B.R. 306, 312, (Bankr. M.D. Fla. 2011); Walker v. Pasteur (In re Aphton Corp.), 423 B.R. 76, 93 (Bankr. D. Del. 2010). 2012] RIGHTING OTHERS’ WRONGS 33 of the people who didn’t.”119 Putting the point even more starkly, he subsequently described the disparity between winners and losers by stating that, “for more than 20 years, Bernard Madoff stole money from some people and gave it to others.”120 Echoing this rhetoric, Picard’s lieutenant, David Sheehan, stated that “[t]hose who didn’t get their money back are entitled to get it from those who have it.”121 These statements have great intuitive appeal, as they rely upon an implicit analogy to two well-established doctrines— namely, the law of unjust enrichment and the law of stolen goods. For both of these doctrines, one party may be compelled to return money or goods illicitly taken from their original owner, even if the former is completely innocent of the illicit taking. Picard and Sheehan’s rhetoric implies that we should conceive of the winners as the innocent recipients of ill-gotten gains or stolen goods, in which case compelling the winners to return their “winnings” to the losers would be consistent with the doctrines governing unjust enrichment and stolen goods. Picard is not alone in seeking to leverage this rhetoric. Both the Securities Investor Protection Corporation and the trustees charged with recovering assets in the wake of other Ponzi schemes have also sought to support clawback suits by analogizing the transfers they seek to avoid to instances of unjust enrichment or stolen goods.122 It behooves us, then, to 119 Michael Rothfeld, Madoff Investors Brace for Lawsuits, WALL ST. J., July 26, 2010, at C1, available at http://online.wsj.com/article/ SB10001424052748704719104575389141620473502.html (internal quotation marks omitted). 120 THE MADOFF RECOVERY EFFORT: AN UPDATE CALL WITH THE TRUSTEE AND HIS COUNSEL FROM BAKER HOSTETLER, at 1, (Mar. 8, 2011, 3:00 PM), available at http://207.58.180.20/document/news/000018-2011-march-8-picard-sheehan-openingstatements-for-march-8-press-call.pdf; see also Alan Rappeport, 123 Claims Filed over Madoff Payouts, FIN. TIMES, Dec. 1, 2010, at 25, available at http://www.ft.com/cms/s/0/ 0aa84be4-fcdf-11df-ae2d-00144feab49a.html#axzz1os4RzPPa (quoting from the complaint for the clawback suit filed against a hedge fund operator in which Picard alleges that “[t]he transfers received by the defendant constitute non-existent profits supposedly earned in the account, but, in reality, they were other people’s money . . . .” (internal quotation marks omitted)). 121 Madoff Recovery, supra note 120, at 6. Joe Nocera, the New York Times columnist, echoes these words in his arguments supporting the clawback suits: “[T]he net winners’ gains came from the pockets of the net losers. That’s how a Ponzi scheme works. If you buy a stolen watch, and its real owner wants it back, don’t you have an obligation to return it?” Joe Nocera, Suspense Is Over in Madoff Case, N.Y. TIMES, June 26, 2012, at A23. 122 Thus, the receiver appointed by the SEC in the Stanford International Bank fraud has sought to recover money from innocent beneficiaries of the Ponzi scheme by advancing, inter alia, a claim that they were unjustly enriched. Receiver’s First Amended Complaint Against Certain Stanford Investors ¶¶ 39-42, Janvey v. Alguire, 846 F. Supp. 2d 662 (N.D. Tex. 2011) (No. 03:09-CV-0724-N), available at http://www.stanfordfinancialreceivership.com/documents/Receivers_First_Amended_ 34 BROOKLYN LAW REVIEW [Vol. 78:1 consider the force of the analogies. In this Part, I address each of the purportedly analogous doctrines in turn. A. The Law of Unjust Enrichment The law of unjust enrichment holds that “[a] person has a right to have restored to him a benefit gained at his expense by another, if the retention of the benefit by the other would be unjust.”123 An unjust enrichment analysis includes the following inquiries: “(i) Was the defendant enriched? (ii) Was it at the expense of [the] claimant? (iii) Was it unjust?”124 An affirmative answer to each of these questions entails that a defendant has been unjustly enriched. Such a defendant will be required to restitute the plaintiff, unless the defendant can marshal an established defense.125 A recitation of the bare elements of the doctrine of unjust enrichment cannot tell us whether the Madoff winners were in fact unjustly enriched. For one thing, whether the winners’ profits were accrued at the expense of the losers turns on whether the losers maintain a claim to the money that the winners received. This is precisely the question under debate. Suppose that the winners and losers invested in Schmadoff’s legitimate investment scheme instead of Madoff’s fraud. Suppose further that the investment scheme, while profitable for many years, suddenly goes bust as a result of an extraordinary event that no one could have predicted and that was no one’s fault. For example, imagine that a meteor strikes the building where Schmadoff had his offices, destroying the Complaint_Against_Certain_Stanford_Investors.pdf. And, the SIPC, supporting the trustee’s interpretation of net equity, argued that: in a brief Unless the fictitious trades in BLMIS are avoided, claimants who were advantaged by the broker’s fraud, that is, investors who received withdrawals from BLMIS that actually consisted of other investors’ money under the guise of investment profits . . . will be allowed to benefit at the expense of other equally innocent investors. Memorandum of Law of the Securities Investor Protection Corporation in Support of Trustee’s Motion for an Order Upholding Trustee’s Determination Denying “Customer” Claims for Amounts Listed on Last Statement, Affirming Trustee’s Determination of Net Equity, and Expunging Those Objections with Respect to the Determinations Relating to Net Equity at 36, Sec. Inv. Prot. Corp. v. Bernard L. Madoff Inv. Sec. LLC (In re Bernard L. Madoff), No. 08-01789 (BRL) (Bankr. S.D.N.Y. Oct. 16, 2009), available at http://www.madofftrustee.com/document/dockets/000450-519-memorandum-of-law.pdf. 123 Warren Seavey & Austin Scott, Restitution, 54 LAW Q. REV. 29, 32 (1938). See generally id. at 36-37 (collecting paradigmatic statements of the doctrine). 124 BIRKS, supra note 9, at 39. 125 Id. 2012] RIGHTING OTHERS’ WRONGS 35 vault where he had stored half of the investors’ money in anticipation of a large stock purchase, while the other half was already invested in the market. Although Schmadoff’s firm was appropriately insured, insurance does not cover this contingency, and so half of the money investors thought they had is now gone. Over the years, some investors withdrew more money than they had deposited, while other investors had not recouped all, or even any, of their principal at the time of the vault’s destruction. The former set of investors would have been enriched, but it seems a stretch to say that they were enriched at the expense of the latter, even though their withdrawals have left fewer resources to be distributed among the latter. Similarly, the Madoff winners’ withdrawals have also left fewer resources to be distributed among the losers. But why should we think that their “winnings” come at the expense of the losers if we do not think that the Schmadoff winners gain at the expense of the Schmadoff losers? Even if the Madoff winners (and perhaps the Schmadoff winners, too) have gained at the expense of the losers, it is not at all clear that they have gained unjustly. The paradigmatic case of unjust enrichment involves the mistaken payment of a non-existent debt,126 such as when A forgets that she has already discharged her debt to B and pays B twice. Clearly, the Madoff case is distinct from this paradigmatic case. Other cases involve “failures of consideration, shades of fraud and pressure, and taking advantage of vulnerable people.”127 The second of these factors is most apt here, and it might ground the losers’ right to recovery under the following established principle: “If X takes C’s money without C’s consent and gives it to D, then D becomes indebted to C in the sum received.”128 Here, X would be Madoff, D a winner, and C a loser, and the principle would apply so long as we were licensed in construing the case as one in which Madoff took the losers’ money without their consent. In response, one might point to an exception to the principle and contend that D need not return the money to C if 126 Id. at 5, 73 (referring to this case as “the core of the core” of unjust enrichment doctrine); Dennis Klimchuk, The Normative Foundations of Unjust Enrichment, in THE LAW OF UNJUST ENRICHMENT 81, 82 (Robert Chambers et al., eds., 2009). 127 BIRKS, supra note 9, at 41-42 (citing these, along with cases of mistake, as an exclusive list of unjust factors). 128 Id. at 86 (distilling the principle behind the House of Lords’ decision in Lipkin Gorman v. Karpnale Ltd., [1991] 2 A.C. 548 (H.L.) (Eng.)). Cf. Zoe Sinel, Through Thick and Thin: The Place of Corrective Justice in Unjust Enrichment, 31 OXFORD J. LEGAL STUD. 551, 551 (2011) (“Clearly, one should return what one was not meant to receive and for which one gave nothing in return.”). 36 BROOKLYN LAW REVIEW [Vol. 78:1 D received it in exchange for a bona fide purchase. Thus, if an attorney embezzles money from his law firm and uses it to buy himself a lavish dinner at the Ritz, the Ritz need not return any of the proceeds of the meal to the law firm, because it supplied the food and drink in exchange for the money paid.129 Moreover, this result holds even if the Ritz marks up its prices exorbitantly to ensure that its profit margin is, for example, ninety percent of the purchase price.130 Leveraging this exception, one might argue that the Madoff winners are like suppliers of goods who receive illgotten gains in a genuine, legitimate exchange. This will not do, however. If Madoff’s fraud vitiates the claimant’s consent and thereby renders the transfer between a losing investor and Madoff illicit, then so too it vitiates the legitimacy of the exchange between Madoff and the winning investor. As such, this appears to be a case where the law of unjust enrichment would compel the Madoff winners to return their winnings to the Madoff losers.131 But it is just at this point that the law of unjust enrichment is on its weakest footing. To be sure, courts have found that defendants must return funds that have been “misdirected from the plaintiff’s bank account or trust fund by a fraudulent . . . third party,”132 even though the defendant bears no responsibility for the fraud. The rationale in these cases emphasizes the plaintiff’s lack of responsibility for the transfer; the defendant’s lack of responsibility is taken to be irrelevant.133 But why should this be? As Kit Barker asks, “Why is the defendant, who is no more causally implicated in events than anyone else, obliged to remedy the plaintiff’s bad luck? Is there not an equally strong case, for example, for compensating the plaintiff . . . from a public fund, rather than looking to private law for a restitutionary remedy?”134 Indeed, one might make the point 129 The example is Birk’s variation on the Lipkin Gorman case. See BIRKS, supra note 9, at 86. 130 See id. 131 Assuming, as I am in this Section, that the Madoff winners in question were blamelessly ignorant of the fraud, they would have rights of rescission that protected money withdrawn equal to the principle they had invested. See, e.g., Katz, supra note 11, at 453-54 (describing the transferee’s right of rescission as an antecedent debt of the estate, owed in exchange for the value the transferee had invested with the debtor). 132 Kit Barker, The Nature of Responsibility for Gain: Gain, Harm and Keeping the Lid on Pandora’s Box, in THE LAW OF UNJUST ENRICHMENT, supra note 126, at 162 (citations omitted) (citing relevant case law). 133 Id. at 165-66. 134 Id. at 166. 2012] RIGHTING OTHERS’ WRONGS 37 more forcefully by arguing that imposing the remedy exclusively on the defendant treats him as a mere means. It “uses the defendant as an instrument in the service of the plaintiff’s interests.”135 One can find two responses to these queries in the scholarly literature on unjust enrichment, but neither is ultimately convincing. First, some have suggested that liability here vindicates not the plaintiff’s particular interest but instead “the value of autonomy more generally, a value in which the defendant can be understood to have an interest, no less than the plaintiff. So liability does not treat the defendant as a mere means.”136 The argument seems to be that both the plaintiff and the defendant gain from the imposition of liability insofar as liability vindicates the autonomy of each. But a problem remains. The prospect, or even reality, of gain does not undercut the concern that the defendant is being used as a mere means. Analogously, we might say that, in cases of false conviction, the innocent individual who is punished shares in a benefit that her punishment produces—namely, the general deterrence that will make others less likely to commit a similar crime and that will make the defendant less likely to be victimized by such a crime. Still, the defendant is being treated as a mere means because she is singled out for punishment without cause, even if she, along with others, enjoys the benefit her punishment generates. The defendant serves as an instrument for the gain, even if the gain is one in which she can partake. A second line of response acknowledges that “there is nothing uniquely, morally significant” about the defendant who is innocent of the fraud from which he gains.137 Nonetheless, it makes sense to have him “insure” the plaintiff against her loss “because he happens to have an obvious surplus fund” (i.e., the proceeds deriving from the plaintiff’s loss).138 Along these lines, some allege that a “localised” or “internal” distributive norm operates between the plaintiff and defendant such that fairness, rather than corrective justice, compels return of the 135 Klimchuk, supra note 126, at 97. Klimchuk is trying to rescue Hanoch Dagan’s account of unjust enrichment, according to which the doctrine is intended to vindicate the value of autonomy generally. See, e.g., HANOCH DAGAN, THE LAW AND ETHICS OF RESTITUTION (2004). 136 Klimchuk, supra note 126, at 97. 137 Barker, supra note 132, at 168 (emphasis omitted). 138 Id. 38 BROOKLYN LAW REVIEW [Vol. 78:1 money.139 Regardless of the justificatory force of this reasoning in the standard case of unjust enrichment from a fraud involving a passive defendant, it is not at all clear that it applies convincingly to the Madoff clawback suits. The Madoff winner had a legitimate expectation that his investment would yield returns; therefore his withdrawals might not constitute “an obvious surplus fund.” Even those who believe that fairness normally dictates return of the transferred funds recognize an exception where returning the transferred funds would cause the defendant to suffer harm himself.140 In the Madoff case, the winners relied on the legitimacy of their “winnings”; many of them spent that money thinking that it had been honestly invested and earned.141 Because the money that winners would be forced to give up is not a surplus, they would be worse off at the end of the day.142 Put differently, fairness does not necessarily compel the result that arises in the standard case of unjust enrichment, and that the Madoff trustee demands.143 In sum, one can say that the winners in the Madoff case have been unjustly enriched only if (i) they have been enriched at the expense of the losers, and (ii) the circumstances of their enrichment involve an injustice. But whether or not these conditions apply depends on our understanding of the entitlements of winners and losers alike. The law of unjust enrichment does not illuminate, let alone determine, those 139 See id. at 167 (discussing Dennis Klimchuk, Unjust Enrichment and Corrective Justice, in UNDERSTANDING UNJUST ENRICHMENT 111 (J. Neyers et al. eds., 2004) and PETER CANE, RESPONSIBILITY IN LAW AND MORALITY 208 (2002)). 140 See, e.g., HANOCH DAGAN, UNJUST ENRICHMENT 40 (2004); Barker, supra note 132, at 168. 141 See, e.g., Madoff’s Victims, MADOFFSCANDAL.COM: THE LARGEST FRAUD THAT THE WORLD HAS EVER SEEN, http://www.madoffscandal.com/madoffs-victims/ (last visited Mar. 12, 2012) (describing Ira Roth, whose withdrawals from his Madoff account were used to pay for his college tuition and his grandmother’s living expenses). 142 See Barker, supra note 132, at 168. 143 Picard has instituted a hardship program, such that winners who can demonstrate hardship will be excused from having to return their “winnings.” See The Hardship Program, MADOFF RECOVERY INITIATIVE, http://www.madoff.com/hardshipprogram-17.html (last visited Feb. 24, 2012). The hardship standard that Picard has set is an onerous one. Among the factors Picard lists in order to qualify for the hardship program are the following: “[i]nability to pay for necessary living expenses, such as housing (including loss of home due to foreclosure), food, utilities and transportation”; “[i]nability to pay for necessary medical expenses”; “[i]nability to pay for the care of dependents”; and having “[d]eclar[ed] personal bankruptcy.” Id. Yet even a more liberal standard would not vitiate the concern raised in the text accompanying this note. Again, the concern is that the defendant may have reasonably relied on the legitimacy of his earnings and so reasonably spent the money that the trustee now claims belongs to the plaintiff. Requiring the defendant to repay that money leaves him worse off even if he is not otherwise financially strapped. 2012] RIGHTING OTHERS’ WRONGS 39 entitlements. Only a prior inquiry into the relationship that ought to exist between winners and losers can do so, and I undertake that inquiry in Part V. It will be useful to turn to the law of stolen goods first, however, to see whether it can provide useful insights. B. The Law of Stolen Goods The rule requiring a person who unwittingly purchases a stolen item to return that item is a fixture of Anglo-American law and is among the legal rules widely known by the layperson and legal sophisticate alike. The “He who hath not cannot give” rule dates back to Roman times,144 and today it can be found in the UCC,145 as well as in the UCC’s English counterpart.146 Yet, notwithstanding the entrenched nature of the rule governing stolen goods, it turns out that there is little to support it, and it is largely irrelevant to the Madoff case in any event. Why does the law favor the original owner over the good faith purchaser of a stolen item? There are two kinds of rationales adduced in support of the rule—those grounded in considerations of efficiency, and those grounded in considerations of fairness. Under the former, it has been argued that resting priority with the original owner encourages vigilance on the part of would-be purchasers to ensure proper title in the item they are thinking about purchasing.147 Prioritizing the original owner also deters theft, by making it more difficult for the thief to off-load the fruits of his crime. Yet considerations of efficiency might weigh just as strongly on the other side. We might instead want to encourage vigilance on the part of owners to ensure that they protect their possessions or purchase insurance to cover their losses. And we might want to ensure the fluidity of the market for goods by conferring upon the good faith purchaser a sense of repose.148 So long as he had no reason to know that his purchase had been stolen from someone else, he may rest easy in the belief that it will not be repossessed should its origins be 144 See, e.g., BLACK’S LAW DICTIONARY 813 (2d ed. 1910). “A purchaser of goods acquires all title which his transferor had or had power to transfer.” U.C.C. § 2-403 (1989). 146 “[W]here goods are sold by a person who is not their owner, and who does not sell them under the authority or with the consent of the owner, the buyer acquires no better title to the goods than the seller had.” The Sale of Goods Act, 1979, § 21(1) (U.K.). 147 See, e.g., Derek Fincham, Towards a Rigorous Standard for the Good Faith Acquisition of Antiquities, 37 SYRACUSE J. INT’L L. & COM. 145, 162 (2010). 148 See Emily A. Graefe, Note, The Conflicting Obligations of Museums Possessing Nazi-Looted Art, 51 B.C. L. REV. 473, 481 (2010). 145 40 BROOKLYN LAW REVIEW [Vol. 78:1 uncovered. For precisely these reasons, the rule operates the opposite way in civil law countries, where good faith purchasers typically enjoy priority and original owners are denied recovery. In sum, the efficiency-based considerations for the rule of stolen goods are hardly decisive in establishing the original owner’s priority. But nor are the fairness-based considerations, as we shall now see. Fairness seeks to favor the original owner on the presupposition that the original owner will have imbued the item with more personal meaning than the good faith purchaser. Where the property in question is “personal” under Margaret Jane Radin’s conception of that term—being bound up with its original owner’s conception of herself—it makes sense to return the item to the original owner.149 Thus, for example, we can imagine a wedding ring that had been in the original owner’s family over multiple generations, and for that reason carries a personal dimension that the good faith purchaser could not appreciate. Fairness would dictate that we privilege the property rights of the original owner, who values the ring for both pecuniary and sentimental reasons, over those of the good faith purchaser, who has only a pecuniary attachment to the ring. A second fairness-based consideration goes not to the enhanced value the item might hold for the original owner, but instead to the circumstances of its theft. In these instances, the original owner has had the item taken from her against her will.150 As in cases of Nazi-looted art, for example, where the item was stolen as part of a genocidal campaign,151 we might say that the original owner has sustained not only a material loss but also an expressive injury, given the ethnic animus motivating the crime. In this kind of case, the original owner has borne the greater loss and, in recognition of that fact, fairness would again dictate return of the stolen good. Both of these rationales strike me as no more than presumptively compelling. In many cases, the more personal attachment or the more injurious loss may reside on the side of the original owner. But there will surely be exceptions. For example, if the good faith purchaser had sold his kidney in 149 See Margaret J. Radin, Property and Personhood, 34 STAN. L. REV. 957 (1982). Menachem Mautner, “The Eternal Triangles of the Law”: Toward a Theory of Priorities in Conflicts Involving Remote Parties, 90 MICH. L. REV. 95, 151-52 (1991). 151 See, e.g., Austria v. Altmann, 541 U.S. 677 (2004) (affirming a judgment in favor of the plaintiff, who sued the Austrian government for the return of six Gustav Klimt paintings that had belonged to her family prior to the Holocaust). 150 2012] RIGHTING OTHERS’ WRONGS 41 order to acquire the funds to buy the wedding ring that had been an heirloom in the original owner’s family, we might imagine that his fiancée attaches special significance to the ring in light of the sacrifice made to get it for her. This significance might be no less compelling than the significance that the ring holds for its original owner. Similarly, the original owner might have sustained a garden-variety theft, while the good faith purchaser was duped into buying the stolen good as part of a scam that exploits a special vulnerability, causing the good faith purchaser and members of her group to suffer. This is the case in instances of affinity fraud, in which the fraudster preys upon others with whom he shares ethnic or religious ties.152 In these cases, the good faith purchaser will have been subject to an expressive injury (such as one motivated by ethnic or racial animus) while the original owner was not. In sum, the fairness rationales appear to provide merely presumptive reasons for privileging the original owner, not absolute grounds for doing so. In any event, it is difficult to see why these rationales should be relevant when we are dealing with a fungible good, such as money. The family ring or Nazi-looted Gustav Klimt painting cannot be shared by two owners, but money can easily be divided between them. So we need not think about privileging the winner or the loser of an investment fraud in the same way that we need to contemplate privileging the original owner or the good faith purchaser for a theft of a unique object. Moreover, there is a further distinction between a case of stolen goods and financial fraud that is worth underscoring. In the case of a financial fraud like Madoff’s, each investor was a potential victim of theft. To return to our two-person Ponzi scheme involving Smith and Jones, consider the following: Although Smith cashed out early and Jones was left exposed, the situation could have proceeded precisely the opposite way, with Jones cashing out early and Smith bearing the loss. Further, it is not simply that either of them could have been the victim of fraud. Each was the victim of fraud. This is true not 152 The SEC defines an affinity fraud as fraud that “prey[s] upon members of identifiable groups, such as religious or ethnic communities, the elderly, or professional groups. The fraudsters who promote affinity scams frequently are . . . members of the group . . . . These scams exploit the trust and friendship that exist in groups of people who have something in common.” Affinity Fraud: How to Avoid Investment Scams that Target Groups, SEC.GOV, http://www.sec.gov/investor/pubs/affinity.htm (last modified Sept. 6, 2006). 42 BROOKLYN LAW REVIEW [Vol. 78:1 only in those cases where winning investors believed they had money left in their Madoff accounts but later learned that they would not recover it based on the bankruptcy court’s definition of net equity. Even the investor who had liquidated her account and received exactly the amount she believed she was owed can be said to have been a victim of fraud insofar as she invested her money under false pretenses. Both were the intended “dupees” of a fraudster; that only one of them suffered the pecuniary consequences of having been duped is merely a matter of luck, for which neither bears responsibility. There is, accordingly, a moral equivalence between Smith and Jones, and between any innocent winner and innocent loser in a Ponzi scheme. By contrast, there need not be a moral equivalence between the good faith purchaser of a stolen good and the individual from whom it was stolen; this will especially be the case where the good has changed hands more than once, and where the last seller was innocently ignorant of the good’s illicit provenance. In sum, the law of stolen goods derives its rationale from a set of potentially dubious presumptions, and these have little relevance to the relationship between Ponzi scheme winners and losers in any case. Further, even if one were to remain convinced that fairness demands loss sharing among Ponzi scheme winners and losers, it would nevertheless be unfair to proceed with the clawback suits, given that we do not require innocent beneficiaries of other kinds of wrongs to share in the losses that the victims of those wrongs sustain, as we shall now see. IV. OTHER ANALOGOUS DOCTRINES? The legal response to the Madoff case cannot be assessed in isolation. The Madoff Ponzi scheme collapsed at the same time as—and as a result of—the 2008 financial meltdown. With stock values plummeting, Madoff’s customers sought to withdraw their money en masse, but Madoff was unable to satisfy all of their claims at once. We know now that the financial crisis was precipitated in no small part by acts of wrongdoing. Fraud itself increased in the years preceding the meltdown.153 Moreover, among the acts and events identified to 153 See Page Perry, LLC, Financial Scams Are Becoming More Common as the Economy Deteriorates, INVESTMENT FRAUD LAW. BLOG (Apr. 13, 2009), http://www.investmentfraudlawyerblog.com/2009/04/financial_scams_are_becoming_m.html (“The Federal Bureau of Investigation reported that corporate fraud more than doubled from 279 cases in 2003 to 529 in 2007 . . . . The financial frauds include various forms of theft, such as Ponzi Schemes and embezzlement.”). 2012] RIGHTING OTHERS’ WRONGS 43 have caused the crisis, instances of recklessness, willful blindness, and exploitation figure prominently.154 Yet the response to the financial crisis has all but eschewed any grandscale attempt to compensate those who lost money through no fault of their own. This Part seeks to distinguish the clawback suits against innocent winners in a Ponzi scheme from other restitutionary measures that adversely affect innocent beneficiaries of a corporate or financial wrong. In Part IV.A, I focus on executive compensation, while in Part IV.B I address shareholder losses resulting from corporate or financial wrongs. A. Executive Compensation Clawbacks Outside of the avoidance provisions of bankruptcy laws, the only individuals who are eligible targets for clawback actions are corporate executives, and only when their companies issue earnings restatements to correct for earlier mistaken earnings reports.155 More specifically, each of the three federal statutes that permit executive compensation clawbacks developed in response to cases of dramatic financial wrongdoing. In particular, the Sarbanes-Oxley Act of 2002 154 See, e.g., THE FIN. CRISIS INQUIRY COMM’N, THE FINANCIAL CRISIS INQUIRY REPORT XV-XX (2011), available at http://www.gpo.gov/fdsys/pkg/GPO-FCIC/pdf/GPOFCIC.pdf. 155 The focus here is on clawback actions that arise independent of the clawback target’s participation in the underlying wrong. Since 1971, the SEC has enjoyed power to seek restitution from corporate executives or corporations that have engaged in financial fraud, with the inaugural case involving insider trading. SEC v. Tex. Gulf Sulphur Co., 446 F.2d 1301, 1307-08 (2d Cir. 1971). Yet, until the 1990s, the rationale for these SEC clawback suits was to deter wrongdoing, and not to distribute the returned money to those whom the insider trading had injured. See SEC v. Fischbach Corp., 133 F.3d 170, 175 (2d Cir. 1997) (“Although disgorged funds may often go to compensate securities fraud victims for their losses, such compensation is a distinctly secondary goal.”); Zimmerman, supra note 1, at 527-28. Compensation became a primary goal of SEC disgorgement actions “in 1990, when Congress passed the Securities Enforcement Remedies and Penny Stock Reform Act. The Penny Stock Reform Act . . . expressly authorized the SEC to design rules for the distribution of such awards.” Zimmerman, supra note 1, at 528 (citations omitted). Further, Section 308 of Sarbanes-Oxley, the “Fair Funds” provision, grants the SEC authority to seek “any equitable relief that may be appropriate or necessary for the benefit of investors.” Sarbanes-Oxley Act of 2002, Pub. L. No. 107-204, §§ 305(b), 308, 116 Stat. 745, 779 (codified at 15 U.S.C. § 78u(d)(5) (2006)). As Aaron Zimmerman describes, In the six complete fiscal years since Congress passed the Fair Funds Act, the SEC has brought between 218 and 335 judicial enforcement actions per year. In the 2009 calendar year alone, the SEC distributed over $2.1 billion to investors—more than twice as much as the amount the SEC collected between 1984 and 1992. See Zimmerman, supra note 1, at 529-30 (citations omitted). 44 BROOKLYN LAW REVIEW [Vol. 78:1 (SOX)156 was passed in the wake of the Enron and Worldcom scandals;157 the Dodd-Frank Act of 2010 (Dodd-Frank)158 was passed in the wake of the subprime mortgage crisis and ensuing financial meltdown in 2007 and 2008;159 and the Emergency Economic Stabilization Act of 2008 (EESA)160 was passed in conjunction with the bailout program that the financial meltdown necessitated.161 Under each statute, the triggering event is a finding that the corporation in question issued a materially inaccurate earnings statement.162 A further triggering event occurs under Dodd-Frank upon a finding that the corporation otherwise materially failed to comply with a federal securities reporting regulation.163 The scope of each clawback provision varies: SOX restricts its clawback provisions to the corporation’s CEO and CFO.164 EESA permits clawing back compensation from the CEO and the next twenty highest-paid executives.165 And DoddFrank, the most expansive of the three, subjects any executive of the corporation to a clawback action.166 On the other hand, Dodd-Frank contemplates a less severe clawback than does either SOX or EESA. Dodd-Frank restricts the clawback amount to that in excess of what the executive would have earned under the correct earnings statement,167 while both SOX 156 Sarbanes-Oxley Act of 2002, Pub. L. Nos. 107-204, 116 Stat. 745. See Larry E. Ribstein, Market vs. Regulatory Responses to Corporate Fraud: A Critique of the Sarbanes-Oxley Act of 2002, 28 J. CORP. L. 1, 3 (2003). 158 Dodd-Frank Wall Street Reform and Consumer Protection Act, Pub. L. No. 111-203, 124 Stat. 1376 (2010). 159 See William E. Cohen, Foreword to DAVID SKEEL, THE NEW FINANCIAL DEAL: UNDERSTANDING THE DODD-FRANK ACT AND ITS (UNINTENDED) CONSEQUENCES ix (2010). 160 Emergency Economic Stabilization Act of 2008, div. A, Pub. L. No. 110-343, 122 Stat. 3765. 161 See, e.g., Sandra Seitman, Note, Uncle Sam’s New Piggy Bank: Confronting Crisis Through TARP and Federal Oversight, BUS. L. BRIEF, Fall/Winter 2009-2010, at 53. 162 Sarbanes-Oxley Act of 2002, § 304(a); Dodd-Frank Wall Street Reform and Consumer Protection Act, § 954; Emergency Economic Stabilization Act of 2008, § 11(b)(3)(B). 163 Dodd-Frank Wall Street Reform and Consumer Protection Act, § 954. 164 See, e.g., Joseph E. Bachelder III, Clawbacks Under Dodd-Frank and Other Federal Statutes, HARV. L. SCH. F. ON CORP. GOVERNANCE & FIN. REG. (June 9, 2011, 9:14 AM), http://blogs.law.harvard.edu/corpgov/2011/06/09/clawbacks-under-doddfrank-and-other-federal-statutes/. 165 See id. 166 See id. 167 See id. A separate provision of Dodd-Frank applies to failed financial companies and targets “any current or former senior executive or director substantially responsible for the failed condition of the covered financial company” for a clawback of “any compensation received during the 2-year period preceding the date on which the Corporation was appointed as the receiver of the covered financial company, except that, in the case of fraud, no time limit shall apply.” Dodd-Frank Wall Street Reform and Consumer Protection Act, H.R. 4173, 111th Cong. § 210(S) (2010). Since this 157 2012] RIGHTING OTHERS’ WRONGS 45 and EESA permit recovery of all of the incentive-based compensation belonging to the targeted executive.168 The reachback period under Dodd-Frank is the three years preceding the reporting error or failure, while it is twelve months under SOX and there is no specified reach-back period under EESA.169 Importantly, these statutes permit clawbacks independently of whether the targeted individual bears a culpable connection to the triggering event.170 Each inflicts its clawback measures on both “innocent” and culpable executives alike.171 One might then think that these statutes, similar to the Ponzi scheme clawback actions, stand for the proposition that an individual ought not profit from another’s wrongdoing, whether or not that individual is culpable of the wrongdoing. Nonetheless, there are significant differences between the executive clawback statutes and the Ponzi scheme clawback cases. As compared with the Ponzi scheme clawbacks, executive clawbacks are at once more compelling and less harsh. Even in cases where the executive did not participate in the false or fraudulent financial accounting, one could argue that restitution of the excess compensation—i.e., the incentivebased pay that used the falsely inflated figures as the basis for calculating the executive’s bonuses, etc.—is nonetheless warranted. Under Dodd-Frank, for example, the executive clawback only rectifies an over-payment and returns the executive to the position she would have occupied had the provision contemplates only those officers or directors who bear a culpable connection to the company’s failure, I do not consider it further. 168 For the relevant provision, see Jesse Fried & Nitzan Shilon, Excess-Pay Clawbacks, 36 J. CORP. L. 721, 730 (2011). 169 See generally Bachelder, supra note 164. 170 See, e.g., SEC v. Jenkins, No. 09-CV-0510-PHX-RJB, slip op. (D. Ariz. Nov. 16, 2011), available at http://www.wlrk.com/docs/SECVJenkins09-cv-1510-136.pdf (holding that the SEC may claw back executive compensation even when the executive in question was not guilty of the misconduct that necessitated the restatement); ROPES & GRAY, COURT SAYS SARBANES-OXLEY ALLOWS “CLAWBACKS” OF EXECUTIVE’S BONUSES, available at http://www.ropesgray.com/files/Publication/09095ca9-bef7-49e2aa9d-45eab883df2f/Presentation/PublicationAttachment/6fc9ecd8-5f53-45bc-89dc48b37b701ba7/06142010TaxBenefitsAlert.pdf (last visited Mar. 12, 2012); Bachelder, supra note 164 (“EESA § 111(b)(3)(B) contains no provision limiting it to cases of misconduct.”); Liz Skola, The Dodd-Frank Act Requires Publicly-Traded Companies to Adopt Compensation Clawback Policies, SEC. LITIG. BLOG (Aug. 5, 2010, 9:05 AM), http://securities.litigation.alston.com/blog.aspx?entry=3869 (“The recent no-fault interpretation of the Sarbanes-Oxley clawback is codified in the Dodd-Frank Act clawback statute.”). 171 For the view that an executive might not be innocent of a corporate wrong even if she neither participated in, knew about, or was obligated to know about, the wrong, see Amy J. Sepinwall, Guilty by Proxy: Expanding the Boundaries of Responsibility in the Face of Corporate Crime, 63 HASTINGS L.J. 411, 435-45 (2012). 46 BROOKLYN LAW REVIEW [Vol. 78:1 corporation’s accounting been accurate from the start.172 Thus, she retains whatever financial rewards are owed to her by virtue of what the company did in fact earn—unlike the winning Ponzi scheme investor, who is forced to return all of her profits. Further, even the more severe clawbacks that SOX and EESA permit—where the executive may be compelled to return all of her incentive-based pay—appear more justifiable than do the Ponzi scheme clawbacks. For one thing, the executive faces a shorter reach-back period than does the Ponzi scheme investor.173 Moreover, the executive may not feel the sting of any clawback she faces, since corporations are permitted to insure their officers and directors against clawbacks at the shareholders’ expense, such that the insurance policy would cover the executive’s obligations to return money pursuant to a successful clawback action.174 By contrast, Ponzi scheme investors cannot insure their investments against fraud. In any event, even while financial regulators are permitted to pursue executive clawbacks, this is a remedy that 172 Usha Rodrigues puts the point nicely: “If you get a bonus because you meet a goal, and it later turns out that the goal wasn’t really met because someone messed with the numbers, then you need to give the money back. Even if you didn’t do anything wrong, you didn’t really earn that money.” Usha Rodrigues, Clawbacks, Outrage, and Interpretation, CONGLOMERATE (Aug. 10, 2009), http://www.theconglomerate.org/2009/ 08/clawbacks-outrage-and-interpretation.html (internal quotation marks omitted). 173 More specifically, the reach back period is no more than three years under any of the federal statutes for the executive, while state law permits avoidance of a fraudulent transfer up to six years prior to the scheme’s collapse. See supra notes 16869 and accompanying text. State law follows one of two forms—the Uniform Fraudulent Conveyances Act (UFCA) or Uniform Fraudulent Transfers Act (UFTA). There is no uniform reach-back period among UFCA states, though the range is between two and six years; the UFTA provides a four-year reach-back period. See White, supra note 88, at 358-59. 174 Reynolds Holding & Una Galani, Pushing Back on Clawbacks, N.Y. TIMES, Dec. 19, 2011, at B2, available at http://www.nytimes.com/2011/12/20/business/ pushing-back-on-clawbacks.html. For example, the FDIC sued three executives at Washington Mutual, the failed bank, seeking to recover $900 million from them on the allegation that they took excessive risks in order to reap short-term profits. See, e.g., Louise Story, Ex-Bank Executives Settle F.D.I.C. Lawsuit, N.Y. TIMES, Dec. 13, 2011, at B5, available at http://www.nytimes.com/2011/12/14/business/ex-bank-executivessettle-fdic-suit.html. The executives ended up settling for $64 million, but they paid only $400,000 of that out of pocket; the remainder was covered by their clawback insurance. See id. Corporations and insurance companies seek to justify the insurance coverage by arguing that the clawback provisions are intended for restitutionary, and not punitive, purposes, and so it doesn’t matter whether the returned money comes from the executive’s pocket or instead that of the insurance company. See id. Their position would seem to overlook the deterrent aspect of clawbacks, which can succeed only if the executive personally suffers a pecuniary consequence as a result of her company’s mistaken statements. 2012] RIGHTING OTHERS’ WRONGS 47 commentators revile175 and that even the SEC regulators seem to shun.176 Although companies issued 4609 earnings restatements between 2006 and 2009, the SEC exercised its Sarbanes-Oxley authority to seek executive clawbacks in only eleven instances.177 While Dodd-Frank’s clawback provisions were meant to increase the number of such actions by allowing both shareholders and the SEC to litigate them, this aspect of Dodd-Frank has met substantial criticism178 and has not been 175 See, e.g., Larry Ribstein, Punishing Innocent Executives: SOX’s Litigation Time Bomb Goes Off, IDEOBLOG (July 22, 2009, 11:53 AM), http://busmovie.typepad.com/ ideoblog/2009/07/punishing-innocent-executives-soxs-litigation-time-bomb-goes-off.html; Russell G. Ryan, The SEC vs. CEO Pay, WALL ST. J., Aug. 4, 2009, at A.11, available at http://www.chline.wsj.com/article/SB10001424052970204619004574324511579902986.html. 176 Cf. Manning G. Warren III, Equitable Clawback: An Essay on Restoration of Executive Compensation, 12 U. PA. J. BUS. L. 1135 (bemoaning the under-utilization of a common law doctrine that would allow private individuals seeking forfeiture of compensation as a remedy to sue executives who had breached their fiduciary duties). 177 See, e.g., Fried & Shilon, supra note 168, at 731. The SEC took action against transgressing corporations in a number of notable cases of corporate wrongdoing. In these cases, the SEC filed complaints against executives implicated in the wrongdoing but declined to pursue clawbacks. See, e.g., Complaint at 1-2, SEC v. Dell Inc., No. 1:10-cv-01245 (D.D.C. July 22, 2010), available at http://www.sec.gov/ litigation/complaints/2010/comp21599.pdf (SEC’s action against Dell Computers, its CEO, and its CFO for overstating earnings between 2002 and 2006); see also Taking Away Dell’s Cookie Jar, ECONOMIST ONLINE (July 23, 2010, 5:58 PM) http://www.economist.com/blogs/newsbook/2010/07/dells_sec_settlement. Dell agreed to pay a penalty of $100 million to settle SEC charges that it “manipulated its accounting over an extended period to project financial results that the company wished it had achieved.” Press Release, U.S. Sec. & Exch. Comm’n, SEC Charges Dell and Senior Executives with Disclosure and Accounting Fraud (July 22, 2010) (citation omitted) (internal quotation marks omitted), available at http://www.sec.gov/ news/press/2010/2010-131.htm. The CEO and CFO each “agreed to pay a $4 million penalty to settle the case without admitting or denying wrongdoing, but didn’t return any pay,” which implies that this was not a true “clawback.” Kara Scannell, Clawbacks Divide SEC, WALL ST. J., Aug. 7, 2010, at B3, available at http://online.wsj.com/article/ SB10001424052748703988304575413671786664134.html. Similarly, in a case brought by the SEC against Hank Greenberg, former CEO of AIG, the SEC alleged that under Greenberg’s leadership AIG “faced a number of financial challenges that, had they been properly reported or accounted for, would have exposed significant missteps in AIG’s operations and caused the company to miss certain key earnings and growth targets.” Complaint at 46, SEC v. Greenberg, No. 09 Civ. 6939 (S.D.N.Y. 2009), available at http://online.wsj.com/public/resources/ documents/SECcomplaintgreenberg806.pdf. The SEC complaint sought disgorgement of ill-gotten gains and civil penalties pursuant to Section 21(d)(3) of the Exchange Act (15 U.S.C. § 78u(d)(3) (2010)) but, of particular relevance here, did not seek to clawback any incentive-based compensation, even though the SEC had the authority to do so under Section 304 of Sarbanes-Oxley. Id.; see also Stephen Bainbridge, “Unlike French wine, fraud cases don’t get better with age,” PROFESSORBAINBRIDGE.COM (Aug. 11, 2009, 12:19 PM), http://www.professorbainbridge.com/professorbainbridgecom/2009/08/ unlike-french-wine-fraud-cases-dont-get-better-with-age.html. 178 See, e.g., Donald Delves, Clawback Requirement Removes Board Discretion, FORBES (July 14, 2009, 10:09 AM), available at http://www.forbes.com/sites/donalddelves/ 2011/07/14/clawback-requirement-removes-board-discretion/. Delves argues that clawbacks are ill-advised because they may make accounting departments less likely to uncover errors as employees within these departments will fear retaliation from the 48 BROOKLYN LAW REVIEW [Vol. 78:1 invoked even in cases involving the financial institutions whose failures brought the global markets to the brink of collapse.179 Finally, even if executive clawback actions were to become commonplace, they would still be a far cry from investor clawback actions, the tool of choice in the recovery efforts of the Madoff trustee.180 The difference arises, at least in part, because unlike the innocent Ponzi scheme investor, the executive cannot plausibly contend that she reasonably relied on the veracity of the earnings statement and, in turn, the legitimacy of her bonus payment for the year in question. The executive is not a disinterested party without access to the relevant financial records, who simply takes the statements and the money that they engender at face value.181 This is not to CEO who is forced to return incentive-based pay. Id. Alternatively, Delves argues that clawbacks may just encourage boards to structure executive pay in a way that does not key it to the company’s performance. Id. Such board action would run counter to DoddFrank’s goal of aligning the interests of the executive and her corporation. Greg Michaels, G20 Leaders Have the Right Idea, DEALBREAKER (Sept. 16, 2009, 10:17 AM), http://dealbreaker.com/2009/09/g20-leaders-have-the-right-idea/ (offering the tongue-incheek suggestion that politicians zealous about clawbacks should consider passing legislation that would allow for recoupment of a politician’s salary in the event that her successor inherits problems for which she bears responsibility). 179 Thus, James E. Cayne, the former chief executive of Bear Stearns, still lives in his $28.24 million apartment at the Plaza Hotel; Joseph J. Cassano the former chief executive of A.I.G. Financial Products, kept more than $100 million in compensation; and E. Stanley O’Neal, who was the chief executive of Merrill Lynch, retired with a pay package valued at more [than] $300 million. Steven M. Davidoff, In F.D.I.C.’s Proposal, Incentive for Excessive Risk Remains, N.Y. TIMES (DEALBOOK) (Apr. 12, 2011, 6:00 PM), http://dealbook.nytimes.com/2011/04/12/ in-f-d-i-c-s-proposal-incentive-for-excessive-risk-remains/. 180 The law does prohibit a corporation from issuing dividends if it is insolvent, or if the distribution would make it so. See Clark, supra note 94, at 554-60. So, shareholders are prospectively barred from receiving funds that would hinder repayment of the corporation’s creditors. But a prospective bar on receiving a profit to which one is not affirmatively entitled is a far cry from a claim that one must return a received profit to which one legitimately believed oneself entitled. In any event, there are a number of ways in which the corporation can circumvent the bar, as Clark details. Id. at 556-58. Shareholders might well receive profits that would diminish the assets available for distribution to the corporation’s creditors. Further, the circumstances under which these profits would be subject to clawback are far more constrained than the general clawback provisions. See id. at 558-59 n.154 (There are “provisions in corporate laws specifically stating the conditions under which stockholders may be liable to corporate creditors for improper dividends received . . . . Some of these provisions are clearly more lenient than those applicable to the ordinary fraudulent transferee or grantor, e.g., provisions immunizing from any duty to disgorge dividends those stockholders who were ignorant of the impropriety of the dividends, even when the dividends were paid while the corporation was insolvent.” (citation omitted)). 181 One way to put the difference between the executive’s relationship to her company’s financial performance and the winning Ponzi scheme investor’s relationship to the actual finances of the scheme would be to note that the latter is an “arm’s length bargain,” while the former is not. See, e.g., Merrill v. Abbott (In re Universal Clearing 2012] RIGHTING OTHERS’ WRONGS 49 suggest that there is an implicit kind of culpability that the executive bears—i.e., negligence or a failure of due diligence— which justifies the clawback. The executive may be genuinely and permissibly ignorant of the financial errors. Still, it is her corporation, and if its earnings statements contain errors, she should be denied the benefits of the mistake.182 Instead, a more promising parallel to the Ponzi scheme clawback case is the circumstance in which an innocent shareholder suffers pecuniary consequences as a result of a wrong committed by the corporation. B. Shareholder-Funded Restitution Two general kinds of cases occur where shareholders appear to suffer pecuniary consequences as a result of corporate conduct of which they are innocent. The first is the garden-variety case where the corporation faces a fine or damages award and paying it will lower share value. Though the shareholder thereby incurs a potential loss, this is not a true clawback because the shareholder is not being asked to return money that she had already received. Nonetheless, it is worth examining this case because one might think it represents a strand of doctrine where innocent investors suffer in order to defray the losses of the victims of another’s wrong— in this case, the corporation’s. Accordingly, it is possible that this example could provide support for clawbacks targeting innocent Ponzi scheme investors. The second kind of case involves straightforward shareholder clawbacks and arises when an insolvent corporation has undergone a leveraged buyout. Here, the creditors can seek to reclaim money that the corporation’s former shareholders received in selling their shares to the corporation’s management-cum-owners in the leveraged buy-out (LBO) process. House Co.), 77 B.R. 843, 862 (D. Utah 1987) (stating that the test for good faith “is whether the transaction in question bears the earmarks of an arm’s length bargain”) (citation omitted). Madoff himself insisted that his investors lacked both the financial wherewithal and the means to have uncovered the fraud: “Although I explained the Strategy to them they were not sophisticated enough to evaluate it properly . . . . They were not in a position to perform the necessary due diligence and did not have access to necessary financial info or records.” See Toobin, supra note 8, at 15 (internal quotation marks omitted); see also id. at 19. 182 Cf. Sepinwall, supra note 171, at 434 (providing an account that would hold executives responsible for corporate wrongs independent of whether the executives satisfy the traditional hallmarks of individual culpability). 50 BROOKLYN LAW REVIEW [Vol. 78:1 1. Consequences to Shareholders of Corporate Wrongdoing When a corporation finds itself faced with a financial penalty or significant damages judgment, shareholders might see the value of their shares drop.183 This might seem unfair in light of the traditional separation between ownership and control, which entails that shareholders have no say over the corporation’s day-to-day activities184 and therefore no available means to prevent the wrongful conduct that precipitates a penalty or judgment. Moreover, the unfairness would be even more apparent in cases where those who hold shares at the time of redress purchased their shares after the wrongdoing had occurred but at a price that did not reflect the possibility that the corporation might face the specific penalty or judgment in question—for example, because the corporate wrong had not been disclosed or even discovered at the time the investor purchased her shares. To make matters more concrete, consider fraud-on-themarket cases, where the corporation misstates its financial situation and paints a rosier picture than is warranted. In light of the fraudulent statement, share prices rise. To take advantage of the rise in share price, some investors holding shares in the corporation choose to sell, and those who buy the shares then pay an artificially inflated price. When the fraud comes to light, those who bought the shares at an inflated price will sue the corporation for damages, rather than the exshareholders who profited from the corporation’s fraud. If the buying shareholders prevail in their suit, it is the corporation’s current shareholders—who might well include the plaintiffs in the suit!—who will suffer, at least if the corporation’s share price drops as a result.185 183 See, e.g., V.S. Khanna, Corporate Criminal Liability: What Purpose Does It Serve?, 109 HARV. L. REV. 1477, 1495 (1996) (“Imposing sanctions on a corporation for the acts of its managers or employees presumably decreases the corporation’s net worth. Shareholders [. . .] bear the brunt of such a decrease . . . .” (citation omitted)). Cf. Daniel R. Fischel & Alan O. Sykes, Corporate Crime, 25 J. LEGAL STUD. 319, 349 (1996) (addressing criminal fines, and arguing that “in the case of a corporation, the burden of a punitive award will fall primarily on the shareholders, most of whom usually have no connection to the wrongdoing in question.”). 184 The classic text articulating this conception of the corporation is ADOLF BERLE & GARDINER MEANS, THE MODERN CORPORATION AND PRIVATE PROPERTY (1932). 185 See, e.g., William W. Bratton & Michael L. Wachter, The Political Economy of Fraud on the Market, 160 U. PA. L. REV. 69, 73 (2011). 2012] RIGHTING OTHERS’ WRONGS 51 One might then be inclined to say that the SEC’s actions here require innocent parties to contribute to defraying the losses of the victims of a wrong, in much the same way that innocent Ponzi scheme “winners” are made to contribute to defraying the losses of the “losers” of the Ponzi scheme. But there are important distinctions. For one thing, it is not clear that those who own shares at the time the corporation is subject to the penalty or judgment do in fact sustain a loss. The company’s share price might take a dip, but unless the shareholder is compelled to sell in the immediate aftermath of the penalty’s imposition, this may represent only a paper loss. Second, shareholders enjoy limited liability; the most any shareholder can lose is the amount of her investment. By contrast, a Ponzi scheme winner who no longer has the money subject to the clawback can, in principle, have her wages garnished or assets seized in order to satisfy the trustee’s claims against her. Third, if the company is forced to disgorge only the funds corresponding to the total amount by which the share value was artificially inflated, and without incurring an additional financial penalty, then the current shareholders come to occupy a position no worse than the one they would have occupied had the fraud never occurred. Finally, it is not the loss in share value that compensates the corporation’s victims. The money shareholders lose is not the same money that helps to make the victims whole. Indeed, the drop in share price may correspond only very loosely to the fine or damages award that has been imposed on the corporation.186 For all of these reasons, cases where innocent shareholders sustain a loss in share value as a result of the corporation’s restitutionary or compensatory obligations are vastly different from those faced by innocent investors in the Madoff clawback actions, who may be compelled to return money that they legitimately thought was theirs in order to compensate the Madoff losers. As such, innocent shareholders in these cases do not face the unfairness that the innocent targets of a Ponzi scheme clawback suit face. In fact, it is not clear that the former face any unfairness at all. 186 This would be the case if, for example, analysts project that the corporation stands to earn significant profits in the coming quarters and these projections offset the reduction in share price caused by the penalty. 52 BROOKLYN LAW REVIEW [Vol. 78:1 2. Shareholder Clawbacks in the Wake of a Leveraged Buyout There is, however, one type of case where a shareholder can be required to return money she made in the market— namely, where she has sold her shares as part of an LBO and the target corporation goes bankrupt shortly thereafter. In a typical LBO, management privatizes a publicly traded corporation by buying back all of the outstanding shares and delisting the corporation. In order to purchase the outstanding shares, management often borrows money from a third-party— e.g., a bank—and secures its loan with the target corporation’s assets, thereby increasing the target corporation’s liabilities to the potential detriment of the corporation’s existing creditors.187 As one commentator explains, the corporation’s “new debt is likely to be senior secured debt. Thus, by definition, LBOs adversely affect existing creditors of the company by reducing the assets available for the satisfaction of obligations owed to them.”188 In the event that the acquired corporation becomes insolvent shortly after the buyout, the question arises as to whether the share purchases constituted fraudulent transfers, such that a bankruptcy trustee would be permitted to seek to claw back the money that the former shareholders received when they sold their shares to management.189 Some commentators and courts have argued that the fraudulent transfer provisions should not extend to the LBO context.190 Nonetheless, the vast majority of courts have approved the use of clawback suits against former shareholders in this context.191 Requiring former shareholders to return money in the wake of the insolvency of a corporation in which they no longer 187 See, e.g., Borowitz & Hahn, supra note 114, at 67, 70-71; Robert J. White, Leveraged Buyouts and Fraudulent Conveyance Laws Under the Bankruptcy Code—Like Oil and Water, They Just Don’t Mix, 1991 ANN. SURV. AM. L. 357, 359, 362 & n.29 (1992). 188 Kathryn V. Smyser, Going Private and Going Under, 63 IND. L.J. 781, 786 (1987–1988). 189 In addition to pursuing clawbacks against the former shareholders, the bankruptcy trustee could also target the lending bank, which has been “arguably enriched at [the] creditors’ expense,” Franci J. Blassberg & John M. Vasily, The Lender’s Perspective on Leveraged Acquisitions, 676 PLI/Corp 69, 127 (1990). 190 See, e.g., Kupetz v. Wolf, 845 F.2d 842, 848 (9th Cir. 1988); Baird & Jackson, supra note 96, at 834. 191 See generally Borowitz & Hahn, supra note 114, at 78 (noting that “the applicability of fraudulent conveyance law, as currently enacted, to leveraged buyouts is clear, and the vast majority of courts to have considered the issue have so held” and collecting representative cases). For a scholarly defense of this doctrinal development that seeks to counter Baird and Jackson’s arguments (see supra note 94), see generally Smyser, supra note 188. 2012] RIGHTING OTHERS’ WRONGS 53 hold shares might seem like the height of unfairness—both because the shareholders had presumably given “fair value” in the form of their ownership shares and because the shareholders appear to be innocent of the conduct leading to the acquired corporation’s bankruptcy. As such, we might think that there are relevant similarities between this set of clawbacks and the clawbacks that innocent investors in a Ponzi scheme face. A closer look, however, reveals important differences. First, there need be no relationship between the price at which the shareholders sell their shares and the fair market value of the shares. In a barely solvent corporation, for example, the price that management is willing to pay may be keyed to the amount of the loan it can secure, rather than the value of the equity interest in the company. The bank might determine the loan amount without regard to the corporation’s already existing debt. After all, the bank will enjoy priority over existing creditors; as long as the target corporation can secure the bank’s loan, the bank has no reason to concern itself with the corporation’s existing obligations.192 Thus, in a world without shareholder clawbacks, an LBO would be attractive to a “buyer, seller and third party lender precisely because it [would] allow[] all parties to the buyout to shift some portion of the risk of loss associated with their investment in the company to the ‘investors’ in the company who are not involved in the buyout— the other creditors.”193 This is especially true in the case where the target corporation is already financially troubled, since the shareholders couldn’t readily sell their shares on the secondary market. An LBO thereby provides them with a way both to obtain more money for their shares than they otherwise could, and to “withdraw[] their capital from exposure to total loss in the event the company [were to go] bankrupt.”194 Moreover, unlike the case in which the corporation incurs more debt to fund an entrepreneurial activity that might eventually be profitable, “a leveraged buyout involves a transaction in which the corporate debtor pledges valuable assets ‘without getting anything in return’ because the loan proceeds are used to pay the selling shareholders.”195 Further, the existing shareholders are not without the power to promote, or even mandate, the LBO. In the process, 192 193 194 195 See Smyser, supra note 188, at 798. Id. at 799. Id. at 798. Id. at 803. 54 BROOKLYN LAW REVIEW [Vol. 78:1 the existing shareholders effectively jump the queue that would exist in the event of a bankruptcy, given that the shareholders’ equity interest in the company is subordinate to the claims of the company’s creditors. Had the public corporation gone bankrupt, the shareholders would have been able to claim only the value remaining after creditors had been paid; by forcing the corporation to buy back the shareholders’ stock before the company declares bankruptcy, the shareholders enjoy a priority over the company’s creditors that they are not entitled to. The role shareholders play in an LBO, then, is not like the role innocent winners play in a Ponzi scheme. Instead, the shareholders’ role more closely resembles the role played by a group of Ponzi scheme investors who, knowing of the fraud and seeing the scheme approach the brink of collapse, encourage its operator to find new investors or seek to recruit new investors themselves.196 These investors participate in the scheme in a way that makes them complicit in it;197 they hardly count as innocent winners.198 It does not seem at all unfair to require such accomplices to return any money they have withdrawn. Doing so is consistent with the classic dictate that an individual may not profit from her own wrongdoing199 but instead must redress her victims.200 In a similar vein, it is not untoward to ask the former shareholders of an LBO to return the money they received from selling their shares where they encouraged, or perhaps even directed, the sale. Again, all of 196 This is the role that Sonja Kohn, an Austrian banker, is alleged to have played in the Madoff Ponzi scheme. See, e.g., Diana B. Henriques & Peter Lattman, Madoff Trustee Seeks $19.6 Billion from Austrian Banker, N.Y. TIMES (DEALBOOK) (Dec. 10, 2010, 12:22 PM), http://dealbook.nytimes.com/2010/12/10/madoff-trusteeseeks-19-6-billion-from-austrian-banker (“[A]ccording to the complaint [Picard filed against Kohn], she knowingly raised billions of dollars in cash to sustain Mr. Madoff’s fraud in exchange for at least $62 million in secret kickbacks . . . .”). 197 See, e.g., Model Penal Code § 2.06(3) (1985) (stating that a person is criminally liable as an accomplice if “(a) with the purpose of promoting or facilitating the commission of the offense, he, (i) solicits [the] other person to commit it, or (ii) aids or agrees or attempts to aid such other person in planning or committing it, or (iii) having a legal duty to prevent the commission of the offense, fails to make proper effort [to prevent it]”). 198 But cf. Sharp Int’l Corp. v. State St. Bank & Trust Co. (In re Sharp Int’l Corp.), 403 F.3d 43 (2d Cir. 2005) (finding no lack of good faith where bank knew that Ponzi scheme operator was recruiting new investors to raise funds to repay bank, because bank did not encourage the conduct and bank had no duty to notify the recruited investors that they were going to be duped). 199 See, e.g., Riggs v. Palmer, 115 N.Y. 506, 506 (1889) (denying grandson his inheritance because he killed his grandfather precisely in order to benefit from the provisions of the deceased’s will). For an extended discussion of the case, see RONALD DWORKIN, LAW’S EMPIRE 15-20, 130-31 (1986). 200 See 1 HILLIARD, supra note 1, at 83. 2012] RIGHTING OTHERS’ WRONGS 55 this suggests that the typical shareholders in an LBO are situated differently from the innocent investors in a Ponzi scheme.201 From the now well-established practice of clawing back money from the investors in the LBO context, then, we cannot infer anything about the justifiability of clawbacks against innocent Ponzi scheme winners. V. EXPANDING RESTITUTION In Part II, I argued that only a very strained reading of the fraudulent transfer provisions would support clawing back money from innocent Ponzi scheme investors, and in Parts III and IV, I sought to establish that no other doctrine permits reclaiming money from the innocent beneficiaries of a wrong who reasonably relied on the authenticity of their earnings and whose profits cannot be construed as a windfall. Therefore, the clawback suits against innocent winners in a Ponzi scheme are anomalous. These winners incur restitutionary obligations that the law does not impose on other innocent beneficiaries of a wrong. At this point, one could seek to repudiate clawback suits altogether, arguing that if we are not prepared to have the innocent beneficiaries of wrongdoing restitute the wrongdoing’s victims across the board, we should not do so in the Ponzi scheme context alone. Instead, this Part adopts the opposite approach, arguing that we should recruit all innocent investors in our attempts to make the victims of financial fraud whole in 201 But what about the former shareholder who did nothing to encourage, let alone direct, the leveraged buyout, and who did not know and had no reason to know that the company would be over-leveraged if the LBO were to occur? Is she not in a position that is the moral equivalent of the innocent Ponzi scheme winner? It strikes me that even here there is firmer justification for a clawback against the shareholder than against the winner, for as a result of the LBO the shareholder succeeds in enjoying a higher priority than the company’s creditors, even while the creditors would have had a higher priority than the shareholder had both still had an interest in the company at the time of its bankruptcy. By contrast, the winner has a priority equal to that of the loser, and so at least cannot be accused of having jumped the queue, as it were. Nevertheless, even if the shareholder in question has played no role in encouraging the LBO, and even if we set aside the concern about her enjoying undue priority over the corporation’s creditors, it is not clear that a clawback action against her serves to undermine the objections to a clawback action against the innocent Ponzi scheme winner. Instead, we might well want to object to clawback actions against both. Cf. In re Estate of Wolf & Vine, Inc., 77 B.R. 754, 760 (C.D. Cal. 1987) (objecting to a clawback suit in the wake of an LBO against innocent former shareholders, on the ground that the share purchase “was an entirely fair transaction from the seller’s perspective. In the Court’s view, it is an unwarranted extension of the fraudulent conveyance laws, or any laws, to attempt to deprive [the former shareholders] of the value they received in exchange for their business.”), aff’d sub nom. Kupetz v. Wolf, 845 F.2d 842 (9th Cir. 1988). Both cases, that is, might well involve an indefensible effort to recoup money in order to defray another’s losses. 56 BROOKLYN LAW REVIEW [Vol. 78:1 Part V.A, and beginning to develop a proposal for how this might be done in Part V.B. A. The Winners Reasonably Believed in the Authenticity of Their Winnings While the innocent Ponzi scheme winners are no less entitled to the “profits” they withdrew than are its losers, nor are they more entitled to them. However, the same can be said of any investor who profits from an arms-length investment. The innocent winners in a Ponzi scheme are no less entitled to their earnings than the winners in a legitimate investment scheme are entitled to the money they earn on their investment. That is the central insight motivating the arguments set forth here. Where some investors come out ahead and others come out behind, and where luck is the only feature that separates the two, we might well want to counteract its effects. It is better to reclaim some money from the winners and transfer it to the losers, so that all share in the losses equitably. This is not to say that all cases in which fortune chooses the winner entail an obligation, or even a reason, for the winner to share her winnings among all of the game’s participants. For example, we would not think that the person holding a winning lottery ticket has any reason, let alone an obligation, to share the jackpot with all of the other lottery ticketholders. One clear way to draw a line between the lottery case and the Ponzi scheme case is to look to the participants’ reasonable expectations. The lottery ticketholders know that only one of them will win, that the others will have supplied the money the winner wins, and that luck alone will determine the winner. The Ponzi scheme investors, on the other hand, reasonably conceive of themselves as sitting in the same boat: All who invest at the same time would win or lose together, and whether they were to win or lose would turn, they believe, on the scheme operator’s investment savvy, not the point in time at which they were to choose to withdraw their funds (which cannot be said to enhance or diminish the putative investors’ level of desert, given their presumed ignorance of the fraudulent nature of the scheme).202 At least in cases of financial 202 See supra notes 41-48 and accompanying text (presenting reasons to think the Madoff Ponzi scheme winners were blamelessly ignorant of his fraud). A real-life case bears out the claim that those Ponzi scheme winners who cashed out early are no 2012] RIGHTING OTHERS’ WRONGS 57 wrongdoing, where all investors are innocent and yet some profit from the wrongdoing while others lose out, we might want those who have come out ahead to help defray the losses of those who would have otherwise come out behind.203 Two questions present themselves at this point. First, why should we conceive of the scope of restitution as specific to a particular fraud, such that there is a special restitutionary relationship between the winners and losers of that fraud, rather than a general relationship that operates between winners and losers in the market as a whole? Second, why think that only those who benefit from a fraud may be made to offer restitution, rather than thinking that anyone who wins in the market—whether through a fraudulent or legitimate investment vehicle—ought to contribute? I address these questions in turn. Suppose that we were to decide that the “winners” in some financial frauds should have to give up their winnings and that the “losers” should receive compensation. Why require that restitution operate strictly between winners and losers of more or less deserving than those who had open accounts at the time of the scheme’s collapse and lost money they had invested or at least profits they thought they had earned: Steve Simkin and Laura Blank divorced in 2006, split the $5.4 M in their Madoff account equally between them. Ms. Blank cashed out shortly thereafter, receiving 50% of the then-stated value of the money in their Madoff account. Mr. Simkin did not seek to withdraw most of his share of the money in the Madoff account and, when the scheme went bust, he lost the money he believed the account had held. He sought to sue Ms. Blank for a rescission of this part of their divorce agreement, arguing that, unbeknownst to them at the time, the Madoff account never existed, and so should not have been counted among the couple’s joint assets. Mr. Simkin lost at the trial level, but won on appeal. New York’s highest state court then reversed, on the ground that the Madoff account did exist—at least until December 2008, any time before which Mr. Simkin could have sought to cash out for the full amount he believed the account contained. See, e.g., Peter Lattman, Court Says Madoff Victim Can’t Redo Terms of His Divorce, N.Y. TIMES (DEALBOOK) (Apr. 3, 2012, 7:51 PM), http://dealbook.nytimes.com/ 2012/04/03/court-says-madoff-victim-can’t-redo-terms-of-his-divorce/. The Simkin-Blank dispute, then, presents us with a case in which a court effectively refuses to compel a particular winner to restitute a particular loser even though the court had no reason to think that the winner deserved her winnings any more than the loser deserved his losses. Other cases in which one set of participants in a game or scheme fares far better than another solely as a matter of luck may be more complicated. (Consider, for example, the fortunes of the shareholders of a non-mining corporation at the time that it unexpectedly strikes gold relative to those of the prior shareholders who had cashed out before the gold strike.) I leave these more complicated cases to one side. 203 The notion that the winners and losers sit in the same boat appears to have escaped the notice of some members of both parties, as they proceed on an “every man for himself,” basis, to use the words of one Madoff investor, and engage in a “reality-show kind of fighting.” Eric Konigsberg, Investors in a Competition for a Piece of the Madoff Pie, N.Y. TIMES, June 29, 2009, at B1 (quoting one of the Madoff claimants) (internal quotation marks omitted), available at http://www.nytimes.com/2009/06/29/29madoff.html. 58 BROOKLYN LAW REVIEW [Vol. 78:1 the same fraud? That is, why should the Madoff winners restitute the Madoff losers, rather than investors who were defrauded by Countrywide, for example? We now know that Countrywide overcharged customers who were desperately hanging onto their home loans—a federal offense for which it paid $108 million in fines204—and discriminated against Black and Hispanic borrowers, for which it paid an additional $335 million fine.205 These fines presumably diminished the share value of those who held shares in Bank of America, which acquired Countrywide in 2008, at the time the fines were paid. Those who sold shares in Countrywide or Bank of America before the offenses were uncovered presumably received more money for their shares than they were worth, since Countrywide’s offenses inflated the share value at the time of sale.206 It might then be reasonable to think that the investors who innocently profited by selling Countrywide’s fraudulently inflated shares owe some or all of the profits they earned to those who bought the shares at an artificially inflated price, or to those whose shares diminished in value as a result of Countrywide’s fines. But again, why think that restitution should operate just between the Countrywide investors? To take an example that hits even closer to the Madoff scandal, consider that shareholders in “J.P. Morgan Chase [collectively] earned after-tax profits totaling $435 million between 1993 and 2008 as a result of the billions of dollars Madoff deposited in the bank using his investors’ money.”207 Yet no clawbacks are being pursued against these shareholders. Why shouldn’t the Madoff winners help defray the losses of the Countrywide losers, and why shouldn’t the Countrywide or J.P. Morgan Chase winners help make the 204 Fed. Trade Comm’n, Press Release: Countrywide Will Pay $108 Million for Overcharging Struggling Homeowners; Loan Servicer Inflated Fees, Mishandled Loans of Borrowers in Bankruptcy (June 7, 2010), available at http://www.ftc.gov/opa/2010/06/ countrywide.shtm. 205 See, e.g., Charlie Savage, Countrywide Will Settle a Bias Suit, N.Y. TIMES, Dec. 21, 2011, at B1, available at http://www.nytimes.com/2011/12/22/business/ussettlement-reported-on-countrywide-lending.html. 206 See, e.g., Ben Protess, Bank of America Profit Drops 37%, N.Y. TIMES (DEALBOOK) (Apr. 15, 2011, 7:27 AM), http://dealbook.nytimes.com/2011/04/15/bank-ofamerica-profit-drops-nearly-36/?smid=pl-sare (“Bank of America reported a 37 percent drop in first-quarter earnings on Friday, as the nation’s biggest bank continued to battle the legacy of the mortgage crisis and legal problems linked to the ill-fated acquisition of Countrywide Financial.”). 207 Louis R. Davis & Linus Wilson, Estimating JP Morgan Chase’s Profits from the Madoff Deposits, 14 RISK MGMT. & INS. REV. 1, 107-19 (2011). 2012] RIGHTING OTHERS’ WRONGS 59 Madoff losers whole?208 The answer is surely related in part to administrative convenience; the trustee in the Madoff case does not have authority to claw back money from individuals who did not have accounts with Madoff. However, administrative convenience is relevant only if we have already determined that there is an obligation on the part of those who win in a fraudulent scheme of which they were ignorant to defray the losses of those who lose, whether from that same fraudulent scheme or from another. The innocent winners in a Ponzi scheme are not more responsible for the losers’ losses than is anyone else who is innocent of the fraud. So, we must turn to the second question—why think that those who innocently profit from a fraud bear obligations of restitution that those who profit from a legitimate investment lack? This question lacks a good answer. The innocent winners in a Ponzi scheme are innocent not just in the sense that they did not know—and had no reason to know—of the fraud, but also in the sense that, from their perspective, their withdrawals represented earnings as legitimate as the earnings they would have reaped from a genuine investment vehicle. It is on this ground that Judge Rakoff held that innocent investors in Madoff’s scheme may avail themselves of the Bankruptcy Code’s safe harbor provision,209 which “precludes the Trustee from bringing any action to recover from any of Madoff’s customers any of the monies paid by Madoff Securities to those customers except in the case of actual fraud.”210 Importantly, Judge Rakoff readily acknowledged that no securities were bought or sold, and that Madoff himself would not have been permitted to avail himself of the safe harbor provision.211 Nonetheless, “[f]rom the standpoint of Madoff Securities’ customers (except for any who were actual participants in the fraud), the settlement payments made to them by Madoff Securities were entirely bona fide, and they 208 Alan Strudler has intriguingly pursued questions of this kind in the context of large-scale accidents. Alan Strudler, Mass Torts and Moral Principles, 11 L. & PHIL. 297, 323-25 (1992). Strudler argues that even if one is merely causally responsible, and not morally responsible for accidental harm, one nonetheless bears an obligation to repair the harm that innocent bystanders lack. Whatever the merits of Strudler’s account for cases of mere causal responsibility, it is inapposite where, as here, one cannot even say that the innocent beneficiaries of the fraud caused the injury that the losers sustained. 209 Picard v. Katz, 462 B.R. 447, 451 (S.D.N.Y. 2011). The safe harbor provision is contained in 11 U.S.C. § 546(e) (2006). 210 Katz, 462 B.R. at 451-52. 211 See Picard v. Katz, 466 B.R. 208, 212 (S.D.N.Y. 2012). 60 BROOKLYN LAW REVIEW [Vol. 78:1 therefore are fully entitled to invoke the protections of section 546(e) [i.e., the safe harbor provision].”212 Judge Rakoff also implied elsewhere that what matters is the investors’ reasonable belief and, so long as that belief is reasonable, the court must treat the investors as if the belief were true,213 at least for purposes of the avoidance actions.214 Judge Rakoff’s position supports the idea that the innocent investors reasonably relied on the authenticity of their withdrawals. Where a Madoff winner spent the money she withdrew—whether on grandchildren’s college tuition, living expenses, or even extravagant travel215—it might be unfair to pursue a clawback action against her, even if she is not so destitute as to be able to meet the trustee’s hardship standard.216 More to the point, since the latter set of investors has no more ground for relying on the legitimacy of their withdrawals than the winning Ponzi scheme investors have, it is unfair to treat Ponzi scheme winners differently from investors who withdraw money from a legitimate investment vehicle. As one commentator notes, “by what grace of God were many of us fortunate enough not to have relied on a 212 Katz, 462 B.R. at 452 n.3. See, e.g., Katz, 466 B.R. at 211 (“[If] Madoff Securities was fairly viewed by the defendants and other customers as engaged in the business of effecting transactions in securities . . . [then] the Trustee . . . may well be barred from [pursuing avoidance actions except in cases of actual fraud due] to the application of § 546(e).” (emphasis added)). 214 Peter Henning has noted that Rakoff’s position conflicts with the Second Circuit’s net equity position, which declines to use as the basis of recovery the amounts investors believed they had in their Madoff accounts. See Henning, supra note 12. Still, Rakoff did not have before him the question of what investors were owed; he was addressing the different question of what they could, or could not, be made to return. It is possible that there is a principled basis upon which one could credit the investors’ reasonable beliefs for purposes of the clawback suits but not for purposes of determining their net equity. 215 See, e.g., Madoff’s Victims, MADOFFSCANDAL.COM: THE LARGEST FRAUD THAT THE WORLD HAS EVER SEEN, http://www.madoffscandal.com/madoffs-victims/ (last visited Mar. 12, 2012) (describing Ira Roth, whose withdrawals from his Madoff account were used to pay for his college tuition and his grandmother’s living expenses); U.S. Attorney’s Letter and Attached Victim Impact Statements (Mar. 13, 2009), United States v. Madoff, No. 09 Crim. 213 (DC) (S.D.N.Y. June 15, 2009), available at http://www.cbsnews.com/ htdocs/pdf/Madoff--Victim_Impact_Statements.pdf (quoting from Letter from Ted and Sue Rehage to Senators Baucus, Grassley, and United States Senate Finance Committee members, which stated: “As a result [of our Madoff losses], our traveling will be curtailed with no more 9 or 10 weeks with the grandkids which is disappointing for all of us. Now it will be a week or two in state at best.”). 216 For Picard’s list of the indicators he believes relevant to determining hardship, see Hardship Program, THE MADOFF RECOVERY INITIATIVE, http://www.madoff.com/hardship-program-17.html (last visited Mar. 12, 2012). 213 2012] RIGHTING OTHERS’ WRONGS 61 Madoff . . . or somebody like [him]?”217 It may be no more than “dumb luck” that separates Ponzi scheme winners from those who win in a legitimate investment.218 And why should luck play such a decisive role in how one fares?219 In particular, why should we expect more from the innocent beneficiaries of a fraud than we expect from the innocent beneficiaries of a legitimate investment? The simple answer is that we should not. If this correct, one of two implications follows—either we should permit losses to remain where they fall, or we should enlist the Ponzi scheme winners along with all other investment winners to provide restitution. If the foregoing comments about luck have any intuitive appeal, they militate strongly in favor of the latter alternative. To allow losses to remain where they fall is to allow luck to govern how the winning and losing investors fare. But we can do better than that; we need not bow to luck’s whims. A form of restitution that gathers resources from all investment winners provides a more appropriate solution. B. Market-Wide Restitution A handful of commentators have championed the idea that winners and losers in a Ponzi scheme should together share in the losses the fraud has caused. Yet these commentators contemplate only intra-scheme restitution; they presume but do not defend the existence of a special connection binding the winners of a particular fraud to the losers of that fraud.220 By contrast, Part V.A demonstrated that all of those 217 Jeffrey M. Lipshaw, Disclosure and Judgment: “We Have Met Madoff and He Is Ours,” 35 U. DAYTON L. REV. 139, 139 n.1 (2009). 218 Id. at 139. 219 Indeed, many Madoff winners maintain that they were actually less greedy than were other winning investors in the market, having forsaken higher returns for Madoff’s steady but comparatively modest returns. So, if one did want to invoke the notion of desert, the Madoff winners would, at least on this basis, fare better than the investors in legitimate but aggressive and higher-performing schemes. See, e.g., Jon Healy, Are Bernard Madoff’s Victims Greedy?, L.A. TIMES (Aug. 19, 2011, 2:58 PM), http://opinion.latimes.com/opinionla/2011/08/are-bernard-madoffs-victims-greedy.html. Cf. Complaint at *2 ¶ 3, Haines v. Mass. Mut. Life Ins., 2009 WL 958069 (D. Mass. 2009) (No. 1:09cv10182), available at http://clients.oakbridgeins.com/clients/blog/ haines.pdf (seeking class action relief against Madoff feeder funds and alleging that “[p]laintiffs and the other investors in these funds were not wild speculators rolling the dice for high returns, but rather safe-conservative investors looking to protect and grow their retirement funds.”). 220 See Cherry & Wong, supra note 15, at 408-10 (arguing for the desirability of ex ante clawbacks—i.e., provisions in the contract that a prospective investor signs that requires the investor to share in the losses should fraud emerge); Pozza, Jr. et al., supra note 4, at 131 (“[A] fundamental principle should be that all victims share the 62 BROOKLYN LAW REVIEW [Vol. 78:1 who innocently win in the market are similarly situated, whether their winnings arise from legitimate or fraudulent investment vehicles. All of them share responsibility for restituting fraud’s victims. Implementing this insight need not involve a novel crafting of policy. Instead, one or both of two currently debated tax initiatives would do the trick, by effectively raising the money needed to sustain a fraud compensation fund. The first is a variant on the financial transactions tax (FTT), also called a Tobin Tax.221 While the idea for such a tax emerged in the 1970s and was originally conceived as a restraint on currency speculation, there has been a renewed vigor in calls for adoption of a more encompassing FTT after the 2008 financial meltdown.222 In particular, as its supporters now envision it, the FTT would be assessed on most financial transactions and would affect most asset classes.223 The recent enthusiasm for an FTT stems from two policy goals that supporters believe it will serve. First, it will curb “socially useless” short-term equity transactions,224 and second, it will impose some of the costs of risky bank activity on the banks that contribute to systemic risk.225 But there is an additional benefit, especially relevant here. An FTT would raise money that could be used to compensate the victims of fraud. In particular, investment winners would contribute money to the compensation fund in proportion to the amount of their winnings, and the FTT rate could vary depending on whether the seller stood to reap a net gain from the transaction. A base tax would apply in all cases and its revenues could serve both policy goals described above. An additional tax could be levied against investment gains, with the money raised financing a pain on an equal basis. Simply because someone has cashed out before discovery or received proceeds for years, which are traceable to other Ponzi victim investments, should not allow them to have less pain than those who have received back little or nothing from the Ponzi schemer.”). 221 See, e.g., Edmund Conway, Joseph Stiglitz Calls for Tobin Tax on All Financial Trading Transactions, TELEGRAPH (Oct. 5, 2009), http://www.telegraph.co.uk/ finance/financialcrisis/6262242/Joseph-Stiglitz-calls-for-Tobin-tax-on-all-financial-tradingtransactions.html; Carsten Volkery, Euro Zone Split over Financial Transaction Tax, DER SPIEGEL (Mar. 13, 2012), http://www.spiegel.de/international/europe/ 0,1518,820965,00.html. 222 See, e.g., Volkery, supra note 221. The G20 had debated, but failed to agree upon, an FTT at its September 2009 meeting. 223 Id. 224 See, e.g., Paul Krugman, Taxing the Speculators, N.Y. TIMES, Nov. 27, 2009, at A39. 225 Thus, a bill was introduced in the House entitled, “H.R. 4191: Let Wall Street Pay for the Restoration of Main Street Act of 2009.” H.R. 4191, 111th Cong. § 1 (2009). 2012] RIGHTING OTHERS’ WRONGS 63 fraud victim compensation fund. In this way, the added tax would affirm the moral equivalence between the innocent winners and losers in financial transactions, as well as the moral equivalence between the innocent winners of a fraudulent scheme and the innocent winners of a legitimate one. A second option, which could be implemented in addition to, or instead of, the varying rate FTT, would be to answer the calls to raise the capital gains tax226 and to devote some of the revenue garnered from the tax increase to a fraud compensation fund. Here, too, the measure would recognize that, from the perspective of the innocent investor, it may be purely a matter of luck whether her investment dollars landed in a legitimate investment vehicle or a fraudulent one. The money set aside for fraud compensation—whether funded through an FTT, an increase in the capital gains tax, or both—would operate as a second tier of relief, after money garnered from the fraudster and her associates had been exhausted. Thus, trustees would still be needed in the wake of a fraud in order to identify those with a culpable connection to the fraud, to pursue clawbacks and punitive damages against them, and to ferret out claimants who knew or should have known about the fraud. Yet since either scheme would remove the need to seek clawbacks from innocent investors, the fund’s administration would be far more streamlined, and innocent winners would save a significant amount of money that they currently devote to defending themselves in clawback suits. While the foregoing proposal paints in broad strokes and many of the details remain to be worked out, it does suggest that ready solutions exist for ensuring that victims of fraud receive redress. More to the point, the proposed initiatives would appropriately distribute the burdens of restitution to all of those who profit from their investments. CONCLUSION Clawback suits against innocent beneficiaries of a fraud can be sustained neither by statute nor by other doctrines. Indeed, these suits are exceptional insofar as they demand that innocent individuals or entities return money they reasonably 226 See, e.g., Eliot Spitzer, The “Romney Rule”: Why Raising Capital Gains Taxes is Morally Right and Economically Wise, SLATE (Feb. 6, 2012, 12:32 PM), http://www.slate.com/articles/news_and_politics/the_best_policy/2012/02/the_romney_rule _raising_capital_gains_taxes_is_both_morally_right_and_good_for_the_economy_.html. 64 BROOKLYN LAW REVIEW [Vol. 78:1 believed was theirs in order to redress another’s wrongdoing. Yet the innocent winners of a fraud are no more responsible for the losers’ losses than is anyone else. Although we should not require that the victims of fraud bear their losses alone, we need not require that restitution derive solely from those who also had the misfortune of choosing the same, fraudulent investment vehicle. The market is a place where fraud may well be ineradicable.227 All those who subject their fates to its whims and who come out ahead as a result should share responsibility to redress the wreckage that fraud inflicts. 227 See, e.g., Elizabeth Warren, Reforming a Corrupt Club, WASH. POST, July 20, 2012, at A19, available at http://www.washingtonpost.com/opinions/elizabethwarren-libor-fraud-exposes-a-rotten-financial-system/2012/07/19/gJQAvDnDwW_ story.html; Felix Salmon, Why Finance Can’t Be Fixed with Better Regulation, REUTERS BLOG (July 23, 2012), available at 2012 WLNR 15675134. Rescuing Dignitary Torts from the Constitution Cristina Carmody Tilley† INTRODUCTION Modern First Amendment doctrine is often celebrated for its unflinching protection of speakers—both institutional and individual—who are sued for injuries their words inflict. But the past fifty years of robust Speech and Press Clause jurisprudence threatens to eliminate the rights of individuals seeking recourse for dignitary injuries imposed by speakers. That result is normatively inconsistent with social values in even the earliest legal systems. It dismantles a socially agreed convention for peaceful resolution of interpersonal disputes, which is crucial to the prevention of violent self-help in American society and one of the key functions of intentional tort law. Most important, it is not mandated by the text of the Constitution itself. This article begins by orienting the besieged dignitary torts—defamation, invasion of privacy, and intentional infliction of emotional distress (IIED)—within a theory of tort law that justifies the provision of a state-sanctioned forum for adjudication of private disputes. While loss-shifting and accident regulation theories have little to offer when evaluating the dignitary torts, which are by definition intentional and not mere accidents, a recent version of the corrective justice theory of torts—civil recourse—suggests that a tort forum is crucial for injuries to personality in a way that might not be true for injuries to property or body. The article then documents the threat to this forum posed by the Supreme Court’s imposition of a tort-diminishing theory of the First Amendment from 1964 to the present. The article suggests that if the Court’s free † Visiting Assistant Professor of Law, Northwestern University School of Law; J.D., Northwestern University School of Law, 1999. Thanks to Andrew Koppelman, Martin Redish, and Marshall Shapo for helpful comments on early drafts of this piece. 65 66 BROOKLYN LAW REVIEW [Vol. 78:1 speech doctrine continues on its current trajectory, it will force the abolition of these torts, in practice if not in theory. However, interposition of the Ninth Amendment, which prohibits construction of the First Amendment to disparage rights “retained by the people,” gives the dignitary torts a foothold within the structure of the Constitution. If the dignitary torts have arguable parity with the First Amendment, then courts are not bound by the Constitutional text to vault speech rights over the right to sue for dignitary injuries and therefore must account for those dignitary rights when analyzing the scope of any First Amendment immunity from common-law liability. Various Ninth Amendment theories suggest that the set of rights “retained” by the people can be filled with natural rights, with rights that are a part of Western law “history and tradition,” with state rights recognized at the time of the American founding, or with state rights developed consistent with constitutional jurisprudence after the founding. This article documents the historical development of the dignitary torts in order to evaluate whether they fit within any of the theories of “retained rights” under the Ninth Amendment. Defamation, invasion of privacy, and intentional infliction of emotional distress were recognized obliquely in Greek law and were recognized explicitly as a monolithic cause of action in Roman law. Indeed, the provision of a state-sponsored forum for vindicating the dignitary interests invaded by these wrongs coincided with the decline in violence in these societies. Even after the fall of Rome, independent sovereign states in Europe and their colonies in North America continued to recognize the dignitary torts, albeit more distinctly in some legal systems than in others. By the time of the American founding, defamation was explicitly embraced by the common law of the states. Moreover, protection of privacy and emotional tranquility interests were often smuggled into the pre-ratification common law in the guise of defamation actions. In addition, after ratification, these dignitary torts developed more fully into freestanding causes of action. At the turn of the century, invasion of privacy had begun to evolve into an acknowledged tort, and by the mid-twentieth century, courts began to embrace IIED. This created a fullbodied common law of dignitary torts well before the Court’s expansion of the First Amendment into the dignitary torts arena, starting in 1964. Thus, the article argues that defamation, invasion of privacy, and intentional infliction are entitled to constitutional respect and are protected by the Ninth Amendment from intraconstitutional diminishment. A 2012] RESCUING DIGNITARY TORTS 67 failure to reassert the dignitary torts within the constitutional framework, the article concludes, undervalues the prudential benefits derived from giving victims of dignitary injury a peaceful forum for seeking recourse. A return to self-help— whether in the form of extrinsic violence or suicide—is a distinct possibility if the dignitary torts continue to languish within the constitutional scheme. Placing these torts on firm constitutional footing is necessary to protecting “the whole man.”1 After discussing the significance of the dignitary torts in Part I and summarizing the history of the Court’s increasingly dismissive treatment of these causes of action in Part II, the article suggests in Part III that the torts can be rescued from irrelevance by applying the Ninth Amendment as a rule of construction that governs conflicts between enumerated rights and unenumerated but retained rights. This rule would only apply to the rights protected by the dignitary torts if they are reasonably described as “rights retained” whose constitutional status is provided for by the Ninth Amendment. The article outlines four Ninth Amendment theories for filling the “rights retained”—natural-law rights, rights enshrined in Western legal tradition, state-law rights existing at the time of ratification, and state-law rights developed post-ratification. What follows in Part IV is a brief history of the torts within Western law, from Rome through England and the colonial and modern American periods. This timeline serves as the basis for determining whether reputation, privacy, and emotional tranquility are properly described as rights retained. The article concludes that these rights were retained under any of the four theories and consequently do not automatically lose out to the enumerated free speech right when the two clash. Finally, Part V of the article proposes a test—borrowed from choice of law theory—that could guide courts when deciding which of the two conflicting rights, enumerated or unenumerated-but-retained, should take priority in a given circumstance. The “comparative impairment” test would examine the internal and external effects of the competing legal regimes—here, speech protection and dignity protection—and select the one whose external application would least impair the internal effect of its competitor. This test guarantees that the interests served by each law would be methodically evaluated within a given set of 1 Robert C. Post, The Social Foundations of Defamation Law: Reputation and the Constitution, 74 CALIF. L. REV. 691, 700 (1986) [hereinafter Post, Defamation] (quoting anthropologist John Davis). 68 BROOKLYN LAW REVIEW [Vol. 78:1 facts, and that neither would be gratuitously disparaged in contravention of the Ninth Amendment’s rule of construction. I. THE SIGNIFICANCE OF THE DIGNITARY TORTS Though a mainstay of American law, scholars cannot seem to agree why we have torts.2 Three theories of the purpose of tort are in the fore today: first, the theory that tort exists to provide compensation for accidental injuries; second, that it exists to manage and shift risk; and third, that it provides individual corrective justice. Without delving too deeply into any of these theories, it is easy to conclude that while the first two may be legitimate descriptions of the rationale for negligence law, which by definition involves inadequate care in response to risk, they do not explain why we allow victims of intentional torts to recover. As some torts experts have observed, intentional torts such as defamation and invasion of privacy have “nothing to do with” negligence law.3 This article’s concern is limited to the dignitary torts which are a subset of intentional torts. The only one of the current theories that takes adequate account of intentional torts is the corrective justice model. This may explain why the Supreme Court has undervalued the dignitary torts when weighed against speech. Throughout the 1900s, scholars grew disenchanted with the theory that tort was designed to dole out individual justice—a theory based on the view that the state had to monopolize violence in order to prevent private attacks when individuals felt their rights had been violated.4 The corrective justice theory of torts has experienced a renaissance in the past decade, with one gloss on the concept— civil recourse theory—taking a leading role. But whether the idea of corrective justice is in vogue or not, it is worth examining why scholars are so willing to discard as a rationale for torts, or at least for the intentional dignitary torts, an idea that they substitute for private vengeance. That theory seems uniquely suited, and indeed crucial, for the dignitary torts. The modern disdain among some scholars for the “vengeance prevention” function of tort law seems to reflect 2 See John C.P. Goldberg & Benjamin C. Zipursky, Torts as Wrongs, 88 TEX. L. REV. 917, 923-28 (2010); Jason M. Solomon, Equal Accountability Through Tort Law, 103 NW. U. L. REV. 1765, 1772 (2009). 3 Goldberg & Zipursky, supra note 2, at 977. 4 See Solomon, supra note 2, at 1772. 2012] RESCUING DIGNITARY TORTS 69 contempt for the feudal societies that responded to private warfare with a state-sponsored alternative.5 That function, they suggest, has little purchase in a contemporary society more concerned with allocating the cost of accidents than with preventing already diminishing interpersonal violence.6 This skepticism does not extend as obviously, however, to the intentional dignitary torts of defamation, invasion of privacy, and intentional infliction of emotional distress. The behavior underlying these torts does more than inflict property damage or even physical injury that the modern man is expected to rationally commodify. Instead, it invades an individual’s sense of worth and dignity, important values in a relational society.7 As one sociologist has said, each “individual must rely on others to complete the picture of him of which he himself is allowed to paint only certain parts.”8 Thus, violations of the dignitary interest are the least susceptible to rational response and the most ripe for a state-sponsored diversion of vengeful impulses. Scholars have taken up two camps in treating the relationship between defamation, invasion of privacy, and intentional infliction. Some insist that each of the torts serves different interests that dictate different substantive requirements and distinct legal treatment.9 Others suggest that 5 See id. at 1781. See id. 7 “[I]ndividual personality [is] constituted in significant aspects by the observance of rules of deference and demeanor . . . . Violation of these rules can thus damage a person by discrediting his identity and injuring his personality. Breaking the ‘chain of ceremony’ can deny an individual the capacity to become ‘a complete man . . . .’” Robert C. Post, The Social Foundations of Privacy: Community and Self in the Common Law Tort, 77 CALIF. L. REV. 957, 963 (1989) [hereinafter Post, Privacy] (quoting Erving Goffman, The Nature of Deference and Demeanor, in INTERACTION RITUAL: ESSAYS ON FACE-TO-FACE BEHAVIOR 47, 51 (1967) [hereinafter Goffman, Deference]). Post has observed that despite efforts to distinguish the elements of privacy and IIED torts, “the boundary between the two . . . is obscured . . . [because] the common law . . . is primarily interested in maintaining the forms of respect deemed essential for social life” regardless of what they are called. Id. at 971. 8 Id. at 962-63 (citing Goffman, supra note 7, at 47). 9 The “separatists” identify wholly distinct interests underlying the torts. For instance, Robert Post explains that the interest underlying defamation is protection of “reputation,” whereas the interest underlying invasion of privacy is protection of “emotions.” Post, Privacy, supra note 7, at 958; Post, Defamation, supra note 1, at 691-92. Meanwhile, another scholar defines the right underlying IIED as “the individual’s interest in emotional tranquility,” Daniel Givelber, The Right to Minimum Social Decency and the Limits of Evenhandedness: Intentional Infliction of Emotional Distress by Outrageous Conduct, 82 COLUM. L. REV. 42, 43 (1982), which sounds identical to the interest Post claims to be protected by the privacy tort. Further complicating this effort to neatly cleave the policy goals of the three torts is Post’s view that “reputation” can be conceived of as “property,” “honor,” and “dignity,” at least the latter two of which seem to occupy the same ground as “emotional tranquility.” Post, Defamation, supra note 1, at 693. 6 70 BROOKLYN LAW REVIEW [Vol. 78:1 all three stem from essentially the same social concerns and acknowledge substantial overlap among them.10 Historically, the dignitary torts were treated as a unitary cause of action, protecting a key component of personal security—namely, interests in individual personality.11 The fracturing of this interest into distinct torts has marginalized the underlying interest they protect. Further, it has incented plaintiffs to migrate strategically among the torts depending on which is most hospitable to a particular claim in light of increasing constitutional constraints. Tracing these branches of dignitary tort back to the single trunk they evolved from forces analysts to confront the broad scope and historical pedigree of the interest involved and the extent to which modern law diminishes it. In short, defamation, invasion of privacy, and IIED are treated in American law as separate torts, and courts strive to treat them as doctrinally autonomous. But at the same time, they stem from the same basic underlying basket of social interests, best summarized as “personality” interests, but taking account of reputation, honor, dignity, and emotional tranquility.12 Encroachment on these personal interests continues as a major cause of violence in contemporary America. According to psychologist Steven Pinker, “most of what we call crime is, from the point of view of the perpetrator, the pursuit of justice.”13 According to one well-known statistic, only about onetenth of homicides in the United States are committed to 10 These scholars see the torts as more similar than distinct. As one has summarized, “[T]he torts of libel, invasion of privacy and intentional infliction of emotional distress overlap to a certain degree because all three are aimed either exclusively or in part at redressing mental suffering.” Robert E. Drechsel, Intentional Infliction of Emotional Distress: New Tort Liability for Mass Media, 89 DICK. L. REV. 339, 350 (1985). Early in the development of privacy and IIED law, one early scholar went so far as to suggest that the three should all be melded into a single tort “to constitute a single, integrated system of protecting plaintiff’s peace of mind against acts of the defendant intended to disturb it.” John W. Wade, Defamation and the Right of Privacy, 15 VAND. L. REV. 1093, 1125 (1962). This result would have replicated the approach of the Roman law from centuries ago, where all three torts—defamation, IIED, and invasion of privacy—were recognized and developed under the single heading of iniuria. See infra Part IV.A.2 for a discussion of Roman law and iniurial liability. 11 See infra Part IV.A. 12 Notably, Congress appeared to reach the conclusion that the three torts can in effect be interchangeable, defining “defamation” in its recently passed libel tourism bill to include “forms of speech [that] are false, have caused damage to reputation or emotional distress, have presented any person in a false light, or have resulted in criticism, dishonor or condemnation of any person.” Securing the Protection of Our Enduring and Established Constitutional Heritage (SPEECH) Act, 28 U.S.C.A. § 4101(1) (West 2011). 13 STEVEN PINKER, THE BETTER ANGELS OF OUR NATURE 83 (2011). 2012] RESCUING DIGNITARY TORTS 71 achieve a premeditated goal—such as killing a burglary victim or police officer in order to complete or hide a crime.14 “The most common motives for homicide are moralistic: retaliation after an insult, escalation of a domestic quarrel, punishing an unfaithful or deserting romantic partner, and other acts of jealousy, revenge, and self-defense.”15 Local cultures that draw a wider boundary around personal dignity also see more violence in response to affronts. For instance, according to Pinker, “the American South is marked by . . . a culture of honor[,] . . . [which only sanctions violence as] retaliation after an insult or other mistreatment.”16 Thus, torts whose essence is the affront to personal honor are more likely to incite vengeance. If so, the provision of a state-sponsored forum for resolution as a substitute for that violent self-help remains a legitimate purpose for tort law.17 The dignitary torts, then, are not just or even primarily a means to a money judgment. The availability of a forum for community adjudication of local norms of interpersonal 14 Id. Id. 16 Id. at 99; see also William L. Prosser, Insult and Outrage, 44 CALIF. L. REV. 40, 46 (1956) [hereinafter Prosser, Insult and Outrage] (noting that Mississippi, Virginia, and West Virginia had historically sanctioned “antidueling codes” in an effort to tamp violence that arose from insult). 17 To be sure, failure to provide a state-sponsored forum for vindicating dignitary interests may have other negative consequences, such as a reluctance to run for public office because of the constitutionally mandated forfeiture of self-protective legal recourse by candidates and public officials. On a smaller, but equally antidemocratic, scale, shrinking the dignitary torts may lead even private individuals to opt out of public or private speech that could result in incompensable injuries. For instance, a class of plaintiffs recently challenged Facebook’s practice of transforming pictures and comments of users who “liked” sponsored stories on specific products into “endorsement” ads for the products. Somini Sengupta, So Much for Sharing His “Like,” N.Y. TIMES, June 1, 2012, at A1. To avoid being featured in a potentially embarrassing endorsement, users had to refrain from “liking” a product. Notably, in response to the suit, Facebook initially argued that all such users were “public figures” to their friends. If so, then under the test for defamation liability set forth in New York Times v. Sullivan, 376 U.S. 254 (1964), Facebook would not have been liable for any dignitary torts under current First Amendment law unless it acted with intent or reckless disregard—a complex standard to apply to ads generated by algorithm. Facebook has since settled and is modifying its endorsement practices. Somini Sengupta, To Settle Lawsuit, Facebook Alters Policy for Its Like Button, N.Y. TIMES, June 22, 2012, at B2, available at http://www.nytimes.com/2012/06/22/technology/to-settle-suit-facebook-alters-policies-forlike-button.html. The pre-modification result—discouraging Facebook users from speaking out in favor of a product or issue in order to avoid a dignitary invasion—is a net reduction in speech brought about by precisely the standards in current First Amendment law meant to increase speech. Justice White predicted just this turn of events in his dissent from the majority opinion in Gertz v. Robert Welch, Inc., 418 U.S. 323, 400 (1974) (White, J., dissenting) (“It is not at all inconceivable that virtually unrestrained defamatory remarks about private citizens will discourage them from speaking out and concerning themselves with social problems.”). 15 72 BROOKLYN LAW REVIEW [Vol. 78:1 behavior, and the possibility of public opprobrium against the defendant who invaded the dignity of the plaintiff, is a substantial portion of the recourse provided by this area of law. This is true whether or not money is ultimately awarded. Indeed, one study revealed that many defamation plaintiffs would have accepted an apology from the defendants they eventually sued, and they would have sought money damages only when the defendants refused to express remorse for their actions.18 The Court’s erosion of these torts’ potency, described below, therefore has a significant impact on both the legal treatment of individuals and community control of local norms in American law. II. DIGNITARY TORTS AND THE COURT The past half century of First Amendment development is poised to vitiate the role of the dignitary torts in vindicating personality interests. In the latter half of the twentieth century, the Court handed down a series of opinions that essentially constricted the state common law of defamation in order to accommodate First Amendment speech goals. The first and most celebrated of these cases, New York Times Co. v. Sullivan,19 devised a test to identify the common-law claims that fell under the canopy of First Amendment protection. According to the Court, if the plaintiff was a public official and the speaker published with less than “‘actual malice’ . . . knowledge . . . or reckless disregard” of the likelihood the speech was false, defendant liability is unconstitutional.20 Notably, in Sullivan and subsequent cases, the Court departed from its usual practice of simply invalidating a common-law precept or jury verdict and remanding for further development at the state court level. 18 THE COST OF LIBEL: ECONOMIC AND POLICY IMPLICATIONS 25 (Everette E. Dennis & Eli M. Noam eds., 1989). 19 N.Y. Times Co. v. Sullivan, 376 U.S. 254 (1964). Sullivan on its own did not necessarily spell the trivialization of dignitary interests or the proportionally greater likelihood of resort to self-help developed later in the article, as its scope was limited to suits by public officials. Public officials are among those least likely to batter their attackers. But Justice Scalia’s arguably obscene gesture to a reporter in 2006 and the attack of Rep. Robert Etheridge (D-N.C.) on a camera-wielding protester in 2010 suggest that no class of would-be plaintiff is immune from vengeful impulses. See Justice Scalia’s Under-the-Chin Gesture, NPR.ORG (Mar. 30, 2006), http://www.npr.org/templates/story/story.php?storyId=5312065; Jeff Zeleny, Etheridge, Caught on Video, Apologizes, N.Y. TIMES CAUCUS BLOG (June 14, 2010, 2:20 PM), http://thecaucus.blogs.nytimes.com/2010/06/14/etheridge-caught-on-video-apologizes. Still, Sullivan was the beachhead that led to the current situation. 20 Sullivan, 376 U.S. at 279-88. 2012] RESCUING DIGNITARY TORTS 73 Instead, it repeatedly crafted tort rules of decision to be applied as a matter of constitutional law.21 Thus, “after twenty-five years and twenty-seven [cases] . . . defamation law was effectively disabled, at least in the sphere of public affairs . . . .”22 Specifically, from 1964 until 1991, the Court replaced a system wherein each of the fifty states was free to allow recovery for defamation under its own common law—allocating its own burdens of proof, standards of review, and the like—with a system in which the Constitution ostensibly requires that: To recover for libel or slander, a public official must prove that the defendant acted with actual malice. Elected officials, candidates for public office, and appointed officials who have or appear to the public to have substantial responsibility for or control over governmental affairs must be treated as public officials. The same rules apply to public figures, and anyone who is involved in the resolution of important public questions, or who by reason of his or her fame shapes events in areas of concern to society, is treated as a public figure. To prove actual malice, the plaintiff must show that the defendant knew the defamatory statement was false, or had serious doubts about its truth. That must be shown by clear and convincing proof, and each reviewing court must subject a finding of actual malice to independent review instead of the normal clearly erroneous standard. Private persons who are not public figures but who are defamed in connection with matters of public concern must meet all the preceding requirements in order to recover presumed or punitive damages but may recover for actual injury by showing that the defendant was negligent. All of the preceding types of plaintiffs must bear the burden of proving that the defamatory statement is false. States may not permit recovery for rhetorical hyperbole, statements that cannot be reasonably interpreted as stating actual facts about the plaintiff, or deliberate misquotation that does not materially alter the meaning, and those determinations are to be made as a matter of law rather than left to juries.23 As a result of this constriction, defamation plaintiffs have migrated to other tort theories to vindicate their interests. One 1985 study observed a spike in intentional infliction claims against the media beginning in the 1970s, just as the Court’s drive to “disable” defamation law gained momentum.24 Evidence suggests that, after Sullivan, claims for invasion of privacy also jumped.25 The full-scale diversion of defamation to privacy torts 21 David A. Anderson, First Amendment Limitations on Tort Law, 69 BROOK. L. REV. 755, 784-87 (2004). 22 Id. at 776. 23 Id. at 787-88 (footnotes omitted). 24 Drechsel, supra note 10, at 346. 25 Anderson, supra note 21, at 776-77 (“[A]s long as other tort theories remain available, plaintiffs will try to shift their claims into those . . . categories . . . . A 74 BROOKLYN LAW REVIEW [Vol. 78:1 may have been thwarted by a 1967 holding suggesting that Sullivan applied to privacy claims.26 The Court initiated its overhaul of the dignitary torts by recalibrating defamation, but the movement has gained momentum significantly in recent years as it has begun its assault on IIED. The Court now appears poised to shrink the refuge that IIED provides for dignitary injuries by diminishing the intentional infliction tort, again to accommodate a generous interpretation of First Amendment imperatives. In Hustler v. Falwell,27 the Court determined that public figure IIED plaintiffs cannot recover against defendants when injury is inflicted via publication unless they meet the Sullivan test by proving that something in the publication was false and that the defendant knew or recklessly disregarded the possibility of falsehood.28 The Court explained that standards considered constitutionally uncontroversial throughout the balance of tort law, such as liability premised on the defendant’s bad motive, had to give way in the intentional infliction tort in cases where the injury was inflicted against a public person via speech.29 In 2011, the Court expanded this reasoning. In Snyder v. Phelps,30 it held that even private figures suing non-media speakers for IIED cannot prevail when the speaker inflicts injury with speech on public issues. Importantly, the Court failed to apply even the minimally tort-protective standard it had announced in Falwell, where the actual malice test was imported to IIED claims. Snyder appeared to snuff out any rash of claims for intrusion and related torts in the 1980s and 1990s was widely thought to be the result of the increasing difficulty of recovering for defamation.”); cf. CLARENCE JONES, WINNING WITH THE NEWS MEDIA 359 (2005). 26 Time, Inc. v. Hill, 385 U.S. 374 (1967). Though the Sullivan idea of balancing tort against speech may broadly apply to privacy claims, the use of culpable falsehood as a fulcrum is not an obvious fit for the privacy torts. Although the invasion of privacy in Hill took the form of a “false light” claim where misrepresentation was an element of the tort, accuracy is irrelevant to the three other privacy torts—public disclosure of private facts, right of publicity claims, and invasion of privacy. If falsehood is not an element of a dignitary tort, the speaker’s culpability for circulating false speech has no utility to distinguish between protected and unprotected speech. 27 Hustler Magazine, Inc. v. Falwell, 485 U.S. 46 (1988). As in Hill, using the culpability for falsehood to distinguish between protected and unprotected speech in the IIED context is a clumsy tool. Although the speech in Hustler was untrue satire and thus susceptible to a Sullivan test, much IIED speech, such as creditor threats or disrespect of the dead, will be injurious but not necessarily false. In those cases, the test does not help distinguish between speech that merits First Amendment protection and speech that is unprotected. 28 Falwell, 485 U.S. at 56. 29 Id. at 53. 30 Snyder v. Phelps, 131 S. Ct. 1207 (2011). 2012] RESCUING DIGNITARY TORTS 75 tort–speech balance by neglecting the actual malice test altogether. The speech at issue in Snyder was a funeral protest with picket signs that arguably suggested, among other things, that the deceased was a homosexual.31 The protestors presumably circulated this false statement of fact knowingly or recklessly. The Court did not apply the Sullivan actual malice rule—which was adapted to IIED in Falwell—to permit recovery despite the fact that the protestors’ speech arguably contained knowing falsehoods about a private person.32 Justice Breyer, in his concurrence, described the case’s stark conceptual choice as a clash between First Amendment values and the state interest in protecting its citizens via common-law tort.33 As Breyer summarized, the Court concluded that the speech interest in the case trumped the individual emotional interest without using the actual malice test.34 The Court’s silence on actual malice in the Snyder case amounted to a facial decision that speech trumps tort regardless of the precise speech or activity involved—a decision that takes the Court even further down the anti-tort path it staked out in 1964. Writing several years before Snyder, David Anderson predicted that if the First Amendment were interpreted to require that tort law impose absolutely no burdens on truthful speech touching a matter of public concern, the eventual result 31 Id. at 1225 (Alito, J., dissenting). Some of the other signs, held aloft near the church funeral for deceased soldier Matthew Snyder, read “God Hates You,” “You’re Going to Hell,” and “Thank God for Dead Soldiers.” Snyder’s father, the plaintiff, claimed that the signs and the consequent news coverage resulted in his depression and physical illness, and prevented him from recalling his son without thinking of the picketers. Id. at 1213-14 (majority opinion). 32 To be sure, application of the actual malice rule in Snyder might have resulted in a finding that the speech interest was weightier than the dignitary interest represented by the tort. In fact, the outcome of the case is consistent with this reasoning. What is notable, however, is the Court’s neglect of the standard and its automatic assumption that speech trumped tort without any analytical consideration of the competing interests. See Snyder, 131 S. Ct. at 1219-20 (“What Westboro said, in the whole context of how and where it chose to say it, is entitled to ‘special protection’ under the First Amendment, and that protection cannot be overcome by a jury finding that the [speech] was outrageous. . . . As a Nation we have chosen . . . to protect even hurtful speech on public issues . . . .”). 33 Id. at 1221-22 (Breyer, J., concurring). 34 Id. at 1221; see also Benjamin C. Zipursky, Snyder v. Phelps, Outrageousness, and the Open Texture of Tort Law, 60 DEPAUL L. REV. 473, 490 (2011) (discussing the benefits of applying the actual malice test to both public and private figures suing for IIED inflicted via speech on matters of public concern, citing Eugene Volokh’s argument along these lines found, inter alia, at Eugene Volokh, Freedom of Speech and the Intentional Infliction of Emotional Distress Tort, 2010 CARDOZO L. REV. DE NOVO 300, 304 (2010)). 76 BROOKLYN LAW REVIEW [Vol. 78:1 would be abolition of “tort liability . . . arising from that category of speech.”35 Snyder seems to make good on that prediction. Comparing the status of state common-law torts prior to Sullivan and post-Snyder leads to one conclusion: the Court is steadily shrinking the province of tort law that protects dignitary interests and inversely expanding the reach of First Amendment speech protections. III. THE CONSTITUTIONAL BASIS FOR HONORING DIGNITARY TORTS The First Amendment’s encroachment upon the dignitary torts is often justified by observing that, although the basket of dignitary interests is valuable as a matter of social policy, the Framers drafted a Constitution that vaults speech above those interests.36 The resolution of the dignity-versus-speech question may, however, require more than facile recourse to the First Amendment. The Framers constructed a preemptive textual counterweight to the First Amendment in the Ninth Amendment, which prohibits the denial or disparagement of “rights retained by the people” in favor of rights enumerated in the Constitution.37 Several theories of the Ninth Amendment 35 Anderson, supra note 21, at 777. See, e.g., Snyder, 131 S. Ct. at 1220 (“[W]e cannot . . . punish[] . . . the speaker. As a Nation we have chosen . . . to protect even hurtful speech on public issues to ensure that we do not stifle public debate.” (emphasis added)). 37 U.S. CONST. amend. IX. The Ninth is the only explicit repository for these rights. But the document as a whole reinforces the view that the dignitary torts are not shut out of its scope. First, as many have observed, the Ninth and Tenth Amendments can be said to work in tandem, with the Ninth specifying that the people retained the set of unenumerated rights and the Tenth giving them the right to “confer powers upon their state governmental agents” in furtherance of those rights, among other ends. CALVIN MASSEY, SILENT RIGHTS: THE NINTH AMENDMENT AND THE CONSTITUTION’S UNENUMERATED RIGHTS 107 (1995); see also Rosenblatt v. Baer, 383 U.S. 75, 92 (1966) (Stewart, J., concurring) (observing that the Ninth and Tenth Amendments together recognize the value of individual dignity and the role of the states in providing a forum for its vindication). Second, both the original public understanding of the First Amendment and several normative theories of free expression suggest that the First Amendment, on its own terms, accounts for dignitary interests. For instance, many contemporaneous accounts of the adoption of the First Amendment suggest that its primary goal was to thwart central government efforts to restrain speech via criminal libel statutes or licensing schemes, see, e.g., Mark P. Denbeaux, The First Word of the First Amendment, 80 NW. U. L. REV. 1156, 1176 (1986), not to thwart individual citizens seeking recourse from other individuals whose words injured them, with a community cross-section of jurors setting intracommunity norms as to the reasonableness of particular types of speech. The existence of defamation actions at the time the First Amendment was adopted is often seen as “freezing” the balance between 36 2012] RESCUING DIGNITARY TORTS 77 suggest that the rights protected by the dignitary torts may be among those “retained by the people” and thus shielded from disparagement relative to those enumerated in the Constitution. The Ninth Amendment is often derided as no more than a “punchline”38 or an “inkblot,”39 and the Supreme Court has not relied on it as the basis for any line of decisions.40 Still, constitutional scholars seem convinced that it must stand for something, and they have focused for the past two decades on various theories that would give it meaning.41 Most of these theories suggest that “rights retained” have status as independent constitutional rights, thus playing the same judicially enforceable “oversight” role with regard to state or federal law as do the enumerated constitutional rights.42 If these theories are correct, the composition of “rights retained” is crucial and politically charged, since these rights could serve as the basis for striking down legislation. Perhaps because the stakes under these theories are so high, and because scholars of different political camps are wary of ceding policy ground, there speech and reputation as it stood at the time of ratification. See id. Moreover, even modern First Amendment theory suggests a place for the dignitary rights as a subset of expressive rights. For example, to the extent that the purpose of the First Amendment is to foster “self-realization,” via “individual choice and intellectual development,” that purpose is served by allowing individuals to vindicate privacy rights absent which they might not engage in particular intellectual endeavors. See, e.g., MARTIN H. REDISH, FREEDOM OF EXPRESSION: A CRITICAL ANALYSIS 5 (1984). The same protection for privacy can be derived from, among others, a “liberty model” of free speech, where expression is protected if it “defines, develops, or expresses the self.” See id. at 49 (internal quotation marks omitted) (discussing the work of Edwin Baker). As one writer has summarized, “the same principles that underlie freedom of expression also give rise to other rights, such as personal security, privacy [and] reputation.” Steven J. Heyman, Righting the Balance: An Inquiry into the Foundations and Limits of Freedom of Expression, 78 B.U. L. REV. 1275, 1280 (1998). In short, the Ninth Amendment argument for acknowledging the rights represented by the dignitary torts is not a constitutional outlier, but in fact is consistent with the document read as a whole. 38 Jeffrey Jackson, The Modalities of the Ninth Amendment: Ways of Thinking about Unenumerated Rights Inspired by Philip Bobbitt’s Constitutional Fate, 75 MISS. L.J. 495, 496 n.1 (2006) [hereinafter Jackson, Modalities]. 39 Ryan C. Williams, The Ninth Amendment as a Rule of Construction, 111 COLUM. L. REV. 498, 500 & n.1 (2011). 40 Jackson, Modalities, supra note 38, at 496. 41 See KURT LASH, THE LOST HISTORY OF THE NINTH AMENDMENT 304-05 (2009) (explaining that Justice Reed suggested in United Public Workers of America (CIO) v. Mitchell, 330 U.S. 75 (1947), that the amendment merely reinforced the idea that the states retained all powers not enumerated in the Constitution, not that it identified independent rights that could be asserted to contest the exercise of a federal power). More recently, leading theorists have taken different views, such as Randy Barnett’s position that the amendment is a freestanding source of individual rights, and Kurt Lash’s contention that it is a limitation on federal government power to override “the people’s” right to local self-government. Williams, supra note 39, at 50608 & n.41 (outlining these and other well-known theories). 42 Williams, supra note 39, at 505-06. 78 BROOKLYN LAW REVIEW [Vol. 78:1 has been little agreement as to the content of the “rights retained.”43 In recent years, a more modest theory of the Ninth Amendment has emerged. That theory holds that the provision is not an independent source of constitutional rights but rather a rule of construction that governs when unenumerated-butretained rights clash with enumerated rights.44 The retained rights are not judicially enforceable in the sense that they can be used to strike down popular legislation. Instead, the Ninth Amendment directs that retained rights cannot be assigned categorical secondclass status when they conflict with enumerated rights. Courts need not “enforce” retained rights as they would enumerated rights, but their interpretation of enumerated rights must not automatically crowd out the rights retained.45 Although this theory does not create a new class of judicially enforceable constitutional rights, it still requires identification of the rights “retained” under the Amendment. The underlying proposals for filling out the set of “rights retained” are identical regardless of the structural role assigned to them under the different Ninth Amendment theories. Four such theories have been identified in Ninth Amendment literature: “natural-law” rights as originally publicly understood by the Framers; rights deemed “natural” by virtue of their deep roots in Western and American legal 43 Id. This development is not surprising, given that the revival in Ninth Amendment interest followed Justice Goldberg’s concurrence in Griswold v. Connecticut, 381 U.S. 479, 486 (1965) (Justice Goldberg pointed to the Ninth Amendment as a source of judicial authority to enforce “fundamental” individual rights infringed by state laws, such as Connecticut’s ban on birth control.). Not only did Goldberg propose a potent role for the Ninth Amendment, but he did it in a case fraught with controversial policy implications. Among the general structural theories of the Ninth Amendment are those suggesting that it merely reaffirms the limitations on federal government powers by barring the implication that carving out individual rights in the Bill of Rights allowed expansion of federal power anywhere beyond the carve-out, see, e.g., Laurence Claus, Protecting Rights from Rights: Enumeration, Disparagement, and the Ninth Amendment, 79 NOTRE DAME L. REV. 585, 587-88 (2004), and those reaching the opposite conclusion that the language reserves space for the expansion of individual constitutional rights protected from federal government reach, see Williams, supra note 39, at 505-06. 44 Claus, supra note 43, at 592. Other rules of construction have also been suggested, including a rule that non-enumeration does not foreclose the position that a right may be within an enumerated right, see, e.g., MASSEY, supra note 37, at 11 (summarizing the view of Laurence Tribe), or that retained rights are not elevated to a constitutional level, but keep the same status they had historically regardless of the fact that some other rights were enumerated within the Constitution, see, e.g., Williams, supra note 39, at 530. 45 Claus, supra note 43, at 617-18. 2012] RESCUING DIGNITARY TORTS 79 tradition; state-law rights at the time of ratification; and statelaw rights post-ratification. A. Natural-Law Rights as Originally Publicly Understood by the Framers The “natural-law rights” theory of the Ninth Amendment suggests that any right understood at the time of ratification to belong to individuals, as distinct from rights derived from membership in a centrally governed society, was among those “‘rights retained’ by the people.”46 The Ninth Amendment’s use of the phrase “rights retained” is “the language of Lockean social compact theory.”47 Under Lockean theory, all human beings have rights in the state of nature, including the right to “ownership of one’s own body and the product of one’s labors, [as well as] . . . the right to use violence . . . [in retaliation when] others” violate those natural rights.48 The delegates to the Constitutional Convention, in drawing a constitution, decided which “natural rights” to relinquish to a central government to achieve a “common good,” and which to retain.49 Examples of such retained rights might be the right to travel, the right to pursue a job, the right to selfdefense, or even, as some of the Framers joked during debates over ratifying the Bill of Rights, “the right to wear a hat, and to go to bed when one pleases.”50 Notably, the founding generation viewed individual rights and government powers as mutually exclusive; that is, “rights began where powers ended, and 46 Jeffrey Jackson, Blackstone’s Ninth Amendment: A Historical Common Law Baseline for the Interpretation of Unenumerated Rights, 62 OKLA. L. REV. 167, 170-71 (2010) [hereinafter Jackson, Blackstone]. 47 Michael W. McConnell, The Ninth Amendment in Light of Text and History, 2009-2010 CATO SUP. CT. REV. 13, 15 (2010). 48 Id. at 16. 49 Id. at 15-16 (quoting Brutus, On the Lack of a Bill of Rights, in THE COMPLETE FEDERALIST AND ANTI-FEDERALIST PAPERS 749, 750 (2009), and explaining that some natural rights were relinquished to the central government, while others were retained by individuals). 50 Id. at 17-18. Notably, some have suggested that the Ninth Amendment also protects the right of citizens to collectively adopt state and local policies. Id. at 17 n.17 (citing Kurt Lash, A Textual-Historical Theory of the Ninth Amendment, 60 STAN. L. REV. 895 (2008)). This view of the Ninth Amendment is one reason it is often paired with the Tenth, which seems to protect the rights of “the people” as a collective entity. LASH, supra note 41, at 90. To the extent that dignitary torts are creatures of state statute or common law, they may also be considered within the protections offered by the Tenth Amendment as well as the Ninth. See, e.g., MASSEY, supra note 37, at 75 (explaining that both amendments stemmed from a single original proposal, which simultaneously shielded rights and limited federal government powers). 80 BROOKLYN LAW REVIEW [Vol. 78:1 powers began where rights ended.”51 The failure to grant government a power necessarily implied that the inverse individual right was retained, so that rights need not be explicitly enumerated in the constitutional text. But once enumeration of rights within the Bill of Rights became inevitable, it became obvious that the Framers could not enumerate every right they might wish individuals to retain. The Ninth Amendment is viewed by some as a solution to the necessarily incomplete enumeration given in the Bill of Rights, serving as a general placeholder for natural-law rights that the Framers did not intend to relinquish but had not thought specifically to enumerate.52 Thus, if dignitary rights were among the natural-law rights designed to be “retained” by the Framers, they fit within the Ninth Amendment rule of construction and need not take a back seat to enumerated rights. The Framers looked to two primary sources to determine the scope of naturallaw rights: the theories of John Locke and the English constitutional and common law as found within Blackstone’s Commentaries.53 Those theories are discussed in the historical review of the dignitary torts given in Part IV. B. Rights Embedded in Western Legal Tradition A broader and less well-developed version of the “natural-law” theory of rights retained contends that they are those within the “history and traditions of our national 51 MASSEY, supra note 37, at 67. This perspective is vastly different from the modern view, which tends to view rights as “trumping governmental powers.” Id. One reason that the values underlying dignitary torts have so withered may be that tort law evolved from a system designed to vindicate “rights” to one designed to manipulate “interests” to achieve efficient policy ends. Thus, tort law values were “rights” at the time of the founding, capable of exerting equal and opposite pressure on the enumerated “right” of free speech. By the time of Sullivan, however, tort law values were mere “interests” to be achieved by the use of state government power, which would be trumped by the free speech “right” inherent in the First Amendment. See, e.g., Kenneth J. Vandevelde, A History of Prima Facie Tort: The Origins of a General Theory of Intentional Tort, 19 HOFSTRA L. REV. 447, 456-62 (1990) (summarizing the struggle between two leading American torts scholars, Thomas Cooley and Oliver Wendell Holmes, where Cooley aligned with Blackstone in advocating that tort law was “a series of remedies for invasions of . . . rights,” while Holmes argued that tort liability is a function of “public policy, rather than subjective moral fault.”). Steven Heyman has observed that when the First Amendment was adopted, free speech rights were part of a natural-law fabric, and thus were considered “bounded by the rights of others,” so that government was obliged not just to protect speech but to “ensure that this liberty was not used to violate other fundamental rights.” Heyman, supra note 37, at 1279. 52 MASSEY, supra note 37, at 70-74. 53 Jackson, Blackstone, supra note 46, at 171. 2012] RESCUING DIGNITARY TORTS 81 experience.”54 A “historical” view of retained rights does not depend on “the absence []or presence of positive law bearing upon a particular claimed right,” but instead requires a longitudinal examination of the “traditions from which [American law] developed as well as the traditions from which it broke,” and their ongoing evolution.55 Part IV provides a detailed historical examination of the Western legal traditions from which American law developed, documenting their deepseated roots and historical status, from Greek and Roman law through Anglo-Saxon and English common law. C. State Rights—at Ratification and After Ratification The “state rights” theory of the Ninth Amendment suggests that the “rights retained” for Ninth Amendment purposes are the rights “derived from state law,” including state constitutions, statutes, and common law.56 Some versions of the “state rights” view suggest that the relevant rights are those that were in existence at the time of ratification.57 Others, in contrast, suggest that rights recognized or created by the states after ratification come within the “rights retained” umbrella so long as they were not unconstitutional when adopted.58 As one article has summarized, under the “state rights” theory, “the ninth amendment . . . preserves rights existing under state laws already ‘on the books’ in 1791 plus those rights which the states would thereafter see fit to enact.”59 The development of the American law of dignitary torts within state constitutions, statutes, and common law is traced in Part IV below.60 Under any of these plausible theories of the Ninth Amendment,61 the evisceration of the dignitary torts becomes a 54 Calvin R. Massey, The Natural Law Component of the Ninth Amendment, 61 U. CIN. L. REV. 49, 100 (1992). 55 Id. at 100-01. 56 Russell L. Caplan, The History and Meaning of the Ninth Amendment, 69 VA. L. REV. 223, 259 (1983). 57 Id. at 248; Claus, supra note 43, at 595, 620-21. 58 Claus, supra note 43, at 595, 620-21. 59 Caplan, supra note 56, at 248, 263. 60 See infra Part IV.B. 61 These models by no means exhaust the various approaches taken to define the “rights retained” by the people in the Ninth Amendment. Others include the residual rights theory, the collective rights model, and the federalism model. See, e.g., Randy Barnett, The Ninth Amendment: It Means What It Says, 85 TEX. L. REV. 1, 11-21 (2006) (summarizing theories). It is beyond the scope of this article to test the dignitary torts within each of these models; the point of the article is that recourse to the First 82 BROOKLYN LAW REVIEW [Vol. 78:1 more complicated constitutional matter than mere application of the First Amendment. It requires an assessment of whether the rights protected by the dignitary torts—reputation, dignity, privacy, and emotional tranquility—can be identified as natural-law rights, as rights deeply rooted within Western legal history and tradition, or as state-created rights either in 1791 or at any time between the ratification and the Court’s first assault on the dignitary torts in 1964.62 If so, they must at least be accounted for in the constitutional calculus, even if the ultimate decision is to accord them less weight through a test that “optimal[ly] accommodat[es]” between dignitary and speech interests.63 But if the dignitary interests are accounted for and then balanced, their normative appeal need not be discounted as constitutionally insignificant, which is a tendency that appears throughout the First Amendment cases involving speech torts.64 IV. THE HISTORIC PEDIGREE OF THE DIGNITARY TORTS— ANCIENT AND MODERN Evaluating the status of the personality interests as “rights retained” under any of the foregoing theories requires placing them on a timeline. Only then can one determine whether they are natural rights as understood by the Founders at the time of ratification, rights developed through a longstanding tradition of Western legal culture from which American law developed, rights created by state law at the time of ratification, or rights created by state law postratification. This section briefly recounts the ancestry of each tort within the Western legal tradition underlying American Amendment is not sufficient to justify speech preference every time a speech right clashes with a dignitary right. That the dignitary rights have some constitutional heft within at least some theories of the Ninth Amendment undermines the mechanistic response of those who consistently choose speech by arguing that they have no other constitutional choice. 62 Attempting to draw inviolate lines between these theories is futile, as even scholars in different camps often seem to acknowledge that the ideas overlap and have been used interchangeably. See, e.g., Suzannah Sherry, Natural Law in the States, 61 U. CIN. L. REV. 171, 216 (1992-93) (stating that Eighteenth and early Nineteenth Century American lawyers thought that state constitutions “merely reflect[ed] natural law”). 63 Claus, supra note 43, at 618; see infra notes 193-97, 224 and accompanying text. 64 See, e.g., Snyder v. Phelps, 131 S. Ct. 1207, 1220 (2011); see also Gertz v. Robert Welch, Inc., 418 U.S. 323, 369-72 (1974) (White, J., dissenting at length based on the view that the ongoing constitutionalization of defamation had wiped out the states’ ability to protect reputational interests). For a discussion of Snyder v. Phelps, see Part II, supra notes 30-35 and accompanying text. 2012] RESCUING DIGNITARY TORTS 83 law. The canvass moves from Greek and Roman law, where the torts were originally viewed as a broad unitary cause of action; to Anglo-Saxon law, which also recognized personality interests generally; and finally to the Elizabethan and modern English systems, where more differential treatment was given to these interests, but where courts over time seemed willing to compensate for an infringement on each dignitary interest. A. Ancient Law Western tort law is a direct descendant of the law of delict conceived in ancient Greece and Rome.65 The law of early Greece began to mature before the law of Rome, and the writing of Greek poets and philosophers summarizing Greek legal theory was well known in the Roman world, which developed a sophisticated legal system over several centuries.66 The ancient Greek culture had a significant, if indirect, impact on the development of Western law. 1. Greece Prior to the written codification of law in Greece— commonly registered at 621 BC with the first Greek written legal code, the Code of Draco—evidence of the development of Greek law can be found in works of literature and philosophy, and later in unwritten customary law.67 Even the earliest of these sources reveal that dignitary slights accomplished by speech and conduct were considered ripe for private civil adjudication in large part because they were likely to provoke violence. For instance, the poet Hesiod, who described the norms in existence in the seventh and sixth centuries BC, wrote that slander and libel were considered delicts: “A man owns no better treasure than a prudent tongue; . . . Bad words flung at others bounce back with double strength.”68 Moreover, 65 M. Stuart Madden, The Graeco-Roman Antecedents of Modern Tort Law, 44 BRANDEIS L.J. 865, 909 (2006). 66 Id. at 865. “[A]lthough laws and legal procedures were known in various forms in other parts of the world, the Greeks created something different. For the first time the law was made available to and was intended to be used by the entire citizenry.” MICHAEL GARAGIN, EARLY GREEK LAW 146 (1986). 67 See RUSS VERSTEEG, LAW IN THE ANCIENT WORLD 189, 190 (2002); Madden, supra note 65, at 868-85. 68 Madden, supra note 65, at 871 (quoting HESIOD, Works and Days, in THEOGONY, WORKS AND DAYS, SHIELD, II 370-72, at 74 (Apostolos N. Athanassakis trans., 2d ed. 2004)). 84 BROOKLYN LAW REVIEW [Vol. 78:1 Hesiod’s writing suggests that the Greek notion of slander and libel was not restricted to speech that diminished reputation but also covered speech that inflicted emotional injury, such as gossip: “[I]t is easy to get a bad reputation but hard to live with it and harder to shed it. What is said of you does not vanish, if many say it; such talk is a kind of god.”69 Writing at about 350 BC, Aristotle specified certain wrongs that required an act of court to restore the status quo ante of equality between the injurer and the injured, and among these “violent” wrongs requiring correction were “abuse, [and] insult.”70 The Code of Draco was the first written law promulgated in Athens, but there is little evidence today of its specific provisions.71 What is known is that Draco’s sometimes harsh penalties for prohibited conduct were designed “as a substitute for unrestrained self-help . . . to curb violent conduct, particularly revenge.”72 The later and better-respected Code of Solon, which ameliorated much of the harshness associated with the Draconian code, reflected the value Greek law placed on dignitary interests. First, Solon’s code set a specific penalty for libel, a portion of which went to the victim of the speech and a portion of which was paid to the state.73 It barred “speaking ill of anyone while in a temple, in court at trial, in public offices, or while at festival contests.”74 Moreover, that code did not stop at protecting the reputations of citizens in the community. It also barred libeling the dead, “not on account of injury to the dead, but in respect to the quiet of families” and “the peace and honor of Athens.”75 This text suggests that Greek law did not set up artificial distinctions between the interrelated dignitary interests of reputation, privacy, and emotional tranquility. Instead, it recognized that speech could intrude on more than one of these interests simultaneously because the interests are virtually unitary.76 69 Id. at 871 n.19 (quoting HESIOD, supra note 68, II 760-64, at 83). Id. at 883 (quoting ARISTOTLE, NICOMACHEAN ETHICS, in INTRODUCTION TO ARISTOTLE, bk. V, ch. 2, at 402). 71 VERSTEEG, supra note 67, at 194. 72 Id. at 195. 73 GARAGIN, supra note 66, at 65; VERSTEEG, supra note 67, at 254. 74 VERSTEEG, supra note 67, at 254. 75 Gregory C. Lisby, No Place in the Law: The Ignominy of Criminal Libel in American Jurisprudence, 9 COMM. L. & POL’Y 433, 442-43 (2004) (quoting MARTIN L. NEWELL, THE LAW OF SLANDER AND LIBEL IN CIVIL AND CRIMINAL CASES 5-6 (1914)). 76 Notably, Greek and Roman law were unique at the time in that they set a monetary value for incursions on dignitary interests in order to allow intra-community 70 2012] RESCUING DIGNITARY TORTS 85 Ultimately, Greek law is recognized for developing rigorous systems of thought about the relative rights of individuals and the state, and for establishing the philosophical underpinnings of tort law. But, despite the Solonian codification and the “Reinscription” of the laws of Solon and the homicide law of Draco at the close of the fifth century BC, ancient Greece is not celebrated for an elaboration of these analyses into a practical code applicable to a wide variety of disputes. This milestone was supplied by Rome. 2. Rome Some say that Rome’s greatest legal legacy was the development of private law, a substantial portion of which dealt with delicts.77 One of the three major delicts was iniuria, variously translated as insult or outrage.78 The scope of iniurial liability is sometimes said to capture “injuries less than death to humans.”79 Generally agreed to be found within Table VII of resolution without recourse to violence, rather than characterizing the behavior exclusively as a crime leading to state punishment. Greece did recognize the speech crime “hubris,” which included “abusive and humiliating public assaults.” This was considered difficult to prove because it required proving an “arrogant, self-righteous, irresponsible” state of mind. Lisby, supra note 75, at 441. In essence, Greek law served as a “bridge” between societies that treated similar offenses as crimes subject to statesponsored punishment and the later law of Rome and its Western descendants, which largely treated dignitary affronts as private law matters. Id. For instance, the Babylonian Code of Hammurabi of 1770 BC barred insults to women and false accusations of capital crimes, but punished them by branding and death, respectively. Id. Unlike that system, Greece moved towards the private-law treatment of such offenses, and Rome conclusively treated intra-community injuries inflicted via speech as private law matters, while retaining a criminal response to public speech against civic leaders. Cristina Carmody Tilley, Reviving Slander, 2011 UTAH L. REV. 1025, 1032-40. 77 KATHERINE FISCHER DREW, THE LAWS OF THE SALIAN FRANKS 12 (1991). It is no surprise that tectonic shifts in Roman society led to the creation of the first formal system of private law in Rome. Although kings held power at one time in ancient Rome, the aristocracy was dissatisfied with their rule and deposed them. In their stead, two offices of Consul were established to oversee administrative matters of the state. Plebians, who had been protected from the caprice of the patricians by the monarchy, now found themselves subject to application of the law as devised by those patricians without notice to the lower classes. In response to plebian demands, a committee was appointed to set out all the laws in writing. The result was the Twelve Tables. The tables were “a comprehensive collection or code of rules . . . consist[ing] for the most part of ancient Latin custom, but . . . [incorporating some] rules of Greek Law.” W.W. BUCKLAND, A TEXT-BOOK OF ROMAN LAW FROM AUGUSTUS TO JUSTINIAN 2 (1921). But see ANDREW BORKOWSKI, TEXTBOOK ON ROMAN LAW 26 (1994) (questioning Greek connection). 78 BORKOWSKI, supra note 77, at 303; W.W. BUCKLAND & ARNOLD MCNAIR, ROMAN LAW AND COMMON LAW 295 (1936); BRUCE W. FRIER, A CASEBOOK ON THE ROMAN LAW OF DELICT 177 (1989). 79 ALAN WATSON, STUDIES IN ROMAN PRIVATE LAW 253 (1991). 86 BROOKLYN LAW REVIEW [Vol. 78:1 the Twelve Tables, the provision for iniuria may be translated as follows: If a person has maimed another’s limb, let there be retaliation in kind unless he makes agreement for composition with him. If he has broken or bruised freeman’s bone with hand or club, he shall undergo penalty of 300 pieces; if slave’s, 250. If he has done simple harm [to another], penalties shall be 25 pieces.80 Most scholars agree that when the Twelve Tables were adopted in the fifth century BC, the “simple harm” provision was aimed primarily at minor physical injuries. Rapidly, however, this “catch-all” provision of the iniuria delict was interpreted to include a raft of non-physical injuries to interests described in the literature as “dignity and personal well-being”81 or freedom from “contempt of the personality.”82 As one scholar has summarized, “Iniuria . . . serves to protect the individual by creating a legally defensible perimeter for his or her personal life.”83 Thus, one thousand years later, by the time the Emperor Justinian codified Roman law in the Corpus Juris Civilis, the delict of iniuria as expanded by juristic interpretations and various amendatory edicts was described as: [I]nflicted not only by striking with the fist, a stick, or a whip, but also by vituperation for the purpose of collecting a crowd, or by taking possession of a man’s effects on the ground that he was in one’s debt; or by writing, composing, or publishing defamatory prose or verse, or contriving the doing of any of these things by some one else; or by constantly following a matron, or a young boy or girl below the age of puberty, or attempting anybody’s chastity; and, in a word, by innumerable other acts.84 Examining the fact patterns that led to non-physical iniurial liability, one sees that the category dealt neatly with the behavior underlying the IIED tort of the American system. Iniuria protected corpus, dignitas, and fama, roughly translated as body, dignity, and reputation. The following behavior was all considered iniuria because it violated the dignity interest: (1) behavior defiling dead bodies or estates, such as defacing 80 Id. FRIER, supra note 78, at 177. 82 BUCKLAND, supra note 77, at 585; H.F. JOLOWICZ & BARRY NICHOLAS, HISTORICAL INTRODUCTION TO THE STUDY OF ROMAN LAW 171 (3d ed. 1972). 83 FRIER, supra note 78, at 177. 84 Francis L. Coolidge, Jr., Note, Iniuria in the Corpus Juris Civilis, 50 B.U. L. REV. 271, 272 (1970). 81 2012] RESCUING DIGNITARY TORTS 87 graves;85 (2) harassment relating to one’s financial affairs, such as restricting a person’s access to his property or publicly calling him a debtor;86 (3) overtures upon the chastity of a modest person, such as a public proposition;87 (4) insulting or hurtful speech, including the use of epithets or the incitement of a mob; (5) invasion of privacy, such as interference with a person’s domus, which, roughly translated, means the place where a person’s daily affairs take place;88 and, (6) defamation, which included publishing defamatory prose or verse.89 A short comparison with American tort law shows a remarkably similar cluster of behaviors leading to liability. Early surveys of cases coming under the heading of the “new tort” of intentional infliction of emotional distress in the United States identify the following as classic fact patterns: (1) “the mishandling of dead bodies, whether by mutilation, disinterment, interference with burial, or other forms of intentional disturbance;”90 (2) the tactics of “collecting creditors,”91 which include “violent cursing, abuse and accusations of dishonesty,”92 threatening a lawsuit or arrest, and advertising the debt to family, neighbors, and employers; (3) 85 “[H]itting with stones the statue on the tomb of another’s father, digging up and removing bones or a body buried by someone else not a relative, on one’s land, burying a wealthy dead man without the appropriate expense, . . . [and] injury done to a corpse” were all considered iniuria. CHITTHARANJAN FELIX AMERASINGHE, DEFAMATION AND OTHER ASPECTS OF THE ACTIO INIURIARUM IN ROMAN-DUTCH LAW 330 (1968) (footnotes omitted). 86 For instance, behavior casting doubt on a person’s right to possess property, such as “prevent[ing] the removal of . . . property” or “sealing up the house of an absent debtor” as recourse for implied default, was considered an affront to dignity—an insult that amounted to iniuria. Id. at 327. So were “objecting to a judgment debtor’s retaining any provisions or his bed,” or “addressing a person as one’s debtor when he was not.” Finally, abuse of legal process was considered iniuria. Id. at 327-30. 87 “[D]ebauching [or abducting] a boy under seventeen, . . . soliciting a woman or a girl . . . [for the purpose of sex], indecently accosting or following [a woman or a girl],” attempting to induce adultery, adultery itself and exposing of the genitals to a woman or a girl were all considered iniuria. Id. at 329 (footnotes omitted). 88 Thus, a person need not possess his domus to have a cause of action for iniuria, and even if he did possess a large estate, interference with zones that include outbuildings or stables was not iniuria. Moreover, interference with business premises, if access to those premises was meant to be limited, could be iniuria. Domus-related iniuria seems to have as its “common factor . . . not . . . possession but some form of right to privacy understood in a rather elementary sense.” Id. at 326-27. 89 For instance, shouts, whether alone or in a group, directed at an individual, were considered iniuria. So was the deployment of “foul or obscene” language against an individual. Id. at 330. 90 William L. Prosser, Intentional Infliction of Mental Suffering: A New Tort, 37 MICH. L. REV. 874, 885-86 (1939) (hereinafter Prosser, Intentional Infliction). 91 Id. at 884. 92 Prosser, Insult and Outrage, supra note 16, at 48. 88 BROOKLYN LAW REVIEW [Vol. 78:1 public accusations of unchastity against teenage girls;93 (4) the convening of crowds to raise a disturbance against an individual;94 (5) actions of “[e]victing landlords” who “tear[] up the premises, smok[e] out the tenants, or throw[] the furniture about;” and (6) “oppressive and outrageous conduct, such as verbal or written abuse, vituperation, and threats.”95 Notably, the five classic American IIED patterns align exactly with the Roman iniurial patterns: disrespect for the dead, harassment by creditors, allegations of unchastity, invasions of privacy, and abusive speech.96 The Roman law’s solicitude for these interests of “personality” reflected the momentum away from a tribal society and toward a more complex and civilized social order. The ever more vigilant protection of personality interests was a device to exchange money or public rehabilitation for violent vengeance in order to honor an “unremitting concern with public order.”97 One torts expert has opined that the more sophisticated a society, the more developed will be “legal protection to nonmaterial interests of personality like selfrespect, reputation, and privacy.”98 93 Prosser, Intentional Infliction, supra note 90, at 885. Prosser, Insult and Outrage, supra note 16, at 47, 49. 95 Prosser, Intentional Infliction, supra note 90, at 881. 96 Notably, some behavior that was considered a violation of fama, or reputational, interests, such as the raising of a clamor against a plaintiff or the use of insulting or offensive language, falls within the modern tort of defamation and is similar if not identical to the dignitas violations. Among these behaviors were: calling a person a slave, casting doubts on someone’s modesty, imputing of debt default, and holding a frugal funeral for a wealthy man. AMERASINGHE, supra note 85, at 332. And some speech was considered iniuria as a reputational violation even if it was not thought to assault a person’s dignity, placing it on all fours with the defamation tort. For instance, “composing, publishing or procuring the publication . . . of a defamatory writing,” or any conduct that “excit[ed] odium . . . against anyone,” was considered an incursion upon one’s reputation and therefore iniuria. Id. at 331-32. Similarly, many of the behaviors captured by iniuria, such as violating the domus, or physically shadowing a vulnerable person, would be captured by one of the privacy torts today. In short, Roman iniuria was a flexible cause of action, covering numerous overlapping “personality” interests without attempting to extricate them for distinct legal treatment. 97 FRIER, supra note 78, at 177 (quoting J.G. FLEMING, AN INTRODUCTION TO THE LAW OF TORTS 192 (1985)). See id. at 1 (“Delictual liability is thought to have originated, in archaic Roman law, as a substitute for immediate personal vengeance.”); BUCKLAND, supra note 77, at 571 (“It was in origin a legal substitute for self-help, which in this case meant revenge.”). 98 FRIER, supra note 78, at 177; Cf. Solomon, supra note 2, at 1783-84 (observing that such a forum to avenge interpersonal wrongs may be seen as condoning uncivilized impulses). 94 2012] B. RESCUING DIGNITARY TORTS 89 Modern Law After the fall of Rome, many of the European countries that grew up in its stead took Roman civil law as their foundation. “[I]t is a commonplace with legal historians that Roman law was in course of time made, often in modified form, the basis of large parts of what we have come to call the Civil Law Systems,” observed one legal historian in 1969.99 England, however, which developed a common-law system, did not explicitly incorporate principles of Roman law. Thus, while many civil-law systems in Europe retained the flexible approach to incursions upon dignity, honor, feelings, and reputation,100 England initially peeled off all of the non- 99 THE ROMAN LAW READER 170 (F.H. Lawson ed., 1969). The fact that numerous European and civil-law countries matter-of-factly recognized the dignitary rights in their legal systems reinforces their place as “universal,” “civilized” rights for natural-law purposes, further supporting their Ninth Amendment status as “rights retained.” See, e.g., Sherry, supra note 62, at 204. The iniurial action against outrage and insult largely survived in the civillaw countries that carried forward the Roman system. “[M]any civil code jurisdictions [including Argentina, Austria, Chile, France, Italy, Liberia, Spain, and West Germany], drawing from the Corpus Juris Civilis, have incorporated similar provisions concerning injury into their legal systems.” See Coolidge, supra note 84, at 284. For instance, Roman-Dutch law applied in South Africa and Ceylon “was also concerned with dignitas in general as an interest to be protected” even where reputation was not assailed. AMERASINGHE, supra note 85, at 276. Specifically, the Roman-Dutch cause of action actio iniuriarum considers breaches of contract, where humiliating, to be actionable, as are breaches of promise to marry; public use of abusive language or epithets, see id. at 290; interference with rights such as school access or public honors; wrongs against chastity; unjustified denials of credit; unjustified threats of lawsuit; and interference with tombs or burials. These causes of action correspond directly to Roman iniuria patterns, which also targeted abusive speech, creditor conduct, accusations of unchastity, and disrespect for the dead. In fact, the accepted gulf between private law regulating individual relationships and public law regulating the interaction between the state and the individual emerged in European systems as a direct result of the Roman law example. See Peter E. Quint, Free Speech and Private Law in German Constitutional Theory, 48 MD. L. REV. 247, 255 (1989). Much of the vacuum left by the fall of the Roman Empire was filled by Germanic tribes. By 534, the Franks controlled most of what had been Roman Gaul. The ruler at that time, Clovis, took a distinctly Roman approach to governance. Predictably, within the Frankish codes, great emphasis is placed on dignity, both in terms of reputation and emotional well-being. The Lex Salica of the Franks contains, within the chapter “Concerning Abusive Terms,” seven distinct sections. DREW, supra note 77, at 94. These sections assign penalties for statements that diminish reputation, such as accusations of illicit behavior including pederasty, prostitution, “throwing down [the] shield,” and informing. Id. But they also assign sanctions to statements that reflect ill opinion of a would-be plaintiff and arguably invade the emotional sphere more than the reputational interest, such as claiming that someone “is covered in dung,” or is “a fox” or “a rabbit.” Id. Another chapter sanctions false imputations of indebtedness and baseless repossession. Id. at 115. Finally, as in Roman law, an entire chapter of Frankish law, with seven distinct sections, outlines causes of action for “Despoiling Dead Bodies.” Id. at 118-19. 100 90 BROOKLYN LAW REVIEW [Vol. 78:1 pecuniary dignitary interests as incompensable. It interpreted reputation as a form of property and developed a complex system of defamation law. It ostensibly declined to recognize suits for outrage or insult. In practice, however, it often allowed compensation for these injuries when pleaded as defamation, and Anglo-American courts have recently reintegrated these interests into the common law as freestanding torts. This development is traced below. 1. Common Law and the English Experience The history of the dignitary torts in English common law is far more circuitous than in neighboring civil-law countries.101 England consciously declined to take Roman law as the basis for its system. “We have received Roman law,” explained one historian, “but we have received it in small homeopathic doses, at different periods, and as and when required. It has acted as a tonic to our native legal system, and not as a drug or a poison. When received it has never been continuously developed on Roman lines.”102 Roman law is generally not a source of precedent in English courts.103 Despite this latter-day disavowal, early Anglo-Saxon law appears to have adopted the same broad, flexible approach found in Roman law. Arising from “customary or traditional material” in these cultures, codes promulgated by Anglo-Saxon Given these strong legal protections for dignitary interests encompassing reputation, honor, and emotional well-being, it is no surprise that modern German law is extremely protective of personality interests. Not only does the German Civil Code allow individuals to seek a remedy from “a person who ‘intentionally causes injury to another person in a manner contrary to good morals,’” Quint, supra, at 253, but the country’s 1949 Constitution, known as the Basic Law, recognizes the rights of individuals to “[h]uman dignity,” and “the free development of [their] personality,” often thought to include a right to privacy. Id. at 257, 299. In fact, the German Federal Constitutional Court, designed primarily to address constitutional questions, has wrestled with “the permanent state of tension” arising from the conflict between the cultural acceptance of the Civil Code and the occasionally conflicting dictates of the Basic Law. Id. at 290; see also Melius de Villiers, The Roman Law of Defamation, 34 L.Q. REV. 412, 418 (1918). A similar tension has been replicated in the European Convention on Human Rights, Article 10, which protects freedom of expression, and Article 8, which protects individual privacy. See, e.g., Jessica Hodgson, What Articles 8 and 10 of the European Convention on Human Rights Mean, GUARDIAN (Mar. 27, 2002, 8:54 AM), http://www.guardian.co.uk/media/2002/mar/27/pressandpublishing.privacy4. 101 See supra note 100. 102 THE ROMAN LAW READER, supra note 99, at 206 (quoting W.S. HOLDSWORTH, HISTORY OF ENGLISH LAW IV 293 (1924)). 103 Id. at 215. But see BILL GRIFFITHS, AN INTRODUCTION TO EARLY ENGLISH LAW 31 (1995) (explaining that Anglo-Saxon law did incorporate Frankish law, which drew on Roman law). 2012] RESCUING DIGNITARY TORTS 91 kings set forth specific penalties for specific injuries just as in the Roman Twelve Tables.104 One scholar has said that, in the Anglo-Saxon system, as in Rome, the predetermined penalties for specific wrongs were designed to minimize interpersonal violence. “[I]t illustrates how sensitive this society was to considerations of mere dignity, and how easily a trivial brawl could flare up into a feud unless damped down at once by some satisfaction . . . .”105 One of the earliest Anglo-Saxon law codes, given by Aethelbert of Kent at the beginning of the seventh century, recognizes dignity as a touchstone and sets forth “seizing or pulling by the hair” as among the physical injuries requiring compensation.106 This prohibition was not viewed as a species of assault but rather as a blot on the victim’s feelings or reputation. “The act is, of course, one of humiliation within a cultural tradition . . . [that] laid special emphasis on the status of hair length . . . .”107 The code given by the subsequent kings, Hlothere and Eadric, broadened the prohibition and suggested that penalties must be made for words that damage reputation or dignity. According to the decrees, “If one man calls another a perjurer in a third man’s house, or accosts him abusively with insulting words, he shall pay one shilling to him who owns the house, 6 shillings to him he has accosted, and 12 shillings to the king.”108 That the payment is made not just to the victim but to the property owner and to the king suggests that the violent effects likely to be produced by the words are a substantial portion of the rationale for the prohibition. The state has an interest in preempting the violence and thus fixes a price for the words, along with directing individual compensation. The laws of King Alfred, dating from the 870s, developed the concept of slander with more specificity. Integrating Biblical commands, Alfred’s code advised in a preface against “giv[ing] credence to the word of a false 104 By the time the Anglo-Saxons settled there, England had been to a degree cut off from its Roman contacts for some time . . . and had always been out on the fringes of Roman territory . . . . [so] there was no need to retain Roman-law courts or Roman law in Germanic Britain and therefore Roman legal ideas . . . seem to have had little if any influence on Anglo-Saxon law. DREW, supra note 77, at 25. 105 GRIFFITHS, supra note 103, at 10 (quoting K.P. WITNEY, THE KINGDOM OF KENT 96 (1982)) (internal quotation marks omitted). 106 Id. at 36 (emphasis omitted). 107 Id. at 36 n.22 (citations omitted). 108 F.L. ATTENBOROUGH, THE LAWS OF THE EARLIEST ENGLISH KINGS 21 (1922) (footnote omitted). 92 BROOKLYN LAW REVIEW [Vol. 78:1 man . . . [or] repeat[ing] any of his assertions.”109 It also advised against spreading rumors or gossip, and set a talion for slander—the defendant could have his tongue cut out or pay the plaintiff and keep his tongue.110 All of these early Anglo-Saxon laws were promulgated for use in a society comprising mainly insular local agrarian communities, and the laws emphasized popular participation.111 This use of community assemblies to mediate community disputes about compromised honor became less practical after Alfred’s death, when closed agrarian communities gave way to a more integrated society and a more centralized government.112 In addition, the movement of more individuals into the servile class meant that fewer in the country could carry weapons, so that insults between lower class individuals were resolved more often by an exchange of money than by duels.113 Men of status, in contrast, continued to defend their honor by duels.114 The early Anglo-Saxon law continued to treat all dignitary interests as compensable in private actions until the Norman conquest of England in 1066. Even then, however, defamation appears to have been peeled off from the actions for invasion of privacy and emotional injury more as a product of jurisdictional development than as the result of a considered analysis. Defamation came to be defined as charging another with a violation of canon law, and it was delegated to the ecclesiastical courts.115 In contrast, local English or Norman assemblies retained jurisdiction over disputes involving insults that did not explicitly sully the victim as a canon law violator.116 As the disintegration of the decentralized feudal structure diminished the manorial courts, however, “denial of a [common-law court] remedy at Westminster c[a]me to be denial of a right,”117 and during the Elizabethan period, the commonlaw courts began hearing actions for defamation. Unlike their predecessors in the manorial courts, these actions were strictly 109 GRIFFITHS, supra note 103, at 52. Id. at 68. 111 Anthony D’Amato & Stephen B. Presser, Anglo-Saxon Law, in GUIDE TO AMERICAN LAW: EVERYONE’S LEGAL ENCYCLOPEDIA 251, 252 (1985). 112 GRIFFITHS, supra note 103, at 15. 113 Colin Rhys Lovell, The “Reception” of Defamation by the Common Law, 15 VAND. L. REV. 1051, 1053-54 (1962). 114 Id. at 1053. 115 Id. at 1054. 116 See id. at 1054-55. 117 Van Vechten Veeder, The History and Theory of the Law of Defamation, 3 COLUM. L. REV. 546, 556 (1903). 110 2012] RESCUING DIGNITARY TORTS 93 limited to charges affecting reputation. Just as the ecclesiastical courts had offered a remedy only for charges of violating canon law, the common-law courts offered a remedy only for charges of committing a crime.118 Thus, like the canon law, the common law “thereby exclud[ed] . . . merely violent or offensive language from its definition of defamation.”119 Moreover, by 1593, the ecclesiastical courts ceded litigation over words that caused special damage or temporal loss to the common-law courts.120 As a result of these developments, English law had serendipitously evolved so that “[t]he gist of the action on the case for words was the [monetary] damage caused to the plaintiff and not the insult itself.”121 In time, however, the English common law bent to accommodate claims for words that violated mental tranquility without diminishing reputation. This development brought English law back into line with longstanding Western traditions despite a departure of several hundred years. By 1897, the English common law specifically developed the tort of intentional infliction of nervous shock in Wilkinson v. Downton.122 The court concluded that where a practical joker told a woman her husband had been “smashed up” just to see her reaction, the act was calculated “to infringe her legal right to personal safety” and thus was a good cause of action.123 Intentional infliction of nervous shock, which turns on the foreseeability of some physical manifestation of shock, has been applied by English courts for more than a century to the same fact patterns seen in Roman and Anglo-Saxon law, such as spitting on a plaintiff, cutting her hair against her will, or “throwing a coin contemptuously on the plaintiff’s hospital bed.”124 In all of these circumstances, the physical contact causes negligible pain, but the non-physical dignitary implications weigh heavily on the plaintiff’s emotional wellness. In fact, for the past several decades, English, Canadian, and Australian commentators have been urging the adoption of a tort for the intentional infliction of pure 118 Lovell, supra note 113, at 1063. Id. 120 See R.C. Donnelly, History of Defamation, 1949 WIS. L. REV. 99, 112 (1949). 121 Id. at 115. 122 2 Q.B. 57, 58 (1897). 123 Id. at 59; see also Denise G. Réaume, Indignities: Making a Place for Dignity in Modern Legal Thought, 28 QUEEN’S L.J. 61, 66-67 (2002). The evolution of English law to provide some protection for non-economic injuries to emotional well-being coincided with the abolition of formalistic writs to more flexible models of pleading. 124 Réaume, supra note 123, at 74. 119 94 BROOKLYN LAW REVIEW [Vol. 78:1 emotional harm; some have even suggested extending the tort to a unitary claim for assault on dignity.125 In contrast, English courts have not aligned with the majority of Western countries in recognizing a freestanding right to sue in tort for invasions of personal privacy. Writing in 1962, one scholar stated “with some confidence that English law does not recognise what [American] Judge [Thomas] Cooley called ‘the right to be left alone.’”126 But as with intentional infliction of emotional distress, there is some evidence that English courts occasionally tried to protect privacy interests by stretching other causes of action to cover them. Most famously, in Prince Albert v. Strange,127 a man was prevented from exhibiting and selling copies of impressions he had procured of etchings made by Queen Victoria and Prince Albert. The case was not explicitly decided in terms of privacy, rather as a violation of the royals’ proprietary rights in the commercial uses of the etchings.128 The court hazarded, however, that in the alternative, the proposed exhibition could have been enjoined on the basis of “breach of trust, confidence[,] or contract.”129 That suggestion was the springboard for Warren and Brandeis’s seminal article, The Right to Privacy, proposing the development of an independent tort for privacy violations.130 English scholars and legislatures supported the development of similar actions in English common law throughout the twentieth century, but to no avail.131 Notably, at least one suggested that in the absence of a discrete privacy tort, courts could vindicate plaintiffs by invoking the intentional infliction of nervous shock tort announced in Wilkinson.132 In sum, English courts have long recognized a tort of defamation and have reintegrated into their common law the idea of 125 Id. at 73 (citations omitted). Brian Neill, The Protection of Privacy, 25 MOD. L. REV. 393, 394 (1962) (quoting THOMAS COOLEY, TORTS 29 (2d ed. 1888)). 127 41 Eng. Rep. 1171 (1849). 128 Neill, supra note 126, at 395. (In fact, this reasoning is similar to the “right of publicity” branch of American privacy torts.). 129 Id. at 396. 130 Samuel D. Warren & Louis D. Brandeis, The Right to Privacy, 4 HARV. L. REV. 193, 203-05 (1890). 131 See, e.g., Neill, supra note 126, at 400-02; Percy H. Winfield, Privacy, 47 L. Q. REV. 23 (1931). 132 Neill, supra note 126, at 402. Today, English experts have suggested that the incorporation in the U.K. Human Rights Act of 1998 of the European Convention on Human Rights, Article 8, which guarantees a right of privacy, is leading to English acceptance of a common-law privacy right. Basil Markesinis et al., Concerns and Ideas About the Developing English Law of Privacy (And How Knowledge of Foreign Law Might Be of Help), 52 AM. J. COMP. L. 133, 133-34 (2004). 126 2012] RESCUING DIGNITARY TORTS 95 vindicating emotional injuries, while they continue to award damages only covertly to plaintiffs whose privacy was invaded. 2. English Theory—Natural Law As English courts were developing common-law doctrine on recourse for dignitary rights, English scholars were considering the same ideas from a more abstract perspective— one that informed the Framers’ thinking about the relationship between individuals and the state. Although many English philosophers and legal scholars developed theories of natural law, the two primary guides for the Framers were John Locke and William Blackstone.133 a. Locke Locke and other natural-law rights theorists of the Enlightenment developed the idea that the capacity for reason meant that all human beings were entitled to dignity, regardless of rank or social status.134 Locke, in particular, contended that natural rights should be recognized with “a place . . . in governance.”135 Among the natural rights Locke discussed was an “ownership interest in one’s own personhood,” a right which had “considerable reach” and was “inextricably tied up with the inherent dignity and liberty of the individual.”136 Specifically, Locke observed that natural law prohibited speech that can injure a third party’s well-being: [I]n customary intercourse among men and in communal life who is bound to hold a conversation about his neighbour and to meddle with other people’s affairs? No one, surely. Anyone can without harm either talk or be silent. But if perchance one wants to talk about another person, the law of nature undoubtedly enjoins that one’s talk be candid and friendly and that one should say things that do not harm that other person’s reputation and character.137 133 See, e.g., Caplan, supra note 56, at 260; Jackson, Blackstone, supra note 46, at 171. 134 Libby Adler, The Dignity of Sex, 17 UCLA WOMEN’S L.J. 1, 9 (2008). Id. 136 J. Harvie Wilkinson III, The Dual Lives of Rights: The Rhetoric and Practice of Rights in America, 98 CALIF. L. REV. 277, 284 (2010). 137 JOHN LOCKE, Essay 7, Is the Binding Force of the Law of Nature Perpetual and Universal? Yes, in ESSAYS ON THE LAW OF NATURE 195-96 (Oxford Univ. Press 1989) (1954). 135 96 BROOKLYN LAW REVIEW [Vol. 78:1 b. Blackstone Blackstone’s Commentaries are also considered a touchstone for interpreting constitutional language because they were a virtual hornbook for colonial lawyers and constitutional draftsman.138 Notably, the “natural law” explicated by Blackstone had “roots running deep into the soil of ancient Greece and Rome.”139 Blackstone identified three “absolute rights, . . . vested in [men] by the immutable laws of nature.”140 These three were the right of “personal security,” which consisted of a person’s “uninterrupted enjoyment of his life, his limbs, his body, his health, and his reputation”; “personal liberty,” which consisted of “the power of locomotion, of changing situation, or moving one’s person to whatsoever place one’s own inclination may direct”; and “the right of . . . property, [which consisted] of the free use, enjoyment, and disposal of all [an individual’s] acquisitions, without any control or diminution, save only by the laws of the land.”141 Blackstone also recognized among the “relative” rights necessary to effectuating these absolute rights an entitlement to “apply to the courts for speedy redress of injuries.”142 Reputation is recognized textually among Blackstone’s natural-law rights, and it is beyond dispute that it was considered one of the “Rights of Englishmen” incorporated into colonial law.143 In addition, some adherents of Blackstone have suggested that privacy is among his fundamental rights, although it is not within the explicit text.144 For instance, a 138 Albert W. Alschuler, Rediscovering Blackstone, 145 U. PA. L. REV. 1, 4-7 (1996). Not all who participated in drafting the Constitution were uncritical of Blackstone, who was not a supporter of the colonies. Id. 139 Id. at 17 (quoting LIVA BAKER, THE JUSTICE FROM BEACON HILL: THE LIFE AND TIMES OF OLIVER WENDELL HOLMES 249 (1991)). Blackstone’s underlying Roman law orientation is not surprising, given that he sought and was denied an appointment to teach Roman law at Oxford. Rebuffed, he developed a specialty in English law. One wonders whether the received wisdom that English law took no notice of Roman law results from the fact that the leading mouthpiece for English law was denied recognition as a Roman law scholar. See id. at 4-5. 140 1 WILLIAM BLACKSTONE, COMMENTARIES *124. 141 Michael B. Kent, Jr., Pavesich, Property and Privacy: The Common Origins of Property Rights and Privacy Rights in Georgia, 2 J. MARSHALL L.J. 1, 11-12 (2009) (quoting 1 BLACKSTONE, supra note 140, at *138) (internal quotation marks omitted). 142 Jackson, Blackstone, supra note 46, at 208. 143 Id. at 207 (citing 1 BLACKSTONE, supra note 140, at *129). 144 To be clear, the concept of privacy relevant to this article is a tort concept, enforceable by one private individual by post-invasion suit against another private individual. The concept of a constitutional right to privacy from government intrusion, originally recognized in Griswold v. Connecticut, 381 U.S. 479 (1965), is not the subject of this article. The distinction between privacy as tort and privacy as individual right 2012] RESCUING DIGNITARY TORTS 97 Georgia court that was among the first to embrace a tort right to privacy “cited Blackstone as additional support for [the recognition of a privacy tort], explicitly rooting the right of privacy in Blackstone’s conceptions of personal security and personal liberty.”145 Privacy can also be found as a component of Blackstonian property rights, the court reasoned, because the property right of “quiet enjoyment” is violated when “the common scold” tramples on the individual’s right “to use, occupy, and enjoy the general functioning of . . . society in a quiet and peaceable manner.”146 This right is protected by punishing “the scold” in tort.147 Similarly, Blackstone’s reference to “health” as a component of personal security suggests that mental health (today recognized as a medical dimension of the emotional tranquility protected by IIED) is arguably among Blackstone’s natural rights. English scholars, this survey suggests, recognized all three interests—privacy, reputation, and emotional security—as natural-law rights, which in turn, influenced the American experience. 3. The American Experience American law, in the form of state constitutions and state common law, strongly endorsed the right of individuals to protect their reputations via common-law tort suits at the time of ratification. Further, the evolution of the common law over the next 150 years shows that American courts gradually moved from informally recognizing privacy and emotional security rights to explicit adoption of tort causes of action for their invasion. a. State Constitutions A survey of state constitutions in effect at the time of ratification illustrates that the freedoms of speech and of the press were not contemporaneously considered to foreclose the private right to sue for defamation. Americans of the period tended to “assume[] that certain types of speech or press— including blasphemous, obscene, fraudulent, or defamatory against the government was noted by Justice Black in Griswold. See id. at 510 n.1 (Black, J., dissenting). 145 Kent, supra note 141, at 12 (citing Pavesich v. New Eng. Life Ins. Co., 50 S.E. 68, 70 (Ga. 1905)). 146 Id. at 18-19. 147 Id. at 18, 19 n.88. 98 BROOKLYN LAW REVIEW [Vol. 78:1 words—lacked or should lack constitutional protection.”148 In fact, a number of state constitutions specifically wrote in protection for the right to sue for defamatory statements. Pennsylvania’s 1790 constitution, for instance, “said that every citizen may freely speak, write, and print on any subject, being responsible for the abuse of that liberty.”149 The Delaware, Massachusetts, and Kentucky Constitutions, which were also in effect during the ratification periods, followed suit.150 The original public understanding of the internal limits on freedom of speech and press was not limited to defamatory statements alone. During the debate over the 1780 Massachusetts Constitution, one proposed speech and press clause barred restrictions on speech freedoms “unless in Cases where it is extended to the abuse, or injury of Private Characters.”151 This trend towards state constitutional protection of the right to sue for libel152 had expanded, not contracted, by the time the 148 Philip A. Hamburger, Natural Rights, Natural Law, and American Constitutions, 102 YALE L.J. 907, 935 (1993). As recently as 2012, the Supreme Court reiterated that several categories of speech, including “advocacy intended, and likely, to incite imminent lawless action, . . . obscenity, . . . defamation, . . . speech integral to criminal conduct, . . . ‘fighting words,’ . . . child pornography, . . . fraud, . . . true threats, . . . and speech presenting some grave and imminent threat the government has the power to prevent” are not presumptively protected speech. United States v. Alvarez, 132 S. Ct. 2537, 2544 (2012) (plurality opinion) (citations omitted). The consistency of these categories, many of which involve personality interests longprotected in Western law, corroborates this initial view that the First Amendment can be applied with reference to other considerations. 149 Hamburger, supra note 148, at 936 n.83 (citing PA. CONST. of 1790, art. IX, § 7) (emphasis added). Notably, this understanding has also informed First Amendment scrutiny of speech-restrictive statutes and regulations addressing obscenity, volume, and likelihood of inciting violence. See, e.g., Heyman, supra note 37, at 1279 (noting that government restrictions on obscenity, perjury and the like are widely considered uncontroversial). 150 Hamburger, supra note 148, at 936 n.83. 151 Id. (emphasis added). 152 To be clear, this article is concerned solely with the ability of private individuals to sue in tort for speech-inflicted injuries. The latitude of the states to provide for criminal prosecution of libel is an entirely different issue, although historically many states provided for both civil and criminal remedies for speech injuries. See, e.g., Lisby, supra note 75, at 456-57. The criminal and the civil causes of action share one justification; both were initially designed to prevent violence. However, today, criminal libel actions are viewed more as a species of seditious libel, generally brought not because the words at issue are likely to cause violence requiring state oversight, but because the words criticize government or government officers. See id. at 473-74 (discussing the relationship between purely civil libel, criminal libel based on apolitical but incendiary speech, and criminal libel arising from criticism of government). Although the Court has long held that the provision of a state forum for resolution of private conflicts is a form of state action triggering the Fourteenth, and consequently the First, Amendments, the action of the state in passing a law ex ante prohibiting entire categories of anti-government speech is qualitatively different than the action of the state in establishing a mechanism whereby private individuals can 2012] RESCUING DIGNITARY TORTS 99 Fourteenth Amendment was ratified, which ultimately resulted in application of the First Amendment against not just the federal government, but state governments as well. In 1868, twenty-seven of the thirty-seven states’ constitutions featured language “explicitly contemplat[ing] the bringing of at least some libel suits.”153 b. State Common Law At the founding, and for almost two centuries after, states offered their courts as a forum for the resolution of private disputes between individuals arising from incursions on dignity. Until the early 1900s, the only common-law cause of action permitting redress for dignitary harms was defamation (strictly cabined between slander and libel, at the time), so most dignitary harms were pleaded as defamation. However, some of the “defamation” cases appear to involve slights to interests other than reputation. The “defamation” category was used to smuggle in litigation over the broader basket of dignitary interests.154 Eventually, in part because of the changing nature of newspapers and in part because of expansion of the common law to include actions for invasion of privacy and intentional infliction, some dignitary lawsuits that might have been awkwardly slotted as “defamation” entered into the privacy and intentional infliction channels of tort. i. Slander and Libel Coming as they did from England and its legal structure, the colonies’ recognition of a common-law cause of action for defamation is not surprising. The use of libel and slander lawsuits was apparently seen as a safety valve to prevent the eruption of violence and conflict within what was peacefully settle dignitary conflicts ex post with the aid of juries that will determine and apply local community norms. 153 Steven G. Calabresi & Sarah E. Agudo, Individual Rights Under State Constitutions When the Fourteenth Amendment Was Ratified in 1868: What Rights Are Deeply Rooted in American History and Tradition?, 87 TEX. L. REV. 7, 45-46 (2008). 154 Of course, because these interests were not connected to any explicit cause of action, fewer of them were likely pleaded than might have been warranted. The point is that plaintiffs did successfully sue for injuries on the outer edge of the “reputation” interest that would have been more accurately described as dignitary interests in privacy or emotional tranquility had those causes of action been articulated at the time. See, e.g., infra notes 193-94, 203 and accompanying text. 100 BROOKLYN LAW REVIEW [Vol. 78:1 still a community of pioneers.155 Thus, in the typical civil defamation suit of the time, the plaintiff and defendant knew each other, and both were known to the jurors. “People almost always handled their own cases, and courts applied flexible rules that in many ways resembled the practices of local and church tribunals of medieval England more than the complicated doctrines and procedures of modern defamation law.”156 Money damages were usually small and were often replaced or supplemented with public apologies or acknowledgment of wrongdoing.157 The goal was “to minimize feelings of hostility and ‘to make a balance’ between the parties.”158 Civil libel suits that resolved “small” conflicts between private individuals were valued by the colonists as a means of restoring the community norm of “harmony and cooperation,” much valued by people who had left England in part to opt out of “wrenching economic and social change” there.159 For instance, one Merrill sued for slander a New Hampshire man who asked a neighbor: “What will Merrill do next? Kimball has had his barn burnt, and Hoit will have his burnt within a fortnight. We know persons about here bad enough to do this[.]”160 This example shows that civil lawsuits were considered an appropriate means for community members to weigh in on the acceptable boundaries of gossip and speculation over local affairs among neighbors. By the early 1800s, politicians began bringing civil libel 161 suits. Dramatic changes in the average newspaper also multiplied the number and types of speech injuries at issue in defamation cases: [The so-called popular press] added corps of ambitious reporters to dig out stories of everyday tragedy and triumph, introduced regular sports columns to hold the attention of male readers, and added features on domestic life to attract a loyal corps of female customers. Newer technologies eventually allowed for inexpensive reproduction of photographs, an innovation that helped bring immigrants with few or no reading skills in English into the reading public. And new 155 NORMAN L. ROSENBERG, PROTECTING THE BEST MEN: AN INTERPRETIVE HISTORY OF THE LAW OF LIBEL 16 (1986). 156 Id. 157 Id. 158 Id. 159 Id. at 22-23. 160 Merrill v. Peaslee, 17 N.H. 540, 540 (1845); see also Chaddock v. Briggs, 13 Mass. 248, 250-51 (1816) (remarking that a local minister had engaged in a “drunken frolic” was cause for a slander suit by the minister). 161 ROSENBERG, supra note 155, at 121. 2012] RESCUING DIGNITARY TORTS 101 styles of story construction made newspaper reading easier for everyone. James Scripps, for example, believed that a good paper could be measured by the number of stories, preferably brief ones, that it contained; the more items that could be crammed into a single issue, the better the paper. Of course, this practice, by itself, increased the possibility for libel suits. The colorful content of popular journalism created more than the chance for greater numbers of libel suits; it also produced new types of defamation cases. By opening all kinds of areas of hitherto private life, including family affairs and sexual morality, to constant newspaper scrutiny, the popular press sought to expand the definition of what issues were in the public domain. Carried to its logical conclusion, popular journalism on the marketplace model implied that whatever appeared in the papers—and was purchased by the sovereign readers—was a public matter. But plaintiffs who were not public people in the traditional sense . . . did not always accept marketplace logic. If they . . . sued for libel, their suits could raise . . . tricky public-private distinctions . . . .162 In fact, libel suits began to mushroom with the rise of the popular press. The New York Herald, for instance, completed a study in 1869, which found that the press had, “recent[ly],” been sued more than 700 times.163 Predictably, several of these suits eventually reached the Supreme Court. Whether the Court ultimately ruled for or against the press, the fact that it did not hesitate to apply the state common law of defamation to the facts at hand implies that the common-law adjudication of libel and slander cases was not seen as inconsistent with the First Amendment Press Clause.164 For instance, in Washington Post Co. v. Chaloner, the Court reversed and remanded a libel case against the Washington Post brought by a local socialite.165 The paper reported that the plaintiff had a “nervous breakdown as a result of the tragedy at his home, Merry Mills, . . . when he shot and killed John Gillard, while the latter was abusing his wife, who had taken refuge at . . . Chaloner’s home.”166 The Court found that the jury instructions were erroneous because they directed the jury that the report was libelous per se, rather than allowing the jury to weigh the meaning of the complained-of words in context.167 Mention of any First Amendment protection from tort liability 162 Id. at 186-87. Id. at 197. 164 See, e.g., Wash. Post Co. v. Chaloner, 250 U.S. 290 (1919); Peck v. Tribune Co., 214 U.S. 185 (1909). 165 250 U.S. at 291, 294. 166 Id. at 291 (internal quotation marks omitted). 167 Id. at 293. 163 102 BROOKLYN LAW REVIEW [Vol. 78:1 for the newspaper is conspicuously absent. A similar analysis applies to Peck v. Tribune Co., where the reversal in plaintiff’s favor was premised on the finding that her reputation was compromised by an advertisement falsely stating that she endorsed whisky as a medicinal tool.168 The Court focused entirely on the elements of the tort cause of action, without considering any role for the First Amendment.169 ii. Invasion of Privacy Colonial courts did not embrace a freestanding tort for invasion of privacy. Occasionally, however, they did protect privacy interests even without the benefit of a developed tort cause of action. Early New England courts allowed suits against defendants who “[bore tales] from house to house.”170 As early as 1661, there is evidence of “antigossip” litigation in the Connecticut colony.171 In 1668, a Plymouth litigant “succeeded in having the court admonish three persons ‘for opening a certaine box in his house, wherin were his writings.’”172 In dicta, courts recognized the right to privacy as early as 1769, observing that “[every man] has certainly a right to judge whether he will make [his own sentiments] public.”173 And, notably, it appears that colonists seeking to vindicate privacy interests in the absence of explicit torts for their invasion regularly turned to defamation as a vehicle.174 After the ratification, as the rise of the penny press led to a new news product, replete with photographs, “sob sister” columns, and sensational crime stories, more Americans found themselves the subject of news coverage.175 The number of “defamation” cases that were filed based on unwanted exposure 168 214 U.S. at 189-90. Id. 170 DAVID H. FLAHERTY, PRIVACY IN COLONIAL NEW ENGLAND 105 (1967) (internal quotation marks omitted). 171 Id. at 105 n.60. 172 Id. at 119. 173 Warren & Brandeis, supra note 130, at 198 n.2. 174 FLAHERTY, supra note 170, at 248. Some have ventured that “[p]rivacy as an all-encompassing constitutional right was . . . not a part of the legal tradition inherited from England by the colonies which would have been secured in either a state or federal bill of rights.” Caplan, supra note 56, at 267 (footnote omitted). But, of course, the fact that privacy may have been recognized as an individual right of lessthan-constitutional weight does not disqualify it from status as a Ninth Amendment “right retained.” 175 See ROSENBERG, supra note 155, at 186-87; see also supra notes 162-63 and accompanying text. 169 2012] RESCUING DIGNITARY TORTS 103 rather than a classic diminishment of reputation rose accordingly. Some examples of nonreputational fact patterns that led to findings of defamation beginning before the turn of the century include: stating that a man’s “sister had been arrested for larceny,” running an advertisement in which a known teetotaler was depicted as endorsing alcohol, running an advertisement in which an athlete was depicted as endorsing chocolate, or running a picture of a wrestler next to one “of a gorilla in an article on evolution.”176 Plaintiff victories suggest that in all of these cases the courts were responding to injuries that did not exactly diminish reputation—an athlete would not be reviled by the community for a food endorsement—but were nevertheless real—his identity was usurped by a third party for commercial purposes without his consent.177 An early response to the perceived overreaching of the modern press was a renowned law review article, The Right to Privacy, published in 1890 by Samuel Warren and Louis Brandeis.178 On the heels of the groundbreaking proposal that courts should recognize privacy as a freestanding right belonging to individuals and redressable in tort, rather than as an offshoot of property or contract law, many common-law courts began to recognize various species of privacy torts.179 While the development of a distinct law of privacy solved the problem of these claims masquerading as defamation, it introduced the problem of defamation claims seeking refuge in the privacy torts.180 That a given fact pattern may be just as reasonably classified as defamation as invasion of privacy follows from the fact that American law strives—likely because of its outgrowth from English law rather than civil law—to maintain the two torts as distinct when in fact they address 176 Wade, supra note 10, at 1094-95 n.11 (citations omitted). See, e.g., Note, The Right to Privacy in Nineteenth Century America, 94 HARV. L. REV. 1892, 1907 (1981). 178 Warren & Brandeis, supra note 130. 179 As the law developed, a “complex of four” privacy torts emerged: “intrusion upon . . . seclusion or . . . private affairs”; “public disclosure of embarrassing facts”; “false light”; and “[misa]ppropriation of the plaintiff’s name or likeness.” Wade, supra note 10, at 1095 n.13 (quoting William L. Prosser, Privacy, 48 CALIF. L. REV. 383, 389 (1960)). Misappropriation of name or image has in recent years shifted from the common law to the statutory realm, with most statutes providing statutory damages for unconsented use of personality elements if the plaintiff cannot prove consequential damages. See, e.g., Aubrie Hicks, Note, The Right to Publicity After Death: Postmortem Personality Rights in Washington in the Wake of Experience Hendrix v. Hendrixlicensing.org, 36 SEATTLE U. L. REV. 275, 276 (2012). This evolution suggests that one branch of privacy law, at least, has reintegrated some elements of property and contract. 180 Wade, supra note 10, at 1095. 177 104 BROOKLYN LAW REVIEW [Vol. 78:1 similar defendant behavior and protect plaintiff interests that are so infinitesimally different as to be essentially inextricable.181 Notably, the Court in Peck v. Tribune Co. did not foreclose the possibility of permitting the plaintiff to recover for the unconsented use of her photograph in a whisky advertisement, known in modern parlance as the right of publicity subset of the privacy tort.182 The plaintiff had pleaded both causes, and the Court reversed the dismissal of her defamation count without holding that the privacy count was untenable as a matter of law.183 iii. Intentional Infliction of Emotional Distress Just as privacy interests evolved from covert to overt treatment in the American common law, scholars writing early in the twentieth century demonstrated that courts often evaded the confines of tort law to compensate egregiously inflicted mental anguish well before formally acknowledging these interests in a specific tort. There is little documentation that courts vindicated claims of emotional distress through defamation or other avenues at the time of the ratification. However, by 1890, Warren and Brandeis reported matter-of-factly that “the legal value of ‘feelings’ is now generally recognized,” whether as damages parasitic to a physical injury, damages to a parent stemming from tort injuries to a child, or as a subset of defamation damages.184 Despite discernible patterns among the cases where emotional injury was compensated, the injuries were not yet categorized as a separate tort because they were thought not to bear sufficiently “distinct and definite features of [their] own.”185 In the 1936 article often credited as the springboard for the American tort of intentional infliction of emotional distress, 181 For instance, truth is a defense to a complaint for defamation but not to most privacy causes of action. See, e.g., Melville B. Nimmer, The Right to Speak from Times to Time: First Amendment Theory Applied to Libel and Misapplied to Privacy, 56 CALIF. L. REV. 935, 958-59 (1968). Further, a defamatory statement must lower the plaintiff’s reputation in the eyes of the community, whereas a privacy invasion turns on offense reasonably felt by the plaintiff himself. See id. Historically, defamation law treated written and spoken statements differently, see, e.g., Tilley, supra note 76, passim, whereas privacy law generally does not distinguish between statements based on the mechanics of communication. 182 214 U.S. 185, 190 (1909). 183 Id. at 188, 190. 184 Warren & Brandeis, supra note 130, at 197-98 n.1. 185 Prosser, Insult and Outrage, supra note 16, at 40 (arguing that the cause had become sufficiently distinct to warrant independent treatment). 2012] RESCUING DIGNITARY TORTS 105 Calvert Magruder demonstrated that when necessary, courts compensated emotional injuries behind the fig leaf of other torts.186 So, for instance, where a hospital patient had to wait eleven hours to be discharged because of an unpaid bill, the court called it false imprisonment and compensated him; where a railroad conductor failed to stop a drunken passenger from kissing a female passenger, the court found the company liable; where speech mortified plaintiffs even though hearers did not believe its contents, courts were known to call it defamation and give a verdict.187 Magruder, later joined by William Prosser, argued that courts should accord “independent legal protection” for “the interest in mental and emotional peace” via a new tort.188 Magruder summarized the types of conduct that judges had been compensating sub rosa or wringing their hands and rejecting, proposing that these behavioral patterns should be the province of this new cause of action. The patterns included: publicly accusing a woman of unchastity;189 insulting treatment of customers in public places of business such as shops, telegraph offices, or railway cars;190 falsely circulating reports that a school child was illegitimate;191 public posters identifying debtors;192 unfounded attempts to sue and harassment in the course of bill collection;193 and “mishandling of corpses.”194 Of course, these fact patterns are almost identical to those found in the Roman law of iniuria summarized in Part IV.A.2.195 By 1948, the American Law Institute announced in a supplement to its first Restatement of Torts that an 186 See Calvert Magruder, Mental and Emotional Disturbance in the Law of Torts, 49 HARV. L. REV. 1034 (1936). 187 Id. at 1034-35 & nn.5, 8 & 9. 188 Id. at 1035. 189 Id. at 1051. 190 Id. at 1052-53. 191 Id. at 1059. 192 Id. at 1060. 193 Id. at 1063. 194 Id. at 1064; see also Zipursky, supra note 34, at 502-03 (summarizing classic cases via Prosser). 195 Surprisingly, though Magruder acknowledges the “deep human feelings involved” in many of these circumstances, he did not indicate any historical basis for the creation of the “new” tort. See Magruder, supra note 187, at 1066-67. Nor did Prosser or any other law professors advocating for the tort credit its Roman law forerunner. It is unclear why these scholars, steeped in tort history and theory, did not acknowledge the debt owed to Roman law. One turn-of-the century survey of American law schools summarized that “Roman law [has] almost disappeared from the law school curriculum, even as an educational and academic subject,” which may explain the silence. THE ROMAN LAW READER, supra note 99, at 222. 106 BROOKLYN LAW REVIEW [Vol. 78:1 independent tort of intentional infliction of emotional distress had been fully enough developed to merit recognition.196 In sum, all the dignitary rights and the corollary rights to sue for their invasion have a deep, nearly atavistic lineage within Western legal culture. As one scholar has summarized their history: We have interests in mental tranquility, in reputation, in privacy. . . . The recognition of all these things as interests presumably took place over millennia. They are now part of our evolved selves. . . . Gradually, recognized interests undergo a metamorphosis into a recognition of rights. . . . As society evolves, it establishes various instruments through which these rights are announced and sometimes advertised. One of these, a constantly developing repository of rights, is the common law.197 V. THE STATUS OF DIGNITARY TORTS AS NINTH AMENDMENT “RIGHTS RETAINED” Under the modest Ninth Amendment “rule of construction” theory, enumerated rights do not automatically trump retained rights when the two clash merely because the former are enumerated. Instead, courts interpreting the reach of enumerated rights must attempt to calibrate their reading of the enumerated right to avoid crowding out the right retained. Applying this theory, this section considers how well each of the dignitary torts—defamation, intentional infliction, and invasion of privacy—fits within each of the “rights retained” models—Framers’ original public understanding of natural-law rights, “Western-legal-tradition” rights, 1791 state-law rights, and post-1791 state-law rights. It concludes that defamation indisputably fits within all four models; invasion of privacy fits within at least the Western-legal-tradition and post-1791 models, and possibly the natural-law and 1791 models; and intentional infliction also clearly fits within at least the Western-legal-tradition and post-1791 models, and possibly the natural-law model. 196 RESTATEMENT (FIRST) OF TORTS § 46 (Supp. 1948). State courts throughout the country shifted from an implicit to an explicit recognition of the IIED tort over the forty-year period from 1939 through 1979. See, e.g., Geoffrey Christopher Rapp, Defense Against Outrage and the Perils of Parasitic Torts, 45 GA. L. REV. 107, 135-36 (2010) (describing history of IIED adoption in American courts and the tort’s current status as the “majority rule”). 197 MARSHALL SHAPO, AN INJURY LAW CONSTITUTION 37-38 (2012). 2012] A. RESCUING DIGNITARY TORTS 107 Dignitary Interests as “Natural-Law” Rights as Understood by the Framers 1. Defamation The status of a right to reputation as a natural-law right is virtually indisputable. Even applying the most restrictive Ninth Amendment definition of natural-law rights, those identified by Locke and Blackstone, one sees uniform textual agreement that men have a right to protect their reputations against incursions by private parties. As outlined in Part IV.B.2, Locke explicitly wrote that natural law prohibited individuals from speech that would harm “[an]other person’s reputation.”198 Blackstone’s Commentaries, too, explicitly state that man’s absolute right to personal security included an “uninterrupted enjoyment of his . . . reputation.”199 2. Privacy There is less support within Blackstone and Locke for the proposition that privacy is among the individual rights retained under the Ninth Amendment, though the concepts do appear. Locke’s view that men have an “ownership interest” in their own “personhood”200 presages the work of Warren and Brandeis describing longstanding judicial intuition that the law should protect a party’s name and image from third-party co-opting without consent, whether as an element of property law or, eventually, as a freestanding tort. Locke’s admonition against “meddl[ing] with other people’s affairs”201 further reflects a recognition of an individual zone that should be free from scrutiny. Similarly, Blackstone’s identification of “personal security” and “personal liberty” as absolute rights has been interpreted by some courts as approval of private tort actions for invasions of privacy.202 198 LOCKE, supra note 137, at 196. See 1 BLACKSTONE, supra note 140, at *138 (discussed in Kent, supra note 141). 200 Wilkinson, supra note 136, at 284. 201 See LOCKE, supra note 137, at 195-96. 202 Kent, supra note 141, at 12 (citing Pavesich v. New Eng. Life Ins. Co., 50 S.E. 68 (Ga. 1905)). 199 108 BROOKLYN LAW REVIEW [Vol. 78:1 3. Intentional Infliction of Emotional Distress Although neither Blackstone nor Locke make explicit textual reference to a private-law right of emotional tranquility, which is today protected by the IIED tort, their works clearly imply that this interest is a dimension of the natural-law rights of man. First, Locke focused on the “inherent dignity” of the individual and suggested that this right cast a long legal shadow. Thus, it is no surprise that he determined that natural law governed “intercourse among men and in communal life” and barred speech that would inflict harm not just on a person’s reputation—a version of self used in external exchanges—but also on his “character,” a more private version of self that encompasses emotion, self-image, and self-worth derived not internally but from external social assessments.203 Similarly, Blackstone’s references to “personal security” and “personal liberty” have also been interpreted to extend a right to enjoy “the general functioning of society in a quiet and peaceable manner,” which arguably encompasses the right to be free from emotional harassment inflicted via social interactions. B. Dignitary Interests as Natural-Law “Western-LegalTradition” Rights 1. Defamation The fact that Greece, Rome, and England all recognized a right to reputation enforceable against private parties fortifies the conclusion that reputation is among the “rights retained” under the individual rights theory.204 2. Privacy Privacy, too, has been protected as a private right throughout Western legal traditions, albeit less assertively. The most well-developed privacy tort is found in Rome, where iniuria explicitly allowed private actions for invasions of privacy. There is less evidence of privacy protection in the ancient law of Greece and the early regimes in the civil-law 203 See Post, Privacy, supra note 7, at 962-63 (quoting Goffman on the theory that violations of social deference rules can injure the personality and inhibit “the complete man”). 204 See supra Part IV. 2012] RESCUING DIGNITARY TORTS 109 countries. In England, privacy has not been recognized as a right protected by a common-law cause of action. Of the three dignitary torts, privacy has the weakest claim to natural-law status under the historical theory of natural-law rights. 3. Intentional Infliction of Emotional Distress The protection of emotional well-being against onslaught from private actors is entrenched in centuries of Western legal tradition. In ancient Greece, Aristotle wrote that abuse and insult should be the subject of civil litigation rather than interpersonal violence,205 and the Code of Solon barred the use of harsh words in places of solace and the incitement of families by speaking ill of the dead.206 Rome’s law of intentional infliction was even more developed, allowing actions for defiling dead bodies or graves, harassment of debtors, sexual aggression, and the use of abusive language.207 Early AngloSaxon law was consistent with its continental counterparts, recognizing causes of action for words and gestures that led to “humiliation.”208 Later, emotional well-being as a private-law right was orphaned when England transitioned from manorial and ecclesiastical courts to a system of common-law writs. This development does not significantly alter the place of the interest within the Western legal scheme, however, for two reasons. First, it was the result of historical accident209 rather than considered analysis. Second, the tort has reemerged in English common law this century, demonstrating that it represents persistent and deep-seated Western legal values. 205 Madden, supra note 65, at 883 (quoting ARISTOTLE, supra note 70, at 402). See VERSTEEG, supra note 67, at 254; Lisby, supra note 75, at 442-43. See supra notes 85-90 and accompanying text. 208 See GRIFFITHS, supra note 103, at 36 n.22. To be sure, English law formally departed from this tenet of Western law for a time. As the common-law courts developed during the Elizabethan period, they took jurisdiction over defamation and the protection of reputation, leaving “insult” cases to the local manorial courts. Those courts fell into disuse as England evolved from an agrarian to an industrial society. However, by 1897, the English courts began to reintegrate emotional injury into the tort scheme. See Réaume, supra note 123, at 66-67. 209 See supra notes 118-24. 206 207 110 C. BROOKLYN LAW REVIEW [Vol. 78:1 Dignitary Interests as State Rights in 1791 1. Defamation Colonial courts recognized private lawsuits for slander and libel, and colonists seeking to resolve disputes that interfered with community harmony frequently pursued them.210 The right to reputation was recognized in the laws of the people of the states at the time of ratification and often was explicitly called for in state constitutions.211 In short, “On any plausible reading of the Ninth Amendment, the right to reputation falls among the ‘others retained by the people’” under 1791 state law.212 2. Privacy Tort actions for invasion of privacy were not explicitly found in the statutes or constitutions of the states at the time of ratification. Nor did the common law overtly recognize privacy causes of action. There is evidence, however, that colonists asserted privacy causes of actions in the seventeenth century.213 For example, some colonies entertained “antigossip” cases, while others censured defendants who opened containers in order to read writings not meant to be public.214 And in the eighteenth century, courts were known to observe in dicta the intuition that individuals were in sole control of how far they wished to thrust themselves into the public eye.215 Further, litigants protesting speech that unwillingly exposed them to neighbors took refuge in the established torts of slander and libel.216 Privacy has a strong claim of recognition under state law of 1791. 3. Intentional Infliction of Emotional Distress Historical evidence suggests that neither colonial courts nor state statutory or common law at the time of the ratification recognized a distinct tort for outrage or intentional 210 See supra notes 158-60. See Claus, supra note 43, at 617 n.101; Tilley, supra note 76, at 1054 n.251; see also supra notes 151-53. 212 See Claus, supra note 43, at 617. 213 See supra notes 172-75 and accompanying text. 214 See supra notes 172-73. 215 See Warren & Brandeis, supra note 130, at 198 n.2; supra note 175. 216 See supra note 176. 211 2012] RESCUING DIGNITARY TORTS 111 infliction of emotional distress. Of course, given the interrelationship between reputation, dignity, and emotional tranquility, there is a possibility that courts adjudicating common-law slander and libel claims at the time used that vehicle to account for emotional injury. But there is little documentation that courts were vindicating emotional distress claims. Notably, the substantial early twentieth century scholarship supporting the initiation of the IIED cause of action found just this “gaming” of the available torts in its surveys of common law.217 The earliest of those cases are traced back only to the mid-nineteenth century, however, well after ratification. Whether writers did not research back through the late 1700s, or whether they did so and unearthed no examples of “hidden” emotional distress claims is not clear. At any rate, intentional infliction does not appear to have Ninth Amendment status as a right protected by the common law in 1791. D. Dignitary Interests as State Rights Between 1791 and 1964 1. Defamation As outlined above, tort causes of action to protect reputation were well-recognized at the time of ratification. In the years between ratification and the adoption of the Fourteenth Amendment, the majority of states drafted explicit protection for some type of libel in their constitutions. These tort causes of action continued to thrive for the two centuries until the Court constitutionalized the tort in New York Times Co. v. Sullivan.218 2. Privacy Some colonies appeared to protect privacy interests without explicitly recognizing privacy torts. By 1890, however, the proliferation of cameras and the rise of the penny press, with its emphasis on sensational coverage of average individuals, led to a push for privacy torts.219 Warren and Brandeis’s renowned article, The Right to Privacy, urged courts to develop tort causes of action for invasion of privacy, rather than bend the defamation tort or property-law concepts to 217 218 219 See, e.g., Magruder, supra note 187, at 1034-35. 376 U.S. 254 (1964). See supra notes 180-81. 112 BROOKLYN LAW REVIEW [Vol. 78:1 protect this dignitary interest.220 By 1964, the privacy torts had been described as having been “well established in the United States for a number of years now.”221 3. Intentional Infliction of Emotional Distress The development of the intentional infliction tort followed a pattern remarkably similar to the privacy torts. In fact, in their piece advocating privacy torts, Warren and Brandeis noted that despite technical restrictions on tort recovery for emotional harm, “the legal value of ‘feelings’” was generally recognized by 1890. Just as courts wishing to protect privacy interests before the advent of the privacy torts used defamation as a vehicle, courts wishing to protect emotional tranquility interests used the same tool, along with the concept of parasitic damages and bystander damages, to allow recovery for non-physical injuries that were linked (however tenuously) to a physical harm.222 In 1936, the first of a series of law review articles urged overt recognition of a tort for intentional infliction of emotional distress, and by 1948, the American Law Institute in a supplement to the Restatement of Torts, had complied. A number of state courts had already recognized the tort, and they continued to do so over the next several decades.223 Consequently, the tort was widely, though not uniformly, accepted throughout the states as part of the common law prior to 1964. E. Summary of Dignitary Tort Status Under Ninth Amendment Theories Surveying the history of the dignitary torts from ancient Western-law regimes through the colonial period, the ratification, and up through the mid-twentieth century, it appears that each of these torts succeeds under at least one of the theories for filling the Ninth Amendment set of “rights retained.” Respect for the right to reputation, limits on exposure to the public world, and emotional tranquility are 220 Warren & Brandeis, supra note 130, at 203-05. Wade, supra note 10, at 1094. Not surprisingly, given the unitary dignitary interest from which the privacy and defamation torts arose, courts that had protected privacy by application of defamation law now began to protect reputation by application of the privacy torts when the particular requirements of defamation would have left a plaintiff unprotected. Id. at 1095. 222 See supra notes 186-87. 223 Givelber, supra note 11, at 43 nn.8-9. 221 2012] RESCUING DIGNITARY TORTS 113 consistent hallmarks of Western legal systems, from ancient Roman and Greek law, through civil law in Europe and early Anglo-Saxon law. English common law inadvertently suppressed legal vindication of these rights in the medieval and Elizabethan eras, but their eventual reemergence in the modern era shows that the cultural value attached to these rights is deep-seated within Western law. American law, too, has long honored the reputational interest and, after vindicating privacy and emotional tranquility rights via defamation for decades, has returned to the system established by Roman law to allow compensation for all three interests. This history supports the argument that privacy and emotional tranquility may be identified among the rights retained by the Ninth Amendment under an individual rights theory. Under the natural-law theory of “rights retained,” it is indisputable that the right to vindicate reputation via defamation is a right retained. Further, Locke’s and Blackstone’s writings suggest— certainly less overtly—a recognition of individual rights to emotional tranquility and some measure of control over exposure to the outside world. Under a 1791 state-rights theory, it is again indisputable that the right to reputation vindicated via the defamation torts is a right retained. Slander and libel were well-recognized common-law causes of action at the time of ratification and were often acknowledged in state constitutions. Less certain, but not beyond question, is the argument that privacy may have been among the rights recognized by the common law in 1791. Although no explicit privacy cause of action existed in tort until the twentieth century, there is ample evidence that colonial courts, and those after the ratification, strove to protect privacy through the torts available at the time, primarily defamation. In contrast, there is very little evidence that colonial courts or those at the time of ratification viewed emotional tranquility as a right meriting overt or even covert protection in tort. In fact, emotional harm was considered too speculative to support damages in tort. Thus, under the originalist state-rights theory of the Ninth Amendment, it is unlikely that the right to emotional wellbeing is among the “rights retained.”224 224 The disconnect between the “natural-law” status of intentional infliction and the 1791 status of intentional infliction can be chalked up to historical accident. The cause of action had been recognized for centuries, was peeled off from defamation during intramural jurisdictional battles in England as the legal system there cycled 114 BROOKLYN LAW REVIEW [Vol. 78:1 Under an “evolving” state-rights theory, including among “rights retained” those adopted by state statute or common law after the ratification, all three dignitary torts would have constitutional status under the Ninth Amendment. Defamation, of course, had longstanding roots within English and American law. By the early twentieth century, state courts had followed the lead of Warren and Brandeis and developed extensive tort theories to protect privacy. And shortly thereafter, courts began to embrace the tort of intentional infliction of emotional distress to allow money damages for purely non-physical emotional harms. These two latter-day American torts were well-established throughout the country by 1964, when the Court initially began to apply the First Amendment to cabin the dignitary tort of defamation. This article is agnostic as to which of these theories should fill the empty set of “rights retained,” in part because the theories seem to be different in formulation but nearly identical in result. In fact, concepts of “natural law,” “common law,” and “history and tradition” often seem interchangeable. As a matter of theory, there may be principled distinctions between the different sets of law, but for purposes of finding a constitutional foothold for the dignitary torts, any or all of them will suffice. Indeed, this has been a faint but consistent suggestion from the time of ratification through the modern era of the First Amendment. One of the first drafts of what eventually became the Ninth Amendment, crafted by Roger Sherman of Connecticut, states that: The people have certain natural rights which are retained by them when they enter Society, Such are the rights of Conscience in matters of religion; of acquiring property and of pursuing happiness & Safety; of Speaking, writing and publishing their Sentiments with decency and freedom . . . . Of these rights therefore they Shall not be deprived by the Government of the united States.225 That one of the primary contributors of the Ninth Amendment specifically noted—in a draft of the precise amendment that, this article argues, governs construction of through ecclesiastical, manorial, and common-law courts, and eventually made its way back into both English common law and American common law. That it was “out of vogue” in 1791 should not alter its Ninth Amendment status when it fits under the other two theories for filling the “rights retained” set. See, e.g., supra notes 113-25 and accompanying text. 225 THE RIGHTS RETAINED BY THE PEOPLE: THE HISTORY AND MEANING OF THE NINTH AMENDMENT app. A, at 351 (Randy Barnett ed., 1989) (emphasis added). 2012] RESCUING DIGNITARY TORTS 115 the speech right when it clashes with dignitary interests—an internal limitation on the speech rights conferred by the government suggests that the Ninth Amendment has always provided a structural foothold for the dignitary torts within the constitutional scheme. This view was reasserted as recently as 1965, when the Court was just beginning the constitutionalization of the defamation tort. In Rosenblatt v. Baer, where the Court held that the government-employed operator of a municipal recreation area was subject to the scrutiny provided for public officials in Sullivan, Justice Stewart’s concurrence pointed to the Ninth Amendment as a structural counterweight to the First when speech and dignitary interests clash: It is a fallacy . . . to assume that the First Amendment is the only guidepost in the area of state defamation laws. It is not. . . . The right of a man to the protection of his own reputation from unjustified invasion and wrongful hurt reflects no more than our basic concept of the essential dignity and worth of every human being—a concept at the root of any decent system of ordered liberty. The protection of private personality, like the protection of life itself, is left primarily to the individual States under the Ninth and Tenth Amendments. . . . [T]his does not mean that the right is entitled to any less recognition by this Court as a basic of our constitutional system.226 The dignitary torts are—under more than one theory of Ninth Amendment rights retained—entitled to some consideration within the constitutional scheme. In short, they cannot mechanistically be subordinated to the First Amendment simply because they are inflicted via speech. VI. A NINTH AMENDMENT “COMPARATIVE IMPAIRMENT” TEST A faithful application of the Ninth Amendment requires that changes to the scope of the dignitary torts achieved via application of the First Amendment must be the product of constitutional balancing, and at least some consideration of the social values they serve. Given the ambiguous scope of the Ninth Amendment—prohibiting both “denial” of a right retained via application of another enumerated right and “disparagement” of a right retained—the amendment’s text does not dictate the balancing test that should be applied to resolve clashes of enumerated versus retained rights. Laurence 226 Rosenblatt v. Baer, 383 U.S. 75, 92 (1966) (Stewart, J., concurring). 116 BROOKLYN LAW REVIEW [Vol. 78:1 Claus has suggested that the text points to a “hard” version of the Ninth Amendment that places identifiable limits on the exercise of constitutional rights, and a “soft” version that sets up a “balancing [i]nquiry” between the retained right and the constitutional right.227 A “hard” Ninth Amendment, which would prohibit the application of any constitutional right to invalidate a contrary retained right—at least under a staterights model—essentially amounts to reverse preemption.228 This result seems impractical and inconsistent with the intent of the Framers. A “soft” Ninth Amendment, however, is far easier to conceive and apply. In the contest of rights versus rights, where categorical hierarchy of enumerated rights is barred by the Ninth Amendment, some other tumbler must be used to sort the competing interests and determine which right prevails. This process—comparing the contrary commands given by two sources of law absent any textual guidance—is remarkably similar to the exercise undertaken by courts conducting choice of law inquiries. This article proposes that a relatively modern choice of law analysis—comparative impairment—supplies a neat test for prioritizing among competing enumerated and unenumerated-but-retained rights. Not coincidentally, one delegate suggested modifying the Ninth Amendment by replacing the word “disparage” with the word “impair,” which he claimed was a clearer indication of the Framers’ intent.229 Although the proposal was rejected, it provides some insight into the underlying concerns of the Framers for purposes of devising a Ninth Amendment balancing test. Comparative impairment, a member of the “interest analysis” family of choice of law systems, proposes that every law has two effects—one internal and one external. When the laws of two states conflict, its author suggests, a court should identify the internal and external effects of the two laws.230 Courts adjudicating a case with multistate elements and conflicting state laws should choose whichever one will, when applied, least impair the internal effectiveness of the competing law. So, for instance, in the classic example given by proponent William Baxter, State X has a usury statute protecting a 227 Claus, supra note 43, at 618-20. See, e.g., Calvin Massey, The Anti-Federalist Ninth Amendment and Its Implications for State Constitutional Law, 1990 WIS. L. REV. 1229, 1232 (1990). 229 Williams, supra note 39, at 517-18. 230 William F. Baxter, Choice of Law and the Federal System, 16 STAN. L. REV. 1, 17-18 (1963). 228 2012] RESCUING DIGNITARY TORTS 117 particular class of borrowers and State Y does not.231 In a case where a protected X borrower gets a loan from a Y lender, X law should apply. Why? [Applying Y law] would give maximum scope to Y’s policies but would seriously impair those of X. The protection X has afforded its borrowers probably has several consequences. Local lenders may make loans to the better risks within the class at the maximum legal rate, a rate somewhat lower than otherwise would have been afforded them, rather than forego entirely that segment of business. But another part of the protected class is denied local loans and therefore has an incentive to borrow outside the state. If [Y law is applied], . . . the purpose of the X lawmakers will be substantially impaired by the emergence of a flock of lenders just across the state line. . . . [Applying X law] affords maximum implementation of the policies of both states. . . . [T]he objectives of X, the borrower’s state, would be shielded from wholesale evasion: the nature of the transaction assures that prior to extending credit the lender will discover in most cases the borrower’s residence and in many cases other characteristics of membership in the protected class [and would decline the loan application without incurring any injury].232 Importing this “comparative impairment” test to the Ninth Amendment context would achieve similar results. The objectives of neither the dignitary torts nor the Speech and Press Clauses would be categorically wiped out if the Court were to decide which took priority by examining the relative impairment on the other and choose the one that worked the lesser impairment in the particular circumstance.233 231 Id. at 14. Id. at 14-15. 233 Granted, this approach would not give speakers bright-line guidance in every case ex ante. However, because the dignitary interests are treated via private, tort causes of action rather than via criminal statute, the speech at interest is not categorically prohibited. The speakers would be free to circulate their statements, but would be at risk of being ordered to internalize via monetary payment the externalities imposed by their speech if it injured a third party. Absent application of the First Amendment to this segment of tort law, the speaker and the injured would be in the same relative position as the rancher and the farmer in Coase’s notorious The Problem of Social Cost. R.H. Coase, The Problem of Social Cost, reprinted in LAW, ECONOMICS AND PHILOSOPHY: A CRITICAL INTRODUCTION WITH APPLICATION FOR THE LAW OF TORTS (Mark Kuperberg & Charles Beitz eds., 1983); see also Justin Desautels-Stein, The Market as a Legal Concept, 60 BUFF. L. REV. 387, 450-54 (2012). Coase’s Theorem applies just as well to the speaker-injured scenario as it does to the rancher-farmer: left to their own devices (assuming the existence of dignitary torts to stand in for physical vengeance but removing the constitutional insulation from liability for the speaker, a tenable assumption given that Coase does not see the common law as state action, but as a predicate for bargaining, whereas application of First Amendment restrictions to the common law is more akin to state action), the two parties would bargain toward an economically efficient outcome. In the speech scenario, the likely outcome is the provision of insurance for speakers whose words might injure. In fact, defamation insurance existed at the time Sullivan was decided, although the Court did not 232 118 BROOKLYN LAW REVIEW [Vol. 78:1 For example, in Sullivan, if the Court applied comparative impairment, it would have found that the internal effect of Alabama’s defamation law was to protect the reputations of its citizens from false statements. The external effect of the state law was to permit heavy damage awards against publishers, including out-of-state papers such as the Times, which was considered by many in the state an “outside agitator.”234 The internal effect of the First Amendment is to protect speakers from state regulation of their speech. The external effect of the First Amendment is to permit speech even when it could harm an individual’s reputation. Applying Alabama’s defamation law as interpreted by the state court, rather than applying the First Amendment in the case, would have achieved the law’s internal goal—protecting the reputation of Commissioner L.B. Sullivan235—but would have significantly impaired the right of the New York Times to speak free from state regulation. In contrast, applying the First Amendment to protect the Times’ ability to run an advertisement criticizing government officials fully realizes the internal goals of the enumerated right. It does not, however, significantly impair the internal effect of Alabama’s defamation law. While that law was designed to protect individual reputations, several of its elements were apparently not satisfied in the Sullivan case, the jury’s verdict notwithstanding.236 Thus, a comparative impairment analysis points to a preference for the enumerated right in this case. consider whether the market was already providing efficient protection for injurious speakers. Notably, defamation insurance policies continue to be sold today, primarily to media companies (although increasingly as riders to homeowner policies for poorly capitalized bloggers). This dynamic raises the interesting possibility that between the Constitution and the market, speech is overinsured and thus, speakers are incentivized to produce more injurious speech. This is a particularly dangerous problem when crossreferenced with the diminishment of the dignitary tort recourse. 234 N.Y. Times Co. v. Sullivan, 376 U.S. 254, 294 (1964). 235 Id. at 256. 236 For example, it is debatable whether Sullivan was actually “identified” in the advertisement. See, e.g., id. at 288-89 (expressing the Court’s view that the jury erred in finding that the ad, in which “[t]here was no reference to respondent . . . either by name or official position” was “of and concerning him” as required by Alabama law). In addition, the falsehoods in the advertisement were arguably immaterial, including a mistake regarding the song that activists sang during a university protest and a characterization of the police as having “rung” the campus when, in fact, they were not standing in an unbroken ring. See id. at 258-59. Further, a cynic might wonder whether the average member of the (white) community in Montgomery actually held Sullivan in lower esteem for taking a hard line against the civil rights activists whose efforts were not supported by most city residents. The Court suggested as much. See id. at 260. 2012] RESCUING DIGNITARY TORTS 119 The same comparative impairment analysis yields a different result in Snyder. There, the internal effect of the Maryland intentional infliction law was to protect individuals from emotional anguish inflicted by those who speak abusively of or disrespect the dead. The external effect of the law is to extract monetary payment from speakers whose words injure and thereby potentially chill injurious speech.237 Again, the internal effect of the First Amendment is to protect speakers from state regulation of their speech, while the external effect of the amendment is to permit speech even when it can inflict emotional anguish. Here, application of the Maryland intentional infliction law would have achieved its internal effect by vindicating the plaintiff-father for slurs about his deceased son that were circulating on the day of his son’s funeral and in perpetuity thereafter on the Internet. The external effect of its application would have been to require the funeral protesters to compensate the father for the injury their chosen method of protest inflicted. However, barring them ex ante from protesting as they wished would not be an effect of applying the Maryland law, so there is little impairment of the internal effect of the First Amendment. Had they wished to avoid the ex post compensation ordered by the jury, they could have vigorously discussed their views on the American military and homosexuality generally without circulating false and demeaning information about the plaintiff’s son, a private individual. In contrast, applying the First Amendment as the Court did achieved the First Amendment internal effect of protecting the protesters’ speech, but significantly impaired the father’s right to be made whole for the injuries the protesters inflicted. Thus, because application of the First Amendment more impairs the internal working of the IIED right retained than application of the right retained impairs the right to speech, the right retained is preferred under a “comparative impairment” Ninth Amendment analysis. One could argue that the Court’s requirement in Sullivan that public figures prove a speaker’s “actual malice” before recovering in defamation is sufficient to balance free speech interests against dignitary tort interests.238 Why, then, is 237 See, e.g., supra notes 30-35 and accompanying text (discussing the speech at issue in Snyder and the externalities of that speech imposed on the plaintiff-father). 238 Claus, for one, has stated that a “soft” version of the Ninth Amendment would require, in a defamation case, that “the interest underlying defamation law must be accorded its appropriate weight.” Claus, supra note 43, at 618-19. In Sullivan, the Court did not wipe out the Alabama cause of action for defamation altogether, and did 120 BROOKLYN LAW REVIEW [Vol. 78:1 it inadequate to satisfy the demands of the Ninth Amendment? Most important, it fails because current speech–tort jurisprudence is not conducted within an acknowledged Ninth Amendment framework, meaning that balancing the rights of the individual and state to legal recourse for dignitary injuries against the rights of speakers is not a mandatory step in the analysis. Snyder, in which the Court indicated that it had no choice but to protect the injurious speech, illustrates the fact that absent a Ninth Amendment requirement to acknowledge and balance the “right retained,” the constitutional right can automatically occupy the field.239 Second, the “actual malice” test has been so embroidered by corollary principles that it no longer functions as a neutral test for sifting through the facts and interests represented by a particular case.240 Finally, because tort suits are brought by individual plaintiffs, and because the actual malice test inquires only into the status of the plaintiff and the actions of the defendant, the interests of the state in permitting common-law recovery for dignitary torts are not fully accounted for.241 The Ninth Amendment mandates a mechanism by which dignitary rights are weighed in such cases, and “actual malice” in its existing incarnation fails because it is optional and arguably constitutionalizes an undervaluation of the dignitary interests. Comparative impairment, in contrast, would be a mandatory test compelled by the Ninth Amendment rule of construction when enumerated rights clash with unenumeratedbut-retained rights. In addition, it requires articulation of the intended effects of the dignitary and speech laws and calculation not wipe out the New York Times’ speech rights altogether. Instead, it “narrowed the . . . reach of state defamation law” and employed a “limiting construction of the constitutional right to freedom of speech” by permitting private individuals to sue for defamation without the application of First Amendment guard rails, and permitting public figures to recover only in limited circumstances where the speaker had abused its free speech rights by knowingly or recklessly publishing untruths that blemished reputation. Id. One could interpret this as a “soft” test under which the interests served by Alabama defamation law were considered and assigned an “optimal” weight in relation to the speech rights involved. 239 See supra note 32 and accompanying text; see also Snyder v. Phelps, 131 S. Ct. 1207, 1219-20 (2011). 240 In particular, constitutional rules that carve wide latitude for speech about “public figures” who have no influence on public affairs but are merely of some interest to the public, allowing “rhetorical hyperbole,” permitting deliberate non-material misquotation, shifting the burden of proof on key issues from the defendant to the plaintiff, taking consideration of key elements from the jury and imposing a standard of de novo rather than clearly erroneous review on appeal leave virtually no room to consider the dignitary rights of the plaintiff or the state’s interest in allowing peaceful recourse for dignitary injuries. See Anderson, supra note 21, at 787. 241 See id. at 771-74. 2012] RESCUING DIGNITARY TORTS 121 of the impairment that would result for each if the others were applied. This is a methodical approach that guarantees some valuation of dignitary interests regardless of where the speech– dignity line is ultimately drawn in a particular case. CONCLUSION Current First Amendment theory consistently undervalues the role of the dignitary torts.242 If the Constitution incorporates a preference for speech over the right to protect dignitary interest, it compels this result. But if dignitary interests have some constitutional parity with speech rights, speech will not always automatically trump dignity. This article suggests that under the “right-versus-right” rule of construction theory of the Ninth Amendment, dignitary rights are protected from the diminishment that necessarily follows from an expansive reading of the First Amendment. Freed from constitutional compulsion to shrink dignitary torts, courts may take into account the social value of those torts and reassert them accordingly within the constitutional scheme. Tort law serves a crucial social goal. First and foremost, it offers a peaceful means of resolving private disputes. Human nature responds to perceived wrongs with vengeance. “Tort law promotes the law’s civilizing function.”243 Thus, “an imbalance [between tort law and speech law] could lead to . . . extralegal and socially dangerous self-help.”244 Indeed, news accounts suggest that those who are hamstrung in asserting their dignity interests against speech, particularly children and teens, may resort to self-help in the form of suicide or interpersonal violence.245 242 Not coincidentally, perhaps, this erosion has coincided with what some torts advocates describe as a certain scholarly contempt for the entire field of tort law. “Torts seems often to be conceived as a course that teaches students how common law allocates the costs of accidents,” and as a result, is viewed as “ad hoc and esoteric.” Goldberg & Zipursky, supra note 2, at 918. 243 Deana Pollard Sacks, Snyder v. Phelps, The Supreme Court’s Speech-Tort Jurisprudence, and Normative Considerations, 120 YALE L.J. ONLINE 193, 199 (2010) (internal quotation marks omitted). 244 Id. at 194. 245 See, e.g., Robert D. Richards, Sex, Lies and the Internet: Balancing First Amendment Interests, Reputational Harm, and Privacy in the Age of Blogs and Social Networking Sites, 8 FIRST AMEND. L. REV. 176, 179-80 (2009) (documenting instances in which the inability to assert reputational interests in the face of demeaning speech led to self-help); see also A.G. Sulzberger, In Small Towns, Gossip Moves to Web, and Turns Vicious, N.Y. TIMES, Sept. 20, 2011, at A1 (reporting that comments on Topix news sites in rural areas had “provoked fights and caused divorces”). In many of these high-profile cases, the injured could not assert dignity rights against the speaker 122 BROOKLYN LAW REVIEW [Vol. 78:1 These insights apply with unique force in the subset of torts that compensate for lost dignity, honor, reputation, or well-being. Unlike other torts, where loss allocation is arguably the foremost goal, a money verdict is often more symbolic than compensatory in the dignitary torts.246 The mere fact of a verdict in the plaintiff’s favor, regardless of the dollar amount, can serve to restore the plaintiff and the defendant to the equal status they occupied prior to the dignity-injuring speech, thus valuing both speech and the interests it can harm.247 To the extent that American society values lower rates of interpersonal violence, courts and policymakers should reevaluate a constitutional scheme that has over the past decades significantly undermined the availability of the dignitary torts to peacefully vindicate these interests. because the speaker was anonymous. However, the impulse to self-help arguably arises regardless of the reason the injured is thwarted in a quest for vindication, whether it be inability to identify him or a legal doctrine that tells him his well-being is less important than the speech that harmed him. See PINKER, supra note 13, at 99 (explaining that “retaliation after an insult” is one of the triggers for violence that leads to homicide). 246 See, e.g., Walter V. Schaefer, Defamation and the First Amendment, 52 U. COLO. L. REV. 1, 15 (1980) (“[C]oncentration upon a money judgment as the appropriate remedy for defamation is a defect that has plagued the common law since it first undertook to substitute a legal remedy for private vengeance.”); see also THE COST OF LIBEL, supra note 18, at 25 (documenting that a substantial number of plaintiffs would have forgone tort suits if they had been offered an apology for the complained-of speech). 247 See, e.g., Solomon, supra note 2, at 1784 n.105 (outlining theories that tort law establishes expectations that injurer and injured are equals). NOTES Giving Battered Immigrant Fiancées a Way Out of Abusive Relationships PROPOSED AMENDMENTS TO THE IMMIGRATION AND NATIONALITY ACT INTRODUCTION Ayana is an Ethiopian woman who fell in love with Jason, a United States Citizen (USC) from New York City.1 They met at the hotel where Ayana worked while Jason was vacationing in Addis Ababa. During their courtship, which lasted several years, Ayana bore three children over the course of Jason’s many visits to her country. In 2010, Jason filed a petition for a K Visa, which allowed Ayana, along with her children, to leave her home in Ethiopia and move to the United States as Jason’s fiancée.2 In order to obtain the visa, Ayana and Jason were required to show 1 This is a hypothetical real-world situation, using pseudonyms, which reflects the facts of real clients’ stories from my work as an Edward V. Sparer Public Interest Law Fellow at African Services Committee in New York City during the summer of 2011. 2 The K-1 Visa allows a foreign fiancée to immigrate to the United States in order to marry her intended USC spouse. The K-2 Visa is granted to derivative beneficiaries, such as Ayana’s children, who move with the K-1 Visa holder as intended immigrants. SARAH IGNATIUS & ELISABETH S. STICKNEY, NAT’L LAWYERS GUILD, IMMIGRATION LAW AND THE FAMILY § 8:26 (2011); see also id. § 9:54 n.3 (“The visa itself is known as the K visa. The principal receives a K-1 visa; derivative beneficiaries receive K-2 visas.”). This note will refer generally to the principal K-1 Visa beneficiary, like Ayana, as a “K Visa holder.” A K Visa holder can be a man (fiancé) or a woman (fiancée) who is engaged to be married. Fiancé Definition, MERRIAM-WEBSTER.COM, http://www.merriamwebster.com/dictionary/fiance (last visited Sept. 26, 2012); Fiancée Definition, MERRIAM-WEBSTER.COM, http://www.merriam-webster.com/dictionary/fiancee (last visited Sept. 26, 2012). I will generally use the feminine term fiancée to refer to abused K Visa holders, since the majority of them are women. However, when a specific usage is pertinent for illustrative purposes, I will use one term or the other (e.g. Ayana’s fiancé, Jason vs. Jason’s fiancée, Ayana). 123 124 BROOKLYN LAW REVIEW [Vol. 78:1 evidence of their relationship, as well as their intent to marry within ninety days of Ayana’s arrival in the United States.3 Unfortunately, shortly after she moved into Jason’s apartment in New York City, Ayana was surprised to find that Jason was not the man she had fallen in love with. He started abusing Ayana and using drugs in front of their children, he strictly controlled the family’s finances, and he even threatened to have her deported if she did not obey him. Since Ayana spoke almost no English, was unfamiliar with her new surroundings, and had very little money of her own, she felt isolated and completely dependent upon Jason. Moreover, because she feared deportation, she was reluctant to contact the police to report the violence that Jason used to control her. Although unfamiliar with the intricacies of U.S. immigration law, Ayana knew that she would risk overstaying her visa if she failed to marry Jason within the K Visa’s ninetyday window. She was aware that, ultimately, refusing to marry Jason would result in forfeiting her right to apply for permanent residency in the United States as an immediate relative of a USC.4 However, Ayana knew that staying in this abusive relationship would be unhealthy for her and her children, so she made the brave decision to leave Jason and seek refuge in a domestic violence shelter. Once there, she was able to find legal assistance with the child custody proceedings Jason had initiated against her, in which he raised Ayana’s lack of valid immigration status as a reason to grant him custody of the children.5 Yet despite the legal support Ayana 3 See infra notes 27-33, describing the evidentiary requirements of the K Visa. A K-1 Visa holder is only eligible to adjust to conditional permanent resident status on the basis of marriage to the USC who petitioned for the K Visa. IGNATIUS & STICKNEY, supra note 2, § 8:26; see also Markovski v. Gonzales, 486 F.3d 108, 111 (4th Cir. 2007) (“[T]he language of the statute itself is not ambiguous and bars beneficiaries of the K-1 Visa from adjusting status on any basis other than marriage to the petition sponsor.”); Kalal v. Gonzales, 402 F.3d 948, 949 (9th Cir. 2005) (“A K-1 Visa is issued for the sole purpose of facilitating a valid marriage between an alien and a [USC], and that marriage must take place within ninety days of entry.” (citing 8 U.S.C.A. §§ 1101(a)(15)(K)(i), 1184(d)(1) (West 2012))). 5 This should serve as an illustration of how an abusive USC partner might use the abused immigrant’s status as a tool to exert control over her. “An abusive husband may easily use his spouse’s immigration status, or lack thereof, as a means of control and repression.” Katerina Shaw, Note, Barriers to Freedom: Continued Failure of U.S. Immigration Laws to Offer Equal Protection to Immigrant Battered Women, 15 CARDOZO J.L. & GENDER 663, 665 (2009). This “means of control” can be even more severe when it concerns an abused immigrant fiancée who has not yet married her abusive partner. But even for those like Ayana in child custody proceedings, the relevance of her immigration status may be left to the discretion of the Family Court under the “best interests of the child” standard, and Ayana may nevertheless be given full custody of the children if she is deemed the more suitable parent despite her lack of 4 2012] IMPROVEMENTS FOR IMMIGRANT FIANCÉES 125 received, she had few options, if any, to adjust her immigration status; by not marrying Jason, she had relinquished the legal basis to adjust her immigration status to conditional permanent residency.6 This example illustrates an all-too-frequent conundrum that beleaguers K Visa holders who are abused by their intended spouses.7 Although Congress has enacted numerous measures intended to protect battered immigrants,8 such measures have focused on battered immigrant spouses of USCs or lawful permanent residents (LPRs), whereas abused immigrant fiancées have been left out in the cold. For example, the Violence Against Women Act of 1994 (VAWA) was intended to “permit[] battered immigrant women to leave their batterers without fearing deportation.”9 Among other protections, VAWA created—by amending the Immigration and Nationality Act (INA)10—what is known as the “VAWA selfpetition,” which allows abused spouses of USCs and LPRs to file for adjustment of immigration status—to that of permanent residency—on their own behalf, rather than relying on their abusive spouses to sponsor their applications for adjustment of status.11 Unfortunately, VAWA’s self-petition provision does not permit abused women who travel to the United States on fiancée visas to file self-petitions unless they have married their intended spouses, since marriage is the basis for adjustment of status.12 Instead, their options are limited: (1) return to their home countries;13 (2) remain in the United States illegally; (3) valid immigration status. Although she could win the child custody battle, she would still lack legal status and would remain subject to deportation. 6 See supra note 4. 7 Although, presumably, immigrant men as well as women may be abused by their partners, for the purposes of this note, and for editorial ease, it will be assumed that the hypothetical abused partner is a woman. “Approximately 95% of all domestic violence victims are women.” Timm v. Delong, 59 F. Supp. 2d 944, 951 (D. Neb. 1998) (quoting H.R. REP. NO. 103-395, at 26 (1993)). “Unlike most violence against men, most violence against women takes place within family or intimate relationships.” Sally F. Goldfarb, The Supreme Court, The Violence Against Women Act, and the Use and Abuse of Federalism, 71 FORDHAM L. REV. 57, 106 n.309 (2002). Perhaps this underscores a need to address the plight of abused immigrant men, who may be overlooked. Nevertheless, the focus of this note is on abused immigrant K Visa holders, most of whom are women. 8 See, e.g., discussion infra Part II. 9 Hernandez v. Ashcroft, 345 F.3d 824, 841 (9th Cir. 2003) (alteration in original) (citing H.R. REP. NO. 103-395, at 25 (1993)) (internal quotation marks omitted). 10 See 8 U.S.C.A. § 1101 (West 2012). 11 8 U.S.C.A. § 1154(a)(1)(A)(v)(I)(cc) (West 2011). 12 See supra note 4. 13 This option may be very dangerous for some women, because of the lack of domestic violence law enforcement in other countries, for example, as discussed infra notes 42-48 and accompanying text. 126 BROOKLYN LAW REVIEW [Vol. 78:1 proceed with the marriage to an abusive partner; or (4) seek some other less desirable and more arduous avenue to legal immigration status, such as a U Visa or T Visa.14 If the K Visa holder does not marry her abusive fiancé during the K Visa’s ninety-day window—and instead leaves him to escape the abuse—a devastating cascade of events will ensue: her visa will expire, she will no longer possess legal immigration status, and she will be precluded from self-petitioning under VAWA.15 Worst of all, she will be subject to removal from the United States.16 The exclusion of abused fiancées from VAWA selfpetitions, and the lack of adequate immigration relief alternatives, creates a perverse incentive for battered women to remain with their batterers in order to receive immigration benefits.17 This is the same incentive that the VAWA selfpetition was designed to eliminate among vulnerable immigrant populations; in particular, the self-petition was intended to empower women to extricate themselves from abusive relationships without fearing a violation of immigration law. As noted by the U.S. Court of Appeals for the Ninth Circuit: Congress’s goal in enacting VAWA was to eliminate barriers to women leaving abusive relationships. . . . The notion that Congress would require women to remain with their batterers in order to be eligible for the forms of relief established in VAWA is flatly contrary 14 Both of these types of visas, as well as other types of immigration relief, and their drawbacks for K Visa holders, are discussed infra at Part III. These other avenues to relief are less desirable in comparison to the self-petition because they do not provide immediate adjustment of status to lawful permanent residence. In addition, their evidentiary requirements may make these forms of relief more arduous to obtain, as discussed infra at Parts III.B and III.C. 15 8 U.S.C.A. §§ 1154, 1255(d); see also Markovski v. Gonzales, 486 F.3d 108, 110 (4th Cir. 2007) (“On its face, subsection (d) [of § 1255 of the Immigration and Nationality Act (INA)] prohibits an alien who arrived on the K-1 fiancé visa from adjusting his status on any basis whatever save for the marriage to the K-1 visa sponsor.”); AUSTIN T. FRAGOMEN, JR. ET AL., IMMIGRATION PROCEDURES HANDBOOK § 20:5 (2012). 16 See, e.g., Kalal v. Gonzales, 402 F.3d 948 (9th Cir. 2005) (denying petition for review of Board of Immigration Appeals’ decision that summarily affirmed an immigration judge’s removal order, where alien failed to marry her petitioning USC fiancé and instead married another after the ninety-day marriage period had lapsed). 17 The benefits that may be available to fiancées who marry their abusers and subsequently file self-petitions include eligibility to adjust status to become an LPR, to be authorized to work, and to receive certain public assistance. See IGNATIUS & STICKNEY, supra note 2, §§ 8:24, 8:42; U.S. Dep’t of Health & Human Servs., Domestic Violence Fact Sheet: Access to HHS-Funded Services for Immigrant Survivors of Domestic Violence, HHS.GOV, http://www.hhs.gov/ocr/civilrights/resources/specialtopics/ origin/domesticviolencefactsheet.html (last updated Aug. 22, 2012). 2012] IMPROVEMENTS FOR IMMIGRANT FIANCÉES 127 to Congress’s articulated purpose in enacting [the cancellation of removal provision].18 Few would doubt that protecting abused immigrant fiancées—some of the most vulnerable members of our society— is a noble cause, yet even a modest proposal for immigration reform is naturally met by some resistance. Foremost among concerns is that offering new forms of immigration relief to K Visa holders could increase opportunities for fraud, both by those initially applying for K Visas—who may lack genuine intent to marry their USC petitioners—and by those claiming abuse once they arrive in the United States.19 However, instances of such fraud are rare,20 and moreover, current evidentiary requirements in the K Visa application and VAWA self-petition process provide ample deterrents to combat fraud.21 Most importantly, the need to protect abused K Visa holders, who are currently relegated to a state of legal limbo, is profound enough to warrant added protections.22 This note, for the first time in the academic literature, examines the failure of U.S. immigration laws to adequately protect battered immigrant fiancées and proposes legal amendments to ameliorate this problem. Part I describes the fiancée visa (K Visa) process and highlights the unique position in which abused immigrant fiancées find themselves in relation to U.S. immigration law. Part II provides a historical overview of the VAWA self-petition and related provisions in U.S. immigration law that were devised to protect battered immigrants. Part III outlines potential relief currently available to abused K Visa holders and addresses the inadequacies of 18 Hernandez v. Ashcroft, 345 F.3d 824, 841 (2003). The court referred to section 244(a)(3) of the INA, which details the procedures for “suspension of deportation,” now known as “cancellation of removal.” See 8 U.S.C.A. § 1229(b) (West 2008); see also NAT’L IMMIGRATION PROJECT OF THE NAT’L LAWYERS GUILD, 1 IMMIGRATION LAW & DEFENSE § 8:17 (2012) [hereinafter 1 IMMIGR. L. & DEF.] (discussing “cancellation of removal for certain nonpermanent residents”). 19 See, e.g., Battered Immigrant Women Protection Act of 1999: Hearing on H.R. 3083 Before the Subcomm. on Immigration and Claims of the H. Comm. on the Judiciary, 106th Cong. (2000) [hereinafter H.R. 3083 Hearing], available at http://commdocs.house.gov/committees/judiciary/hju66253.000/hju66253_0f.htm; infra Part IV.A. Additional concerns include the increased number of immigrants who may benefit from expanding protections, as well as the fact that providing additional relief to K Visa holders would treat them more like married self-petitioners than temporary nonimmigrants. See H.R. 3083 Hearing, supra, at 36, 39. 20 See, e.g., James A. Jones, Comment, The Immigration Marriage Fraud Amendments: Sham Marriages or Sham Legislation?, 24 FLA. ST. U. L. REV. 679, 698700 (1997); see also infra notes 189-91 and accompanying text. 21 See infra Part IV.A. 22 For a more thorough discussion of counter-arguments, see infra notes 184-95. 128 BROOKLYN LAW REVIEW [Vol. 78:1 those remedies. Finally, Part IV offers practical solutions to the troubling legal position of abused immigrant fiancées like Ayana. Ultimately, this note argues that Congress should amend the INA to allow abused immigrant fiancées to file selfpetitions for adjustment of immigration status, or alternatively, that certain requirements of the U Visa23 should be relaxed in order to allow abused fiancées to safely and effectively seek lawful adjustment of their immigration status. I. THE K VISA PROCESS AND THE UNIQUE POSITION OF K VISA HOLDERS IN RELATION TO U.S. IMMIGRATION LAW Before coming to the United States, Ayana, like other K Visa holders, was in a unique position in relation to U.S. immigration law because she planned to immigrate to the United States but was not yet eligible to do so, since the basis for permanent residency—her marriage to Jason—had yet to take place.24 Moreover, Ayana was “technically ineligible to enter . . . on a temporary nonimmigrant visa” because of her intent to become a permanent resident.25 The K Visa solves this problem by granting fiancées “a nonimmigrant visa which recognizes the beneficiary’s intent to immigrate based on her planned marriage.”26 However, obtaining a K Visa is no simple task. First, the K Visa applicant (i.e., the prospective immigrant) must be engaged to a USC who files a petition form I-129F for her visa application.27 After the petition is approved, U.S. Citizenship and Immigration Services (USCIS)28 will conduct a background 23 The U Visa is available to immigrant victims of certain qualifying crimes who are, have been, or are likely to be helpful in the investigation or prosecution of those crimes. 8 U.S.C. § 1101(a)(15)(U)(i) (2006). In particular, this note will argue that the “law enforcement certification” requirement—which is difficult for many abused fiancées to satisfy—should be lifted for K Visa holders. See infra Parts III.B and IV.B. 24 IGNATIUS & STICKNEY, supra note 2, § 14:5. 25 Id. 26 Id.; see also 3A AM. JUR. 2D Aliens and Citizens § 912 (2012). A K-1 visa holder is not an immigrant, but rather, as relevant here, is a person who “is the fiancee or fiance of a citizen of the United States and who seeks to enter the United States solely to conclude a valid marriage with the petitioner within ninety days after admission.” Kalal v. Gonzales, 402 F.3d 948, 950 (9th Cir. 2005) (quoting 8 U.S.C. § 1101(a)(15)(K)(i)). 27 Only USCs, not LPRs, are eligible to petition for their immigrant fiancées to receive K Visas. IGNATIUS & STICKNEY, supra note 2, § 14:7; see also 22 C.F.R. § 41.81 (2006). For more detailed information on the K Visa process and required forms, see U.S. Citizenship & Immigration Servs., I-129F, Petition for Alien Fiancé(e), USCIS.GOV, www.uscis.gov/i-129f (last updated July 25, 2012). 28 USCIS is the office within the U.S. Department of Homeland Security (DHS) which “oversees lawful immigration to the United States.” About Us, 2012] IMPROVEMENTS FOR IMMIGRANT FIANCÉES 129 check of the petitioner and forward the application to the consulate in the applicant’s country.29 There, the K Visa applicant must apply for the visa and submit to an interview with a consular official, where she must provide a sworn statement that she intends to marry her USC petitioner fiancé within ninety days of her admission into the United States.30 An applicant will be denied a K Visa “unless there is satisfactory evidence that the parties ‘have a bona fide intention to marry, and are legally able and actually willing to conclude a valid marriage in the United States within a period of ninety days after the alien’s arrival.’”31 To adequately demonstrate their mutual intent to marry, the couple must show that they have met within the two years before the petition was filed.32 To this end, the couple may provide evidence such as “affidavits, trip itineraries, plane ticket stubs, letters, phone bills, photographs taken of the couple together, and any other evidence which would corroborate the personal meeting.”33 The K Visa expires ninety days after the fiancée’s admission into the United States, under the expectation that the immigrant fiancée will marry the USC petitioner within that period of time.34 Once the fiancée marries the petitioner, and prior to their second anniversary, she can apply to adjust her immigration status to conditional permanent residency.35 If, USCIS.GOV, http://www.uscis.gov/aboutus (last updated Sept. 12, 2009); see also Department Components, DHS.GOV, http://www.dhs.gov/department-components (last visited Sept. 23, 2012); U.S. Dep’t of Homeland Sec. Organizational Chart, DHS.GOV, http://www.dhs.gov/xlibrary/assets/dhs-orgchart.pdf (last visited Sept. 23, 2012). DHS subsumed the Immigration and Naturalization Service (INS) in 2003, after passage of the Homeland Security Act of 2002, whereby USCIS assumed the immigration services (i.e. visa adjudication) functions of INS. Patricia Medige, Immigration Issues in a Security-Minded America, COLO. LAW., Mar. 2004, at 11-13 (U.S. Customs and Border Patrol (CBP) and Immigration Customs and Enforcement (ICE) assumed the inspection and enforcement functions of INS, respectively.); Who Joined DHS, DHS.GOV, http://www.dhs.gov/who-joined-dhs (last visited Sept. 25, 2012). 29 IGNATIUS & STICKNEY, supra note 2, § 14:7. 30 22 C.F.R. § 41.81(a)(2); IGNATIUS & STICKNEY, supra note 2, § 14:7. 31 Kalal, 402 F.3d at 950 (quoting 8 U.S.C. § 1184(d)). 32 IGNATIUS & STICKNEY, supra note 2, § 14:6. However, this requirement may be waived “only if it is established that compliance would result in extreme hardship to the petitioner or that compliance would violate strict and long-established customs of the K-1 beneficiary’s foreign culture . . . .” 8 C.F.R. § 214.2(k) (2011). 33 IGNATIUS & STICKNEY, supra note 2, § 14:6. 34 Id. § 14:7. 35 Id. § 14:9. Although the INS proposed a regulation that would prohibit adjustment to conditional residency status after a marriage exceeds two years, it is currently unclear whether the fiancée may adjust after the two-year anniversary. Id. § 14:9 n.3. But once conditional permanent residence is granted, the K Visa applicant and her spouse must file a Form I-751 to remove the conditional status of permanent residency within ninety days prior to the two year anniversary of the award 130 BROOKLYN LAW REVIEW [Vol. 78:1 however, they fail to marry during the ninety-day period, she will be prevented from adjusting her immigration status36 and will ultimately risk removal from the United States.37 These requirements present a special problem for K Visa holders who find themselves in abusive relationships before marrying their USC petitioners.38 If the relationship becomes abusive during the ninety-day window and before the marriage occurs, the immigrant fiancée will find herself in quite a predicament: if she decides not to marry her fiancé, she will be unable to obtain the immigration benefits of marriage and she will either become an out-of-status alien,39 be required to return home, or be forced to seek another form of immigration relief. On the other hand, she may be inclined to stay with her abusive fiancé in order to avail herself of the of conditional permanent resident status, and failure to timely do so without good cause will result in termination of such status and the initiation of removal proceedings. 8 C.F.R. § 216.4(a)(1), (a)(6) (2009). If all goes as planned, however, a K Visa applicant will eventually be able to adjust her status to lawful permanent residence and become a naturalized citizen, provided she is otherwise admissible pursuant to the INA. 36 8 U.S.C.A. § 1255(d) (West 2011); IGNATIUS & STICKNEY, supra note 2, § 14:5. But “[u]nder VAWA 2005, a K visa holder can change status to that of a T or UVisa.” Id. For a discussion of these remedies and why they are currently inadequate to protect abused immigrant fiancées in all cases, see infra Part III. 37 IGNATIUS & STICKNEY, supra note 2, § 14:7 n.23. “If she does not marry within that time, the beneficiary fiancé(e) becomes removable.” Id. 38 As in the case of “mail order brides,” where “it is not uncommon, after the fiancée has arrived on her K Visa and married the petitioning U.S. citizen, for the relationship to become an abusive one,” id. § 14:16, abuse does arise prior to marriages for some K Visa holders. Often this relationship will develop in person when the USC is courting the alien fiancée while abroad, rather than in a “mail order bride” scenario. In these situations, it is also not uncommon for “sex tourists” to court women and then become abusive and domineering once they bring the women to the United States. The USC may abuse the fiancée and then refuse to marry her, thereby using the K Visa holder’s resulting lack of immigration status as a means of holding power over her. E-mail and Telephone Interview with Andrea Panjwani, Supervising Attorney, African Servs. Comm. (Aug. 26, 2011) [hereinafter Panjwani Interview] (on file with author). Additionally, although the International Marriage Broker Regulation Act of 2005 (IMBRA) addressed some problems in the “mail order bride” industry— including limiting the number of K Visa petitions that may be filed by the same USC and creating a database to track repeat K Visa petitioners—IMBRA does not fully address the problems that face K Visa beneficiaries who enter their engagements through ordinary (in-person courtship) methods, but then find themselves in abusive relationships. See Christina Del Vecchio, Note, Match-Made in Cyberspace: How Best to Regulate the International Mail-Order Bride Industry, 46 COLUM. J. TRANSNAT’L L. 177, 200-01 (2007). 39 The term “out of status” means that she will no longer have valid immigration status and will be considered undocumented. See Out of Status Definition, Glossary of Visa Terms, U.S. DEP’T OF STATE, http://travel.state.gov/visa/frvi/ glossary/glossary_1363.html (last visited Sept. 25, 2012). 2012] IMPROVEMENTS FOR IMMIGRANT FIANCÉES 131 VAWA self-petition after the marriage is concluded.40 Given that the self-petition was specifically designed to remove abused immigrant spouses’ incentive to remain with their abusive spouses solely in order to obtain immigration benefits, the strict requirements of the K Visa—absent a safety valve similar to the VAWA self-petition—have produced a counterintuitive result.41 An immigrant fiancée should not be encouraged by the immigration laws to proceed with a marriage to an abusive partner. Yet that is exactly the situation women like Ayana are facing. Some may argue that Ayana—or any abused K Visa holder—can simply return to her country of origin since she did not marry her fiancé within requisite ninety days. However, returning home could be dangerous for several reasons.42 For example, if an abused K Visa holder is deported, she would be more vulnerable to future violence at the hands of her abusive partner, who could follow her and take advantage of the paucity of legal protections and remedies available to domestic violence victims in her home country.43 This is why some scholars have noted that immigration policy should not be based upon “the erroneous belief that deportation [will] bring an end to the domestic violence.”44 Additionally, many women “face severe social stigma if they [are] forced to return to their countries of origin after divorcing or separating from their husbands.”45 In some situations, such women may be forced to endure “political persecution, war, torture, jail, extreme poverty, disease, entrenched gender discrimination, or death.”46 40 This scenario assumes an element of shrewdness on the part of the immigrant fiancée, or could arise in a case where the fiancée encounters a lawyer or an acquaintance who gives her advice about her immigration options. 41 See supra notes 9, 17-18, and accompanying text. 42 Aside from being risky, returning home can also be problematic if the abused immigrant has had children with the USC and if she is deemed the more suitable parent, which is likely to be the case if her fiancé is abusive, as seen in Ayana’s custody battle. See supra note 5 and accompanying text. Indeed, it may be against public policy to remove an abused K Visa holder from the United States if it would result in “constructive deportation” of a USC child. See generally Jessie M. Mahr, Note, Protecting Our Vulnerable Citizens: Birthright Citizenship and the Call for Recognition of Constructive Deportation, 32 S. ILL. U. L.J. 723 (2008) (arguing that “constructive deportation” of USC children should be acknowledged, despite courts’ reluctance to do so, because, they reason, an alien parent who is ordered deported may simply leave a USC child—who has a right to remain in the United States—behind). 43 Leslye E. Orloff & Janice V. Kaguyutan, Offering a Helping Hand: Legal Protections for Battered Immigrant Women: A History of Legislative Responses, 10 AM. U. J. GENDER SOC. POL’Y & L. 95, 104, 133 (2001). 44 Id. at 104. 45 Id. at 135. 46 Id. at 136. 132 BROOKLYN LAW REVIEW [Vol. 78:1 It is not difficult to understand why a battered immigrant who returned home because she refused to proceed with the marriage would be similarly stigmatized.47 This danger is magnified in certain countries from which fiancées emigrate, where cultures may view a woman as married once she leaves the country to live with her husband-to-be.48 Nor should it be overlooked that the deportation of abused K Visa holders may result in a “chilling effect on other immigrant victims of domestic violence, making them reluctant to seek any help from the justice system.”49 It would be just as troubling if the law coerced future K Visa holders to endure abuse and marry their abusers in order to avoid deportation and avail themselves of other immigration benefits, such as the VAWA self-petition. Regrettably, however, the promise of VAWA—to allow immigrant women who suffer domestic violence to free themselves from their abusers without fearing legal penalties—is still inaccessible to Ayana and many other battered K Visa holders. II. HISTORY OF U.S. PROTECTIONS FOR BATTERED IMMIGRANT WOMEN U.S. immigration policy has been revised to protect battered immigrants numerous times since the early 1900s, yet abused immigrant fiancées have often been excluded.50 The prevalence of domestic violence in the United States, particularly violence that affects immigrant women, sheds some light on the dire need for such protections. When VAWA was first under consideration in 1993, congressional findings indicated that “in 1991 at least 21,000 domestic crimes against women were reported to police every week,” and that in addition to this astonishing rate, “domestic violence crimes [were] vastly under reported.”51 A 2000 study estimated that during their lives, nearly one-third of women in the United States suffer physical abuse by their husbands or other males they live 47 For an example, see N. v. Sweden, App. no. 23505/09, HUDOC (July 20, 2010), available at http://hudoc.echr.coe.int/sites/eng/pages/search.aspx?i=001-99992 (Eur. Ct. H.R.), discussed infra notes 175-78 and accompanying text. 48 See infra note 175 and accompanying text. 49 Orloff & Kaguyutan, supra note 43, at 104. 50 See, e.g., infra note 184 and accompanying text (discussing the proposed amendment to the Battered Immigrant Women Protection Act of 1999, H.R. 3083, which would have permitted abused K Visa holders to file VAWA self-petitions). 51 Orloff & Kaguyutan, supra note 43, at 109. 2012] IMPROVEMENTS FOR IMMIGRANT FIANCÉES 133 with.52 At that time, it was also estimated that “approximately 4.8 million intimate partner rapes and physical assaults [were] perpetrated against women annually.”53 Although the “annual incidence of domestic violence has decreased by 53 percent” since the passage of VAWA in 1994, “domestic and sexual violence remain a significant and widespread problem.”54 A more recent survey in 2010 indicated that more than one-third of women and one-quarter of men “in the United States have experienced rape, physical violence, and/or stalking by an intimate partner in their lifetime.”55 Today, virtually onequarter of women in the United States “report experiencing severe physical violence by an intimate partner . . . .”56 Not surprisingly, in light of these statistics, U.S. Surgeons General have underscored domestic violence as the most significant threat to women’s health in the United States.57 Because of their unique position as dependents of their abusers for legal immigration status, many immigrant women comprise an especially at-risk segment of society.58 For example, one study of female Latina and Filipina immigrants found that 48 percent of those surveyed reported an increase in domestic violence after they arrived in the United States.59 Additionally, in a separate study, 9 percent of the female respondents said that the abuse did not start until after they had immigrated.60 A full quarter of those respondents said that they decided not to leave their abusive partners because of their immigration status and fears of deportation.61 Another study, conducted by the National Institute of Justice, showed that 65 percent of the 52 Id.; see also FAMILY VIOLENCE PREVENTION FUND, INTIMATE PARTNER VIOLENCE IN IMMIGRANT AND REFUGEE COMMUNITIES 10 (2009). 53 Orloff & Kaguyutan, supra note 43, at 97. 54 S. REP. NO. 112-153, at 2 (2012). 55 MICHELE C. BLACK ET AL., NAT’L CTR. FOR INJURY PREVENTION & CONTROL, NATIONAL INTIMATE PARTNER AND SEXUAL VIOLENCE SURVEY: 2010 SUMMARY REPORT 2 (2011). 56 S. REP. NO. 112-153, at 3 (emphasis added). 57 Orloff & Kaguyutan, supra note 43, at 109 (citing S. REP. NO. 103-138, at 41-42 (1993)). 58 Shaw, supra note 5, at 665 (citing Giselle Aguilar Hass et al., Battered Immigrant and U.S. Citizen Spouses, LEGAL MOMENTUM, Apr. 24, 2006, at 2-3, available at http://www.legalmomentum.org/assets/pdfs/wwwbatteredimmsanduscspouses.pdf); see also FAMILY VIOLENCE PREVENTION FUND, supra note 52, at 12. 59 Shaw, supra note 5, at 665 (citing Mary Ann Dutton et al., Characteristics of Help-Seeking Behaviors, Resources and Service Needs of Battered Immigrant Latinas: Legal and Policy Implications, 7 GEO. J. POVERTY L. & POL’Y 245, 250 (2000)). 60 Hass et al., supra note 58, at 3 (discussing a survey conducted by AYUDA in the District of Columbia). 61 Id. 134 BROOKLYN LAW REVIEW [Vol. 78:1 women surveyed said that their abusers threatened them with deportation following their arrival to the United States.62 Troubling congressional findings that preceded the passage of VAWA in 1994 indicated that “[d]omestic battery problems can become terribly exacerbated in marriages where one spouse is not a citizen, and the non-citizen[’]s legal status depends on his or her marriage to the abuser.”63 At the time, the House Report also stressed that “[c]urrent law fosters domestic violence in such situations by placing full and complete control of the alien spouse’s ability to gain permanent legal status in the hands of the citizen.”64 While USC and LPR spouses are no longer given “full and complete control” over their spouses’ immigration status because of the VAWA self-petition, current law still affords abusive USCs a great deal of control over their immigrant fiancées’ ability to obtain permanent legal status.65 For women and their children who have immigrated to the United States, the dangers of abusive relationships are often more acute.66 For example, between 34 and 49.8 percent of immigrant women in the United States fall prey to domestic violence.67 This number spikes to 59.5 percent where only those immigrant women who are married are concerned.68 Further exacerbating the negative effects of domestic violence against immigrant women, many simply do not attempt to avail themselves of healthcare, law enforcement, or social services because of language and cultural barriers.69 These circumstances may help to explain why domestic violence against immigrant 62 Id. Disturbingly, some USC’s will actually engage in a form of immigration fraud in order to exert control over their immigrant partners, by having the immigrant travel to the United States on a K Visa although they are already married. Id. at 4. 63 H.R. REP. NO. 103-395, at 26 (1993). 64 Id. 65 See discussion supra Part I. 66 Orloff & Kaguyutan, supra note 43, at 110. But see FAMILY VIOLENCE PREVENTION FUND, supra note 52, at 11 (“According to a survey of literature . . . available research indicates that [intimate partner violence] is not more prevalent, and may be less prevalent, among immigrant and refugee population groups than others.”). 67 Karyl Alice Davis, Comment, Unlocking the Door by Giving Her the Key: A Comment on the Adequacy of the U-Visa as a Remedy, 56 ALA. L. REV. 557, 557 (2004) (citing H.R. 3083 Hearing, supra note 19, at 58 (statement of Leslye Orloff, Director, Immigrant Women Program, NOW Legal Defense and Education Fund)). 68 Id. 69 FAMILY VIOLENCE PREVENTION FUND, supra note 52, at 11-12, 50-51; Davis, supra note 67, at 558; see also S. REP. NO. 112-153, at 12 (2012) (“The abusers of undocumented immigrants often exploit the victims’ immigration status, leaving the victim afraid to report the abuse to law enforcement and fearful of assisting with the investigation and prosecution of associated crimes.”). 2012] IMPROVEMENTS FOR IMMIGRANT FIANCÉES 135 women occurs more often than is reported.70 In fact, a Department of Justice study found that just over 30 percent of documented immigrants officially report abuse.71 It is unsurprising, then, to find that undocumented immigrants who fear deportation report abuse at even lower rates, falling as low as 14 percent.72 It is difficult to obtain data on the prevalence of abuse against K Visa holders, perhaps because “a battered spouse [or fiancée] may be deterred from taking action to protect himself or herself, such as filing for a civil protection order, filing criminal charges, or calling the police, because of the threat or fear of deportation.”73 This disinclination to act may stem from an abused immigrant’s limited knowledge of English, a lack of savvy regarding the legal system and protections available to her, financial dependence on an abusive partner, or cultural isolation.74 An abused immigrant fiancée may be even more reluctant than an abused immigrant spouse to take official action because she stands on shakier ground in relation to U.S. immigration law, without the availability of the VAWA selfpetition. Now that the self-petition exists, as counterintuitive as it may seem, a battered K Visa holder like Ayana has an 70 Davis, supra note 67, at 558 (“[S]tatistics likely underestimate the number of victims.”); see also FAMILY VIOLENCE PREVENTION FUND, supra note 52, at 11 (describing the limited availability of data). 71 Juliette Terzieff, More Services Reach Abused Immigrant Women, WOMEN’S ENEWS (Aug. 11, 2005), http://www.womensenews.org/story/domesticviolence/050811/more-services-reach-abused-immigrant-women. Among all females in the United States as of 2008, the Bureau of Justice Statistics found that “49% of the intimate partner violence against [them] was reported to police.” SHANNAN CATALANO ET AL., BUREAU OF JUSTICE STATISTICS FEMALE VICTIMS OF VIOLENCE 2 (2009), available at http://bjs.ojp.usdoj.gov/content/pub/pdf/fvv.pdf. 72 See Terzieff, supra note 71. 73 H.R. REP. NO. 103-395, at 26 (1993); see also Laura Jontz, Note, Eighth Circuit to Battered Kenyan: Take a Safari—Battered Immigrants Face New Barrier When Reporting Domestic Violence, 55 DRAKE L. REV. 195, 197 (2006) (confirming that data on the prevalence of abuse is difficult to obtain because many incidents go unreported). I have been unable to locate data for statistics relating specifically to abused immigrant fiancées. Of course, it is possible that the incidence of domestic violence against immigrant fiancées is lower than for immigrant spouses, perhaps because domestic violence may not develop early in the relationship and it may increase in frequency and severity as the relationship progresses beyond marriage. Nevertheless, it can be presumed that such violence toward immigrant fiancées does occur at fairly high rates. For example, applying the aforementioned rates of domestic violence among immigrant women—the lowest rate of 34 percent, for example—to the 30,445 K-1 immigrant fiancées admitted to the United States in 2010, it appears that approximately 10,351 K Visa holders could have experienced abuse in that year alone. DEP’T OF HOMELAND SEC., 2010 YEARBOOK OF IMMIGRATION STATISTICS 66 tbl. 25: Nonimmigrant Admissions by Class of Admission: Fiscal Years 2001 to 2010 (2011), available at http://www.dhs.gov/xlibrary/assets/statistics/yearbook/2010/ois_yb_2010.pdf. 74 See Hass et al., supra note 58, at 2. 136 BROOKLYN LAW REVIEW [Vol. 78:1 even greater incentive to remain with her abuser until marriage; then, at least, she could file a self-petition and gain LPR status without further relying on her abusive partner. A. Pre-VAWA Policies Prior to the enactment of VAWA, immigration law in the United States gave USC and LPR spouses complete control over their immigrant spouses’ legal status.75 The doctrine of coverture, for example, a “legislative enactment of the common law theory that the husband is the head of the household,” essentially stripped women of their legal existence once they were married.76 In U.S. immigration law, this tradition informed policies whereby American women automatically acquired their husbands’ citizenship—and lost their U.S. citizenship—upon marriage to a foreigner.77 While the doctrine of coverture was repealed by subsequent laws—such as the Immigration and Nationality Act of 1952, which made immigration law gender-neutral and thus gave women the ability to sponsor their alien husbands’ lawful immigration status78—the laws concerning the conferral of legal immigration status on immigrant spouses were “still rooted in the coverture mentality.”79 Virtually all of the power remained in the hands of the USC or LPR spouse, because the immigrant spouse’s status depended on the voluntary sponsorship of the citizen or LPR spouse.80 And since women comprise the greater proportion of domestic violence victims, immigrant fiancées, and immigrant spouses, they are the most dependent on the sponsorship of 75 Orloff & Kaguyutan, supra note 43, at 99. Id. at 100 (citing S. REP. NO. 81-1515, at 414 (1951)) (internal quotation marks omitted); see also Ryan Lilienthal, Note, Old Hurdles Hamper New Options for Battered Immigrant Women, 62 BROOK. L. REV. 1595, 1602 n.31 (1996) (quoting 1 WILLIAM BLACKSTONE, COMMENTARIES *442 (1783) (alteration in original) (emphasis omitted)): 76 By marriage, the husband and wife are one person in the law: that is, the very being or legal existence of the woman is suspended during the marriage, or at least is incorporated and consolidated into that of the husband: under whose wing, protection, and cover, she performs every thing; and is therefore called . . . a feme-covert, . . . is said to be covert-baron, or under the protection and influence of her husband, her baron, or lord; and her condition during her marriage is called her coverture. 77 78 79 80 Orloff & Kaguyutan, supra note 43, at 100. Id. at 101. Id. Id. 2012] IMPROVEMENTS FOR IMMIGRANT FIANCÉES 137 their partners and are most dramatically affected by a spouse’s refusal to sponsor their adjustment of status.81 This disparity in power, prior to VAWA, ensured “that the immigrant spouse [was] faced with an impossible choice: either remain in an abusive relationship or leave, become an undocumented immigrant[,] and be potentially deprived of home, livelihood and perhaps child custody.”82 While these dire circumstances have been mitigated by more modern laws protecting battered immigrants,83 major impediments remain for battered immigrant fiancées living in the United States on K Visas, due to their ineligibility to self-petition. The Immigration Marriage Fraud Amendments of 1986 (IMFA)84 actually enhanced petitioning USC and LPR spouses’ control over their immigrant spouses by creating a presumption that all immigration marriages were fraudulent until proven otherwise, and by preventing alien spouses from becoming LPRs without their petitioning spouses’ sponsorship.85 However, IMFA did provide the U.S. Attorney General with discretionary power to grant LPR status to an immigrant spouse, independent of her husband’s sponsorship, if she demonstrated “extreme hardship or good faith/good cause.”86 Yet both of these provisions were still fraught with difficulty for immigrant spouses because domestic violence was generally not interpreted as adequate grounds for either waiver.87 The 1990 Battered Spouse Waiver was an early congressional attempt specifically designed to protect battered immigrants.88 While it provided some benefits to abused immigrant spouses, such as allowing those who had already obtained conditional resident status to gain LPR status without relying on their spouses for a joint petition,89 the “battered spouse 81 Id. Id. (internal quotation marks omitted). 83 See infra Parts II.B, III.B, and III.C (describing the VAWA self-petition, U Visa, and T Visa, respectively). 84 Immigration Marriage Fraud Amendments of 1986, Pub. L. No. 99-639, 100 Stat. 3537 (1986). 85 Orloff & Kaguyutan, supra note 43, at 101-02. 86 Id. at 102 (citing 8 U.S.C. § 1186a(c)(4) (1994) (internal quotation marks omitted)). 87 Id. at 103. 88 See Orloff & Kaguyutan, supra note 43, at 105 (noting that the battered spouse waiver “was the first piece of legislation that recognized domestic violence as a problem experienced by immigrant wives dependent on their spouses for immigration status” (citing Immigration Act of 1990, Pub. L. No. 101-649, § 701, 104 Stat. 4978 (1990) (codified as amended at 8 U.S.C. § 1186a(c)(4) (1994)))). 89 Id. at 105-06. 82 138 BROOKLYN LAW REVIEW [Vol. 78:1 waiver” still stipulated that an immigrant spouse could not in the first instance become a conditional resident without her spouse’s initial sponsorship.90 This perpetuated immigrant spouses’ dependence on their abusive husbands, and it thus preserved the control that abusive spouses had over their immigrant spouses. B. Violence Against Women Act of 1994 (VAWA) and Subsequent Revisions The Violence Against Women Act of 1994 (VAWA)91 did much to solve this problem. In addition to the broader goals of enhancing protection for battered women nationwide and providing funding for law enforcement and domestic violence service providers,92 VAWA offered shelter via laws specifically designed to help immigrant women who are abused by USC or LPR spouses.93 Representing a significant paradigm shift for battered immigrant spouses, VAWA included the “self-petition” provision,94 which allows an abused immigrant spouse to file for LPR status without her abusive spouse’s sponsorship.95 1. Congressional Intent of VAWA 1994 The VAWA 1994 legislation was lauded as “an essential step in forging a national consensus that our society will not tolerate violence against women.”96 Congress passed the Act as “a comprehensive statutory enactment designed to address ‘the escalating problem of violent crime against women,’ as part of the larger Violent Crime Control and Law Enforcement Act of 1994 . . . .”97 The self-petition was intended, in part, to “permit[] battered immigrant women to leave their batterers without fearing deportation.”98 This helped to alleviate the plight of 90 Id. at 107. 8 U.S.C. § 1154 (2006). 92 Orloff & Kaguyutan, supra note 43, at 108. 93 Id. at 109. 94 8 U.S.C. § 1154(a)(1)(A)(iii)(I). 95 Orloff & Kaguyutan, supra note 43, at 114. 96 Id. at 109 (quoting S. REP. NO. 103-138, at 41-42 (1993)). 97 Doe v. Doe, 929 F. Supp. 608, 610 (D. Conn. 1996) (citing S. REP. NO. 103138, at 38 (1993)). 98 Hernandez v. Ashcroft, 345 F.3d 824, 841 (9th Cir. 2003) (alteration in original) (citing H.R. REP. NO. 103-395, at 25 (1993)) (internal quotation marks omitted); see also Pub. L. No. 106-386, 114 Stat. 1464, 1518 (2000) (noting congressional findings that “the goal of the immigration protections for battered immigrants included in the Violence Against Women Act of 1994 was to remove immigration laws as a barrier that kept battered immigrant women . . . locked in abusive relationships”). 91 2012] IMPROVEMENTS FOR IMMIGRANT FIANCÉES 139 abused immigrant spouses by removing the incentive to remain with their abusive spouses to obtain the benefits of sponsorship based on marriage.99 Underscoring the need for the self-petition, at least one scholar has noted a study where 72.3 percent of USCs and LPRs who batter their immigrant spouses never file the immigration papers.100 Before VAWA, an abusive USC or LPR could still exert control over his spouse’s immigration status, even embracing the ability to have her deported, all the while remaining free from prosecution for domestic violence he perpetrated against her.101 2. Eligibility to Self-Petition Under VAWA VAWA codified that a spouse of an abusive USC or LPR may file a self-petition for adjustment of immigration status by showing that she: (1) married a USC or LPR in good faith, (2) had been battered or suffered “extreme cruelty” at the hands of her spouse, (3) resided with the abusive spouse, and (4) was a person “of good moral character.”102 Under VAWA 1994, the battered spouse also had the burden of showing that deportation would result in “extreme hardship.”103 In order to reduce the burden on battered immigrant spouses, Congress included a requirement that “any credible evidence” be accepted in adjudicating self-petitions and “battered spouse waiver” cases.104 3. VAWA 2000 When Congress reauthorized VAWA in 2000,105 it amended numerous provisions of VAWA to remove barriers 99 Nonetheless, the self-petition avenue to lawful permanent residency is unavailable to abused fiancées. 100 Orloff & Kaguyutan, supra note 43, at 111; see also Dutton et al., supra note 59, at 259 (noting that those abusive USC and LPR spouses who did file immigration documents often waited for nearly four years or longer to do so). 101 Orloff & Kaguyutan, supra note 43, at 113. 102 Id. at 114; see also 3A AM. JUR. 2D Aliens & Citizens § 461 (2011); FRAGOMEN ET AL., supra note 15, § 13.1. The protections afforded to battered immigrants, including the right to self-petition if the statutory elements are satisfied, are gender-neutral and extend to both men and women. 8 C.F.R. § 204.2(c) (2001); see also Orloff & Kaguyutan, supra note 43, at 114. 103 Shaw, supra note 5, at 671. This “extreme hardship” provision was repealed by VAWA 2000, discussed infra at Part II.B.3. 104 Orloff & Kaguyutan, supra note 43, at 116 (internal quotation marks omitted). In the 2009 fiscal year, 6374 VAWA petitions were approved and 1671 were denied. 1 IMMIGR. L. & DEF., supra note 18, § 4:58. 105 Battered Immigrant Women Protection Act of 2000 (BIWPA), Pub. L. No. 106-386 § 1501, 114 Stat. 1464 (2000). 140 BROOKLYN LAW REVIEW [Vol. 78:1 and loopholes, and to more accurately implement the congressional intent behind the law.106 For example, VAWA 2000 abrogated the requirement that abused spouses show “extreme hardship” that would result from deportation, and it permitted women who divorced their abusive spouses or who were widowed to file self-petitions within two years of the divorce or the batterer’s death.107 It further allowed for the filing of self-petitions by battered spouses whose LPR spouses had been stripped of their immigration status (e.g., for certain criminal convictions), so long as abused spouses filed selfpetitions within two years of their spouses’ loss of status.108 Significantly, VAWA 2000 created the U Visa, a new visa category designed to afford protection and legal status to immigrant victims of crime who are, have been, or are likely to be helpful in prosecuting the crimes perpetrated against them.109 The tremendous importance of the U Visa lies in its provision of legal status to battered immigrants who are undocumented or who are ineligible to self-petition under VAWA because they are not married to their abusers.110 The U Visa is therefore ostensibly available to abused K Visa holders such as Ayana,111 yet certain pitfalls of the U Visa process make it an unenviable or even unobtainable form of immigration relief for battered immigrant fiancées.112 106 See, e.g., id. § 1502(b): The purposes of this title are— (1) to remove barriers to criminal prosecutions of persons who commit acts of battery or extreme cruelty against immigrant women and children; and (2) to offer protection against domestic violence occurring in family and intimate relationships that are covered in State and tribal protection orders, domestic violence, and family law statutes. 107 Shaw, supra note 5, at 672. See id. 109 8 U.S.C.A. § 1101(a)(15)(U) (2011); see also Deanna Kwong, Note, Removing Barriers for Battered Immigrant Women: A Comparison of Immigrant Protections Under VAWA I & II, 17 BERKELEY WOMEN’S L.J. 137, 150-51 (2002); Shaw, supra note 5, at 672. For further discussion of the U Visa as a remedy for K Visa holders, see infra Part III.B. 110 Shaw, supra note 5, at 672. 111 See Mary B. Clark, Falling Through the Cracks: The Impact of VAWA 2005’s Unfinished Business on Immigrant Victims of Domestic Violence, 7 U. MD. L.J. RACE, RELIG., GENDER & CLASS 37, 51 (2007) (“The creation of the U Visa is an extremely important advance for the rights of battered immigrant women as it offers protection to female domestic violence victims who are ineligible for VAWA self-petitions because of their abuser’s lack of a marital relationship or lawful immigration status.”). 112 See infra Part III.B. 108 2012] IMPROVEMENTS FOR IMMIGRANT FIANCÉES 141 VAWA 2000 extended protection further still, enabling an abused immigrant spouse to file a self-petition if her marriage is legally invalid due to her husband’s act of bigamy, of which she was unaware.113 This ensures that such an abused immigrant— despite having a marriage to a USC or LPR that is legally void because of the USC or LPR’s previously existing legal marriage to another partner—would not be precluded from filing a VAWA selfpetition.114 While this was not the case under VAWA 1994, today, provided that she is otherwise eligible, a battered immigrant spouse may still file a self-petition even if her marriage was technically illegal owing to her abuser’s bigamous practices.115 4. VAWA 2005 VAWA’s third implementation, in 2005,116 provided additional protections to abused immigrant women because, even after VAWA 1994 and VAWA 2000, several shortcomings remained in the legislation’s protection of battered immigrants.117 Among other innovations, VAWA 2005 amended the U Visa provisions to provide greater protections for family members of U Visa applicants who may obtain lawful status derivatively,118 and it offered additional remedies for abused immigrants in removal hearings, such as the “motion to reopen.”119 Although the self-petition remained unavailable to abused K Visa holders, VAWA 2005 placed certain limitations on K Visa petitioners (i.e., USC fiancés) designed to protect the immigrant beneficiaries of the visas.120 For instance, the USC petitioner 113 Clark, supra note 111, at 48. See IGNATIUS & STICKNEY, supra note 2, § 4:36 (“Until the passage of VAWA 2000, it was imperative that the marriage creating the relationship between the noncitizen and the abuser be legally valid at the time that the noncitizen filed her selfpetition . . . .”). 115 Id. Although the term “intended spouse” appears at first glance to include K Visa holders, alas it does not. A fuller discussion of the bigamy exception in the selfpetition provision appears infra at Part IV.A. 116 Violence Against Women and Department of Justice Reauthorization Act of 2005, Pub. L. No. 109–162, 119 Stat. 2964 (2006). 117 See generally Clark, supra note 111. 118 Id. at 56. 119 Id. at 54-55. If granted, a motion to reopen provides for “a new determination [in immigration court] based on new material evidence which was not available and which could not have been discovered prior to and presented at the original hearing.” 1 IMMIGR. L. & DEF., supra note 18, § 9:13. 120 Clark, supra note 111, at 54-55. Although Clark states that “relief is available to women who have been brought to the United States on K Fiancé Visas” in a section titled “Relief for K Fiancé Visa Self-Petitioners,” id., it is unclear what is meant by “relief.” Clark’s article does not provide a citation for the above proposition. Additionally, since K Visa holders are not eligible to self-petition under VAWA, see supra Part II.B.2, it 114 142 BROOKLYN LAW REVIEW [Vol. 78:1 applying for a K Visa on behalf of his immigrant fiancée must disclose criminal convictions, must wait two years between petitions (if he becomes engaged to another individual), and cannot apply for more than two K Visas in ten years without the immigrant fiancée receiving notification from the Department of Homeland Security (DHS) that hers is the USC’s third petition.121 While VAWA has been critical in relieving immigrant women from the perils associated with domestic violence, U.S. immigration law nevertheless provides unequal treatment to different categories of abused immigrants.122 Indeed, many abused K Visa recipients are condemned to a legal “no(wo)man’s-land,” where they are unable to access the remedies afforded to spouses of USCs or LPRs. C. VAWA Reauthorization in 2012 In 2011, Senator Patrick Leahy (D-Vt.) introduced the Violence Against Women Reauthorization Act of 2011123 in the U.S. Senate. The Senate passed the bill by a bipartisan 68-to31 vote, but the House of Representatives subsequently passed a competing bill, H.R. 4970, by a 222-to-205 vote along party lines.124 While the first version of the Senate bill would have provided additional protections to K Visa holders—such as a broader definition of background information about USC fiancé petitioners that the Secretary of Homeland Security must provide to prospective K Visa beneficiaries125—the amended bill removed those protections126 and failed to provide the panoply of seems that Clark’s title for the section is a misnomer as she refers to other types of relief aside from the self-petition. Clark does, however, outline restrictions on K Visa petitioners that are designed to protect K Visa beneficiaries. Clark, supra note 111, at 54-55. 121 Clark, supra note 111, at 54-55; Olga Grosh, Note, Foreign Wives, Domestic Violence: U.S. Law Stigmatizes and Fails to Protect “Mail-Order Brides,” 22 HASTINGS WOMEN’S L.J. 81, 101 (2011). Some of these requirements derive from the International Marriage Broker Regulation Act of 2005 (IMBRA), Pub. L. No. 109-162 §§ 831, 832(a)(2)(A), 119 Stat. 3066 (2006), which was also passed along with VAWA 2005. 122 Shaw, supra note 5, at 664. 123 S. 1925, 112th Cong. (2011); S. REP. NO. 112-153 (2012). 124 Bill Summary & Status of S. 1925, 112th Cong. (2011), available at http://thomas.loc.gov/cgi-bin/bdquery/z?d112:S.1925:; Bill Summary & Status of H.R. 4970, 112th Cong. (2012), available at http://thomas.loc.gov/cgi-bin/bdquery/z? d112:HR04970:@@@R. 125 See S. 1925, 112th Cong. § 808 (2011), available at http://www.gpo.gov/ fdsys/pkg/BILLS-112s1925is/pdf/BILLS-112s1925is.pdf. 126 See S. 1925, 112th Cong., as amended, available at http://www.gpo.gov/ fdsys/pkg/BILLS-112s1925rs/pdf/BILLS-112s1925rs.pdf. The bill passed by the House, however, did contain similar provisions. See H.R. 4970, 112th Cong. § 803 (2012). 2012] IMPROVEMENTS FOR IMMIGRANT FIANCÉES 143 safeguards that K Visa holders like Ayana need. The House bill would enact even more stringent policies affecting abused immigrants.127 Concurrently, in a disturbing development for Ayana and her similarly situated “sisters,” Congressman Lamar Smith (R-Tex.) and other House Republicans introduced the HALT Act,128 which could subject undocumented immigrants to detention and possible removal if they report domestic violence.129 This would be a surprising departure from congressional efforts to protect battered immigrants, even those who do not possess legal immigration status.130 The HALT Act could hinder such efforts to provide adequate protection for battered immigrant women and discourage reporting of domestic violence. Accordingly, if a VAWA reauthorization bill is passed, it should 127 See, e.g., Delay on Domestic Violence, Editorial, N.Y. TIMES, July 24, 2012, at A20, available at http://www.nytimes.com/2012/07/24/opinion/delay-on-violenceagainst-women-act.html. (“The [House] bill did not include new protections for . . . immigrant . . . victims contained in the Senate measure. It also rolled back protections for immigrant women, including for undocumented immigrants who report abuse and cooperate with law enforcement.”); see also Ramsey Cox, Senate Democrats Tell Speaker Boehner to Adopt Their Domestic Violence Bill, HILL: FLOOR ACTION BLOG (July 24, 2012, 5:08 PM), http://thehill.com/blogs/floor-action/senate/239837-senatedemocrats-request-speaker-boehner-adopts-their-version-of-vawa. 128 Hinder the Administration’s Legalization Temptation (HALT) Act, H.R. 2497, 112th Cong. (2011), available at http://thomas.loc.gov/cgi-bin/t2GPO/http://www.gpo.gov/ fdsys/pkg/BILLS-112hr2497ih/pdf/BILLS-112hr2497ih.pdf [hereinafter HALT Act]. The companion bill in the Senate is S. 1380, 112th Cong. (2011), available at http://thomas.loc.gov/cgi-bin/t2GPO/http://www.gpo.gov/fdsys/pkg/BILLS-112s1380is/pdf/ BILLS-112s1380is.pdf. As of November 17, 2012, neither bill had been passed out of its committee. The HALT Act would temporarily suspend certain forms of immigration relief, such as inadmissibility waivers, cancellations of removal, and designations of Temporary Protected Status, until January 21, 2013. 129 See Kase Wickman, Bill Would Penalize Immigrants Who Report Domestic Violence, RAW STORY (Oct. 12, 2011, 12:27 PM), http://www.rawstory.com/ rs/2011/10/12/bill-would-penalize-immigrants-who-report-domestic-violence. Opponents of the HALT Act argued that it would affect battered undocumented immigrants because it would suspend the form of relief known as deferred action, which may be used as an alternative to removal of undocumented immigrants who report abuse. Marcos Restrepo, Two Bills Would Expand, Diminish Govt. Protection for Abused Women, AM. INDEP. (Oct. 12, 2011, 9:26 AM), http://americanindependent.com/ 198582/two-bills-would-expand-diminish-govt-protection-for-abused-women. However, the bill does provide an exception which would allow a grant of deferred action for aliens “to be tried for . . . crime[s], or [as] . . . witnesses at trial,” “for any other significant law enforcement . . . purpose,” or “for a humanitarian purpose where the life of the alien is imminently threatened.” HALT Act, supra note 128, § 2(f). These exceptions might be applicable to battered immigrants who report domestic violence— if they were assisting law enforcement or if the abuse put their lives in imminent danger—but it would depend on how DHS interprets the law and how it chooses to exercise discretion case-by-case. Regardless, the HALT Act seems unlikely to pass at this time due to a lack of bipartisan support. 130 For a more detailed discussion of the U Visa, which provides some protection to documented and undocumented immigrants who are victims of certain crimes, see infra Part III.B. 144 BROOKLYN LAW REVIEW [Vol. 78:1 include the amendments proposed below, which would confer the protections that abused K Visa holders deserve. In a statement at a recent U.S. Senate hearing discussing the reauthorization of VAWA, Senator Leahy said that despite the progress made in the seventeen years since the passage of VAWA in 1994: [O]ur country still has a long way to go. . . . . . . [A]s we look toward reauthorization of [VAWA], we have to continue to ensure that the law evolves to fill unmet needs. . . . We . . . [must prioritize] our response to the high rates of violence experienced by . . . immigrant women.131 Indeed, the law should evolve to fill the unmet needs of K Visa holders who are abused before marriage. The proposals I outline below in Part IV would be significant advancements in this process. D. Recent Steps to Eliminate Discrimination in Immigration Law In 2011, Senator Leahy also introduced Senate Bill 821 in an effort to “eliminate discrimination in the immigration laws,” by amending the INA to allow same-sex “permanent partners of [USCs] or [LPRs] to obtain [LPR] status in the same manner as spouses . . . .”132 Although this bill could be 131 The Violence Against Women Act: Building on Seventeen Years of Accomplishments: Hearing Before the S. Comm. on the Judiciary, 112th Cong. 112-132, at 2 (2011) (statement of Sen. Leahy, Chairman, S. Comm. on the Judiciary), available at http://judiciary.senate.gov/hearings/testimony.cfm?id=3d9031b47812de2592c3baeba61a f68b&wit_id=3d9031b47812de2592c3baeba61af68b-0-1. 132 Uniting American Families Act of 2011, S. 821, 112th Cong. (2011), available at http://thomas.loc.gov/cgi-bin/t2GPO/http://www.gpo.gov/fdsys/pkg/BILLS112s821is/pdf/BILLS-112s821is.pdf. Specifically pertinent to this note is the provision which provides that: Section 101(a) (8 U.S.C. [§] 1101(a)) [would be] amended— (1) in paragraph (15)(K)(ii), by inserting “or permanent partnership” after “marriage”; and (2) by adding at the end the following: “(52) The term ‘permanent partner’ means an individual 18 years of age or older who— “(A) is in a committed, intimate relationship with another individual 18 years of age or older in which both individuals intend a lifelong commitment; “(B) is financially interdependent with that other individual; 2012] IMPROVEMENTS FOR IMMIGRANT FIANCÉES 145 construed to allow fiancées in same-sex relationships with USCs or LPRs to adjust their status to become LPRs themselves, it would still exclude abused heterosexual K Visa holders because they would likely be able to “contract with [their partners] a marriage cognizable under [the] Act,”133 even if they do not intend to marry their fiancés on account of abuse. Interestingly, although passage of Senate Bill 821 would “eliminate discrimination” by allowing same-sex partners to obtain immigration benefits via “permanent partnerships,”134 it appears that an abused same-sex partner could more easily avail herself of the VAWA self-petition—even if she had been living with her partner for less than ninety days, provided the bill’s other requirements are satisfied—whereas an abused opposite-sex partner in the United States on a K Visa would be precluded from doing so unless she married her petitioning fiancé.135 This result would seem contrary to VAWA’s aim to disincentivize battered partners from remaining with abusers, as well as Senate Bill 821’s promise of ending immigration law’s discrimination. INADEQUATE REMEDIES CURRENTLY AVAILABLE TO BATTERED FIANCÉE VISA HOLDERS III. Although adjustment of immigration status, and thus the VAWA self-petition, is unavailable to a K Visa holder “if not married to and adjusting on the basis of the original petitioner,”136 there are other potential avenues to lawful immigration status for abused immigrant fiancées.137 However, “(C) is not married to, or in a permanent partnership with, any individual other than that other individual; “(D) is unable to contract with that other individual a marriage cognizable under this Act; and “(E) is not a first, second, or third degree blood relation of that other individual.[”] Id. § 2. 133 See id. (proposed definition “(D)” of the term “permanent partner”). Id. pmbl. See id. This is not to argue that S. 821 should not be passed, but only to point out the disparate application that the bill would have on abused K Visa holders as compared to those same-sex partners that would be protected by the bill. 136 LAURA L. LICHTER, Adjustment of Status, Admissibility and Waivers of Inadmissibility, A.L.I.-A.B.A. CLE SN039, at 217, 222 (2008); see also supra Parts I and II. 137 USCIS publishes a pamphlet designed to inform abused immigrants of their rights. U.S. CITIZENSHIP & IMMIGRATION SERVS., INFORMATION ON THE LEGAL RIGHTS AVAILABLE TO IMMIGRANT VICTIMS OF DOMESTIC VIOLENCE IN THE UNITED STATES AND 134 135 146 BROOKLYN LAW REVIEW [Vol. 78:1 these alternatives—which include different types of visas and defensive immigration court pleadings—provide inadequate relief for abused K Visa holders. This section will detail each type of relief and its inadequacies in turn. A. Cancellation of Removal If Ayana chooses to remain in the United States without valid immigration status and is subsequently placed in removal proceedings, she may be eligible for non-LPR “cancellation of removal.”138 However, Ayana could avail herself of this form of relief only after she shows that she has maintained continuous physical presence in the United States for at least ten years, has been a “person of good moral character” during that time, has not been convicted of certain criminal offenses, and that her removal from the country would result in “exceptional and extremely unusual hardship” to a spouse, parent, or child who is a USC or LPR.139 It is clearly unreasonable to expect that a K FACTS ABOUT IMMIGRATING ON A MARRIAGE-BASED VISA FACT SHEET, available at http://www.uscis.gov/portal/site/uscis/menuitem.5af9bb95919f35e66f614176543f6d1a/?vg nextoid=8707936ba657d210VgnVCM100000082ca60aRCRD&vgnextchannel=8a2f6d26d1 7df110VgnVCM1000004718190aRCRD (last updated Jan. 1, 2011) [hereinafter USCIS PAMPHLET]. In the section concerning the immigration rights of victims of domestic violence, USCIS lists three remedies: VAWA self-petitions, cancellation of removal, and U Visas (for victims of crime). However, the pamphlet notes that because of inadequate knowledge of immigration laws, and due to language barriers and cultural isolation, “immigrants are often afraid to report acts of domestic violence to the police or to seek other forms of assistance. Such fear causes many immigrants to remain in abusive relationships.” Id.; see also Grosh, supra note 121, at 103 (discussing the Government Accountability Office’s report on USCIS’s implementation of provisions of IMBRA, particularly USCIS’s failure to make its pamphlet available to women in languages other than English and through media other than the Internet). “More importantly, the pamphlet does not state explicitly that a victim of domestic violence will not be deported if she seeks help from the police or immigration authorities.” Id. Perhaps the USCIS pamphlet does not make such a stipulation because deportation is possible when undocumented immigrants report abuse, especially if they apply for relief—such as a U Visa—that is subsequently denied. 138 8 U.S.C. § 1229b(b) (2006). Cancellation of removal is a form of relief from removal (deportation) that allows recipients to remain in the United States and immediately grants them lawful permanent residency. See 1 IMMIGR. L. & DEF., supra note 18, § 8:17. 139 1 IMMIGR. L. & DEF., supra note 18, § 8:17. Continuous physical presence generally means that the applicant has not left the United States for more than 90 days during a single trip or 180 days in aggregated departures. Id. The showing of “exceptional and extremely unusual hardship” must be in relation to the alien’s spouse, parent, or child (i.e., not the alien herself) and must be “substantially beyond that which ordinarily would be expected to result from the alien’s deportation.” Id. (citing H.R. CONF. REP. NO. 828, 104th Cong. (1996)) (internal quotation marks omitted). Cf. 8 U.S.C. § 1229b(a) (LPR Cancellation), which provides a more lenient standard—such as maintaining LPR status for at least five years and continuous physical presence for seven years, and does not require a showing of hardship to a spouse, parent, or child— 2012] IMPROVEMENTS FOR IMMIGRANT FIANCÉES 147 Visa holder—who is abused within ninety days of her arrival— would surreptitiously remain in the United States for ten years, without legal status or work authorization, and in constant fear of being discovered by ICE, to simply raise this defense to deportation after removal proceedings have been initiated against her. And this form of relief is completely unavailable to K Visa holders who do not have a USC or LPR spouse, parent, or child. Another type of defensive relief known as “VAWA cancellation”140 may be available, but this could only be based on Ayana having a child in common with a USC or LPR abuser and that child having suffered abuse at the USC or LPR parent’s hands.141 Since VAWA cancellation is based on abuse of the child and does not concern itself with abuse of the immigrant fiancée, Ayana would again be unable to seek lawful status unless Jason has also abused her children. Even if Ayana were eligible for VAWA cancellation, she would have to perform a juggling act if she seeks to defensively raise it in immigration court: she would have to continuously stay in the United States, hoping that removal proceedings are not initiated against her until after three years pass.142 Moreover, K Visa holders who have no children in common with their abusers would be altogether barred from pleading VAWA cancellation in immigration court. Evidently, cancellation of removal is anything but a viable remedy for most K Visa holders. B. U Visas for Victims of Crimes, Including Domestic Violence Congress created the U Visa as part of the Battered Immigrant Women Protection Act of 2000 (also known as for granting cancellation of removal to certain LPRs. All forms of cancellation of removal are discretionary and involve a “balancing of equities” concerning the respondent’s life. IGNATIUS & STICKNEY, supra note 2, § 12:67. “Positive equities” that would warrant a favorable exercise of discretion “include family ties in the United States,” “hardship” if removed, and a pattern of employment; negative factors include a lack of rehabilitation (if the respondent has a criminal record) and a lack of ties to the community. Id. 140 See Cecilia Olavarria & Moira Fisher Preda, VAWA Cancellation of Removal, in BATTERED IMMIGRANTS AND IMMIGRATION RELIEF 1 (Nov. 2004), available at http://www.legalmomentum.org/assets/pdfs/www3_4_vawa_cancellation_of_removal.pdf. 141 See 8 U.S.C. § 1229b(b)(2)(A)(i); 1 IMMIGR. L. & DEF., supra note 18, § 8:23. Cancellation of removal under VAWA has more lenient evidentiary requirements than LPR or non-LPR cancellation, such as a three-year continuous presence standard. 8 U.S.C. § 1229b(b)(2)(A)(i). 142 See generally IGNATIUS & STICKNEY, supra note 2, § 4:57. 148 BROOKLYN LAW REVIEW [Vol. 78:1 VAWA 2000),143 in order to provide relief to immigrant victims of crime and battered immigrant women “who are not married to a citizen or permanent legal resident and who have been victims of a crime.”144 As a “new and somewhat untested visa classification,”145 a U Visa grants legal immigration status to “victims of certain serious crimes who have suffered substantial physical or mental harm and can document cooperation with law enforcement.”146 The provision specifically enumerates “domestic violence” as a category of victimization worthy of a U Visa.147 In order to obtain a U Visa, an abused K Visa holder (or other immigrant victim of a qualifying crime) must show that she (1) “has suffered substantial physical or mental abuse as a result of having been a victim of [domestic violence, among other things],” (2) “possesses information concerning the criminal activity,” (3) “has been helpful, is being helpful, or is likely to be helpful to a Federal, State, or local law enforcement official, . . . prosecutor, . . . [or] judge, to [USCIS], or to other . . . authorities investigating or prosecuting the criminal activity,” and (4) that “the criminal activity . . . violated the laws of the United States or occurred in the United States . . . or the territories and possessions of the United States . . . .”148 Once a U Visa is granted, it gives the recipient legal nonimmigrant status, valid for four years,149 and it allows the recipient to pursue LPR status after three years.150 However, the U Visa recipient’s adjustment of status is contingent upon a determination by the Secretary of Homeland Security that it “is 143 Lauren Gilbert, Family Violence and U.S. Immigration Law: New Developments, in 01-03 IMMIGRATION BRIEFINGS 1 & n.2 (citing Pub. L. No. 106-386, 114 Stat. 1464); see also supra Part II.B.3. 144 Davis, supra note 67, at 566 (citing BIWPA, 114 Stat. 1464). 145 SUZANNE B. SELTZER ET AL., N.Y. ANTI-TRAFFICKING NETWORK LEGAL SUBCOMM., IMMIGRATION RELIEF FOR CRIME VICTIMS: THE U VISA MANUAL A-iv (2010); see also Shaw, supra note 5, at 672 (noting that issuance of U Visas did not begin until 2007); Press Release, USCIS, USCIS Publishes New Rule for Nonimmigrant Victims of Criminal Activity (Sept. 5, 2007), available at http://www.uscis.gov/files/pressrelease/Uvisa_05Sept07.pdf. 146 SELTZER ET AL., supra note 145, at A-iv. 147 8 U.S.C. § 1101(a)(15)(U)(i), (iii) (2006); Davis, supra note 67, at 566 n.89 (citing BIWPA, Pub. L. No. 106-386, 114 Stat. 1464). S. 1925, the proposed reauthorization of VAWA discussed supra at Part II.C, would add “stalking” to the list of qualifying crimes that would make a victim eligible for a U Visa. S. REP. NO. 112153, at 12 (2012). 148 8 U.S.C. § 1101(a)(15)(U)(i). The third clause in particular presents a problem for many battered immigrants because law enforcement certification can be difficult to obtain and rarely given, not least because many battered immigrants are afraid to contact the police for fear of deportation. Panjwani Interview, supra note 38. 149 SELTZER ET AL., supra note 145, at A-2 (citing 8 C.F.R. § 214.14(g) (2009)). 150 Id. (citing 8 U.S.C. § 1255(m)). 2012] IMPROVEMENTS FOR IMMIGRANT FIANCÉES 149 justified on humanitarian grounds, to ensure family unity, or is in the public interest.”151 This requirement reveals at least one drawback to the U Visa remedy for abused K Visa holders: in contrast to the VAWA self-petition, U Visa applicants must clear significant administrative hurdles, while “VAWA selfpetitioners can obtain lawful permanent residency once a visa becomes available.”152 While certainly beneficial for K Visa holders and other immigrant victims of violence who are able to satisfy its requirements, another inadequacy of the U Visa for immigrant fiancées is the stringent policy of requiring law enforcement certification that the victim is, has been, or will likely be helpful in investigating or prosecuting a crime.153 A U Visa application will be denied outright if the applicant lacks certification.154 A VAWA self-petition, conversely, does not require law enforcement certification and may be granted based on “any credible evidence.”155 Disconcerting for Ayana is that these certifications can be difficult to obtain, depending on the availability of evidence of abuse and whether or not the battered partner was brave enough to report abuse to the police.156 What is more, law enforcement certification for U Visas is discretionary, whereby the agency may refuse to provide certification even if the applicant has been critically helpful in investigating or prosecuting the crime.157 Applicants who are not represented by counsel may have even greater difficulty because “some agencies may lack 151 Id. at A-23 (quoting 8 C.F.R. § 245.24(b)(6)) (internal quotation marks omitted). Id. at A-9. 153 Notably, the VAWA self-petition does not contain a similar certification requirement. 154 See DEP’T OF HOMELAND SEC., OMB NO. 1615-0104, INSTRUCTIONS FOR FORM I-918, PETITION FOR U NONIMMIGRANT STATUS 4 (2010) [hereinafter INSTRUCTIONS FOR FORM I-918], available at http://www.uscis.gov/files/form/i918instr.pdf; see also Tahja L. Jensen, Comment, U Visa “Certification”: Overcoming the Local Hurdle in Response to a Federal Statute, 45 IDAHO L. REV. 691, 698-99 (2009). 155 Orloff & Kaguyutan, supra note 43, at 116 (internal quotation marks omitted); see also supra note 104 and accompanying text. 156 Panjwani Interview, supra note 38; see also Clark, supra note 111, at 50 (“Obtaining certification may present a challenge in some cases where the police choose not to arrest the abuser or press charges. Further, many advocates could face challenges if their client chooses to drop the charges against her batterer or even refuses to testify in court.”). 157 See Jensen, supra note 154, at 701 (“An agency’s decision to provide a certification is entirely discretionary; the agency is under no legal obligation to complete a Form I-918, Supplement B, for any particular alien.” (quoting INSTRUCTIONS FOR FORM I-918, supra note 154, Supp. B) (internal quotation marks omitted)). 152 150 BROOKLYN LAW REVIEW [Vol. 78:1 understanding about U Visas and the role of certification.”158 Additionally, the abusive partner will usually have to be arrested before law enforcement certification will be issued,159 or the abused fiancée may need to show other evidence such as a temporary restraining order. Oftentimes, a battered immigrant woman will not be aware of these evidentiary requirements and, irrespective of her level of knowledge, will be afraid to even report domestic violence for fear that her abuser will have her deported or that the violence will increase.160 Thus, the requirement of law enforcement certification is often unsatisfied because abused immigrant women are so unlikely to appeal to law enforcement for help.161 Because of these evidentiary difficulties, many lawyers and advocates suggest that other types of evidence, such as the victim’s testimony or that of community members, should be accepted.162 Unfortunately, though, “immigration law has continued to focus on official reports in order to establish abuse. As a result of the subjective nature of the qualification process, no law, including the U-visa, allows women to leave abusive relationships without the fear of deportation.”163 In part, this is because an out-of-status immigrant who applies for a U Visa will be notifying USCIS of her unlawful presence. Thus, if her visa application is denied, she will be removable. Additionally, because of the tenuous nature of their immigration status, K Visa holders are less likely than other battered immigrants— especially spouses, who can self-petition as a last resort—to seek assistance from law enforcement.164 The short, ninety-day 158 SELTZER ET AL., supra note 145, at A-15. Panjwani Interview, supra note 38; see also Sarah M. Wood, Note, VAWA’s Unfinished Business: The Immigrant Women Who Fall Through the Cracks, 11 DUKE J. GENDER L. & POL’Y 141, 150 (2004) (“[I]f law enforcement decides not to press criminal charges against the batterer or decides that the battered woman’s testimony is not reliable, she will be left in the same position that she would have feared in the absence of the U visa.”). 160 See generally USCIS PAMPHLET, supra note 137; see also supra Part II. 161 For example, “[a] survey of Latina immigrants in the District of Columbia found that 21.7% listed fear of being reported to immigration as their primary reason for remaining in abusive relationships.” Davis, supra note 67, at 570-71; see also supra note 137. 162 Davis, supra note 67, at 572. 163 Id. (emphasis omitted) (footnote omitted). Davis argues for independent visa status for H-4 Visa holders (spouses accompanying immigrant workers to the United States) as an alternative to the U Visa because of the troubles abused spouses would face in obtaining law enforcement certification. Id. at 572-73 (“In contrast to the U-visa, independent visa status would not require a victim to contact the police or to prosecute the batterer in order to remain legally in the country or to work.”). 164 See, e.g., Anna Hanson, Legislative Note, The U-Visa: Immigration Law’s Best Kept Secret?, 63 ARK. L. REV. 177, 183 (2010) (“Even applying for a U-visa is a frightening proposition for an undocumented immigrant. Undocumented victims who 159 2012] IMPROVEMENTS FOR IMMIGRANT FIANCÉES 151 timeframe that immigrant fiancées have to marry their partners is already a cause for concern for fiancées who may have doubts after arrival, let alone when abuse arises within that time. A K Visa holder who knows that her immigration status depends upon her marriage to her abusive fiancé will be inclined to proceed with the marriage despite the harm. Sadly, as in the case of immigrant brides who arrive through marriage brokers, many battered K Visa holders have “everything to gain from entering into this arrangement and staying in it, no matter what the circumstances.”165 C. T Visas for Victims of Trafficking T Visas are available to victims of severe forms of trafficking.166 While this visa category takes more creative framing by practitioners to ensure that their clients can satisfy its requirements, it may be applicable to abused K Visa holders who have been brought to the United States by their fiancés through force, fraud, or coercion for the purposes of “sex trafficking” or “involuntary servitude.”167 While “sex trafficking” pertains specifically to using the person for purposes of a commercial sex act, the statute also permits relief for those who are trafficked for “labor or services,” including “involuntary servitude,” and it defines coercion as: “threats of serious harm to or physical restraint against any person; any scheme . . . intended to cause a person to believe that failure to perform an act would result in serious harm to or physical restraint against any person; or the abuse or threatened abuse of the legal process.”168 Domestic violence can arguably be identify themselves to immigration authorities but do not receive U-visas are in immediate danger of deportation.”); see also supra Part I. 165 Grosh, supra note 121, at 105. 166 8 C.F.R. § 214.11(a) (2009). The T Visa was established by the Trafficking Victims Protection Act of 2000 (TVPA). SUZANNE B. SELTZER ET AL., N.Y. ANTITRAFFICKING NETWORK LEGAL SUBCOMM., IDENTIFICATION AND LEGAL ADVOCACY FOR TRAFFICKING SURVIVORS A-iv (3d ed. 2009). Eligibility requires that a T Visa applicant show that she: [1] is or has been a victim of a severe form of trafficking in person; [2] is physically present in the United States due to trafficking; [3] has complied with any reasonable request for assistance in the investigation or prosecution of acts of trafficking in persons (if they are over 18); and [4] would suffer extreme hardship involving unusual and severe harm if removed from the United States. Id. at A-11. 167 168 See 8 C.F.R. § 214.11(a); SELTZER ET AL., supra note 166, at A-2, A-12. SELTZER ET AL., supra note 166, at A-12 to A-13. 152 BROOKLYN LAW REVIEW [Vol. 78:1 characterized in this way. As such, it may be possible for an experienced attorney to successfully argue that an abused K Visa holder like Ayana was trafficked, but this would require satisfying formidable evidentiary burdens like those confronting U Visa applicants.169 Another important consideration regarding the T Visa application process, and indeed for U Visas as well, is the applicant’s immigration status. If a battered K Visa holder has left her abuser before entering into a marriage, and the ninetyday period has lapsed, she will be out of status.170 At that point, initiating an affirmative visa application—such as a T or U Visa—can put her in danger of having removal proceedings initiated.171 For these reasons, a T Visa is an impracticable remedy for most K Visa holders who are abused by their fiancés, at least after the ninety-day marriage window has closed. D. Asylum Asylum is available in the United States to those who satisfy the statutory definition of “refugee,” which requires, among other things, that an asylum-seeker establish “a wellfounded fear of persecution [if returned to her country of origin] on account of race, religion, nationality, membership in a particular social group, or political opinion.”172 An abused K 169 See id. at A-13 to A-14 (“In order to establish that [a] client is a victim of a severe form of trafficking in persons, he or she must either submit an endorsement from a law enforcement agency . . . or sufficient credible secondary evidence, describing efforts to cooperate with law enforcement, as well as the nature and scope of any force, fraud, or coercion used against the victim. This may include, inter alia, evidence that the USCIS has granted the alien’s continued presence in the United States as a victim of trafficking.” (footnotes omitted)). 170 See supra note 39. 171 Id. at A-4 (“The validity of a T applicant’s immigration status is important because if an applicant is not in valid status, and he or she is being brought to the attention of USCIS or ICE, the applicant could be issued a Notice to Appear (NTA), and removal (deportation) proceedings may be commenced.”). 172 8 U.S.C.A. § 1101(a)(42) (West 2011). Withholding of removal is a similar form of relief based on the same five grounds of persecution, though it has a higher evidentiary standard—in that an applicant must show that persecution is “more likely than not” to occur, rather than the “reasonable possibility” standard for asylum which may be satisfied by showing a ten percent chance of persecution. See INS v. CardozaFonseca, 480 U.S. 421, 421, 440 (1987); see also 3A AM. JUR. 2D Aliens and Citizens § 1140 (2012). Withholding also comes with fewer benefits; it only requires that an alien not be refouled (returned) to the country where she would be persecuted. See ANNA MARIE GALLAGHER ET AL., 2 IMMIGRATION LAW SERVICE 2D § 10:231 (2012). An alien who is granted withholding may be removed to a country where she would not be persecuted, and she may not apply for adjustment of status. Id. However, a withholding of removal grantee can obtain work authorization. Id. The Convention 2012] IMPROVEMENTS FOR IMMIGRANT FIANCÉES 153 Visa holder might venture applying for asylum on the grounds that she would be persecuted and stigmatized on account of her membership in a particular social group, but this would be an arduous and uncertain path to legal immigration status because the law is unsettled with respect to how domestic violence victims can fit into this nebulous category.173 Unfortunately, although various social groups encompassing domestic violence victims have been proposed, “a particular social group that is viable for all battered women seeking asylum has not emerged.”174 Difficulty arises both in terms of establishing the requisite “nexus” (i.e., that the persecution was “on account of” membership in the protected group) as well as attempting to define the social group. Interestingly, the European Court of Human Rights (ECtHR) has suggested that women in countries like Afghanistan might face persecution and qualify as refugees because of their status as “women whose engagements to be married have been broken. Unless they marry, which is very difficult given the social stigma associated with these women, social rejection and discrimination continue to be the norm.”175 This indicates that Against Torture (CAT) provides a last-resort form of relief—that an alien cannot be refouled if she would “more likely than not” face torture by the government or with government acquiescence, upon returning to the country of persecution. See generally 8 C.F.R. § 1208.18; 3A C.J.S. Aliens § 1392 (2012). 173 See, e.g., GALLAGHER ET AL., supra note 172, § 10:152; 1 IMMIGR. L. & DEF. supra note 18, § 13:40. The case of Matter of R-A-, 24 I. & N. Dec. 629, 2008 WL 4419696 (B.I.A. Sept. 25, 2008), for example, involves an epic legal battle that finally ended in a grant of asylum for a Guatemalan woman who suffered severe domestic abuse by her husband. GALLAGHER ET AL., supra note 172, § 10:152; After 14 Years, Rodi Alvarado Is Finally Granted Asylum, THOMSON REUTERS, Dec. 21, 2009, available at 86 No. 48 INTERPRETER RELEASES 3074. The Board of Immigration Appeals (BIA) articulated its general standard for what constitutes a particular social group in Matter of Acosta: Members of the group must “share a common, immutable characteristic” that is “one that the members of the group either cannot change, or should not be required to change because it is fundamental to their individual identities or consciences.” Matter of Acosta, 19 I. & N. Dec. 211, 233, 1985 WL 56042 (B.I.A. Mar. 1, 1985). After Matter of R-A-, DHS proposed its own standard for how domestic violence victims can constitute a particular social group and be eligible for asylum. Brief of Dep’t of Homeland Sec. at 4 (B.I.A. Apr. 13, 2009), available at http://cgrs.uchastings.edu/pdfs/ Redacted%20DHS%20brief%20on%20PSG.pdf. However, this standard has not been accepted by the BIA, and while DHS may accept the argument that a domestic violence victim qualifies as a member of a particular social group, it remains unclear when the argument would be successful in Immigration Court or on appeal before the BIA. 174 Marisa Silenzi Cianciarulo & Claudia David, Pulling the Trigger: Separation Violence as a Basis for Refugee Protection for Battered Women, 59 AM. U. L. REV. 337, 363 (2009). Cianciarulo and David discuss how violence escalates after leaving one’s abuser and argue for the recognition of a new social group: “women who have left severely abusive relationships.” Id. at 343 (internal quotation marks omitted). 175 N. v. Sweden, App. no. 23505/09, 15, HUDOC (July 20, 2010), available at http://hudoc.echr.coe.int/sites/eng/pages/search.aspx?i=001-99992 (Eur. Ct. H.R.) 154 BROOKLYN LAW REVIEW [Vol. 78:1 there is hope for abused immigrant fiancées who bring cases before the ECtHR, but it is less clear that a U.S. Immigration Court would accept the argument that a woman would face persecution on account of her failed engagement.176 Despite the ostensible availability of this form of relief, however, the asylum process is fraught with difficulty because of its onerous standards, statutory bars, discretionary nature, and the unresolved status of how victims of domestic violence can qualify as a particular social group. If Ayana can demonstrate a well-founded fear of persecution based on one of the aforementioned grounds, she would be eligible for asylum and, if granted, would not require another form of relief to attain legal status.177 However, a woman who enters the United States on a K Visa has already made evidentiary showings of her intent to immigrate and her good faith intent to marry the USC who petitioned for her K Visa, so applying for asylum would seem to represent a step in the wrong direction. Indeed, she was very close to maintaining legal status; the only hurdle that she failed to surmount was marrying her abuser. Moreover, an abused K Visa holder deserves relief on a basis similar to that of a VAWA self-petitioner—the fact that she has been abused by her USC petitioning fiancé—irrespective of whether or not she has a legitimate fear of returning home. While other asylum seekers may be deserving of protection based on their fears of persecution, Ayana deserves protection because she suffered abuse at the hands of a citizen of the United States who petitioned for her admission in the first instance. Furthermore, affirmatively applying for asylum would put an out-of-status K Visa holder in the same predicament she would be in when applying for a U or T Visa: she would be alerting ICE and USCIS to her undocumented immigration status, thereby subjecting herself to potential removal from the United States. And because of the complex nature of asylum and removal (internal quotation marks omitted) (finding that deportation of an Afghani woman, who divorced her husband and remarried a Swedish man, would violate Article 3 of the European Convention on Human Rights because she would be subjected “to torture or to inhuman or degrading treatment or punishment”). 176 See, e.g., Vellani v. U.S. Att’y Gen., 296 F. App’x 870 (11th Cir. 2008) (upholding denial of asylum, withholding, and CAT relief for Pakistani woman whose fiancé refused to marry her because, although “honor killings” were prevalent in Pakistan, applicant failed to show that she could not avoid persecution by reasonably relocating to another part of the country). 177 This is because an asylum grantee can adjust her immigration status to permanent residency after one year of physical presence as an asylum recipient in the United States. 8 U.S.C.A. § 1159 (West 2011). 2012] IMPROVEMENTS FOR IMMIGRANT FIANCÉES 155 proceedings, she would be at a severe disadvantage if she could not obtain legal counsel. Therefore, as with the potential forms of relief discussed above, asylum and its corollaries (withholding of removal and CAT protection) are all but unattainable for abused immigrant fiancées. IV. PROPOSED SOLUTIONS TO REMOVE ABUSED IMMIGRANT FIANCÉES’ INCENTIVE TO REMAIN WITH THEIR ABUSERS Battered K Visa holders should not be coerced, by the law or by their abusers, to proceed with a marriage to an abusive partner, just as those who have already married their USC petitioner fiancés should not be compelled to remain in abusive marriages for immigration benefits. Nevertheless, Congress has chosen to provide relief only to this latter category of victims via the self-petition. In 2002, then-Senator Joseph Biden remarked that since the passage of VAWA, more than 12,000 applications had been approved for “battered immigrant women escaping abuse and establishing their own residency here . . . [and] there has been a 41 percent decrease in the rate of intimate partner victimization of women. . . . This is not the time to scale back our efforts.”178 In order to remove the perverse incentive that compels some battered K Visa holders to remain with their abusers, I offer some amendments to U.S. immigration law that would allow them to achieve valid immigration status while freeing them from abusive relationships. A. Amend the INA to Allow Abused K Visa Holders to SelfPetition for Adjustment of Immigration Status Dabaghian v. Civiletti179 helps to illustrate why a K Visa holder who does not marry her abusive fiancé within the ninetyday timeframe—and thus has not established the basis for adjusting her immigration status—should nonetheless be entitled to immigration relief. In that case, the Ninth Circuit Court of Appeals “set forth the federal rule regarding the validity of a marriage for purposes of conferring an immigration benefit: ‘If a marriage is not sham or fraudulent from its inception, it is valid for the purposes of determining eligibility’ 178 Leading the Fight: The Violence Against Women Office: Hearing Before the Subcomm. on Crime and Drugs of the S. Comm. on the Judiciary, 107th Cong. (2002) (statement of Sen. Joseph R. Biden, Jr.). 179 607 F.2d 868 (9th Cir. 1979). 156 BROOKLYN LAW REVIEW [Vol. 78:1 for benefits under the Immigration and Nationality Act.”180 Since a K Visa recipient has already adduced evidence—which the U.S. government has accepted—establishing her intent to marry her USC fiancé and thus showing that the intended marriage was “not a sham or fraudulent from its inception,” she should not be precluded from attaining the immigration benefits that would have been available to her if her partner were not abusive and the marriage went forward as planned. The dynamics ultimately dissuading Ayana from proceeding with the marriage are the control and abuse by her fiancé, who wooed her into leaving her home and migrating to the United States. In such cases, it is not the immigrant fiancée who is simply choosing not to marry the abusive fiancé, but the abuser who is making the intended marriage untenable. Significantly, in the VAWA self-petition, there already exists an exception to the requirement of a bona fide marriage whereby an immigrant fiancée who enters into a bigamous marriage unknowingly—that is, she held a good faith belief that her marriage was lawful, but it turned out to be an illegitimate marriage because of the USC or LPR’s already existing marriage to another—would still be eligible to selfpetition even though the marriage was technically unlawful.181 In the hypothetical scenario outlined above,182 Ayana fully intended to enter into a bona fide marriage when she left Ethiopia. She demonstrated this intent to the satisfaction of the U.S. government, which issued her a K Visa under the applicable immigration laws. Yet after her arrival to the United States, the abuse perpetrated upon her by her USC fiancé drove her to flee and caused her to refrain from marrying her abuser. Therefore, since it was her abuser’s actions—and not her own— that drove her from the relationship where she previously intended to conclude a bona fide marriage, the law ought to carve out a narrow exception for abused K Visa holders similar to the exception for VAWA self-petitioners whose marriages are invalid due to the bigamy of their abusers. 180 AUSTIN T. FRAGOMEN, JR. ET AL., 1 IMMIGRATION LAW & BUSINESS § 3:20 (2011) (quoting Dabaghian, 607 F.2d at 869). 181 8 U.S.C.A § 1154(a)(1)(A)(iii)(II) (West 2012) (pertaining to immigrants who marry bigamous USCs); id. § 1154(a)(1)(B)(ii)(II) (pertaining to immigrants who marry bigamous LPRs); see also supra Part II.B.3. 182 See supra notes 1-23 and accompanying text. 2012] IMPROVEMENTS FOR IMMIGRANT FIANCÉES 157 Therefore, I propose that the VAWA self-petition provision, located at 8 U.S.C. § 1154(a)(1)(A)(iii)(II), be amended as follows183: For purposes of subclause (I), an alien described in this subclause is an alien-(aa) (AA) who is the spouse of a citizen of the United States; (BB) who believed that he or she had married a citizen of the United States and with whom a marriage ceremony was actually performed and who otherwise meets any applicable requirements under this chapter to establish the existence of and bona fides of a marriage, but whose marriage is not legitimate solely because of the bigamy of such citizen of the United States; [(CC) who was admitted to the United States pursuant to a K-1 Visa as the fiancé(e) of a citizen of the United States but who failed to enter into a marriage because of that citizen’s abuse; or] [DD] who was a bona fide spouse of a United States citizen within the past 2 years and-(aaa) whose spouse died within the past 2 years; (bbb) whose spouse lost or renounced citizenship status within the past 2 years related to an incident of domestic violence; or (ccc) who demonstrates a connection between the legal termination of the marriage within the past 2 years and battering or extreme cruelty by the United States citizen spouse; (bb) who is a person of good moral character; (cc) who is eligible to be classified as an immediate relative under section 1151(b)(2)(A)(i) of this title or who would have been so classified but for the bigamy of the citizen of the United States that the alien intended to marry; and (dd) who has resided with the alien’s spouse or intended spouse. This note does not argue that the INA should be amended to allow all K Visa holders to adjust their status irrespective of the basis of marriage, but only that it should be narrowly amended to permit those K Visa holders who have been abused within the ninety-day statutory period to file selfpetitions and subsequently adjust their status without being required to marry their abusive partners. Although this 183 The italicized language in brackets represents the proposed amendments. Related sections of the United States Code and the Code of Federal Regulations would likely need to be amended as well. 158 BROOKLYN LAW REVIEW [Vol. 78:1 amendment would constitute a considerable leap in policy by allowing battered K Visa holders to self-petition and ultimately adjust their immigration status to that of lawful permanent resident, it is warranted because, as previously noted, the abuser is the cause of the failed engagement. An abused K Visa holder should not be motivated to proceed with the marriage to her abusive fiancé in order to be eligible to file a VAWA selfpetition. Indeed, incentivizing abused fiancées to complete their marriages is utterly antithetical to the intent of the selfpetition and related provisions, which were enacted to enable abused immigrants to leave their abusers without fearing immigration consequences. Although Congress considered exempting battered K Visa holders from the exclusion on VAWA self-petitions in 1999 and opted not to pass that version of the bill,184 this amendment deserves to be reconsidered. As the Ninth Circuit Court of Appeals noted in Hernandez v. Ashcroft, “[t]he notion that Congress would require women to remain with their batterers in order to be eligible for the forms of relief established in VAWA is flatly contrary to Congress’s articulated purpose in enacting section 244(a)(3).”185 Opponents of the 1999 provision that would have allowed abused K Visa holders to self-petition argued that “[a] person who fails to enter into marriage with the U.S. citizen . . . should be treated just like any other non-immigrant when the rationale for temporary admission no longer applies . . . .”186 However, this argument fails to consider the fact that abuse by the USC petitioner is likely the precise reason an abused K Visa holder in Ayana’s situation would not enter into the intended marriage. She has already proven her intent to enter into the marriage to the satisfaction of the U.S. government,187 and she has relied on the U.S. government’s 184 See H.R. 3083 Hearing, supra note 19, at 89 (prepared statement of Dan Stein, Exec. Dir., Fed’n for Am. Immigration Reform) [hereinafter Stein Statement] (noting that the ninety-day requirement for fiancée visas was instituted by the Immigration Marriage Fraud Act to prevent marriage fraud, and would thus be undermined by the amendment). 185 345 F.3d 824, 841 (9th Cir. 2003). 186 H.R. 3083 Hearing, supra note 19, at 41 (prepared statement of Barbara Strack, Acting Exec. Assoc. Comm’r for Policy & Planning, Immigration & Naturalization Serv.). 187 See, e.g., U.S. DEP’T OF STATE, FOREIGN AFFAIRS MANUAL VOL. 9, DOCUMENTARY REQUIREMENTS 9 FAM 41.81 N4, available at http://www.state.gov/documents/organization/87391.pdf; IGNATIUS & STICKNEY, supra note 2, § 14:6. 2012] IMPROVEMENTS FOR IMMIGRANT FIANCÉES 159 criminal background check to ensure that her fiancé is a safe choice. Drawing the line between the married and the affianced is not warranted when the USC petitioner’s abuse is what caused the planned marriage to collapse. If Ayana could satisfactorily demonstrate the existence of abuse through “any credible evidence”—the same standard that applies to VAWA selfpetitions—the law should provide her with sufficient protections, notwithstanding her failure to proceed with the marriage. Furthermore, concerns about marriage fraud should not motivate Congress to withhold reasonable protections from battered K Visa holders. Some would preclude Ayana from selfpetitioning because, as one opponent argued, it would “undermine[] [the] anti-fraud measure” (i.e., the ninety-day marriage requirement) which “was adopted to prevent the fiance visa from being used for fraudulent entry.”188 Yet the anti-fraud argument overlooks a crucial fact: IMFA was based on flawed research from the start. IMFA was predicated upon an estimate that “as much as 30 percent . . . of the spouse relationships may be fraudulent.”189 However, the Immigration and Naturalization Service (INS) itself “conceded the invalidity of the survey” in subsequent litigation, because the survey was based on data from only three cities and it only concerned cases where officials merely suspected marriage fraud, rather than cases of actual fraud.190 While legislators may express valid concerns about fraudulent circumvention of immigration laws, it has not been shown that abused K Visa holders would exploit their positions as nonimmigrants. Moreover, it is unreasonable to presume that K Visa holders would fabricate abuse; rather, it would be more appropriate to place the burden on the government to prove fraud by a K Visa holder who has already undergone the visa application process.191 188 Stein Statement, supra note 184, at 89. Jones, supra note 20, at 699 (emphasis added) (quoting Immigration Marriage Fraud: Hearings Before the Subcomm. on Immigration and Refugee Policy of the S. Comm. on the Judiciary, 99th Cong. 35 (1985) (statement of INS Comm’r Alan C. Nelson)) (internal quotation marks omitted). At the same hearing, American Immigration Lawyers Association president Jules Coven responded that he “would be extremely surprised to learn, if it could be shown statistically, that more than one or two percent of the ‘green cards’ issued annually on the basis of marriage involved fraud.” Id. 190 Id. (citing Manwani v. INS, 736 F. Supp. 1367 (W.D.N.C. 1990)); see also Manwani, 736 F. Supp. at 1373 (noting that “[t]he INS conceded and the evidence shows that the . . . survey is not a statistically valid study of the suspected or actual incidence of marriage fraud.”). 191 During the application process, the applicant must submit to an interview by consular officials and swear to or affirm her intent to enter into the planned 189 160 BROOKLYN LAW REVIEW [Vol. 78:1 Indeed, reasonable means already exist for preventing fraudulent manipulation of this proposed amendment. For example, immigration law already contains provisions denying adjustment of status petitions for marriages “determined by the Attorney General to have been entered into for the purpose of evading the immigration laws . . . .”192 In order to prevent fraud by K Visa holders who are not actually abused, Congress should simply add a clause addressing this specific concern; if it has been determined that a visa holder acquired the K Visa merely to evade the immigration laws, then she is ineligible to obtain the benefits of a self-petition. This can be enforced through the same process by which fraud is investigated in the K Visa application process: by interviewing the applicant.193 There are already measures to prevent fraudulent accusations of abuse in the self-petition process as well: “[The Department of Homeland Security] can rely on virtually any evidence that comes to its attention suggesting fraud. For example . . . [it can] investigate information provided by an alleged abuser and rely upon it if it can be corroborated.”194 Since a K Visa holder has already established, to the satisfaction of the U.S. government, her good faith intent to marry her USC petitioning fiancé within ninety days of her arrival, adequate “safeguards against fraud” already exist.195 B. Amend the U Visa Requirements to Provide a Reasonable Exception for Abused K Visa Holders Alternatively, the U Visa requirements should be relaxed for abused K Visa holders, specifically by removing the law enforcement certification requirement. This change would allow marriage within ninety days of arrival in the United States. See supra Part I for a discussion of the K Visa application process. 192 8 U.S.C. § 1154(c) (2006). 193 In-person interviews were set forth in an amendment by Senator Chuck Grassley (R-Iowa) as a way to prevent fraud in VAWA self-petitions. See S. REP. NO. 112-153, at 45-46 (2012). Cf. IGNATIUS & STICKNEY, supra note 2, § 5:44 (describing interviews for married couples who are petitioning via form I-751 to remove the conditions on residence for the immigrant spouse). 194 S. REP. NO. 112-153, at 12 n.31. This statement responds to “claims raised by a hearing witness and another U.S. citizen who claimed that she had been a victim of fraud when her non-U.S. citizen [male] spouse filed a VAWA self-petition.” Id. 195 See Wood, supra note 159, at 155 (arguing that illegal immigration will not increase if protections are given to all battered immigrants regardless of marital status). “It is absurd to imagine that women will consciously enter abusive relationships in order to gain legal status or . . . fabricate evidence of abuse sufficiently credible to convince the [government]. The [immigration authorities] ha[ve] already erected numerous safeguards against fraud . . . .” Id. 2012] IMPROVEMENTS FOR IMMIGRANT FIANCÉES 161 the applicant to obtain the benefits of the U Visa, which include lawful immigration status for four years and the ability to file for adjustment of status after three years.196 Moreover, the amendment could be achieved by adding a narrow exception for K Visa holders to allow them to obtain U Visas without meeting the same evidentiary requirements as other undocumented immigrants. This exception is justified because, as previously noted, a K Visa holder has already adequately evidenced her intent to marry her fiancé and complied with the law, at least until the point where abuse began. The reason for noncompliance—e.g., allowing the ninety-day period to lapse without proceeding with the marriage— is due to her fiancé’s abuse rather than a voluntary decision to violate the statute. Further illustrating the need for this exception is the fact that, as discussed above at Parts II and III.B, “abusers of undocumented immigrants often exploit . . . victims’ immigration status, leaving the victim afraid to report the abuse to law enforcement and fearful of assisting with the investigation and prosecution of associated crimes.”197 Therefore, I propose that the U Visa petitioning requirements, located within 8 U.S.C. § 1184(p)(1), be amended as follows198: (1) Petitioning procedures for section 1101(a)(15)(U) visas The petition filed by an alien under section 1101(a)(15)(U)(i) of this title shall contain a certification from a Federal, State, or local law enforcement official, prosecutor, judge, or other Federal, State, or local authority investigating criminal activity described in section 1101(a)(15)(U)(iii) of this title. This certification may also be provided by an official of the Service whose ability to provide such certification is not limited to information concerning immigration violations. This certification shall state that the alien “has been helpful, is being helpful, or is likely to be helpful” in the investigation or prosecution of criminal activity described in section 1101(a)(15)(U)(iii) of this title. [Exception: in the case of an alien who was admitted to the United States pursuant to a K-1 Visa as the fiancé(e) of a citizen of the United States but who failed to enter into a marriage because of that citizen’s abuse, certification shall not be required and the alien shall only be required to demonstrate any credible evidence of abuse, including but not limited to 196 See supra Part III.B. S. REP. NO. 112-153, at 12. Among the proposed amendments explained in the Senate report are an expansion of the annual cap on U Visas and adding “stalking” to the list of qualifying crimes. Id. 198 The italicized language in brackets represents the proposed amendments. Related sections of the United States Code and the Code of Federal Regulations would likely need to be amended as well. 197 162 BROOKLYN LAW REVIEW [Vol. 78:1 photographs, emergency room reports, police reports, affidavits, and victim and witness testimony.] This amendment to the U Visa requirements would enable an abused K Visa holder, such as Ayana, to obtain immigration relief by demonstrating abuse, rather than by requiring her to affirmatively report abuse to police and seek law enforcement certification—something a typical battered immigrant woman is unlikely to do and that could put her at risk of removal if she has already overstayed the K Visa without marrying her abuser.199 Moreover, the law should be more concerned with empowering abused women to escape from relationships where domestic violence occurs, rather than focusing on the prosecution of abusers, to the extent those objectives are at odds with one another. Importantly, the VAWA self-petition does not require applicants to be helpful in investigating or prosecuting domestic violence; K Visa holders should not be made to do so simply because they would prefer not to marry their abusive fiancés. Accordingly, the proposed amendment is a reasonable alternative for abused K Visa holders, who would have a more viable incentive to leave their abusive USC fiancés. CONCLUSION As Congress considers reauthorization of the Violence Against Women Act, it should reflect upon the difficulties affecting abused immigrant fiancées like Ayana who enter the United States on K Visas and experience abuse within the first ninety days of their arrival. Congress should amend the Immigration and Nationality Act to permit women who enter the United States on valid K Visas to file VAWA self-petitions if they subsequently find themselves in abusive relationships with their fiancés, even if they do not ultimately marry their intended spouses. In the alternative, the U Visa provisions should be amended to provide abused K Visa recipients with an easier avenue to legitimate immigration status, without requiring them to report their abuse to the police or obtain law enforcement certification. Reporting abuse should be encouraged, but not required because of abused immigrants’ understandable fears of deportation. Battered K Visa holders like Ayana find themselves trapped in an intolerable position, where they must either remain 199 See supra Part III.B. Of course, applying for a U Visa could also put her at risk of removal—in the event her application is denied—since it would notify the authorities of her unlawful presence (assuming her K Visa has expired). 2012] IMPROVEMENTS FOR IMMIGRANT FIANCÉES 163 with their abusers to secure the immigration benefits associated with marriage, return to their home countries, reside in the United States illegally, or pursue more challenging avenues to legal immigration status. Unjustly, this puts more power in the hands of an abusive USC petitioner, who may still threaten his fiancée with deportation. It also unfairly forces the battered woman to choose between several untenable options, all because of the abuse that has been perpetrated upon her by a citizen of the United States. Obviously, these already dire circumstances are even worse for a battered K Visa holder who has children. Ayana relied on the promises of her fiancé to treat her well and care for her and her children. She endured a long administrative process and demonstrated satisfactory evidence of her intent to enter into a marriage within ninety days of her arrival in the United States. Ayana and her children envisioned a better life. Instead, when she arrived in New York, she was beaten, treated cruelly, and left with nothing but difficult choices. This result is antithetical to VAWA’s promise of enabling battered women to escape from their abusers, and for these reasons, the INA should be amended upon VAWA’s reauthorization to allow for abused K Visa holders to attain legal immigration status without marrying their batterers. Ultimately, if abuse arises within the first ninety days of an immigrant fiancée’s admission into the United States, immigration policy should not create the perverse incentive for her to proceed with her marriage to an abusive fiancé. In the balance between preventing immigration fraud and protecting battered immigrant women, the scales should not tip so far that the vulnerable fall to the wayside. Adam B. Horowitz† † J.D. Candidate, Brooklyn Law School, 2013; B.A., University of Rhode Island, 2002. I would like to thank the Brooklyn Law Review staff for their countless hours of editing and the several professors at Brooklyn Law School—particularly Mark Noferi, Stacy Caplow, and Dan Smulian—who provided helpful critique of this note. Thanks to Andrea Panjwani and African Services Committee for the inspiration. I would also like to extend my heartfelt gratitude to my family and friends who have sustained me through life, and to my second family in Karantaba. Thank you, Mom and Dad, for your love and encouragement. Thanks, Josh, for the life-long technical support. And to Arame, for all that you are. It is my wish that this work serve as a contribution to legal developments based on reason, mindfulness, and compassion. I hope this will give a voice to those who are silenced, and shine light upon those living in shadows. Softwood Lumber’s “Termite” Problem 1 WHY THE EXTENSION OF THE 2006 SOFTWOOD LUMBER AGREEMENT IS RIGHT FOR SOFTWOOD LUMBER BUT WRONG FOR THE MULTILATERAL TRADING SYSTEM INTRODUCTION On January 24, 2012, United States Trade Representative Ron Kirk and Canadian Minister for International Trade Ed Fast signed a two-year extension of the 2006 Softwood Lumber Agreement (SLA 2006),2 extending the agreement through October 12, 2015.3 The SLA 2006 governs the most notorious trade dispute in the history of Canadian-American relations: the Canada-United States softwood lumber dispute.4 The softwood lumber dispute centers on allegations by the United States that the Canadian government unfairly subsidizes its softwood 1 See JAGDISH BHAGWATI, TERMITES IN THE TRADING SYSTEM: HOW PREFERENTIAL AGREEMENTS UNDERMINE FREE TRADE xii (2008). 2 Softwood Lumber Agreement Between the Government of Canada and the Government of the United States of America, U.S.-Can., Sept. 12, 2006, Temp. State Dep’t No. 07-222, KAV 8209, available at http://www.ustr.gov/webfm_send/3254 (last visited Nov. 21, 2012), amended by Agreement Between the Government of Canada and the Government of the United States of America Amending the Softwood Lumber Agreement Between the Government of Canada and the Government of the United States of America, U.S.-Can., Oct. 12, 2006, Temp. State Dep’t No. 07-223, KAV 8310, available at http://www.international.gc.ca/controls-controles/assets/pdfs/softwood/ Agreementamending-en.pdf (last visited Sept. 23, 2011) [hereinafter SLA 2006]. 3 Agreement Between the Government of Canada and the Government of the United States of America Extending the Softwood Lumber Agreement Between the Government of Canada and the Government of the United States of America, as Amended, U.S.-Can., Jan. 23, 2012, http://www.international.gc.ca/controls-controles/softwood-bois_ oeuvre/other-autres/SLA_2012.aspx?lang=eng&view=d (last visited May 16, 2012). 4 See e.g., GREGORY W. BOWMAN, NICK COVELLI, DAVID A. GANTZ & IHN HO UHM, TRADE REMEDIES IN NORTH AMERICA 553 (2010) (“The softwood lumber dispute between the United States and Canada represents the longest-running and perhaps most bitter trade dispute ever between the two countries.”); DAOWEI ZHANG, THE SOFTWOOD LUMBER WAR: POLITICS, ECONOMICS, AND THE LONG U.S.-CANADIAN TRADE DISPUTE 1 (2007) (“Since the value of softwood lumber trade currently exceeds US$7 billion annually, this disagreement easily ranks as the largest trade dispute between the two countries in the modern era, and its longevity has defied many seasoned observers.”). 165 166 BROOKLYN LAW REVIEW [Vol. 78:1 lumber industry, allowing Canadian lumber producers to dump their products into the U.S. market at below production cost.5 In large part, these allegations stem from the countries’ differing systems of forest management.6 In the United States, forest land is mostly privately owned, and market forces generally determine the stumpage fees harvesters must pay for timber.7 In Canada, because the majority of its forests are considered public land, provincial governments set the fees that harvesters must pay.8 Many U.S. lumber producers believe that the Canadian system qualifies as a subsidy, by creating “chronically below-market-value stumpage charges,”9 and have long urged the U.S. government to impose countervailing (CVD) and antidumping (AD) duties on imports of Canadian softwood products.10 Their claims have led to nearly three decades of litigation.11 This dispute should be of particular concern to both Canadians and Americans alike, as Canada is currently the United States’ largest trading partner in goods, with the two 5 See, e.g., Press Release, Coalition for Fair Lumber Imports, U.S. Coalition for Fair Lumber Imports Demands Relief from Canadian Subsidies, Dumping (Apr. 2, 2001), available at http://www.uslumbercoalition.org/doc/4_2_01release.pdf [hereinafter Coalition Demands]. 6 BOWMAN ET AL., supra note 4, at 556 (“In the United States, some 70% of timberlands are privately owned. In Canada, in contrast, 94% of the forests are on provincial or federal government (‘Crown’) lands.”). 7 Michael Hart & Bill Dymond, The Cul-de-Sac of Softwood Lumber, 26 POL’Y OPTIONS no. 9, 2005, at 20. “Stumpage [fees]” are what lumber companies must pay for the right to harvest timber. Id. at 19. 8 Id. at 19-20. 9 Henry Spelter, If America Had Canada’s Stumpage System, 52 FOREST SCI. 443, 444 (2006). Spelter believes that it is “unclear whether this is a subsidy in the sense that the [NAFTA] and [WTO] agreements were meant to deal with, i.e., direct financial aid furnished by a government.” Id. 10 See, e.g., Coalition Demands, supra note 5. In the United States, a domestic industry that believes it is being injured by way of a foreign government subsidizing foreign exporters or a foreign producer dumping an export in the United States at a price lower than its home market price may file a petition with both the International Trade Administration, which is part of the Department of Commerce (Commerce), and the International Trade Commission (ITC), which is an independent agency. U.S. Dep’t of Commerce, An Introduction to U.S. Trade Remedies, IMP. ADMIN., http://ia.ita.doc.gov/intro/index.html (last visited Oct. 29, 2011). Commerce determines whether the import is, in fact, being subsidized or dumped into the market, while the ITC determines whether the import is causing material injury, or threatening to cause an injury, to the domestic industry. Id. “If both Commerce and the ITC make affirmative findings . . . , Commerce instructs U.S. Customs and Border Protection [(CBP)] to assess duties against imports of that product into the United States.” Id. 11 Canada-U.S. Softwood Lumber Trade Relations (1982–2006), FOREIGN AFFAIRS & INT’L TRADE CAN., http://www.international.gc.ca/controls-controles/softwoodbois_oeuvre/notices-avis/82-06.aspx?lang=eng&view=d (last modified Apr. 20, 2009). 2012] SOFTWOOD LUMBER’S “TERMITE” PROBLEM 167 countries trading over $597 billion during 2011 alone.12 More specifically, Canada has historically been the largest source of lumber imports in the United States.13 Culminating with the SLA 2006, the most recent developments in the softwood lumber dispute resulted from what commentators have labeled a “hydra” of litigation.14 Disputes were settled under Chapters 11 and 19 of the North American Free Trade Agreement (NAFTA), the World Trade Organization (WTO) dispute settlement system, and within U.S. domestic courts.15 This overlap is a result of the proliferation of preferential trade agreements (PTAs)16 within the international trading system, which enable parties to seek recourse under multiple dispute settlement regimes.17 Although NAFTA contains a choice of forum clause intended to prevent overlap in dispute settlement,18 the clause does not apply to final AD or CVD determinations, such as those at issue in the 12 Top Trading Partners, U.S. CENSUS BUREAU, http://www.census.gov/ foreign-trade/statistics/highlights/top/top1112yr.html (last visited Dec. 19, 2012). 13 BOWMAN ET AL., supra note 4, at 553. 14 John H. Knox, The 2005 Activity of the NAFTA Tribunals, 100 AM. J. INT’L L. 429, 436 (2006). 15 See infra Part II. 16 Preferential trade agreements (also referred to as “regional trade agreements”) are agreements by which “parties to [the agreement] offer to each other . . . more favorable treatment in trade matters than [what is offered] to the rest of the world, including WTO Members.” Rafael Leal-Arcas, Proliferation of Regional Trade Agreements: Complementing or Supplanting Multilateralism?, 11 CHI. J. INT’L L. 597, 600 (2011). PTAs are a “departure from the WTO [most-favored nation] principle of non-discrimination,” but are WTO-consistent under three rules: (i) GATT Article XXIV:4-10; (ii) the Enabling Clause, and (3) GATT Article V. Id. at 602. The majority of PTAs are in the form of free trade agreements (FTAs), such as NAFTA. BHAGWATI, supra note 1, at 1. Because even those commentators who use the term “regional trade agreements” admit that these agreements “may be . . . concluded between countries not necessarily located in the same geographic region,” I believe that PTAs is a more accurate label. Leal-Arcas, supra, at 600. Between 1985 and 2005, the share of world trade that came from PTAs grew from approximately 20% to around 50%. Id. at 602. To date, various states have notified over 500 PTAs to the WTO Secretariat and numerous others are currently under negotiation. Regional Trade Agreements, WORLD TRADE ORG., http://www.wto.org/english/tratop_e/region_e/region_e.htm (last visited Jan. 7, 2012). Of the 233 PTAs currently in force, approximately 85% are FTAs such as NAFTA. See List of All RTAs, WORLD TRADE ORG., http://rtais.wto.org/UI/ PublicAllRTAList.aspx (last visited Sept. 12, 2012). 17 Jennifer Hillman, Conflicts Between Dispute Settlement Mechanisms in Regional Trade Agreements and the WTO—What Should the WTO Do?, 42 CORNELL INT’L L.J. 193, 194 (2009) (noting the “problems that can arise from the overlap or conflict between these RTA settlement provisions and the Dispute Settlement Understanding of the WTO”). 18 North American Free Trade Agreement Between the Government of the United States of America, the Government of Canada and the Government of the United Mexican States, U.S.-Can.-Mex., art. 2005(6), Dec. 17, 1992, 32 I.L.M. 612, 695 (1993) [hereinafter NAFTA]. 168 BROOKLYN LAW REVIEW [Vol. 78:1 softwood lumber dispute.19 More generally, there is little clarity on the exact legal relationship between PTA and WTO dispute settlement systems.20 General Agreement on Tariffs and Trade (GATT) Article XXIV addresses only the “formation” of PTAs and is silent on issues pertaining to the operational relationship between PTAs and the WTO.21 Moreover, there is no overarching statute that defines the authority of one tribunal in relation to another.22 This uncertainty is directly linked to the superfluous litigation discussed below. The growth of PTAs has several explanations—most notably the stalled Doha Round of multilateral trade negotiations23—and the impact PTAs have on the multilateral trading system is much debated.24 This debate is beyond the scope of the instant analysis. For the purposes of this note, which examines a PTA sub-agreement (the SLA 2006),25 I have accepted the position that PTAs undercut the multilateral trading system. The extension of the SLA 2006 raises two important questions: first, what does it mean for the softwood lumber dispute itself; and, second, what does it mean for the multilateral trading system as a whole? Put differently, if PTAs such as NAFTA are the “termites” of the multilateral trading system,26 can an agreement spawned from NAFTA’s own failures act as an insecticide, helping to exterminate these preferential 19 Id. at art. 2004. Parties have also been reluctant to rely on NAFTA Article 2005 even outside the context of AD and CVD cases. Joost Pauwelyn & Luiz Eduardo Salles, Forum Shopping Before International Tribunals: (Real) Concerns, (Im)Possible Solutions, 42 CORNELL INT’L L.J. 77, 89 (2009). 20 Hillman, supra note 17, at 197. 21 Sungjoon Cho, Breaking the Barrier Between Regionalism and Multilateralism: A New Perspective on Trade Regionalism, 42 HARV. INT’L L.J. 419, 452 (2001). The Doha Declaration includes a negotiating mandate to clarify and improve “disciplines and procedures under the existing WTO provisions applying to regional trade agreements.” World Trade Org., Ministerial Declaration of 14 Nov. 2001, ¶ 29, WT/MIN(01)/DEC/1, 41 I.L.M. 746 (2002). 22 Pauwelyn & Salles, supra note 19, at 84. 23 Leal-Arcas, supra note 16, at 621-23 (listing other economic and political reasons why countries agree to PTAs so frequently); see also BHAGWATI, supra note 1, at 16-47 (listing the “many reasons why PTAs have now turned into a pandemic and a pox on the world trading system”). 24 See, e.g., Cho, supra note 21, at 429-35; Leal-Arcas, supra note 16, at 623-26. 25 The term “PTA sub-agreement” is meant to describe a trade agreement between two countries that have already agreed to a PTA. In this analysis, the PTA sub-agreement at issue is the SLA 2006, between Canada and the United States who are both members of NAFTA. 26 BHAGWATI, supra note 1, at xii (“Acting like termites, PTAs are eating away at the multilateral trading system relentlessly and progressively.”). But see LealArcas, supra note 16, at 629 (arguing that RTAs can “complement” multilateralism). I should note that termites seem like an especially suitable analogy when discussing a trade agreement dealing with softwood lumber. 2012] SOFTWOOD LUMBER’S “TERMITE” PROBLEM 169 agreements? Or, does such an agreement only add to the forces undercutting the long-term prospects for multilateralism? This note will argue that parties directly involved in the Canadian-American softwood lumber trade should welcome the extension of the SLA 2006. But this support should come with pause—especially for those who wish to see the global trading community return more ardently to the multilateral system. While the streamlined dispute settlement process of the SLA 200627 has thus far proven to be the most effective solution to the lumber saga, this is only because the alternative monstrous “hydra” of litigation is impracticable. A workable resolution to NAFTA’s largest and most bitter dispute that fails to directly address the systemic shortcomings of PTAs will only temporarily insulate the parties from the underlying problems and will draw their attention further away from wholesale multilateralism.28 The SLA 2006 is not a grand solution for the problems of the multilateral trading system. This note is divided into five sections. Part I describes the early history of the softwood lumber dispute from 1982 to 2001. Part II highlights the superfluous litigation that occurred between 2001 and 2006, which culminated in the SLA 2006. This section provides a brief overview of the disputes that occurred within NAFTA, the WTO, and U.S. domestic courts, and it highlights the problems that were caused by these overlapping dispute settlement mechanisms. Part III provides an overview of the SLA 2006 and briefly addresses the disputes that have arisen under this agreement. Part IV explains why the SLA 2006 is the most practical solution to the softwood lumber dispute, arguing that a negotiated agreement with a straightforward dispute settlement mechanism is necessary to offset the United States’ stubborn political protection of its softwood lumber industry. Finally, Part V explains how the softwood lumber dispute highlights the shortcomings of PTAs and argues that, in the case of NAFTA, taking lumber out of the equation removes a major incentive to correct these deficiencies. 27 SLA 2006, supra note 2, at art. XIV. See Michael S. Valihora, NAFTA Chapter 19 or the WTO’s Dispute Settlement Body: A Hobson’s Choice for Canada?, 30 CASE W. RES. J. INT’L L. 447, 471 (1998). (“Perhaps the Softwood Lumber Dispute is simply too big for [NAFTA Chapter 19], but the mechanism is sufficient in most circumstances.”). This point, made in 1998, highlights both the atypical size of the softwood lumber dispute, and the shortcomings of NAFTA. A dispute settlement mechanism that is “sufficient in most circumstances” is, by its nature, patently insufficient. 28 170 I. BROOKLYN LAW REVIEW [Vol. 78:1 THE EARLY BATTLES—THE HISTORY OF THE SOFTWOOD LUMBER DISPUTE (1982–2001) The modern history of the softwood lumber dispute is best understood as four discrete “battles”29: Lumber I (1982– 1983), Lumber II (1986–1991), Lumber III (1991–1996), and Lumber IV (2001–2006).30 As one commentator suggests, this history “involves extremely arcane points of anti-dumping and countervailing duty law and an extraordinarily convoluted litigation history.”31 Despite the protracted nature of the dispute, it is important to address each stage in order to understand how and why wood has been the source of a thirtyyear trade war. Accordingly, this note will briefly address Lumber I, II, and III below.32 This note will discuss Lumber IV in greater detail in Part II, given that it culminated in the agreement that is the focus of this note: the SLA 2006.33 A. Lumber I (1982–1983) Lumber I began in 1982 when a coalition of U.S. lumber producers, later known as the Coalition for Fair Lumber Imports (Lumber Coalition), filed a CVD petition with the Department of Commerce (Commerce).34 The petition alleged that the Canadian government subsidized softwood lumber through various programs that set artificially low stumpage rates for Canadian producers.35 Commerce initiated an investigation, but it eventually determined that no subsidy existed within the meaning of domestic CVD law and dismissed 29 BOWMAN ET AL., supra note 4, at 554. Other commentators describe the dispute as “A War between Friends.” See ZHANG, supra note 4, at 1. 30 Canada-U.S. Softwood Lumber Trade Relations (1982–2006), supra note 11. For the purposes of this note, I address Lumber IV as beginning with the expiration of the 1996 Canada-United States Softwood Lumber Agreement, which occurred on March 31, 2001. Id. 31 Jeffrey L. Dunoff, The Many Dimensions of Softwood Lumber, 45 ALTA. L. REV. 319, 320 (2007). 32 Other sources provide excellent summaries of the early history of the dispute in much greater detail. See, e.g., BOWMAN ET AL., supra note 4, at 556-69; ZHANG, supra note 4, at 24-165; Kevin C. Kennedy, A Legal History of the Softwood Lumber Dispute (in a Nutshell), 52 FOREST SCI. 432, 432-36 (2006). 33 See infra Part II. 34 U.S. Dep’t of Commerce, Initiation of Countervailing Duty Investigations; Certain Softwood Lumber Products from Canada, 47 Fed. Reg. 49,878 (Nov. 3, 1982); see also supra note 10 (discussing CVD laws). 35 Certain Softwood Lumber Products from Canada, 47 Fed. Reg. 49,878. 2012] SOFTWOOD LUMBER’S “TERMITE” PROBLEM 171 the petition.36 Lumber I is the only round of the softwood lumber dispute that did not produce a negotiated settlement.37 B. Lumber II (1986–1991) The peace that Lumber I established was short-lived. In 1986, the Lumber Coalition filed a second CVD petition, but this time Commerce issued an affirmative preliminary determination, ruling that Canada’s provincial stumpage programs constituted a 15% subsidy.38 Although an affirmative preliminary determination is usually followed by a final determination, no final determination was reached in Lumber II.39 Rather, the investigation was suspended when Canada and the United States signed a Memorandum of Understanding (MOU) in December 1986, where Canada agreed to impose a 15% tax on exports of softwood lumber to the United States, which Canada could proportionately phase out if the provinces increased their stumpage fees.40 Despite this agreement, both governments reserved their positions as to whether Canada’s stumpage programs qualified as subsidies.41 As a result, the conflict at the root of the dispute remained unresolved. By 1991, Canada’s major lumber exporting provinces had independently increased their stumpage fees and, pursuant to the terms of the agreement, Canada eliminated the export tax for exports from British Columbia and lowered it to 3.1% for exports from Quebec.42 Nevertheless, high-level Canadian officials remained dissatisfied with the agreement. In October 1991, armed with a new dispute settlement 36 U.S. Dep’t of Commerce, Final Negative Countervailing Duty Determinations: Certain Softwood Products from Canada, 48 Fed. Reg. 24,159, 24,159 (May 31, 1983) (finding that the subsidies were “de minimis” and therefore did not constitute subsidies within the meaning of section 701 of the Tariff Act of 1930). CVDs may only be imposed if the countervailable subsidy is above a de minimis level. BOWMAN ET AL., supra note 4, at 128. The standard de minimis threshold for CVD investigations is 1%. Id. 37 David Quayat, The Forest for the Trees: A Roadmap to Canada’s Litigation Experience in Lumber IV, 12 J. INT’L ECON. L. 115, 122 (2009). 38 U.S. Dep’t of Commerce, Preliminary Affirmative Countervailing Duty Determination: Certain Softwood Lumber Products from Canada, 51 Fed. Reg. 37,453 (Oct. 22, 1986). 39 BOWMAN ET AL., supra note 4, at 134. 40 See Statement Regarding the Agreement Between the United States and Canada Concerning Trade in Certain Softwood Lumber Products with Memorandum of Understanding, Agreed Minute and Related Letters, U.S.-Can., Dec. 30, 1986, Temp. State Dep’t No. 87-31, KAV 272, at [i]. 41 Id. ¶ 3(b). 42 BOWMAN ET AL., supra note 4, at 560. 172 BROOKLYN LAW REVIEW [Vol. 78:1 provision under the Canada-United States Free Trade Agreement (CUSFTA)—which permitted review of adverse AD/CVD determinations directly to a binational panel43— Canada terminated the MOU.44 The United States’ reaction was both “swift and unprecedented,”45 and Lumber III was launched before the end of the month. C. Lumber III and the 1996 Softwood Lumber Agreement (1991–2001) Although Canada’s termination of the MOU should have come with little surprise to U.S. officials, Commerce’s swift response was indicative of its disappointment with Canada’s decision.46 On October 31, 1991, Commerce took the exceptional step of self-initiating a CVD investigation for the first time in its history.47 Unlike in Lumber II, Commerce eventually reached a final affirmative subsidy determination, which was soon followed by a final affirmative injury determination by the U.S. International Trade Commission (ITC).48 As a result of these rulings, Canadian lumber exporters faced an unprecedented CVD of 6.51% on all products entering the U.S. market.49 43 Canada-United States: Free-Trade Agreement, U.S.-Can., ch. 19, Dec. 22, 1987, 27 I.L.M. 293 (1988). The Canada-United States Free-Trade Agreement (CUSFTA) was a predecessor to NAFTA. Quayat, supra note 37, at 123. During the negotiations for the CUSFTA, AD/CVD were a source of much controversy. Canada wished to see AD/CVD eliminated, and the United States was intent on retaining them. Knox, supra note 14, at 434. The result was that the parties were allowed to seek review of adverse AD/CVD determinations directly to a binational panel, rather than to the domestic court of the country imposing the duties. Id. Despite the fact that this was meant only to serve as a temporary solution, NAFTA negotiators included it with only “minor modifications.” Id. 44 BOWMAN ET AL., supra note 4, at 560. 45 Quayat, supra note 37, at 123. 46 BOWMAN ET AL., supra note 4, at 560-61. 47 U.S. Dept. of Commerce, Self-Initiation of Countervailing Duty Investigation: Certain Softwood Lumber Products from Canada, 56 Fed. Reg. 56,055 (Oct. 31, 1991); Kennedy, supra note 32, at 434. A CVD investigation is usually initiated by an industry petition. See supra note 10. 48 U.S. Dep’t of Commerce, Final Affirmative Countervailing Duty Determination: Certain Softwood Lumber Products from Canada, 57 Fed. Reg. 22,570 (May 28, 1992); Softwood Lumber from Canada, Inv. Nos. 701-TA-414, 731-TA-928, 57 Fed. Reg. 31389 (July 15, 1992) (final). Under U.S. CVD laws, both a finding of an actionable subsidy and a finding of a material injury are required to apply CVDs. See supra note 10. 49 Certain Softwood Lumber Products from Canada, 57 Fed. Reg. 22,570. Commerce found two types of subsidies—stumpage programs and log export regulations—and determined that they resulted in a net subsidy of 6.51% ad valorem. Id. at 22,570, 22,580, 22,604. Softwood Lumber I ended when Commerce determined that no countervailable subsidy existed. See supra Part I.A. Softwood Lumber II ended with the 1986 Memorandum of Understanding. See supra Part I.B. 2012] SOFTWOOD LUMBER’S “TERMITE” PROBLEM 173 This, however, was only the beginning of Lumber III. The defining characteristic of the modern state of the softwood lumber dispute is a seemingly endless, often controversial course of litigation. And as a sign of things to come, Canada responded by exercising its rights under the recently enacted dispute settlement mechanisms of the CUSFTA and seeking panel review of the United States’ use of trade remedies against its exports of softwood lumber.50 Canada appealed both the ITC’s injury determination51 and Commerce’s subsidy determination.52 These appeals were resolved largely in Canada’s favor. First, in reviewing the affirmative injury determination, the CUSFTA panel rejected the ITC’s finding of material injury and remanded the issue for reconsideration.53 Despite the ITC’s multiple attempts to address the panel’s concerns on remand, the CUSFTA panel continued to rule in Canada’s favor.54 Similarly, in reviewing Commerce’s affirmative subsidy determination, the CUSFTA panel found that a number of Commerce’s findings were unsupported by law and remanded the issue to Commerce for further consideration.55 After one remand, the CUSFTA panel ruled along national lines, with a Canadian majority finding that Commerce’s determinations were again unsupported by U.S. law and remanding with instructions that Commerce make a determination consistent with the panel’s finding that no countervailable subsidy existed.56 50 Chapter 19 is a dispute resolution mechanism that replaces U.S. or Canadian judicial review of final AD/CVD determinations with a binational panel. See supra note 43. 51 United States-Canada Free Trade Agreement Binational Panel Review, In the Matter of: Softwood Lumber from Canada, Reviewing the Final Determinations of the U.S. International Trade Commission, at 1, USA-92-1904-02 (July 26, 1993) [hereinafter Lumber III Injury CUSFTA Panel Decision]. 52 United States-Canada Free Trade Agreement Binational Panel Review, In the Matter Certain Softwood Lumber Products from Canada, at 1, USA-92-1904-01 (May 6, 1993) [hereinafter Lumber III Subsidy CUSFTA Panel Decision]. 53 Lumber III Injury CUSFTA Panel Decision, supra note 51, at 20 (concluding that “the [U.S. International Trade] Commission’s determination of material injury by reason of subsidized Canadian imports is not supported by substantial evidence on the record,” and remanding “the Commission’s final determination for reconsideration”). 54 United States-Canada Free Trade Agreement Binational Panel Review, In the Matter of: Softwood Lumber from Canada, at 8, USA-92-1904-02 (July 6, 1994); United States-Canada Free Trade Agreement Binational Panel Review, In the Matter of: Softwood Lumber from Canada, Decision of the Panel on Review of the Remand Determination of the U.S. International Trade Commission, at 35, USA-92-1904-02 (Jan. 28, 1994). 55 Lumber III Subsidy CUSFTA Panel Decision, supra note 52, at 147. 56 United States-Canada Free Trade Agreement Binational Panel Review, In the Matter of Certain Softwood Lumber Products from Canada, at 7-8, USA-92-1904-01 (Dec. 17, 1993). 174 BROOKLYN LAW REVIEW [Vol. 78:1 Adding to the controversy, the United States appealed the panel’s ruling to an Extraordinary Challenge Committee (ECC).57 The United States alleged that the panel “exceeded its powers, authority and jurisdiction by ignoring the Chapter 19 standard of review” and that certain members of the panel were in “a serious conflict of interest.”58 Ultimately, in another vote running along national lines, the ECC dismissed the United States’ challenges.59 Despite this ruling, Lumber III continued. Although the United States agreed to revoke its CVD order, terminate the collection of all duties, and refund approximately $800 million that Canadian softwood lumber importers had paid,60 Congress responded to the ECC decision by amending U.S. trade law in a manner that “effectively neutralized” the CUSFTA panel findings on subsidy and injury.61 Shortly after the passage of these amendments, and with the Lumber Coalition poised to file a new CVD petition,62 the United States and Canada began negotiating an agreement to resolve Lumber III. The two countries eventually signed the 1996 Softwood Lumber Agreement (SLA 1996),63 and in exchange for Canada’s commitment to reduce its lumber 57 Although Chapter 19 decisions are binding and cannot be appealed in national courts, the ECC may reverse a panel finding where a member of the panel is “guilty of gross misconduct, bias, or serious conflict of interest,” or where a panel “seriously departed from a fundamental rule of procedure” or “manifestly exceeded its powers.” NAFTA, supra note 18, at art. 1904(13). 58 United States-Canada Free Trade Agreement Extraordinary Challenge Proceeding, In the Matter of: Certain Softwood Lumber Products from Canada, at 1112, ECC-94-1904-01 USA (Aug. 3, 1994) (Opinion of Mr. Justice Gordon L.S. Hart). 59 Id. at 33 (Opinion of the Hon. Herbert B. Morgan). Judge Malcolm Wilkey, the retired Chief Judge of the D.C. Circuit, dissented and accused the panel of substituting its judgment for what U.S. law should be, rather than deferring to what U.S. law was, as required by the Chapter 19 standard of review. Id. at 11 (Dissenting Opinion of U.S. Circuit Judge (Ret.) Malcolm Wilkey) (“The United States never contemplated that United States law would be changed by a binational body. If the [Chapter 19] appellate system does not achieve similar results in applying U.S. law, it may not be long continued.”). Despite fears of national bias, as of 2006, the Lumber III review remained the only instance under Chapter 19 where binational panels have split along national lines. Kennedy, supra note 32, at 435. 60 Notice of Panel Decision, Revocation of Countervailing Duty Order and Termination of Suspension of Liquidation, 59 Fed. Reg. 42,029 (Aug. 16, 1994); Drew Fagan & Barrie McKenna, Softwood Duties Coming Home: U.S. to Return About $800million to Canadian Exporters, GLOBE & MAIL (Can.), Dec. 3, 1994, at B1. 61 Quayat, supra note 37, at 125; see also Kennedy, supra note 32, at 435. 62 BOWMAN ET AL., supra note 4, at 565. 63 Softwood Lumber Agreement, U.S-Can., May 29, 1996, available at http://www.international.gc.ca/controls-controles/assets/pdfs/softwood/treaty-e.pdf (last visited Nov. 2, 2011) [hereinafter SLA 1996]. 2012] SOFTWOOD LUMBER’S “TERMITE” PROBLEM 175 exports to the United States through a soft quota,64 the United States agreed not to initiate any new trade actions.65 Few disputes arose under the SLA 1996,66 but, despite a provision for extending the agreement,67 Canada and the United States failed to agree to the terms of an extension. Accordingly, the agreement expired on March 31, 2001.68 While the disputes under Lumber I, II, and III are telling examples of a “[w]ar between [f]riends,”69 not until Lumber IV did it become painstakingly clear that the region’s foremost trade agreement, NAFTA, was incapable of providing a Softwood Lumber armistice. II. THE SOFTWOOD LUMBER “HYDRA”70—LUMBER IV (2001– 2006) Canada deployed what has been aptly described as an “exhaustive” litigation strategy in Lumber IV.71 Following another round of AD/CVD petitions from the Lumber Coalition,72 a “hydra” of litigation ensued under NAFTA Chapters 11 and 19, the WTO dispute settlement system, and U.S. domestic trade law.73 These challenges, which are addressed below,74 created a chaotic overlap between dispute settlement processes that ultimately pushed the parties toward a negotiated settlement in the form of the SLA 2006. Although this agreement 64 Canada was entitled to ship 14.7 billion board feet of lumber duty free annually. Amounts shipped in excess of the amount were subject to a series of escalating export taxes. Id. at art. II(2). 65 Id. at art. I. 66 Sarah E. Lysons, Comment, Resolving the Softwood Lumber Dispute, 32 SEATTLE U. L. REV. 407, 421 (2009). 67 SLA 1996, supra note 63, at art. X. 68 BOWMAN ET AL., supra note 4, at 569. 69 ZHANG, supra note 4, at 1. 70 Knox, supra note 14, at 436. 71 Quayat, supra note 37, at 126. 72 In a move that demonstrates why parties directly involved in the Canadian-American softwood lumber trade should welcome the extension of the SLA 2006, it took all of one business day after the expiration of the SLA 1996 for the Lumber Coalition to file fresh AD/CVD petitions. BOWMAN ET AL., supra note 4, at 569. 73 Knox, supra note 14, at 436. 74 The futility of overlapping dispute-settlement mechanisms is best highlighted through a focus on the concurrent litigation that occurred under NAFTA and the WTO with regards to the United States’ determination that Canada had subsidized its lumber industry. See, e.g., Sydney M. Cone III, Canadian Softwood Lumber and “Free Trade” Under NAFTA, 51 N.Y.L. SCH. L. REV. 840 (2006-2007). These forums, therefore, are discussed first and in the greatest detail. The subsequent discussions regarding dumping determinations, NAFTA Chapter 11, and disputes within the U.S. domestic legal system serve to underscore the convoluted nature of the multilateral trading system’s various dispute settlement mechanisms. 176 BROOKLYN LAW REVIEW [Vol. 78:1 acknowledges the systemic shortcomings of PTAs and the overlapping dispute settlement mechanisms they create, the SLA 2006’s failure to address these issues head on does more to add to the forces undercutting multilateralism than it does to resolve the issues that created the need for an agreement. A. Are Two Heads Better than One?—Canada’s Challenges to the United States’ Subsidy Determinations Under NAFTA Chapter 19 and the WTO Dispute Settlement System Following the Lumber Coalition’s newest AD/CVD petitions, Commerce and the ITC made final affirmative determinations that Canada was subsidizing its softwood lumber industry75 and that the subsidized Canadian softwood lumber imports presented a threat of material injury to the U.S. lumber industry.76 Canada sought review of these determinations under both Chapter 19 of NAFTA and the WTO dispute settlement mechanisms.77 Although Canada was largely successful in its appeals, the “two uncoordinated avenues for resolving disputes” failed—perhaps unsurprisingly—to reach uniform resolutions and allowed the parties to engage in “litigious gamesmanship” that prolonged an already protracted dispute.78 1. Canada’s Success Under NAFTA a. NAFTA’s Review of Commerce’s Affirmative Subsidy Determination Canada was successful in its NAFTA challenge to Commerce’s final affirmative subsidy determination. The NAFTA panel reviewing the determination found that while Canada’s 75 U.S. Dep’t of Commerce, Notice of Final Affirmative Countervailing Duty Determination and Final Negative Critical Circumstances Determination: Certain Softwood Lumber Products from Canada, 67 Fed. Reg. 15,545 (Apr. 2, 2002); U.S. Dep’t of Commerce, Notice of Final Determination of Sales at Less than Fair Value: Certain Softwood Lumber Products from Canada, 67 Fed. Reg. 15,539 (Apr. 2, 2002). 76 Softwood Lumber from Canada, Inv. Nos. 701-TA-414, 731-TA-928, 67 Fed. Reg. 36,022 (May 22, 2002) (final). 77 North American Free Trade Agreement Binational Panel Review, In the Matter of Certain Softwood Lumber from Canada, Final Affirmative Countervailing Duty Determination, at 5, USA-CDA-2002-1904-03 (Aug. 13, 2003) [hereinafter Lumber IV Subsidy NAFTA Panel Decision]; Panel Report, United States—Final Countervailing Duty Determination with Respect to Certain Softwood Lumber from Canada, ¶ 1.1, WT/DS257/R (Aug. 29, 2003) [hereinafter Lumber IV Subsidy WTO Panel Report]. 78 Cone, supra note 74, at 850. 2012] SOFTWOOD LUMBER’S “TERMITE” PROBLEM 177 stumpage program constituted a financial contribution,79 the evidence Commerce relied on did not reveal the existence of a benefit. Accordingly, the panel ruled that the imports had not received an actionable subsidy.80 What resulted was a game of “ping-pong” between Commerce and the panel, where the panel would remand the determination, and Commerce would revise its methodology.81 The result of each revised subsidy determination was a reduction in the CVD rate, and by the time Commerce issued its fifth subsidy finding, it had determined that the benefit given to Canadian producers was de minimis in nature.82 Essentially, Commerce was forced to reluctantly accept the panel’s determination that Canada’s provisional stumpage programs did not confer a benefit on softwood lumber producers, and thus that no actionable subsidy existed. b. NAFTA’s Review of the ITC’s Affirmative Injury Determination Canada was also largely successful in its challenge to the ITC’s affirmative threat of injury determination. According to a NAFTA panel, there was insufficient evidence to support the ITC’s finding.83 Following this decision, another series of remands ensued. This time, however, the panel “lost patience with the game [of ping-pong],”84 refused to remand for further reevaluation, and ordered the ITC to enter a finding of no material injury.85 From NAFTA’s perspective, a U.S. agency had, again, improperly applied its domestic trade laws and improperly subjected Canadian imports of softwood lumber to CVDs. 79 Lumber IV Subsidy NAFTA Panel Decision, supra note 77, at 20. Under U.S. trade law, for a subsidy to be actionable via the imposition of countervailable duties, it must result in both a financial contribution and a benefit to the recipients of the subsidy. Id. at 17. 80 Id. at 35. 81 Knox, supra note 14, at 437. 82 North American Free Trade Agreement Binational Panel Review, In the Matter of Softwood Lumber from Canada, Final Affirmative Countervailing Duty Determination, at 4, USA-CDA-2002-1904-03 (Mar. 17, 2006). 83 North American Free Trade Agreement Binational Panel Review, In the Matter of Softwood Lumber from Canada: Final Affirmative Threat of Material Injury Determination, at 107, USA-CDA-2002-1904-07 (Sept. 5, 2003). 84 Knox, supra note 14, at 437. 85 North American Free Trade Agreement Binational Panel Review, In the Matter of Softwood Lumber from Canada: Final Affirmative Threat of Injury Determination, at 7, USA-CDA-2002-1904-07 (Aug. 31, 2004). The panel noted that, “The Commission has made it abundantly clear . . . that it is simply unwilling to accept this Panel’s review authority under Chapter 19 of the NAFTA and has consistently ignored the authority of this Panel in an effort to preserve its finding of threat of material injury.” Id. at 3. 178 BROOKLYN LAW REVIEW [Vol. 78:1 The United States launched an Extraordinary Challenge to both of the NAFTA panel rulings, but the ECC upheld the panel’s injury ruling86 and, prior to its decision on the panel’s subsidy finding, the two parties agreed to the terms of the 2006 SLA, which ended the challenge.87 Although Canada emerged victorious in the NAFTA rulings, simply cutting off one of the hydra’s heads does not slay the beast. Indeed, Canada’s challenges to the United States’ subsidy determinations also took place under the WTO dispute settlement process. Unfortunately, with no clear roadmap in place to outline the legal relationship between NAFTA and WTO dispute settlement systems,88 the WTO proceedings ran the risk of being, at best, tedious and, at worst, contradictory. 2. Mixed Results at the WTO a. The WTO’s Review of Commerce’s Affirmative Subsidy Determination Canada’s WTO arguments regarding Commerce’s affirmative subsidy determination “mirrored” its arguments before the NAFTA Chapter 19 panel.89 Similar to the NAFTA panel, both a WTO Panel and the Appellate Body (AB) agreed with the United States that the Canadian stumpage programs constituted a financial contribution under WTO subsidy law.90 Yet while NAFTA ruled decisively that the subsidy did not benefit Canadian producers—making it non-actionable—the WTO ruling on this issue is less clear. Although the WTO Panel sided with Canada and ruled that the United States used an improper methodology to 86 North American Free Trade Agreement Binational Panel Review, In the Matter of Certain Softwood Lumber Products from Canada, Opinion and Order of the Extraordinary Challenge Committee, at 2, ECC-2004-1904-01USA (Aug. 10, 2005). Notably, the panel held that “in rare circumstances,” a Panel may remand to the Commission with instructions to enter a decision that the evidence on the record does not support a threat of material injury. Id. at 15. 87 Notice of Suspension of Extraordinary Challenge Committee, 71 Fed. Reg. 28,854 (May 18, 2006). 88 See supra notes 18-22 and accompanying text. In addition to there being no overarching statute that defines the relation between PTA and WTO tribunals, domestic law concepts such as res judicata, lis pendens, and forum non conveniens, which address overlapping authority, do not apply in the NAFTA/WTO context where the two panels are, strictly speaking, applying different law. Pauwelyn & Salles, supra note 19, at 102-13. 89 Quayat, supra note 37, at 135. 90 Appellate Body Report, United States—Final Countervailing Duty Determination with Respect to Certain Softwood Lumber from Canada, ¶ 76, WT/DS257/AB/R (Jan. 19, 2004) [hereinafter Lumber IV Subsidy WTO AB Report]. 2012] SOFTWOOD LUMBER’S “TERMITE” PROBLEM 179 determine that Canada’s stumpage programs resulted in a benefit, the AB reversed this ruling.91 Nevertheless, this reversal focused on the WTO Panel’s flawed reasoning, leaving open the question of whether a benefit existed.92 Indeed, due to an “insufficient factual basis to complete the legal analysis,” the AB was unable to definitively determine whether Canada’s financial contribution had produced a benefit and thus was unable to determine whether both elements for an actionable subsidy existed.93 An issue that a NAFTA panel determined decisively was therefore left unresolved at the WTO. For the United States to successfully defend its affirmative subsidy determination at the WTO, Commerce also needed to show that the alleged subsidies to timber harvesters “pass[ed]-through” to the producers of the softwood lumber imported into the United States.94 Following several WTO Panel and AB reports,95 the AB eventually found against Commerce on this point, ruling that Commerce had conducted a defective pass-through analysis and had failed to comply with its WTO obligations.96 This marked yet another victory for Canada. b. The WTO’s Review of the ITC’s Affirmative Injury Determination Canada’s challenge to the ITC’s injury determination before the WTO was again similar to its challenges brought under NAFTA. Canada attempted to persuade the WTO that the ITC’s affirmative threat of injury finding was not supported by proper evidence.97 A WTO Panel sided with Canada, ruling that an “objective and unbiased decision maker” could not have properly found a threat of injury based upon the evidence presented to the ITC.98 But, the Panel denied Canada’s requests 91 Id. ¶ 119. Id. ¶ 122. 93 Id. 94 Cone, supra note 74, at 847. 95 These included: (i) an August 19, 2003 Panel Report, (ii) a January 19, 2004 Appellate Body Report, and (iii) an August 1, 2005 Panel Report. Id. at 848. 96 Appellate Body Report, United States—Final Countervailing Duty Determination with Respect to Certain Softwood Lumber from Canada, ¶ 96, WT/DS257/AB/RW (Dec. 5, 2005). The AB upheld the panel’s findings that Article 10 of the SCM Agreement and Article VI:3 of the GATT 1994 require a pass-through analysis in circumstances in which a subsidy is received by a harvester, and CVDs are then attached to the imports from an unrelated producer. Id. 97 Panel Report, United States—Investigation of the International Trade Commission in Softwood Lumber from Canada, WT/DS277/R, ¶¶ 4.2-4.62 (Mar. 22, 2004). 98 Id. ¶ 7.89. 92 180 BROOKLYN LAW REVIEW [Vol. 78:1 to recommend that the United States revoke its final determination of threat of injury, stop the application of duties, and return the cash deposits already collected.99 Neither the United States nor Canada appealed the Panel’s decision, but the U.S. response to the ruling gave rise to one of the most controversial events of Lumber IV.100 This suspect response underscored both the lengths the United States was willing to go to protect its softwood lumber industry and the opportunities for manipulation available within overlapping dispute settlement forums.101 3. The United States Uses a WTO Defeat to Mitigate Adverse NAFTA Rulings After the WTO Panel’s ruling that no threat of injury existed, the ITC undertook a new injury determination and again concluded that a substantial increase of Canadian softwood lumber imports presented a threat of material injury to the U.S. industry.102 From the United States’ perspective, this “new” affirmative injury finding meant that earlier rulings by multiple NAFTA panels—finding the ITC’s injury determination to be unsubstantiated by the evidence—were now moot because the ITC had made, and Commerce had adopted, a new finding.103 Put differently, the United States attempted to “use[] a WTO defeat to justify ignoring several adverse NAFTA Panel findings.”104 Canada challenged the ITC’s new threat of injury finding at the WTO, but its legitimacy was never definitively ascertained. First, a WTO Panel ruled that the ITC had cured the defects identified in the original WTO ruling, which in 99 Id. ¶¶ 8.7-8.8. Quayat, supra note 37, at 134. 101 BOWMAN ET AL., supra note 4, at 581. 102 U.S. Trade Rep., WTO Dispute Settlement Proceeding Regarding Investigation of the International Trade Commission in Softwood Lumber from Canada, 70 Fed. Reg. 36,687 (June 24, 2005). Under U.S. law, WTO rulings do not automatically bind the Executive. Rather, Section 129 of the Uruguay Round Amendments Act allows the U.S. Trade Representative to request that the ITC “issue a determination in connection with the particular proceeding that would render the Commission’s action . . . not inconsistent with the findings of the panel or Appellate Body.” 19 U.S.C § 3538(a)(4) (2006). 103 U.S. Dep’t of Commerce, Amendment to Antidumping and Countervailing Duty Orders on Certain Softwood Lumber Products from Canada, 69 Fed. Reg. 75,916, 75,917 (Dec. 20, 2004); Quayat, supra note 37, at 134. 104 BOWMAN ET AL., supra note 4, at 581. 100 2012] SOFTWOOD LUMBER’S “TERMITE” PROBLEM 181 essence affirmed the ITC’s new injury determination.105 The AB, however, set aside this ruling, finding that the Panel had applied an improper standard of review and had failed to perform a complete analysis.106 But the AB did not complete the analysis itself.107 The AB reasoned that “completing the analysis . . . would require us to review extensive aspects of the [ITC]’s threat of injury and causation analyses, and would require us to engage in a comprehensive examination of highly complex and contested facts.”108 In the end, the AB was “unable to make a recommendation to the Dispute Settlement Body,” and the validity of the ITC’s “new” injury determination was never definitively settled under WTO law.109 Although U.S. attempts to nullify the adverse NAFTA rulings were deemed improper once the issue reached the United States Court of International Trade (CIT),110 the discordant overlap between NAFTA’s and the WTO’s dispute settlement mechanisms allowed the United States to—at least temporarily—disregard a PTA dispute settlement panel’s rulings under the guise of complying with the rules of the multilateral trading system. Among the dangers associated with incongruous legal forums, this is perhaps the most alarming. B. New Allegations—Dumping Claims Under NAFTA Chapter 19 and the WTO In addition to allegations of illegal subsidies, Lumber IV also included, for the first time, a dumping claim against Canadian lumber producers.111 This claim ultimately turned on 105 Reversing its earlier finding, the Panel was unable to “conclude that an objective and unbiased investigation authority could not find that [the evidence] supported the conclusion reached by the USITC.” Panel Report, United States— Investigation of the International Trade Commission in Softwood Lumber from Canada, Recourse to Article 21.5 of the DSU by Canada, ¶ 7.39, WT/DS277/RW (Nov. 15, 2005). 106 Appellate Body Report, United States—Investigation of the International Trade Commission in Softwood Lumber from Canada, Recourse to Article 21.5 of the DSU by Canada, ¶ 138, WT/DS277/AB/RW (Apr. 13, 2006) [hereinafter Lumber IV Injury WTO AB Report]. 107 The AB only has the authority to “uphold, modify, or reverse the findings” of a WTO Panel. There is no provision at the WTO for remand with instructions. “This means that the legal issue involved can be resolved only if the [AB] completes the analysis itself.” DANIEL C.K. CHOW & THOMAS J. SCHOENBAUM, INTERNATIONAL TRADE LAW: PROBLEMS, CASES, AND MATERIALS 54 (2008). 108 Lumber IV Injury WTO AB Report, supra note 105, ¶ 160. 109 Id. ¶ 163. 110 See infra Part II.D. 111 BOWMAN ET AL., supra note 4, at 569. Dumping occurs under U.S. law when a foreign producer sells an export in the United States at a price lower than its home 182 BROOKLYN LAW REVIEW [Vol. 78:1 the United States’ use of a controversial practice known as “zeroing,” which often results in higher margins with respect to dumping calculations.112 As with Canada’s challenges to the United States’ subsidy determinations, Canada appealed to two independent dispute settlement bodies in order to resolve a single claim. After the AB upheld a WTO Panel ruling that sided with Canada and found that the United States’ use of zeroing was a violation of the WTO’s Antidumping Agreement,113 a NAFTA Chapter 19 Panel essentially incorporated the WTO’s decision and directed Commerce to make a determination on dumping without using the zeroing technique.114 While the two dumping rulings were consistent with one another, the duplicative litigation again highlights the inefficiency that plagued Lumber IV.115 C. Investor-State Claims Under NAFTA Chapter 11 Adding to the “[s]paghetti bowl of WTO and NAFTA proceedings,”116 Lumber IV also included claims under NAFTA market price. See 19 U.S.C. § 1673 (2006). Dumping investigations are conducted much in the same way as subsidy investigations. See supra note 10. 112 When zeroing is applied, the analysis treats the margins for transactions made at [less than fair value] (dumped) in accordance with the actual amounts (positive numbers), while transactions with dumping margins of less than zero (that is, made at more than fair value) are treated as zero rather than as negative numbers. Under such circumstances, higher non-dumped export prices do not offset the lower dumped export prices. BOWMAN ET AL., supra note 4, at 574. This has the potential to inflate the margins of dumping. Id. 113 Appellate Body Report, United States—Final Dumping Determination on Softwood Lumber from Canada, ¶ 117, WT/DS264/AB/R (Aug. 11, 2004). 114 North American Free Trade Agreement Binational Panel Review, In the Matter of Certain Softwood Lumber Products from Canada: Final Affirmative Antidumping Determination, at 2, USA-CDA-2002-1904-02 (June 9, 2005). 115 See, e.g., Lysons, supra note 66, at 423-24 (arguing that Canada’s litigation strategy in Lumber IV “increased costs to both Canadian and American taxpayers” and added to “the political tensions between the two countries . . . [making] settlement negotiations difficult”). The Canadian federal government spent an estimated $13 million on softwood legal fees from 2005 to 2006 alone. Sources indicate that when one combines the spending of the Canadian federal government, the provinces, individual forest companies, and forest lobby groups, the figure rises to more than $300 million over the course of Lumber IV. Sylvain Larocque, Legal Tab in Lumber Battle May Hit $300M, TORONTO STAR, Oct. 30, 2006, at A3, available at http://www.thestar.com/ news/canada/article/113100--legal-tab-in-lumber-battle-may-hit-300m. 116 Joost Pauwelyn, Adding Sweeteners to Softwood Lumber: The WTONAFTA ‘Spaghetti Bowl’ Is Cooking, 9 J. INT’L ECON. L. 197 (2006). The term “spaghetti bowl,” when discussing international trade, has been attributed to Professor Jagdish Bhagwati and is meant to describe the chaotic scene that results from multiple trade 2012] SOFTWOOD LUMBER’S “TERMITE” PROBLEM 183 Chapter 11.117 Three Canadian lumber producers initiated separate arbitration proceedings against the United States,118 alleging that its conduct in investigating and imposing of AD and CVD orders had violated their rights to national treatment,119 most-favored-nation treatment,120 and the minimum standard of treatment guaranteed under customary international law.121 In the end, the arbitral tribunal found that Chapter 11 does not encompass claims where the allegations confront the administration of trade remedy laws.122 In other words, the parties could not use Chapter 11 as an end run around Chapter 19.123 Although this ruling prevented yet another decision on the legitimacy of the United States’ use of its trade laws, the simple initiation of arbitration proceedings during Lumber IV is another example of the seemingly endless cycle of litigation that the participants faced. It was not until after the dispute reached U.S. courts that a final disposition was achieved. To the chagrin of many, however, this finality would not come by agreements crisscrossing one another like spaghetti noodles. See, e.g., BHAGWATI, supra note 1, at 61. Lumber IV is a prime example of this confusion. 117 NAFTA Chapter 11 deals with investor-state arbitrations and contains provisions designed to protect cross-border investors and facilitate the settlement of investment disputes. NAFTA, supra note 18, at art. 1101-138. 118 Tembec, Inc. v. United States, Notice of Arbitration and Statement of Arbitration Claim (NAFTA 2004), available at http://www.state.gov/documents/ organization/27805.pdf; Terminal Forest Prods. Ltd. v. United States, Notice of Arbitration (NAFTA 2003), available at http://www.state.gov/documents/organization/31360.pdf; Canfor v. United States, Notice of Arbitration and Statement of Claim (NAFTA 2002), available at http://www.state.gov/documents/organization/13203.pdf. 119 “Each Party shall accord to investors [and investments of investors] of another Party treatment no less favorable than that it accords, in like circumstances, to its own investors [and investments of its own investors] . . . .” NAFTA, supra note 18, at art. 1102(1)-(2). 120 “Each Party shall accord to investors [and investments of investors] of another Party treatment no less favorable than that it accords, in like circumstances, to investors [investments of investors] of any other Party or of a non-Party . . . .” Id. at art. 1103(1)-(2). 121 “Each Party shall accord to investments of investors of another Party treatment in accordance with international law, including fair and equitable treatment and full protection and security.” Id. at art. 1105(1). 122 Canfor v. United States; Terminal Forest Prods. Ltd. v. United States, Decision on Preliminary Question, ¶ 273 (NAFTA 2006), available at http://www.state.gov/ documents/organization/67753.pdf [hereinafter Canfor Arbitration Decision]. 123 See Quayat, supra note 37, at 132-33. The SLA 2006 resulted in the withdrawal of all claims under NAFTA Chapter 11. See SLA 2006, supra note 2, at art. XI(2) (“The operation and application of Section B of Chapter Eleven of the NAFTA is hereby suspended with respect to any matter arising under the SLA 2006 and any measure taken by a Party that is necessary to give effect to or implement the SLA 2006. Consequently, no claim under Section B of Chapter Eleven of the NAFTA may be made against a Party by investors of the United States or Canada in respect of any such matter or measure.”). 184 BROOKLYN LAW REVIEW [Vol. 78:1 way of judicial disposition, but rather through a negotiated settlement—calling into question the purpose of the previous five years’ battles.124 D. The End of Litigation—Claims Under United States Law By the time the parties agreed to the “Basic Terms” of the SLA, the softwood lumber saga had entered a third arena: the CIT. Litigation involving a single trade dispute was now pending in three separate forums. But with Canada poised to claim victory, a deal was struck, and the SLA 2006 brought an end to litigation before the effects of the CIT’s rulings were realized.125 Nevertheless, it is important to briefly address the two principal issues that were raised before the CIT, adding to the complexity of Lumber IV. First, several interested Canadian private and governmental parties brought suit to have the so-called “Byrd Amendment” struck down.126 The amendment called for the distribution of AD/CVD duties directly to members of an industry that successfully obtained protection under U.S. trade law.127 This essentially created a financial incentive for companies to file trade remedy petitions.128 The CIT sided with Canada and halted future distributions under the Byrd Amendment for actions brought against NAFTA parties.129 The United States eventually repealed the amendment, which made it clear to the Lumber Coalition that further litigation would not result in the direct delivery of any money to the U.S. lumber industry.130 Second, another group of Canadian private and governmental parties sought to challenge what they characterized as an unlawful exercise of statutory authority by 124 See, e.g., Eliot J. Feldman, Deal or No Deal: Snatching Defeat from the Jaws of Victory, 13 INT’L TRADE L. & REG. 91, 95 (2007) (arguing that “instead of winning free trade through legal proceedings, including a confirmation that Canadian provincial governments do not subsidise softwood lumber production or exports, Canada accepted draconian managed trade for potentially nine years”). 125 See infra Part III. 126 Can. Lumber Trade Alliance v. United States, 517 F.3d 1319, 1333-34 (Ct. Int’l Trade 2008). 127 19 U.S.C. § 1675c (repealed 2006). 128 Quayat, supra note 37, at 138. 129 Can. Lumber Trade Alliance, 517 F.3d at 1344 (affirming a 2006 CIT declaratory judgment that the Byrd Amendment did “not apply to antidumping and countervailing duties assessed on imports of goods from Canada or Mexico”). 130 Feldman, supra note 124, at 91. 2012] SOFTWOOD LUMBER’S “TERMITE” PROBLEM 185 the United States in its attempts to evade NAFTA panel rulings under the guise of implementing a WTO panel decision.131 A three-judge CIT panel, headed by the Chief Justice, ruled that Section 129—the tool that the United States used in its attempt to moot the NAFTA Panels’ adverse rulings on the ITC’s threat of injury findings—did not permit the substitution of a new injury determination to support existing duty orders.132 Consequently, the court validated the original NAFTA rulings, which held that the United States’ CVD/AD orders were improper, and it found that NAFTA panel review had the same legal effect as review in a U.S. court.133 The United States was, therefore, without a legal basis for maintaining its CVD/AD orders, and the Canadian parties were “entitled to a full refund of the deposits collected on softwood lumber.”134 The United States had, in effect, improperly collected over $5 billion worth of deposits.135 Over the course of Lumber IV, a disagreement over the lawfulness of differing forest management systems produced nearly thirty international and domestic decisions.136 The discordant dispute settlement mechanisms gave Canada multiple “bites at the apple” and permitted both superfluous and disingenuous litigation.137 Nevertheless, it finally appeared that the CIT’s decisions would allow Canada to claim a definite victory. Yet with this end in sight,138 it was the negotiating table, not the courtroom, that finally brought Lumber IV to a close. 131 See supra Part II.A.3; see also Tembec, Inc. v. United States, 441 F. Supp. 2d 1302, 1306 (Ct. Int’l Trade 2006) (“[Plaintiffs] allege that the United States has illegally continued to enforce antidumping (‘AD’) and countervailing duty (‘CVD’) orders following the illegal implementation of an affirmative injury determination issued by the ITC pursuant to section 129 of the Uruguay Round Agreements Act (‘URAA’).”). 132 Tembec, 441 F. Supp. 2d at 1336 (“Because section 129 only applies where the United States has lost before the WTO, Congress expected that adoption of WTO recommendations with respect to an ITC determination would result in determinations revoking all or part of an existing order, if implementation were necessary at all.” (emphasis added)). 133 Tembec, Inc. v. United States, 461 F. Supp. 2d 1355, 1364 (Ct. Int’l Trade 2006). 134 Quayat, supra note 37, at 143; see also Tembec, 461 F. Supp. 2d at 1367 (“The legislative history makes it clear that Congress did not set up a system to retain duties that are not owed.”). 135 BOWMAN ET AL., supra note 4, at 553. 136 See Quayat, supra note 37, at 116. Quayat counts twenty-six NAFTA (including panel and appellate body) and WTO decisions. Combined with the various decisions of the CIT, this number rises to nearly thirty. 137 Lysons, supra note 66 at 423. 138 The Canadian government appears to disagree with this proposition. Canada pressed its softwood lumber industry to accept the SLA 2006 by arguing the opposite: that litigation would never end. Feldman, supra note 124, at 95. 186 III. BROOKLYN LAW REVIEW [Vol. 78:1 “SNATCHING DEFEAT FROM THE JAWS OF VICTORY”139— THE TERMS OF THE 2006 SOFTWOOD LUMBER AGREEMENT On September 12, 2006, despite, or perhaps as a result of,140 Canada’s legal victories during Lumber IV, Canadian and American authorities signed the SLA 2006—a negotiated settlement that ended the most recent and heavily litigated round of the softwood lumber dispute.141 The impacts of the agreement were twofold. First, it brought stability and clarity to the dispute settlement process—much to the delight of those involved in the Canadian-American softwood lumber trade. And second, it removed much of the parties’ incentive to address NAFTA’s shortcomings head on—which should raise concerns for those who are committed to strengthening the multilateral trading system. But before addressing the conflicting impacts of the agreement and its subsequent extension, it is important to first understand what the parties actually agreed to. A. The United States Retains Its Spoils—The Issue of Duty Deposits Despite the CIT’s determination that Canada was entitled to a full refund of the deposits collected on softwood lumber,142 the SLA 2006 failed to deliver such a result.143 Under the terms of the agreement, the United States agreed to revoke its AD/CVD orders and refund approximately $4.5 billion144 in deposits it collected since 2002.145 The United States, therefore, was permitted to retain $1 billion of illegally collected duties.146 This included $500 million to the members of the Lumber Coalition, which some viewed as “a reward for 139 Id. at 91. See Quayat, supra note 37, at 144-46 (arguing that rather than using “litigation as a path to victory,” Canada used “litigation as a negotiating tool,” and “secured a sufficiently broad range of legal victories to create a significant incentive for the [United States] to find a negotiated settlement”). 141 SLA 2006, supra note 2; Quayat, supra note 37, at 116. 142 See supra Part II.D. 143 SLA 2006, supra note 2, at art. III-IV. 144 Softwood Lumber: Canada-U.S. Softwood Lumber Agreement— Backgrounder, FOREIGN AFFAIRS & INT’L TRADE CAN., http://www.international.gc.ca/ controls-controles/softwood-bois_oeuvre/notices-avis/agreement-accord.aspx?lang=eng&view=d (last modified Feb. 13, 2012). 145 SLA 2006, supra note 2, at art. III-IV. 146 Id. at Annex 2C(5). 140 2012] SOFTWOOD LUMBER’S “TERMITE” PROBLEM 187 sponsoring . . . illegal trade actions” and a “nest egg that will finance future trade harassment,”147 and $450 million for a “meritorious initiatives” account, which was viewed as “a gift” to the U.S. government.148 Needless to say, this outcome was deeply problematic for opponents of the settlement.149 B. Canada Agrees to Less than Free-Trade—The Issue of Export Measures The SLA 2006 has also been criticized for codifying protectionist trade remedies.150 Under the agreement, various regions in Canada are subject to a three-tier tariff or a tariffrated quota system.151 When lumber prices are below $315 per unit, Canadian lumber exporters pay either: (a) a 15% export tax, or (b) a 5% tax accompanied by a volume restraint on exports.152 As the price of lumber increases, export charges decline and export quotas increase.153 Only when lumber prices go over $355 per unit is lumber imported without export charges or volume restraints.154 As those opposed to extending the agreement point out, “the price [of lumber] has risen above the $355 threshold only once” since 2006, meaning that the 147 Softwood Lumber Deal: Hearing Before the Standing Comm. on Int’l Trade, 39th Parliament 1st Sess. at 5 (2006) (statement of Mr. Normand Rivard, Council Chair, United Steelworkers), available at http://www.parl.gc.ca/content/hoc/ Committee/391/CIIT/Evidence/EV2326139/CIITEV23-E.PDF [hereinafter Canadian Parliament Softwood Lumber Hearing]. 148 Id. at 2 (statement of Dr. Elliot Feldman, Trade Lawyer, Baker & Hostetler LLP); see also SLA 2006, supra note 2, at Annex 2C(5). 149 See Feldman, supra note 124, at 94 (arguing that “had litigation continued on its course without extra-legal interference from the two sovereign governments . . . , Canadian industry would have received back all of its money and the [U.S.] industry would have received none”). Eventually, however, Mr. Feldman (or at least the clients he represents) came to support extending the SLA 2006. That support was based on the fact that “Canada’s softwood lumber industry paid a very significant initiation fee for the SLA, $1 billion,” and “in light of its prior payment and sacrifice, now looks to whatever continuing benefits may be derived from the SLA according to its already agreed terms.” Letter from Elliot J. Feldman, Baker & Hostetler LLP, on behalf of the Ontario Forest Indus. Assoc. and the Conseil de l’Industrie Forestière du Québec, to Mary Sullivan Smith, Dir. for Can. Affairs, Office of the U.S. Trade Rep. (Oct. 6, 2011), available at http://www.regulations.gov/#!documentDetail;D=USTR-2011-0011-0002 (follow “View Attachment: PDF” hyperlink). 150 Soft in Wood and Head U.S.-Canadian Lumber Deal Makes a Mockery of Free Trade, FIN. TIMES, Apr. 29, 2006, at 6 [hereinafter Soft in Wood and Head] (arguing that “[i]f private companies were to attempt, on their own, to strike this kind of anti-competitive deal, they would be rightly hauled before [U.S.] and Canadian authorities. Yet the latter can call it managed trade, and get away with it.”). 151 SLA 2006, supra note 2, at art. VII. 152 Id. 153 Id. 154 Id. 188 BROOKLYN LAW REVIEW [Vol. 78:1 vast majority of softwood lumber imported from Canada has arrived subject to trade restrictive duties and volume restraints.155 This fact gives credence to those who argue that the agreement is one that would make the “Comecon officials of the Soviet era look like relative Friedmanites.”156 C. Slaying the Softwood Hydra—The Issue of Dispute Settlement Mechanisms The proliferation of PTAs and the lack of legal certainty governing their relationship with WTO dispute settlement mechanisms have negatively affected the softwood lumber dispute by providing the parties with a near endless recourse to dissonant legal forums. The SLA 2006 mitigates this problem by streamlining the dispute settlement process.157 If the parties fail to “arrive at a satisfactory resolution of the matter” through consultations, the agreement authorizes the parties to arbitrate the matter in the London Court of International Arbitration (LCIA).158 Moreover, the SLA 2006 specifically protects against the potential for overlapping adjudication. For the duration of the agreement, “neither Party shall initiate any litigation or dispute settlement proceedings with respect to any matter arising under the SLA 2006, including proceedings pursuant to the Marrakesh Agreement Establishing the World Trade Organization or Chapter Twenty of the NAFTA.”159 Additionally, the United States is not permitted to “self-initiate” any AD or CVD investigations for the duration of the agreement, and private parties involved in various lawsuits were forced to consent in writing to terminate all outstanding NAFTA and domestic legal proceedings.160 These provisions limit adjudication of the softwood lumber 155 Letter from Gerald M. Howard, Pres. & CEO, Nat’l Ass’n of Home Builders, to Mary Sullivan Smith, Dir. for Can. Affairs, Office of the U.S. Trade Rep. (Oct. 14, 2011), available at http://www.regulations.gov/#!documentDetail;D=USTR2011-0011-0003 (follow “View Attachment: PDF” hyperlink) [hereinafter Howard, USTR Comment] (labeling homebuilders, remodelers, and homebuyers as “downstream consumers”). 156 Soft in Wood and Head, supra note 150, at 6. 157 SLA 2006, supra note 2, at art. XIV. 158 Id. at art. XIV(4)-(6). This procedure is “unusual” in that the LCIA is known as a nongovernmental commercial arbitration institution that typically administers matters between private parties as opposed to sovereign governments. John R. Crook, United States and Canada Arbitrate a Softwood Lumber Dispute in the London Court of International Arbitration, 102 AM. J. INT’L L. 192, 192 (2008). 159 SLA 2006, supra note 2, at art. XIV(2). 160 Id. at art. V & Annex 2A. 2012] SOFTWOOD LUMBER’S “TERMITE” PROBLEM 189 dispute to a single forum, the LCIA, effectively “slay[ing] the softwood lumber hydra.”161 D. Agree to Disagree—Disputes Under the SLA 2006 Despite successfully addressing one of the major problems facing Lumber IV, the SLA 2006 was not designed to resolve the underlying legal issues of the dispute. The positions of both parties—with regard to the validity of the United States’ AD/CVD orders and the legal effect of courts’ or other dispute settlement bodies’ decisions regarding those orders— were explicitly reserved.162 Therefore, it is not surprising that limiting the forums in which disputes can arise has not ended all conflict with regard to the softwood lumber dispute. To date, the United States has filed three separate Requests for Arbitration under the SLA 2006, and decisions in each case indicate that the LCIA is an effective tribunal.163 The first request by the United States protested Canada’s alleged failure to properly calculate export quotas during the first six months of 2007.164 The tribunal largely sided with the United States, ruling that Canada had failed to properly calculate quotas on exports from certain regions and consequently ordering Canada to impose an additional 10% charge on exports from those regions.165 Separately, another tribunal was formed in response to the United States’ request to consider whether certain provincial assistance programs—which Quebec and Ontario put into place to aid Canadian softwood lumber producers and exporters—breached Canada’s obligation under the anticircumvention provisions of the SLA 2006.166 The tribunal again agreed with the United States, finding that certain measures 161 Knox, supra note 14, at 436. See generally Lysons, supra note 66, at 430 (noting that the dispute settlement provision of the SLA 2006 is “evidence of lessons learned in the softwood lumber dispute”). 162 SLA 2006, supra note 2, at art. XI(1). 163 See Lysons, supra note 66, at 431 tbl.2 (noting the faster schedule stipulated in the SLA 2006 as compared to NAFTA and the WTO). 164 United States v. Canada, Request for Arbitration, ¶¶ 12-14 (LCIA Aug. 13, 2007), http://www.ustr.gov/sites/default/files/us_request_for_arbitration.pdf. 165 United States v. Canada, Case No. 7941, Award on Remedies, at 148 (LCIA Feb. 23, 2009), http://www.ustr.gov/sites/default/files/award_on_remedy.pdf. 166 United States v. Canada, Request for Arbitration, ¶ 4 (LCIA Jan. 18, 2008), http://www.ustr.gov/sites/default/files/provincial_us_request_for_arbitration.pdf. The “Anti-circumvention” provision of the SLA 2006 states that “[n]either Party . . . shall take action to circumvent or offset the commitments under the SLA 2006.” SLA 2006, supra note 2, at art. XVII. 190 BROOKLYN LAW REVIEW [Vol. 78:1 taken by Canada violated its obligations under the agreement.167 Yet, the tribunal sided with Canada on how to calculate the remedy and granted significantly less compensation than was initially sought by the United States.168 Following this ruling, both Canada and the United States offered their continued support for the agreement.169 Given the litigious back and forth of Lumber IV, these responses are encouraging.170 The most recent Request for Arbitration, brought by the United States in early 2011, involved U.S. allegations that timber harvested from public lands in British Columbia’s interior region was being sold at prices below those provided for under the timber pricing system, which was grandfathered under the SLA 2006.171 Canada fought these allegations, arguing that the increased amount of low-priced timber from British Columbia was the result of a mountain pine beetle infestation and was not a violation of the SLA 2006’s anticircumvention provisions.172 In July of 2012, the LCIA sided with Canada and dismissed the U.S. claims in their entirety.173 Although the Lumber Coalition was “very disappointed” with the ruling, it has reiterated its “respect and appreciat[ion] [for] the efforts of [the LCIA] and the U.S. government to grapple with the complex issues involved in this case.”174 167 United States v. Canada, Case No. 81010, Award, ¶ 415 (LCIA Jan. 20, 2011), http://www.ustr.gov/webfm_send/2573. 168 Id. 169 Barrie McKenna, Lumber Deal Still A Good One Despite New Arbitration Loss, Ottawa Says, GLOBE & MAIL (Can.), Jan. 21, 2011; Lumber Deal is Safe, Emerson has Heard, TORONTO STAR, Mar. 6, 2008, at B2 (noting that the Canadian trade minister received assurances from the United States Trade Representative that the SLA 2006 was safe). Following the ruling, the president of the Quebec Forest Industry Council stated that, “[t]he Canadian government has indicated it intends to comply with the ruling and impose the additional export charges by the end of February [2011].” U.S. Prevails in Lumber Dispute with Canada, But Falls Short on Remedy, 29 INSIDE U.S. TRADE, Jan. 28, 2011, available at 2011 WLNR 1763804. 170 See supra Part II. 171 United States v. Canada, Case No. 111790, Request for Arbitration, ¶ 4 (LCIA Jan. 18, 2011), http://www.ustr.gov/webfm_send/2484. 172 United States v. Canada, Case No. 111790, Canada’s Response to Request for Arbitration, ¶¶ 1-6 (LCIA, Feb. 17, 2011), http://www.international.gc.ca/controlscontroles/assets/pdfs/softwood/Resp_Req_%20Arbitration_Can_2011_02_17%20.pdf (alleging that the United States has attempted to “create a violation of the SLA out of the devastation inflicted on the forests of British Columbia by the Mountain Pine Beetle”). 173 United States v. Canada, Case No. 111790, Final Award, ¶ 439 (LCIA July 26, 2012), http://www.international.gc.ca/controls-controles/assets/pdfs/softwood/111790.pdf. 174 Press Release, U.S. Lumber Coal., U.S. Lumber Coalition Disappointed by Arbitral Decision Regarding British Columbia Softwood Lumber Agreement Timber Pricing Violations (July 18, 2012), available at http://www.uslumbercoalition.org/ doc/press_release_07-18-12.pdf. 2012] SOFTWOOD LUMBER’S “TERMITE” PROBLEM 191 Despite these continued disputes, the extension of the SLA 2006 offers the best hope for lumber peace to both Canada and the United States. Without first addressing the underlying conflicts between the dispute settlement mechanisms in NAFTA and the WTO, a return of the softwood lumber hydra, in the form of a prospective “Lumber V,” would force the parties back into a costly and ineffective system of trade litigation. IV. WHY THE 2006 SOFTWOOD LUMBER AGREEMENT IS RIGHT FOR SOFTWOOD LUMBER Supporters of the SLA 2006 extension argued that it has “brought an element of stability and predictability to trade in softwood lumber products.”175 Those who wished to see it expire derided it as protectionist and claimed that it “reduces the incentive for the U.S. [lumber] producers . . . to increase production and improve efficiency of their mills so as to be internationally competitive,” which ultimately has a negative economic effect on consumers.176 While there is truth to both of these statements, a negotiated agreement that streamlines the dispute settlement process is necessary to offset the United States’ aggressive support for its softwood lumber industry. Furthermore, although the SLA 2006 is not a complete victory for either country, new trading partners have the potential to alleviate the remaining tensions between the parties, increasing the likelihood that the SLA 2006 extension will bring internal peace to the softwood lumber dispute. A. A Stable and Predictable Dispute Resolution Mechanism Is Needed to Offset the United States’ Obdurate Political Protection of Its Softwood Lumber Industry An exasperated Prime Minister Jean Chretien once reminded President George W. Bush, “You want gas, you want oil and you don’t want wood? It’s too bad, but if you have free 175 Letter from David A. Yocis et al., Picard Kentz & Rowe LLP, on behalf of the U.S. Lumber Coal., to Mary Sullivan Smith, Dir. for Can. Affairs, Office of the U.S. Trade Rep. (Oct. 14, 2011), http://www.regulations.gov/#!documentDetail;D=USTR-2011-00110004 (follow “View Attachment: PDF” hyperlink) [hereinafter Yocis, USTR Comment]. 176 Howard, USTR Comment, supra note 155 (labeling homebuilders, remodelers, and homebuyers as “downstream consumers”). The National Association of Home Builders, whose members construct approximately 80% of the new homes built each year in the United States, is a trade association whose “mission is to enhance the climate for housing and the building industry.” Id. 192 BROOKLYN LAW REVIEW [Vol. 78:1 trade, you have free trade.”177 While this statement is theoretically sound, in reality trade does not exist in isolation, and when it is influenced by political favoritism, economic logic does not always prevail.178 The United States has shown tremendous political resolve in its commitment to protect its softwood lumber industry and has brazenly used controversial litigation tactics in order to stretch the limits of that protection. Conversely, such steadfastness does not exist north of the border. Until U.S. resolve is weakened or until the overlapping dispute settlement mechanisms of global trade are disentangled in a way that prevents disingenuous litigation, a negotiated agreement with a single dispute resolution forum is the only outcome capable of guiding softwood lumber through the current mix of regionalism and multilateralism in the international trading regime. 1. Political Support Within the United States for Trade Restrictions on Canadian Softwood Lumber Influential Senators from lumber-producing states, such as Max Baucus (D-Mont.), have long expressed their desire for a negotiated settlement to the lumber dispute in order to limit imports of Canadian softwood products. In an attempt to “spark a return . . . to the negotiating table,” Baucus went so far as to introduce the Softwood Lumber Duties Liquidation Act in 2004, which sought to liquidate $3 billion in Canadian duty deposits prior to the resolution of ongoing legal appeals surrounding those deposits.179 Although Canadian lumber industry insiders downplayed the legislation, characterizing it as a “message bill and not a serious threat,” evidence indicates that past U.S. Presidents have responded to Senators’ softwood lumber demands by supporting restrictions on imports of Canadian 177 Barry Brown, Lumber Dispute Could Affect State’s Imports of Canadian Gas, BUFFALO NEWS, Aug. 23, 2001, at E1. 178 See, e.g., Daniel N. Adams, Comment, Back to Basics: The Predestined Failure of NAFTA Chapter 19 and Its Lessons for the Design of International Trade Regimes, 22 EMORY INT’L L. REV. 205, 228 (2008) (noting that the SLA 2006 was a bargain “heavily influenced by political considerations”). During a 2009 Canada-United States Law Institute Conference on “North American Dispute Resolution,” John Terry, a Canadian trade lawyer, argued that, “despite the dispute settlement mechanisms [Canada has] put into place, realpolitik tends to continue to play the role it has always or has traditionally played.” John A. Terry, Canadian Speaker, North American Dispute Resolution, Proceedings of the Canadian-United States Law Institute Conference (Apr. 2-4, 2009), in 34 CAN.-U.S. L.J. 399, 416 (2010). 179 Baucus Pressures Canada on Lumber with Bill to Liquidate Duties, INSIDE U.S. TRADE, Nov. 19, 2004, available at 2004 WLNR 10906271. 2012] SOFTWOOD LUMBER’S “TERMITE” PROBLEM 193 lumber.180 Indeed, evidence from both Lumber III and Lumber IV shows that such demands were catalysts for trade restrictions. After Canada notified the United States of its plans to withdraw from the MOU signed during Lumber II,181 a group of sixty-four Senators wrote a letter to the President, demanding that the Administration take action against Canada.182 The letter threatened that “if [diplomatic or trade] remedies are not pursued, we are prepared to find a legislative remedy to fully offset Canada’s timber subsidies.”183 Lumber III was initiated in the immediate wake of this threat, with Commerce selfinitiating trade proceedings against Canada.184 Then, with the SLA 1996 set to expire, a group of fifty-one Senators wrote to the President, urging him “to make resolving the problem of subsidized lumber imports from Canada a top trade priority.”185 The response to this petition was Lumber IV, launched on the first business day after the 1996 agreement expired.186 At minimum, these two letters coincided with major events in the softwood lumber dispute and highlight the broad level of political protection enjoyed by the U.S. lumber industry.187 Most 180 Id. In all four rounds of the softwood lumber dispute, Senators involved themselves indirectly in the negotiations by writing letters to the President, Commerce, and the USTR, urging them to resolve the dispute through negotiation with Canada or by imposing trade restrictions. Daowei Zhang & David Laband, From Senators to the President: Solve the Lumber Problem or Else, 123 PUB. CHOICE 393, 393-94 (2005) (conducting a roll call analysis to identify the factors influencing a Senator’s willingness to sign letters demanding that the executive branch solve the lumber problem and showing that the economic importance of the lumber industry in a Senator’s home state is positively correlated with signatory on these letters and that the presence of a large housing industry in a state makes a Senator less likely to sign these letters). 181 See supra Part I.B. 182 Zhang & Laband, supra note 180, at 397. 183 Id. 184 See supra Part I.C. 185 Zhang & Laband, supra note 180, at 399. 186 See supra Part II. 187 Commentators argue that these Senators are influenced by the highly effective lobbying efforts of the Lumber Coalition. Zhang & Laband, supra note 180, at 407 (arguing that their findings are consistent with the “interest group theory of political decision making” whereby a “small but concentrated softwood lumber industry can successfully lobby their elected officials such as Senators and demand protection from foreign competition, despite the fact that such protectionism harms the economic welfare of the nation as a whole”). Although the Lumber Coalition has faced opposition in its quest to impose trade penalties on Canadian lumber, primarily from the National Association of Home Builders, the opposition has proven ineffective in its lobbying efforts as compared to the Lumber Coalition. Id. at 396, 398. As recently as 2011, Lumber Coalition officials have publicly stated that, “in the absence of an agreement between the two governments, the Coalition would have no choice but to petition for new antidumping and countervailing duty orders against unfairly traded softwood lumber products from Canada.” Yocis, USTR Comment, supra note 175. Considering the Lumber Coalition filed fresh AD/CVD petitions on the first business day after the 194 BROOKLYN LAW REVIEW [Vol. 78:1 recently, at least twenty-three members of Congress formally offered their support for the SLA 2006 extension.188 In a letter to the United States Trade Representative, these lawmakers offered their support for extending the agreement in exchange for an “iron clad commitment that any Canadian violations will be addressed in a timely and effective manner.”189 2. Controversial Litigation Tactics Utilized by the United States to Protect Its Softwood Lumber Industry In addition to overt political support for trade restrictions, the United States has also proved willing to push the legal envelope in its attempts to protect its domestic softwood lumber industry. The most blatant example of this controversial gamesmanship is evident from the United States’ attempt to moot the unfavorable NAFTA rulings regarding the ITC’s injury determinations, under the guise of WTO compliance.190 Although the CIT denounced this particular practice,191 it is indicative of how far the U.S. government is willing to go to protect domestic lumber interests.192 Until a solution is found to deal with the discordant overlap of dispute settlement mechanisms, other opportunities to thwart the system will remain. Therefore, express agreements like the SLA 2006 are—at least for the time being—essential in providing legal clarity and limiting the parties’ ability to manipulate the incongruous relationship between NAFTA and the WTO.193 expiration of SLA 1996, the parties would be well served to give credence to these warnings. See supra Part II. One commentator also notes that the SLA 2006 delivered $500 million to the Lumber Coalition, “many times more than enough to protect its interests,” which means the “[Lumber] Coalition is more than ready for trade action were it to think more restraints needed.” Feldman, supra note 124, at 96. 188 Rossella Brevetti, 23 House Lawmakers Condition Support for Lumber Pact Extension on Enforcement, 28 Int’l Trade Rep. (BNA) 1755 (Oct. 27, 2011). 189 Id. 190 See supra Part II.A.3. 191 See supra Part II.D. 192 BOWMAN ET AL., supra note 4, at 581; Quayat, supra note 37, at 134. 193 See Pauwelyn & Salles, supra note 19, at 117 (arguing that the best short term solution to address forum shopping among international tribunals is to regulate overlaps with explicit treaty clauses). 2012] SOFTWOOD LUMBER’S “TERMITE” PROBLEM 195 3. Canada’s Lackluster Response to the United States’ Steadfast Support of Its Lumber Industry In contrast to the United States’ commitment to the lumber trade, Canada’s support for its own lumber industry does not appear as steadfast. During the negotiations of the SLA 2006, some have argued that newly elected Canadian Prime Minister Stephen Harper prioritized restoring ties with the Bush Administration over supporting the Canadian lumber industry.194 Prior to announcing the SLA 2006, Canada had to persuade most of its softwood lumber producers to refrain from objecting publicly to an agreement that the industry did not favor.195 Today, Canada continues to waver in its support. Critics contend that the federal government “still strong-arms provincial governments to change [their] forestry practices.”196 And the government has applauded British Columbia for increasing the amount of its forest land put to auction.197 These actions suggest that—despite numerous legal victories to the contrary—the Canadian federal government believes that the provinces do subsidize their production of exported lumber, and they offer a contrast to the rigid support for the industry found south of the border.198 In explaining why Canadian lumber producers consented to the SLA 2006, the executive director of the Alberta Forest Products Association stated, “We picked the best of two bad situations.”199 This may be the most apt description of the current agreement. Although far from perfect, the SLA 2006 appeases U.S. demands for managed trade and provides Canada with a degree of legal certainty absent from the overlapping dispute settlement mechanism of NAFTA and the WTO. And while Canada may still have misgivings about its neighbor’s fickle free trade preferences, new markets will provide Canada with options to escape the restricted U.S. market, and they will offer the United States relief from an otherwise continued influx of Canadian products. 194 Adams, supra note 178, at 228. Feldman, supra note 124, at 91; Canadian Parliament Softwood Lumber Hearing, supra note 147, at 5 (statement of Normand Rivard, Council Chair, United Steelworkers) (opposing the SLA 2006). 196 Feldman, supra note 124, at 97. 197 Id. 198 Id. 199 Josie Newman, Timber Accord Rankles Canadian Firms, CHRISTIAN SCI. MONITOR, Oct. 18, 2006, at 7, available at http://www.csmonitor.com/2006/1018/ p07s02-woam.html. 195 196 BROOKLYN LAW REVIEW [Vol. 78:1 B. New Lumber Markets Will Allow Canada and the United States to Mitigate Any Lasting Tensions Throughout much of the softwood lumber dispute, the United States has been Canada’s only major export market for softwood lumber.200 Recently, however, lumber exports to China have grown significantly, and Canada’s reliance on the U.S. market has declined.201 May 2011 was the first month in which the value of softwood lumber from British Columbia exported to China outstripped that exported to the United States.202 China’s purchases of softwood lumber from Canada grew from 9.04% of Canadian softwood exports in 2010 to 21.4% in 2011.203 This corresponded with a drop in Canada’s softwood exports to the United States, from 66.71% of total exports in 2010 to 54.63% in 2011.204 This diversification of Canada’s lumber market will only alleviate U.S. concerns that too much Canadian lumber is entering its market, and it will provide the Canadian lumber industry with alternative trading options if it finds the terms of the SLA 2006 too onerous. While critics abound, and future conflicts are sure to emerge, the SLA 2006 both effectively slays the softwood lumber hydra and appeases the obdurate demands of U.S. lawmakers. Unfortunately, an unwanted side effect of this peace is that it removes a major incentive to address the monstrous dispute resolution system that exists beneath the softwood lumber dispute. In short, while the SLA 2006 is a workable solution to the softwood lumber dispute, it also adds to the perilous forces undercutting the multilateral trading system. V. A PYRRHIC VICTORY—WHY THE SLA 2006 ADDS TO THE FORCES UNDERCUTTING THE MULTILATERAL TRADING SYSTEM Before the SLA 2006 was signed, commentators predicted that the new dispute settlement system proposed in the agreement “spell[ed] the end of NAFTA’s [C]hapter 19, and 200 BOWMAN ET AL., supra note 4, at 553-54. Forest Product Markets, NAT. RES. CAN., http://cfs.nrcan.gc.ca/pages/330 (last updated Oct. 22, 2012). 202 Jeremy Hainsworth, British Columbia Lumber Exports to China Outstrip in Value Softwood Exports to U.S., 28 Int’l Trade Rep. (BNA) 1249 (July 28, 2011). 203 Id. 204 Id. 201 2012] SOFTWOOD LUMBER’S “TERMITE” PROBLEM 197 in many ways the end of NAFTA itself.”205 If this were the lasting impact of the SLA 2006, it would be cause for celebration: a response to the failures of NAFTA would have highlighted a major problem brought on by the proliferation of PTAs—namely, discordant dispute resolution—and brought about the demise of one of those problematic agreements. Unfortunately, this did not occur, and Chapter 19 is still used today.206 Indeed, since 2006, the most bitter trade dispute in North America has been immunized from many of the problems caused by the existence of PTAs. Unless Canada and the United States recognize that the SLA 2006’s straightforward dispute settlement mechanism is what has alleviated their softwood lumber problems and choose to apply a similarly coherent principle to the larger trading regime, the extension of the SLA 2006 is, at most, a Pyrrhic victory. A. A Dispute Settlement Cacophony—The Problems with Preferential Trade Agreements Although some argue that “overlapping legal systems [are] unavoidable” in today’s global landscape,207 the softwood lumber dispute presents a telling example of the “wastefulness and potential futility” of such overlap in hotly contested trade disputes.208 Specifically, the unresolved fragmentation between regionalism and multilateralism creates at least three serious 205 Canadian Parliament Softwood Lumber Hearing, supra note 147, at 1 (statement of Dr. Elliot Feldman, Trade Lawyer, Baker & Hostetler LLP). 206 See, e.g., North American Free Trade Agreement Binational Panel Review, In the Matter of: Certain Welded Large Diameter Line Pipe from Mexico, at 1, USAMEX-2007-1904-03 (Aug. 29, 2011) (reviewing the ITC’s decision “that revocation of [an] antidumping order on Certain Large Diameter Line Pipe from . . . Mexico would not likely result in the continuation or recurrence of material injury to the domestic industry within a reasonably foreseeable time”). 207 See, e.g., Elizabeth Trujillo, Disaggregating the Regional-Multilateral Overlap: The NAFTA Looking-Glass, 19 IND. INT’L & COMP. L. REV. 533, 558 (2009). According to Trujillo, “In order to preserve its power, the WTO must share its adjudicatory power and force regional and bilateral tribunals to settle matters regionally” and must become “the coordinating force of the global trade system by creating concrete linkages to its Member States and their regional concerns.” Id. at 568. 208 Cone, supra note 74, at 849 (arguing that free trade areas comprising the United States and countries with substantially less economic strength “run the risk of becoming extensions of hegemonic U.S. policies”); see also Dunoff, supra note 31, at 337 (noting that other trade disputes raise similar issues, but arguing that “with three different lines of litigation proceeding virtually simultaneously before domestic fora, NAFTA panels, and WTO panels, the Softwood Lumber dispute presents in a particularly stark form the issues raised by litigation before multiple fora”). 198 BROOKLYN LAW REVIEW [Vol. 78:1 problems for the current international trade dispute settlement system.209 First, it prolongs the underlying dispute.210 Despite numerous legal victories over the course of Lumber IV, it took Canada over five years to slay the softwood lumber hydra.211 Moreover, the longer the dispute carried on, the more opportunities there were for U.S. agencies to issue additional determinations, each of which started the challenge process anew.212 Second, when multiple forums address the same issue, the possibility of inconsistent judgments increases.213 In particular, state practices, such as the United States’ use of zeroing, may be deemed valid in one forum and invalid in another.214 Finally, the existence of multiple forums gives rise to litigious gamesmanship. If a state is able to win even a partial affirmation of an AD/CVD ruling, as the United States did at the WTO during Lumber IV,215 its trade agencies may argue that, notwithstanding adverse rulings in one forum, success in another provides legal cover to ignore the unfavorable result. During the course of the softwood lumber dispute, the relationship among the various dispute settlement forums spanned a “continuum from deference to defiance,”216 but there was an ever-present possibility that one of the issues discussed above would surface and derail any apparent progress. Canada and the United States addressed this concern by drafting a PTA sub-agreement, the SLA 2006, which effectively trumped NAFTA and the WTO with a new dispute resolution mechanism exclusively for softwood lumber disputes.217 As will be shown below, this was a misguided attempt to solve a much deeper problem. 209 Dunoff, supra note 31, at 332. Knox, supra note 14, at 436. 211 See supra Part II. 212 Knox, supra note 14, at 436. 213 Id. 214 Dunoff, supra note 31, at 332 (noting that by late 2004, the United States’ use of zeroing had been upheld in both the U.S. Court of Appeals for the Federal Circuit and NAFTA, but that the WTO’s AB had found the zeroing to be inconsistent with U.S. obligations under international trade law). 215 See supra Part II.A.2.b. 216 Dunoff, supra note 31, at 337-38. 217 See supra Part III. 210 2012] B. SOFTWOOD LUMBER’S “TERMITE” PROBLEM 199 PTA Sub-Agreements Deter a Return to Multilateral Trade While PTAs have their own set of problems, the additional risks of PTA sub-agreements are twofold. They both pilfer from the finite amount of human and administrative capital available to conduct trade agreements, and they remove incentives to address the larger issues at stake. One of critics’ main concerns with the proliferation of PTAs is that their negotiation, ratification, implementation, and enforcement come at the expense of the multilateral system.218 PTA sub-agreements take this problem one step further by focusing additional human and administrative energy on agreements that are further removed from multilateral objectives. This would not be a cause for concern if these sub-agreements solved the fundamental shortcomings of PTAs. Unfortunately, agreements such as the SLA 2006 merely immunize certain key industries from the drawbacks of PTAs while leaving others to languish in an entangled mess of trade agreements. The SLA 2006 acknowledges the problems with bilateral agreements, yet it provides the largest trade dispute in Canadian-American relations with immunity from those problems. As of 2006, the “longest running and perhaps most bitter trade dispute ever between the two countries” is no longer saddled with a cacophony of dispute settlement mechanisms.219 With billions in trade now beyond the convoluted interplay between NAFTA and the WTO, Canada and the United States are that much less likely to address the problems of overlapping jurisdiction.220 While the saying is that things get worse before they get better, those in the multilateral trading community might worry that PTA sub-agreements are an example of things getting better before they get worse. 218 As a World Bank study noted, “[r]eserves of administrative skill, political capital, or imagination are finite; if they are devoted to a [PTA] they are not available for multilateral objectives.” Dunoff, supra note 31, at 334 (citation omitted). 219 BOWMAN ET AL., supra note 4, at 553. 220 Id. (noting that Canada exported nearly $7 billion worth of softwood lumber to the United States in 2000). By 2011, bilateral trade in softwood lumber had decreased to $3 billion. Canada Applauds Softwood Lumber Ruling on British Columbia’s Timber-Pricing System, FOREIGN AFF. & INT’L TRADE CAN., http://www.international.gc.ca/ media_commerce/comm/news-communiques/2012/07/18a.aspx?view=d (last modified July 19, 2012). 200 BROOKLYN LAW REVIEW [Vol. 78:1 CONCLUSION Softwood lumber’s termite problem is an infestation that concerns the entire trading community, and PTA subagreements are not the insecticide that the multilateral system is waiting for. If Canada and the United States are to assist in addressing the real issues at stake, they must look beyond creating a solution only for lumber. Rather than allowing an armistice in the softwood lumber dispute to serve as an excuse to ignore the concerns surrounding PTAs, the two parties must recognize why the SLA 2006 has been able to mitigate the dispute and extend that rationale to the greater disconnect between NAFTA and the WTO. The SLA 2006 replaces a discordant dispute settlement scheme with a straightforward and efficient arbitral tribunal. Until Canada and the United States integrate a similar solution into the larger trading system, the lessons of the softwood lumber dispute will continue to go unheeded. K. Craig Reilly† † J.D. Candidate, Brooklyn Law School, 2013; B.A., Princeton University, 2007. Many thanks to all of those who provided invaluable assistance throughout the writing process. A special thank you to Professor Claire Kelly, the editors and staff of the Brooklyn Law Review, and my unofficial editor and new wife Caitlin. Count Your Chickens Before They Hatch HOW MULTIPLE PREGNANCIES ARE ENDANGERING THE RIGHT TO ABORTION INTRODUCTION Reconciling the constitutional right to procreate with the constitutional right to abortion produces a paradox. The former protects citizens’ interests in having a child, and the latter protects women’s interests in terminating a pregnancy. Yet, the right to procreate can also directly implicate a woman’s right to terminate her pregnancy. Indeed, sweeping medical advancements in the area of reproductive technology put this incongruity in sharp relief. “Assisted Reproductive Technology” refers to treatment methods that infertile women use to attain pregnancy.1 According to the Centers for Disease Control and Prevention, “[Assisted Reproductive Technology] includes all fertility treatments in which eggs and sperm are handled.”2 In vitro fertilization (IVF) is one of the most popular techniques used in the United States to assist women in achieving pregnancy.3 During an IVF procedure, it is customary to implant more than one embryo in the woman’s uterus, with the hope that at least one embryo will result in a pregnancy.4 However, one of the common, well-known outcomes of an IVF procedure is for a woman to attain multiple pregnancies after one cycle of implantation.5 Since the United 1 Marsha Garrison, Regulating Reproduction, 76 GEO. WASH. L. REV. 1623, 1623 (2008). 2 Ctrs. for Disease Control & Prevention, Assisted Reproductive Technology (ART), CDC.GOV, http://www.cdc.gov/art (last visited Nov. 3, 2011). 3 Id. 4 Kirsten Riggan, Regulation (or Lack Thereof) of Assisted Reproductive Technologies in the U.S. and Abroad, CTR. FOR BIOETHICS & HUMAN DIGNITY (Mar. 5, 2011), http://cbhd.org/content/regulation-or-lack-thereof-assisted-reproductive-technologiesus-and-abroad. 5 Fact Sheet: Fertility Drugs and the Risk of Multiple Births, AM. SOC’Y FOR REPROD. MED., http://www.asrm.org/Fertility_drugs_and_the_risk_of_multiple_births/ (last visited Sept. 21, 2012) [hereinafter Fact Sheet: Fertility Drugs]. 201 202 BROOKLYN LAW REVIEW [Vol. 78:1 States supports the notion of “patient autonomy”6 and does not limit the number of embryos that can be transferred into a woman’s uterus during a cycle, physicians and patients are free to choose how many embryos are actually implanted in a single cycle.7 Although professional medical organizations, such as the American Society for Reproductive Medicine and the Society for Assisted Reproductive Technology, provide guidelines for embryo transplantation according to a woman’s age, these guidelines represent only nonbinding recommendations.8 The unpredictability of the IVF procedure has prompted enormous scrutiny from legal scholars and the general public. For example, in 2009, Nadya Suleman—commonly known as “Octomom”9—gave birth to octuplets with the assistance of IVF.10 Suleman already had six other children who were conceived through IVF.11 Furthermore, it soon came to light that Suleman was an unemployed single mother who was receiving public assistance and had serious psychological problems.12 Inevitably, questions arose about the ethical and moral implications of the dearth of legislation regulating embryo transfer and the IVF procedure.13 Suleman’s story highlights the controversy of “unfit mothers” who gain the ability to bear more children than they are capable of providing for through IVF. On the other hand, IVF’s increasing prevalence has also drawn attention to women on the opposite end of the spectrum: women who undergo IVF, knowing that it will likely result in multiple pregnancies, and then choose to reduce their pregnancy to fewer fetuses. “Multifetal pregnancy reduction” describes procedures involving multiple fetuses where a woman chooses to terminate one or more fetuses.14 In the past, doctors have performed reductions for women carrying multiple fetuses because a multifetal pregnancy is significantly more dangerous than a 6 Garrison, supra note 1, at 1633. See Riggan, supra note 4. 8 Id. 9 See Alan Duke, Nadya Suleman’s Doctor Loses California Medical License, CNN (June 1, 2011), http://articles.cnn.com/2011-06-01/us/california.octuplets.doctor.revoked_ 1_kamrava-fertility-doctor-embryos?_s=PM:US; Riggan, supra note 4. 10 Randal C. Archibold, Octuplets, 6 Siblings, and Many Questions, N.Y. TIMES, Feb. 4, 2009, at A14. 11 Duke, supra note 9. 12 Deborah L. Forman, When “Bad” Mothers Make Worse Law: A Critique of Legislative Limits on Embryo Transfer, 14 U. PA. J.L. & SOC. CHANGE 273, 277 (2011). 13 See Archibold, supra note 10. 14 Ruth Padawer, The Two-Minus-One Pregnancy: Unnatural Selection, N.Y. TIMES, Aug. 10, 2011, (Magazine), at 24, available at http://www.nytimes.com/2011/ 08/14/magazine/the-two-minus-one-pregnancy.html. 7 2012] TWIN REDUCTIONS AND THE ABORTION RIGHT 203 twin or single pregnancy15—although generally doctors will not reduce any further than a twin pregnancy, barring health risks.16 Reducing a twin pregnancy, also known as “twin reduction,” is increasingly controversial. In fact, a growing number of women undergoing IVF treatments are opting for a twin reduction, even when there are no health risks to the mother or the fetuses.17 Many physicians have refused to perform the procedure altogether, claiming that twin reductions are more unethical than multifetal pregnancy reductions18 because a twin reduction is often chosen for “social” reasons rather than for medical reasons.19 This aspect of twin reductions enables the public to equate it with abortions. A woman’s right to an abortion is a fundamental right protected by the U.S. Constitution. The Supreme Court decided Roe v. Wade on January 22, 197320 and determined that the right to privacy under the Fourteenth Amendment encompasses a woman’s decision to terminate her pregnancy.21 The Court later reaffirmed its central holding from Roe in Planned Parenthood v. Casey.22 Although the Court unexpectedly changed course in its analysis, introducing the concept of personal autonomy rather than the right to privacy to justify its holding, it concluded that a woman’s right to an abortion is a fundamental right.23 The Supreme Court has rarely visited the abortion issue since Casey in 1992. However, given the advancement of assisted reproductive technology in general, and IVF in particular, coupled with a lack of legislation regarding the procedure, new questions are emerging as to what decisions are encompassed within the meaning of personal autonomy. This note explores the implications IVF may have on the notion of personal autonomy as enunciated in Casey. The note will present two protected fundamental rights—the right to procreate and the right to an abortion—and analyze the 15 Id. Id. at 25. 17 Id. 18 Id. 19 See Mark I. Evans & David W. Britt, Multifetal Pregnancy Reduction: Evolution of the Ethical Arguments, 28 SEMINARS IN REPROD. MED. 299-300 (2010), available at http://www.compregen.com/pdf/ethicalarguments.pdf; Gretchen Sisson, Having One-Minus-One Choices, ABORTION GANG (Aug. 15, 2011), http://www.abortiongang.org/ 2011/08/having-one-minus-one-choices/. 20 Roe v. Wade, 410 U.S. 113, 153 (1973). 21 Id. 22 Planned Parenthood of Se. Pa. v. Casey, 505 U.S. 833, 845-46 (1992). 23 Id. at 869. 16 204 BROOKLYN LAW REVIEW [Vol. 78:1 inherent conflict between them. In particular, this note will discuss how twin reductions lead the public to question the right to abortion, rather than the countervailing right to procreate and the unregulated IVF procedure. Finally, the note will demonstrate that the current state of abortion rights already endangers a woman’s right to privacy and therefore should not be targeted to solve problems associated with twin reductions. Rather, to effectively preserve both the right to abortion and the right to reproductive freedom, the legislature should enact regulations to more strictly govern the use of the IVF procedure. Part I of this note briefly summarizes the IVF procedure and its place within the legal landscape. This section also further describes the twin reduction procedure. Part II provides background and analysis of the Supreme Court precedents governing the legal doctrines that twin reductions implicate. Part III presents moral and ethical considerations that arise from twin reductions and why the practice is often associated with regular abortions. Part IV explains why abortion rights are currently susceptible to deterioration. Finally, Part V will propose possible solutions to the issue of twin reductions and other problems resulting from an unregulated IVF process. I. IN VITRO FERTILIZATION A. The Procedure IVF is the artificial process of fertilizing a female egg with sperm in a laboratory.24 A typical IVF “cycle”25 begins with the woman undergoing about two weeks of hormone therapy to increase the number of eggs her ovaries produce.26 The eggs are then retrieved and harvested through different outpatient procedures.27 Finally, the eggs are placed in a petri dish and 24 CHARLES P. KINDREGAN, JR. & MAUREEN MCBRIEN, ASSISTED REPRODUCTIVE TECHNOLOGY: A LAWYER’S GUIDE TO EMERGING LAW AND SCIENCE 91 (2d ed. 2011). 25 An IVF procedure is referred to as a cycle because “the procedure consists of several steps that take place over a period of about two weeks and is not a single medical procedure at one point in time.” Id. at 94. 26 Id. at 93. 27 There are various outpatient procedures used for the retrieval of the eggs during which the eggs are aspirated from the ovary by either placing a needle, guided by ultrasound through the vaginal wall, by laparoscopic surgery or by Trans-Abdominal Oocyte Retrieval. Typically only one local 2012] TWIN REDUCTIONS AND THE ABORTION RIGHT 205 fertilized.28 As cell division begins and “the zygote is between 2 and 16 cells,”29 the embryos are either transplanted into the woman’s uterus or cryopreserved.30 Each cycle of IVF is financially burdensome.31 Rates vary among fertility clinics, but the cost for each cycle is typically between $10,000 and $20,000,32 averaging around $12,400.33 Most states do not require insurance companies to cover IVF, and if they do, coverage is limited.34 Because each cycle does not guarantee a pregnancy, many women go through several cycles without any success.35 Very few people can afford to pay for IVF cycles themselves,36 and as a result, it is common practice for physicians to transfer multiple embryos into a woman’s uterus during one cycle, leading to the high and distinct possibility of multiple pregnancies.37 B. Legal Landscape Governing the Number of Implanted Embryos The United States has no actual legislation regulating the IVF procedure itself. This laissez-faire approach gives anesthe[tic] is required for this process, but general anesthesia in the form of conscious sedation may be used. Id. (citing Tracey S. Pachman, Disputes over Frozen Preembryos and the “Right Not to Be a Parent,” 12 COLUM. J. GENDER & L. 128, 129 (2003) and authorities cited therein). 28 Id. at 94. 29 Id. 30 Id. at 91. Each instance of egg implantation does not guarantee a pregnancy. Therefore, multiple eggs are fertilized at once, “so that the process can be repeated if necessary.” Id. at 94. Cryopreserved embryos are the fertilized eggs, which are not implanted in an IVF cycle and are persevered for possible future implantation. If a patient decides against future implantation, the fertility clinics are usually left with the conundrum about what to do with these “surplus” embryos. See id. at 121. A large controversy exists regarding the disposition of cryopreserved embryos; however, that issue is beyond the scope of this note. 31 Id. at 95. 32 Id.; see also State Laws Related to Insurance Coverage for Infertility Treatment, NAT’L CONF. ST. LEGISLATURES, http://www.ncsl.org/issues-research/health/ insurance-coverage-for-infertility-laws.aspx (last updated Mar. 2012). 33 Frequently Asked Questions About Infertility, AM. SOC’Y FOR REPROD. MED., http://www.asrm.org/awards/index.aspx?id=3012 (last visited Jan. 16, 2012). 34 See State Laws Related to Insurance Coverage, supra note 32. “Since the 1980s, 15 states . . . have passed laws that require insurers to either cover or offer coverage for infertility diagnosis and treatment.” Id. However, this coverage does not necessarily extend to IVF procedures. “While most states with laws requiring insurance companies to offer or provide coverage for infertility treatment include coverage for in vitro fertilization, [several of those states] have laws that specifically exclude coverage for the procedure.” Id. 35 KINDREGAN & MCBRIEN, supra note 24, at 95. 36 Id. 37 See Riggan, supra note 4. 206 BROOKLYN LAW REVIEW [Vol. 78:1 doctors and patients38 complete control without any legal restrictions. Instead, the entire field of IVF is solely guided by professional medical organizations such as the American Society for Reproductive Medicine and the Society for Assisted Reproductive Technology. These organizations’ guidelines encourage physicians to inform patients about the risks39 and costs of IVF,40 and they state the recommended number of embryos to transfer based on the woman’s age41 and other factors.42 Should the physician or patient decide to transfer more than the recommended number of embryos, the guidelines provide for an exception,43 so long as the physician documents “the justification for exceeding the recommended limits . . . in the patient’s permanent medical record.”44 Even if physicians fail to follow the recommendations, they will not be liable under the law.45 Outside of the United States, many countries have enacted legislation that limits the number of embryos that can be transferred during an IVF cycle.46 For example, Germany, 38 See, e.g., Fact Sheet: Fertility Drugs, supra note 5 (“Before the placement of these embryos . . . [the patient and the] doctor will decide how many embryos to place in [the] womb.”). 39 Like any medical procedure, IVF comes with certain risks during each cycle. During the initial drug therapy, ovary stimulation can cause rare, but significant physical side effects, such as nausea or vomiting, shortness of breath, weight gain, severe abdominal pain, among others. In Vitro Fertilization: IVF, AM. PREGNANCY ASS’N, http://www.americanpregnancy.org/infertility/ivf.html (last updated May 2007). Egg retrieval can cause bleeding and infections. Id. These side effects are very rare and only occur in one percent or less of cases. Id. However, the existence of possible risks provides another incentive for multiple-embryo transfers, increasing the chance of pregnancy so that a patient need not endure another IVF cycle. 40 Practice Comm., Soc’y for Assisted Reprod. Tech. & Practice Comm., Am. Soc’y for Reprod. Med., Guidelines on Number of Embryos Transferred, 92 FERTILITY & STERILITY 1518, 1518 (2009) [hereinafter Guidelines on Number of Embryos], available at www.sart.org/publications/detail.aspx?id=3966. 41 The guidelines suggest the following recommendations for the number of embryos transferred: For women under the age of thirty-five, one or two embryos; for ages of thirty-five to thirty-seven, two or three embryos; for ages of thirty-eight to forty, three to four embryos; and for over the age of forty, up to five embryos. Id. 42 Additional factors include embryo quality, opportunity for cryopreservation, patient’s previous results with IVF, and accumulation of newer techniques. Id. 43 Id. at 1519. 44 Id. 45 See Molly Hennessy-Fiske, Octuplets Doctor Could Still Lose Medical License, L.A. TIMES (Feb. 10, 2011), http://articles.latimes.com/2011/feb/10/local/la-me0210-kamrava-20110210 (“[F]ertility specialists are not required to adhere to strict standards concerning how many embryos they implant.”). Although physicians are not legally bound, they may face repercussions for noncompliance from state medical boards. See Duke, supra note 9 (“The California Medical Board ruled that Dr. Michael Kamrava committed ‘gross negligence’ with ‘repeated negligent acts, for an excessive number of embryo transfers’ into Suleman in 2008.”). 46 See Riggan, supra note 4. 2012] TWIN REDUCTIONS AND THE ABORTION RIGHT 207 Italy, Spain, and Switzerland have implemented regulations limiting the number of embryos to three per cycle.47 The United Kingdom’s Human Fertilization and Embryo Authority has restricted the number of embryos to no more than two for women under the age of forty and no more than three for women over forty.48 Among other countries, Belgium and Sweden have endorsed the idea of a single embryo transfer, where “a fresh embryo is transferred in the first cycle and single cryopreserved embryos are transferred in subsequent cycles.”49 European countries have been successful in reducing the number of multiple pregnancies following such regulations.50 However, the United States has yet to follow Europe’s approach, currently relying on standards and guidelines rather than federally imposed regulations that would limit the number of embryos transferred during each IVF cycle. C. Problems Associated with a Lack of Regulation As with most areas of medical practice, IVF procedures are largely self-regulated on a voluntary basis.51 The sole piece of legislation the federal government has enacted relating to the IVF procedure is the Fertility Clinic Success Rate and Certification Act of 1992,52 which requires all clinics to submit reports regarding their pregnancy success rates per IVF cycle.53 The report allows patients to compare clinics based on their rates of patient pregnancy. The higher the rate of successful pregnancies, the more attractive a clinic appears to a patient struggling with infertility. Therefore, clinics may transfer a higher number of embryos to increase their success rate,54 despite the dangers of a multiple pregnancy.55 At the same 47 Id. Id. 49 Id. 50 Urška Velikonja, The Costs of Multiple Gestation Pregnancies in Assisted Reproduction, 32 HARV. J.L. & GENDER 463, 467 (2009). 51 Id. at 465; see also Garrison, supra note 1, at 1631. (“[A]cross all areas of medical practice, the law of medical choice is dominated by the principle of patient autonomy.”). Therefore, courts generally do not interfere in this area, and emphasize the notion that a human being should have complete control over decisions that relate to their body. Id. 52 42 U.S.C. §§ 263a-1 to -7 (2006). 53 Id. § 263a-1. 54 Velikonja, supra note 50, at 483. Furthermore, clinics are not required to report the actual number of multiple pregnancies or the number of children born with medical problems—thus depriving the patient of important, useful information. Id. 55 See infra Part I.D. 48 208 BROOKLYN LAW REVIEW [Vol. 78:1 time, patients who desperately want children are incentivized to choose clinics that are willing to transfer a greater number of embryos.56 If a clinic refuses to implant the number of embryos that the patient demands, she can simply find a competitor clinic57 that is willing to comply with her request.58 Therefore, many doctors will agree to the patient’s demand for multiple embryo transfer, even if it means noncompliance with the medical standards.59 The general discretion given to doctors and their patients has its advantages,60 but an abuse of the discretion inevitably leads to moral and ethical concerns among society. Nadya Suleman, widely known as “Octomom,” provides a pertinent example of the scrutiny that the lack of embryo transfer legislation invites.61 After she gave birth to octuplets by utilizing IVF, it was disclosed62 that Suleman’s physician, Michael Kamrava, implanted twelve embryos into her womb.63 Suleman had six other children, also conceived through IVF,64 three of whom had developmental disabilities.65 In addition, Suleman was an unemployed single mother receiving public assistance,66 56 Velikonja, supra note 50, at 482. The fertility industry has rapidly grown into more than $1 billion business, providing for strong competition among clinics. Stephanie Saul, Birth of Octuplets Puts Focus on Fertility Clinics, N.Y. TIMES (Feb. 11, 2009), http://www.nytimes.com/ 2009/02/12/health/12ivf.html. “The industry has doubled in size . . . . At last count, the number of procedures was up to 134,260 and there were more than 483 clinics across the country.” Id. 58 Id. 59 Id. 60 An unregulated industry allows doctors and scientists to experiment and procure new medical advancements. Velikonja, supra note 50, at 465. Furthermore, fertility patients enjoy the freedom to choose the reproductive methods that best suits their needs and preferences. Id. 61 See Forman, supra note 12, at 275; Radhika Rao, How (Not) to Regulate ARTs: Lessons from Octomom, 21 ALB. L.J. SCI. & TECH. 313, 313-14 (2011); see also Saul, supra note 57. 62 Originally, Suleman claimed that Dr. Kamrava had implanted six embryos, and two of them had divided into twins, but Dr. Kamrava admitted that he had in fact implanted twelve embryos. Shari Weiss, Octomom Nadya Suleman’s Doctor, Michael Kamrava, Loses Medical License After Long Investigation, N.Y. DAILY NEWS (June 2, 2011), http://articles.nydailynews.com/2011-06-02/gossip/29631720_1_michaelkamrava-octomom-nadya-suleman-fetal-reduction; Molly Hennessy-Fiske, Suleman Doctor Says Implanting a Dozen Embryos Was Wrong, L.A. TIMES (Oct. 22, 2010), http://articles.latimes.com/2010/oct/22/local/la-me-1022-octuplets-doctor-20101022; see also Saul, supra note 57. 63 Hennessy-Fiske, supra note 62. The ASRM Guidelines provides that only two eggs should be implanted in a woman of Suleman’s age; however, Suleman had been implanted with six times the recommended amount of embryos. Guidelines on Number of Embryos, supra note 40, at 1518; see also Weiss, supra note 62. 64 Weiss, supra note 62. 65 Forman, supra note 61, at 273. 66 Weiss, supra note 62. 57 2012] TWIN REDUCTIONS AND THE ABORTION RIGHT 209 propelling her further toward public condemnation as an irresponsible and unfit mother.67 Dr. Kamrava was also the subject of a prolonged investigation by California’s medical board,68 resulting in the revocation of his medical license.69 Kamrava claimed that Suleman insisted on the dozen-embryo transfer, and that she had agreed to undergo fetal reduction if she became pregnant with more than triplets.70 The medical board rejected Kamrava’s defense, emphasizing that the initial consideration of an appropriate number of embryos transferred is imperative and that doctors should not rely on the fetal reduction procedure in the event that multiple pregnancies result.71 Suleman’s circumstances transformed the public attitude toward IVF, animating concerns regarding the lack of embryo transfer legislation and prompting state legislatures to act.72 Ultimately, none of the proposed legislation passed,73 and multiple pregnancies still occur at significantly high rates74—a fact that brings to the forefront another controversial aspect of IVF: multifetal pregnancy reductions. 67 Forman, supra note 61, at 273; Rao, supra note 61, at 313. The investigation led by the California medical board was to determine “whether accepted standards of medical practice has been violated.” See Saul, supra note 57. Administrative law judge Daniel Juarez “found that Kamrava committed gross and repeated negligence by implanting Suleman with an excessive number of embryos . . . [but that he] was unlikely to repeat his mistakes.” Hennessy-Fiske, supra note 45. Judge Juarez recommended that the medical board place Kamrava on five years’ probation, instead of revoking his license. Id. The board eventually rejected the recommendation and revoked Kamrava’s license. Weiss, supra note 62. It has been suggested the close review of Kamrava was largely due to the fact that there is a lack of regulation combined with the “international notoriety of the octuplets.” HennessyFiske, supra note 45. 69 Weiss, supra note 62. However, Kamrava can petition for reinstatement of his medical license three years after the date of revocation. Id. 70 Hennessy-Fiske, supra note 62; Saul, supra note 57. 71 Weiss, supra note 62. 72 Forman, supra note 61, at 278; Rao, supra note 61, at 313. Georgia and Missouri were among states that proposed bills that would specifically limit the permissible number of embryos to transfer for each IVF cycle. Rao, supra note 61, at 314; Forman, supra note 61, at 278. 73 Forman, supra note 61, at 278; Rao, supra note 61, at 314. 74 AM. SOC’Y FOR REPROD. MED., MULTIPLE PREGNANCY AND BIRTH: TWINS, TRIPLETS & HIGH-ORDER MULTIPLES—A GUIDE FOR PATIENTS 3 (2012) [hereinafter MULTIPLE PREGNANCY AND BIRTH], available at http://www.asrm.org/uploadedFiles/ASRM_Content/ Resources/Patient_Resources/Fact_Sheets_and_Info_Booklets/multiples.pdf. The 2008 Assisted Reproductive Technology Report produced by the Center for Disease Control and Prevention further advises that the percentage of multiple pregnancies might have been higher than reported, due to pregnancies that end before the number of fetuses is determined. CTRS. FOR DISEASE CONTROL & PREVENTION, 2008 ASSISTED REPRODUCTIVE TECHNOLOGY REPORT 25, available at http://www.cdc.gov/art/ART2008/index.htm (last visited Nov. 24, 2012) [hereinafter ART2008]. 68 210 D. BROOKLYN LAW REVIEW [Vol. 78:1 Multifetal Pregnancy Reductions75 Multiple pregnancies create tremendous health risks to both the mother and fetuses.76 Women are at a higher risk of pregnancy complications, such as miscarriage, premature labor, gestational diabetes, anemia, and post-partum hemorrhaging.77 Furthermore, the fetuses are at great risk of premature birth, low birth weight, cerebral palsy, and other long-term medical and developmental complications.78 As a result, physicians perform multifetal pregnancy reductions to lower the number of fetuses that will be carried to term in order to increase the chance of a healthy and successful pregnancy.79 Pregnancy reduction procedures usually take place within the first twelve weeks of the pregnancy.80 Potassium chloride is injected into the gestational sac81 of the fetus or fetuses to terminate the fetal heart motion.82 Often, doctors perform ultrasounds to detect if any of the fetuses have abnormalities, because abnormal fetuses are most frequently selected for reduction.83 When considering a pregnancy reduction, patients are strongly urged to discuss the possible outcomes with their doctors and spouses before making a final determination about the future of their pregnancy.84 75 “Multifetal pregnancy reduction” is the medical term used by medical professional organizations and physicians to describe the procedure that reduces the number of fetuses in the uterus. It is also known as “selective reduction” or “pregnancy reduction.” MULTIPLE PREGNANCY AND BIRTH, supra note 74, at 9, 14. I will use the term “pregnancy reduction” to refer to this procedure. 76 Id. 77 Id.; Fact Sheet: Fertility Drugs, supra note 5; see also Riggan, supra note 4. 78 MULTIPLE PREGNANCY AND BIRTH, supra note 74, at 8; Fact Sheet: Fertility Drugs, supra note 5; see also Riggan, supra note 4. 79 Fact Sheet: Fertility Drugs, supra note 5. One out of three multiple pregnancies also result in a natural pregnancy reduction, where the woman’s body itself reduces the number of fetuses. Id. 80 Id. 81 At this early stage of pregnancy, “the fetus is enclosed in a fluid-filled pouch, called a gestational sac.” Id. 82 Id.; see also ROBERT BLANK & JANNA C. MERRICK, HUMAN REPRODUCTION, EMERGING TECHNOLOGIES, AND CONFLICTING RIGHTS 92 (1995). 83 BLANK & MERRICK, supra note 82, at 92. 84 Fact Sheet: Fertility Drugs, supra note 5. It’s hard for most couples to decide to have multifetal pregnancy reduction, especially if [the patient] has tried hard to get pregnant in the first place. If [a patient is] thinking about having this procedure, [the patient and their] partner should talk to [their] doctor who may recommend a visit with a maternal-fetal medicine specialist or get professional counseling before the procedure. Both partners need to be comfortable with their decision and may need emotional support prior to and immediately following the procedure. 2012] TWIN REDUCTIONS AND THE ABORTION RIGHT 211 Throughout the 1990s, physicians held opposing views on whether it was even necessary to reduce triplets to twins.85 Eventually, as technology progressed and the pregnancy reduction procedure evolved,86 physicians agreed that reducing triplets to twins was safer than carrying triplets to term.87 On the other hand, a twin pregnancy has been considered safe for both the mother and the fetuses,88 resulting in many doctors refusing to reduce a twin pregnancy to a “singleton”89 and generating rhetoric that equates twin pregnancy reductions to abortions.90 E. Twin Reductions Twin reductions spark intense public debate in the abortion context, not only among those who are pro-life, but also among those who identify themselves as pro-choice.91 Because multiple pregnancies are a well-known result of IVF, women undertake the procedure informed that a twin pregnancy is a very likely possibility.92 Furthermore, recent reports released by the Center for Disease Control and Prevention have confirmed Fact Sheet: Complications and Problems Associated with Multiple Births, AM. SOC’Y FOR REPROD. MED., http://www.asrm.org/uploadedFiles/ASRM_Content/Resources/ Patient_Resources/Fact_Sheets_and_Info_Booklets/complications_multiplebirths.pdf (last visited Jan. 16, 2012). 85 Padawer, supra note 14, at 25. 86 Pregnancy reductions came with a high risk of miscarriages. However, with better ultrasound equipment and higher physician “technical expertise,” the number of miscarriages effectively decreased. Id. 87 Id. 88 See A.J. Antsaklis, Reduction of Multifetal Pregnancies to Twins Does Not Increase Obstetric or Prenatal Risks, 14 OXFORD J. HUMAN REPROD. 1338, 1338 (1998). The study compared twin pregnancies resulting from assisted reproduction with standard twin pregnancies, and observed “no significant difference in miscarriage rate, mean gestational age at delivery, mean neonatal weight at birth or perinatal mortality rate.” Id.; see also Twin Pregnancies from Assisted Conception Are No More Risky than Those Resulting from Spontaneous Conception, STORKNET (Feb. 24, 2004), http://www.storknet.com/cubbies/infertility/news-twins.htm (noting that researchers at four academic medical centers monitored twin pregnancies and found that assisted reproduction conception did not contribute to an increased risk to the pregnancy). 89 Singleton is a term used to describe a pregnancy carrying a single fetus. See e.g., MULTIPLE PREGNANCY AND BIRTH, supra note 74, at 14. 90 Padawer, supra note 14, at 25. 91 See generally Jennifer Fulwiler, What Pro-Choice Intellectual Honesty Looks Like, NAT’L CATH. REG. (Aug. 12, 2011, 7:12 AM), http://www.ncregister.com/ blog/jennifer-fulwiler/what-pro-choice-intellectual-honesty-looks-like; Anna North, The Complicated Ethics of Twin Reductions, JEZEBEL (Aug. 12, 2011, 1:00 PM), http://jezebel.com/5830054/the-complicated-ethics-of-twin-reduction. 92 See ART2008, supra note 74 (reporting that twin pregnancies accounted for 29% of all overall births resulting from IVF pregnancies); see generally MULTIPLE PREGNANCY AND BIRTH, supra note 74; Fact Sheet: Fertility Drugs, supra note 5. 212 BROOKLYN LAW REVIEW [Vol. 78:1 that twin births in the United States are escalating,93 and the rise in twins is largely attributed to the growing popularity of IVF treatments.94 As a result, patients who undergo fertility treatment and affirmatively choose to reduce their twin fetuses to a singleton without the attendant health risks are viewed in a somewhat different light than those with multifetal pregnancy reductions. Unlike multifetal pregnancy reductions, twin reductions convert the existing controversy surrounding the lack of embryo transfer regulation into a misplaced debate regarding abortion rights.95 The attitude equating twin reductions to abortions is largely due to the fact that twin pregnancies are considered to be safe. Accordingly, reducing down to a singleton pregnancy is viewed as an “elective” procedure,96 and therefore the procedure has engendered attacks on constitutional abortion rights. Even though twin reductions are seen as an unpleasant result of IVF, the public outcry to eliminate twin reductions often resorts to restricting abortion rights rather than targeting the source of the problem: an unregulated embryo transfer system. Why does twin reduction add fuel to the abortion controversy? 93 Ctrs. for Disease Control & Prevention, Multiple Births, CDC.GOV, http://www.cdc.gov/nchs/fastats/multiple.htm (last updated Nov. 30, 2011). In 2009, one in every thirty babies born in the United States was a twin, a significant increase over the one in fifty-three rate in 1980. Id. Nationally, 3.3 percent of all births were twins in 2009, up from 2 percent in 1980. Id. 94 Joyce Martin, an epidemiologist who co-authored the CDC Birth report, expressed that an increase in twins were expected as more women are delaying pregnancy until they are over thirty. For some unknown reason, women over thirty years of age are more likely to conceive twins naturally than younger women. About a third of the twin birth rate increase can be attributed to that. However, the remaining portion of the rise of twin births is due to fertility drugs and treatments. Attack of the Twins! Older Moms, IVF Spurring More Double Births, N.Y. DAILY NEWS (Jan. 5, 2012), http://articles.nydailynews.com/2012-01-05/news/30595170_1_twins-older-momsfertility-drugs; Janice D’Arcy, Twins are Multiplying, Raising New Questions for the Nature vs. Nurture Debate, WASH. POST (Jan. 5, 2012), http://www.washingtonpost.com/blogs/onparenting/post/twins-are-multiplying-raising-new-questions-for-the-nature-vs-nurturedebate/2012/01/05/gIQALYOAdP_blog.html; Robin Wulffson, New CDC Report: Twin Birth Rate Soaring in U.S., EMAXHEALTH (Jan. 5, 2012, 2:05 PM), http://www.emaxhealth.com/ 11306/new-cdc-report-twin-birth-rate-soaring-us. Furthermore, the greatest increase in twin rates was reported for women 40 and older, who are more likely to require fertility treatments and more likely to implant a higher number of embryos in a single IVF cycle. D’Arcy, supra; Wulffson, supra. Another interesting aspect reported is that over the last three decades, the twin rate increase was not uniform for Caucasian and African American women. Without fertility treatment, African Americans have a higher rate of twin pregnancies. Wulffson, supra; Attack of the Twins!, supra. The increase in Caucasian twins conveys the disparity that exists with the availability of IVF treatments among different races and socioeconomic classes. 95 See infra Part III. 96 Robin Marty, The “Elective” Selective Reduction, RH REALITY CHECK (Aug. 10, 2011, 4:47 PM), http://www.rhrealitycheck.org/blog/2011/08/10/elective-selective-reduction. 2012] TWIN REDUCTIONS AND THE ABORTION RIGHT 213 The answer has to do with the initial desire of desperately wanting children and the subsequent termination, which requires the selection of one of the fetuses. It can be difficult to reconcile the fact that a woman who struggles with infertility and crosses significant emotional, physical, and financial leaps to become pregnant would subsequently choose to terminate a pregnancy for non-medical reasons. Antiabortion activists argue that it is immoral for the woman to initiate a pregnancy knowing it could result in a termination that is not justified on health risk grounds.97 Some even say that a woman loses her personal autonomy when she initially chooses IVF and therefore has a greater responsibility to carry the pregnancies to term.98 Heated debates ensue about the nature of the selection: the patient is essentially choosing or selecting one fetus over the other.99 Typically, if one fetus has a genetic disorder or other complications, it is not surprising that the healthier fetus is chosen to survive.100 However, if a patient has two equally healthy fetuses, her selection of one over the other becomes a contentious issue.101 The inquiries presented above summarize the controversial nature of twin reductions. Personal autonomy and reproductive freedom are staples of American values, reflected in the Constitution. Twin reductions are an example of the conundrum that inevitably develops when reproductive choices increase. The ethical and moral considerations that have emerged from twin reductions are a source of dispute and confusion. In addition, the societal response to these concerns is further complicated by the fact that twin reductions accentuate the apparent conflict between two fundamental rights. It is therefore helpful to examine the doctrines implicated by twin reductions, given that legislatures must account for two types of reproductive choices that are guaranteed by the fundamental right of privacy but are not often seen together. 97 See, e.g., Thomas Peters, Coin Toss Abortion? Why Our Protracted National Tolerance for Abortion Must End, LIVEACTION (Aug. 16, 2011), http://liveaction.org/ blog/coin-toss-abortion-why-our-protracted-national-tolerance-for-abortion-must-end/. 98 See Danielle Friedman, A New Debate over In Vitro, DAILY BEAST (July 26, 2010, 8:03 AM), http://www.thedailybeast.com/articles/2010/07/27/can-ivf-women-havean-abortion.html. 99 See William E. May, “Reducing” Pregnancies and “Wanting” Children, CHRISTENDOM, http://www.christendom-awake.org/pages/may/reducing-pregnancies.htm (last updated Sept. 28, 2011). 100 See Liza Mundy, Too Much to Carry?, WASH. POST (May 20, 2007), http://www.washingtonpost.com/wp-dyn/content/article/2007/05/15/AR2007051501730.html. 101 See Peters, supra note 97. 214 II. BROOKLYN LAW REVIEW [Vol. 78:1 THE HISTORY OF CONFLICTING FUNDAMENTAL RIGHTS Twin reductions invoke constitutional concerns primarily in two situations: (1) IVF, where an affirmative choice to procreate is made, and (2) the reduction procedure, where an affirmative choice to terminate a part of the pregnancy is made. The Supreme Court has ultimately recognized that a right to procreate is fundamental and intermingled with a broad right to privacy. On the other hand, the right to abortion is much narrower because the Court has recognized that states have an interest in intervening and limiting it. An analysis of the constitutional protections will reveal that, in comparison to the right to procreate, abortion is a much narrower right that is already in danger of state intrusion. A. Protection of the Right to Procreate The Supreme Court has established the right to procreate as a fundamental right, as evidenced by the fact that states cannot compel a person to procreate102 nor can they obstruct a person’s ability to procreate.103 The cases dealing with the latter support the idea that access to IVF is a constitutionally protected right. In Skinner v. Oklahoma,104 the Court struck down an Oklahoma statute that compelled sterilization of habitual criminals.105 Even though the rights to marriage and procreation are not explicitly listed in the Constitution, the Court declared that those rights were “basic civil rights of man” and “fundamental to the very existence and survival” of individuals.106 The Court applied a strict scrutiny standard of review to invalidate the statute,107 declaring the choice of whether to procreate as a paramount right that should be free from unnecessary state intrusion.108 102 See infra Part III. The Court’s abortion precedents prohibit states from imposing an undue burden on a woman’s right to terminate her pregnancy. See generally Planned Parenthood of Se. Pa. v. Casey, 505 U.S. 833 (1992). 103 See Eisenstadt v. Baird, 405 U.S. 438, 453 (1972); Griswold v. Connecticut, 381 U.S. 479, 497 (1965); Skinner v. Oklahoma, 316 U.S. 535, 541 (1942). 104 316 U.S. 535. 105 Id. at 541. 106 Id. 107 Id. (“We advert to them merely in emphasis of our view that strict scrutiny of the classification which a State makes in a sterilization law is essential . . . .”). 108 Id. 2012] TWIN REDUCTIONS AND THE ABORTION RIGHT 215 Subsequently, in Griswold v. Connecticut,109 the Court struck down a law prohibiting the use of contraception, holding that the law infringed upon a married couple’s right to privacy that is enshrined within the “zone of privacy created by several fundamental constitutional guarantees.”110 A married couple’s right to privacy was extended to individuals in Eisenstadt v. Baird.111 The Court emphasized, “If the right of privacy means anything, it is the right of the individual, married or single, to be free from unwarranted governmental intrusion into matters so fundamentally affecting a person as the decision whether to bear or beget a child.”112 The Court clarified that the constitutional right to privacy not only protects an individual’s general decision whether to procreate,113 but also that it protects access to the particular method chosen to achieve or avoid procreation.114 The emphasis on “individual” autonomy applies neutrally to both men and women, regardless of their marital status.115 Through these precedents, therefore, IVF, which enables an individual to bear a child, is protected by an individual’s right to procreate.116 B. The Right to Abortion The broad privacy right found in the penumbra of constitutional guarantees that protect an individual’s choice to procreate117 did not extend to the right to abortion.118 Instead, the 109 381 U.S. 479 (1965). Id. at 485. The Court found the zone of privacy within the penumbra of expressed constitutional rights. It reasoned that the First, Third, Fourth, and Fifth Amendments created this zone of privacy protection. Id. at 484. The Court further held that a law that destructs the privacy given to married couples is “repulsive to the notions of privacy surrounding the marriage relationship.” Id. at 486. (“We deal with a right of privacy older than the Bill of Rights . . . .”). 111 405 U.S. 438 (1972). 112 Id. at 453. The Court relied on the prior precedents from Griswold and Skinner as a basis for its holding. Id. 113 Id. at 453-54. 114 In the present case, the means chosen was contraceptives to avoid procreation, and a state could not ban access to these contraceptives. Id. at 453. See generally Carey v. Population Serv. Int’l, 431 U.S. 678 (1977) (striking down a state statute that limited the distribution of nonprescription contraceptives to licensed pharmacists as unconstitutionally interfering with the rights of individuals to use contraceptives.). 115 Eisenstadt, 405 U.S. at 453-54. 116 Lower federal courts have also interpreted these precedents to uphold IVF procedures as constitutional. See, e.g., Lifchez v. Hartigan, 735 F. Supp. 1361, 1377 (N.D. Ill. 1990) (“It takes no great leap of logic to see that within the constitutionally protected choices that includes the right to have access to contraceptives, there must be included within that cluster the right to submit to a medical procedure that may bring about, rather than prevent, pregnancy.”) 117 See supra note 111 and accompanying text. 110 216 BROOKLYN LAW REVIEW [Vol. 78:1 Court placed abortion rights in a narrower privacy doctrine, substantially increasing a state’s power to intrude on the right.119 The first landmark abortion case the Supreme Court decided was Roe v. Wade, where the Court struck down a Texas law banning abortions.120 The Court recognized abortion as a fundamental right protected by the Fourteenth Amendment’s Due Process Clause.121 Therefore, any law attempting to restrict abortions would have to pass the “strict scrutiny test.”122 The Court did not find the state’s interests—protecting women’s health and protecting the potentiality of fetal life—to be sufficiently compelling to uphold an outright ban on abortions.123 However, the Court explicitly stated that a woman’s right to an abortion is not absolute124 by acknowledging that states have sufficient interests to warrant some regulation, even in areas encroaching on a fundamental right.125 To balance the interests, the Court created a “trimester approach,”126 emphasizing that a state’s interest in protecting the life of the mother and the life of the fetus becomes increasingly compelling as the pregnancy term progresses.127 The Court held that the state’s interests 118 The Court made clear that the right to abortion would not fall in the same realm as the right to procreate: The pregnant woman cannot be isolated in her privacy. She carries an embryo and, later, a fetus . . . . The situation therefore is inherently different from marital intimacy . . . or procreation, or education, with which Eisenstadt and Griswold . . . were . . . concerned. As we have intimated above, it is reasonable and appropriate for a State to decide that at some point in time another interest, that of health of the mother or that of potential human life, becomes significantly involved. The woman’s privacy is no longer sole and any right of privacy she possesses must be measured accordingly. Roe v. Wade, 410 U.S. 113, 159 (1973) (citation omitted). 119 “We, therefore, conclude that the right of personal privacy includes the abortion decision, but that this right is not unqualified and must be considered against important state interests in regulation.” Id. at 154. 120 Id. at 162. 121 Id. at 153 (“This right to privacy, whether it be founded in the Fourteenth Amendment’s concept of personal liberty and restrictions upon state action, as we feel it is, . . . is broad enough to encompass a woman’s decision whether or not to terminate her pregnancy.” (emphasis added)). 122 Id. at 155. Under the strict scrutiny test, a government restriction on a fundamental right must be narrowly tailored to fulfill a legitimate and compelling government interest. Otherwise, the state regulation is ruled unconstitutional in violation of the Due Process Clause. 123 Id. at 153. 124 Id. (“[A]ppellant and some amici argue that a woman’s right is absolute and that she is entitled to terminate her pregnancy at whatever time, in whatever way, and for whatever reason she alone chooses. With this we do not agree.”). 125 Id. at 154. 126 Id. at 163. 127 Id. at 162-63. 2012] TWIN REDUCTIONS AND THE ABORTION RIGHT 217 during the first trimester are not sufficiently compelling to restrict first trimester abortions.128 Furthermore, during the second trimester, the state may protect its interest in the mother’s health, as long as the regulations “reasonably relate” to her health.129 However, the Court determined that, because states have a compelling interest in protecting the potential life of the fetus, states may regulate or even ban abortions during the third trimester, reasoning that this was the period when the fetus typically becomes viable.130 This trimester approach was overruled in Planned Parenthood v. Casey,131 in part because technological advancements paved the way for a more precise determination of the point of fetal viability,132 but also to give recognition to state interests.133 The Court emphasized that the rigid trimester framework presented in Roe “misconceives the nature of the pregnant woman’s interests and . . . undervalues the State’s interest in potential life . . . .”134 The Court expanded its analysis of abortion and recognized the right as part of the right to privacy encompassed within a broader concept of liberty and personal autonomy protected by the Fourteenth Amendment, which includes the ability to make choices involving the most “intimate and personal” matters and the right to define one’s own concept of existence.135 The Court reaffirmed that a woman has a right to abortion before viability,136 but it also emphasized that a state has “legitimate interests from the outset of the pregnancy in protecting the health of the woman and the life of the fetus that may become a child.”137 In order to highlight that some governmental intrusion may be warranted, the Court established the “undue burden” standard, which replaced the previous strict scrutiny test.138 “A 128 Id. at 163. Id. 130 Id. 131 Planned Parenthood of Se. Pa. v. Casey, 505 U.S. 833, 872 (1992). 132 Id. at 860. At the time of Roe, viability was thought to occur at twenty-eight weeks, but by 1992, viability was determined to occur as early as twenty-three weeks. 133 “[I]t must be remembered that Roe v. Wade speaks with clarity in establishing not only the woman’s liberty but also the State’s ‘important and legitimate interest in potential life.’ That portion of the decision in Roe has been given too little acknowledgment and implementation by the Court in its subsequent cases.” Id. at 871. 134 Id. at 873 (emphasis added). 135 Id. at 857. 136 Id. at 846. 137 Id. 138 Id. at 876. (“The very notion that the State has a substantial interest in potential life leads to the conclusion that not all regulations must be deemed 129 218 BROOKLYN LAW REVIEW [Vol. 78:1 finding of an undue burden is shorthand for the conclusion that a state regulation has the purpose or effect of placing a substantial obstacle in the path of a woman seeking to abort an unviable fetus.”139 In Casey, the Court emphasized that, notwithstanding a woman’s right to abortion, a state has substantial “interest[s] in the potential life within the woman,”140 and “[n]ot all governmental intrusion is of necessity unwarranted.”141 Furthermore, the Court explicitly acknowledged that a State has an interest in protecting potential life throughout a woman’s pregnancy142: Though the woman has a right to choose to terminate or continue her pregnancy before viability, it does not at all follow that the State is prohibited from taking steps to ensure that this choice is thoughtful and informed. Even in the earliest stages of pregnancy, the State may enact rules and regulations designed to encourage her to know that there are philosophic and social arguments of great weight that can be brought to bear in favor of continuing the pregnancy to full term and that there are procedures and institutions to allow adoption of unwanted children as well as a certain degree of state assistance if the mother chooses to raise the child herself. The Constitution does not forbid a State or city, pursuant to democratic process, from expressing a preference for normal childbirth.143 Thus, after Casey, a state may not ban abortions outright before viability,144 but it may enact regulations to “promote the State’s profound interest in potential life,”145 as long as it does not place an undue burden on a woman’s right to abortion.146 After viability, “the State in promoting its interest in the potentiality of human life may, if it chooses, regulate, and even proscribe, abortion except where it is necessary, in appropriate medical judgment, for the preservation of the life or health of the mother.”147 unwarranted. Not all burdens on the right to decide whether to terminate a pregnancy will be undue.”). 139 Id. at 877. 140 Id. at 875. 141 Id. 142 Id. at 876. 143 Id. at 872 (internal quotation marks omitted). 144 Id. at 879. 145 Id. at 878. (emphasis added) (“[T]hroughout the pregnancy, the State may take measures to ensure that the woman’s choice is informed, and measures designed to advance this interest will not be invalidated as long as their purpose is to persuade the women to choose childbirth over abortion.”). 146 Id. 147 Id. at 879 (citations omitted). 2012] TWIN REDUCTIONS AND THE ABORTION RIGHT 219 Casey’s departure from Roe altered the right to abortion in three significant ways. First, Roe’s trimester framework prohibited governmental intrusion in the first trimester, but by adopting the undue burden approach in Casey, the Court dismantled the period once set aside for the woman to make her decision free from governmental intrusion and firmly established that the state has an interest in the fetus from the outset of the pregnancy.148 Second, Casey’s undue burden approach still identifies the right to abortion as fundamental, but it does not invalidate a state’s imposition on a woman’s decision-making process when exercising that right.149 Therefore, states are free to enact regulations to influence a woman’s choice about her abortion, as long as the state does not infringe on the right to abortion outright.150 Third, the undue burden standard undoubtedly granted significant weight to a state’s interest in potential life, broadening the number of permissible abortion regulations.151 Despite these restrictions, IVF and the reduction procedure remain largely unregulated. However, public outcry is growing in recognition of the ethical and moral concerns presented by situations—like twin reductions—that result from unregulated embryo transfers. These ethical and moral concerns have redirected the public’s focus onto the termination aspect of twin reductions, even though such concerns fundamentally stem from the IVF procedure itself. III. WHY TWIN REDUCTIONS BECOME ANALOGOUS TO ABORTIONS Medically speaking, a reduction procedure is not the same as an abortion.152 Nevertheless, society uses the term “twin reductions” and abortions interchangeably. Some anti-abortion activists have even gone so far as to claim that a twin reduction is a cowardly “euphemism for murder.”153 Others have claimed 148 See Caitlin E. Borgmann, Abortion, The Undue Burden Standard, and The Evisceration of Women’s Privacy, 16 WM. & MARY J. WOMEN & L. 291, 310 (2010). 149 Casey, 505 U.S. at 877 (“What is at stake is the woman’s right to make the ultimate decision, not a right to be insulated from all others in doing so.”). 150 Id. 151 See Priscilla J. Smith, Give Justice Ginsburg What She Wants: Using Sex Equality Arguments to Demand Examination of the Legitimacy of State Interests in Abortion Regulation, 34 HARV. J.L. & GENDER 377, 396 (2011). 152 An abortion terminates the fetus and empties the uterus, whereas, a reduction does not result in an empty uterus. Mundy, supra note 100. 153 Albert Mohler, This Isn’t Meddling—It’s Murder, CHRISTIAN POST (Aug. 17, 2011, 10:26 AM), http://www.christianpost.com/news/this-isnt-meddling-its-murder54062; Peter Saunders, “Selective Reduction”—A Euphemism for Deliberately Killing One 220 BROOKLYN LAW REVIEW [Vol. 78:1 that abortion is the “safety net” for IVF, referring to twin reductions.154 Why is there such a concentrated effort to lobby bringing twin reductions under the umbrella of abortions? Perhaps the best explanation is that a twin reduction is often seen as “elective” rather than medically necessary.155 Therefore, people tend to scrutinize the reasons why a woman might choose twin reductions, and such intense scrutiny ends up underscoring the same ethical and moral dilemmas that are attributed to abortions in the normal course. Those dilemmas are particularly used by anti-abortion activists to explain why they think abortion is “wrong” and should be illegal. However, twin reductions go one step further and cause additional outrage in light of the initial use of IVF to attain a pregnancy that is later partially terminated. Thus, although the focus on the reason equates twin reductions to abortions, twin reductions also raise issues that result from IVF and the initial choice to procreate. To illuminate this controversial landscape, imagine the following hypothetical scenarios that highlight the similar ethical and moral considerations associated with twin reductions and abortions. After each hypothetical, an explanation will present the main ethical and moral issues stemming from each situation. These observations will demonstrate that the problems associated with twin reductions are in fact quite different and are a result of engaging in the initial IVF process. A. Hypotheticals156 In the hypotheticals below: (1) all patients are informed of the high possibility of multiple pregnancies; (2) all patients are implanted with two or more embryos, either as a result of the patient’s choice, the doctor’s choice, or both; (3) none of the patients or fetuses are in danger of any health risks; and (4) all or More Babies, NAT’L RIGHT TO LIFE NEWS TODAY (Jan. 11, 2012), http://www.nationalrighttolifenews.org/news/2012/01/selective-reduction-a-euphemismfor-deliberately-killing-one-or-more-babies; Rebecca Taylor, Pro-Life Review of Top 10 Bioethic Stories from 2011, LIFENEWS.COM (Jan. 3, 2012, 7:28 PM), http://www.lifenews.com/2012/01/03/pro-life-review-of-top-10-bioethics-stories-from-2011. 154 Rebecca Taylor, Abortion: The “Safety Net” for IVF, MARY MEETS DOLLY (Nov. 23, 2010, 9:10 AM), http://www.marymeetsdolly.com/blog/index.php?/archives/994Abortion-the-safety-net-for-IVF.html. 155 Marty, supra note 96. 156 All hypotheticals, including names and facts are fictional. I constructed these hypotheticals through the different sources and cases I studied. Some are, of course, exaggerated to emphasize the possible controversies. 2012] TWIN REDUCTIONS AND THE ABORTION RIGHT 221 of these patients live in State X, a fictitious state in the United States that has no legislation regarding the permissible number of embryos transferred per IVF cycle. 1. Caroline: Post-Menopausal Pregnancies Caroline is a fifty-year old single woman and a prominent marketing executive. She has never been married and has not found her ideal partner. Due to the amount of stress she experienced and the time commitment required to achieve her career goals, Caroline has never tried to have a child. However, now that she is a successful executive, she decides that she wants a child in her life. Because of her age, it is difficult for her to conceive naturally, so she begins IVF treatments. Caroline is now pregnant with twins but has decided that she does not want to raise two children by herself at her age. Therefore, she asks her doctor to perform a twin reduction. To begin, a massive debate already exists regarding the age when a woman should no longer be able to procreate. Caroline is fifty years old, so the only way she would realistically be able to have a child is through IVF. Many critics condemn postmenopausal pregnancies as “an unnatural act.”157 Furthermore, Caroline does not want to raise two children by herself, even though she can afford it financially. Anti-abortionists would conclude that Caroline is fashioning her life as she wants and would label her reasoning as “profoundly selfish.”158 2. Laura & Will: Consumerism Laura, a high-school teacher, and Will, a mechanic, have been married for twenty-five years and have two children. They decide that they are ready for another child. However, Laura has trouble conceiving naturally. After five years of IVF treatments, Laura is finally pregnant with twins. The couple decides that they do not have the energy to take care of two newborns in addition to raising their other two children. Furthermore, they do not believe they are financially capable of supporting four children, particularly after the exorbitant IVF treatments. Laura fears that she will not be able to devote 157 Lylah Alphonse, Too Old to Be a Parent? Post-Menopausal Pregnancy Triggers Moral Outrage, ALLVOICES (Dec. 18, 2009, 2:32 PM), http://www.allvoices.com/contributednews/4840901-too-old-to-be-a-parent-postmenopausal-pregnancy-triggers-moral-outrage. 158 Ryan Sprague, “This Is Not What I Want for My Life,” RYANSPRAGUE.COM (Jan. 11, 2012), http://www.ryansprague.com/2012/01/11/this-is-not-what-i-want-for-my-life. 222 BROOKLYN LAW REVIEW [Vol. 78:1 enough time and attention to her older children and is terrified that she will become a bad mother. However, she states that she would forego twin reduction had she conceived the twins naturally. Will fully supports her decision. Laura and Will are a middle-class couple who already have two children, but who choose to have more children. This would be viewed as “willful disregard” of their prior experiences.159 However, a larger issue highlighted in this scenario is Laura’s statement that she would have kept both children had they been conceived naturally. First, the couple’s rationale that they were not financially secure to afford two children is cast into doubt. Raising a child born through IVF will not cost more than raising a natural born child. A natural child would pose the same problems the couple predicts they will face if they do not reduce the pregnancy.160 Moreover, this scenario highlights a major criticism of IVF and abortions: consumerism of reproductive health.161 The possibility that an IVF baby is treated differently than a natural baby is a major source of concern.162 Furthermore, Laura’s statements can be construed as justifying abortion because of the way the pregnancy was conceived. Anti-abortion activists will view this reasoning as “dehumanizing children”163 and will claim that abortion allows women to play God and dispose of otherwise healthy and viable children.164 3. Rob & Jackie: Selection Rob is a successful real-estate mogul who yearns for a son to carry on his family’s name and businesses. Jackie is unable to conceive children naturally and begins IVF treatments in hopes of giving Rob a son. Jackie is pregnant with twins, one boy and one girl. Because she is a stay-at-home 159 Id. Lynne Marie Kohm, A Hitchhiker’s Guide to ART: Implementing SelfGoverned Personally Responsible Decision-Making in the Context of Artificial Reproductive Technology, 39 CAP. U. L. REV 413, 426 (Children born through IVF are “the same as people conceived the old-fashioned way.” (internal quotation marks omitted)). 161 See generally Judie Brown, Consumerism in the Womb, AM. LIFE LEAGUE (Aug. 16, 2011), http://www.all.org/article/index/id/OTE0NQ; Frances Kelly, From Octomom to MomMinusOne, Is Sex in America Too “Consumerish”?, RENEW AM. (Aug. 12, 2011), http://www.renewamerica.com/columns/kelly/110812. 162 See Brown, supra note 161; Kelly, supra note 161. 163 Brown, supra note 161. 164 Ken Connor, Infertility and Abortion: When Playing God Destroys Lives, LIFENEWS (Oct. 13, 2012, 10:17 AM), http://www.lifenews.com/2012/10/03/infertilityand-abortion-when-playing-god-destroys-lives/. 160 2012] TWIN REDUCTIONS AND THE ABORTION RIGHT 223 mother, Jackie is thrilled with the idea of raising twins. Rob, on the other hand, does not want to raise a girl. He convinces Jackie that daughters are much more difficult to handle. Jackie eventually agrees and decides to reduce her pregnancy, choosing the male fetus over the female. This scenario presents a chief source of resentment that anti-abortionists have over twin reductions. Because there are originally two fetuses, pro-lifers view the procedure as a selection process, where one fetus is “selected” to survive over the other.165 Here, Rob only desires a male child and persuades his wife to abort the female fetus. With twin reductions, gender preference is one of the primary ways that the patient decides which fetus to keep.166 The moral and ethical implications of gender selection practices in general relate to a contentious issue within society.167 If the gender is the same or the patient has no preference, the doctor usually chooses the fetus that is easier to access,168 which ignites another source of concern for antiabortionists.169 Indeed, numerous conservatives have coined twin reductions as “coin toss” abortions, “where one twin lives and one twin dies simply because one twin is closer to the abortionist’s needle.”170 Lastly, by referring to this procedure as a “selection,” many conservatives view it as treating children as disposable commodities.171 B. How Do We Fix This? These issues inevitably cause anti-abortionists to add twin reductions to their list of reasons to ban abortions. The issues presented in the hypotheticals illustrate the questionable ethical practices associated with twin reductions. It is thus reasonable to pursue government regulation. However, to suggest, as many have, that abortion rights are too broad and should be reined in is a mistake. Anti-abortion activists who voice their concern about twin reductions rarely call for regulation of the IVF process. The attack solely targets the termination aspect of the pregnancy, even though most twin 165 May, supra note 99. Mundy, supra note 100. 167 See Meredith Leigh Birdsall, An Exploration of “The ‘Wild West’ of Reproductive Technology”: Ethical and Feminist Perspectives on Sex-Selection Practices in the United States, 17 WM. & MARY J. WOMEN & L. 223, 234 (2010). 168 Mundy, supra note 100. 169 Peters, supra note 97. 170 Id. 171 May, supra note 99. 166 224 BROOKLYN LAW REVIEW [Vol. 78:1 reductions occur as a result of IVF and the number of embryos implanted in a single cycle.172 In light of the fact that abortion rights have been significantly weakened over the past decades and remain in uncertainty today, twin reductions should not perpetuate further attacks on the right to abortion. Therefore, an effective solution to the twin reduction problem should target the IVF practice directly rather than abortion more broadly. IV. THE CURRENT SUSCEPTIBILITY OF ABORTION RIGHTS A. Post-Casey Weakening of the Right to Abortion As mentioned in Part II, the Court in Casey held that states have a legitimate interest in potential life and are permitted to enact regulations to advance their interest, so long as those regulations do not pose an undue burden on the right to abortion.173 Many scholars have lamented that although Casey was technically a victory for the right to abortion, in reality the decision enabled the state to further interfere with a woman’s right to abortion.174 For example, in Gonzales v. Carhart,175 the Court upheld the Partial-Birth Abortion Ban Act, which bans a particular method of abortion so long as a safe, alternate abortion method is available.176 Some argue that the Gonzales decision, by affirming the Court’s protection of the state interest in potential life, opened the floodgates for government intrusion.177 They fear that the state interest will become so broad that, when coupled with the Court’s lack of scrutiny, it will inevitably allow regulations that chip away at the right to abortion.178 This fear may already be justified, as evidenced by numerous state legislatures’ attempts to restrict abortions179 by 172 See Evans & Britt, supra note 19, at 299; Trisha Macnair, Selective Reduction in Pregnancy, BBC HEALTH BLOG, http://www.bbc.co.uk/health/physical_ health/pregnancy/pregnancy_reduction.shtml (last updated June 2008) (stating that “Selective reduction became more common as a result of IVF techniques”); see generally Padawer, supra note 14. 173 See generally Part II supra. 174 See Borgmann, supra note 148, at 291 (“Casey’s ‘undue burden’ test has fostered extensive encroachments on women’s personal privacy.”); Smith, supra note 151 at 379 (Through Casey, “the ability of a state to regulate abortion in furtherance of its interest in protecting potential life has expanded . . . .”). 175 550 U.S. 124 (2007). 176 Id. at 129. 177 Smith, supra note 151, at 379-80. 178 Id. 179 See Anna Holmes, GOP Candidates Revive Issue of Birth Control, WASH. POST, Jan. 12, 2012, at C1, available at http://www.washingtonpost.com/lifestyle/style/conversation- 2012] TWIN REDUCTIONS AND THE ABORTION RIGHT 225 developing new ways to leverage the broad and vaguely defined term “interest in potential life.” Some states have tried to implement “fetal pain”180 measures, which encourage patients to request anesthesia because the fetus is “capable of feeling pain.”181 These measures publicize a state’s moral opposition to abortion and also convey another aspect of Casey that is extremely beneficial for states. The Court’s decision in Casey granted states the ability to persuade a woman, throughout the course of her pregnancy, to opt out of an abortion.182 This resulted in a proliferation of “informed consent” laws, which require doctors to describe the abortion procedure to their patients183 using a graphic script drafted by the state.184 Another purpose behind informed consent laws is to warn the woman of possible regret if she goes through with her choice to terminate her pregnancy.185 Furthermore, compulsory ultrasound laws are designed to dissuade women from choosing abortion by forcing them to look and listen to the ultrasound of an unwanted pregnancy.186 Such measures not only convey the state’s obvious opposition to abortion, but they also essentially harass women during their decision-making process by attempting to torment them with guilt.187 Moreover, state legislatures have recently attempted to use the democratic process to eradicate abortion rights. One example of this strategy can be gleaned from the recent “Personhood Amendment” proposals.188 The purpose of these amendments is to declare an embryo as a person, thereby entitling it to full legal rights and consequently equating over-abortion-continues-39-years-later/2012/01/05/gIQA5j0luP_story_1.html (“By the end of [2011], 135 measures had been enacted [in efforts to threaten abortion rights] . . . a record number of abortion restrictions.”). 180 Borgmann, supra note 148, at 319. 181 Smith, supra note 151, at 397. 182 See Brown, supra note 161. 183 Borgmann, supra note 148, at 319; Smith, supra note 151, at 398. 184 Borgmann, supra note 148, at 320. 185 Id. 186 Id. at 319; see generally GUTTMACHER INST., STATE POLICIES IN BRIEF: REQUIREMENTS FOR ULTRASOUND (Oct. 2012), available at http://www.guttmacher.org/ statecenter/spibs/spib_RFU.pdf; see also Smith, supra note 151, at 397. 187 See Jonathan Gray, Compulsory Ultrasound Audiences and Feminism, ANTENNA (Feb. 27, 2012), http://blog.commarts.wisc.edu/2012/02/27/compulsory-ultrasoundaudiences-and-feminism/; Carolyn Jones, “We Have No Choice”: One Woman’s Ordeal with Texas’ New Sonogram Law, TX. OBSERVER (Mar. 15, 2012, 9:03 AM), http://www.texasobserver.org/we-have-no-choice-one-womans-ordeal-with-texas-newsonogram-law/. 188 Erik Eckholm, Push for “Personhood” Amendment Represents New Tack in Abortion Fight, N.Y. TIMES (Oct. 25, 2011), http://www.nytimes.com/2011/10/26/us/ politics/personhood-amendments-would-ban-nearly-all-abortions.html. 226 BROOKLYN LAW REVIEW [Vol. 78:1 abortion to murder.189 Mississippi, Nevada, and Alabama, among other states, have enacted such initiatives,190 which are viewed as “the most extreme in a field of extreme anti-abortion measures that have been before the states this year.”191 The personhood initiative goes beyond the abortion restrictions adopted by states—such as the informed consent laws—because its main purpose is to “narrow or hamper access to abortions by, for example, sharply restricting the procedures at as early as 20 weeks, curbing insurance coverage and imposing expensive regulations on clinics.”192 If the proposals are initially successful but later declared unconstitutional by the Supreme Court, abortion rights activists claim that the amendment could “disrupt vital care and force years of costly court battles.”193 The more dangerous prospective result of the personhood amendments is that they would allow states to interpret Roe to uphold abortion restrictions by reasoning that an embryo’s right to life outweighs a woman’s privacy rights.194 Even if voters disapprove the personhood initiatives, it is clear that “personhood groups” will not give up the fight to declare an embryo a person and will continue to push this agenda to attack abortion rights.195 B. The Political Landscape of Abortion The current composition of the Supreme Court makes many scholars uneasy about the future of Roe.196 The previous years dominated by the Republican Party have seen a shift among the bench toward the conservative end of the spectrum.197 189 Id.; see also Laura Bassett, Nevada Judge Rules Fetal Personhood Initiative Misleading to Voters, HUFFINGTON POST (Dec. 19, 2011, 6:34 PM), http://www.huffingtonpost.com/2011/12/19/nevada-fetal-personhood_n_1159082.html; Robin Marty, Mississippi Plans to Push “Personhood” Through Legislature After Voters Say No, CARE2 (Jan. 4, 2012, 11:00 PM), http://www.care2.com/causes/mississippi-plansto-push-personhood-through-the-legislature-after-voters-say-no.html; Mike McClanahan, Voters May Define Start of Human Life: Alabama Personhood Bill, CBS42 NEWS (Jan. 3, 2012, 9:08 PM), http://www.cbs42.com/content/localnews/story/Voters-may-definestart-of-human-life-Alabama/3pN4m91MaEa8sOLFF6b_cQ.cspx. 190 See Bassett, supra note 189; Marty, supra note 189; McClanahan, supra note 189. 191 Eckholm, supra note 188. 192 Id. 193 Id. 194 See Rita M. Dunaway, The Personhood Strategy: A State’s Prerogative to Take Back Abortion Law, 47 WILLAMETTE L. REV. 327, 328 (2011); Tom Venzor, Protecting the Unborn Child: The Current State of Law Concerning the So-Called Right to Abortion and Intervention by the Holy See, 89 NEB. L. REV. 1132, 1140 (2011). 195 See, e.g., Marty, supra note 189. 196 See Borgmann, supra note 148, at 311; Smith, supra note 151, at 403. 197 Smith, supra note 151, at 403. 2012] TWIN REDUCTIONS AND THE ABORTION RIGHT 227 Since Justice O’Connor’s retirement, Justice Kennedy is now seen as the swing vote on abortion issues.198 Scholars are not confident that Justice Kennedy will protect abortion rights,199 claiming that his interpretation of Casey’s undue burden standard “gives unprecedented weight to the state’s interest in the embryo or fetus, thereby permitting all manner of encroachments on the privacy of women seeking abortions.”200 Furthermore, presidential elections generally play an important role in the political climate for abortion rights. First, presidents often have the opportunity to appoint a new Supreme Court Justice during their term in office.201 If a Supreme Court justice retires at any point during a Republican administration, it is more than likely that a conservative justice will be appointed202 who will uphold the current Republican agenda to abolish abortion rights.203 Second, a Republican President would almost surely pursue anti-abortion policies and strengthen public opposition to abortion. It is undisputed that “[t]he assault on women’s reproductive health is a central part of the Republican agenda.”204 For example, the Republican Party tends to support “personhood amendments,” which would declare that human life begins at the moment of fertilization, granting legal rights to human embryos and banning all abortions.205 Therefore, it is vital to acknowledge 198 Borgmann, supra note 148, at 311; Smith, supra note 151, at 403. Smith, supra note 151, at 403. 200 Borgmann, supra note 148, at 311. 201 See U.S. CONST. art. II, § 2. 202 See, e.g., Alan Wirzbicki, Election’s Winner May Shape Supreme Court, BOS. GLOBE, Oct. 1, 2012, at A1, available at http://www.bostonglobe.com/news/politics/ 2012/09/30/supreme-court-could-reshaped-next-four-years/0UfIGTSjcQFXZKpbCmrQ0H/ story.html (“Republican presidents have made it a greater priority to appoint conservative Supreme Court justices.”). 203 See 2012 Republican Party Platform, WHITE HOUSE 2012, http://whitehouse12.com/republican-party-platform/ (last visited Nov. 7, 2012) (“We support the appointment of judges who respect traditional family values and the sanctity of innocent human life.”). 204 Editorial, Republicans Versus Reproductive Rights, N.Y. TIMES, Jan. 8, 2012, at A18, available at http://www.nytimes.com/2012/01/09/opinion/republicans-versusreproductive-rights.html. 205 2012 Republican Party Platform, supra note 203 (“[W]e assert the sanctity of human life and affirm that the unborn child has a fundamental individual right to life which cannot be infringed. We support a human life amendment to the Constitution and endorse legislation to make clear that the Fourteenth Amendment’s protections apply to unborn children.”); see also Erik Eckholm, Republican Presidential Candidates Embrace Granting Legal Rights to Human Embryos, N.Y. TIMES (Dec. 22, 2011, 1:31 PM), http://thecaucus.blogs.nytimes.com/2011/12/22/republican-presidentialcandidates-embrace-granting-legal-rights-to-human-embryos; Peter Hamby, GOP Platform Committee Approves Tough Anti-Abortion Stance, CNN (Aug. 21, 2012, 11:51 199 228 BROOKLYN LAW REVIEW [Vol. 78:1 that a Republican victory in presidential elections inevitably throws abortion rights into a state of limbo. V. SOLUTIONS TO TWIN REDUCTIONS For the reasons presented in Part IV, I again emphasize that the right to abortion is not the key to solving the moral and ethical dilemmas resulting from twin reductions. Rather, the unregulated field of IVF represents the true root of the twin reduction problem. The dearth of regulation regarding embryo transfer increasingly generates ethical problems. Therefore, the most effective solution is to limit the number of embryos transferred in an individual cycle. Recent studies have shown that, particularly as IVF techniques advance, a single embryo transfer is just as effective in achieving pregnancy as two or three embryos.206 However, doctors have a difficult time convincing patients of this fact.207 The longstanding idea is that the more embryos, the better the chances of a pregnancy; as a result, patients who are desperately seeking pregnancy are hesitant to accept that a single embryo could be equally as effective.208 Therefore, it is imperative that professional medical associations and doctors themselves promote this new idea. Patients need to become comfortable with the effectiveness of a single embryo, and this will only occur if the medical community proactively informs them of this preferred method. Additionally, another possible solution is enactment of actual legislation. But this poses a few problems of its own. First, IVF implicates the right to procreate, which is broadly protected and would be subject to strict scrutiny by the Court if it were infringed.209 Moreover, the United States is generally very deferential to doctors and patients in the area of medicine.210 Patient autonomy plays a big role in the relationship between the government and its regulation of medicine.211 Therefore, any actual IVF legislation would also clash with this traditional AM), http://politicalticker.blogs.cnn.com/2012/08/21/gop-platform-committee-approvestough-anti-abortion-stance/. 206 See Kim Carollo, One Embryo Better than Two in In Vitro Fertilization, ABC NEWS (Dec. 21, 2010), http://abcnews.go.com/Health/WomensHealth/singleembryo-transfer-effective-safer-double-embryo-transfer/story?id=12451473. 207 See id. 208 Id. 209 See generally supra Part II. 210 Garrison, supra note 1, at 1631-32. 211 Id. 2012] TWIN REDUCTIONS AND THE ABORTION RIGHT 229 notion. However, legislation may be permissible because IVF is a medical procedure and a state has a recognized interest in maintaining health and safety standards for its citizens.212 Since multiple pregnancies pose tremendous health risks,213 a state may be able to enact legislation directed at regulating the occurrence of multiple pregnancies. Moreover, since a single embryo transfer may be just as effective in producing a pregnancy, any infringement on the right to procreate would be minimal at best. On the other hand, perhaps granting more authority to professional medical associations, such as the American Society of Reproductive Medicine or the Society for Assisted Reproductive Technologies, would curb the abuse of embryo transfers. Currently, these associations have no authority to enforce their guidelines. If the medical associations had more power, this would likely help to minimize the market incentives for physicians to deviate from the guidelines. Regardless of which solutions society chooses to pursue, the most important objective is that changes be made to impact embryo transfers directly. Any of these proposed changes would only represent an initial step toward preventing future problems associated with multiple pregnancies. CONCLUSION The increasing availability of reproductive choices is a double-edged sword. On one hand, IVF has brought happiness and fulfillment to many people who struggle with infertility. On the other hand, with more choices comes the increased pressure of ethical and moral responsibility. Choices should remain and continue to increase, but there is also a need for the individual to wisely consider all aspects and consequences of their choices, given that they will impact the society in which we live. Twin reductions are an excellent example of how individual choices affect society. One person’s enjoyment of reproductive freedom, by engaging in IVF, can cause negative repercussions for women’s privacy and autonomy. It is easy for the public to engage in a general attack on abortion rights or to view individual instances of twin reductions and make negative judgments. However, the choices we make for ourselves about our bodies, our lifestyles, and our families are private. These 212 213 Planned Parenthood of Se. Pa. v. Casey, 510 U.S. 833, 857 (1992). See generally supra Part I. 230 BROOKLYN LAW REVIEW [Vol. 78:1 choices should not require justification. With reproductive freedom, we must never forget that whatever personal choice we make for ourselves can impact the existence of choices for others. Priyanka Shivakumar† † J.D. Candidate, Brooklyn Law School, 2013; B.A., The George Washington University, 2007. I would like to thank the Brooklyn Law Review editorial staff for their incredible patience and assistance. I am also grateful to my fantastic family and friends for their unwavering support and encouragement. I am indebted to Nicholas Jackson for being my invaluable sounding board and for continuously believing in me. Finally, I give my deepest gratitude to my mother, Jyothi, and my father, Shivakumar, for their unconditional love and selflessness throughout my life. Dedicated in loving memory of Matthew Phillips, a twin, who inspired me always to write. “Only Dust Remains[?]” 1 THE 9/11 MEMORIAL LITIGATION AND THE REACH OF QUASI-PROPERTY RIGHTS INTRODUCTION On September 12, 2011, at a quiet Pennsylvania field softened from days of rainfall, several families gathered for a private funeral service to bury three coffins in the ground.2 The approximately-six-foot steel boxes held not bodies, but the fragmented and unidentified remains of the passengers from United Airlines Flight 93 (United 93), one of the airplanes hijacked by terrorists on 9/11.3 United 93 crashed into this same field in Shanksville ten years earlier, killing everyone on board.4 Because the plane plunged into the earth at more than 570 miles per hour, only eight percent of the victims’ remains were ultimately recovered.5 Nevertheless, partial remains for each of the forty victims were identified.6 This fact brought closure to the families, who had reached a consensus regarding the final resting place of their loved ones’ commingled remains.7 Over the previous ten years, family members had attended countless memorials for the victims of United 93, but they could now declare, “This will be our last funeral . . . .”8 Nearly 300 miles away in New York City, the families of victims of the World Trade Center (WTC) attack lacked similar closure and accord.9 Unlike at Shanksville, the remains of more than 1100 victims had yet to be identified.10 For the last ten 1 WTC Families for a Proper Burial, Inc. v. City of New York, 567 F. Supp. 2d 529, 532 (S.D.N.Y. 2008), aff’d, 359 F. App’x 177 (2d Cir. 2009). 2 See Katharine Q. Seelye, At a 9/11 Site, a “Last Funeral,” N.Y. TIMES, Sept. 10, 2011, at A9. 3 Id. 4 Id. 5 Id. 6 Id. 7 Id. 8 Id. 9 See Anemona Hartocollis, An Unsettled Legacy for 9/11 Remains, N.Y. TIMES, Apr. 1, 2011, at MB1. 10 See Jo Craven McGinty, As 9/11 Remains Are Identified, Grief Is Renewed, N.Y. TIMES, Nov. 12, 2011, at A1; see also Seelye, supra note 2, at A9. At the Pentagon, 231 232 BROOKLYN LAW REVIEW [Vol. 78:1 years, the Office of the Chief Medical Examiner of New York City (OCME) has housed the unidentified remains in a temporary structure adjacent to its Manhattan office building.11 At that site, forensic scientists continue to test the remains for DNA identification. In 2013, however, New York City (City) officials plan to transfer the 9000-plus unidentified fragments to a repository located underneath the National September 11 Memorial and Museum (Memorial).12 There, OCME will have sole access to the facility to continue DNA testing, except for family members wishing to visit the site.13 Memorial administrators claim that the remains repository was established “[i]n response to overwhelming feedback received from families,”14 and that it “will provide a dignified and reverential setting for the remains to repose—temporarily or in perpetuity—as identifications continue to be made.”15 In the months preceding the tenth anniversary of the 9/11 attacks, the media reported a growing dispute between some of the victims’ families and City officials concerning the relocation of the remains to the Memorial repository.16 These families denounced the planned repository, arguing that they were neither properly notified nor given the opportunity to participate in the decision.17 Additionally, they contended that placing the remains within a museum would be disrespectful to the memory of the victims.18 In response, Memorial officials issued a statement summarizing their efforts to reach out to the WTC families regarding the repository.19 The release noted five of the 184 victims’ remains also were never identified. See id. All unidentified remains were buried at Arlington National Cemetery. See id. 11 See Remains Repository at the World Trade Center Site, 9/11 MEMORIAL, http://www.911memorial.org/remains-repository-world-trade-center-site (last visited Jan. 16, 2012) [hereinafter Remains Repository]. 12 See Hartocollis, supra note 9, at MB1 (outlining how the objecting families, “appalled by the idea of remains that could belong to their loved ones being turned into a lure for tourists, want[ed] them kept in a separate above-ground memorial that would be treated like hallowed ground”). 13 See Remains Repository, supra note 11. The repository “will not be accessible or visible to the public” and any family member wishing to visit the facility will be permitted access without having to pay an admission fee to enter the Memorial. Id. 14 Id. 15 Id. (emphasis added). 16 Hartocollis, supra note 9, at MB1. 17 See id. 18 See id. 19 See 9/11 MEMORIAL, SUMMARY OF OUTREACH REGARDING PLANS TO RELOCATE THE CITY OF NEW YORK’S OFFICE OF CHIEF MEDICAL EXAMINER’S (OCME’S) REPOSITORY FOR THE UNIDENTIFIED AND UNCLAIMED REMAINS OF 9/11 VICTIMS, available at http://s3.documentcloud.org/documents/97985/memorial-museum-response.pdf (last visited Oct. 20, 2012) [hereinafter SUMMARY OF OUTREACH]. 2012] “ONLY DUST REMAINS?” 233 that a committee purportedly representing the victims’ families, and assembled under the aegis of the Lower Manhattan Development Corporation (LMDC),20 had approved the repository proposal, and it detailed how, from 2002 to 2006, LMDC sought input from the families via direct mailings and public forums.21 The dissenting families subsequently requested the names and addresses of all the victims’ next of kin from the City in order to poll them about the proposed repository.22 After the City refused, they filed for injunctive relief in New York court.23 In Regenhard v. City of New York, the New York County Supreme Court sided with the City, concluding that releasing the names and addresses “would constitute an unwarranted invasion of personal privacy.”24 The court explained that the City had “no obligation to seek the families’ input as to where the unidentified human remains will be located—they are only required to disclose the information as to where the remains will be located.”25 The dissenting families appealed the decision, which is currently pending.26 Regenhard has significance beyond its seemingly exiguous purposes. In particular, this preliminary lawsuit raises a more fundamental and perhaps more difficult question: who is legally empowered to determine the final disposition of these unidentified human remains? Like most jurisdictions in the United States,27 New York has recognized the surviving next 20 In November 2002, LMDC announced that it was creating the Memorial Mission Statement Drafting Committee in order to “draft a mission statement that will be used to guide the development” of the WTC Memorial. Press Release, LMDC, Committees Created to Draft WTC Memorial Mission Statement and Program (Nov. 12, 2002), available at http://www.renewnyc.com/displaynews.aspx?newsid=e3f871881ed5-4193-943b-5fd10befab20. The starting point for the statement would be a preliminary draft authored by the LMDC Families Advisory Council. Id. LMDC said that the mission statement would incorporate “extensive public input . . . through Advisory Councils, public forums in every borough and New Jersey, a questionnaire sent to relatives of every World Trade Center victim, and thousands of emails sent to LMDC.” Id.; cf. Families Advisory Council Meeting Minutes, LMDC (Aug. 13, 2002), available at http://www.renewnyc.com/AboutUs/AdvisoryMeetings.aspx. 21 See SUMMARY OF OUTREACH, supra note 19. 22 See Anemona Hartocollis, Poll of 9/11 Families Is Sought over Unidentified Remains, N.Y. TIMES (June 2, 2011), http://cityroom.blogs.nytimes.com/2011/06/02/pollof-911-families-is-sought-over-unidentified-remains/. 23 See Order to Show Cause at 1-2, Regenhard v. City of New York, No. 109548/2011 (N.Y. Sup. Ct. Aug. 18, 2011). 24 Regenhard, No. 109548/2011, slip op. at 6 (N.Y. Sup. Ct. Oct. 25, 2011). 25 Id. at 7. 26 See Maria Alvarez, 9/11 Families Appeal to Judge on Victims List, NEWSDAY (Aug. 20, 2012), http://www.newsday.com/long-island/9-11-families-appeal-to-judge-onvictims-list-1.3916407. 27 See, e.g., Fuller v. Marx, 724 F.2d 717, 719 (8th Cir. 1984) (Arkansas law); Enos v. Snyder, 63 P. 170, 171 (Cal. 1900); Culpepper v. Pearl St. Bldg., Inc., 877 P.2d 234 BROOKLYN LAW REVIEW [Vol. 78:1 of kin’s right to immediate possession of the deceased’s body for preservation and burial as a legally protected interest since as early as 1857.28 Often referred to as a “quasi-property right,”29 or alternatively as the “right of sepulcher,” this common-law creation vests something less than full ownership in the next of kin “to choose and control the burial, cremation, or other final disposition of a dead human body.”30 Under New York law, the next of kin has the right to receive the body once the coroner’s office has concluded its statutorily-authorized investigative duties.31 However, whether the quasi-property right extends to unidentified remains possessed by the medical examiner upon completion of its responsibilities remains unsettled.32 The primary question this note seeks to answer is whether the New York quasi-property right attaches to the commingled and yet-to-be-identified remains of WTC victims. While the answer to this question may appear trivial in light of 877, 880 (Co. 1994); Dunahoo v. Bess, 200 So. 541, 542 (Fla. 1941); Louisville & N. R. Co. v. Wilson, 51 S.E. 24, 26-27 (Ga. 1905); Beam v. Cleveland, C., C. & St. L. Ry. Co., 97 Ill. App. 24, 28 (App. Ct. 1901); Anderson v. Acheson, 110 N.W. 335, 336 (Iowa 1907); Blanchard v. Brawley, 75 So. 2d 891, 893 (La. App. 1st Cir. 1954); Radomer Russ-Pol Unterstitzunf Verein v. Posner, 4 A.2d 743, 747 (Md. 1939); Weld v. Walker, 130 Mass. 422, 423 (1881); Doxtator v. Chicago & W.M. Ry. Co., 79 N.W. 922, 922 (Mich. 1899); Larson v. Chase, 50 N.W. 238, 238 (Minn. 1891); Spiegel v. Evergreen Cemetery, 186 A. 585, 586 (N.J. 1936); Barela v. Hubbell Co., 355 P.2d 133, 136 (N.M. 1960); Gurganious v. Simpson, 197 S.E. 163, 164 (N.C. 1938); Wynkoop v. Wynkoop, 42 Pa. 293, 301 (1862); Pierce v. Proprietors of Swan Point Cemetery, 10 R.I. 227, 242-43 (1872); Griffith v. Charlotte, Columbia & Augusta R.R., 23 S.C. 25, 32 (1885); Coty v. Baughman, 210 N.W. 348, 350 (S.D. 1926); Terrill v. Harbin, 376 S.W.2d 945, 947 (Tex. Civ. App. 1964); Smart v. Moyer (In re Estate of Moyer), 577 P.2d 108, 110 (Utah 1978) (holding that the right to a decedent’s body “is a property right of a special nature . . . [but] should [not] be regarded as an absolute property right . . . .”); Nichols v. Cent. Vt. Ry. Co., 109 A. 905, 907-08 (Vt. 1919); Sanford v. Ware, 60 S.E.2d 10, 13-14 (Va. 1950); Koerbor v. Patek, 102 N.W. 40, 45-46 (Wis. 1905). 28 See Correa v. Maimonides Med. Ctr., 629 N.Y.S.2d 673, 675 (Sup. Ct. 1995) (“The law is well settled that the surviving next of kin have a right to the immediate possession of a decedent’s body for preservation and burial and that damages will be awarded against any person who unlawfully interferes with that right or improperly deals with the decedent’s body.”); In re Widening of Beekman St., 4 Brad. Sur. 503, 530, 532 (N.Y. 1857). 29 Pierce, 10 R.I. at 238. 30 Kimberly E. Naguit, Note, Letting the Dead Bury the Dead: Missouri’s Right of Sepulcher Addresses the Modern Decedent’s Wishes, 75 MO. L. REV. 249, 250 (2010). 31 See Shipley v. City of New York, 908 N.Y.S.2d 425, 427-32 (App. Div. 2010). 32 See, e.g., WTC Families for a Proper Burial, Inc. v. City of New York, 567 F. Supp. 2d 529, 537 (S.D.N.Y. 2008) (finding that “[n]o case has extended . . . a right to an undifferentiated mass of dirt that may or may not contain undetectable traces of human remains not identifiable to any particular human being”), aff’d, 359 F. App’x 177 (2d Cir. 2009); Comite en Memoria del Vuelo 587 Inc. v. Hirsch, No. 100382/2005, slip op. at 3 (N.Y. Sup. Ct. Apr. 26, 2005) (noting that no New York State “case, statute, rule or regulation . . . deals specifically with a situation where human remains are unable to be identified or are identified in increments”). 2012] “ONLY DUST REMAINS?” 235 the extraordinary facts of the Memorial case,33 the issue is not novel. The families of the American Airlines Flight 58734 crash victims litigated this very issue, but New York law failed to provide these families with a mechanism to decide how to dispose of the remains held by OCME.35 The disposition of unidentified remains also arose in the aftermath of Hurricane Katrina, and one commentator noted the “urgent need for . . . application and contemplation” of the quasi-property right in mass-disaster events.36 More recently, newspapers chronicled how the Dover Air Force Base mortuary disposed of military service-members’ cremated and unidentifiable remains by dumping them in landfills.37 DNA testing has “found increasing use as a means to identify remains after . . . mass disasters,” and “[s]uccessful identifications have been made in recent years following aircraft crashes and for misplaced crematory corpses.”38 Therefore, an analysis of the Memorial litigation carries implications extending far beyond the unique facts of the case. For the time being, OCME has the right to possess the remains indefinitely while it continues DNA testing. As 33 For purposes of this note, in order to avoid confusion with WTC Families, a 2008 case in S.D.N.Y., I will refer to the current dispute over the relocation of the WTC victims remains as the “Memorial case” or “Memorial litigation.” 34 Flight 587 crashed into Belle Harbor, Queens on November 12, 2001 shortly after takeoff from John F. Kennedy International Airport, killing all 260 passengers and crew aboard the aircraft as well as five people on the ground. See Verified Petition at 2-3, Hirsch, No. 100382/2005; see also Amy Z. Mundorff, Anthropologist-Directed Triage: Three Distinct Mass Fatality Events Involving Fragmentation of Human Remains, in RECOVERY, ANALYSIS, AND IDENTIFICATION OF COMMINGLED HUMAN REMAINS 123, 126 (B. Adams & J. Byrd eds., 2008). 35 See Hirsch, No. 100382/2005, slip op. at 3. 36 Sarah Tomkins, Priam’s Lament: The Intersection of Law and Morality in the Right to Burial and Its Need for Recognition in Post-Katrina New Orleans, 12 UDC/DCSL L. REV. 93, 94 (2009); see also Laura Maggi, Katrina Dead Interred at New Memorial, TIMES-PICAYUNE (Aug. 29, 2008), http://www.nola.com/news/index.ssf/2008/08/ katrina_dead_interred_at_new_m.html. 37 See Craig Whitlock & Mary Pat Flaherty, Hundreds of Troops’ Ashes Put in Landfill, WASH. POST, Dec. 7, 2011, at A1, available at http://www.washingtonpost.com/ world/national-security/air-force-dumped-ashes-of-more-troops-in-va-landfill-thanacknowledged/2011/12/07/gIQAT8ybdO_print.html. 38 C.H. Brenner & B.S. Weir, Issues and Strategies in the DNA Identification of World Trade Center Victims, 63 THEORETICAL POPULATION BIOLOGY 173, 173 (2003) (citations omitted); see also Dorothy Nelkin & Lori Andrews, Do the Dead Have Interests? Policy Issues for Research After Life, 24 AM. J.L. & MED. 261, 285 (1998) (describing a California case where “[t]he emotional distress of relatives was also at issue in . . . a 1991 class action against mortuaries, funeral homes and crematoriums that had handled as many as 16,000 bodies”). For additional information on the 1991 class action case, see Suit Says UCLA Medical School Illegally Disposed of Bodies, L.A. TIMES, Nov. 1, 1996, at 4, available at http://articles.latimes.com/1996-11-01/local/me60189_1_body-program. 236 BROOKLYN LAW REVIEW [Vol. 78:1 discussed below, improvements in forensic DNA analysis have enabled OCME to identify WTC victims in ways that were impossible ten years ago.39 It is conceivable that OCME will eventually be able to identify remains for most, and possibly all, of the WTC victims.40 Nevertheless, thousands of fragments will likely never be identified. If and when the medical examiner terminates DNA testing, some entity, individual, or collection of individuals will have to decide what to do with the residual remains. As the dispute over the Memorial repository indicates, the WTC families care deeply about the final disposition of their loved ones’ remains, and some have been willing to litigate the issue. This note contends that in situations like the Memorial case, where the next of kin claim a quasi-property right over commingled and unidentified remains, the complex web of New York common and statutory law relegates the remains to a state of legal limbo. The next of kin are able to claim or waive their rights to any remains identified by OCME in the future, but they cannot assert their quasi-property rights to immediate possession of these remains until they are affirmatively identified. At the same time, OCME, which ostensibly possesses the right to dispose of unidentified human remains, is unlikely to do so while claims are outstanding. Consequently, any residual remains will persist as OCME laboratory specimens in perpetuity, subject of course to further advances in DNA testing. It certainly appears, as one participant in this dispute has lamented, that “since unidentified remains potentially belong to all the families, they belong to none.”41 Though no perfect solution exists, legislators need not acquiesce to the status quo. New York City law should be modified to establish standards and procedures to ensure mandatory repatriation and consultation with the next of kin when determining how commingled and unidentified remains should be put to rest. Part I of this note will briefly summarize recent advances in forensic DNA analysis to demonstrate that, inevitably, the City will have to grapple with who controls the WTC residual remains’ final disposition. Part II will evaluate current New York law governing the disposition of human remains, concluding that it relegates unidentified remains to a 39 See infra Part I. See infra Part I. Chip Colwell-Chanthaphonh & Alice M. Greenwald, “The Disappeared”: Power over the Dead in the Aftermath of 9/11, 27 ANTHROPOLOGY TODAY, June 2011, at 6. 40 41 2012] “ONLY DUST REMAINS?” 237 state of legal limbo. Part III will then survey the origins, underpinnings, and scope of the modern quasi-property right, concluding that the Memorial case has highlighted the outer boundary of the right: DNA identification. Finally, this note recommends that New York City modify its laws governing the disposition of human remains. Specifically, the City should look to repatriation of Native American remains under the Native American Graves Protection and Repatriation Act,42 a federal statute that endeavors to resolve analogous collective disputes over unidentified human remains. I. ADVANCES IN FORENSIC DNA ANALYSIS HAVE IMPROVED THE PROSPECT OF IDENTIFYING REMAINS FOR MOST OF THE WORLD TRADE CENTER VICTIMS On September 11, 2001, 2753 people perished at the World Trade Center after terrorists flew two commercial jets into the towers.43 In the aftermath, “the Mayor of New York City directed [OCME] to do everything humanly possible to identify every fragment of human remains.”44 Given the unprecedented nature of the WTC disaster with respect to the volume and condition of the remains,45 forensic DNA analysis constituted the most efficacious means to identify the victims.46 The vast majority of the victims were fragmented by the towers’ collapse, which amalgamated body parts with the steel, concrete, and glass of the destroyed 42 25 U.S.C. §§ 3001-3013 (2006). OFFICE OF THE CHIEF MED. EXAMINER, WORLD TRADE CENTER OPERATIONAL STATISTICS (last updated Oct. 16, 2012) [hereinafter WTC OPERATIONAL STATISTICS] (on file with the author). While some sources vary on the total fatalities and other statistics, this note uses OCME’s official tabulations unless otherwise noted. 44 Glenn R. Schmitt, Introduction to Excerpts from Lessons Learned from 9/11: DNA Identification in Mass Fatality Incidents, 1 S. NEW ENG. ROUNDTABLE SYMP. L.J. 13, 17 (2006). 45 Leslie G. Biesecker et al., DNA Identifications After the 9/11 World Trade Center Attack, 310 SCIENCE 1122, 1122 (2005). 46 Robert Shaler & Thomas J. Bode, DNA Identification of the Missing After the WTC Attacks: A Cooperative Public/Private Effort, FORENSIC MAG., Aug.-Sept. 2011, available at http://www.forensicmag.com/article/dna-identification-missing-afterwtc-attacks-cooperative-publicprivate-effort; see also Brenner & Weir, supra note 38, at 177 (noting that “[i]n most cases little but DNA [could] possibly be used to identify [WTC victims]”). These predictions proved prescient as 88% of the 999 victims identified by a “single modality” were identified by DNA. WTC OPERATIONAL STATISTICS, supra note 43. Nearly “one-third of all the decedents (over half of those ultimately identified) would not have been identified” but for DNA analysis. James R. Gill et al., The 9/11 Attacks: The Medicolegal Investigation of the World Trade Center Fatalities, 6 FORENSIC PATHOLOGY REVS. 181, 186 (2011). 43 238 BROOKLYN LAW REVIEW [Vol. 78:1 buildings.47 Some victims “disappeared without a trace”48 as body parts were exposed to 1000°C fires that took over three months to squelch, leaving them nearly indistinguishable from inorganic material.49 These problems were compounded by OCME’s understandable unpreparedness for a disaster of this magnitude.50 Initial estimates placed the number of potential victims at 20,000.51 Accordingly, Dr. Charles Hirsch, the Chief Medical Examiner, made the unprecedented decision “to DNAtest every piece of human remains no matter how small,” ensuring that no potential victims would be overlooked.52 Expectations that OCME scientists would promptly identify all WTC victims by DNA testing proved to be misguided.53 The extreme conditions at the WTC site quickly deteriorated the quality of DNA profiles, overwhelming contemporary scientific capabilities.54 Moreover, the remains 47 Biesecker et al., supra note 45, at 1122; Zoran M. Budimlija et al., World Trade Center Human Identification Project: Experiences with Individual Body Identification Cases, 44 CROATIAN MED. J. 259, 259 (2003) (cataloguing “the impact of the aircrafts and abnormally high temperatures due to the fuel explosion, collapse of the towers, prolonged exposure to different weather conditions, fire and water, as well as the use of heavy equipment in the recovery effort”); Mitchell M. Holland et al., Development of a Quality, High Throughput DNA Analysis Procedure for Skeletal Samples to Assist with the Identification of Victims from the World Trade Center Attacks, 44 CROATIAN MED. J. 264, 265 (2003). 48 Brenner & Weir, supra note 38, at 177; see also WTC Families for a Proper Burial, Inc. v. City of New York, 567 F. Supp. 2d 529, 531 (S.D.N.Y. 2008) (“Approximately 1,100 of the victims perished without leaving a trace, utterly consumed into incorporeality by the intense, raging fires, or pulverized into dust by the massive tons of collapsing concrete and steel.”). 49 Biesecker et al., supra note 45, at 1122. Moreover, tissue fragments recovered many months after the collapse had deteriorated due to “bacterial and other processes . . . .” Id. 50 See Shaler & Bode, supra note 46 (noting that despite its status as the “largest forensic DNA laboratory in the United States,” the operation “would require nonexistent resources . . . .”); Biesecker et al., supra note 45, at 1123 (describing how “OCME recognized that its computers and data communication facilities were inadequate for this project”). 51 Gill et al., supra note 46, at 183. 52 Mundorff, supra note 34, at 128. The decision was unprecedented because “[i]vestigators in mass fatality events generally do not DNA-test every fragment . . . .” Id. 53 See David W. Chen, New Test for 9/11 ID’s is Moving Much Slower than Scientists Hoped, N.Y. TIMES, Nov. 30, 2002, at B3 (noting how the identification “process has unfolded far more slowly than anticipated” and OCME had not yet identified remains for fifty-one percent of the victims in November 2002). In April of 2002, OCME had identified 968 decedents after examining 19,219 remains and by December 2008, 657 additional victims had been identified. Gill et al., supra note 46, at 186. 54 Shaler & Bode, supra note 46; see also Biesecker et al., supra note 45, at 1122 (noting that the conditions at WTC “made it difficult to isolate and genotype the DNA from the specimens”); Amy Z. Mundorff et al., DNA Preservation in Skeletal Elements from the World Trade Center Disaster: Recommendations for Mass Fatality Management, 54 J. FORENSIC SCIENCE 739, 739 (2009) (describing how “UV radiation, 2012] “ONLY DUST REMAINS?” 239 consisted of thousands of bone fragments and, according to one OCME director, a “robust, reliable, and rapid method for extracting DNA from bones did not exist” in 2001.55 As of this writing, fortyone percent of the victims have yet to be even partially identified.56 OCME currently possesses over 8500 unidentified human remains57 out of the nearly 22,000 fragments recovered after the towers’ collapse.58 Recent advances in forensic science, however, have brought the original forecast closer to fruition.59 Over time and in cooperation with private industry, OCME has developed the ability to extract viable DNA samples from bone fragments.60 Ten years later, scientists at OCME continue the laborious work of evaluating hundreds of remains per month “in an ongoing attempt to match a name to each piece of human remains recovered from [the WTC].”61 Whereas OCME scientists could only evaluate a few fragments per day ten years ago, improved technology now allows them to analyze several hundred per month.62 Better techniques for extracting viable DNA from miniscule and degraded samples led OCME to generate thirty-two new identifications in the last five years.63 OCME scientists “have utilized these advances to go back and retest inconclusive fragments every few years, often succeeding where they had previously failed.”64 The improved technology has borne fruit. In May and August 2011, OCME successfully matched DNA for two previously unidentified WTC victims.65 humidity, moisture, heat, fire, and mold . . . contributed to the advanced state of decomposition of the remains and to the degradation of DNA”). 55 Shaler & Bode, supra note 46. 56 WTC OPERATIONAL STATISTICS, supra note 43. 57 The remains consist of “mainly bone fragments but also tissue that has been dehydrated for preservation.” Hartocollis, supra note 9. 58 See WTC OPERATIONAL STATISTICS, supra note 43. 59 See N.Y. Univ. Langone Med. Ctr., A Decade Later, the Office of the Chief Medical Examiner Upholds Its Promise to Identify Every Remnant of the Lives Lost in the World Trade Center Attacks, NEWS & VIEWS, July-Aug. 2011, at 5 [hereinafter A Decade Later]. 60 Id. at 5; see also Shaler & Bode, supra note 46 (discussing the development and efficacy of coordination with private companies like Bode Technology Group, Celera and Orchid Biosciences to develop ever-refined techniques to analyze DNA in bone fragments). 61 A Decade Later, supra note 59, at 5. 62 Id. 63 Id. For a comprehensive review of the scientific processes utilized in the WTC identification effort, see generally Mundorff et al., supra note 54; Biesecker et al., supra note 45; Holland et al., supra note 47; Budimlija et al., supra note 47. 64 A Decade Later, supra note 59, at 5. 65 See Al Baker, A 9/11 Victim Is Identified by the Medical Examiner, N.Y. TIMES (Aug. 23, 2011, 5:53 PM), http://cityroom.blogs.nytimes.com/2011/08/23/a-911-victim-isidentified-by-the-medical-examiner/; Anemona Hartocollis, First New Identification of 9/11 240 BROOKLYN LAW REVIEW [Vol. 78:1 OCME now identifies remains on a daily basis.66 Thus, improvements in DNA typing raise the prospect that most, if not all, WTC victims will be partially identified.67 It now appears, however, that the original goal of identifying every single fragment has yielded to a more feasible target: identifying each victim.68 Indeed, OCME has publicly committed itself to testing the remains until every victim has been identified.69 This shift accords with previous mass-disaster identification efforts, where “the standard of care is to identify each victim, not each remain.”70 Thus, the families and the City must confront the nearcertain prospect that DNA testing will end without identifying all of the WTC remains. Consequently, the question arises as to who should determine the final disposition of any residual human remains. In Part II, this note examines the existing legal framework in New York concerning the disposition of human remains in order to determine which party holds the power to decide this question. II. NEW YORK LAW HAS NOT ADEQUATELY ADDRESSED THE DISPOSITION OF UNIDENTIFIED REMAINS In dismissing the Regenhard petition,71 the New York County Supreme Court wrote that neither the City nor OCME was obligated “to seek the families’ input as to where the unidentified remains will be located—they are only required to disclose the information as to where the remains will be located.”72 The court, however, cited no statute, regulation, or Victim Since 2009, N.Y. TIMES (May 12, 2011, 6:38 PM), http://cityroom.blogs.nytimes.com/ 2011/05/12/first-new-identification-of-911-victim-since-2009/. 66 McGinty, supra note 10, at A1. 67 A Decade Later, supra note 59, at 5. Dr. Charles Hirsch, Chief Medical Examiner recently stated: “This process is not time limited . . . . Ten years ago, we promised the victims’ families that we would never quit working to identify every last individual who died that day—and we’re going to keep that promise. It’s a sacred obligation.” Id. 68 See Brenner & Weir, supra note 38, at 177 (concluding that “there is no prospect of attaining a closed-system” and setting “a plausible upper bound for the eventual number of [WTC victim] identifications” at 2100). 69 See Gill et al., supra note 46, at 194; Hartocollis, supra note 65; Letter from Charles S. Hirsch, Chief Medical Examiner (Sept. 21, 2006) (on file with author) (“Recent advances in the technique for extracting DNA from bone . . . have provided us the opportunity to renew our efforts to identify your loved ones. We are working actively on World Trade Center identifications, and new identifications will be forthcoming.”). 70 Budimlija et al., supra note 47. 71 See supra text accompanying notes 23-26. 72 Regenhard v. City of New York, No. 109548/2011, slip op. at 7 (N.Y. Sup. Ct. Oct. 25, 2011). 2012] “ONLY DUST REMAINS?” 241 case to support that assertion.73 In the following sections, this note will analyze the few laws that exist concerning the disposition of unidentified remains to determine whether the Regenhard court was correct. A. Statutes and Cases Governing the Disposition of Human Remains Both New York State statutes and New York City municipal ordinances govern the authority and responsibilities of OCME.74 As one court has noted, “the statutory powers and discretionary authority of [OCME] are extensive.”75 Pursuant to the New York City Charter, Chapter 12, section 557 (Section 557), OCME is empowered to “provide forensic and related testing and analysis . . . in furtherance of investigations concerning persons both alive and deceased . . . .”76 Moreover, subdivision 557(f) grants OCME the authority to “perform the functions of the city mortuary . . . including the removal, transportation and disposal of unclaimed or unidentified human remains . . . .”77 Thus, OCME ostensibly holds the legal right to determine the final disposition of the WTC unidentified remains. Where human remains are identifiable, the statutory “person in control of disposition” is entitled to the remains upon completion of autopsies, DNA testing, or other authorized analysis.78 Absent testamentary direction by the deceased, New York Public Health Law (PHL) section 4201 determines the person in control of disposition.79 It codifies the common-law order of priority,80 beginning with the surviving spouse and 73 See id. N.Y. PUB. HEALTH LAW § 4200 (McKinney 2011); N.Y.C. R. & REGS. § 205.01 (2011). 75 Shipley v. City of New York, 908 N.Y.S.2d 425, 430 (App. Div. 2010). 76 N.Y.C. CHARTER § 557(f)(3) (Supp. I 2011). 77 Id. § 557(f)(2) (emphasis added). 78 See N.Y. PUB. HEALTH LAW § 4201(2)(a) (delineating “in descending priority [the persons who] shall have the right to control the disposition of the remains of such decedent”). 79 Id. § 4201(2). 80 See, e.g., Secord v. Secor, 18 Abb. N. Cas. 78, 81-82 (N.Y. Sup. Ct. 1870) (“In the absence of a testamentary direction, is it not better that the husband should bury the wife, and the wife the husband, than that the door should be opened to an unseemly contest between the surviving parent and the next of kin?”); Frank W. Grinnell, Legal Rights in the Remains of the Dead, 17 GREEN BAG 345, 347-52 (1905) (citing cases explicating the general rule that in the absence of a will, the right to determine burial falls to the spouse first, and then descending to the children, grandchildren, parents, and siblings). 74 242 BROOKLYN LAW REVIEW [Vol. 78:1 devolving to any surviving children, parents, and siblings.81 PHL section 4201 further provides that the “person in control of disposition . . . shall faithfully carry out the directions of the decedent to the extent lawful and practicable . . . in a manner appropriate to the moral and individual beliefs and wishes of the decedent . . . .”82 Should a dispute arise over the remains’ disposition, the statute dictates that it “shall be resolved by a court of competent jurisdiction” pursuant to an Article Four proceeding under the New York Civil Practice Law and Rules.83 A New York appellate court evaluated the interplay between OCME’s statutory powers and the quasi-property right84 in Shipley v. City of New York.85 In that case, an OCME medical examiner, while performing an autopsy, removed and retained the brain of the plaintiffs’ son and returned the body without informing the plaintiffs that their son’s brain was still in his possession.86 The parents sued for damages based on a quasi-property theory.87 In its defense, OCME contended that “the common-law right of sepulcher cannot infringe upon [OCME’s] expansive authority . . . to discharge its duties in the exercise of its professional discretion.”88 The court wrote that OCME’s “statutory powers[,] . . . [though] extensive[,] . . . [are] not unlimited.”89 The state law governing disposition, autopsy, and dissection of cadavers, said the court, “reflects [the] concerns for respecting the corporal remains of decedents and protecting the feelings of family members by strictly limiting the circumstances under which autopsies may be performed.”90 Specifically, PHL section 4215 “safeguards the rights of the next of kin to receive [the] remains for burial” once the “legitimate purposes of an autopsy have been satisfied . . . .”91 That is, under the court’s interpretation, section 4215 “implicitly acknowledges” the common-law quasi-property right to possess the remains.92 By 81 82 83 84 85 86 87 88 89 90 91 92 N.Y. PUB. HEALTH LAW § 4201 (2)(a)(i-v). Cf. N.Y.C. R. & REGS. § 205.01 (2011). N.Y. PUB. HEALTH LAW § 4201(2)(c). Id. § 4201(8). See infra Part III. 908 N.Y.S.2d 425, 429-31 (N.Y. App. Div. 2010). Id. at 427. Id. Id. at 429. Id. at 430. Id. (alteration in original) (citation and internal quotation marks omitted). Id. Id. The statute at the time read: 2012] “ONLY DUST REMAINS?” 243 mandating the return of the human remains, the statute “strikes an appropriate balance between fulfillment of the legitimate scientific and investigative duties of [OCME] and the recognition of the long-established rights of next of kin to receive and provide final repose to the remains of their loved ones.”93 Since the medical examiner in Shipley had no further legitimate need to retain the decedent’s brain, the court concluded that plaintiffs had a valid cause of action against OCME.94 Whereas Shipley involved the removal of an identifiable brain from a corpse, Comite en Memorial del Vuelo 587 Inc. v. Hirsch concerned a quasi-property action over commingled and unidentified remains.95 In Hirsch, which preceded Shipley by five years, the Comite en Memoria del Vuelo 587 Inc. (the Committee), representing the families of the victims of American Airlines Flight 587 (Flight 587),96 filed a mandamus action to compel OCME to bury the victims’ unidentified remains.97 OCME had identified partial remains for all 265 victims but could not identify 308 residual fragments through DNA testing.98 When the families discovered that OCME intended to inter these residual remains in a “nondescript common burial ground,” they objected vociferously. Instead, the families proposed that OCME bury the unidentified remains in a private cemetery chosen by the relatives.99 The Committee had held a meeting of family members representing 100 of the crash victims, who approved by majority vote a plan to entomb the remains at Trinity Cemetery in New York City.100 However, several families that did not participate in the vote objected and submitted a letter to OCME complaining that the vote was flawed.101 In response, In all cases in which a dissection has been made, the provisions of this article, requiring the burial or other lawful disposition of a body of a deceased person, and the provisions of law providing for the punishment of interference with or injuries to it, apply equally to the remains of the body after dissection as soon as the lawful purposes of such dissection have been accomplished. Id. (emphasis added) (quoting N.Y. PUB. HEALTH LAW § 4215(1)) (internal quotation marks omitted). 93 Id. at 431. 94 Id. at 427. 95 Comite en Memoria del Vuelo 587 Inc. v. Hirsch, No. 100382/2005, slip op. at 1, 3 (N.Y. Sup. Ct. Apr. 26, 2005). 96 See supra note 34. 97 Hirsch, No. 100382/2005, slip op. at 1. 98 See id. at 2. 99 See Verified Petition, supra note 34, at 3. 100 See id. at 5-6. 101 See id. at 7. 244 BROOKLYN LAW REVIEW [Vol. 78:1 the medical examiner’s office announced that it would not release the remains without either unanimous consent from the surviving next of kin or a court order.102 In its supporting briefs, the Committee stressed that it was not “seeking custody and control of the unidentified remains or that they be released to it.”103 Rather, it contended that OCME, as legal custodian, was required to transfer the remains to Trinity Cemetery as there was no longer any investigative reason to withhold the remains.104 OCME, claimed the Committee, had an “affirmative and non-discretionary duty,” under PHL section 4200,105 to ensure that the remains received a “decent burial within a reasonable time after the crash of Flight 587.”106 Since the families had already voted for the Trinity location, a “decent burial” consisted of complying with their referendum.107 In response, OCME justified its decision to delay disposing of the unidentified remains based on “continuous, contentious and significant dissent among groups of next of kin . . . .”108 Even so, OCME contended that it had no obligation to seek input from the victims’ families. Under the Rules of the City of New York, Title 24, subsection 205.01(d), OCME conceded, it would normally be required to release human remains to the next of kin.109 But in the case of unidentifiable remains, there were no identifiable next of kin for purposes of the statute.110 In this situation, OCME “maintains custody and control over the remains” and, accordingly, “it is within the discretion of OCME to dispose of the remains in an appropriate manner to be determined by OCME.”111 102 See id. See Reply Memorandum of Law in Support of the Application of Petitioner Comite en Memoria del Vuelo 587 Inc. at 2, Hirsch, No. 100382/2005 [hereinafter Reply Memorandum of Law] (emphasis omitted). 104 See id. at 2. 105 Hirsch, No. 100382/2005, slip op. at 1. New York Public Health Law Section 4200(1) provides that “[e]xcept in the cases in which a right to dissect it is expressly conferred by law, every body of a deceased person, within this state, shall be decently buried or incinerated within a reasonable time after death.” N.Y. PUB. HEALTH LAW § 4200(1) (McKinney 2011). 106 Hirsch, No. 100382/2005, slip op. at 1 (emphasis omitted). 107 See Reply Memorandum of Law, supra note 103, at 2. 108 See Respondent’s Memorandum of Law in Support of the Verified Answer at 3, Hirsch, No. 100382/2005. 109 Id. at 3-4. 110 Id. at 4. 111 Id. 103 2012] “ONLY DUST REMAINS?” 245 The court denied the petition and dismissed the suit on multiple grounds.112 First, the court held that the Committee lacked standing because it could not demonstrate that it was “the appropriate entity to act as the representative of the interests” of all the next of kin.113 The Committee’s Trinity Cemetery proposal, ratified by a majority vote of the representatives of only 100 victims, could not be said to represent the majority will of the representatives of all 265 victims.114 Furthermore, the court found no “safeguards” in place “to protect the interests” of the non-voting families.115 Any decisions about the remains’ disposition, ruled the court, required “direct participation” by the “appropriate” next of kin.116 The court also addressed the merits of the petition, holding that the plaintiffs had failed to state a legally cognizable claim.117 The court correctly noted, like in Shipley, that the pertinent statutes “make it clear that, if there were no further investigatory reason for [OCME] to retain remains of an identified decedent, the [medical examiner] is obligated to promptly release such remains . . . upon the demand of the decedent’s next of kin.”118 But the court distinguished an identified decedent from the remains in the case at bar: [N]either of the parties has cited (nor has the court’s own research revealed) any case, statute, rule or regulation which deals specifically with a situation where human remains are unable to be identified . . . . Under the current circumstances and apparently without regulatory or statutory guidance, the OCME has established a suitable procedure to obtain direction for the disposition of remains from the victims’ next of kin as they become identified . . . .119 The “suitable procedure” that the court referred to was OCME’s policy of providing a “Release Authorization” to any families wishing to claim remains identified in the future.120 The release “gave the next of kin the choice of claiming any remains identified in the future or authorizing the OCME to dispose of 112 The court dismissed the proceeding on three separate grounds. First, the Committee lacked standing. Hirsch, No. 100382/2005, slip op. at 2-3. Second, the Committee failed to join all necessary parties. Finally, the Committee failed to state a legal claim for relief. Id. at 2-4. 113 Id. at 2-3. 114 Id. at 3. 115 Id. 116 Id. 117 Id. 118 Id. 119 Id. at 3-4. 120 Id. at 2. 246 BROOKLYN LAW REVIEW [Vol. 78:1 such remains as deemed appropriate by the OCME.”121 Under such a procedure, the families were faced with the unenviable choice between assigning away their rights to the remains and waiting for piecemeal identifications conditioned upon advances in DNA testing. Had the Committee vote represented a majority of the 265 victims’ representatives here, under the court’s ruling the vote still would not have been binding unless every legal representative had participated. While the latter requirement supposedly safeguards the interests of all the families, it effectively precludes collective decisions over the disposition of unidentified remains. Paradoxically, because the court reasoned that “decisions to be made with respect to the interment of the remains of a loved one are so highly personal,” none get to decide unless all decide.122 In the Memorial case,123 OCME has likewise provided release authorization forms to the victims’ next of kin. The responses have varied: “Some families retrieve[d] new remains right away, conducting small ceremonies and reopening graves to bury them. Some [have] wait[ed] for years, and are still waiting, in order to collect them all at once. Families of about 150 victims have asked not to be notified at all.”124 Unless relatives inform OCME that they do not wish to be notified temporarily or permanently, they “will continue to receive calls for as long as [OCME], aided by advancing technology, makes identifications.”125 Two years after Hirsch was decided, the New York City Council amended Section 557,126 subdivision (f),127 thus granting OCME the authority to “perform the functions of the city mortuary . . . including the removal, transportation and disposal of unclaimed or unidentified human remains . . . .”128 The legislative record reveals that the amendments were viewed as mere housekeeping measures updating the New York City Charter to reflect responsibilities that OCME had 121 Id. (citation omitted). Id. at 3. 123 See supra note 33. 124 McGinty, supra note 10, at A1. 125 Id. 126 See supra notes 76-77 and accompanying text. 127 NEW YORK CITY, N.Y., LOCAL LAW NO. 53 (2007), available at http://legistar.council.nyc.gov/LegislationDetail.aspx?ID=447342&GUID=7EB32EF259DF-401E-889B-D8B96EBDBD1D&Options=ID%7cText%7c&Search=medical+examiner (follow “Local Law” hyperlink under “Attachments”) (last visited Oct. 30, 2012). 128 Id. The current Charter contains the exact same language. See N.Y.C. CHARTER § 557(f)(2) (Supp. I 2011). 122 2012] “ONLY DUST REMAINS?” 247 already been performing.129 In other words, the Council rubberstamped the proposed language without considering, or even contemplating, its scope or consequences.130 As the preceding analysis demonstrates, unidentified remains exist in a legal limbo. Until a fragment is identified, the families have no right to determine its disposition and OCME has no legal duty to release it. And under the black letter law, OCME may dispose of unidentified remains even where the next of kin wish to claim them.131 If the dissenting families end up litigating the WTC remains, the courts would have to determine whether Section 557 precludes the next of kin from claiming unidentified remains in OCME’s possession. Sparse case law exists interpreting Section 557, but in a prior case concerning WTC remains, the court suggested that the next of kin have no proprietary interest in unidentified remains, and thus no legal authority to determine the manner of disposal.132 129 See Transcript of the Minutes of the Committee on Health at 3, Council of the City of New York (Oct. 11, 2007) [hereinafter Health Committee Transcript], available at http://legistar.council.nyc.gov/LegislationDetail.aspx?ID=447342&GUID= 7EB32EF2-59DF-401E-889B-D8B96EBDBD1D&Options=ID%7cText%7c&Search= medical+examiner (statement of Joel Rivera, Chairman, Comm. on Health) (“This legislation would update the law to reflect changes in technology and increase responsibilities that [OCME] has taken on over time.”); Press Release, Office of Communications, Council of the City of New York, Updating Responsibilities of Office of the Chief Medical Examiner (Oct. 17, 2007), available at http://legistar.council.nyc.gov/LegislationDetail.aspx?ID=447342&GUID=7EB32EF259DF-401E-889B-D8B96EBDBD1D&Options=ID%7cText%7c&Search=medical+examiner (“The Council is also voting on legislation to amend the City Charter to reflect new responsibilities of the Office of the Chief Medical Examiner (OCME). Due to restructuring and advances in technology OCME has taken on new duties that are not reflected in the Charter, such as performing the functions of City mortuaries, and conducting DNA and other forensic testing. These will now be codified as formal responsibilities of OCME.”). 130 The only testimony the Committee on Health heard was from a single OMCE representative, who read from a prepared statement. See Health Committee Transcript, supra note 129, at 5-8. The only mention of unidentified remains in the statement was a description of how OCME was responsible for “transporting and storing the remains of unidentified people and unclaimed people. Id. at 6-7. After the testimony, Committee chairperson opined, “I think this is just a common sense process that we’re going through right now.” Id. at 9. He then opened the floor to the other committee members, who asked no questions. See id. 131 N.Y.C. CHARTER § 557(f)(3). 132 See WTC Families for a Proper Burial, Inc. v. City of New York, 567 F. Supp. 2d 529, 537 (S.D.N.Y. 2008), aff’d, 359 F. App’x 177 (2d Cir. 2009). 248 B. BROOKLYN LAW REVIEW [Vol. 78:1 The Precursor Case to the Memorial Litigation: WTC Families for a Proper Burial, Inc. v. City of New York Finds No Property Interest in Intangible and Unidentifiable Human Remains On September 12, 2001, the City began relocating the WTC debris to Fresh Kills, the inveterate garbage dump located in Staten Island, so that federal and local officials could begin the colossal task of scrutinizing the wreckage for evidence and human remains.133 The initial, ad-hoc process for prospecting remains by rake and shovel evolved over ten months to increasingly sophisticated screening mechanisms whereby 480,000 tons of commingled organic and inorganic materials were sifted through screens less than one-quarter inch thick.134 The miniscule pieces passing through these screens, referred to as “fines,” included cremated remains of WTC victims.135 Families of the victims earnestly believed that City officials had promised to segregate the fines containing human remains from the residual waste stored at the landfill, in order to accord dignity to the memory of the victims and ensure that the remains would ultimately receive a proper burial.136 In September 2004, however, several family members visited Fresh Kills and discovered that sanitation employees had been commingling the fines with household garbage and consigning the mixture underneath a layer of earth.137 After failing to convince the City to remedy the purported wrong,138 some of the families established a nonprofit corporation139 in order to effectuate a proper burial site for the fines. The corporation subsequently filed a lawsuit140 in federal district court to compel 133 WTC Families, 567 F. Supp. 2d at 532; Amended Complaint at ¶¶ 28-30, WTC Families, 567 F. Supp. 2d 529 (No. 05CV7243). 134 Amended Complaint, supra note 133, ¶¶ 31-40. 135 Id. ¶¶ 42-46. 136 Id. ¶¶ 47-49; WTC Families, 567 F. Supp. 2d at 533. 137 Amended Complaint, supra note 133, ¶¶ 51-53; WTC Families, 567 F. Supp. 2d at 534. 138 Amended Complaint, supra note 133, ¶¶ 55-63. 139 World Trade Center Families for a Proper Burial, Inc. was incorporated in 2003 and professed to act on behalf of nearly 1000 families whose loved ones perished at the WTC. See WTC Families, 567 F. Supp. 2d at 533 (noting that the nonprofit was incorporated “with the stated purposes of representing the bereaved families, retrieving the remains of 9/11 victims located at Fresh Kills, and providing a proper burial and resting place for the remains”); Amended Complaint, supra note 133, ¶¶ 5-6. 140 The Air Transportation Safety and System Stabilization Act of 2001 grants the United States Court for the Southern District of New York “original and exclusive jurisdiction over all actions brought for any claim (including any claim for loss of 2012] “ONLY DUST REMAINS?” 249 the City to reclaim the cremated fines, remove them from Fresh Kills, and establish a cemetery for their final resting place.141 In WTC Families for a Proper Burial, Inc. v. City of New York, the plaintiff families claimed that the City violated the Due Process Clause (DPC) of the Fourteenth Amendment, 42 U.S.C. § 1983, and New York State law “by depriving [them] of their rights over the remains of their deceased relatives, including their right to provide a proper and decent burial for their deceased family members.”142 Plaintiffs argued that their quasi-property rights to the victims’ remains were entitled to DPC protection under federal law. Neither federal nor state law, according to plaintiffs, distinguished cremated remains from an intact body.143 Accordingly, the families retained a proprietary right to the “body parts, bone fragments, small tissue particles and cremated remains” at Fresh Kills.144 Having assumed responsibility for the recovery effort, the City “owed [the families] a duty of reasonable care to insure that such recovery effort was properly done.”145 The City moved to dismiss the suit, contending that the DPC did not impose “an obligation to search and sift the WTC material in any particular manner.”146 In its briefs, the City argued that while no Second Circuit or New York State court had yet considered whether the quasi-property right in the deceased’s remains rises to the level of a DPC-protected property interest,147 the case at bar should nevertheless be dismissed because plaintiffs could not demonstrate that identifiable remains were present at the landfill.148 In other words, the family property, personal injury, or death) resulting from or relating to the terrorist-related aircraft crashes of September 11, 2001.” Pub. L. No. 107-42, 115 Stat. 230 (2001). 141 WTC Families, 567 F. Supp. 2d at 532; see also Anemona Hartocollis, Landfill Has 9/11 Remains, Medical Examiner Wrote, N.Y. TIMES, Mar. 24, 2007, at B3 (describing how “family members are trying to force the city to separate many thousands of tons of debris that they believe still includes body parts and other human remains from the landfill, and to create a formal burial place for them”). 142 Amended Complaint, supra note 133, ¶¶ 68-95. Plaintiffs also alleged a cause of action, inapposite for purposes of this note, for violation of their right to free exercise of religion because the City purportedly prevented the families from burying their loved ones according to their religious tenets. See id. ¶¶ 81-84. 143 Id. ¶ 3. 144 Id. 145 Id. ¶ 8. 146 Defendants’ Memorandum of Law in Support of Their Motion to Dismiss the Amended Complaint or in the Alternative for Partial Summary Judgment, at 3, WTC Families, 567 F. Supp. 2d 529 (S.D.N.Y. 2008) (No. 05CV7243) [hereinafter Defendants’ Memorandum of Law]. 147 See infra Part III. 148 Defendants’ Memorandum of Law, supra note 146, at 28-29. 250 BROOKLYN LAW REVIEW [Vol. 78:1 members, at most, could only prove that “the remains of some undifferentiated and unspecified victims of the WTC disaster” may have been commingled with the debris at Fresh Kills.149 Mindful of the families’ irreparable emotional anguish, the court nevertheless held that plaintiffs had failed to state a legally cognizable claim and dismissed the suit.150 The court recognized that New York common law grants the next of kin the right to possess, and determine the final disposition of, a decedent’s remains.151 The court, however, qualified that right as constituting something less than “a property right in the ordinary sense of the term . . . .”152 Rather, it “extends only as far as necessary to entitle the next of kin to protection from violation or invasion of the place of burial, and to protect the next of kin’s right to ensure a proper burial.”153 Moreover, the court found the quasi-property right operative only in cases where the next of kin claim possession over “identifiable, recoverable bodies . . . .”154 Neither the plaintiffs nor the court itself could find a case which extended “such a right to an undifferentiated mass of dirt that may or may not contain undetectable traces of human remains not identifiable to any particular human being.”155 Accordingly, the court concluded that “[w]ithout something tangible or identifiable, there is no property right.”156 And without a property right, the DPC claim must fail: [T]his case concerns a total and complete absence of identifiable remains of any identifiable person. And just as that crucial fact was fatal to plaintiffs’ Constitutional claims, it is fatal as well to plaintiffs’ state law claims . . . . [W]ithout identified remains of an identifiable deceased, there is no person, or part of a person, and there can be no right, to bury . . . . [P]laintiffs have no property right in an undifferentiated, unidentifiable mass of dirt that may or may not contain the remains of plaintiffs’ loved ones.157 149 Id. at 29. WTC Families, 567 F. Supp. 2d at 534. Id. at 537 (citing Colavito v. N.Y. Donor Network, Inc., 356 F. Supp. 2d 237, 243 (E.D.N.Y. 2005)). 152 WTC Families, 567 F. Supp. 2d at 537. 153 Id. 154 Id. 155 Id. 156 Id. (emphasis added) (citing Comite en Memoria del Vuelo 587 Inc. v. Hirsch, No. 100382/2005, slip op. at 3 (N.Y. Sup. Ct. Apr. 26, 2005)). 157 Id. at 541-42. 150 151 2012] “ONLY DUST REMAINS?” 251 WTC Families cited Hirsch for the proposition that there can be no property interest in unidentifiable remains.158 As precedent for that assertion, Hirsch is dubious at best. The Hirsch court merely concluded that no case law, statute, or regulation directly deals with a situation where OCME possesses yet-to-be-identified remains.159 The Memorial case presents an opportunity for the New York courts to reconsider whether Hirsch and WTC Families remain good law. The facts of the Memorial case are distinguishable from WTC Families in one major respect. There is no doubt that OCME possesses WTC victims’ remains, whereas in WTC Families, the court made a factual determination that “all human remains that could be identified, were identified. Only dust remains.”160 That is, the WTC Families court rested its decision partly on the fact that there was no concrete proof that the fines contained human remains at all. No such ambiguity exists in the Memorial case. Thus, the courts may have the opportunity to decide whether the quasi-property right embraces tangible and potentially-but-not-currently-identifiable human remains. While the courts can easily avoid settling this issue on any number of technicalities,161 this note argues that the courts, and ultimately the legislature, should directly confront this issue. III. THE QUASI-PROPERTY RIGHT IN CORPSES If the dissenting families are to succeed in challenging the City’s plan to transfer the unidentified remains to the Memorial repository, they must establish a legal basis for their authority to determine the final disposition of the remains held by OCME. That necessarily entails proving that the next of kin have a quasi-property right to the remains. Within the quasiproperty right: [T]he law has recognized in the kin having the duty of burial a right to possession of the body so that the duty can be carried out. This is a right to receive possession of the body immediately and in the same condition it was in at the time of death. There is also a correlative duty imposed upon anyone who may have the possession 158 Id. at 537. Hirsch, No. 100382/2005, slip op. at 3. 160 WTC Families, 567 F. Supp. 2d at 532. 161 See Brotherton v. Cleveland, 923 F.2d 477, 480 (6th Cir. 1991) (describing how courts “confronted with determining the nature of the [quasi-property] right have avoided characterizing it” as property and settled suits on other grounds). 159 252 BROOKLYN LAW REVIEW [Vol. 78:1 not to mutilate the body and to deliver possession. The right to possession of the body exists only in order to aid the accomplishment of the duty of burial and, therefore, should only be co-extensive with that duty.162 While a surviving spouse or relative may not have the same property interest in a dead body as he or she would in a house or automobile, he or she does have a proprietary right to exclusive possession of a corpse for the purpose of burial.163 In the proceeding sections, this note will survey the origin and scope of the modern quasi-property right to determine whether it embraces unidentified human remains. A. What Is Property? The meaning of the quasi-property interest in a dead body lacks consistency.164 According to one recent commentator, “The right to burial is an academic subject which could encompass several volumes . . . .”165 Proprietary rights to corpses are nonexistent in some jurisdictions but are expansive in others.166 Courts have held body parts to be both protected and unprotected as a property of sorts under the Due Process Clause.167 To understand what it means to have a quasiproperty right in a dead body, it is necessary to contrast the right from general conceptions of property. Under the prevailing scholarly view,168 property is viewed as a metaphorical bundle of rights, with each stick or twig in the bundle representing a right relative to the world at 162 B. Joan Krauskopf, The Law of Dead Bodies: Impeding Medical Progress, 19 OHIO ST. L.J. 455, 458 (1958) (citing Finley v. Atl. Transp. Co., 220 N.Y. 249 (1917)). 163 Melissa A.W. Stickney, Note, Property Interests in Cadaverous Organs: Changes to Ohio Anatomical Gift Law and the Erosion of Family Rights, 17 J.L. & HEALTH 37, 43 (2002). 164 See Elizabeth E. Appel Blue, Redefining Stewardship over Body Parts, 21 J.L. & HEALTH 75, 105-06 (2008) (noting that “currently, there is no consensus in the courts over how to treat bodies . . . [and] the law of the body remains in a state of confusion and chaos” (internal quotation marks omitted)). 165 Tomkins, supra note 36, at 94. 166 See Appel Blue, supra note 164, at 106 (finding that “American jurisdictions are today divided between the ‘no property’ jurisdictions and the ‘quasiproperty’ jurisdictions, with each side claiming a majority”). 167 For cases finding a Due Process Clause entitlement in a dead body, see Brotherton v. Cleveland, 923 F.2d 477 (6th Cir. 1991), and Newman v. Sathyavaglswaran, 287 F.3d 786 (9th Cir. 2002). For cases rejecting due process claims, see Fuller v. Marx, 724 F.2d 717 (8th Cir. 1984), and Lawyer v. Kernodle, 721 F.2d 632 (8th Cir. 1983). 168 See Stickney, supra note 163, at 42 (describing how property “has been broadly defined as consisting of a bundle of rights, an analogy the Supreme Court has employed a number of times” (citing Kaiser Aetna v. United States, 444 U.S. 164, 176 (1979))). 2012] “ONLY DUST REMAINS?” 253 large.169 “Property,” therefore, has a legal meaning distinct from its pedestrian connotation, and “has been described as an aggregation of a person’s legally protected expectations in regard to a [thing].”170 The right to a thing, commonly labeled an entitlement, is traditionally dichotomized as either a property right or personal right.171 The former defines an “entitlement to a certain thing (proprietary rights in rem) and the law protects this entitlement against the world as a whole.”172 The latter defines an “entitlement which is enforceable against a specific person or a specific class of persons (rights in personam), such as those which result from obligations like liability in tort or contractual entitlements.”173 The right to something in rem is stronger than an in personam right because it protects the “property” of the “owner” from a larger, indefinite class of persons.174 Legal niceties aside, property simply can be understood as rights that the government guarantees and enforces through the courts.175 Some of the most prominent rights include “the rights of possession, exclusion, use, and disposition, the right to enjoy fruits or profits, and the right of destruction.”176 For courts to recognize a property interest, “the party must have a sufficient number of the ‘twigs’ in the property bundle, though not the complete bundle. There is, however, no bright-line test for determining the threshold amount of ‘twigs’ necessary to establish a property interest.”177 But does the quasi-property right contain enough of these twigs for the WTC families to “own” the unidentified remains? 169 See, e.g., NILS HOPPE, BIOEQUITY—PROPERTY AND THE HUMAN BODY 49 (2009). Michael H. Scarmon, Brotherton v. Cleveland: Property Rights in the Human Body—Are the Goods Oft Interred with Their Bones?, 37 S.D. L. REV. 429, 429 (1991). 171 See HOPPE, supra note 169, at 70. 172 Id. 173 Id. 174 See generally THOMAS W. MERRILL & HENRY E. SMITH, THE OXFORD INTRODUCTIONS TO U.S. LAW: PROPERTY 9 (2010) (“Because the [in rem] right attaches to the object, rather than to particular people, it is universally binding on all who encounter the object.”). 175 See Roy Hardiman, Toward the Right of Commerciality: Recognizing Property Rights in the Commercial Value of Human Tissue, 34 UCLA L. REV. 207, 215 (1986). 176 Erik S. Jaffe, Note, “She’s Got Bette Davis[’s] Eyes”: Assessing the Nonconsensual Removal of Cadaver Organs Under the Takings and Due Process Clauses, 90 COLUM. L. REV. 528, 549 (1990). 177 Stickney, supra note 163, at 43. 170 254 B. BROOKLYN LAW REVIEW [Vol. 78:1 Historical Origin of the American Quasi-Property Right English common law, inherited by the American colonies, did not recognize a human corpse as property.178 Instead, a dead body was considered “nullius in bonis,” the property of no one.179 Authority over human remains belonged to ecclesiastical courts, which “monopolized the judicial power over the subject of burial . . . .”180 As a result of this jurisdictional peculiarity, family members had “no property interest in the body or ashes of an ancestor,” and thus no legal remedy “for disturbance of a corpse.”181 This led to an absurd result, whereby surviving next of kin could sue for things like defacing the headstone but not for exhuming the body from the grave.182 When the United States severed political ties with its colonial master, the states jettisoned ecclesiastical jurisdiction.183 As a consequence, states were free to develop autonomous property rules concerning corpses.184 Most repudiated the perceived injustices of the English system,185 first by granting jurisdiction over dead bodies in courts of law.186 Ensuing familial disputes led courts to reconsider whether someone could validly claim that a dead body was his property. Empowered with jurisdiction, several courts began to modify the no-property-in-acorpse rule.187 178 See Larson v. Chase, 50 N.W. 238, 238-39 (Minn. 1891). See id. at 239 (citing Lord Coke, Third Part of the Institutes of the Law of England, 3 CO. INST. 203 (1797)). 180 R.P. Taylor, Right of Sepulture, 53 AM. L. REV. 359, 359-60 (1919); see also Pettigrew v. Pettigrew, 56 A. 878 (Pa. 1904); Pierce v. Proprietors of Swan Point Cemetery, 10 R.I. 227, 238 (1872); Ritter v. Couch, 76 S.E. 428 (W. Va. 1912); Denay L. Wilding Knope, Comment, Over My Dead Body: How the Albrecht Decisions Complicate the Constitutional Dilemma of Due Process & the Dead, 41 U. TOL. L. REV. 169, 176 (2009). 181 Wilding Knope, supra note 180, at 175-76. 182 See id.; cf. In re Widening of Beekman St., 4 Brad. Sur. 503, 519-20 (N.Y. 1857). 183 See, e.g., REMIGIUS N. NWABUEZE, BIOTECHNOLOGY AND THE CHALLENGE OF PROPERTY 46 (2007); Tanya K. Hernández, The Property of Death, 60 U. PITT. L. REV. 971, 993 (1999); Knope, supra note 180, at 175-76. 184 See Stickney, supra note 163, at 41. 185 See Wilding Knope, supra note 180, at 176 (describing how American courts, “[l]acking ecclesiastic influence and disliking the potential injustice that the noproperty system created . . . , devised a way around the rule, and . . . assumed jurisdiction over dead bodies” (citations and internal quotation marks omitted)); cf. Pettigrew, 56 A. at 879; Pierce, 10 R.I. at 235-39; Ritter, 76 S.E. at 430. 186 Larson v. Chase, 50 N.W. 238, 238 (Minn. 1891). 187 Id. One court went as far as holding that “the bodies of the dead belong to the surviving relations . . . as property, and that they have the right to dispose of them as such, within restrictions analogous to those by which the disposition of other property may be regulated.” Bogert v. City of Indianapolis, 13 Ind. 134, 138 (1859) (emphasis added). 179 2012] “ONLY DUST REMAINS?” 255 [S]ome American courts [started] to recognize a right to possession of a body for burial, which they recognized as a property right of sorts. Eventually, recognizing that property might not be the best description of the right to a corpse for burial, some courts in the United States articulated a hybrid term they called quasi-property which gave families and friends a right to claim a corpse to effect a burial, but not for any other reason . . . .188 The judiciary, however, did not stray far from the English no-property rule; almost no early American courts seemed willing to view a corpse as property “in the common commercial sense of that term.”189 Instead, the courts came up with the concept of “quasi-property,” which gave the next of kin the right to “possession of a dead body for the purposes of decent burial.”190 C. The Quasi-Property Right Is an In Rem Property Interest The quasi-property right was not created in a vacuum. It is not a static concept but has evolved in response to “changed conditions of society” and scientific advances.191 The first incarnation, from the mid- to late-nineteenth century, arose from exhumations and internecine familial disputes over the burial locus.192 Ecclesiastical jurisdiction having been discarded, the courts placed a duty upon the next of kin to ensure that decedents were properly and timely buried. The courts, therefore, conferred a corresponding legal right upon the survivors in order to reinforce this obligation and protect 188 Appel Blue, supra note 164, at 106. Larson, 50 N.W. at 239-40. 190 Id. at 238-39 (holding that a widow “had the legal right to the custody of [her husband’s] body for the purposes of preservation, preparation, and burial” and could maintain a cause of action for the defendant’s unlawful dissection of the husband’s cadaver); see also Pierce, 10 R.I. at 242 (holding that although “the body is not property in the usually recognized sense of the word, [it may be considered] as a sort of quasi property, to which certain persons may have rights”); but see Bogert, 13 Ind. at 138 (holding that dead bodies belong to the next of kin “as property”). 191 Foley v. Phelps, 37 N.Y.S. 471, 473 (App. Div. 1896) (noting “the obdurate common-law rule has been very much relaxed, and changed conditions of society, and the necessity for enforcing that protection which is due to the dead, have induced courts to re-examine the grounds upon which the common-law rule reposed, and have led to modifications of its stringency”); see also Brotherton v. Cleveland, 923 F.2d 477, 481 (6th Cir. 1991) (explaining that “[t]he importance of establishing rights in a dead body has been, and will continue to be, magnified by scientific advancements”). 192 See, e.g., Bogert, 13 Ind. at 135 (concerning illegal interment of a dead body in a municipal cemetery); In re Donn, 14 N.Y.S. 189, 190-91 (Sup. Ct. 1891); Wynkoop v. Wynkoop, 42 Pa. 293, 293 (1862) (adjudicating an appeal challenging injunction barring appellant from relocating decedent’s remains to another cemetery); Pierce, 10 R.I. at 228, 243. 189 256 BROOKLYN LAW REVIEW [Vol. 78:1 the repose of the dead.193 Absent a legal right and remedy, the criminal law punished the intermeddler and the civil law taxed the vandal, but the survivor would be powerless to reinter the body.194 Thus, in In re Donn,195 the court explained that unless the next of kin received the right to possess and control “the body of their deceased relative, it might be left unprotected: and in case a corpse should be found in the possession of one who had invaded the grave and disinterred it, they would be powerless to reclaim it.”196 The courts could adhere to the noproperty rule because a corpse had no pecuniary value at that time.197 There was simply no other path for a dead body to take other than directly to the cemetery. Consequently, the courts saw no calamitous ramifications to labeling a body as a property of sorts, because it easily settled internecine disputes among families as to who should control death.198 The courts granted an in rem interest which they enforced through equitable remedies like injunctions.199 The late-nineteenth century, however, saw an “outpouring” of New York cases litigating rights to cadavers as a result of modern conditions and scientific innovation.200 First, the transformation of kinship and “loosened family ties” led to contests over control of the decedent’s remains, often between a man’s widow and his children.201 Second, cremation gradually became a preferred alternative to interment and the next of kin brought suits against the deceased’s testator challenging such a disposition of the body.202 Finally, the demand for human cadavers for medical research led enterprising individuals to 193 See In re Donn, 14 N.Y.S. at 190. See In re Widening of Beekman St., 4 Brad. Sur. 503, 522, 530 (N.Y. 1857). 195 In re Donn, 14 N.Y.S. at 189. 196 Id. at 190. 197 In re Beekman St., 4 Brad. Sur. at 529 (“[M]uch of the apparent difficulty of this subject arises from a false and needless assumption, in holding that nothing is property that has not a pecuniary value. The real question is not of the disposable, marketable value of a corpse, or its remains, as an article of traffic, but it is of the sacred and inherent right to its custody, in order to decently bury it, and secure its undisturbed repose.”). 198 See, e.g., Weld v. Walker, 130 Mass. 422 (1881); Wynkoop v. Wynkoop, 42 Pa. 293 (1862); Pierce v. Proprietors of Swan Point Cemetery, 10 R.I. 227 (1872); Secord v. Secor, 18 Abb. N. Cas. 78 (N.Y. Sup. Ct. 1870). 199 See, e.g., Weld, 130 Mass. at 423; Wynkoop, 42 Pa. at 302-03 (reversing lower court’s injunction ordering removal of the deceased’s body); Pierce, 10 R.I. at 24243; Secord, 18 Abb. N. Cas. at 78, 81. 200 In re Johnson’s Estate, 7 N.Y.S.2d 81, 85 (Sur. Ct. 1938). 201 Id.; see also Secord, 18 Abb. N. Cas. at 78. 202 In re Johnson’s Estate, 7 N.Y.S.2d at 86. 194 2012] “ONLY DUST REMAINS?” 257 engage in the lucrative trade of body snatching.203 In response to the cadaver trade, states enacted “anatomy laws” permitting medical institutions to dissect certain unclaimed bodies, thus mollifying the stringent “common law right to immediate burial intact” and relieving the public duty to effectuate a decent burial for all deceased persons.204 As “cases involving unauthorized mutilations” continued to increase, “courts began to recognize an exclusive right of the next of kin to possess and control the disposition of the bodies of their dead relatives, the violation of which was actionable at law.”205 In this context, the seminal case of Larson v. Chase delineated the quasi-property right quite broadly.206 There, a widow brought a civil action for emotional distress resulting from the defendant’s illegal dissection of her husband’s body, alleging interference with her exclusive right to control the body.207 The defendant argued that the suit failed to state a claim, since a dead body is not property and mental damages could not be sustained without a showing of “actual tangible injury to person or property.”208 The court reasoned that a person’s right to possession of a corpse “leads necessarily to the conclusion that it is his property in the broadest and most general sense of that term, viz., something over which the law accords him exclusive control.”209 Therefore, despite the fact that the widow could not claim damages for pecuniary loss resulting from the dissection itself, the court permitted compensation for mental suffering because it was a “direct, proximate, and natural result” of an interference with the widow’s exclusive right to possession.210 Likewise, in Foley v. Phelps, the New York Appellate Division held that a widow could maintain a civil cause of action for the unauthorized dissection of her husband’s body.211 The court wrote that “changed conditions of society, and the necessity for enforcing that protection which is due to the dead” requires New York courts to reconsider the “obdurate” common 203 See Nelkin & Andrews, supra note 38, at 263; Wilding Knope, supra note 180, at 177-78. 204 Krauskopf, supra note 162, at 459-60; Nelkin & Andrews, supra note 38, at 263. 205 Newman v. Sathyavaglswaran, 287 F.3d 786, 791-92 (9th Cir. 2002). 206 Larson v. Chase, 50 N.W. 238, 239-40 (Minn. 1891). 207 Id. at 238. 208 Id. 209 Id. at 239 (emphasis added). 210 Id. at 239-40. 211 Foley v. Phelps, 37 N.Y.S. 471, 474 (App. Div. 1896). 258 BROOKLYN LAW REVIEW [Vol. 78:1 law rule that there was no property interest in a dead body.212 While the court stopped short of grounding its decision in a full property right, it wrote: Irrespective of any claim of property, the right which inhered in the plaintiff, as . . . [the] nearest relative, was a right to the possession of the body for the purpose of burying it . . . . That right of possession is a clear legal right . . . . The right is to the possession of the corpse in the same condition it was in when death supervened . . . . If this right exists, as we think it clearly does, the invasion or violation of it furnishes a ground for civil action for damages. It is not a mere idle utterance, but a substantial legal principle, that wherever a real right is violated a real remedy is afforded by the law.213 Though the widow had a clear legal right to possess the body, there did not appear to be a remedy. Under the common law, someone who had a right to immediate possession of an item could seek redress of any number of theories, including replevin214 and conversion.215 But since the quasi-property right was something less than full property, these remedies were inapplicable. Instead of finding an in rem right in the next of kin, the court ostensibly found an in personam right sounding in tort law, allowing the widow to recover damages from the defendant for “mental suffering.”216 It is understandable that the court would come out this way. Besides the moral implications of labeling a body as property, it would be almost impossible for the courts to calculate damages for illegal dissections or autopsies since bodies had no readily identifiable value. If the widow here could not collect damages for emotional injury, she would, in effect, have no real remedy for violation of her right to possess her husband’s body. Larson and Foley are among the first in a long line of decisions upholding damages for what has come to be known as intentional infliction of emotional distress (IIED), based on an 212 Id. at 473. Id. at 473-74. 214 See 23 N.Y. JUR. 2D Conversion § 90 (2011) (summarizing that an action in replevin “is to provide a lawful remedy for one who is lawfully entitled to the possession of a chattel that is in the custody of another and who cannot simply take possession if, in so doing, a breach of the public peace will ensue”). 215 See Colavito v. N.Y. Organ Donor Network, Inc., 8 N.Y.3d 43, 49-50 (2006) (“A conversion takes place when someone, intentionally and without authority, assumes or exercises control over personal property belonging to someone else, interfering with that person’s right of possession.” (citation omitted)). 216 Foley, 37 N.Y.S. at 474 (analogizing the quasi-property right to the right to vote as “merely a personal right”). 213 2012] “ONLY DUST REMAINS?” 259 underlying quasi-property right to dead bodies.217 The quasiproperty right subsequently sounded predominantly in tort law, as opposed to actions like replevin or conversion for interference with a possessory right.218 As such, the policy undergirding the quasi-property right came to be understood as merely protecting the emotional sensibilities of the decedent’s family.219 Accordingly, this right has garnered considerable criticism. One commentator notes that this “dubious ‘property right’ . . . cannot be conveyed, can be used only for the one purpose of burial, and not only has no pecuniary value but is a source of liability for funeral expenses.”220 Another critic contends that the purported property interest is a “legal fiction to fashion a remedy” for sympathetic plaintiffs.221 Contrary to the scholarly criticism, the availability of emotional damages actually demonstrates how robust the quasi-property right is and the extent to which courts “have been jealous to protect and enforce” it.222 IIED damages became predominant in quasi-property suits not because the right is spurious or merely a “convenient hook upon which liability is hung,”223 but rather because the “property” at issue was a dead body. For moral and practical reasons, a corpse had no legal 217 See, e.g., Darcy v. Presbyterian Hosp., 95 N.E. 695, 696 (N.Y. 1911) (concluding that Larson “fully meets [the New York Court of Appeals’] approval”); Foley, 37 N.Y.S. at 474; Wilding Knope, supra note 180, at 177 (describing how the quasi-property right came to embrace “the right to refuse an autopsy, the right to prevent the removal of body parts, and the right to recover damages for any outrage, indignity, or injury to the body of the deceased” (quoting Philippe Ducor, The Legal Status of Human Materials, 44 DRAKE L. REV. 195, 229 (1996))). 218 Cf. Michelle Bourianoff Bray, Personalizing Personalty: Toward a Property Right in Human Bodies, 69 TEX. L. REV. 209, 228 (1990) (arguing that “American courts have evolved from protecting the family’s interest in the corpse through property law to contending that there is no property in a corpse and instead protecting the family’s interest through tort law, a position functionally similar to that taken by English courts”). 219 See Hernández, supra note 183, at 991-94. 220 Id. at 994 (quoting WILLIAM PROSSER, THE LAW OF TORTS 44 (2d ed. 1955)). 221 NWABUEZE, supra note 183, at 59 (“The concept of quasi-property is an ingenious invention by the US courts to help a deserving plaintiff. It is a legal fiction. It has no relationship with property in the ordinary sense of that word. The concept of quasi-property is a judicial contrivance that provides a legal basis for judicial remedy. It does not mean that a plaintiff has property interest in a corpse in the traditional sense of property right.” (footnotes omitted)); see also Ga. Lions Eye Bank, Inc. v. Lavant, 335 S.E.2d 127, 128 (Ga. 1985) (“It seems reasonably obvious that such property is something evolved out of thin air to meet the occasion, and that in reality the personal feelings of the survivors are being protected, under a fiction likely to deceive no one but a lawyer.” (internal quotation marks omitted)). 222 Danahy v. Kellogg, 126 N.Y.S. 444, 448 (Sup. Ct. 1910). 223 Carney v. Knollwood Cemetery Ass’n, 514 N.E.2d 430, 434 (Ohio App. 1986) (internal quotation marks omitted). 260 BROOKLYN LAW REVIEW [Vol. 78:1 market value.224 Accordingly, the courts were incapable of quantifying damages in the usual manner for violations like illegal dissections. In the quasi-property context, therefore, IIED constituted a surrogate theory whereby the courts supplanted more traditional claims for interference with a possessory right. As noted earlier, from the earliest inception of the quasi-property right in the American common law, courts adhered to the rule that “there is no right of property in a dead body.”225 The next of kin had an exclusive right to possess the body, but only for a singular purpose: burial. As a result, the right occupied an anomalous position between an in rem and an in personam entitlement.226 This was possibly a curious consequence of the common law system. As one scholar seems to suggest, “Whereas the civil law defines property as the aggregate of these expectations, the common law focuses on the separate legal interests. Under the common law, there is no requirement that an interest satisfy all of these expectations before it qualifies as property.”227 In other words, because American courts only needed to focus on the right to possession in contests over burial of dead bodies, they could happily ignore the inconsistency between granting a right to exclude while simultaneously proclaiming that dead bodies were not property.228 Several authors have argued that via the quasi-property right, the next of kin hold “the most essential sticks in the bundle,” including the right to immediate possession, to determine disposition, and to seek redress.229 Although some 224 See NWABUEZE, supra note 183, at 59. Danahy, 126 N.Y.S. at 447. 226 Compare Larson v. Chase, 50 N.W. 238, 239 (Minn. 1891) (finding that the right to immediate possession for burial is “property in the broadest and most general sense of that term, viz., something over which the law accords [to the next of kin] exclusive control”), with Foley v. Phelps, 37 N.Y.S. 471, 474 (App. Div. 1896) (analogizing the right to possession of a corpse with the right to vote, which “can in no sense be called a pure right of property . . . [but] is merely a personal right”). 227 Hardiman, supra note 175, at 218-19. 228 See Wilding Knope, supra note 180, at 176 (describing how American courts “circumvented the no-property rule by declaring that a decedent’s relatives did have an interest in the body for burial and interment purposes”). 229 Mary L. Clark, Keep Your Hands Off My (Dead) Body: A Critique of the Ways in Which the State Disrupts the Personhood Interests of the Deceased and His or Her Kin in Disposing of the Dead and Assigning Identity in Death, 58 RUTGERS L. REV. 45, 89 (2005); cf. Jaffe, supra note 176, at 553; but see Brian Morris, Note, You’ve Got to be Kidneying Me!: The Fatal Problem of Severing Rights and Remedies from the Body of Organ Donation Law, 74 BROOK. L. REV. 543, 547 (2009) (arguing that the quasiproperty right constitutes “nothing more than a right and corresponding duty to bury or dispose of a body”). 225 2012] “ONLY DUST REMAINS?” 261 twigs are missing, most notably the right to sell or commercially exploit a dead body, the quasi-property right “include[s] more twigs than some interests which have received protection.”230 Therefore, quasi-property should be considered an in rem entitlement and afforded the strongest legal protections. D. The New York Quasi-Property Right Whichever court has jurisdiction to entertain a lawsuit over the WTC victims’ remains,231 substantive New York law will govern whether the families of those WTC victims have a right to claim the unidentified remains.232 As the following subsections illustrate, under existing case law, the quasiproperty right also attaches to body parts, cremated remains, and even the identified remains of WTC victims. 1. The Quasi-Property Right Applies to Constituent Parts of Dead Bodies In Shipley,233 the court had to decide whether the plaintiffs could validly claim a quasi-property right to their son’s excised brain.234 After OCME completed its autopsy, it released the body to the plaintiffs without informing them that the brain had been removed and stored in the examiner’s office.235 The plaintiffs discovered what happened after they had already buried the body.236 The court held that OCME violated the plaintiffs’ quasiproperty right to exclusive and complete possession of their son’s body.237 Shipley therefore stands for the proposition that the quasi-property right embraces claims to constituent body parts removed from a corpse. The WTC victims’ unidentified 230 Jaffe, supra note 176, at 553. The Air Transportation Safety and System Stabilization Act of 2001 grants S.D.N.Y. “original and exclusive jurisdiction over all actions brought for any claim (including any claim for loss of property, personal injury, or death) resulting from or relating to the terrorist-related aircraft crashes of September 11, 2001.” Pub. L. No. 107-42, 115 Stat. 230, 241 (2001). 232 See Memphis Light, Gas & Water Div. v. Craft, 436 U.S. 1, 9 (1978) (explaining that “the underlying substantive interest is created by an independent source such as state law” (internal quotation marks omitted)). 233 See supra Part II.A. 234 Shipley v. City of New York, 908 N.Y.S.2d 425, 427 (App. Div. 2010). 235 Id. 236 Id. at 427-28. 237 Id. at 427, 430-32. See supra notes 85-94 and accompanying text for a review of the court’s analysis. 231 262 BROOKLYN LAW REVIEW [Vol. 78:1 remains are likewise components separated from a human body. But are fragmented pieces of bone and tissue analogous to an intact organ like a brain? Shipley moves a step in the right direction to support quasi-property claims to the WTC remains but requires further support. 2. The Quasi-Property Right Applies to Cremated Remains In the few New York cases where plaintiffs claimed a right to their relatives’ cremated remains, they succeeded.238 For instance, in Schmidt v. Schmidt, the court held that a widow was entitled to her husband’s ashes pursuant to her quasi-property right.239 The court directed her brother-in-law— who had possession of the ashes—to return the remains and awarded damages for emotional distress.240 Booth v. Huff also involved a suit over the right to dispose of cremated human remains.241 After the decedent’s wife, who was seeking a divorce at the time of her husband’s death, scattered his ashes in the Hudson River, his daughters sought damages for mental distress.242 They claimed to be the decedent’s lawful next of kin and that defendant interfered with their quasi-property right to bury the remains by “refusing to turn over the remains and disposing of them without notifying plaintiffs.”243 Although the immediate issue confronting the appellate court involved procedural questions, the court assumed that the quasi-property right inhered to the decedent’s cremated remains so that it did not have to determine who was legally entitled to them.244 3. The Quasi-Property Right Applies to the Identified Partial Remains of the WTC Victims One New York court has already ruled that quasiproperty rights attach to the identified remains of a WTC 238 See infra notes 239-43. 267 N.Y.S.2d 645, 646-47 (Sup. Ct. 1966) (citing Gostkowski v. Roman Catholic Church of Sacred Hearts of Jesus & Mary, 262 N.Y. 320 (1933), and Lubin v. Sydenham Hosp., 26 N.Y.S.2d 18 (App. Div. 1941)). 240 Id. 241 708 N.Y.S.2d 757, 758 (App. Div. 2000). 242 Id. 243 Id. at 759. 244 Id. at 759 n.3. 239 2012] “ONLY DUST REMAINS?” 263 victim.245 Caseres v. Ferrer concerned the right to receive partial remains of Michael Trinidad, who died in the towers on 9/11.246 Partial remains of his body were recovered and identified by OCME through DNA testing.247 Trinidad’s sister had petitioned the lower court for an order releasing the remains from OCME for burial.248 Meanwhile, the decedent’s ex-wife also claimed his remains.249 The Appellate Division affirmed the lower court’s ruling that the remains should be released to the decedent’s sister.250 Because the decedent died intestate, “the only people who have standing to seek possession of the remains for preservation and burial are his surviving next of kin.”251 Therefore, the ex-wife had no standing.252 Under the Rules of the City of New York, Title 24, section 205.01,253 the sister “was the next of kin qualified to receive his remains and to give instructions regarding the burial.”254 Thus, once OCME has affirmatively identified by DNA testing the partial remains of a WTC victim, the quasi-property right attaches and the statutorily defined next of kin are entitled to possession of the remains. IV. NEW YORK CITY SHOULD MODIFY SECTION 557 TO REQUIRE MANDATORY CONSULTATION WITH THE NEXT OF KIN CONCERNING THE DISPOSITION OF CLAIMED BUT UNIDENTIFIED HUMAN REMAINS As evidenced by Part II, the law governing the disposition of unidentified human remains lacks clarity. While Hirsch ruled that the next of kin could collectively determine the remains’ disposition, provided that all directly participate in the process,255 WTC Families concluded that unless remains are identifiable, the next of kin have no proprietary interest in them.256 Both cases stressed the lack of legislative or judicial 245 See Caseres v. Ferrer, 774 N.Y.S.2d 372, 373 (App. Div. 2004). Id. 247 Id. at 372-73. 248 Id. at 372. 249 Id. at 373. 250 Id. 251 Id. at 372-73 (internal quotation marks omitted). 252 Id. at 373. 253 See supra notes 74 and 81 and accompanying text. 254 Caseres, 774 N.Y.S.2d at 373. The sister qualified as next of kin because decedent never remarried, his children were under eighteen and his parents were not alive. Id. 255 See supra text accompanying notes 113-16. 256 See supra text accompanying notes 156-57. 246 264 BROOKLYN LAW REVIEW [Vol. 78:1 guidance on the issue.257 Moreover, although the text of Section 557 literally grants OCME authority to dispose of unidentified remains, the New York City Council rubber-stamped this language without considering, or even contemplating, whether that authority should apply in situations where unidentified remains have been claimed by the next of kin.258 The dispute over the Memorial repository reveals the dangers of this lack of clarity and guidance. A. The Memorial Dispute Revisited Both sides of the divide in the Memorial dispute agree that the families should have the last word over how to determine the final disposition of the WTC victims’ unidentified remains. Advocates of the repository plan argue that this has, in fact, already happened.259 The decision to return the remains to the WTC site, according to Memorial director Alice M. Greenwald, was “a direct result of an extensive consultative process led by [LMDC] . . . .”260 In 2002, LMDC invited the leaders of various 9/11 family advocacy groups to join its Family Advisory Council (FAC). FAC ratified the “idea of a repository” in the summer of 2002.261 Because LMDC selected representatives from the family advocacy groups to speak for all the families in a “republican manner,” a former member maintains, FAC represented the majority will.262 In contrast, the gravamen of the Regenhard lawsuit is that the families were not adequately consulted in decisions concerning the WTC remains.263 The dissenting families contend that they were not represented in the LMDC-led process. Instead, the families propose that a “democratic” process should prevail, in which a decision is fashioned in “consultation 257 See supra text accompanying notes 119, 155. See supra notes 126-30 and accompanying text. 259 See Patricia Cohen, Laying Unidentified Remains to Rest, in A Context for Terror, N.Y. TIMES (June 6, 2012), http://www.nytimes.com/interactive/2012/ 06/04/arts/design/museum-panel.html (quoting Charles G. Wolf, a member of the FAC whose wife died at the WTC); Hartocollis, supra note 22 (quoting a spokesperson for Mayor Michael R. Bloomberg, who stated that the repository plan “was driven by 9/11 family members and the Family Advisory Council”); Hartocollis, supra note 65 (reporting that Memorial “officials have said that the families were adequately consulted and that they believe the [repository] plan reflects the wishes of the majority”). 260 Colwell-Chanthaphonh & Greenwald, supra note 41, at 5. 261 See SUMMARY OF OUTREACH, supra note 19. 262 Cohen, supra note 259. 263 See Hartocollis, supra note 9. 258 2012] “ONLY DUST REMAINS?” 265 with all of the 2,753 families whose loved ones perished on 9/11.”264 To that end, they assert that the City should begin by “writing a letter to all of the victims’ families on this issue, holding a series of forums exclusively for them and inviting them to take a principal role in the decision.”265 Any final disposition, they argue, should represent the will of the majority of families.266 Although these seventeen dissenting families may ultimately represent the minority view with respect to the repository plan, their lawsuit raises serious concerns about the legality, and thus the legitimacy, of that process. Even assuming that the outreach efforts undertaken by LMDC were adequate and the repository plan did, in fact, represent what most family members wanted,267 it is still unclear where LMDC derived the authority to initiate and lead this process. LMDC is a “joint State-City corporation” created after 9/11 to “help plan and coordinate the rebuilding and revitalization of Lower Manhattan,” including the Memorial.268 It is a subsidiary of New York State Urban Development Corporation (doing business as Empire State Development), the state’s “lead economic development agency” whose mandate is to “provide the highest level of assistance and service to businesses in order to encourage economic investment and prosperity . . . .”269 Thus, a subsidiary of a corporate governmental agency charged with assisting business development in Lower Manhattan appointed members to a committee purportedly representing all 2753 victims’ families; the families then ratified the agency’s decision to relocate the remains to the Memorial, and all the while the only on-the-books law mentioning anything about unidentified remains unequivocally granted power to remove, transport, or dispose of them to OCME. It should not be surprising that, absent legislative guidance, such extra-legal measures were taken. This dispute, 264 Cohen, supra note 259. Id. 266 Id. 267 Such an assumption is far from ironclad. A reasonable observer could interpret LMDC’s summary of outreach to the families as merely providing notice of a plan LMDC and FAC had already decided to pursue. See SUMMARY OF OUTREACH, supra note 19. 268 About Us, LMDC, http://www.renewnyc.com/overlay/AboutUs/ (last visited Oct. 10, 2012). 269 About Us: Empire State Development Corporation, LMDC, http://www.renewnyc.com/AboutUs/empire_state_development_corporation.asp (last visited Oct. 19, 2012). 265 266 BROOKLYN LAW REVIEW [Vol. 78:1 therefore, should be seen as a clarion call to legislators to clarify the law governing the disposition of human remains. In the following section, this note suggests one possible solution to the problem of unidentified human remains, borrowed from the repatriation of Native American remains under the Native American Graves Protection and Repatriation Act (NAGPRA).270 B. An Apt Analogy: NAGPRA Mandates Consultation in the Case of Culturally Unidentifiable Human Remains As discussed earlier, the law as it currently exists relegates unidentified remains to a state of legal limbo in situations where next of kin claim commingled and unidentified remains.271 This note recommends that, at a minimum, the New York City Council revisit Section 557 to consider whether it really intended to grant OCME such blanket authority over unidentified human remains. The Council would then have three choices. First, it could simply decide that OCME should have absolute authority over unidentified remains and may dispose of them at its discretion. Second, the Council could modify Section 557 to require that OCME retain possession of unidentified remains indefinitely until advances in DNA testing allow for identification and repatriation. Finally, it could amend Section 557 to provide a mechanism by which the next of kin determine, to the fullest extent practicable, the disposition of unidentified remains. This note argues that the third option represents the best possible outcome. Though DNA identification represents a logical, bright-line threshold before the quasi-property right will obtain, it seems unjust for a government agency—and not the families—to determine the victims’ “final and most enduring state.”272 Indeed, the establishment of the quasiproperty right—though it is inapplicable here—was as much about the needs of the next of kin as it was about according dignity to the decedent: it assists the survivors “in coming to terms with the loss and their grief, particularly where the death was unexpected.”273 Consequently, lawmakers should 270 25 U.S.C. §§ 3001-3013 (2006). See supra Part II. 272 Clark, supra note 229, at 89. 273 Hernandez, supra note 183, at 991-92; Secord v. Secor, 18 Abb. N. Cas. 78 (N.Y. Sup. Ct. 1870) (finding “cogent reasons connected with public policy and the peace of families why . . . the possession of a corpse and right to determine its burial 271 2012] “ONLY DUST REMAINS?” 267 contemplate new standards and procedures for the disposition of claimed but unidentifiable human remains. In devising this new legal framework, the Council should look to the repatriation of unidentified human remains under NAGPRA as a paradigm. Congress enacted NAGPRA274 in 1990 to “remedy inadequacies in state law dealing with the protection of Native American remains and cultural objects.”275 Among various provisions, the statute and its accompanying regulations establish rules and procedures requiring and administering the return of culturally identifiable276 human remains possessed by museums or federal agencies to the appropriate Native American tribe.277 By passing this human-rights legislation, Congress was “concerned with treating Indian remains with dignity and allowing tribes possessory rights over human remains . . . associated with their tribes.”278 Implicit in NAGPRA is the idea that Native American descendants possess quasi-property rights in their ancestors’ remains.279 Additionally, in circumstances where the cultural affiliation of human remains cannot be positively determined by the agency or museum, NAGPRA nevertheless mandates their return if a claimant is able to demonstrate cultural affiliation by a preponderance of the evidence.280 The standard is not one of “scientific certainty”; rather, NAGPRA only requires a “reasonable connection” based on the evidence should follow the administration of the estate[] [including] proper respect to the dead, a regard for the sensibilities of the living, and the due preservation of the public health”). 274 25 U.S.C. §§ 3001-3013. 275 Aaron H. Midler, Note, The Spirit of NAGPRA: The Native American Graves Protection and Repatriation Act and the Regulation of Culturally Unidentifiable Remains, 86 CHI.-KENT L. REV. 1331, 1340 (2011). 276 Under NAGPRA, “cultural affiliation is the repatriation standard for human remains housed in institutional collections.” Id. at 1342. Cultural affiliation is defined as “a relationship of shared group identity that can be reasonably traced historically or prehistorically between members of a present-day Indian tribe or Native Hawaiian organization and an identifiable earlier group.” 25 U.S.C. § 3001(2). Federal agencies and museums that have determined a cultural affiliation between the remains and a lineal descendent, Indian tribe, or Native Hawaiian organization are required to return the remains upon request. 43 C.F.R. § 10.10 (2005). 277 See Jack F. Trope & Walter R. Echo-Hawk, The Native American Graves Protection and Repatriation Act Background and Legislative History, 24 ARIZ. ST. L.J. 35, 58-59 (1992). 278 Kimberly Self, Note, Self-Interested: Protecting the Cultural and Religious Privacy of Native Americans Through the Promotion of Property Rights in Biological Materials, 35 AM. INDIAN L. REV. 729, 752 (2011). 279 Id. 280 43 C.F.R. § 10.10(b)(1)(ii)(B). 268 BROOKLYN LAW REVIEW [Vol. 78:1 proffered by a claimant.281 NAGPRA as initially promulgated, however, left a glaring regulatory hole. It failed to address the disposition of culturally unidentifiable human remains in cases where a claimant was unable to meet the preponderance of the evidence standard.282 In 2010, however, the U.S. Department of the Interior added new regulations to “clarify NAGPRA’s procedures in situations involving culturally unidentifiable human remains.”283 Prior to these amendments, NAGPRA permitted institutions to retain culturally unidentifiable human remains indefinitely.284 Now, however, institutions are required to take measures to repatriate these remains. The crux of the new regulations lies in 43 C.F.R. § 10.11.285 First, subdivision (c) places an affirmative duty upon any museum or federal agency that cannot prove a right of possession286 to culturally unidentifiable human remains to offer to return the remains to the appropriate tribe or organization, in the order of priority delineated in the regulation.287 Second, subdivision (b) triggers a duty on the part of these institutions to “initiate consultation regarding the disposition of culturally unidentifiable remains” with tribes from whose tribal or aboriginal lands the remains had been recovered.288 Consultation is required after an institution receives a repatriation claim and before it offers to transfer control of the human remains.289 The aim of consultation is for the institution “to develop a proposed 281 Midler, supra note 275, at 1343. See id.; Zoe E. Niesel, Comment, Better Late than Never? The Effect of the Native American Graves Protection and Repatriation Act’s 2010 Regulations, 46 WAKE FOREST L. REV. 837, 839 (2011). 283 Niesel, supra note 282, at 839. 284 Midler, supra note 275, at 1331. 285 43 C.F.R. § 10.11. Section 10.11 “applies to human remains previously determined to be Native American . . . but for which no lineal descendent or culturally affiliated Indian tribe or Native Hawaiian organization has been identified.” Id. § 10.11(a). 286 To prove right of possession, the agency or museum must demonstrate that it obtained the human remains “with the voluntary consent of an individual or group that had authority of alienation.” Id. § 10.10(a)(2). Seeking to strike a balance between repatriation claims and the scientific community’s interest in studying ancient human remains, see Midler, supra note 275, at 1331, NAGPRA also contains a “scientific study” exception, which allows an institution in possession of culturally affiliated human remains to suspend the repatriation process if “such items are indispensable for completion of a scientific study, the outcome of which would be of major benefit to the United States.” 25 U.S.C. § 3005(b) (2006); 43 C.F.R. § 10.10(c)(1). Once the study is completed, the institution must repatriate the remains within ninety days. 25 U.S.C. § 3005(b); 43 C.F.R. § 10.10(c)(1). 287 43 C.F.R. § 10.11(c). 288 Id. § 10.11(b)(1). 289 Id. 282 2012] “ONLY DUST REMAINS?” 269 disposition for culturally unidentifiable remains . . . that is mutually agreeable to the parties . . . .”290 By incorporating these two concepts—mandatory repatriation and consultation—into Section 557 in the case of claimed but unidentified remains, the Council would potentially resolve several issues highlighted by the Memorial case. First, mandatory repatriation would switch the burden, requiring OCME to demonstrate valid cause to retain the remains, rather than requiring the next of kin to compel their release. Thus, it would significantly diminish OCME’s ability to withhold the remains indefinitely.291 Second, mandatory consultation would provide a legal mechanism, heretofore nonexistent, to facilitate collective decisions by the next of kin about the remains’ final disposition. Admittedly, NAPGRA’s standard—a disposition “mutually agreeable to the parties”—is vague. But the Council could find any number of dispositions sufficient. One possibility is that the majority will of the families should prevail. Another is for OCME itself to formulate a disposition based on discussions with the next of kin, subject to court approval.292 Perhaps even the FAC’s “republican” model293 may be appropriate, which transitions nicely to the final point: a procedure under the color of law in which all claimants are entitled to consultation confers legitimacy upon the proposed final disposition, whatever its form. According to one expert in the field of repatriation of Native American remains, the “most important stakeholders are the descendants and the best way to resolve conflict is through open and respectful dialogue.”294 Indeed, the dissenting WTC families have stated that they want only an equal voice in the decision over the remains’ disposition.295 If the repository plan received the approbation of a majority of families, they would accept that judgment—but “decisions made by those without authentic authority should not be binding.”296 290 Id. § 10.11(b)(5). To demonstrate a right of possession, OCME would have to point to a legitimate, authorized scientific or investigative duty, akin to NAGPRA’s scientific study exception. See supra note 286. Since, however, OCME could justify retaining claimed remains indefinitely by the simple fact that they are unidentified, the Council should contemplate some kind of “override” provision in which the families’ decision to end DNA testing would trump OCME’s desire to continue it. 292 A judicial inquiry into whether a disposition is “fair, reasonable and adequate,” akin to class action settlements, comes to mind. See generally FED. R. CIV. P. 23(e). 293 See supra text accompanying note 262. 294 Cohen, supra note 259. 295 Colwell-Chanthaphonh & Greenwald, supra note 41, at 5. 296 Cohen, supra note 259. 291 270 BROOKLYN LAW REVIEW [Vol. 78:1 CONCLUSION No one but the Creator knows whose remains are among these remains and whose is not. Therefore, no one family or group of families can lay claim to saying, “my son,” “my daughter,” “my husband,” etc., is among the remains, and no one can have exclusive say of what should happen with them. This is why these remains are still in the custody of [OCME].297 This note set out to discover who is legally empowered to control the disposition of claimed but yet-to-be-identified human remains in the context of the legal battle over New York City’s plan to transfer the WTC victims’ remains to the National September 11 Memorial and Museum. Under the complex web of existing New York laws, these remains float in a state of legal limbo. While the quasi-property right to possession of a decedent’s body is robust, strong enough even to entitle the next of kin to an identified fragment of a WTC victim,298 the Memorial case has circumscribed the boundary of that right: DNA identification.299 So until OCME identifies the remains, the victims’ families have no legal basis to control or dispose of them. Meanwhile, pursuant to a hastily enacted amendment to the New York City Charter, OCME may dispose of unidentified remains even if the next of kin have submitted claims.300 Therefore, this note recommends that the New York City Council reevaluate Section 557 in order to clarify the ambiguities and deficiencies in the law governing unidentified human remains. In doing so, the Council should devise a means for the next of kin, rather than OCME or the City, to determine the remains’ final disposition. These changes should be modeled upon the mandatory repatriation and consultation provisions in NAGPRA. Patrick J. Mulqueen† 297 Cohen, supra note 259 (quoting Charles G. Wolf, a member of the FAC whose wife died at the WTC). 298 See supra Part III.D.3. 299 See supra Part III. 300 See supra Part II.A. † J.D. Candidate, Brooklyn Law School, 2013; B.A., University of Pennsylvania, 2006. To the editors and staff of the Brooklyn Law Review, I am grateful for your patience and hard work. To my mother Karen, I thank you for your unconditional love, support, and encouragement. Everything I am or ever hope to be, I owe to you. Combating Inaccuracies in Criminal Background Checks by Giving Meaning to the Fair Credit Reporting Act INTRODUCTION In today’s workplace, employers are either highly incentivized or legally mandated to ensure that they have knowledge of an employee’s criminal record. As a result, an overwhelming majority of employers now require criminal background checks as a condition of employment,1 and millions of these checks are performed each year.2 Such checks are especially prevalent in the midst of today’s gripping recession, 1 A 2010 survey by the Society for Human Resource Management found that 73 percent of employers conduct criminal background checks on all job candidates, while an additional 19 percent conduct criminal background checks on select job candidates. SOC’Y FOR HUMAN RES. MGMT., BACKGROUND CHECKING: CONDUCTING CRIMINAL BACKGROUND CHECKS (Jan. 22, 2010), available at http://www.shrm.org/ Research/SurveyFindings/Articles/Pages/BackgroundCheckCriminalChecks.aspx. When asked for their primary reasons for conducting criminal background checks, respondents answered as follows: “to ensure a safe work environment for employees” (61 percent); “to reduce legal liability for negligent hiring” (55 percent); “to reduce/prevent theft and embezzlement, other criminal activity” (39 percent); “to comply with applicable state law requiring a background check (e.g. daycare teachers, licensed medical practitioners, etc.) for a particular position” (20 percent); “to assess the overall trustworthiness of the job candidate” (12 percent); “other” (4 percent). Id. (noting that “[p]ercentages do not total to 100% as respondents were allowed multiple choices”). 2 According to a 2008 ABC News investigation, “There has been a surge in interest in criminal background checks in the last 15 years. Private companies conduct millions of such checks a year.” Scott Michels, Advocates Complain of Background Check Errors, ABC NEWS (Oct. 13, 2008), http://abcnews.go.com/TheLaw/ story?id=6017227&page=1. “[E]mployers are relying increasingly on privately maintained criminal history records.” Michael H. Jagunic, Comment, The Unified “Sealed” Theory: Updating Ohio’s Record-Sealing Statute for the Twenty-First Century, 59 CLEV. ST. L. REV. 161, 170 (2011). Although “comprehensive, industry-wide data are not available,” one CRA alone, “ChoicePoint[,] reported that it conducted approximately 3.3 million background investigations during 2002, the vast majority of which included a criminal justice information component.” SEARCH: NAT’L CONSORTIUM FOR JUSTICE INFO. & STATISTICS, REPORT OF THE NATIONAL TASK FORCE ON THE COMMERCIAL SALE OF CRIMINAL JUSTICE INFORMATION 7 (2005), available at http://search.org/files/pdf/rntfcscjri.pdf [hereinafter SEARCH]. 271 272 BROOKLYN LAW REVIEW [Vol. 78:1 which has truly “transformed the employment application process into a survival of the fittest.”3 In general, information relating to arrests, convictions, and other court proceedings is a matter of public record.4 Rather than search these records themselves, employers solicit consumer reporting agencies (CRAs)5 to provide them with consumer reports about potential employees, containing, among other things, information about criminal records.6 Employers ultimately base their hiring decisions in part on the information contained in these consumer reports.7 Not 3 Roberto Concepción, Jr., Pre-Employment Credit Checks: Effectuating Disparate Impact on Racial Minorities Under the Guise of Job-Relatedness and Business Necessity, 12 SCHOLAR 523, 524 (2010). 4 In the seminal case on this matter, Paul v. Davis, the Supreme Court denied a claim alleging that publicizing an arrest record was a violation of constitutional privacy rights. 424 U.S. 693, 713 (1976). The Court definitively stated that the petitioner’s case was based “on a claim that the State may not publicize a record of an official act such as an arrest. None of our substantive privacy decisions hold this or anything like this, and we decline to enlarge them in this manner,” thereby closing the door on any future proceedings attempting to extend constitutional privacy protection to criminal records. Id.; see generally Eric J. Mitnick, Procedural Due Process and Reputational Harm: Liberty as Self-Invention, 43 U.C. DAVIS L. REV. 79 (2009) (providing an overview and critique of the persistence of Paul v. Davis and its progeny). 5 Under the FCRA, [t]he term “consumer reporting agency” means any person which, for monetary fees, dues, or on a cooperative nonprofit basis, regularly engages in whole or in part in the practice of assembling or evaluating consumer credit information or other information on consumers for the purpose of furnishing consumer reports to third parties, and which uses any means or facility of interstate commerce for the purpose of preparing or furnishing consumer reports. 15 U.S.C. § 1681a(f) (2006). In some of the cases discussed in this note, CRAs are referred to as credit reporting agencies. For all intents and purposes, these are the same as consumer reporting agencies. Credit reports and consumer reports are interchangeable terms as well. 6 Under the FCRA, [t]he term “consumer report” means any written, oral, or other communication of any information by a consumer reporting agency bearing on a consumer’s credit worthiness [creditworthiness], credit standing, credit capacity, character, general reputation, personal characteristics, or mode of living which is used or expected to be used or collected in whole or in part for the purpose of serving as a factor in establishing the consumer’s eligibility for . . . (B) employment purposes . . . . Id. § 1681a(d)(1) (footnote omitted). “[C]riminal histories fall under the purview of the FCRA . . . [b]ecause a criminal history touches on an applicant’s ‘character, general reputation, or personal characteristics’ . . . .” Christopher M.A. Lujan, Using Criminal Histories to Make Sound Hiring Decisions, COLO. LAW., Nov. 2008, at 57, 58. 7 However, in making such decisions, employers must be careful not to violate “Title VII of the Civil Rights Act of 1964 (Title VII) which prohibits employment discrimination based on race, color, religion, sex, or national origin.” EQUAL EMP’T OPPORTUNITY COMM’N, EEOC ENFORCEMENT GUIDANCE ON THE CONSIDERATION OF ARREST AND CONVICTION RECORDS IN EMPLOYMENT DECISIONS UNDER TITLE VII OF THE CIVIL RIGHTS ACT OF 1964 (2006), available at http://www.eeoc.gov/laws/ 2012] GIVING MEANING TO THE FCRA 273 surprisingly, “research unequivocally demonstrates that having a criminal record greatly reduces one’s employment opportunities.”8 For this system to have any value, consumer reports must be accurate and up to date; a flawed consumer report can have adverse consequences for both the job-seeking consumer9—who loses a conditional offer of employment—and the employer—who rescinds an offer from a potentially valuable and otherwise qualified employee.10 In 1970, Congress recognized the “vital role”11 that CRAs play in this system and enacted the Fair Credit Reporting Act (FCRA)12 to regulate the production and use of consumer reports.13 To accomplish this goal, the FCRA regulates the information that can be included guidance/arrest_conviction.cfm [hereinafter EEOC GUIDANCE]; see Title VII, codified at 42 U.S.C. § 2000 et seq. (2006); see also Robb Mandelbaum, U.S. Push on Illegal Bias Against Hiring Those with Criminal Records, N.Y. TIMES, June 21, 2012, at B8. To avoid Title VII liability, an employer must be able to show that denial of employment based on a criminal record was consistent with business necessity; that it considered three factors: “the nature and gravity of the offense(s), . . . the time that has passed since the [conviction] and/or completion of the sentence; and [t]he nature of the job held or sought.” EEOC GUIDANCE, supra. According to the Equal Employment Opportunity Commission (EEOC), “[a] policy or practice that excludes everyone with a criminal record from employment will not be job related and consistent with business necessity [as required by statute] and therefore will violate Title VII, unless it is required by federal law.” EQUAL EMP’T OPPORTUNITY COMM’N, QUESTIONS AND ANSWERS ABOUT THE EEOC’S ENFORCEMENT GUIDANCE ON THE CONSIDERATION OF ARREST AND CONVICTION RECORDS IN EMPLOYMENT DECISIONS UNDER TITLE VII (2006), available at http://www.eeoc.gov/laws/guidance/qa_arrest_conviction.cfm; see also 42 U.S.C. § 2000e-2(k)(1)(A)(i). Even where an employer develops a screening system that considers these three factors, the EEOC suggests that an individualized assessment of any excluded applicants will further insulate the employer from Title VII liability. EEOC GUIDANCE, supra (listing factors that should be considered in an individualized assessment). Further, the EEOC treats arrests and convictions differently, as “[a]rrests are not proof of criminal conduct.” Id. Therefore, “an arrest record standing alone may not be used to deny an employment opportunity, [but] an employer may make an employment decision based on the conduct underlying the arrest if the conduct makes the individual unfit for the position in question.” Id. 8 Miriam J. Aukerman, The Somewhat Suspect Class: Towards a Constitutional Framework for Evaluating Occupational Restrictions Affecting People with Criminal Records, 7 J.L. SOC’Y 18, 21 (2005). 9 In the context of this note, the consumer will almost always be a prospective employee. Therefore, this note will use the term employee and consumer interchangeably. 10 See NAT’L CONSUMER LAW CTR., BROKEN RECORDS: HOW ERRORS BY CRIMINAL BACKGROUND CHECKING COMPANIES HARM WORKERS AND BUSINESSES 6 (Apr. 2012), available at http://www.nclc.org/images/pdf/pr-reports/broken-recordsreport.pdf [hereinafter NAT’L CONSUMER LAW CTR.]. A consumer report can be flawed in two ways: it can attribute an erroneous criminal record to an individual or it can report an individual’s criminal record in a flawed manner. In the latter instance, the report may contain information relating to an expunged matter or it may fail to state an ultimate disposition of the matter that was favorable to the consumer. 11 15 U.S.C. § 1681(a)(3) (2006). 12 Id. § 1681 et seq. 13 Id. § 1681(b). 274 BROOKLYN LAW REVIEW [Vol. 78:1 in consumer reports14 and the users with whom that information can be shared.15 In the employment context, before CRAs can prepare a report for an employer, the FCRA also requires disclosure to consumers and their written consent.16 The FCRA mandates that CRAs employ mechanisms to ensure compliance with its provisions. In § 1681e(b), the statute requires that CRAs use “reasonable procedures to assure maximum possible accuracy” when preparing any consumer report.17 In the employment context, § 1681k places heightened compliance requirements on CRAs when consumer reports are created using public records. When such a report is “likely to have an adverse effect” on an employment decision, CRAs must either notify the consumer at the time they send the report to the employer or “maintain strict procedures designed to insure that [the information reported] is complete and up to date.”18 The FCRA creates a private right of action for injured consumers, intended in part as one means of enforcing the statute.19 Yet, the FCRA is not a strict liability statute. Instead, it provides for liability only in cases of negligent or willful noncompliance.20 Thus, an injured consumer’s only recourse against a CRA is to bring a cause of action and prove elements similar to those of a traditional tort claim: that the CRA engaged in a negligent or willful breach of a duty imposed by the FCRA, which proximately caused the consumer’s injury.21 However, due to the FCRA’s general lack of guidance with respect to its requirements, injured consumers and courts have struggled to impose liability on CRAs for violating the statute. Forty years of extensive litigation has produced little clarity as to the types of procedures required for CRA compliance. 14 Id. § 1681c. Id. § 1681b. 16 Id. § 1681b(b)(2). 17 Id. § 1681e(b). 18 Id. § 1681k(a). 19 Cahlin v. Gen. Motors Acceptance Corp., 936 F.2d 1151, 1156 (11th Cir. 1991). 20 15 U.S.C. §§ 1681n-o. Negligent violation of the statute entitles plaintiffs to recover actual damages, while willful violation allows for recovery of both statutory and punitive damages. Id.; see Williams v. LexisNexis Risk Mgmt., No. 3:06-cv-241, 2007 U.S. Dist. LEXIS 62193, at *27-28 (E.D. Va. Aug. 23, 2007) (holding that class certification could be permissible in a case alleging willful violation, even absent any claim for actual damages). In Safeco v. Burr, the Supreme Court held that a CRA willfully violates the FCRA when it acts in reckless disregard of the statutory requirements. 551 U.S. 47, 52 (2007). 21 Bryant v. TRW, Inc., 487 F. Supp. 1234, 1242 (E.D. Mich. 1980) (noting that “[t]he standard of conduct by which the agency’s action is to be judged is deeply rooted in the law of negligence”). 15 2012] GIVING MEANING TO THE FCRA 275 And although the FCRA, in § 1681k, purports to impose a heightened standard on CRAs when furnishing criminal background reports for employment purposes, these problems still persist. Further, § 1681k contains an enigmatic provision allowing CRAs to “opt-out” of its heightened standards (by sending contemporaneous notice to consumers), while providing no corresponding enhancement of consumer protection.22 Therefore, while private litigation may have been intended as a way to enforce the FCRA’s goal of ensuring accuracy in the reporting industry, the reality of engaging in protracted litigation often presents an insurmountable hurdle for consumers seeking relief, and, even then, only after they have been injured by erroneous reports. By amending § 1681k to require that CRAs provide consumers with a copy of their purported criminal records before distributing the report to prospective employers, Congress could solve many of these problems and give meaning to the heightened requirements of § 1681k. The rest of this note is divided into five parts. Part I explores some of the reasons why employers conduct criminal background checks and identifies some of the dangers that over-reliance on these reports poses to consumers, especially in light of documented inaccuracies.23 Part II provides an introduction to the FCRA, its purpose, and some of its relevant provisions. Part III analyzes the requirements for proving a violation of the general compliance procedures contained in § 1681e(b), illustrating the current legal framework’s inadequacies in providing meaningful relief to injured consumers. Part IV explores the supposed heightened compliance requirements of § 1681k and shows how that section fails to meaningfully 22 See infra Part IV.C. In a report issued in April 2012, the National Consumer Law Center (NCLC) found that “evidence indicates that professional background screening companies routinely make mistakes with grave consequences for job seekers.” NAT’L CONSUMER LAW CTR., supra note 10, at 3. The report documented the many types of mistakes found in these reports and their causes, and also addressed some of the same legal issues raised in this note. See generally id. In response to the NCLC report, the National Association of Professional Background Screeners issued a press release denouncing the report’s findings and claiming that “[o]f the small number of reports that are disputed by a consumer, more than 95 percent are ultimately found to be accurate.” Press Release, Nat’l Ass’n of Prof’l Background Screeners, Background Screening Industry Denounces NCLC Report (June 19, 2012), available at http://www.prweb.com/releases/2012/6/prweb9603002.htm. It is not the intention of this note to join in this empirical debate concerning whether or not inaccuracies are rampant in the background screening industry. Instead, given that it is undisputed that some inaccurate criminal background reports are produced, this note focuses on improving the means of recourse available for consumers injured by such reports and offers a legislative suggestion to improve accuracy overall. 23 276 BROOKLYN LAW REVIEW [Vol. 78:1 enhance consumer protection—in large part because the FCRA’s ex-post approach provides consumers an opportunity to identify mistakes in their reports only after the damage has been done. Finally, Part V suggests that amending § 1681k to require that reports be provided to consumers before being supplied to potential employers can ameliorate many of private litigation’s failures in FCRA enforcement. I. CRIMINAL BACKGROUND CHECKS FOR EMPLOYMENT: THE GOOD, THE BAD, AND THE UNRELIABLE A. The Use of Criminal Background Checks Protects Society and Employers There are many reasons why employers conduct criminal background checks of prospective employees, but those reasons all share a central theme: the recognition that certain positions have the potential to be used as a means of inflicting harm—either against the employer or the public.24 In some instances, employers are mandated to conduct these checks by a wide range of state and federal laws prohibiting the employment of people with criminal records in certain fields, such as the healthcare, financial services, trucking, and community care facility industries.25 24 Lujan, supra note 6, at 57 (“[I]f there is a high probability that an employee will interact frequently with the public or handle valuable property, a prudent employer will obtain a criminal history and analyze the relationship between the criminal conduct and the position sought before determining if hiring is appropriate.”); see also supra note 1. While this note focuses on CRA responsibilities and liabilities when providing criminal background in consumer reports, the FCRA also regulates the use of that information by user-employers. 15 U.S.C. § 1681m. For an in-depth discussion of employer responsibilities when soliciting criminal background checks from CRAs, see generally Susan Gardner et al., Does Your Background Checker Put You in Jeopardy?: A Case for Best Practices and Due Diligence, 11 J. LEGAL ETHICAL & REG. ISSUES 111 (2008). 25 Aukerman, supra note 8, at 23; Gardner et al., supra note 24, at 118; James Jacobs & Tamara Crepet, The Expanding Scope, Use, and Availability of Criminal Records, 11 N.Y.U. J. LEGIS. & PUB. POL’Y 177, 177-78 (2008). The requirement of a license for certain jobs poses problems as well. According to a 2006 report by the New York State Bar Association, Over 100 occupations in New York State require some type of license, registration, or certification by a state agency. Although only a few statutes automatically bar people from licensure solely based on past convictions, New York places many statutory restrictions based on an individual’s criminal history through general “good moral character” requirements for almost all licenses. For example, an individual with a criminal conviction cannot obtain a license to work as a barber because “a criminal history indicates a lack of good moral character and trustworthiness required for licensure.” 2012] GIVING MEANING TO THE FCRA 277 Even where criminal background checks are not required by law, many employers will demand them as a condition of employment. Employers tend to view those with criminal records as untrustworthy or unreliable.26 Additionally, the state law doctrine of negligent hiring liability provides a large incentive for employers to insist on conducting criminal background checks.27 Under this doctrine, “[a]n employer may be liable for negligently hiring employees when such negligence results in harm to third parties, even when the harm inflicted by the employee occurs outside the scope of employment . . . .”28 Thus, “a direct duty running from the employer to those members of the public whom the employer might reasonably anticipate would be placed in a position of risk of injury as the result of the hiring” is imposed.29 An employer can be liable if he “knew or should have known” of an employee’s propensities towards criminal acts.30 To avoid potential liability, an employer’s “safest course of action sometimes appears to be automatically disqualifying applicants with criminal histories . . . .”31 As one writer put it, “many companies [have] N.Y. STATE BAR ASS’N, RE-ENTRY AND REINTEGRATION: THE ROAD TO PUBLIC SAFETY, REPORT AND RECOMMENDATIONS OF THE SPECIAL COMMITTEE ON COLLATERAL CONSEQUENCES OF CRIMINAL PROCEEDINGS 60-61 (2006), available at http://www.nysba.org/AM/Template.cfm?Section=Substantive_Reports&ContentID=1141 5&template=/CM/ContentDisplay.cfm [hereinafter STATE BAR REPORT] (quoting Clyde Haberman, He Did Time, So He’s Unfit to Do Hair, N.Y. TIMES, Mar. 4, 2005, at B1). 26 See James B. Jacobs, Mass Incarceration and the Proliferation of Criminal Records, 3 U. ST. THOMAS L.J. 387, 390 (2006). 27 Gardner et al., supra note 24, at 111 (“[W]ith the upsurge in negligent hiring and retention lawsuits, employers [have] continued their prevention efforts by checking the qualifications and backgrounds of prospective and current employees.”); Lujan, supra note 6, at 57 (“Having this information before a hiring decision is made can help in defending the employer against negligent hiring or supervision claims.”); STATE BAR REPORT, supra note 25, at 83. “Virtually all states have recognized a cause of action in tort for persons injured by an employer’s negligence in hiring, retaining or supervising a dangerous employee.” 1 LEX K. LARSON, EMPLOYMENT SCREENING § 10.01 (MB 2012); see also Katherine A. Peebles, Note, Negligent Hiring and the Information Age: How State Legislatures Can Save Employers from Inevitable Liability, 53 WM. & MARY L. REV. 1397, 1404 (2012) (“Every state recognizes the tort of negligent hiring.”). 28 Stephen F. Befort, Pre-Employment Screening and Investigation: Navigating Between a Rock and a Hard Place, 14 HOFSTRA LAB. L.J. 365, 376 (1997). To be successful, “a plaintiff must establish that (1) the employer owed the third party a duty of reasonable care, (2) the employer breached the duty[,] and (3) the breach proximately caused the third party’s harm.” Id. (footnotes omitted). 29 Ponticas v. K.M.S. Invs., 331 N.W.2d 907, 911 n.5 (Minn. 1983). 30 Jennifer Leavitt, Note, Walking A Tightrope: Balancing Competing Public Interests in the Employment of Criminal Offenders, 34 CONN. L. REV. 1281, 1301 (2002) (emphasis added). 31 Id. at 1302. 278 BROOKLYN LAW REVIEW [Vol. 78:1 adopted Ben Franklin’s adage, ‘an ounce of prevention is worth a pound of cure.’”32 B. Over-Reliance on Criminal Background Checks Hurts Offenders and Society While criminal background checks can help employers avoid liability, overzealous reliance on this information leads to an unfounded bias against individuals with criminal records. In theory, “[t]he law conducts a balancing test between the employer’s right to maintain an environment free from criminal behavior and providing individuals with a criminal history the opportunity to work.”33 However, critics of mandated proscription from certain jobs34 and proponents of limiting negligent hiring liability feel that these practices create an insurmountable obstacle for people who have criminal records.35 As a result, while “background screening can be helpful in identifying applicants whose records makes [sic] them unsuitable for a particular position . . . , such screening also discloses records which should not be disqualifying, but which, in practice, are treated as disqualifying by employers.”36 High recidivism rates have been attributed in part to the difficulty of obtaining meaningful employment with a criminal record,37 and it has been suggested that “[r]ehabilitation through employment opportunities is one clear way to stem the tide of ex-offenders leaving and re-entering society through the jailhouse doors.”38 32 Gardner et al., supra note 24, at 111 (quoting Benjamin Franklin, c. 1736). Lujan, supra note 6, at 60. 34 One such critique of “[r]ecord based employment disqualifications [is that they] are imposed by operation of law, without any consideration of their appropriateness for the individual involved.” Aukerman, supra note 8, at 25. 35 “Despite the protections afforded by federal and state law, a demonstrated preference for hiring people without criminal records still exists.” STATE BAR REPORT, supra note 25, at 80; Fruqan Mouzon, Forgive Us Our Trespasses: The Need for Federal Expungement Legislation, 39 U. MEM. L. REV. 1, 45-46 (2008) (stating that a criminal record can carry with it “a stigma so indelible as to subject even non-violent offenders to lifelong sentences”). “The more accessible these records, the more likely the stigma of a criminal conviction, or even an arrest, will endure.” Jacobs & Crepet, supra note 25, at 211. 36 Aukerman, supra note 8, at 23. 37 “Research from both academics and practitioners suggest that the chief factor which influences the reduction of recidivism is an individual’s ability to gain ‘quality employment.’” STATE BAR REPORT, supra note 25, at 50 (citing, e.g., MEASURING RECIDIVISM: CRIMINAL HISTORY COMPUTATION OF THE FEDERAL SENTENCING GUIDELINES, A COMPONENT OF THE FIFTEEN YEAR REPORT ON THE U.S. SENTENCING COMMISSION’S LEGISLATIVE MANDATE, at 12 (May 2004), available at http://www.ussc.gov/publicat/Recidivism_General.pdf). 38 Leavitt, supra note 30, at 1282. 33 2012] C. GIVING MEANING TO THE FCRA 279 Accuracy Is Paramount, but Elusive Whether one agrees with the logic behind them or not, the reality is that criminal background checks are regularly performed. Assuming that these checks are important for employment decisions, it is clear that such reports should contain accurate and complete information. Unfortunately, “[n]o single source exists that provides complete and up-to-date information about a person’s criminal history.”39 Many employers, therefore, rely on information from “commercial databases[, which] are frequently inaccurate . . . .”40 Even information taken directly from courthouse computer systems can be unreliable, as “human errors, court delays, processing lags, and staffing shortages impair the quality of data.”41 “Misspelled words, erroneous birthdates, and transposed address numbers can cause mis- or no information for the report.”42 As a result, courthouse “repositories are notorious for being ‘outdated, inaccurate and incomplete.’”43 Yet, according to Craig Kessler, president of the CRA Backgroundchecks.com, “We’re not in the business of authenticating the identity of individuals. All we do is report the data that’s supplied to us from the courts.”44 This attitude has a direct effect on the accuracy of consumer reports, as illustrated by the experience of Ron Peterson. Peterson, a California resident, was denied employment based on an erroneous criminal report compiled by Backgroundchecks.com.45 According to Peterson, “In Florida I’m a female prostitute (named Ronnie); in Texas I’m currently incarcerated for manslaughter . . . . In New Mexico I’m a dealer of stolen goods. 39 U.S. DEP’T OF JUSTICE, THE ATTORNEY GENERAL’S REPORT ON CRIMINAL HISTORY BACKGROUND CHECKS 6 (2006), available at http://www.justice.gov/ olp/ag_bgchecks_report.pdf [hereinafter ATTORNEY GENERAL’S REPORT]; see also Gardner et al., supra note 24, at 119. 40 Gardner et al., supra note 24, at 119. 41 Id. at 120 (internal quotation marks omitted). 42 Id. 43 Id. at 118 (quoting Jason B. Morris, Criminal Background Checks: You Get What You Pay For, VERIFIER (Background Info. Servs., Cleveland, Ohio) June/July 2004, at 4, available at http://www.employeescreen.com/web/pdfs/verifier_issue3.pdf). “Misinformation can occur for a number of reasons—clerks mis-key information, criminal charges get dropped but not updated in files, or arrested suspects provide authorities with the name and Social Security number of someone else.” Kim Zetter, Bad Data Fouls Background Checks, WIRED (Mar. 11, 2005), http://www.wired.com/ politics/security/news/2005/03/66856?currentPage=all. 44 Zetter, supra note 43. 45 Id. 280 BROOKLYN LAW REVIEW [Vol. 78:1 Oregon has me as a witness tamperer. And in Nevada—this is my favorite—I’m a registered sex offender.”46 Peterson represents one type of consumer that can be hurt by an inaccurate or incomplete criminal background check: those who have never been arrested yet have a criminal history mistakenly ascribed to them. Inaccurate or incomplete reports can also harm individuals who were previously arrested or convicted of crimes because, while their charges might have been dropped or their records expunged, those records might still show up in a criminal background check.47 There is currently no industry-wide data dealing directly with the accuracy of criminal record reports.48 However, a 2004 study by the National Association of State Public Interest Research Groups surveyed credit reports of adults in 30 states.49 The study found that “[f]ifty-four percent (54%) of the credit reports contained personal demographic information that was misspelled, long-outdated, belonged to a stranger, or was otherwise incorrect[.]”50 The study also found that “[a]ltogether, 79% of the credit reports surveyed contained either serious errors or other mistakes of some kind.”51 At least one writer has opined that, “[g]iven that many of the same organizations conduct background and credit checks, errors in conducting one kind of check (credit) should make [us] similarly suspect of the accuracy of the other (background).”52 Given how frequently criminal background checks are performed for employment purposes,53 the pervasiveness of such deficiencies poses a grave problem.54 In a recent class 46 Id. “[C]ommercial databases may also be missing important disposition information that is relevant to a conviction record’s use for employment suitability purposes, such as sealing and expungement orders or entry into a pre-trial or post-trial diversion program.” ATTORNEY GENERAL’S REPORT, supra note 39, at 2. 48 See NAT’L CONSUMER LAW CTR, supra note 10, at 7; SEARCH, supra note 2, at 7. 49 NAT’L ASS’N OF STATE PIRGS, MISTAKES DO HAPPEN: A LOOK AT ERRORS IN CONSUMER CREDIT REPORTS 4 (June 2004), available at http://cdn.publicinterestnetwork.org/ assets/BEevuv19a3KzsATRbZMZlw/MistakesDoHappen2004.pdf. 50 Id. 51 Id. 52 Gardner et al., supra note 24, at 118; see also Zetter, supra note 43 (stating that “[t]here’s no reason to believe that criminal records are any more accurate” than credit reports). 53 See supra note 1. 54 According to a recent study, the current recession has not lead to a significant increase in the percentage of employers that conduct criminal background checks. SOC’Y FOR HUMAN RES. MGMT., BACKGROUND CHECKING: GENERAL BACKGROUND CHECKS 8 (Jan. 22, 2010), available at http://www.shrm.org/ Research/SurveyFindings/Articles/Documents/Background%20Check_General.pptx. Still, it is safe to assume that with a constant rate of background checking, the increase in job 47 2012] GIVING MEANING TO THE FCRA 281 action lawsuit, 665,391 consumers brought a claim against the CRA HireRight, alleging that between 2004 and 2010 HireRight failed to comply with the FCRA in the preparation of consumer reports, all of which contained adverse information about the consumers.55 And that is just a single case against a single agency. In fact, litigation for this issue continues.56 For these injured consumers, winning lawsuits depends on proving that the CRA violated the FCRA—the statute that was implemented to regulate this industry. II. FCRA—PURPOSE AND BACKGROUND In the latter half of the twentieth century, Congress recognized that “[c]onsumer reporting agencies [had] assumed a vital role in assembling and evaluating consumer credit and other information on consumers.”57 Even forty years ago, House Representative and FCRA sponsor Leonor Sullivan remarked: [W]ith the trend towards computerizations and billings and the establishment of all sorts of computerized data banks, the individual is in great danger of having his life and character reduced to impersonal “blips” and key-punch holes in a stolid and unthinking machine which can literally ruin his reputation without cause, and make him unemployable . . . .58 Therefore, in 1970, Congress enacted the FCRA to address what it perceived as the “need to insure that consumer reporting agencies exercise their grave responsibilities with fairness, impartiality, and a respect for the consumer’s right to privacy.”59 To that end, the FCRA’s stated purpose is “to require that consumer reporting agencies adopt reasonable procedures applicants in the past several years has led to a higher incidence of criminal background checks overall. See AP, Employers Post Fewest Job Ads in Five Months, USA TODAY (Nov. 6, 2012, 2:33 PM), http://www.usatoday.com/story/money/business/ 2012/11/06/job-ads-september/1685879/ (“With 12.1 million people unemployed in September [2012], there were 3.4 unemployed people, on average, competing for each open job. In a healthy economy, that ratio is roughly 2-to-1.”). 55 Order of Preliminary Approval of Class Action Settlement at 3, ¶ 3, Ryals v. HireRight Solutions, Inc., No.3:09cv625, (E.D. Va. July 7, 2011). 56 See, e.g., King v. Gen. Info. Servs., Inc., 2012 U.S. Dist. LEXIS 159380 (E.D. Pa. Nov. 6, 2012) (class action suit upholding constitutionality of FCRA); Moore v. First Advantage Enter. Screening Corp., 2012 U.S. Dist. LEXIS 136721 (N.D. Ohio Sept. 24, 2012) (dismissing class allegations and allowing individual claims); Farmer v. Phillips Agency, Inc., 2012 U.S. Dist. LEXIS 146144 (N.D. Ga. Sept. 20, 2012) (denying class certification). 57 15 U.S.C. § 1681(a)(3) (2006). 58 116 CONG. REC. 36570 (1970) (statement of Rep. Sullivan), quoted in Bryant v. TRW, Inc., 689 F.2d 72, 79 (6th Cir. 1982). 59 15 U.S.C. § 1681(a)(4). 282 BROOKLYN LAW REVIEW [Vol. 78:1 for meeting the needs of commerce for consumer credit, personnel, insurance, and other information in a manner which is fair and equitable to the consumer, with regard to the confidentiality, accuracy, relevancy, and proper utilization of such information.”60 In effect, the FCRA “governs the collection, assembly, and use of consumer report information and provides the framework for the credit reporting system in the United States.”61 Enforcement of the FCRA occurs “at the federal and state levels, as well as through private litigation.”62 To accomplish its goal, the FCRA regulates how CRAs compile and distribute consumer reports. Section 1681b lists the “[p]ermissible purposes of consumer reports”63 for which a CRA “may furnish a consumer report.”64 Use of information contained in a consumer report by an employer—the user—to make an employment decision about a prospective employee—the consumer—is one such “[p]ermissible purpose” under the FCRA.65 To comply with § 1681b, CRAs must have procedures requiring “prospective users of the information [to] identify themselves, certify the purposes for which the information is sought, and certify that the information will be used for no other purpose.”66 When the purpose of a consumer report is to make an employment decision, the user is required to provide additional certifications before a CRA may furnish a report. The employer-user must also certify that a written disclosure was made to the consumer,67 that the consumer provided written authorization for the procurement of the report,68 and that “information from the consumer report will not be used in 60 Id. § 1681(b). FED. TRADE COMM’N, 40 YEARS OF EXPERIENCE WITH THE FAIR CREDIT REPORTING, AN FTC STAFF REPORT WITH SUMMARY OF INTERPRETATIONS 1 (2011), available at http://ftc.gov/os/2011/07/110720fcrareport.pdf [hereinafter FTC STAFF REPORT]. 62 Id. at 3. 63 15 U.S.C. § 1681b. 64 Id. § 1681b(a). 65 Id. § 1681b(a)(3)(B). 66 Id. § 1681e(a). CRAs must also “make a reasonable effort” to independently verify such certifications from new users. Id. “What constitutes adequate verification will vary with the circumstances.” FTC STAFF REPORT, supra note 61, at 65. Interestingly, according to one FTC Staff opinion letter, the requirements for such verification are more lax when a CRA only provides consumer reports that contain public records, such as criminal background checks. The staff opinion did not consider such information “sensitive personal information, as in a traditional credit report,” and therefore advised that simply relying on the client’s certification would satisfy the statute. FTC Informal Staff Opinion Letter of William Haynes (June 9, 1998), available at http://www.ftc.gov/os/statutes/fcra/leblanc.shtm. 67 15 U.S.C. § 1681b(b)(2)(A)(i). 68 Id. § 1681b(b)(2)(A)(ii). 61 2012] GIVING MEANING TO THE FCRA 283 violation of any applicable Federal or State equal employment opportunity law or regulation . . . .”69 Additionally, the employer-user must certify that “before taking any adverse action based in whole or in part on the report, [it will provide the consumer with] a copy of the report; and a description in writing of the rights of the consumer . . . .”70 Section 1681c contains the “[r]equirements relating to information contained in consumer reports.”71 Because criminal records are public information,72 there is no specific federal law that prohibits CRAs from providing criminal background checks in consumer reports. However, the FCRA does temporally restrict CRAs’ ability to include information pertaining to criminal records other than criminal convictions—e.g., arrests that did not lead to convictions. With a few exceptions not relevant to this note, CRAs cannot report any arrests that “antedate the report by more than seven years . . . .”73 There is, however, no time limit on reporting information pertaining to criminal convictions.74 The general procedures for CRA compliance with the FCRA, applicable in all situations, are laid out in § 1681e.75 Section 1681e(b) states that “[w]henever a consumer reporting agency prepares a consumer report it shall follow reasonable procedures to assure maximum possible accuracy of the information concerning the individual about whom the report 69 Id. § 1681b(b)(1)(A)(ii). Id. § 1681b(b)(3)(A). “There is no specific period of time an employer must wait after providing a pre-adverse action notice and before taking adverse action against the consumer. Some reasonable period of time must elapse, but the minimum length will vary depending on the particular circumstances involved.” FTC STAFF REPORT, supra note 61, at 52. The problems inherent in this lack of specificity will be discussed in detail, infra Part IV.C. 71 15 U.S.C. § 1681c. 72 See supra note 4. 73 15 U.S.C. § 1681c(a)(2). Some states place further limits on the reporting of criminal records. In New York, for example, in most instances, a consumer report may contain information about an arrest only if it resulted in a criminal conviction or if the charges are still pending. N.Y. GEN. BUS. LAW § 380-j(a)(1) (McKinney 2012). 74 15 U.S.C. § 1681c(a)(5). 75 Prior to enactment of the FCRA, a House amendment was accepted that extended the requirement to follow reasonable procedures to apply to all CRAs—an extension from the original Senate bill that applied this requirement only to CRAs that prepared investigative consumer reports. 116 CONG. REC. 35940 (1970) (remarks of Sen. Proxmire introducing the conference report), quoted in Bryant v. TRW, Inc., 689 F.2d 72, 77-78 (6th Cir. 1982). Additionally, even when subject to the “heightened” requirements of § 1681k, a CRA will have to follow § 1681e(b), and the analysis of a court will often rest on an interpretation of § 1681e(b). See infra notes 157-61 and accompanying text. 70 284 BROOKLYN LAW REVIEW [Vol. 78:1 relates.”76 When CRAs produce consumer reports for employment purposes based on public records, they are subject to ostensibly heightened compliance requirements under § 1681k. If the report is likely to have an adverse effect on an employment decision, CRAs must either notify the consumer at the time they send the report to the employer or use “strict procedures designed to insure that [the report] is complete and up to date.”77 The next two parts of this note will explore how courts analyze private causes of action alleging violations of these two provisions. III. PRIVATE LITIGATION UNDER SECTION 1681E(B) Section 1681e(b) is the general compliance provision in the FCRA and mandates that “[w]henever a consumer reporting agency prepares a consumer report it shall follow reasonable procedures to assure maximum possible accuracy of the information concerning the individual about whom the report relates.”78 The FCRA, however, does not impose strict liability on CRAs for providing erroneous reports.79 Instead, liability can be found if the CRA committed negligent or willful violations of this provision.80 Yet litigation of this provision is no easy task, because the legislative history of § 1681e(b) is, as one Sixth Circuit case called it, “sketchy,”81 and the exact standards required by the provision have remained elusive. The elements required for proving a negligent violation of § 1681e(b) appear simple enough, mirroring the requirements for proving a general tort action: To succeed on a claim under this section, a plaintiff must establish that: (1) the consumer reporting agency was negligent in that it failed to follow reasonable procedures to assure the accuracy of its credit report; (2) the consumer reporting agency reported inaccurate information about the plaintiff; (3) the plaintiff was injured; and (4) the consumer reporting agency’s negligence proximately caused the plaintiff’s injury.82 Basing their analyses on these elements, courts recognize that “[t]he threshold question in a [§] 1681e(b) action 76 15 U.S.C. § 1681e(b). Id. § 1681k(a). 78 Id. § 1681e(b). 79 Cahlin v. Gen. Motors Acceptance Corp., 936 F.2d 1151, 1156 (11th Cir. 1991) (stating that the FCRA “does not make reporting agencies strictly liable for all inaccuracies”). 80 15 U.S.C. §§ 1681n-o. 81 Bryant v. TRW, Inc., 689 F.2d 72, 77 (6th Cir. 1982). 82 Whelan v. Trans Union Credit Reporting Agency, 862 F. Supp. 824, 829 (E.D.N.Y. 1994). 77 2012] GIVING MEANING TO THE FCRA 285 is whether the challenged credit information is inaccurate. If the information is accurate no further inquiry into the reasonableness of the consumer reporting agency’s procedures is necessary.”83 On the other hand, “Whether the credit reporting agency followed reasonable procedures ‘will be a jury question in the overwhelming majority of cases.’”84 In that way, reasonableness, “like other questions concerning the application of a legal standard to given facts . . . , is treated as a factual question even when the underlying facts are undisputed. It therefore cannot be resolved on summary judgment unless the reasonableness or unreasonableness of the procedures is beyond question . . . .”85 Proving causation and injury are also questions for the jury.86 Thus, a CRA may succeed on a motion for summary judgment “only if a court finds, as a matter of law, that a credit report was accurate,”87 thereby employing the “accuracy defense.”88 But, because the definitions of these elements remain unclear, injured consumers struggle to prove their cases. A. Accuracy Is Not Defined by the Statute The inaccuracy of a consumer report is the threshold question in a § 1681e(b) claim, yet the statute provides no definition of the term accuracy, and the circuit courts are split between two different views on the type of accuracy required by the statute.89 This disagreement exists because “[a]ccuracy is quite clearly not a self-defining concept, and [the] FCRA’s fragmentary legislative history provides little, if any, guidance as to how Congress intended this standard to be applied.”90 83 Houston v. TRW Info. Servs., 707 F. Supp. 689, 691 (S.D.N.Y. 1989) (citing Middlebrooks v. Retail Credit Co., 416 F. Supp. 1013, 1015 (N.D. Ga. 1976) (stating that a “court need not reach the issue of ‘reasonableness’ if it finds initially that the report furnished was accurate”)); see also Williams v. LexisNexis Risk Mgmt., No. 3:06cv241, 2007 U.S. Dist. LEXIS 62193, at *18 (E.D. Va. Aug. 23, 2007) (stating that “when a report is in fact accurate, the procedure is per se reasonable”). 84 Adams v. Nat’l Eng’g Serv. Corp., 620 F. Supp. 2d 319, 330 (D. Conn. 2009) (quoting Cahlin, 936 F.2d at 1156); see also Guimond v. Transunion Credit Info. Co., 45 F.3d 1329, 1333 (9th Cir. 1995) (“The reasonableness of the procedures and whether the agency followed them will be jury questions in the overwhelming majority of cases.”). 85 Crabill v. Trans Union, L.L.C., 259 F.3d 662, 664 (7th Cir. 2001). 86 Adams, 620 F. Supp. 2d at 330. 87 Cahlin, 936 F.2d at 1156 (internal quotation marks omitted). 88 Id. “This term of art is actually a misnomer because the burden of proving that a particular report is inaccurate is part of the plaintiff’s case and not an affirmative defense for a defendant credit reporting agency.” Id. at 1156 n.9. 89 Id. at 1157. 90 Id. 286 BROOKLYN LAW REVIEW [Vol. 78:1 One approach to the definition of accuracy—the “business friendly interpretation”91—is known as the “technical accuracy standard.”92 Under this interpretation, “a credit reporting agency satisfies its duty under [§ 1681e(b)] if it produces a report that contains factually correct information about a consumer that might nonetheless be misleading or incomplete in some respect.”93 Courts that adopt the technical accuracy standard fear that requiring more would place too heavy a burden on CRAs.94 By contrast, under the “maximum possible accuracy also known as the “consumer-friendly approach,”95 96 interpretation,” an “entry may be inaccurate within the meaning of [§ 1681e(b)] either because it is patently incorrect, or because it is misleading in such a way and to such an extent that it can be expected to adversely affect credit decisions.”97 The rationale for this approach is based on statutory interpretation and a basic recognition of the FCRA’s purpose. Looking at the statute’s language, “[§ 1681e(b)] does not require that a consumer reporting agency follow reasonable procedures to assure simply that the consumer report be 91 Neil Vanderwoude, Comment, The Fair Credit Reporting Act: Fair for Consumers, Fair for Credit Reporting Agencies, 39 SW. U. L. REV. 395, 400 (2009) (internal quotation marks omitted). 92 Smith v. HireRight Solutions, Inc., 711 F. Supp. 2d 426, 433 n.5 (E.D. Pa. 2010) (citing Holmes v. TeleCheck Int’l, 556 F. Supp. 2d 819, 833 (M.D. Tenn. 2008)). 93 Cahlin, 936 F.2d at 1157. 94 See, e.g., Heupel v. Trans Union LLC, 193 F. Supp. 2d 1234, 1240 (N.D. Ala. 2002) (reluctant to place “too great a burden on credit reporting agencies” and holding that “[r]equiring ‘technical accuracy’ in credit reports best captures the balance Congress struck between consumers’ concern for fair and equitable treatment and reporting agencies’ goal of maintaining accurate and cost-effective credit reporting”); Grant v. TRW, Inc., 789 F. Supp. 690, 692 (D. Md. 1992) (“‘Accuracy’ can be tested by verification whereas a determination of ‘completeness’ requires the exercise of judgment on potentially difficult questions concerning the meaning and effect of contextual information.”). In Alexander v. Moore & Associates, the court criticized the technical accuracy standard as leading to the result “that a consumer reporting agency could report that a person was ‘involved’ in a credit card scam, and without regard to [§ 1681e(b)] fail to report that he was in fact one of the victims of the scam.” 553 F. Supp. 948, 952 (D. Haw. 1982). However, the Grant court rejected the example given by the Alexander court, characterizing it as an “extreme instance[] in which a technically accurate statement is so inherently misleading that it would run afoul of the ‘maximum possible accuracy’ requirement of § 1681e(b).” Grant, 789 F. Supp. at 692. The Grant court felt that “the possibility that such extreme cases might be presented does not justify rewriting the FCRA to render actionable the initial reporting of information which although accurate is deemed to be misleading because it is incomplete.” Id. 95 Smith, 711 F. Supp. 2d at 433. 96 Vanderwoude, supra note 91, at 400. 97 Sepulvado v. CSC Credit Servs., 158 F.3d 890, 895 (5th Cir. 1998) (internal quotation marks omitted). 2012] GIVING MEANING TO THE FCRA 287 accurate, but to assure maximum possible accuracy.”98 Because fairness in consumer reporting is one of the stated purposes of the FCRA,99 courts have held that § 1681e(b), “fairly read, would apply to consumer reports even though they may be technically accurate, if it is shown that such reports are not accurate to the maximum possible extent.”100 Whether a court adopts the “technical accuracy standard” or the “maximum possible accuracy approach” can impact the court’s disposition as to a CRA’s successful use of the accuracy defense, and therefore is fundamental to determining whether a violation of § 1681e(b) occurred.101 A recent case helps to illustrate this point. In Smith v. HireRight, the Eastern District court in Pennsylvania denied the defendant CRA’s motion to dismiss a claim under § 1681e(b).102 Smith, the named plaintiff in this class-action suit, had applied for several truck-driving positions, and each of his prospective employers solicited the defendant, CRA HireRight, to provide them with his consumer report.103 Smith had been arrested once, a few years earlier, but the consumer report prepared by HireRight listed this single incident multiple times.104 In its motion to dismiss, HireRight cited a Sixth Circuit case using the “technical accuracy standard” to argue that “no claim can be stated based on the publication of factually accurate information, even if the information was presented in a format that created some risk it could be misconstrued by a third party.”105 Under this argument, since Smith had been arrested on the date reported, the report contained factually correct, albeit repeated, information.106 But the court rejected this argument and chose to “adopt the maximum accuracy approach over the technical accuracy approach.”107 Having adopted this 98 Alexander, 553 F. Supp. at 952 (internal quotation marks omitted). 15 U.S.C. § 1681(a)(4) (2006). 100 Alexander, 553 F. Supp. at 952. 101 “Although courts have assumed that the so-called ‘accuracy defense’ is a question fit for disposition on motion for summary judgment, they have widely diverged in their interpretations of what constitutes an ‘accurate’ credit report.” Cahlin v. Gen. Motors Acceptance Corp., 936 F.2d 1151, 1156-57 (11th Cir. 1991). 102 Smith v. HireRight Solutions, Inc., 711 F. Supp. 2d 426, 439 (E.D. Pa. 2010). 103 Id. at 430. 104 Id. 105 Reply Memorandum of Law in Further Support of Motion to Dismiss Plaintiff’s Complaint at 3-4, Smith, 711 F. Supp. 2d 426 (No. 09-06007) (citing Holmes v. Telecheck Int’l, 556 F. Supp. 2d 819, 833 (M.D. Tenn. 2008)). 106 Id. (claiming that “no court has ever held that the mere repetition of factually accurate information within a background report renders that report legally inaccurate for the purposes of Section 1681e(b)”). 107 Smith, 711 F. Supp. 2d at 433 n.5. 99 288 BROOKLYN LAW REVIEW [Vol. 78:1 standard, the court held that Smith had pleaded sufficient facts to state a viable cause of action under § 1681e(b) and denied the defendant’s motion to dismiss.108 Had the case been brought in a circuit employing the “technical accuracy standard,” the result would likely have been different. B. The Statute Provides No Guidance on the Reasonable Procedures Required While proving that a CRA supplied inaccurate information is the threshold question often resolved during the summary judgment stage, a plaintiff must still prove the other three elements of a § 1681e(b) claim at trial, beginning with showing that the CRA was negligent or willful when it failed to use reasonable procedures to ensure accuracy. Indeed, as the D.C. Circuit stated, “The reasonableness requirement thus severely limits an agency’s duty to maximally assure precise and complete reporting.”109 The duty imposed by the statute is much like that of the standard tort test: it requires the CRA to do “what a reasonably prudent person would do under the circumstances.”110 Whether a CRA has satisfied this burden will almost always be left up to a jury,111 yet juries are given little guidance by the statute or the courts for determining the reasonableness of such procedures. As was the case with accuracy, the FCRA does not explicitly explain what types of mechanisms would constitute reasonable procedures. Some courts explain that 108 Id. at 438. The court acknowledged that plaintiff’s claim “would not necessarily withstand summary judgment scrutiny.” Id. The burden of proving the inaccuracy of a report has had the effect of deterring at least some class actions from being brought for § 1681e(b) claims. See, e.g., Williams v. LexisNexis Risk Mgmt., No. 3:06cv241, 2007 U.S. Dist. LEXIS 62193, at *13 (E.D. Va. Aug. 23, 2007) (“Asserting a § 1681e(b) claim for the entire class would render the class-action device useless, note Plaintiffs, because it would require an assessment of whether or not each class member’s report was, in fact, inaccurate.”). 109 Koropoulos v. Credit Bureau, Inc., 734 F.2d 37, 45 (D.C. Cir. 1984). This is not to imply that CRAs have no duty above merely reporting information that is provided to them. See Bryant v. TRW, Inc., 689 F.2d 72, 77 (6th Cir. 1982) (holding that the requirement to follow reasonable procedures “requires a consumer reporting agency to do more than correctly report the information supplied to it by creditors”). Still, a CRA will not be strictly liable for errors contained in a report, assuming it did employ reasonable procedures. 110 Bryant v. TRW, Inc., 487 F. Supp. 1234, 1242 (E.D. Mich. 1980) (noting that “[t]he standard of conduct by which the agency’s action is to be judged is deeply rooted in the law of negligence”). Before enacting the FCRA, a House amendment was accepted that changed the standard for liability from gross negligence to ordinary negligence. H.R. REP. NO. 91-1587 (1970) (Conf. Rep.), reprinted in 1970 U.S.C.C.A.N. 4411, 4416, quoted in Bryant, 689 F.2d at 79. 111 See supra notes 84-85 and accompanying text. 2012] GIVING MEANING TO THE FCRA 289 “[j]udging the reasonableness of an agency’s procedures involves weighing the potential harm from inaccuracy against the burden of safeguarding against such inaccuracy.”112 But this balancing act does little to inform or exemplify. Little direction comes from the Federal Trade Commission (FTC). Although tasked with enforcement of the FCRA,113 the FTC lacks the authority to establish firm interpretations of its rules.114 Guidance from an Unofficial FTC Staff Interpretation provides scant illumination: “The exact nature of a ‘reasonable procedure’ is determined by the circumstances surrounding the operation of credit bureau [sic] and may vary from credit bureau to credit 112 Stewart v. Credit Bureau, Inc., 734 F.2d 47, 51 (D.C. Cir. 1984). FTC STAFF REPORT, supra note 61, at 3. Under the Consumer Financial Protection Act of 2010, the FTC now shares its enforcement role with the newly created Consumer Financial Protection Bureau (CFPB). Id. at 1. In August 2012, the FTC brought its first enforcement action against a CRA for violations of the FCRA in connection with employment background screening. Complaint for Civil Penalties, Permanent Injunction, and Other Equitable Relief, United States v. HireRight Solutions, Inc., 12-cv-01313 (D.D.C. Aug. 8, 2012), available at http://ftc.gov/os/caselist/1023130/ 120808hirerightcmpt.pdf; see also Press Release, Fed. Trade Comm’n, Employment Background Screening Company to Pay $2.6 Million Penalty for Multiple Violations of the Fair Credit Reporting Act (Aug. 8, 2012), available at http://www.ftc.gov/ opa/2012/08/hireright.shtm; Editorial, Accuracy in Criminal Background Checks, N.Y. TIMES, Aug. 10, 2012, at A18, available at http://www.nytimes.com/2012/08/10/ opinion/accuracy-in-criminal-background-checks.html?_r=1&hp. The case, brought against CRA HireRight, addressed FCRA violations that may have come to the attention of the FTC after a class action suit against the company settled last year. See id.; supra notes 55, 102-08. The complaint alleged that HireRight violated several provisions of the FCRA, including §§ 1681e(b) and 1681k. See HireRight, 12-cv-01313, ¶¶ 21-38. A settlement with HireRight, announced the same day the complaint was brought, imposed a $2.6 million penalty on the company and permanently enjoined it from further violations of the FCRA. Stipulated Final Judgment and Order for Civil Penalties, Permanent Injunction, and Other Equitable Relief at 3-5, HireRight, 12-cv01313, available at http://ftc.gov/os/caselist/1023130/120808hirerightstip.pdf. 114 “[T]he Commission was specifically denied the power to issue substantive rules and regulations under the Fair Credit Reporting Act and, therefore, may not specify the precise procedures which credit bureaus must follow on an industry-wide basis . . . .” Bryant, 487 F. Supp. at 1241-42 (quoting FED. TRADE COMM’N, UNOFFICIAL STAFF INTERPRETATION NO. 162). Regardless, it is not clear how much weight would be given to FTC interpretations of the FCRA. The issue of how much deference the courts should give to FTC interpretations brings up administrative law issues that are outside the scope of this note. For a discussion of those issues, see Amanda L. Fuchs, Comment, The Absurdity of the FTC’s Interpretation of the Fair Credit Reporting Act’s Application to Workplace Investigations: Why Courts Should Look Instead to the Legislative History, 96 NW. U. L. REV. 339, 347-58 (2001). Unlike the FTC, the CFPB was granted rule-making authority over the FCRA, but has yet to use this power in the context of employment screening and criminal background checks. See NAT’L CONSUMER LAW CTR., supra note 10, at 35. 113 290 BROOKLYN LAW REVIEW [Vol. 78:1 bureau.”115 Therefore, the FTC is relegated to “litigate the question on a case by case basis.”116 Litigating reasonableness on such a case-by-case basis often reduces the issue to a “battle of . . . witnesses,”117 even where the underlying facts of the case are undisputed, causing jury confusion and making the outcome of a case unpredictable. To illustrate this point, consider the recent case of Adams v. National Engineering Service Corp.118 Deborah Adams brought an action against CRA National Engineering Services Corporation (NESC) after she was denied employment based on a consumer report “which inaccurately attributed to [her] felony and misdemeanor convictions belonging to a person with a different first name . . . [and which] emanated from Virginia, a state to which . . . [she] had no connection.”119 The court denied NESC’s motion for summary judgment, finding that the CRA had clearly reported inaccurate information as “it [was] uncontested that the convictions which NESC reported to Guidant did not belong to Adams,”120 and that, as to the other three elements of a § 1681e(b) claim, a reasonable jury could find in Adams’s favor.121 At trial, the jury found for NESC, and Adams subsequently moved for a new trial.122 The court denied her motion because, although “the facts of this case were generally 115 Bryant, 487 F. Supp. at 1241 (quoting FED. TRADE COMM’N, UNOFFICIAL STAFF INTERPRETATION NO. 162). 116 Id. at 1242 (quoting UNOFFICIAL STAFF INTERPRETATION NO. 162, supra note 115). In the decade following the passage of the FCRA, even the consumer reporting industry was unsure of their responsibilities under this provision. An industry publication from 1977 stated: [Y]ou have some flexibility and the law does not spell out what reasonable procedures you must follow. Congress believed that you and the credit granter and the consumer would best determine that, and if there was a conflict, the courts could decide if the procedure was reasonable. This does not give you the license to do anything you please but it recognizes that a procedure may differ between credit bureaus, and both procedures may be perfectly acceptable. RALPH C. CLONTZ, JR., FAIR CREDIT REPORTING MANUAL App. H-113 (rev. ed. 1977), quoted in Bryant, 487 F. Supp. at 1242. 117 Adams v. Nat’l Eng’g Serv. Corp., No. 3:07cv1035, 2010 U.S. Dist. LEXIS 35489, at *6 (D. Conn. Apr. 12, 2010). 118 Adams v. Nat’l Eng’g Serv. Corp., 620 F. Supp. 2d 319 (D. Conn. 2009). 119 Id. at 333 120 Id. at 330. 121 Id. (explaining that “a reasonable jury could find that NESC failed to follow reasonable procedures,” “that Adams was injured when [her potential employer] revoked its contingent offer of employment,” and “that [it] would not have revoked its contingent offer but for NESC’s inaccurate attribution of various felony and misdemeanor convictions to Adams”). 122 Adams, 2010 U.S. Dist. LEXIS 35489, at *3. 2012] GIVING MEANING TO THE FCRA 291 undisputed . . . , the crux of the jury’s role in this case was to determine whether the undisputed actions of [the] defendants constituted negligent and/or willful violations of the law.”123 The court pointed out that “the distinction between a failure to comply with the FCRA and a negligent or willful failure . . . was crucial to the case and the presumptive basis for the jury’s decision.”124 As the court stated, “The trial constituted a battle of the parties’ expert witnesses who attempted to define what the parties’ responsibilities were under the law.”125 In the absence of guidance as to what constitute reasonable procedures under the statute, litigation under the FCRA remains unpredictable and difficult for consumers to win. C. Proving Causation Can Be Very Problematic Even if a plaintiff is able to prove to a jury that a CRA was negligent or willful in failing to follow reasonable procedures under § 1681e(b), she still has to prove the other elements in a § 1681e(b) claim—notably that the CRA’s negligence proximately caused her injury. To exemplify the challenge that this requirement can present, consider the case of Obabueki v. Choicepoint.126 Abel Obabueki had been arrested for a misdemeanor, and two years after pleading “nolo contendere,” his conviction had been “set aside and dismissed.”127 When applying for a job at IBM, Obabueki did not disclose the conviction on his application, believing that it had been expunged from his record and that it could therefore be omitted under the directions on the application.128 IBM subsequently obtained a consumer report on Obabueki from CRA Choicepoint, which “contained information about [Obabueki’s] 1995 conviction but did not mention the 1997 dismissal order.”129 IBM questioned Obabueki about this 123 Id. at *5-6. Id. at *7. 125 Id. 126 Obabueki v. Choicepoint, 236 F. Supp. 2d 278 (S.D.N.Y. 2002), aff’d sub nom. Obabueki v. Int’l Bus. Mach. Corp., 319 F.3d 87 (2d Cir. 2003). 127 Id. at 280. Obabueki’s arrest had taken place in California, and the “conviction was set aside and dismissed by an order pursuant to California Penal Code § 1204.3.” Id. 128 Id. at 280-81. The form directed that “‘arrests without convictions, [and] convictions or incarcerations for which a record has been sealed or expunged’ need not be included . . . .” Id. at 280 (alteration in original). 129 Id. at 281. 124 292 BROOKLYN LAW REVIEW [Vol. 78:1 incident, at which point he provided them with a copy of the 1997 dismissal order.130 Even after reviewing the dismissal order, however, IBM determined that Obabueki had lied on his application, and rescinded its offer of employment.131 After Obabueki showed the 1997 dismissal order to Choicepoint, Choicepoint sent a revised report to IBM which “stated that [Obabueki’s] criminal record was ‘clear,’ and made no mention of either the 1995 conviction or the 1997 dismissal order.”132 However, IBM did not reinstate its offer of employment.133 Obabueki brought an action against Choicepoint, and the jury found that Choicepoint had “negligently fail[ed] to maintain required procedures designed to ensure the completeness and accuracy of its reports.”134 Choicepoint moved for judgment as a matter of law, and the court granted its motion,135 holding that “the evidence produced at trial . . . did not provide a legally sufficient basis for the jury to find as a factual matter that [Obabueki’s] injury was proximately caused by Choicepoint’s negligence.”136 According to the court, “the inaccuracy of the initial report lay in its failure to include the 1997 dismissal order, not in its failure to report that plaintiff had no convictions whatsoever.”137 The court went on to say that “although this inaccuracy may have been caused by Choicepoint’s negligent failure to maintain procedures designed to ensure the accuracy of its reports, the inaccuracy was effectively neutralized . . . when plaintiff faxed a copy of the 1997 dismissal order to . . . IBM.”138 130 Id. Id. 132 Id. Later, when ruling on Choicepoint’s motion for judgment as a matter of law, the court held that Obabueki had no right to a “clean” report. Id. at 283 (accepting Choicepoint’s assertion that “the initial report would have been correct if it had listed the 1997 dismissal order along with the 1995 conviction”). 133 Id. at 282. 134 Id. at 280. 135 Id. 136 Id. at 284. 137 Id. 138 Id. The court further stated: 131 [A]fter evaluating both the initial Choicepoint report and the 1997 order, IBM concluded that [Obabueki] had lied on the [form]. The fact that this conclusion was based on IBM’s possibly erroneous interpretation of the legal effect of the 1997 order is of no consequence to the issue of whether Choicepoint caused [Obabueki’s] injury. While Choicepoint may have provided IBM with incomplete information regarding [Obabueki], the uncontested evidence offered at trial showed that IBM based its decision on information that was complete and accurate. Thus, Choicepoint’s negligence—which may have caused the 2012] GIVING MEANING TO THE FCRA 293 In the court’s eyes, Obabueki lost the job offer because, basing its decision on a full and complete record, IBM decided that Obabueki had lied. And, as the court pointed out, “the FCRA is not a strict liability statute; Choicepoint’s violation of the statute does not relieve plaintiff of his burden to establish that those violations were the proximate cause of plaintiff’s injury.”139 The fact that Choicepoint later determined that Obabueki’s record had been expunged, and left it off the report, was of no consequence to the court.140 IBM was free to make whatever assumptions it wanted about whether his record was expunged, even if those assumptions were erroneous. IV. HEIGHTENED STANDARDS UNDER § 1681K? DEBUNKING THE MYTH The preceding part of this note dealt with problems associated with litigating a claim under § 1681e(b), which is applicable to CRAs in all cases. Recognizing the importance of employment decisions and the decisive effect that a misreported criminal offense can have on such decisions, § 1681k of the FCRA “deals specifically with consumer reports in the employment context and ‘creates heightened standards for procedures used to collect information for employment purposes.’”141 Under this portion of the FCRA, [w]hen a consumer reporting agency furnishes a report that contains matters of public record likely to have an adverse effect upon the consumer’s ability to obtain employment, it is obligated to do one of two things: (1) notify the consumer contemporaneously with the transmission of the report to the user or (2) “maintain strict procedures” designed to ensure the information is “complete and up to date.”142 Focusing first on the second prong of this test, the standard for CRA compliance in the employment context differs in two ways from the general requirement found in § 1681e(b): (1) the CRA must maintain strict, rather than reasonable, procedures, and (2) these procedures must be meant to ensure production of the initial report—cannot be said to have been the proximate cause of IBM’s decision. Id. at 285. 139 Id. Id. at 285 n.4. 141 Smith v. HireRight Solutions, Inc., 711 F. Supp. 2d 426, 438 (E.D. Pa. 2010) (quoting Dalton v. Capital Assoc. Indus., 257 F.3d 409, 417 (4th Cir. 2001)). 142 Id. (emphasis added) (quoting Dalton, 257 F.3d at 417). 140 294 BROOKLYN LAW REVIEW [Vol. 78:1 that information is complete and up to date, and not just to ensure maximum possible accuracy. However, these changes may be misleading because, in practice, they do not result in any heightened standards at all. Section 1681k does not alter the fact that the FCRA is not a strict liability statute, and the important “distinction between a failure to comply with the FCRA and a negligent or willful failure”143 remains. Therefore, to succeed on a § 1681k claim at trial, a plaintiff still must prove the same general elements as in a § 1681e(b) claim, except that “strict procedures” and “complete and up to date” replace “reasonable procedures” and “maximum possible accuracy.” Although the standard for accuracy presents unique problems in this context,144 courts tend to encounter many of the same problems with the “strict procedure” standard as they did when defining “reasonable procedures.”145 Courts often conflate the two, using reasonable procedures as a way to qualify strict procedures.146 When a plaintiff loses on reasonable procedures, he will likely lose on strict procedures as well.147 And, since a plaintiff must also prove that the CRA’s negligence proximately caused his injury, many of the problems that were present in § 1681e(b) persist in § 1681k(a)(1), making it hard to see how this provision imposes “heightened” requirements at all. Turning to the first prong of the test laid out above, § 1681k(a)(1) explicitly offers CRAs a way to “opt-out” of the socalled “heightened” procedures by providing notice to the consumer at the same time as providing a report to an employer.148 If the agency contemporaneously provides notice, its responsibilities revert back to those under the regular § 1681e(b) requirements.149 Since the notice provides no benefit to the consumer,150 § 1681k, as written and as applied, fails to create a meaningful form of heightened protection in the employment context. 143 Adams v. Nat’l Eng’g Serv. Corp., No. 3:07cv1035, 2010 U.S. Dist. LEXIS 35489, at *7 (D. Conn. Apr. 12, 2010). 144 See infra Part IV.A. 145 See infra Part IV.B. 146 See infra note 157 and accompanying text. 147 See infra notes 158-61 and accompanying text. 148 See 15 U.S.C. § 1681k(a) (2006). 149 See infra note 167. 150 See infra notes 168-73 and accompanying text. 2012] A. GIVING MEANING TO THE FCRA 295 The Accuracy Requirement Is Ineffective As for the threshold question of accuracy in the context of employment, it would seem that § 1681k(a)(2) eliminates the effect of the circuit split as to the definition of accuracy under § 1681e(b).151 Because § 1681k(a)(2) requires that reports be complete and up to date, a CRA that reported a criminal record but left out a subsequent expungement would be foreclosed from using the technical accuracy approach as a defense. The language of the statute, however, does not address the fact that many court records are inaccurate, and that CRAs may be reporting inaccurate information from them. According to the statute, reports of public records are “considered up to date if the current public record status of the item at the time of the report is reported.”152 In Henson v. CSC Credit Services,153 the court held that court records are “a presumptively reliable source.”154 Therefore, the court held that “as a matter of law, a credit reporting agency is not liable under the FCRA for reporting inaccurate information obtained from a court’s Judgment Docket, absent prior notice from the consumer that the information may be inaccurate.”155 The court felt that to hold otherwise “would be unduly burdensome and inefficient” for CRAs.156 Therefore, although agencies are subject to heightened standards in the sense that they must ensure that the report reflects the current public records, those standards do not actually produce reports with greater accuracy overall. B. “Strict Procedures” Is Not Defined by the Statute Additionally, in § 1681k, the statute changes the standard from one requiring reasonable procedures to one requiring strict procedures. While the reasonableness of procedures follows the standard torts definition, “strict procedures” is harder to define, and just like with reasonableness, the statute offers no guidance. Because the FCRA does not provide a definition, the courts are left to decide 151 See Smith v. HireRight Solutions, Inc., 711 F. Supp. 2d 426, 433 n.5 (E.D. Pa. 2010); see also supra Part III.A. 152 15 U.S.C. § 1681k(a)(2). 153 29 F.3d 280 (7th Cir. 1994). 154 Id. at 285. 155 Id. 156 Id. at 285-86. 296 BROOKLYN LAW REVIEW [Vol. 78:1 what Congress intended. The result is that courts punt the question to the jury with very little guidance, using “reasonable procedures” as a qualifier, thereby conflating the two standards. In Smith, the court simply stated that “[w]ithout an extensive analysis of what constitutes ‘strict’ as opposed to ‘reasonable’ procedures, it stands to reason that ‘strict’ is necessarily a more stringent standard.”157 At the summary judgment stage, when a plaintiff brings claims under both § 1681e(b) and § 1681k, courts will usually just evaluate the two claims together.158 After finding that a report was inaccurate under § 1681e(b), there will almost always be a question of fact as to the reasonableness of the procedures,159 and courts will, therefore, assume that one exists as to the “strictness” of the procedures, as well.160 Ultimately, this comes down to the same “battle of the witnesses” that was present in § 1681e(b),161 and the result is often the same in both cases: if consumers fail to show that the CRA used reasonable procedures, they will lose on a claim of strict procedures, as well. In this way, the strict procedures required by the statute remain unclear and undefined, and the supposed heightened requirement that it imposes remains largely unenforced. C. Making Matters Worse—Offering CRAs a Way Out To top off the frustrations consumers face in § 1681e(b) and § 1681k(a)(2), the notice provision of § 1681k(a)(1) explicitly offers CRAs a way to “opt-out” of the provisions of § 1681k(a)(2), allowing CRAs to exclusively follow § 1681e(b) 157 Smith v. HireRight Solutions, Inc., 711 F. Supp. 2d 426, 439 (E.D. Pa. 2010). See, e.g., Williams v. LexisNexis Risk Mgmt., No. 3:06cv241, 2007 U.S. Dist. LEXIS 62193, at *18-19 (E.D. Va. Aug. 23, 2007) (explaining that because the Obabueki court was analyzing the adequacy of procedures under the FCRA, the court analyzed the § 1681k claims under § 1681e(b)). 159 See supra notes 84-85 and accompanying text. 160 See, e.g., Adams v. Nat’l Eng’g Serv. Corp., 620 F. Supp. 2d 319, 332 (D. Conn. 2009) (Because it had “already found that there exist[ed] a factual dispute over whether NESC followed reasonable procedures, the court necessarily [held] that there exist[ed] a genuine issue of material fact as to whether it followed strict procedures.”); Poore v. Sterling Testing Sys., Inc., 410 F. Supp. 2d 557, 572 (E.D. Ky. 2006) (“Just as there is an issue of fact as to whether such reliance and procedures were ‘reasonable’ under § 1681e(b), there is an issue of fact as to whether these actions constitute ‘strict’ procedures under § 1681k.”); Obabueki v. Int’l Bus. Mach. Corp., 145 F. Supp. 2d 371, 399 (S.D.N.Y. 2001) (The court approvingly cited Equifax v. Federal Trade Commission, 678 F.2d 1047, 1049 & n.4 (11th Cir. 1982), for its recognizing that the distinction between reasonable procedures and strict procedures “is clearly not without significance,” yet holding that “the disposition of plaintiff’s respective claims under these sections are parallel in this case.”). 161 See supra note 125 and accompanying text. 158 2012] GIVING MEANING TO THE FCRA 297 without providing anything to consumers in return. Therefore, rather than imposing heightened standards, this notice requirement actually harms consumers without helping to ease their burden in litigation. Given that Congress intended to create heightened standards in the employment context through § 1681k, the inclusion of § 1681k(a)(1) is an enigma. Section 1681k applies when a CRA uses public records to create a consumer report for employment purposes and the information contained therein is likely to have an adverse effect.162 The provision mandates that the CRA do one of two things: either follow strict procedures to ensure a complete and up-to-date report under § 1681k(a)(2), or, at the time such public record information is reported to the user of such consumer report, notify the consumer of the fact that public record information is being reported by the consumer reporting agency, together with the name and address of the person to whom such information is being reported.163 Central to understanding this provision is recognizing the problem the statute creates by permitting the CRA to follow either subsection (a)(1) or (a)(2). Because of that choice, stating a valid cause of action for violation of § 1681k “requires Plaintiff to plead facts to establish both that: (1) Defendant failed to timely notify Plaintiff of the report; and (2) Defendant failed to ‘maintain strict procedures designed to insure’ that the potentially adverse report is ‘complete and up to date.’”164 Therefore, failing to comply with the notice provision does not create strict liability for the CRA; if a CRA fails to send timely notice to the consumer, the consumer still must prove that it negligently or willfully violated § 1681k(a)(2).165 Yet a CRA can evade the supposedly heightened requirements under § 1681k(a)(2) by providing contemporaneous notice to both the consumer and the employer.166 Much like the threshold question of accuracy in § 1681e(b) claims, if the CRA provides this notice to the consumer, then that ends the § 1681k inquiry; the CRA does not have to prove that it followed strict procedures. 162 15 U.S.C. § 1681k(a) (2006). Id. § 1681k(a)(1). 164 Smith v. HireRight Solutions, Inc., 711 F. Supp. 2d 426, 439 (E.D. Pa. 2010) (quoting 15 U.S.C. § 1681k(a)). 165 See, e.g., Adams v. Nat’l Eng’g Serv. Corp., No. 3:07cv1035, 2010 U.S. Dist. LEXIS 35489, at *7 (D. Conn. Apr. 12, 2010) (stating that “Even if [the CRA’s] notice to plaintiff was ‘clearly inadequate,’ as the Court found on summary judgment, it does not necessarily follow that [the CRA] was negligent under the law.”). 166 Smith, 711 F. Supp. 2d at 438. 163 298 BROOKLYN LAW REVIEW [Vol. 78:1 Instead, its responsibility reverts back to the general compliance requirements of § 1681e(b).167 What makes this so troubling is that the contemporaneous notice requirement does not provide any meaningful additional protection to the consumer to warrant exemption from the heightened standards of § 1681k(a)(2).168 Contemporaneous notice does not give the consumer an opportunity to dispute the contents of the report before the potential employer receives it.169 Therefore, “By delaying its meaningful accuracy test, the Act allows agencies and furnishers a free pass that can be painfully costly to the defamed consumer.”170 Thus, the smart CRA would always send notice, and thereby avoid having to litigate whether it followed strict procedures or not. The problems that arise when an employer is the first to receive the report demonstrate how this notice mechanism fails to provide any benefit to the consumer. As discussed earlier, the FCRA places a notice requirement on employers who wish to “tak[e] any adverse action based in whole or in part” on information contained in consumer reports—the employer must “provide . . . the consumer . . . with a copy of the report” before taking such adverse action.171 In theory, “The purpose of the notification requirement is to allow individuals to contact the consumer reporting agency and correct any inaccuracies contained in a report, such as incorrect information regarding an individual’s arrest or conviction.”172 In light of the way the statute is worded, however, this requirement fails to provide the consumer any meaningful chance of disputing the record in time to remain a realistic candidate for the position.173 167 See EEOC, Statement of Maneesha Mithal, Meeting of Oct. 20, 2010, available at http://www.eeoc.gov/eeoc/meetings/10-20-10/mithal.cfm#fn12 (“Regardless of whether a CRA chooses to provide the notice or adopt strict procedures, section 1681e(b) of the FCRA still requires CRAs to have reasonable procedures to assure maximum possible accuracy.”). 168 It is a well-documented problem with the FCRA that it does not provide any form of relief until it is too late. See, e.g., ATTORNEY GENERAL’S REPORT, supra note 39, at 100-01; Elizabeth D. De Armond, Frothy Chaos: Modern Data Warehousing and Old-Fashioned Defamation, 41 VAL. U. L. REV. 1061, 1107 (2007). 169 See De Armond, supra note 168, at 1107. 170 Id. 171 15 U.S.C. § 1681b(b)(3)(A) (2006). 172 Lujan, supra note 6, at 59; see also SEARCH, supra note 2, at 60 (“‘[P]readverse action’ notice is intended to give the consumer the opportunity to review the report for accuracy and completeness before the employer makes a final decision.”). 173 This appears to be a fundamental flaw in the statute from its very inception, related to the remedial nature of the statute. In explaining the requirement that an employer provide notice to an employee before taking adverse action—a 2012] GIVING MEANING TO THE FCRA 299 In Johnson v. ADP,174 plaintiff Eric Johnson ran into this very problem. Johnson was denied employment by defendant staffing agency RHI based on an erroneous criminal record in a consumer report compiled by defendant CRA ADP.175 Initially, RHI provided Johnson with a copy of the report and informed him that his employment application was being placed on hold.176 Fourteen days later, RHI informed Johnson that he was no longer being considered as a candidate.177 Johnson sued RHI claiming that it violated the FCRA by disqualifying him so soon after sending the statutorily required notice, effectively denying him an opportunity to dispute the contents of the report.178 The FCRA allows CRAs thirty days to investigate disputes by consumers.179 Johnson argued that since ADP had thirty days to review his report, RHI should have to wait at least thirty days before taking adverse action against him.180 requirement that was added by the House conferees prior to the FCRA’s enactment— then House Representative Sullivan explained, The House conferees succeeded in assuring immediate notification to any individual, who is rejected for . . . employment because of information in a credit report, of the name and address of the agency which made the report on him. Thus, his right to access to his file is made more meaningful—he will automatically be told where to look for information which may be causing him needless harm. The Senate bill would have required the consumer who had been rejected for . . . employment because of adverse information in a credit file to request, in writing, the name and address of the credit reporting bureau in order to check further into the information which may have caused his rejection. 116 CONG. REC. 36571 (1970) (statement of Rep. Sullivan), quoted in Drury v. TNT Holland Motor Express, 885 F. Supp. 161, 165 (W.D. Mich. 1994). This focus on allowing consumers to fix their report ex post exemplifies how the consumer cannot realistically expect to keep the job offer. And, given the aforementioned inadequacies, the FCRA’s protections seem almost meaningless—if a consumer loses one job, then he might have a chance for another, but he will almost never know that he does not have a clean report until he loses that first job. See De Armond, supra note 168, at 1106. This ex-post approach to correcting inaccuracies presents another problem: since “[t]he process of evaluating and choosing employees is a subjective, hidden process with no oversight[,] . . . the notice requirement is in reality no more than a request that employers act in good faith.” Ruth Desmond, Comment, Consumer Credit Reports and Privacy in the Employment Context: The Fair Credit Reporting Act and the Equal Employment for All Act, 44 U.S.F. L. REV. 907, 919 (2010). Additionally, “there is the risk that the employer will still be influenced by the record in his employment decision and find another ostensible reason not to hire the individual, even if a mistake in the record is corrected before the adverse action is taken.” ATTORNEY GENERAL’S REPORT, supra note 39, at 101. 174 768 F. Supp. 2d 979 (D. Minn. 2011). 175 Id. at 981. “[T]he criminal records incorrectly list[ed] his race as ‘black.’” Id. at 984. 176 Id. at 981. 177 Id. 178 Id. at 981, 983. 179 15 U.S.C. § 1681m (2006). 180 Johnson, 768 F. Supp. 2d at 983. 300 BROOKLYN LAW REVIEW [Vol. 78:1 The court disagreed. Looking to the language of the FCRA, the court stated that there is no statutorily “mandate[d] . . . waiting period between the notice and the adverse action.”181 Still, the court recognized that “Congress’s use of the word ‘before’ shows that there must be some time between notice and action.”182 However, in what is now a familiar problem, the court was left looking at a statute that provided a dearth of guidance into exactly how much time “before” would satisfy the statutory requirement. Ultimately, the court felt that the two weeks that RHI waited between notice and taking adverse action satisfied the requirement of the statute.183 The holding in Johnson shows how consumers are hurt when their employer receives a copy of their consumer report before they have a chance to review it. In fact, just one week after RHI denied Johnson employment, ADP concluded that his criminal record had been inaccurate.184 This conclusion was reached within the thirty-day window provided to CRAs, but it was still too late—RHI had already made its decision. And yet RHI had acted, according to the court, completely within its mandated requirements. Further, the court stated in its holding that “[n]othing in the FCRA requires an employer to consider any correction that a reporting agency might make.”185 Therefore, similar to the problems already shown, once the damage had been done by the inaccurate report, nothing could be done to fix it. But, if the FCRA is a “remedial statute[],”186 as the Johnson court called it, then the statute should actually provide some meaningful remedial relief for injured consumers. Further, if providing a private right of action under the FCRA was intended to be a “part of its enforcement mechanism,”187 then bringing a private action should induce CRAs to employ better practices, something which clearly has not happened. V. THE SOLUTION: AMENDING § 1681K In light of Congress’s intention for § 1681k to impose heightened responsibilities on CRAs, the standards in § 1681k(a)(2) must be enhanced by giving meaning to the 181 182 183 184 185 186 187 Id. Id. Id. at 984. Id. at 981. Id. at 984. Id. at 983. Cahlin v. Gen. Motors Acceptance Corp., 936 F.2d 1151, 1156 (11th Cir. 1991). 2012] GIVING MEANING TO THE FCRA 301 requirement of strict procedures and by providing for greater accuracy in background checks. Further, the statute should not provide CRAs an opportunity to “opt-out” of § 1681k(a)(2) through use of the notice provision of § 1681k(a)(1). Modifying this notice requirement and incorporating it into § 1681k(a)(2) may provide a solution to many of the problems outlined in this note. The fact that Congress thought to include a notice provision in § 1681k shows that the lawmakers at least recognized that the consumer is in the best position to identify and fix a mistake in his consumer report. Courts also recognize that “[t]he consumer is in a better position than the credit reporting agency to detect errors appearing in court documents dealing with the consumer’s own prior litigation history.”188 However, although the right intention exists, the methodology is flawed in at least two important ways. First, notifying a consumer that a report of his criminal history is being prepared will not necessarily move that consumer to request a copy of the report. As happens in many cases, information in a criminal history report may be completely erroneous, and the consumer may not realize that he has any reason to suspect errors.189 The consumer may also be motivated by the fear that if he delays production of the report to the employer, he will be viewed as having something to hide. Second, and most important, for such a method to have any meaningful effect on employment decisions, the consumer must have the ability to inspect and correct the report before a potential employer has the opportunity to see it. Providing notice of the report to the consumer at the same time the report is supplied to the employer fails to provide that protection. Therefore, the first step to amending § 1681k is to require the CRA to provide the consumer with a copy of the report before providing it to the employer.190 A simple way to enforce this would 188 Henson v. CSC Credit Servs., 29 F.3d 280, 286 (7th Cir. 1994). ATTORNEY GENERAL’S REPORT, supra note 39, at 100. 190 Noting the problems inherent in the failure of the FCRA to provide a consumer with the opportunity to review his criminal record ahead of a prospective employer is not a novel observation. See, e.g., De Armond, supra note 168, at 1107. It has also been suggested that as a means of consumer protection, “Congress may want to consider imposing the requirement of giving consumers the pre-reporting opportunity to see the information in all reports of criminal records by consumer reporting agencies.” ATTORNEY GENERAL’S REPORT, supra note 39, at 134. More recently, one student writer, aiming to bolster the efficacy of Ohio’s record-sealing statute, proposed that Ohio adopt a credit reporting law that would give consumers access to their criminal record reports prior to their being provided to prospective employers. Jagunic, supra note 2, at 185 (proposing that Ohio “enact credit reporting legislation that allows a consumer to dispute inaccurate and out-of-date information 189 302 BROOKLYN LAW REVIEW [Vol. 78:1 be to impose strict liability on CRAs who fail to do so. Congress, however, clearly did not intend for the FCRA to create strict liability. Instead, the amended § 1681k(a)(1) should be combined with § 1681k(a)(2), and prior notice to the consumer should be considered a “strict procedure” for ensuring that the report is complete and up to date. In this way, the “strict procedures” required in § 1681k would have a definition more rigorous than, and separate from, the “reasonable procedures” required in § 1681e(b), thereby ameliorating many of the problems found in litigation under § 1681k. The D.C. Circuit Court of Appeals suggested that CRAs could provide reports to satisfy the reasonable procedure requirement of § 1681e(b) in Koropoulos v. Credit Bureau.191 There, in the context of a credit report that was incomplete, yet not erroneous or misleading, the court stated that “the likelihood that consumers will be harmed by incomplete reports that are neither misleading nor erroneous is less, and in many cases it may well be a ‘reasonable procedure’ to let the potential creditor supplement the missing information himself.”192 For reasons already discussed,193 leaving the responsibility of fixing a consumer report in the hands of the employer would not work because the consumer is already harmed if the employer views an erroneous report. But, using the framework suggested by the Koropoulos court, CRAs could satisfy “strict procedures” by providing a report to the consumer before showing it to the employer. The analogy works as follows: if allowing a potential creditor to supplement missing information in a credit report could be considered a reasonable procedure for assuring maximum possible accuracy under § 1681e(b), then perhaps before it is provided to a prospective employer”). And, earlier this year, a report by the NCLC stated that CRAs should “send the consumer a notice that they intend to report the negative information before they send the information to the prospective employer, so that incomplete information can be addressed prior to dissemination,” thereby “ensuring that records are complete and up-to-date, and no sealed or expunged information is provided.” NAT’L CONSUMER LAW CTR., supra note 10, at 34. 191 734 F.2d 37 (D.C. Cir. 1984). 192 Id. at 45. The court reasoned that: Imprecise or incomplete reports that are not misleading, although undesirable, are not as noxious as erroneous and misleading ones. The potential creditor is not misled; he is merely missing information which might be relevant to his decision whether to grant credit. Unlike the case of erroneous or misleading reports, the potential creditor can often correct inaccuracies himself by asking the credit applicants or the source to supply the missing information. Id. 193 See supra notes 168-73 and accompanying text. 2012] GIVING MEANING TO THE FCRA 303 providing a copy of a criminal report to the consumer to verify its accuracy could be considered a strict procedure for ensuring the report is complete and up to date under § 1681k. This approach would benefit both the consumer and the CRA. Consumers would have the chance to review their purported criminal records before they are given to potential employers. CRAs would have a clear example of a compliance mechanism that satisfies the strict procedure requirement. Employers would most likely oppose this proposition, claiming that they will be forced to delay hiring schedules and bear added costs. In Johnson, however, the court rejected a similar argument by the CRA that a waiting period between providing consumers with their reports and taking adverse action “would create untenable constraints on employers” by pausing their hiring process pending resolution of any dispute.194 The court held that the language of the FCRA required some waiting period and that the CRA’s position would “lead to absurd results.”195 Given that the FCRA was enacted to ensure accuracy in the credit reporting industry, it would seem that a short delay in the process would not be beyond the reach of the statute. Most disputes could be cleared up rather quickly, and, at that point, the employer could make a well-informed decision based on accurate data. Additionally, since the report would have already been created, the cost of sending a copy to the consumer first would be minimal. CONCLUSION Criminal background checks can provide important information to potential employers about their prospective employees. At the same time, these consumers must be protected by ensuring that what their potential employers find out about them is accurate and up to date. The FCRA aims to regulate the production of consumer reports and places requirements on the CRAs that compile information pertaining to criminal records. When a consumer is injured because of a flawed report, however, the FCRA provides little meaningful relief. Having lost an opportunity for employment, the injured consumer must then engage in protracted litigation with a low chance for success. Additionally, § 1681k of the FCRA—which 194 Johnson v. ADP Screening & Selection Servs., 768 F. Supp. 2d 979, 983-84 (D. Minn. 2011). 195 Id. 304 BROOKLYN LAW REVIEW [Vol. 78:1 purportedly places heightened standards on CRAs in the context of employment—actually only harms consumers, while helping the CRAs. Because the requirements under that section are inadequately defined, the standard of care required is much the same as the general standard of care required under other sections of the FCRA. Additionally, CRAs can “opt-out” of the socalled “heightened” requirements, without giving the consumer anything in return. Amending the FCRA by combining the two choices in § 1681k can provide a solution to these problems. It would give some guidance to courts and juries on the required heightened standard of care in the employment context, and it would eliminate the ability of CRAs to “opt-out” from compliance. Most importantly, it would give the consumer a meaningful chance of avoiding injury in the first place. Noam Weiss† † J.D. Candidate, Brooklyn Law School, 2013; B.A., Sociology, University of Maryland, 2009. I would like to thank the Brooklyn Law Review staff for their hard work in the editing process. I would also like to thank Professors Anita Bernstein and Marilyn Walter for their helpful comments on earlier drafts of this note. Finally, I would like to thank my family, especially my parents, for their continued and unwavering love and support.