\\jciprod01\productn\C\COL\112-3\COL303.txt unknown Seq: 1 19-MAR-12 16:45 NOTES BENEFIT CORPORATIONS: HOW TO ENFORCE A MANDATE TO PROMOTE THE PUBLIC INTEREST Briana Cummings* A new trend has emerged within the past decade: corporations that seek to turn a profit while affirmatively promoting the public interest. To accommodate this trend, six states have recently enacted legislation creating the benefit corporation, a for-profit entity that is legally obligated to promote both a “specific public benefit” of its choosing and the “general public benefit.” Of all the legal and practical challenges facing successful implementation of this new legislation, perhaps the trickiest—and most important—is the need to ensure accountability to this public purpose mandate. This Note argues that the principal components of the accountability scheme adopted by benefit corporation legislation—(1) certification from an independent third party and (2) annual reports to the public—are ill-suited to the regulation of social welfare objectives. Drawing on lessons learned from the use of similar top-down regulatory mechanisms in corporate, nonprofit, and government contexts, this Note explains why the addition of bottom-up and horizontal mechanisms for “mission accountability” may help foster the capacity and internal motivation necessary for benefit corporations to achieve their public benefit obligations. INTRODUCTION Social enterprise1—the use of market-based strategies to promote the public good2—is “one of the . . . fastest growing areas of small business today.”3 First used in the 1980s and 1990s to designate nonprofits * J.D. Candidate 2012, Columbia Law School. 1. Social enterprises are also referred to as blended enterprises, Dana Brakman Reiser, Blended Enterprise and the Dual Mission Dilemma, 35 Vt. L. Rev. 105, 105 (2010) [hereinafter Brakman Reiser, Blended Enterprise]; blended value organizations; hybrid social ventures, Robert A. Katz & Antony Page, The Role of Social Enterprise, 35 Vt. L. Rev. 59, 61–62 (2010); for-benefit corporations, Alissa Mickels, Beyond Corporate Social Responsibility: Reconciling the Ideals of a For-Benefit Corporation with Director Fiduciary Duties in the U.S. and Europe, 32 Hastings Int’l & Comp. L. Rev. 271, 281 (2009); double bottom line corporations, Anthony Bisconti, The Double Bottom Line: Can Constituency Statutes Protect Socially Responsible Corporations Stuck in Revlon Land?, 42 Loy. L.A. L. Rev. 765, 805 (2009); triple bottom line corporations, Stephen J. Haymore, Note, Public(ly Oriented) Companies: B Corporations and the Delaware Stakeholder Provision Dilemma, 64 Vand. L. Rev. 1311, 1313 n.7 (2011); and multiple bottom line corporations, Thomas Kelley, Law and Choice of Entity on the Social Enterprise Frontier, 84 Tul. L. Rev. 337, 347 (2009) [hereinafter Kelley, Law and Choice]. 2. Linda O. Smiddy, Corporate Creativity: The Vermont L3C & Other Developments in Social Entrepreneurship, 35 Vt. L. Rev. 3, 5 (2010). 3. John C. Weiss III, Commentary, Profits for Nonprofits: An Oxymoron?, Daily Rec. (Balt.), Feb. 20, 2004, at IIA. 578 \\jciprod01\productn\C\COL\112-3\COL303.txt 2012] unknown Seq: 2 REGULATING BENEFIT CORPORATIONS 19-MAR-12 16:45 579 that use earned income strategies, the term “social enterprise” has begun more recently to encompass for-profit corporations4—and for-profit venture capitalists5—pursuing social welfare objectives. Social enterprise is on the rise at top business schools like Harvard and Stanford6 and has been called “one of the hottest movements” among young people in the United States.7 A newspaper search uncovered 1,400 articles with the term “social entrepreneur” from 1997 to 2006, up from 94 between 1986 and 1996.8 Social entrepreneurs complain, however, about “legal and structural limits on their ability to pursue social aims.”9 In response, Maryland and Vermont enacted legislation in the spring of 2010 to provide them with a new “off-the-rack legal form”10: the benefit corporation.11 California, Hawaii, New Jersey, and Virginia followed suit in 2011.12 As of this writ4. Katz & Page, supra note 1, at 59–61, 90; see also Mickels, supra note 1, at 281 (noting “for-benefit corporations” are defined in part as being “free[] to engage in any legitimate business activity” and able to “accept debt and equity investments”). 5. Janet E. Kerr, Sustainability Meets Profitability: The Convenient Truth of How the Business Judgment Rule Protects a Board’s Decision to Engage in Social Entrepreneurship, 29 Cardozo L. Rev. 623, 654–59 (2007) [hereinafter Kerr, Sustainability] (describing “venture philanthropists”); see also Thomas Kelley, Rediscovering Vulgar Charity: A Historical Analysis of America’s Tangled Nonprofit Law, 73 Fordham L. Rev. 2437, 2463 (2005) [hereinafter Kelley, Rediscovering] (noting social enterprise and venture philanthropy are two sides of same phenomenon). 6. Katz & Page, supra note 1, at 60. 7. David Gergen, The New Engines of Reform, U.S. News & World Rep., Feb. 20, 2006, at 48, 48. 8. Kerr, Sustainability, supra note 5, at 629–30. 9. Katz & Page, supra note 1, at 78, 85; see also Kelley, Law and Choice, supra note 1, at 341, 352–66 (explaining “cobbled-together” forms “tend to be expensive to create, burdensome to maintain, and . . . legally insecure” (citations omitted)); Gail A. Lasprogata & Marya N. Cotten, Contemplating “Enterprise”: The Business and Legal Challenges of Social Entrepreneurship, 41 Am. Bus. L.J. 67, 98–111 (2003) (describing “the business and legal challenges that arise when nonprofit organizations pursue entrepreneurial strategies”); Hadley Rose, The Social Business: The Viability of a New Business Entity Type, 44 Willamette L. Rev. 131, 134–45 (2007) (advocating creation of new legal entity); Celia R. Taylor, Carpe Crisis: Capitalizing on the Breakdown of Capitalism to Consider the Creation of Social Businesses, 54 N.Y.L. Sch. L. Rev. 743, 746–63 (2009) (arguing “current laws impair” social enterprise and “creation of new entity forms is needed”); infra note 52 (noting limits on nonprofits’ ability to pursue commercial activities). 10. Katz & Page, supra note 1, at 77, 93. 11. Act of Apr. 13, 2010, 2010 Md. Laws 97 (codified at Md. Code Ann., Corps. & Ass’ns §§ 5-6C-01 to -07 (LexisNexis 2007 & Supp. 2011)); Act of May 19, 2010, 2010 Vt. Acts & Resolves 228 (codified at Vt. Stat. Ann. tit. 11A, §§ 21.01–21.14 (2010 & Supp. 2011)). 12. Act of Oct. 9, 2011, ch. 728, 2011 Cal. Legis. Serv. 5886, 5886–93 (West); Act of July 8, 2011, 2011 Haw. Sess. Laws 682 (codified at Haw. Rev. Stat. §§ 420D-1 to -13 (West Supp. 2011)); Act of Mar. 1, 2011, ch. 30, 2011 N.J. Laws 203 (codified at N.J. Stat. Ann. §§ 14A:8-1 to -2, -4 to -5 (West 2011)); Act of Mar. 26, 2011, 2011 Va. Acts 1146 (codified at Va. Code Ann. §§ 13.1-782 to -791 (2011));. see also S.B. 1463, 2009–2010 Leg. Sess., at 98 (Cal. 2010), available at http://www.leginfo.ca.gov/cgi-bin/postquery?bill_number=sb_ 1463&sess=PREV&house=B&author=desaulnier (on file with the Columbia Law Review) (last visited Feb. 23, 2012) (authorizing flexible purpose corporations); W. Derrick Britt, R. R R R R R R \\jciprod01\productn\C\COL\112-3\COL303.txt 580 unknown Seq: 3 COLUMBIA LAW REVIEW 19-MAR-12 16:45 [Vol. 112:578 ing, legislation enabling benefit corporations has passed both houses in New York,13 and has been introduced in Colorado, Michigan, Pennsylvania, North Carolina, and Oregon.14 A benefit corporation looks like a standard corporation in almost all respects but one: It is legally obligated to promote the public interest. The benefit corporation legislation is devoted largely to establishing a means for enforcing this new obligation. This Note argues that the legislation’s framework for enforcing benefit corporations’ new “public benefit” obligation—through new private rights of action for shareholders, certification and regular monitoring by an independent third party, and regular public disclosure of practices and results—may fail to promote, and may in some cases even impede, meaningful accountability for social performance. Instead of a monitoring scheme focused on compliance with fixed outcomes or procedures, and conducted solely by a generalpurpose certification entity and the public at large, this Note proposes an accountability framework that emphasizes organizational learning and adaptability and that complements external accountability to oversight bodies with internal accountability and accountability to professional peers and stakeholders. Part I explains the reasons for the emergence of for-profit social enterprise, the perceived need for new corporate forms to accommodate it, and the benefit corporation legislation’s efforts to meet that need. Part II describes the broader trend of using transparency-based accountability approaches to regulate corporate, nonprofit, and government entities; explains the theoretical basis for this approach; and critiques its application to benefit corporations. Part III proposes an alternative accountability framework. I. MAKING FOR-PROFIT SOCIAL ENTERPRISE POSSIBLE In Part I.A, this Note first describes the for-profit social enterprise trend in general and the factors that brought it about, then explores the creation of benefit corporations in particular. Part I.B explains the legal and practical problems facing for-profit social enterprise. Part I.C details the legislation’s proposed solution to these problems. Todd Johnson & Susan H. Mac Cormac, Cal. Working Grp. for New Corp. Forms, Frequently Asked Questions: Proposed Amendments to the California Corporations Code for a New Corporate Form: The Flexible Purpose Corporation 1 (2010), available at http:/ /www.primakers.net/files/FAQ%20re%20the%20Flexible%20Purpose%20Corp.doc (on file with the Columbia Law Review) (explaining flexible purpose corporations). 13. S.B. 7855, 233d Leg. Sess. (N.Y. 2010) (authorizing incorporation of benefit corporations). 14. S.B. 11-005, 68th Gen. Assemb., 1st Reg. Sess. (Colo. 2011); S.B. 359, 96th Leg., Reg. Sess. (Mich. 2011); S.B. 26, Gen. Assemb., 2011 Sess. (N.C. 2011); H.B. 419, Gen. Assemb., 2011 Sess. (N.C. 2011); H.B. 2745, 76th Leg. Assemb., 2011 Reg. Sess. (Or. 2011); S.B. 433, 2011–2012 Reg. Sess. (Pa. 2011). \\jciprod01\productn\C\COL\112-3\COL303.txt 2012] unknown Seq: 4 REGULATING BENEFIT CORPORATIONS 19-MAR-12 16:45 581 A. The Drive for Corporations with Double Bottom Lines 1. Beyond Corporate Social Responsibility. — The notion that corporations have a moral obligation to protect the public interest, though often disputed,15 is arguably as old as the corporate form itself.16 In the United States, business methods have long been used in the service of socially responsible,17 public,18 and philanthropic19 ends; the corporate social responsibility (CSR) movement—made more visible by companies like Ben and Jerry’s and The Body Shop20—has been on the rise since the 1970s.21 Unlike previous efforts to combine profit-making with public problem solving, however, double bottom line corporations neither treat social responsibility as incidental to profit-making (as do both corporate philanthropy22 and CSR23) nor see profit-making as incidental to the pur15. Proponents of “shareholder theory” argue “there is one and only one social responsibility of business—to . . . engage in activities designed to increase its profits so long as it [does so] . . . without deception or fraud.” Milton Friedman, Capitalism and Freedom 133 (40th anniversary ed. 2002). Proponents of “stakeholder theory” believe corporations should be obligated to consider the interests of nonshareholders affected by the corporations’ actions. Compare Stephen M. Bainbridge, In Defense of the Shareholder Wealth Maximization Norm: A Reply to Professor Green, 50 Wash. & Lee L. Rev. 1423, 1424–25 (1993) (describing shareholder theory as “mainstream” in corporate law), and Taylor, supra note 9, at 748 (“[T]he profit-maximizing model of the corporate form remains firmly in place.”), with Mickels, supra note 1, at 297 (noting growing public support for stakeholder view), and Lumen N. Mulligan, What’s Good for the Goose Is Not Good for the Gander: Sarbanes-Oxley-Style Nonprofit Reforms, 105 Mich. L. Rev. 1981, 2003–04 (2007) (calling stakeholder theory “the preeminent contemporary normative theory of business ethics”). 16. See Lisa M. Fairfax, Doing Well While Doing Good: Reassessing the Scope of Directors’ Fiduciary Obligations in For-Profit Corporations with Non-Shareholder Beneficiaries, 59 Wash. & Lee L. Rev. 409, 412 n.12, 430–33, 436–37 (2002) [hereinafter Fairfax, Doing Well] (describing longstanding debate between shareholder and stakeholder theories); Mulligan, supra note 15, at 2002–03 (same). 17. See D. Gordon Smith, The Shareholder Primacy Norm, 23 J. Corp. L. 277, 290–91 (1998) (noting frequency of business decisions that take into account stakeholder interests that do not enhance shareholder profit). 18. See Kelley, Rediscovering, supra note 5, at 2462 (describing long history in United States of entrepreneurial solutions to social problems); Smiddy, supra note 2, at 7 (noting postcolonial period when privately owned enterprises financed and built many U.S. turnpikes and bridges). 19. See Kelley, Law and Choice, supra note 1, at 347–48 (describing corporate philanthropy going back to early twentieth century). 20. Mickels, supra note 1, at 274. 21. See Kevin T. Jackson, Global Corporate Governance: Soft Law and Reputational Accountability, 35 Brook. J. Int’l L. 41, 48–52 (2010) (giving history of CSR). 22. See Brakman Reiser, Blended Enterprise, supra note 1, at 107 (explaining that even largest corporate philanthropy, Google.org, “is not really a form of blended enterprise . . . [because] Google makes only a small scale commitment to pursue social goals in relation to its profit-making/taking pursuits”); Katz & Page, supra note 1, at 91 n.195 (noting Delaware corporate law puts ceilings on corporate donations to charity). 23. Mickels, supra note 1, at 277 (describing CSR as “do no harm” approach); Taylor, supra note 9, at 745 (same); see also Kelley, Law and Choice, supra note 1, at 350–52 (distinguishing CSR from social entrepreneurship); Janet E. Kerr, The Creative Capitalism R R R R R R R R R R R \\jciprod01\productn\C\COL\112-3\COL303.txt 582 unknown Seq: 5 COLUMBIA LAW REVIEW 19-MAR-12 16:45 [Vol. 112:578 suit of social welfare objectives (as does a nonprofit engaging in commercial activities24). Instead they seek to serve two “co-equal”25 masters (two bottom lines) at once26—to “expressly measure[] [their] success both in terms of [their] financial performance . . . and [their] success in advancing a social mission.”27 Some have therefore described this new corporate form as an entirely new “fourth sector,”28 joining the ranks of the “big three” sectors of government, business, and nonprofits.29 Others have described it as a convergence of the three.30 2. The Forces Behind the Double Bottom Line Idea. — a. Pressures on the Private Sector. — Pressures to merge profit-making and public pursuits come from both the private (corporate) and public (government and nonprofit) sectors. From the corporate side, conscientious consumers, investors, business partners,31 and potential employees32 are motivating corporations to prove outstanding citizenship33 as a means to distinguish themselves in an increasingly competitive global marketplace.34 In polls, American consumers have identified a company’s social responsibility as an increasingly important factor in their purchasSpectrum: Evaluating Corporate Social Responsibility Through a Legal Lens, 81 Temp. L. Rev. 831, 855–60 (2008) [hereinafter Kerr, Creative Capitalism] (same). 24. Kelley, Law and Choice, supra note 1, at 339 (describing nonprofits as “run[ning] commercial activities on the side in order to cross-subsidize their charitable operations”). 25. Smiddy, supra note 2, at 5. 26. See Brakman Reiser, Blended Enterprise, supra note 1, at 105 (“[A]chieving and governing truly blended enterprise means consistently serving two masters . . . .”). 27. Katz & Page, supra note 1, at 86. 28. See Kelley, Law and Choice, supra note 1, at 338–41 (describing emerging fourth sector); Mickels, supra note 1, at 279–80 (same). 29. See David J. Siegel, The Promise of Intersectoral Collaboration, in Organizing for Social Partnership 47, 50–51 (2010) (describing “big three” sectors). 30. See id. at 51 (giving examples of multinational corporations resembling government in their reach and power, and of colleges and universities, though technically nonprofits, being “likened for some time to business enterprises”). 31. See Ernst & Young, Climate Change and Sustainability: Seven Questions CEOs and Boards Should Ask About “Triple Bottom Line” Reporting 3–7 (2010), available at http://www.ey.com/Publication/vwLUAssets/Seven_things_CEOs_boards_should_ask_ about_climate_reporting/$FILE/Seven_things_CEOs_boards_should_ask_about_climate_ reporting.pdf (on file with the Columbia Law Review) (describing sustainability reports); Jackson, supra note 21, at 83 (describing government procurement policies favoring suppliers privately certified for CSR). 32. See Kerr, Creative Capitalism, supra note 23, at 864 (noting Economist survey that found attracting potential employees was a chief benefit to businesses of having defined corporate responsibility policy). 33. Allison M. Snyder, Holding Multinational Corporations Accountable: Is NonFinancial Disclosure the Answer?, 2007 Colum. Bus. L. Rev. 565, 570–71, 599, 603–04 (noting “growing use of voluntary disclosure by corporations”). 34. See Kerr, Creative Capitalism, supra note 23, at 855 (noting firms’ “‘incentive to create a consumer demand for social responsibility so that they can distinguish their goods in the market’” (quoting Larry E. Ribstein, Accountability and Responsibility in Corporate Governance, 81 Notre Dame L. Rev. 1431, 1453 (2006))). R R R R R R R R R \\jciprod01\productn\C\COL\112-3\COL303.txt 2012] unknown Seq: 6 REGULATING BENEFIT CORPORATIONS 19-MAR-12 16:45 583 ing decisions.35 Investors, too, fearing potential penalties and liabilities associated with poor social or environmental performance,36 or wanting to promote social change as an end in itself,37 are increasingly screening corporations’ nonfinancial performance. In 2007, more than $2.7 trillion—about 11% of all assets under professional management in the United States—were invested in portfolios screened for social responsibility.38 Internationally, 381 major global financial institutions, representing assets of $14 trillion, signed the U.N. Principles for Responsible Investment in 2008.39 A number of publicly available investment products have launched in response to this trend: the Dow Jones Sustainability Indexes in 1999;40 the Financial Times Stock Exchange’s FTSE4Good in 35. See Stephen C. Jones & Paul R. McIntyre, LexisNexis Expert Commentaries, Increased Awareness of Global Warming Is Changing the Climate of Corporate Fiduciary Obligations 1 (2008), 2008 Emerging Issues 2480 (Lexis) (on file with the Columbia Law Review) (noting that in 2008 consumer spending on green products and services was estimated at $500 billion). But see Snyder, supra note 33, at 584–85 (“[M]ost consumers are still unwilling to pay premiums for ‘ethical consumption.’” (quoting Dara O’Rourke, World Bank Grp., Opportunities and Obstacles for Corporate Social Responsibility Reporting in Developing Countries, at vi (2004))). 36. See Ernst & Young, supra note 31, at 8 (stating analysts since 1997 “have issued more favorable ratings to companies that have sustainability strategies in place,” believing such strategies “creat[e] value and reduc[e] uncertainty about future . . . profitability”); John W. Bagby, Paula C. Murray & Eric T. Andrews, How Green Was My Balance Sheet?: Corporate Liability and Environmental Disclosure, 14 Va. Envtl. L.J. 225, 337 (1995) (“Environmental liabilities have grown to such immense proportions that they are important to most investors’ decisions . . . .”). 37. See Jackson, supra note 21, at 93 n.362 (explaining factors behind rise in ethical investing, including current role of “the socially conscious generation of the 1960s” in making investment decisions); Jones & McIntyre, supra note 35, at 10 (describing investor groups pressuring companies to respond to climate change); David Monsma & John Buckley, Non-Financial Corporate Performance: The Material Edges of Social and Environmental Disclosure, 11 U. Balt. J. Envtl. L. 151, 190 (2004) (describing use of investment pressure on companies to persuade government of South Africa to end apartheid). 38. Kelley, Law and Choice, supra note 1, at 358–59 (citing Soc. Inv. Forum, 2007 Report on Socially Responsible Investing Trends in the United States 1, 7, 8 (2008)). Some mutual funds now engage exclusively in socially responsible investing (SRI). Kerr, Creative Capitalism, supra note 23, at 851 n.127. 39. Press Release, United Nations Global Compact, Principles for Responsible Investment Initiative: Signatories Double in One Year; Institutional Investors “Taking Implementation to the Next Level” (June 17, 2008), http://www.unglobalcompact.org/ NewsAndEvents/news_archives/2008_06_17a.html (on file with the Columbia Law Review); see also Justine Nolan, Corporate Accountability and Triple Bottom Line Reporting: Determining the Material Issues for Disclosure 2 & n.8 (Univ. of New S. Wales Faculty of Law Research Series, Working Paper No. 15, 2007) [hereinafter Nolan, Corporate Accountability], available at http://law.bepress.com/unswwps/flrps/art15 (on file with the Columbia Law Review) (noting rise in “ethical investing” is “indicative of international trends”). But see Snyder, supra note 33, at 584 (noting SRIs “constitute only a small portion of total investments”). 40. Dow Jones Sustainability Indexes, http://www.sustainability-index.com (on file with the Columbia Law Review) (last visited Feb. 23, 2012). R R R R R R R \\jciprod01\productn\C\COL\112-3\COL303.txt 584 unknown Seq: 7 COLUMBIA LAW REVIEW 19-MAR-12 16:45 [Vol. 112:578 2001;41 and the Global Impact Investing Rating System (GIIRS), endorsed by the Obama Administration in 2011.42 As a result, corporations are more and more weaving social and environmental performance into their efforts to increase the bottom line. Though some debate the profits to be made through good corporate citizenship,43 GlaxoSmithKline gained “a major competitive advantage” after it started selling 90% of its vaccines at or below cost in developing countries; similarly, Toyota’s brand value increased 47% in the five years after it released the Prius hybrid car in the United States.44 These shifts in consumer and investor preferences have stimulated a “new peak” in social and environmental reporting45: In 2007, companies around the world filed more than 2,300 environmental and social reports, up from only 26 such reports in 1992.46 b. Pressures on the Nonprofit and Public Sectors. — While the private sector has become more attentive to goals traditionally associated with the nonprofit and public sectors, these latter two sectors have increasingly experimented with the methods traditionally associated with the private sector. From the nonprofit side, unpredictable shifts in foundations’ funding preferences, funding cuts beginning during the Reagan Administration,47 and the impact of the recent economic crisis on chari41. FTSE4Good Index Series, http://www.ftse.com/Indices/FTSE4Good_Index_ Series/index.jsp (on file with the Columbia Law Review) (last visited Feb. 23, 2012). 42. Anne Field, Obama Gives Big Boost to Global Rating System for Social Enterprises, True/Slant (Apr. 27, 2010, 3:42 PM), http://trueslant.com/annefield/2010/ 04/27/obama-gives-big-boost-to-global-rating-system for social-enterprises/ (on file with the Columbia Law Review). 43. Compare Kerr, Sustainability, supra note 5, at 660–64 (citing research finding “social and environmental performance is positively correlated with financial performance”), and Cynthia A. Williams, The Securities and Exchange Commission and Corporate Social Transparency, 112 Harv. L. Rev. 1197, 1284 (1999) [hereinafter Williams, Transparency] (“[S]ocial, consumer, and investor trends with respect to the corporation’s relationship with society can eventually affect a company’s profitability . . . .”), with Aaron K. Chatterji & Barak D. Richman, Understanding the “Corporate” in Corporate Social Responsibility, 2 Harv. L. & Pol’y Rev. 33, 34 (2008) (noting “inescapable tension . . . between pursuing beneficial social outcomes and striving for maximum profits” and lack of empirical “evidence showing that good deeds lead to good profits”). 44. Kerr, Sustainability, supra note 5, at 629. 45. Snyder, supra note 33, at 570–71, 599, 603–04. 46. Wachovia Bank, The Greening of America 9 (2008), available at https://www. wachovia.com/common_files/GreeningOfAmerica_031908_sm.pdf (on file with the Columbia Law Review); see also Ernst & Young, supra note 31, at 4 (reporting more than two-thirds of Fortune Global 500 companies publish sustainability or corporate responsibility report); David Hess, Regulating Corporate Social Performance: A New Look at Social Accounting, Auditing, and Reporting, 11 Bus. Ethics Q. 307, 311–13 (2001) (noting “recent resurgence of the social reporting movement in Europe” after worldwide lag during 1980s and 1990s); Jackson, supra note 21, at 71 (noting U.N. Global Compact “boasts over 3,500 corporate signatories”). 47. See Lasprogata & Cotten, supra note 9, at 68, 71 (noting Reagan Administration’s policy of privatization and devolution of federal funding to states created “fiscal crisis” for R R R R R R \\jciprod01\productn\C\COL\112-3\COL303.txt 2012] unknown Seq: 8 REGULATING BENEFIT CORPORATIONS 19-MAR-12 16:45 585 table donations48 have pushed the nonprofit sector to the free market to survive.49 New variants that were not around twenty-five years ago include nonprofits with for-profit subsidiaries and for-profits with nonprofit adjuncts.50 For-profits, which do not face the same limits on debt and equity financing,51 commercial activity,52 and accumulating reserves as do nonprofits, are viewed as better able not only to generate resources53 but also to deploy them efficiently.54 The health care industry, for example, which was once entirely not-for-profit, experienced a “dramatic shift” to forprofit control in the 1990s.55 In large part due to rising health costs and declining Medicare reimbursements, 15% of hospitals were for-profit entities by 1998.56 nonprofits over past three decades); Weiss, supra note 3 (describing “severely diminished support” for nonprofits). 48. See Betsy Nelson, Commentary, Philanthropy Is Growing and Changing, Daily Rec. (Balt.), June 12, 2009, at 10A (“[A]n economic crisis . . . has eroded the resource base of both nonprofits and philanthropies and simultaneously increased the demand for those very resources.”). 49. Kelley, Rediscovering, supra note 5, at 2450–60; see also Kara Kridler, Charity Starting at Home: Nonprofits Launch For-Profit Ventures for Funding, Daily Rec. (Balt.), June 2, 2004, at 1A, 3A (noting “nonprofits throughout the country [are] looking for ways to diversify [their] revenue stream[s]” because “charitable donations [have been] slow to recover after the economic slowdown”). 50. Nelson, supra note 48. 51. See Treas. Reg. § 1.501(c)(3)-1(d)(1)(ii) (as amended in 2008) (prohibiting taxexempt public charities from being “organized or operated for the benefit of private interests such as . . . shareholders”); Model Nonprofit Corp. Act Third Edition § 6.40(a) (2008) (prohibiting nonprofits from paying dividends); Henry B. Hansmann, The Role of Nonprofit Enterprise, 89 Yale L.J. 835, 838 (1980) (providing definitive discussion of nondistribution constraint). 52. See, e.g., Kelley, Rediscovering, supra note 5, at 2472–87 (discussing legal restrictions on nonprofits’ commercial activity); Lasprogata & Cotten, supra note 9, at 74–86 (same). 53. See, e.g., Chatterji & Richman, supra note 43, at 33 (noting “belief that corporations have the financial resources, human capital, and global influence to advance progressive causes”). 54. See Gerald Grace, Education Is a Public Good: On the Need to Resist the Domination of Economic Science, in Education and the Market Place 125, 125–36 (David Bridges & Terence H. McLaughlin eds., 1994) (describing argument that public education “would be delivered more efficiently and effectively to its consumers” if government left its control to “‘hidden hand’ of market forces”); Martha Minow, Public and Private Partnerships: Accounting for the New Religion, 116 Harv. L. Rev. 1229, 1243–44 (2003) (arguing for-profit competition may improve social services); Lewis D. Solomon, The Role of For-Profit Corporations in Revitalizing Public Education: A Legal and Policy Analysis, 24 U. Tol. L. Rev. 883, 925–26 (1993) (arguing for-profit competition may stimulate more creative and efficient school systems); Taylor, supra note 9, at 747 (“[B]ecause of their potential for efficiency and economies of scale, corporations are uniquely positioned to promote social welfare.”). 55. Fairfax, Doing Well, supra note 16, at 415–18 & n.23. 56. Id. R R R R R R R R \\jciprod01\productn\C\COL\112-3\COL303.txt 586 unknown Seq: 9 COLUMBIA LAW REVIEW 19-MAR-12 16:45 [Vol. 112:578 Government services, too, including prisons, foster care, and welfare systems, are increasingly being operated by private, for-profit entities.57 K-12 education was among the last major industries controlled by the public sector; by 2002, for-profit entities ran about 250 public schools, serving more than 120,000 students and accounting for about 10% of the total amount spent on education.58 A shortage of funds is not the only reason for the increasing attention to for-profits as potential vehicles to achieve social objectives. Many see corporations as “so pervasively powerful and comparatively unregulated, in many cases even displacing governments, that society will be well ordered only if those ultra-powerful corporations look beyond the interests of their owners and respond directly to society’s needs.”59 For example, corporations can evade government efforts to regulate wages or pollution by moving operations overseas. In 2000, therefore, the United Nations launched the Global Compact to reach out to corporations as an essential partner in the effort to prevent human rights violations,60 and the 2002 World Summit on Sustainable Development encouraged government, business, and nonprofits to work together to reduce global poverty.61 B. The Call for New Legal Forms The benefit corporation is not the first effort to introduce new corporate forms to support for-profit social enterprise. In 2004, for example, England created the community interest company (CIC);62 in 2008, Vermont enacted the low-profit limited liability corporation (L3C).63 L3C 57. Lisa M. Fairfax, Achieving the Double Bottom Line: A Framework for Corporations Seeking to Deliver Profits and Public Services, 9 Stan. J.L. Bus. & Fin. 199, 200, 207–11 (2003) [hereinafter Fairfax, Achieving]. 58. Fairfax, Doing Well, supra note 16, at 418–19. 59. Kelley, Law and Choice, supra note 1, at 349; see also Chatterji & Richman, supra note 43, at 37, 45 (noting “domestic governments have become increasingly unable to control the social consequences of market forces” because of globalization). 60. Justine Nolan, The United Nations’ Compact with Business: Hindering or Helping the Protection of Human Rights?, 24 U. Queensl. L.J. 445, 446–48 (2005) [hereinafter Nolan, United Nations]. 61. Siegel, supra note 29, at 47. 62. Companies (Audit, Investigations and Community Enterprise) Act, 2004, c. 27, § 26 (U.K.); see also Community Interest Company Regulations, 2005, S.I. 2005/1788, art. 3, ¶ 1 (U.K.) (laying out “community interest test”); Taylor, supra note 9, at 764–66 (explaining CICs). 63. Act of Apr. 30, 2008, 2008 Vt. Acts & Resolves 91 (codified at Vt. Stat. Ann. tit. 11, § 3001(27) (2010)). The L3C form does not really satisfy the “two masters” definition of a double bottom line corporation, see supra notes 22–30 and accompanying text, since “L3C legislation makes clear that although the company may make money, its profit-making activities must serve its charitable purpose.” Smiddy, supra note 2, at 6. See I.R.C. § 4944(c) (2006) (providing that no significant purpose of L3C enterprise can be generating profit); Treas. Reg. § 53.4944-3(a)(1)(ii) (1972) (same). For an explanation of the L3C form, see generally Robert Lang, Ams. for Cmty. Dev., What Is the L3C?: Basic Explanation (2010), available at http://www.americansforcommunitydevelopment.org/downloads/WhatIsThe R R R R R R R \\jciprod01\productn\C\COL\112-3\COL303.txt 2012] unknown Seq: 10 REGULATING BENEFIT CORPORATIONS 19-MAR-12 16:45 587 legislation is now pending or has already been adopted in a number of states.64 Part I.B explains why Maryland, Vermont, New Jersey, Virginia, Hawaii, and California have attempted to create an entirely new corporate form, rather than follow these existing models. Part I.B.1 explains the legal barriers to corporations pursuing multiple bottom lines. Part I.B.2 describes the most important practical barriers to this dual mission—namely, the difficulty raising capital and the need to ensure fidelity to nonfinancial goals—and explains why these practical barriers have not yet been adequately resolved by earlier innovations.65 1. Legal Barriers to Multiple Bottom Lines. — Despite the common perception that corporate directors are legally bound to maximize shareholder wealth,66 existing law in many respects permits directors to take into account nonshareholder interests. Neither the Securities and Exchange Commission (SEC),67 nor the Model Business Corporation Act,68 nor corporate statutory law in Delaware69 or any other state70 requires corporate officers to maximize shareholder wealth. In some scenarios, case law imposes a fiduciary duty to prioritize shareholders’ financial interests above nonshareholder interests,71 but this duty is largely restricted to a narrow set of scenarios (primarily corporate takeovers or reorganizations)72 and, in thirty-three states, has been superseded by soL3C.pdf (on file with the Columbia Law Review); Kelley, Law and Choice, supra note 1, at 371–76. 64. Lang, supra note 63, at 1; see, e.g., Act of Jan. 15, 2009, 2009 Mich. Pub. Acts 249 (codified at Mich. Comp. Laws § 450.4102(m) (2009)). 65. For a list of sources giving a more comprehensive view of the problems facing forprofit social enterprise, see supra note 9. 66. See Dodge v. Ford Motor Co., 170 N.W. 668, 684–85 (Mich. 1919) (ordering Ford to pay out shareholder dividends rather than use money to make more affordable cars for public); Stephen M. Bainbridge, Corporation Law and Economics § 9.2 n.1, at 410 (2002) (“Dodge . . . establish[ed] . . . [the] basic rule . . . that the board [of directors] has a duty to maximize shareholder wealth.”); Einer Elhauge, Sacrificing Corporate Profits in the Public Interest, 80 N.Y.U. L. Rev. 733, 736 (2005) (critiquing view that “traditional fiduciary duties require corporate managers to . . . maximize corporate profits”). 67. Monsma & Buckley, supra note 37, at 201. 68. See Model Bus. Corp. Act § 3.01(a) (2010) (describing permissible corporate purposes). 69. See Del. Code Ann. tit. 8, § 102(a)(3) (2001 & Supp. 2010) (permitting corporate charters to state that firm’s purpose “is to engage in any lawful act or activity”). 70. See Lynn A. Stout, Why We Should Stop Teaching Dodge v. Ford, 3 Va. L. & Bus. Rev. 163, 169 (2008) (“Do [state corporation codes] . . . limit the corporate purpose to shareholder wealth maximization? . . . [T]he answer is ‘not just “no” but “hell no.”’”). 71. See, e.g., Paramount Commc’ns Inc. v. QVC Network Inc., 637 A.2d 34, 43–44 (Del. 1993) (requiring directors to maximize shareholder gains when controlling share in company changes hands); Revlon, Inc. v. MacAndrews & Forbes Holdings, Inc., 506 A.2d 173, 182 (Del. 1986) (requiring same when company goes up for sale). 72. See, e.g., Paramount Commc’ns Inc. v. Time Inc., 571 A.2d 1140, 1142, 1150–51 (Del. 1990) (holding directors may consider nonshareholder interests in business reorganizations that do not involve change of control); Unocal Corp. v. Mesa Petroleum Co., 493 A.2d 946, 954 (Del. 1985) (holding same in context of defending against takeover R R R R \\jciprod01\productn\C\COL\112-3\COL303.txt 588 unknown Seq: 11 COLUMBIA LAW REVIEW 19-MAR-12 16:45 [Vol. 112:578 called “constituency statutes.”73 Constituency statutes, also known as “stakeholder” statutes or “nonshareholder” statutes, explicitly allow corporate directors and officers to consider nonshareholder interests in the context of a takeover struggle, and also, in most constituency statutes, in ordinary business decisions.74 Even in states with constituency statutes that do not apply to ordinary business decisions, or in states (most notably Delaware) without any constituency statute at all, directors who consider nonshareholder interests are effectively insulated from liability by the business judgment rule, under which courts almost always defer to any business decision made with deliberation and in good faith.75 As a result of this rule, one scholar observed “there is no modern case in which a court has overturned a manager’s decision because that decision placed public interests above shareholder interests.”76 2. Practical Barriers to Multiple Bottom Lines. — Probably more significant than the legal challenges facing corporations with multiple bottom lines are the practical ones: raising capital and ensuring fidelity to both “masters.” a. Attracting Capital. — Double bottom line corporations struggle to raise capital because they do not fit the settled categories and expectations of existing sources of capital. On the one hand, they usually cannot promise business investors market-rate returns. On the other hand, foundations and governments are leery of giving grants to a profit-making entity.77 Individuals and corporations may also hesitate to contribute to forprofit social enterprises, especially since only their donations to nonprofits are tax-deductible.78 attempts); Shlensky v. Wrigley, 237 N.E.2d 776, 780 (Ill. App. Ct. 1968) (holding Chicago Cubs directors’ decision not to schedule night games so as to protect surrounding neighborhood did not violate duty to shareholders); Fairfax, Doing Well, supra note 16, at 434–59 (noting although “[c]ourts never formally rejected the shareholder primacy model,” they seem in practice to have moved away from it); Judd F. Sneirson, Green Is Good: Sustainability, Profitability, and a New Paradigm for Corporate Governance, 94 Iowa L. Rev. 987, 1003 (2009) (claiming post-Dodge cases finding duty to maximize shareholder wealth “are few and far between and relatively obscure”). But see Taylor, supra note 9, at 760 (describing successful shareholder suit against socially conscious Ben & Jerry’s founders for resisting lucrative purchase offer from Dutch conglomerate Unilever). 73. For a list, see Fairfax, Doing Well, supra note 16, at 460 n.285. 74. Id. at 412 n.11, 462–64. 75. Id. at 439–40; see also Kerr, Sustainability, supra note 5, at 633–39 (arguing “social entrepreneurship fulfills the board’s fiduciary duties [and] is protected by the business judgment rule”). 76. Fairfax, Doing Well, supra note 16, at 440 (citing William H. Simon, What Difference Does It Make When Corporate Managers Have Public Responsibilities?, 50 Wash. & Lee L. Rev. 1697, 1698 (1993)). But see Taylor, supra note 9, at 760 (describing successful shareholder suit against Ben & Jerry’s for refusing lucrative purchase offer). 77. See Kelley, Law and Choice, supra note 1, at 352–55 (noting difficulties for-profit entities face obtaining funding from government and foundations). 78. See I.R.C. § 170(c) (2006) (permitting donors to deduct contributions to charities from their income taxes). R R R R R R R \\jciprod01\productn\C\COL\112-3\COL303.txt 2012] unknown Seq: 12 REGULATING BENEFIT CORPORATIONS 19-MAR-12 16:45 589 b. Fidelity to Mission. — The second major problem facing hybrid corporations is finding a way to prevent neglect of the social bottom line if the company assumes new leadership (the “‘legacy problem’”),79 if controlling shares are acquired by someone who wants to prioritize profitmaking,80 or in response to market pressures.81 This problem of “locking in assets” to a corporation’s dual mission has not been solved by existing business forms like the closely held corporation, partnership, or limited liability company: Though these forms have greater flexibility than publicly held corporations to pursue nonprofit-making activities, their vulnerability to changes in leadership or ownership leaves little assurance that they will remain committed to these public-interest activities over time.82 Both the CIC and L3C forms try to solve the asset lock problem by restricting payout of dividends; in both cases, this restriction has turned off would-be investors, thus exacerbating the capital formation problem.83 In addition to locking in assets, accountability mechanisms are needed to prevent “greenwashing”—that is, corporations making “‘grandiose statements of corporate citizenship’”84 to enhance their profiles, 79. Katz & Page, supra note 1, at 95–97 (quoting Susan H. Mac Cormac et al., The Emergence of New Corporate Forms: The Need for Alternative Corporate Designs Integrating Financial and Social Missions, in Summit on the Future of the Corporation: Paper Series on Corporate Design 88, 97 (Allen White & Marjorie Kelley eds., 2007), available at http://www.corporation2020.org/SummitPaperSeries.pdf (on file with the Columbia Law Review)); Kelley, Law and Choice, supra note 1, at 359–61 (“Dedicated social entrepreneurs fear that if . . . multiple-bottom-line organizations become financially successful . . . [they] might be purchased by new owners who are dedicated exclusively to generating profits.”). The most famous example is Ben & Jerry’s, a socially responsible corporation whose owners were required by a court to sell to the highest bidder. See Taylor, supra note 9, at 760 (describing purchase of Ben and Jerry’s). 80. Smiddy, supra note 2, at 10 (explaining equity investors can vote on significant company matters and elect company managers). But see Fairfax, Achieving, supra note 57, at 225–28 (arguing shareholders pose no threat to corporation’s social mission because in practice they just rubber stamp whatever directors decide to do). 81. Fairfax, Achieving, supra note 57, at 228–32, 238; see also Fairfax, Doing Well, supra note 16, at 466, 470–72 (describing evidence that, after converting to for-profit status, hospitals reduced charitable services and schools cut costs at expense of student learning). 82. Brakman Reiser, Blended Enterprise, supra note 1, at 107–08. 83. See id. at 107–14 (explaining why CIC and L3C forms have trouble raising capital); Elizabeth Schmidt, Vermont’s Social Hybrid Pioneers: Early Observations and Questions to Ponder, 35 Vt. L. Rev. 163, 186–89 (2010) (explaining same based on interviews of early users of L3C form); see also Regulator of Cmty. Interest Cos., Dep’t for Bus. Innovation & Skills, Summary of the Responses to the Consultation on the Dividend and Interest Caps 8 (2009), available at http://www.bis.gov.uk/assets/bispartners/ cicregulator/docs/consultations/09-1645-community-interest-companies-consultationcaps-summary-of-responses.pdf (on file with the Columbia Law Review) (describing financiers’ complaints that dividend caps in CICs “unduly limit[ ] incentive to those that might make an equity investment”). 84. Oliver F. Williams, The UN Global Compact: The Challenge and the Promise, 14 Bus. Ethics Q. 755, 762 (2004) (quoting S. Prakash Sethi, Global Compact Is Another Exercise in Futility, Fin. Express (New Delhi, India), Sept. 7, 2003, available at http://www. R R R R R R R R \\jciprod01\productn\C\COL\112-3\COL303.txt 590 unknown Seq: 13 COLUMBIA LAW REVIEW 19-MAR-12 16:45 [Vol. 112:578 without actually accomplishing much for people in need85—and to simply prevent directors from using the pretense of pursuing nonshareholder interests to advance their own personal interests without any accountability.86 C. The Benefit Corporation Solution: Accountability to Mission The benefit corporation statutes address the legal barriers to double bottom lines by protecting directors of benefit corporations from liability for considering nonshareholder interests, both in the ordinary course of business and in the context of takeovers.87 The aim is to remove any lingering doubt left by constituency statutes about the scope of benefit corporations’ liabilities.88 The bulk of the legislation, however, addresses the practical barriers to successful hybrid corporations, by providing a framework for “mission accountability”—that is, for monitoring and enforcing benefit corporations’ effective pursuit of their public interest mission.89 In this way, the financialexpress.com/news/global-compact-is-another-exercise-in-futility/91447/0 (on file with the Columbia Law Review)). 85. Kelley, Law and Choice, supra note 1, at 348; see also Mickels, supra note 1, at 277 n.43 (noting criticism of corporate “philanthropists” who “‘[m]ake as much money as [they] can, even if they exploit the poor to do so—but then donate a tiny portion of the profits for social causes’” so they can brag about their generosity (quoting Muhammad Yunus, Creating a World Without Poverty 16 (2007))); Nolan, United Nations, supra note 60, at 462 (noting it has “consistently been alleged that a number of companies are simply using their participation in the [U.N.] Global Compact as a marketing tool”); John Tyler, Negating the Legal Problem of Having “Two Masters”: A Framework for L3C Fiduciary Duties and Accountability, 35 Vt. L. Rev. 117, 143 (2010) (noting “concern about possible abuse [of the L3C form] and wariness about the potential to mislead both the public and foundations”). 86. Fairfax, Doing Well, supra note 16, at 433; see also Sneirson, supra note 72, at 1015 (describing same concern). 87. Md. Code Ann., Corps. & Ass’ns § 5-6C-07(C) (LexisNexis Supp. 2011); Vt. Stat. Ann. tit. 11A, § 21.09(a)(3) (Supp. 2011); see also Dave Gram, States Move to Let Firms Pursue Social Mission, UTSanDiego.com (Apr. 11, 2010), http://utsandiego.com/news/ 2010/apr/11/states-move-to-let-firms-pursue-social-mission (on file with the Columbia Law Review) (describing Vermont’s benefit corporation legislation as enabling socially responsible companies like Ben & Jerry’s to avoid takeover motivated by finances alone). Benefit corporations are therefore required to incorporate in a state with a constituency statute. Brakman Reiser, Blended Enterprise, supra note 1, at 115. 88. Benefit Corp Info. Ctr., Legal FAQs [hereinafter Benefit Corp, Legal FAQs], http://benefitcorp.net/for-attorneys/legal-faqs (on file with the Columbia Law Review) (last visited Jan. 20, 2012) (“[T]he lack of case law regarding [constituency] statutes leaves . . . directors . . . with a lack of clarity about how a court would rule if directors made a decision based on broader considerations than just the highest offer.”); see also supra notes 73–74 and accompanying text (describing constituency statutes). 89. For an explanation of “mission,” or “performance,” accountability, see Robert D. Behn, Rethinking Democractic Accountability 9–10 (2001) (presenting concept in government context); Dana Brakman Reiser, Enron.org: Why Sarbanes-Oxley Will Not Ensure Comprehensive Nonprofit Accountability, 38 U.C. Davis L. Rev. 205, 208, 212–15, 226–30 (2004) [hereinafter Brakman Reiser, Enron.org]; Alnoor Ebrahim, The Many Faces of Nonprofit Accountability 9–10 (Harvard Bus. Sch., Working Paper No. 10-069, R R R R R \\jciprod01\productn\C\COL\112-3\COL303.txt 2012] unknown Seq: 14 REGULATING BENEFIT CORPORATIONS 19-MAR-12 16:45 591 legislation aims not only to lock in assets to benefit corporations’ dual commitments and prevent greenwashing, but also to help these businesses raise capital—at least from some sources90—by signaling to socially responsible investors, consumers, donors, and potential employees and business partners91 that a certified benefit corporation is in fact producing social and environmental returns worthy of financial support.92 This Part lays out the accountability framework created by the benefit corporation legislation, focusing on for what (Part I.C.1) and to whom (Part I.C.2) the corporations are made accountable. 1. Accountable for What? — Under existing law, corporate and nonprofit directors already owe fiduciary duties of care, good faith, and loyalty.93 In neither the corporate nor the nonprofit context, however, can these traditional duties effectively enforce social and environmental obligations. The duties of care and good faith concern how decisions are 2010) (distinguishing performance and mission accountability and noting relationship between them). 90. The signaling approach will not work for foundations, which are limited to making qualified “program-related investments” (PRIs). See Smiddy, supra note 2, at 6, 13 n.21 (noting that, in contrast to other companies, “[c]ompanies organized as an L3C would meet specified criteria qualifying them as eligible to be the recipient of PRIs made by foundations”). 91. See supra Part I.A.2.a (describing desire of consumers, investors, suppliers, and employees to support socially responsible businesses). 92. See, e.g., Lawmakers Back “Benefit Corporations,” Wash. Post, Mar. 31, 2010, at A13 (“House bill sponsor . . . said . . . that [the Maryland benefit corporation legislation] creates the ‘socially and environmentally-conscious branding that hundreds of corporations’ are seeking.”); Letter from Michael H. Shuman to Jamie Raskin, Senator, Md. Senate (Feb. 24, 2010), available at http://www.bcorporation.net/resources/bcorp/ documents/Shuman-testimony.pdf (on file with the Columbia Law Review) (arguing proposed benefit corporation legislation in Maryland would help conscientious consumers “find and selectively purchase [benefit corporations’] goods and serves [sic]” and help “attract[] like-minded investors”); Field, supra note 42 (“The underlying goal [of the benefit corporation certification system] is all about raising money . . . .”); see also Katz & Page, supra note 1, at 71–74, 93–94 (suggesting “active monitoring and accountability” of for-profit social enterprises as means to signal their social returns to “employees willing to accept below-market compensation” as well as to “mission-sympathetic” investors, donors, and consumers); Kelley, Law and Choice, supra note 1, at 361, 367 (noting “[s]ocial entrepreneurs believe that to succeed in gaining support . . . from the various sources of capital they need access to—charitable, governmental, and private—they must create a recognizable brand” that inspires “confidence that a corporation’s expressed commitment to nonfinancial bottom lines is more than mere marketing”). But see Chatterji & Richman, supra note 43, at 50 (“While social investing and consumption have been increasing in recent years . . . it is still unclear whether consumer and investor based strategies . . . have the potential to engage a broad swath of society.”). 93. See, e.g., Del. Code Ann. tit. 8, § 141(j) (2001) (applying same enabling rules to business and nonprofit corporations); Model Nonprofit Corp. Act § 8.30 (2008) (explaining nonprofit directors’ fiduciary duties); Linda Sugin, Resisting the Corporatization of Nonprofit Governance: Transforming Obedience into Fidelity, 76 Fordham L. Rev. 893, 894 (2007) (“The ALI Principles of the Law of Nonprofit Organizations explicitly adopted fiduciary obligations for nonprofit directors that were based on the principles applicable to business boards.”). R R R R R \\jciprod01\productn\C\COL\112-3\COL303.txt 592 unknown Seq: 15 COLUMBIA LAW REVIEW 19-MAR-12 16:45 [Vol. 112:578 made, not what their substantive content is;94 the duty of loyalty requires only that directors place the corporation’s interests above their own personal interests.95 Under existing law, then, directors escape liability as long as they do “not act with complete disregard to the consequences of their decisions”96 and do not steal.97 Some say nonprofit directors owe the additional duty of obedience to mission—that is, the duty to carry out the mission of the organization as expressed in the legal documents creating it—but neither the Revised Model Nonprofit Corporation Act nor the American Law Institute’s (ALI’s) Draft Principles recognizes this duty.98 The benefit corporation legislation adds in two ways to these duties. First, going beyond most constituency statutes, it requires directors to consider the impact of a proposed buyout not just on shareholders but on all stakeholders (employees, suppliers, customers, and the wider community).99 Second, and more importantly, it requires them, in the ordinary course of business, to create a “material, positive impact,” both with respect to any “specific public benefit” they espouse and with respect to the “general public benefit.”100 This latter obligation is meant to guard against a company pursuing a single narrow public good, such as clean94. Model Bus. Corp. Act § 8.30 & cmt. (2010) (“Section 8.30 sets forth the standards of conduct for directors by focusing on the manner in which directors perform their duties, not the correctness of the decisions made.”); Fairfax, Doing Well, supra note 16, at 439 n.157 (“Most states have enacted statutes to this effect.”). 95. See Principles of the Law of Nonprofit Orgs. § 310 cmt. (a)(1) (Tentative Draft No. 1, 2007) (requiring directors, under duty of loyalty, to act in organization’s best interests and to handle conflicts of interest appropriately); Harvey J. Goldschmid, The Fiduciary Duties of Nonprofit Directors and Officers: Paradoxes, Problems, and Proposed Reforms, 23 J. Corp. L. 631, 646–49 (1998) (describing duty of loyalty as concerned only with fraud, self-dealing, and conflicts of interest). 96. Sugin, supra note 93, at 911, 913 (explaining “the duty of care and the duty of loyalty are composed largely of procedural or structural elements, as opposed to substantive ones”); see also In re Walt Disney Co. Derivative Litig., 825 A.2d 275, 289 (Del. Ch. 2003) (alleging breach of good faith when “defendant directors consciously and intentionally disregarded their responsibilities” (emphasis omitted)); Kerr, Creative Capitalism, supra note 23, at 835–39 (describing limited scope of duties of care and good faith). 97. Katz & Page, supra note 1, at 95. 98. Sugin, supra note 93, at 897; see also Principles of the Law of Nonprofit Orgs. § 300 cmt. g(3) (“These Principles . . . do not employ the terminology of a duty of obedience.”). 99. Md. Code Ann., Corps. & Ass’ns § 5-6C-07(a)(1) (LexisNexis 2007 & Supp. 2011); Vt. Stat. Ann. tit. 11A, § 21.09(a)(1) (2010 & Supp. 2011); see also Fairfax, Doing Well, supra note 16, at 461 n.290 (explaining most states’ constituency statutes use permissive language); Taylor, supra note 9, at 750 (“[C]orporate constituency statutes have not fulfilled the promise they initially seemed to offer.”); Benefit Corp, Legal FAQs, supra note 88 (“Constituency statutes are permissive . . . . The objective of Benefit corporation legislation is to . . . require directors to consider non-financial interests.” (emphasis added)); supra notes 74–76 and accompanying text (discussing constituency statutes). 100. Md. Code Ann., Corps. & Ass’ns §§ 5-6C-01(c)–(d), 5-6C-06; Vt. Stat. Ann. tit. 11A, §§ 21.03(a)(4), 21.08(a)–(c). R R R R R R R R R \\jciprod01\productn\C\COL\112-3\COL303.txt 2012] unknown Seq: 16 REGULATING BENEFIT CORPORATIONS 19-MAR-12 16:45 593 ing up a river, while ignoring its effect on the public in every other respect.101 The legislation declines to define “material positive impact,” “specific public benefit,” or “general public benefit,” for fear of chilling market innovation to develop performance standards and deterring businesses from incorporating under this new form.102 Instead, it leaves definition of these terms in the short term to the courts and in the long term to market forces leading to recognized standards for assessing performance.103 2. Accountable to Whom? — Having created these obligations, the legislation then sets out a framework for enforcing them. First, it gives shareholders and directors standing to sue to enforce them. Second, it gives an independent third-party auditor the power to grant or withhold certification. Third, it requires benefit corporations to give an account of their performance to the public at large. a. Accountability to Shareholders. — Shareholders and directors are given standing to commence or maintain a “benefit enforcement proceeding” for “failure to pursue the general public benefit purpose of the benefit corporation or any specific public benefit purpose set forth in its articles of incorporation.”104 Shareholder suits have historically played a limited role in corporate accountability, however, both because of procedural hurdles105 and because of substantive rules like the business judgment rule.106 In the nonprofit context, too, lack of financial incentive or standing and collective action problems have made shareholder suits an ineffective tool for mission accountability.107 Perhaps in recognition of this, the benefit corporation legislation devotes much more attention to 101. Benefit Corp, Legal FAQs, supra note 88. 102. Id.; see also Md. Code Ann., Corps. & Ass’ns § 5-6C-01(d) (suggesting a “specific public benefit” may include “providing . . . beneficial products or services,” “promoting economic opportunity . . . beyond the creation of jobs in the normal course of business,” “preserving the environment,” “improving human health,” “promoting the arts, sciences, or advancement of knowledge,” “increasing the flow of capital to entities with a public benefit purpose,” or “accomplish[ing] any other . . . benefit for society or the environment” (emphasis added)); Vt. Stat. Ann. tit. 11A, § 21.03(a)(6) (giving largely identical suggestions). 103. Benefit Corp, Legal FAQs, supra note 88. 104. Vt. Stat. Ann. tit. 11A, §§ 21.09(e), 21.13. 105. Fairfax, Achieving, supra note 57, at 221–25, 241. 106. Id. at 241 (“One can expect that the courts’ traditional reluctance to overturn corporate decisions [because of business judgment rule] would apply with even greater force in the context of double bottom line companies . . . .”); see supra notes 75–76 and accompanying text (explaining business judgment rule). 107. Mulligan, supra note 15, at 1988; see also Jaclyn A. Cherry, Update: The Current State of Nonprofit Director Liability, 37 Duq. L. Rev. 557, 571 (1999) (explaining damages from derivative actions flow back to nonprofit itself); Sugin, supra note 93, at 906–08 (arguing shareholders lack incentive to enforce interests of broader public); Denise Ping Lee, Note, The Business Judgment Rule: Should It Protect Nonprofit Directors?, 103 Colum. L. Rev. 925, 935 (2003) (discussing collective action problems). R R R R R R \\jciprod01\productn\C\COL\112-3\COL303.txt 594 unknown Seq: 17 COLUMBIA LAW REVIEW 19-MAR-12 16:45 [Vol. 112:578 outlining the auditing and reporting requirements for the new corporate form than the shareholder lawsuit provisions. b. Accountability to a Third-Party Auditor. — Perhaps the most important prong of the legislation’s accountability framework,108 certification, requires that a benefit corporation spell out its public interest values in its charter; fulfill certain reporting requirements (discussed below); and submit to third-party auditing of its societal impact, as measured against an independent “third party standard.”109 Certification standards and performance evaluations are currently provided by many third-party standards organizations, including Global Reporting Initiative (GRI), Greenseal, Underwriters Laboratories, ISO2600, Green American, and B Lab,110 the nonprofit that drafted the benefit corporation legislation in Maryland and Vermont.111 To receive and maintain “B” certification, benefit corporations must earn at least eighty out of two hundred points on the B Impact Assessment.112 c. Accountability to the Public. — Finally, the legislation makes benefit corporations accountable to the public in two ways. First, the B label itself serves a “branding” function to alert the public that the benefit corporation has undergone scrutiny.113 Second, benefit corporations must publish an annual Benefit Report online.114 The report must disclose (1) the findings from the third-party audits; (2) board minutes showing the directors discussed the impact of their decisions on employees, suppliers, consumers, the community, the environment, and other stakeholders; and 108. See Taylor, supra note 9, at 760 (“[T]he B corporation ‘model’ amounts to little more than a new certification scheme . . . .”). 109. Md. Code Ann., Corps. & Ass’ns § 5-6C-01(e) (LexisNexis 2007 & Supp. 2011); Vt. Stat. Ann. tit. 11A, § 21.03(a)(4). 110. Benefit Corp Info. Ctr., List of Standards, http://benefitcorp.net/selecting-athird-party-standard/list-of-standards (on file with the Columbia Law Review) (last visited Feb. 23, 2012). 111. Kelley, Law and Choice, supra note 1, at 366–67. B Lab, “[d]edicated to using the power of business to solve social and environmental problems,” has three primary initiatives: advancing public policies such as the benefit corporation legislation, creating the B Corporation certification system, and developing the Global Impact Investing Ratings System (GIIRS). Certified B Corp., B Lab, BCorporation.net [hereinafter B Lab], http://www.bcorporation.net/new-about (on file with the Columbia Law Review) (last visited Jan. 20, 2012); see supra note 42 and accompanying text (noting Obama Administration’s endorsement of GIIRS). 112. B Corp Certification Certification Overview, BCorporation.net, http://www. bcorporation.net/Certification-Overview (on file with the Columbia Law Review) (last visited Feb. 23, 2012). B Lab’s rating system, the B Lab Impact Assessment, was originally launched in 2007. Version 3.0 was launched in spring 2011. Certified B Corp., B Lab Governance, BCorporation.net, http://www.bcorporation.net/Governance (on file with the Columbia Law Review) (last visited Feb. 23, 2012). 113. See supra notes 90–92 and accompanying text (describing signaling function of certification). 114. Md. Code Ann., Corps. & Ass’ns § 5-6C-08; Vt. Stat. Ann. tit. 11A, §§ 21.10, 21.14. The report must also be delivered to all shareholders and the Secretary of State. Md. Code Ann., Corps. & Ass’ns § 5-6C-08; Vt. Stat. Ann. tit. 11A, §§ 21.10, 21.14. R R R R \\jciprod01\productn\C\COL\112-3\COL303.txt 2012] unknown Seq: 18 REGULATING BENEFIT CORPORATIONS 19-MAR-12 16:45 595 (3) the statement of an independent Benefit Director indicating how the board reached each material decision.115 In this way, the report is intended to create accountability both for process (how decisions are reached) and for results (as measured in the third-party audits).116 II. THE TRANSPARENCY PANACEA The benefit corporation legislation follows a transparency-based accountability model. Part II.A describes the current popularity of this model and the theory behind it. Part II.B argues that, by applying this model to corporate social performance, the benefit corporation legislation may be taking the wrong approach regarding both for what and to whom benefit corporations should be accountable. A. Public Disclosure: The New Accountability Paradigm This Part discusses the broader transparency-based accountability trend. Part II.A.1 describes the current popularity of auditing and disclosure strategies across sectors. Part II.A.2 explains the theoretical framework underlying the use of these strategies. 1. The Trend. — Justice Louis Brandeis famously called sunlight “the best of disinfectants” nearly a century ago117 and U.S. securities laws have relied on record-keeping and disclosure since the stock market crash of 1929.118 A series of corporate119 and nonprofit120 accounting scandals in the 1990s, however, and the economic collapse of 2007–2008121 stimulated “palpable public demand” for “greater transparency and accountability from institutions that have significant political, economic, or social power”122 and, consequently, an unprecedented surge in disclosure115. Md. Code Ann., Corps. & Ass’ns § 5-6C-08; Vt. Stat. Ann. tit. 11A, § 21.10, 21.14. 116. Benefit Corp, Legal FAQs, supra note 88. 117. Louis D. Brandeis, Other People’s Money and How the Bankers Use It 92 (1914). 118. Adam Sulkowski & Steven White, Financial Performance, Pollution Measures, and the Propensity to Use Corporate Responsibility Reporting: Implications for Business and Legal Scholarship, 21 Colo. J. Int’l Envtl. L. & Pol’y 491, 492–93 (2010). 119. See Monsma & Buckley, supra note 37, at 173 n.77 (citing Enron, WorldCom, and Arthur Andersen scandals); see also Donald C. Langevoort, Internal Controls After Sarbanes-Oxley: Revisiting Corporate Law’s “Duty of Care as Responsibility for Systems,” 31 J. Corp. L. 949, 954 (2006) [hereinafter Langevoort, Internal Controls] (explaining factors leading to these scandals). 120. See James J. Fishman, Improving Charitable Accountability, 62 Md. L. Rev. 218, 219 n.1 (2003) (discussing misconduct by nonprofit directors); Lasprogata & Cotten, supra note 9, at 72–73 (citing scandals at United Way of America and Red Cross); Mulligan, supra note 15, at 1982 (noting U.S. “nonprofit sector . . . recently has been pummeled with a spate of . . . scandals”). 121. See Sugin, supra note 93, at 893–94 (describing outcry over excessive executive compensation); Jones & McIntyre, supra note 35, at 10 (describing regulatory fallout of subprime mortgage crisis and global credit market collapse). 122. Langevoort, Internal Controls, supra note 119, at 965. R R R R R R R \\jciprod01\productn\C\COL\112-3\COL303.txt 596 unknown Seq: 19 COLUMBIA LAW REVIEW 19-MAR-12 16:45 [Vol. 112:578 based accountability reforms.123 In 2002, Congress passed “the most significant federal securities legislation since the 1930s,”124 the SarbanesOxley Act, which imposes extensive disclosure, corporate governance, and auditing requirements on large publicly traded corporations.125 On its heels followed a series of Sarbanes-Oxley-like proposals for nonprofits126 by the IRS,127 state legislatures,128 and others.129 Unifying these reforms are the requirements of public financial disclosure and thirdparty auditing.130 Many see in this emerging “transparency trend”131 a promising means to improve accountability for social and environmental perform123. See Ebrahim, supra note 89, at 12 (“Disclosure statements and reports are among the most widely used tools of accountability . . . .”); Jones & McIntyre, supra note 35, at 10 (“Changes [in corporate regulation] over the last decade have related primarily to disclosure obligations . . . .”). 124. Publisher’s Editorial Staff 2008, LexisNexis, Closely Held Corporations and Nonprofits: Implications of Adopting SOX Governance Measures 1 (2008), 2008 Emerging Issues 2990 (Lexis) [hereinafter Closely Held Corporations] (on file with the Columbia Law Review). 125. Sarbanes-Oxley Act of 2002, Pub. L. No. 107-204, pmbl., 116 Stat. 745, 745 (codified in scattered sections of 15, 18, 28, and 29 U.S.C. (2006)) (describing statute as an “Act [t]o protect investors by improving the accuracy and reliability of corporate disclosures made pursuant to the securities laws”); see also Brakman Reiser, Enron.org, supra note 89, at 243 (describing Sarbanes-Oxley as response to “spate of for-profit corporate scandals”). 126. Closely Held Corporations, supra note 124, at 3–5. 127. In 2008, the IRS overhauled Form 990, which requires public disclosure of nonprofits’ investments, expenses, compensation, activities, etc. Adrian Burns, Dramatic Changes in Nonprofit Sector Usher in 990 Overhaul, Business First (Columbus) (July 17, 2008, 4:27 PM), http://www.bizjournals.com/columbus/stories/2008/07/21/focus1.html (on file with the Columbia Law Review); see I.R.C. § 6104 (2006) (explaining disclosures required by Form 990); I.R.C. § 6104(d)(1)(A), (B) (requiring completed Form 990s to be publicly available); Peter Swords, Nonprofit Coordinating Comm. of N. Y., How to Read the IRS Form 990 and Find Out What It Means (May 2006), http://www.npccny.org/Form _990/990.htm (on file with the Columbia Law Review) (providing nontechnical overview of 990 Form); see also IRS and Financial Documentation, GuideStar, http://www2.guidestar. org/rxg/about-us/irs-and-financial-documentation.aspx (on file with the Columbia Law Review) (last visited Feb. 23, 2012) (presenting disclosures required by Form 990). 128. California, Connecticut, Kansas, Maine, and New Hampshire enacted such reforms. Mulligan, supra note 15, at 1992. Massachusetts and New York are considering more aggressive proposals. Closely Held Corporations, supra note 124, at 4. Much of the financial documentation states require from nonprofits is available online. Mulligan, supra note 15, at 1990. 129. See, e.g., Marion R. Fremont-Smith, The Search for Greater Accountability of Nonprofit Organizations: Recent Legal Developments and Proposals for Change, 76 Fordham L. Rev. 609, 609 (2007) (arguing law of charities is moving toward corporate model of accountability that focuses on audits and financial controls); Panel on the Nonprofit Sector, Strengthening Transparency, Governance, Accountability of Charitable Organizations: A Final Report to Congress and the Nonprofit Sector 4–8 (2005), available at http://www.fmaonline.net/media/Executive%20Summary.pdf (proposing SarbanesOxley-like regulations for nonprofits). 130. Mulligan, supra note 15, at 1983, 1992. 131. Monsma & Buckley, supra note 37, at 158–59. R R R R R R R R R \\jciprod01\productn\C\COL\112-3\COL303.txt 2012] unknown Seq: 20 REGULATING BENEFIT CORPORATIONS 19-MAR-12 16:45 597 ance—not only by nonprofits,132 government,133 and hybrid organizations,134 but also traditional for-profits.135 In 2001, for example, France became the first country to mandate systematic disclosure of social and environmental performance by major corporations.136 Recent statutes and guidelines in Australia,137 England,138 and South Africa139 require social performance disclosures by corporations or investment funds. In the United States, most corporate social and environmental reporting is still voluntary,140 though some of the federal securities laws explicitly require environmental disclosure,141 additional mandates for disclosure of climate change-related risks may be on the horizon,142 and many argue 132. See, e.g., Sugin, supra note 93, at 924 (arguing “[a]dditional disclosure requirements may be the most effective mechanism for enforcing obedience” to mission by nonprofit directors). 133. See, e.g., Patricia M. Broadfoot, Education, Assessment and Society 104 (1996) (noting assessments and public disclosure of their results “have grown during the past decade . . . into one of the most prominent features of many governments’ educational strategy”). 134. See, e.g., Fairfax, Achieving, supra note 57, at 201–02, 246–52 (proposing nonfinancial performance of double bottom line corporations be monitored by independent audit committee modeled on financial audit committees required by SEC, New York Stock Exchange, and NASDAQ). 135. See, e.g., Don Tapscott & David Ticoll, The Naked Corporation 62–93 (2003) (arguing transparency is panacea to cure all corporate ills); Larry Cata Baker, From Moral Obligation to International Law: Disclosure Systems, Markets and the Regulation of Multinational Corporations, 39 Geo. J. Int’l L. 591, 593 (2008) (advocating mandatory disclosure to promote “moral” behavior by transnational corporations); Sarah Dadush, Profiting in (Red): The Need for Enhanced Transparency in Cause-Related Marketing, 42 N.Y.U. J. Int’l L. & Pol. 1269, 1312–36 (2010) (arguing cause-related marketing should be subject to more reporting requirements). 136. Loi 2001-420 du 15 mai 2001 de nouvelles regulations économiques [Law 2001420 of May 15, 2001 on New Economic Regulations], Journal Officiel de la République Française [J.O.] [Official Gazette of France], May 16, 2001, pp. 7776, 7798; see also Lucien J. Dhooge, Beyond Volunteerism: Social Disclosure and France’s Nouvelles Régulations Economiques, 21 Ariz. J. Int’l & Comp. L. 441, 445 (2004) (concluding this law reveals growing imperative for social disclosure). 137. Financial Services Reform Act 2001 (Cth) s 1013D(1)(1) (Austl.) (requiring institutions offering financial products with investment component to disclose extent to which environmental or social considerations are taken into account in selecting investments). 138. Occupational Pension Schemes (Investment, and Assignment, Forfeiture, Bankruptcy etc.) Amendment Regulations, 1999, S.I. 1999/1849, art. 2, ¶ 4(b) (U.K.) (requiring trustees of pension funds to disclose extent to which they take social and environmental considerations into account in their investment strategies). 139. Code of Corporate Practices and Conduct of 2002 § 5.1.1 (S. Afr.) (requiring all companies listed on Johannesburg Stock Exchange to report annually on social and environmental policies and practices). 140. See supra notes 45–46 and accompanying text (describing corporations’ voluntary social and environmental reporting). 141. Monsma & Buckley, supra note 37, at 158; Tracy Soehle, SEC Disclosure Requirements for Environmental Liabilities, 8 Tul. Envtl. L.J. 527, 551 (1995). 142. Jones & McIntyre, supra note 35, at 6. R R R R R \\jciprod01\productn\C\COL\112-3\COL303.txt 598 unknown Seq: 21 COLUMBIA LAW REVIEW 19-MAR-12 16:45 [Vol. 112:578 these laws should require disclosure of social performance as well.143 To facilitate this type of disclosure, NGOs, nonprofits, and government have developed hundreds of new social and environmental performance codes.144 2. The Theory Behind Social Reporting. — This model of mission accountability has been called SAAR (social auditing, accounting, and reporting), or simply social reporting.145 The major components of this model are (1) “verification by independent auditors,” who should “evaluat[e] . . . a company’s performance against certain standards” and “include a report of their findings in the company’s published social report”; (2) “an annual, publicly disclosed report”; and (3) an incentive mechanism, such as “the development of a compliance label given to corporations who produce social reports that meet certain minimum requirements . . . . Corporations could use these labels on their products or in their promotional literature.”146 This approach is in essence the same taken by the benefit corporation legislation.147 143. See Eric Engle, What You Don’t Know Can Hurt You: Human Rights, Shareholder Activism and SEC Reporting Requirements, 57 Syracuse L. Rev. 63, 66 (2006) (arguing SEC should require companies to report human rights, environmental, and labor relations practices because that information is material to investment decisions); Cyrus Mehri, Andrea Giampetro-Meyer & Michael B. Runnels, One Nation, Indivisible: The Use of Diversity Report Cards to Promote Transparency, Accountability, and Workplace Fairness, 9 Fordham J. Corp. & Fin. L. 395, 439–42 (2004) (arguing SEC should require Diversity Report Cards to promote transparency and accountability through disclosure of hiring, compensation, and promotion practices); Williams, Transparency, supra note 43, at 1284–89 (arguing SEC should require corporate disclosures of social, environmental, and labor practices). 144. Ebrahim, supra note 89, at 16; see Bond, Quality Standards, Codes and Initiatives, Bond.org.uk, http://www.bond.org.uk/pages/quality-standards-codes-andinititatives-2.html (on file with the Columbia Law Review) (last visited Feb. 23, 2011) (providing links to codes); Indep. Sector, Compendium of Standards, Codes, and Principles of Nonprofit and Philanthropic Organizations, IndependentSector.org, http:// www.independentsector.org/issues/accountability/standards2.html (on file with the Columbia Law Review) (last visited Feb. 23, 2011) (same). Well-known guidelines include the Organisation for Economic Co-operation and Development (OECD) Guidelines for Multinational Enterprises (1976); the International Labor Organisation (ILO) Tripartite Declaration of Principles Concerning Multinational Enterprises and Social Policy (1977), Nolan, Corporate Accountability, supra note 39, at 10; the Global Reporting Initiative’s (GRI) Sustainability Reporting Guidelines, Global Reporting Initiative, Sustainability Reporting Guidelines (2011), available at https://www.globalreporting.org/ resourcelibrary/G3.1-Guidelines-Incl-Technical-Protocol.pdf (on file with the Columbia Law Review); the SA8000 standard, Soc. Accountability Int’l, Social Accountability 8000 (2008), available at http://www.sa-intl.org/_data/n_0001/resources/live/2008StdEnglish Final.pdf (on file with the Columbia Law Review); and Social Return on Investment (SROI), Sara Olsen & Alison Lingane, Social Return on Investment: Standard Guidelines 7 (2003) (unpublished working paper), available at http://repositories.cdlib.org/crb/wps/8/ (on file with the Columbia Law Review). 145. Hess, supra note 46, at 308. 146. Id. at 307–08, 310, 316, 320–21. 147. See supra Part I.C.2.b (describing auditing, accounting, and certification requirements in benefit corporation legislation). R R R R \\jciprod01\productn\C\COL\112-3\COL303.txt 2012] unknown Seq: 22 REGULATING BENEFIT CORPORATIONS 19-MAR-12 16:45 599 The SAAR approach embodied in the benefit corporation legislation relies not just on (1) third-party audits and (2) public disclosure, but also on two additional pieces: (3) performance-based sanctions tied to market pressure and (4) “objective,” standardized, and quantitative performance metrics.148 These last two pieces are critical. The SAAR approach—as distinct from other disclosure-based models149—seeks to regulate corporate behavior by threatening reputational, rather than legal, sanctions,150 on the belief that “consumer pressure is the quickest, cheapest, and least adversarial enforcement mechanism for private codes of conduct.”151 Corporations are presumed to value their reputations so highly152 that if forced to be transparent, the threat of media exposure and public opprobrium will keep them in line.153 Mandatory disclosure functions in this model to prevent the information asymmetries between companies, consumers, and investors that lead to market failure.154 148. See Ebrahim, supra note 89, at 13 (explaining disclosure statements and reports are “external approaches to accountability, enforced through punitive threats such as the loss of nonprofit status”). 149. See Michael C. Dorf & Charles F. Sabel, A Constitution of Democratic Experimentalism, 98 Colum. L. Rev. 267, 314–23 (1998) (describing theory of democratic experimentalism that requires actors with local knowledge to share with those facing similar problems). 150. See Hess, supra note 46, at 308–09, 313, 321 (arguing social reporting is better alternative than traditional “command and control regulation,” such as Clear Air Act Amendments of 1977 and Occupational Safety and Health Act of 1970); Jackson, supra note 21, at 88–99 (describing “reputational accountability” as alternative to “legal accountability” as means to induce CSR); Mulligan, supra note 15, at 1990 (explaining disclosure requirements are motivated by lack of state and federal funding and hope of fostering “public oversight”); Stuart Rees, The Fraud and the Fiction, in The Human Costs of Managerialism 15, 15–16 (Stuart Rees & Gordon Rodley eds., 1995) [hereinafter Human Costs] (describing trend of “managerialism” as trying to “cut back on the responsibilities of government and rely on market forces” and “competition”); Sugin, supra note 93, at 893–94 & n.4 (describing public reporting as alternative to government regulation). 151. Veronica Besmer, The Legal Character of Private Codes of Conduct: More than Just a Pseudo-Formal Gloss on Corporate Social Responsibility, 2 Hastings Bus. L.J. 279, 306 (2006). 152. See Hess, supra note 46, at 313 (describing corporation’s reputation as an increasingly valuable asset); Monsma & Buckley, supra note 37, at 177 n.95 (noting that in 2004 study of directors attending 34th World Economic Forum in Davos, Switzerland, “ninety-two percent . . . perceived reputation as important to their corporate strategies”). 153. See Hess, supra note 46, at 313, 321 (“Disclosure can . . . help to improve corporate behavior due to any corporation’s desire to avoid negative publicity . . . .”); Jackson, supra note 21, at 86 & n.319 (describing successful media campaigns against companies that used sweatshops); Langevoort, Internal Controls, supra note 119, at 965 (“Institutions (and their leaders) that inappropriately conceal or dissemble are punished more harshly in the news media and in markets of various sorts . . . .”). 154. See, e.g., David W. Case, Corporate Environmental Reporting as Informational Regulation: A Law and Economics Perspective, 76 U. Colo. L. Rev. 379, 414–27 (2005) (arguing environmental disclosures reduce information asymmetries and increase opportunities for efficient bargaining); Chatterji & Richman, supra note 43, at 40 (noting R R R R R R R R R R R \\jciprod01\productn\C\COL\112-3\COL303.txt 600 unknown Seq: 23 COLUMBIA LAW REVIEW 19-MAR-12 16:45 [Vol. 112:578 A common criticism of this model is that collecting and reporting data is excessively burdensome,155 particularly for small companies,156 produces no information useful for improving practices,157 and diverts resources from achieving the corporation’s mission.158 These costs, critics argue, do not come with concomitant gains in accountability, first, because the public is too overloaded with information to pore through extensive corporate disclosures159 and, second, because they cannot always make sense of the material disclosed anyway.160 To mitigate these impact of information asymmetries on markets and on corporate social responsibility); Monsma & Buckley, supra note 37, at 182 & n.113 (same); Snyder, supra note 33, at 577–79 (same). 155. See Langevoort, Internal Controls, supra note 119, at 966–68, 971–72 (explaining how auditors, attorneys, management consultants, and others who gain financially from increased corporate reporting exaggerate amount of reporting necessary under Sarbanes-Oxley to risk-averse corporate directors); Donald C. Langevoort, Monitoring: The Behavioral Economics of Corporate Compliance with Law, 2002 Colum. Bus. L. Rev. 71, 117 (“Monitoring-based systems have unexpectedly serious (and probably immeasurable) costs, which society should not impose without strong reason.”). 156. See Ebrahim, supra note 89, at 15 (“A . . . concern raised by small nonprofits is that their limited staff and resources are stretched too thin by evaluation and reporting requests of funders . . . .”); Closely Held Corporations, supra note 124, at 7 (discussing concerns about costly Sarbanes-Oxley disclosure requirements being imposed on small companies). 157. See Jennifer A. O’Day, Complexity, Accountability, and School Improvement, 72 Harv. Educ. Rev. 293, 300, 302 (2002) (arguing under current accountability regimes “[t]eachers and schools are constantly bombarded by information,” much of it “irrelevant to the improvement of instruction and learning”); Ebrahim, supra note 89, at 21 (“[O]nerous data requirements can lead nonprofits to develop monitoring and evaluation systems that . . . are of limited value for internal learning and decision making.”). 158. Robert Behn calls this interference of monitoring and accountability requirements with “basic program operating capacity” the classic “accountability dilemma.” Behn, supra note 89, at 10–12, 15; see also Langevoort, Internal Controls, supra note 119, at 966–68, 971–72 (arguing Sarbanes-Oxley has led to “labor-intensive formalism” that focuses on “routines and details deep within the organization without enough attention to their overall strategic significance” and thus to “misallocation of . . . resources”); Sugin, supra note 93, at 894 (“Audit requirements . . . are expensive for organizations, diverting both resources and attention from . . . programs.”). 159. See Katie Cunningham & Marc Ricks, Why Measure: Nonprofits Use Metrics to Show that They Are Efficient. but What If Donors Don’t Care?, Stan. Soc. Innovation Rev., Summer 2004, at 44, 47–51 (finding donor interest in financial accountability negligible); Mulligan, supra note 15, at 1997–99, 2001 (“[T]hese [nonprofit] disclosure documents seem fated to languish in the basements of state attorneys generals’ offices.”); Troy A. Paredes, Blinded by the Light: Information Overload and Its Consequences for Securities Regulation, 81 Wash. U. L.Q. 417, 419 (2003) (arguing average investor experiences information overload). 160. See Hess, supra note 46, at 311–12 (noting corporations stopped disclosing their social activities in 1980s because of “the inability of the public to understand and appreciate the reports”); Mulligan, supra note 15, at 2000 (“[H]aving vast amounts of data without the resources to intelligently review and employ it is of no value . . . .”). A counterargument to this criticism might be that mandatory reporting is useful as a mechanism to generate internal attention to the things the corporation is required to report on, whether or not the public pays any attention. Reporting requirements in a SAAR/benefit corporation model, however, might not serve this function very well. See R R R R R R R R R R \\jciprod01\productn\C\COL\112-3\COL303.txt 2012] unknown Seq: 24 REGULATING BENEFIT CORPORATIONS 19-MAR-12 16:45 601 problems, the SAAR approach views the independent auditor not just as inspector, but also, primarily, as information trader—analogous to the role played in financial markets by independent raters of securities— filtering disclosures for consumers, investors, and donors.161 The auditor’s social performance metrics should be “objective” (so consumers can trust them),162 standardized (so consumers can compare results across companies),163 and quantifiable (so they are quick and easy to understand).164 The benefit corporation legislation likewise requires that benefit corporations be evaluated against a set of mission-related standards that are (1) “objective” (developed externally by an “independent third infra Part II.B.2.c (describing how external accountability models undermine intrinsic motivation). 161. See Mulligan, supra note 15, at 2000 (“[D]isclosure . . . is normatively valuable only when institutions are established . . . that enable interested parties to make use of the data to further some other ends . . . .”); Snyder, supra note 33, at 582–84, 611 (“[D]isclosure fails as a market mechanism . . . [g]iven the . . . lack of intermediaries to translate the data . . . .”). 162. See Besmer, supra note 151, at 306 (arguing for “objectively verifiable standard” to enhance effectiveness of “consumer pressure . . . [as an] enforcement mechanism”); Kerr, Creative Capitalism, supra note 23, at 848 (arguing it is “critical” to “employ an objective framework” to evaluate corporate claims of social responsibility). 163. See Chatterji & Richman, supra note 43, at 39 (noting “the proliferation of codes” for measuring nonfinancial performance causes “confusion among consumers”); Nicole Dando & Tracey Swift, Transparency and Assurance: Minding the Credibility Gap, 44 J. Bus. Ethics 195, 195–96 (2003) (arguing for common metric for social, ethical, and environmental performance data to enhance value of corporate disclosures); Leila Janah, The Many Bottom Lines of Businesses, TechCrunch (July 18, 2010), http://techcrunch. com/2010/07/18/the-many-bottom-lines-of-businesses/ (on file with the Columbia Law Review) (same); see also Simon Zadek, Peter Pruzan & Richard Evans, Building Corporate Accountability 42 (1997) (arguing quality of social performance codes should be judged, in part, by their comparability); Nolan, Corporate Accountability, supra note 39, at 8 (noting use of GRI guidelines as required by King II Report in South Africa “is expected . . . [to] lead to greater standardization in disclosure practices”). 164. See Clark C. Abt, The Social Audit for Management 45–46 (1977) (attempting to create social balance sheet by placing dollar values on firm’s “social assets” and “social liabilities”); Case, supra note 154, at 438 (arguing GRI reporting system’s “‘standardization, comparability, and computerization’” results in “enhanced . . . monitoring and benchmarking” (quoting Bradley C. Karkkainen, Information as Environmental Regulation: TRI and Performance Benchmarking, Precursor to a New Paradigm?, 89 Geo. L.J. 257, 290 (2001))); Kerr, Sustainability, supra note 5, at 642–43 (“[T]he ability to numerically measure . . . social impact is crucial . . . .”); Snyder, supra note 33, at 591, 612 (criticizing GRI’s social performance guidelines as using “broad qualitative language” that is difficult to aggregate and compare and that requires “prose” to communicate, and advocating the “readily understandable format” of “objective calculations”); Social Footprint: Measuring Corporate Sustainability Performance, Bus. Credit, June 2006, at 38, 38 (launching first nonfinancial reporting method able to mathematically calculate bottom-line impact of corporations on society); Olsen & Lingane, supra note 144, at 6 (noting first step of SROI approach is to “quantify [the] non-financial impact of operations per unit”). R R R R R R R R R R \\jciprod01\productn\C\COL\112-3\COL303.txt 602 unknown Seq: 25 COLUMBIA LAW REVIEW 19-MAR-12 16:45 [Vol. 112:578 party”); 165 (2) standardized; (3) quantifiable; 166 and (4) translated into the simple, consumer-friendly “B” label.167 These four pieces of the basic SAAR approach—third-party audits, public disclosure, standardized measures of performance, and marketbased sanctions—are visible in recent efforts to regulate a range of industries, such as Total Quality Management (TQM) in business,168 “standards-based reform” in public education,169 and federal nursing home regulations.170 Much of the discussion of the benefit corporation model that follows therefore draws on lessons learned from implementing substantially similar approaches to accountability in these other contexts. B. The Illusory Promise of External Auditing, Standard Metrics, and Market Pressure Most current criticisms of the SAAR model focus on the challenges of implementing it properly.171 For example, one implementation challenge is ensuring the objectivity and independence of the third-party au165. See supra notes 109–110 and accompanying text (describing “independent third party standard” requirement). 166. See infra notes 180–188 and accompanying text (describing focus on quantitative standards in audits of benefit corporations). 167. See supra Part I.C.2.b (describing B Lab’s “B” certification standard). 168. See Craig Bremner, Picturing Contemporary Management, in Human Costs, supra note 150, at 243, 244–45 (describing TQM as measuring compliance with quantifiable, “objective” standards to ensure quality outcomes). One of the questions on the B Lab assessment tool is “Do you use an established methodology for quality assurance [such as] TQM . . . ?” Certified B Corp., The B Impact Assessment 2010: Version 2.0 at 11 (2010) [hereinafter B Impact Assessment], available at http://www.bcorporation.net/ resources/bcorp/documents/2010-B-Impact-Assessment%20%281%29.pdf (on file with the Columbia Law Review). 169. See O’Day, supra note 157, at 294 (“The most widespread and well-developed policy approach [to school accountability in United States] . . . is the outcomes-based bureaucratic model . . . evident in most states and districts and codified in extreme form in the . . . federal . . . No Child Left Behind Act (NCLB) of 2001.”); Terry M. Moe, Politics, Control, and the Future of School Accountability 16 (2002) (unpublished manuscript) (on file with the Columbia Law Review) (noting large business organizations like Business Roundtable remain major backers of standards-based education reform movement, which “mirrors their own emphasis on managerial efficiency”); see also Broadfoot, supra note 133, at 235–36 (noting similar education reforms in England make “increasingly explicit [the] role of parents as ‘consumers’ of education” in combination with “quality assurance and control devices”). 170. See William Hovey, The Worst of Both Worlds: Nursing Home Regulation in the United States, Pol’y Stud. Rev., Winter 2000, at 43, 46–47 (describing federal nursing home regulations in Omnibus Budget Reconciliation Act of 1987 as involving standards, performance assessments, and sanctions). 171. Other criticisms of the benefit corporation legislation are that it does not solve the “asset lock” problem, Kelley, Law and Choice, supra note 1, at 369, that it relies on a shallow source of capital—socially responsible investors—to solve the capital formation problem, id., and that it does not go beyond the “do no harm” requirements of CSR, Taylor, supra note 9, at 761. R R R R R R R \\jciprod01\productn\C\COL\112-3\COL303.txt 2012] unknown Seq: 26 REGULATING BENEFIT CORPORATIONS 19-MAR-12 16:45 603 ditors.172 Another is resolving the considerable—and until now intractable—technical difficulties involved in obtaining valid and reliable social outcome metrics.173 Part II.B argues that even without these implementation challenges, however, the benefit corporation’s SAAR approach is poorly suited to achieving meaningful accountability to mission. It argues that because there are important distinctions between a social bottom line and a financial bottom line, the benefit corporation legislation misconceives both for what (Part II.B.1) and to whom (Part II.B.2) benefit corporations should be held accountable. 1. Accountability for What. — The social reporting model appeals because it looks so much like management strategies long used to regulate corporations’ financial performance: standards, measurement, and market competition. Social “outputs,” however, are fundamentally different from financial ones; indeed, “it could be argued that the raison d’être of the public service was that its ‘outputs,’ to use the current jargon, were so different from those of the market that they required different management styles.”174 Standards, measurement, and reporting may play useful roles in regulating benefit corporations’ social performance, but only, this Note argues, to the extent these tools are adapted to those qualities of social goals that distinguish them from financial goals. a. Quantitative Process and Performance Standards. — The first of these qualities is that achievement of social goals can often be meaningfully measured only over the long term, not in quarterly or even annual reports. Second, social goals are complex and “normally highly resistant to quality reduction.”175 Third, and as a corollary to both the long-term nature of social projects and their complexity, standards for social performance are highly subject to change, as new information is gained or priorities shift. For example, Morgan Stanley was sued for sex discrimination shortly after it was included on a list of “100 Best Employers for Working Moms.”176 Similarly, a group that wants to improve graduation rates in low-income communities may decide that reaching this goal requires shifting its strategy from research and advocacy to organizing tutoring 172. See Brakman Reiser, Blended Enterprise, supra note 1, at 115 (noting incentives for B Lab to be lax in its audits); Chatterji & Richman, supra note 43, at 36–37 (describing phenomenon of “regulatory capture”). 173. See, e.g., Broadfoot, supra note 133, at 13 (noting “size and quality of the critical literature that now exists about the shortcomings of assessment procedures”); Sugin, supra note 93, at 919 (“Measuring effectiveness may be the most intractable problem that charities have.”); Ebrahim, supra note 89, at 14 (noting nonprofits’ concerns about “the difficulty, reliability, and expense” of measuring long-term outcomes). These difficulties are most visible in the education and healthcare sectors, where “[s]tandards and their certification are most ubiquitous and longstanding.” Id. at 16. 174. Brian Easton, The Rise of the Generic Manager, in Human Costs, supra note 150, at 39, 40–41. 175. Brakman Reiser, Enron.org, supra note 89, at 217. 176. Chatterji & Richman, supra note 43, at 34 & n.7. R R R R R R R R \\jciprod01\productn\C\COL\112-3\COL303.txt 604 unknown Seq: 27 COLUMBIA LAW REVIEW 19-MAR-12 16:45 [Vol. 112:578 and counseling programs.177 Finally, achievement of social goals often depends on adaptation to individualized, nonreplicable situations. Making an accurate medical diagnosis, for example, often requires the ability to treat unpredictable cases or make new discoveries.178 Education, too, “‘since it deals in the first place with organisms, and in the second place with individualities, is not analogous to a standardizable manufacturing process.’”179 For all of these reasons, social performance defies meaningful assessment with reference to fixed, determinate, or uniform criteria. As noted above, however, the social reporting approach in general, and the benefit corporation accountability framework in particular, heavily concentrates on quantitative standards. For example, B Lab suggests that a benefit corporation’s annual report to the public should include such indicators of “mission-related performance” as: “[q]uantifiable targets related to your mission,” “[q]uantifiable results from your mission (e.g., lbs of carbon offset),” and “[c]onsistent variables of measurement which allow comparisons to previous years.”180 Similarly, the following measures of mission-related performance are typical of those in B Lab’s auditing survey: • What % of the company is owned by full-time employees? • What % of management is from previously excluded populations? • What % of employees participated in company-organized community service days last year? • What was the average annual % of net profits or net revenues that your company gave to charity in the last two fiscal years?181 Answers to these items are assigned point values, which are aggregated to produce a single numerical score.182 The likely consequences of this mismatch between the long-term, complex, evolving, and qualitative nature of social goals and the fixed, reductionistic, quantitative nature of B Lab’s standards for measuring their achievement are two-fold. First, the quantitative nature of B Lab’s 177. Brakman Reiser, Enron.org, supra note 89, at 228–29. Whether this shift “constitute[s] a meaningful deviation from the nonprofit’s mission . . . cannot be made by calculation or objective logic alone.” Id. 178. J.S. Carroll & A.C. Edmondson, Leading Organizational Learning in Health Care, 11 Quality & Safety Health Care 51, 53 (2002). 179. Raymond E. Callahan, Education and the Cult of Efficiency: A Study of the Social Forces that Have Shaped the Administration of Public Schools 121 (1962) (quoting Benjamin C. Gruenberg, Some Economic Obstacles to Educational Progress, Am. Teacher, Sept. 1912, at 90). 180. B Impact Assessment, supra note 168, at 4. 181. Id. at 6, 13–15. 182. Certified B Corp., Become a B Corp, BCorporation.net [hereinafter Become a B Corp], http://www.bcorporation.net/become-a-b-Corp (on file with the Columbia Law Review) (last visited Feb. 23, 2012). R R \\jciprod01\productn\C\COL\112-3\COL303.txt 2012] unknown Seq: 28 REGULATING BENEFIT CORPORATIONS 19-MAR-12 16:45 605 standards could restrict the universe of what can qualify as a “B”-worthy corporate social mission, since some objectives (e.g., planting trees, serving a given number of “community service days”) are more quantifiable than others (e.g., teaching good citizenship). Second, exclusive reliance on quantitative standards can make it impossible to identify how best to achieve a given mission.183 When it comes to performance of social goals, many “critical sources” of failure escape definition or measurement in technical or quantitative terms.184 “For instance, the Columbia space shuttle disaster of 2003 was attributed primarily to the culture at NASA, which was seen to have changed little from that which prevailed at the time of the Challenger disaster seventeen years earlier.”185 Similarly, research attributes corporate crime to various kinds of organizational failure, such as incompatible corporate goals, failures of communication, and organizational culture.186 In the context of regulating safety in a nuclear power plant, many of the most important questions are questions of degree—such as “how well the duty holder has carried out the risk management process and how effective its controls are”—rather than “tick-a-box” questions such as, “Have workers been trained?,” “Is personal protective equipment . . . available?,” and “[Has] the duty holder . . . gone through the risk management process[?]”187 As Andrew Hopkins explained, major accidents have occurred even when workers have been trained and provided with protective equipment; neither training nor equipment is of any avail if it is not the right kind or quality of training or equipment.188 b. Objective Process and Performance Standards. — Another quality that distinguishes benefit corporations’ “public benefit” goals from traditional stakeholder maximization goals is that different constituencies often desire different—and sometimes conflicting—social “outputs.”189 Even different constituencies that in general terms want the same output—e.g., to “improve mental health” or “increase diversity in the workplace”—may 183. Franco Furger, Accountability and Systems of Self-Governance: The Case of the Maritime Industry, Law & Pol’y, Oct. 1997, at 445, 446. 184. Id. at 446. 185. Andrew Hopkins, Beyond Compliance Monitoring: New Strategies for Safety Regulators, Law & Pol’y, Apr. 2007, at 210, 212–13. 186. Furger, supra note 183, at 446 (“An approach to risk management based essentially on technical requirements may miss the social and organizational nature of many environmental risks.”); see also Carroll & Edmondson, supra note 178, at 51, 53 (“[N]ot all problems can be reduced to technical solutions.”). 187. Hopkins, supra note 185, at 210–13. 188. Id. at 210, 213 (citations omitted). 189. See Jackson, supra note 21, at 66 (noting danger of stakeholders “engag[ing] in power-wars over their respective interests”); Mulligan, supra note 15, at 1986 (“[C]ompeting constituencies often push nonprofit corporations to seek differing goals . . . [making] articulati[on] [of] . . . a coherent mission . . . more difficult.”); Ebrahim, supra note 89, at 14 (“[T]he question of what should be evaluated may vary according to . . . stakeholder[] . . . .”); see also Taylor, supra note 9, at 761 (noting possibility of intracorporation disagreement about goals). R R R R R R R \\jciprod01\productn\C\COL\112-3\COL303.txt 606 unknown Seq: 29 COLUMBIA LAW REVIEW 19-MAR-12 16:45 [Vol. 112:578 define this output differently. For example, one problem with ultra vires lawsuits to enforce nonprofit directors’ duties is “the potential for divergent positions within a state about what constitutes ‘charitable’ or ‘exempt’ activity.”190 Defining and implementing “public benefit” purposes therefore involves the inescapably subjective and in most cases political tasks of (1) prioritizing among competing interests and (2) choosing among divergent understandings of how these interests should be conceptualized, measured, and pursued. The benefit corporation legislation, however, holds benefit corporations accountable to purportedly value-neutral standards. It does this not only explicitly—by requiring “objective” performance standards set by an “independent” third party191—but also implicitly. That is, by requiring benefit corporations to accommodate all stakeholder interests at once, and not indicating how benefit corporations are to prioritize among different stakeholders, the legislation trivializes possible conflicts among them.192 Moreover, by leaving it to the “market” to determine performance criteria,193 the legislation requires that standards be developed that, if not entirely value-neutral, are at least widely enough accepted to be beyond the need for public debate.194 The benefit corporation legislation therefore presents a second mismatch between its performance standards (value-neutral) and benefit corporations’ social mission (value-laden). The potential consequences of this mismatch can be predicted by looking at other contexts where a similar mismatch occurs. Education reform is one such context. As in the benefit corporation context, policymakers implementing standards-based reform in public education have tried to “take education out of the realm of opinion.”195 For example, the National Education Goals Panel declared that “‘national content standards should address only the core academic areas’ . . . and not ‘non-academic areas such as values, beliefs, [and] . . . attitudes.’”196 As in the benefit corporation context, this effort 190. Tyler, supra note 85, at 156. 191. See supra note 109 and accompanying text (discussing third-party auditing standards). 192. See Md. Code Ann., Corps. & Ass’ns § 5-6C-08 (LexisNexis 2007 & Supp. 2011) (requiring benefit corporations to break their assessment tools into separate sections for questions relating, respectively, to employees, suppliers, and community members); Vt. Stat. Ann. tit. 11A, § 21.10, 21.14 (2010) (same); Hess, supra note 46, at 317 (“To ensure that the corporation is meaningfully considering all stakeholder groups, . . . the social report should be divided into separate sections for each group.”); see also B Impact Assessment, supra note 168, at 1 (showing “B Impact Assessment,” with standards in areas of “Accountability,” “Employees,” “Consumers,” “Community,” and “Environment”). 193. See supra text accompanying notes 102–103 (discussing planned role of market forces in shaping standards). 194. See Broadfoot, supra note 133, at 124 (noting use of standardized assessments “require[s] a considerable measure of agreement over . . . objectives.”) 195. Callahan, supra note 179, at 87. 196. Diane Ravitch, National Standards in American Education: A Citizen’s Guide 166 (The Brookings Inst. ed., 1995) (quoting Statement on Voluntary National Education R R R R R R R \\jciprod01\productn\C\COL\112-3\COL303.txt 2012] unknown Seq: 30 REGULATING BENEFIT CORPORATIONS 19-MAR-12 16:45 607 to purge mission statements and performance standards of “opinions” and “values” seems futile: Decisions about what is worth knowing and teaching are inherently decisions about what people value.197 Many argue that this reliance on purportedly noncontroversial performance standards masks the “value assumptions” behind education reform efforts and that this, in turn, has short-circuited explicit discussion about competing values.198 These critics argue that research and policy debates about accountability in education have thus centered on the technical issues of implementation of assessment tools to the exclusion of achieving a value consensus about the educational goals to be assessed.199 What is wrong with stripping values from the public debate about a social project? One problem with taking the end-goal as a given is that doing so may freeze in time the “ideological and political commitments” embedded in this goal and “chill the[ir] evolution and development.”200 In the education context, American public school curricula—framed in terms of purportedly timeless “academic” standards—have remained stagnant for decades. In the meantime, not only have values evolved, but the economy has also transformed and globalized, and new research on Content Standards, in Promises to Keep: Creating High Standards for American Students, Report on the Review of Education Standards from Goals 3 and 4 Technical Planning Group to the National Education Goals Panel 68, 68 (1993)). Similarly, Virginia “Governor Douglas Wilder said that he would not support ‘value-based education’ . . . [and the] Michigan legislature . . . mandate[ed] the development of a state ‘model . . . curriculum,’ which ‘shall not include attitudes, beliefs, or value systems.’” Id. (quoting H.B. 5121, 87th Leg., Reg. Sess., § 1278(1) (Mich. 1993)). 197. See Broadfoot, supra note 133, at 236 (“[W]hat is ‘worth’ knowing, and hence every aspect of educational policy, is essentially a value question.”). 198. Id. at 123, 163, 226, 230–31 (arguing reliance on purportedly objective standards masks potential disagreement about them and thus “excludes explicit discussion of different . . . options in terms of competing values”); see also Rees, supra note 151, at 24 (“[I]n many circles management is presented as unable to engage in debate about objectives because, by its focus on rationality and efficiency, it stands beyond political and moral controversy.”). 199. Broadfoot, supra note 133, at 226; see also John I. Goodlad, A Place Called School: Prospects for the Future 290 (1984) (“My own conclusion, as a long-term student of curriculum reform, is that there has not been intensive, sustained attention to the content of elementary and secondary education for some time.”); Neil Postman, The End of Education: Redefining the Value of School 26 (1995) (“There was a time when educators became famous for providing reasons for learning; now they become famous for inventing a method.”); Landon E. Beyer & Michael W. Apple, Values and Politics in the Curriculum, in The Curriculum: Problems, Politics, and Possibilities 3, 3-11 (Landon E. Beyer & Michael W. Apple eds., 2d ed. 1998) (arguing standards-based accountability movement in education has provoked much less analysis of content of new state curriculum standards than it has research on methods of ensuring teachers’ implementation of these standards in classroom); Decker F. Walker & Jon Schaffarzick, Comparing Curricula, 44 Rev. Educ. Res. 83, 108 (1975) (noting based on review of research that “we so rarely, so sporadically, and so feebly consider what matters to address and what to emphasize in schools”). 200. Brakman Reiser, Enron.org, supra note 89, at 229. R R R R \\jciprod01\productn\C\COL\112-3\COL303.txt 608 unknown Seq: 31 COLUMBIA LAW REVIEW 19-MAR-12 16:45 [Vol. 112:578 human learning (and on other countries’ very different content standards) has accumulated.201 As two scholars of curriculum put it: Perhaps if as many people in schools, in government, and in foundations asked as insistently for evidence that schools were attempting to teach worthwhile and defensible things as ask whether the schools have taught what they set out to teach, we would have more and better research and maybe even better schools.202 Einstein warned about this “‘[p]erfection of means, but confusion of ends,’”203 and “[t]he film Dr. Strangelove brilliantly satirized” this phenomenon in its depiction of “the absorption of a bomber crew in the exacting technical procedure of dropping nuclear weapons on a country.”204 2. Accountability to Whom. — a. Accountability to Oversight Bodies and the Market. — The benefit corporation model holds corporations accountable to the public at large, or the “marketplace.” As Hess explains, SAAR is “consistent with the idea of a Marketplace of Morality.”205 Under this theory, “market participants essentially ‘vote’ on appropriate corporate behavior with their purchase decisions. . . . For the marketplace of morality to work efficiently, . . . corporations must understand and be responsive to the moral preferences within capital, consumer, and labor markets . . . .”206 Similarly, the benefit corporation legislation leaves it to third-party evaluators and the courts in the short term and to “the market” in the long term to give content to the terms “general public benefit” and “specific public benefit”—that is, to define the standards by which benefit corporations’ performance will be measured.207 b. Accountability to Service Deliverers and Their Intended Beneficiaries. — In addition to the diffuse public, however, benefit corporations have two 201. See, e.g., David Perkins, Smart Schools 22–23 (1992) (describing research showing knowledge students acquire in school is often “inert”—inaccessible to them outside specific context in which they originally learned it). 202. Walker & Schaffarzick, supra note 199, at 108; see also, e.g., Curtis C. McKnight et al., The Underachieving Curriculum: Assessing U.S. School Mathematics from an International Perspective 89 (1987) (reporting results of large-scale quantitative comparison showing that U.S. curriculum varies substantially from world trends in its slow pace, repetitiveness, fragmentation, and emphasis of breadth over depth, and that these features have remained remarkably resistant to change over time); William Schmidt, Richard Houang & Leland Cogan, A Coherent Curriculum: The Case of Mathematics, Am. Educator, Summer 2002, at 1, 3 (concluding based on extensive comparative study that U.S. curriculum “is highly repetitive, unfocused, unchallenging, and incoherent”). 203. Albert Einstein, The New Quotable Einstein 117 (Alice Calaprice ed., 2005) (quoting broadcast recording for science conference in London, Sept. 28, 1941). 204. Stanley Milgram, Obedience to Authority: An Experimental View 7 (1975). 205. Hess, supra note 46, at 323–24. 206. Id. at 323; see also Thomas W. Dunfee, The Marketplace of Morality: First Steps Toward a Theory of Moral Choice, 8 Bus. Ethics Q. 127 (1998) (presenting theory). 207. See supra note 103 and accompanying text (describing use of “market” to shape performance standards). R R R \\jciprod01\productn\C\COL\112-3\COL303.txt 2012] unknown Seq: 32 REGULATING BENEFIT CORPORATIONS 19-MAR-12 16:45 609 other distinct constituencies: (1) the more targeted beneficiaries of the corporation’s “specific public benefit” and (2) the employees of the corporation. These two constituencies arguably belong in an effective accountability framework for public-oriented organizations. First, those targeted by a corporation’s “specific public benefit” arguably have a greater moral claim than do those not directly targeted (i.e., “independent third parties” or the diffuse public) to be involved in defining standards for performance. For example, traditional large-scale development programs in the 1980s, involving expensive infrastructure projects like dams and power plants, were “largely designed and implemented without the participation of the target populations, and often not only failed to achieve their desired result, but caused serious adverse consequences in the communities in which they were implemented.”208 Second, even when the organization’s activities implicate the diffuse public (e.g., through its environmental performance) certain specific constituencies and the service providers themselves may be more competent than “independent third parties” or the broader public to set standards for performance. For example, when asked to identify the causes of a safety incident at a nuclear power plant, employees were readily able to pick out a number of important causes, including complexity in layers of management, confusion about who had checked what already, politeness toward new hires that may have interfered with communication, and the failure of specialists to consider the impact of their work on the whole.209 Outsiders, by contrast, find it hard to know the right questions to ask; their efforts to hold organizations accountable often create make-work rather than meaningful inquiry.210 Courts, recognizing their own institutional incompetence to arbitrate disputes about an organization’s adherence to its social mission, have already shown a desire to defer to the judgments of nonprofit directors in defining their own organizational mission.211 208. Taylor, supra note 9, at 766 n.117. 209. John S. Carroll, Organizational Learning Activities in High-Hazard Industries: The Logics Underlying Self-Analysis, 35 J. Mgmt. Stud. 699, 707 (1998); see also Karin Solondz, The Cost of Efficiency, in Human Costs, supra note 150, at 211, 218 (arguing that for this reason “[i]t is not in the employer’s own best interest to reduce the bargaining position of the employee to the point where the employee is not able to help ensure and contribute to the quality of the employer’s own product”). 210. Susan Sturm, The Architecture of Inclusion: Advancing Workplace Equity in Higher Education, 29 Harv. J.L. & Gender 247, 267 & n.81 (2006) (noting courts’ difficulty conducting audits of affirmative action policies). For example, “the subtle and structural dynamics producing women’s under-participation” in certain professions may be absent from “current judicial and administrative definitions of discrimination.” Id. at 262. 211. See, e.g., In re Multiple Sclerosis Serv. Org. of N.Y., Inc., 496 N.E.2d 861, 865, 868 (N.Y. 1986) (finding nonprofit directors had power to determine scope of organization’s mission and were not bound to purposes stated in its founding documents); Sugin, supra note 93, at 902 (“[In re MSSO] should stand for [the] important principle[] . . . that courts defer to the directors’ judgment about the charitable goals of the organization . . . .”). R R R \\jciprod01\productn\C\COL\112-3\COL303.txt 610 unknown Seq: 33 COLUMBIA LAW REVIEW 19-MAR-12 16:45 [Vol. 112:578 c. Balancing Accountability to Different Stakeholders. — Both Hess’s SAAR model and the benefit corporation legislation seem to conflate the “marketplace” and “stakeholders”: For example, after describing the “marketplace of morality,” Hess concludes, “In summary, the goal of the regulatory system should be to guide corporations in being responsive to the expectations and demands of its [sic] stakeholders.”212 Others have noted, however, that “upward accountability” to the “public and oversight bodies” not only is distinct from, but can in some cases also interfere with, “internal accountability” on the part of those carrying out a social project,213 as well as “downward accountability” to their intended beneficiaries (“the stakeholders”).214 Exclusive accountability to independent third parties or the public at large can interfere with “accountability to self and colleagues”215 in two ways. First, it can undermine the ability of the service deliverers themselves to define their own mission.216 For example, when statewide curriculum standards were introduced in American public education in the 1990s,217 they were drafted by state legislators, who, under pressure from their constituents, simplified the wording of the standards and removed such politically charged terms as “environment,” “mental and physical health,” “stewardship,” “construct meaning,” “analyze and evaluate,” “aesthetic,” “ethics,” and “social responsibilities.”218 The result, many complained, were state curriculum frameworks that served more as public relations documents than as research-based guides to good teaching.219 A teacher involved in writing the Missouri state standards complained, “In 212. Hess, supra note 46, at 322–24. 213. See Broadfoot, supra note 133, at 223 (distinguishing “‘bureaucratic’ accountability” from “‘professional’ accountability to self and colleagues for maintaining self-imposed standards”). 214. Ebrahim, supra note 89, at 13 (distinguishing “upward” accountability “to the public and oversight bodies” from “downward accountability to stakeholders”); see also Broadfoot, supra note 133, at 223 (distinguishing “bureaucratic accountability” from “‘moral’ accountability, the responsiveness of the system to clients”). 215. Broadfoot, supra note 133, at 223. 216. See Sugin, supra note 93, at 900–03 (noting one problem with ultra vires suits to enforce nonprofit’s duty of obedience to its original mission is that they deter flexible responses to changing circumstances). 217. See U.S. Dep’t of Educ., Making a Difference: No Child Left Behind, ED.gov, www.ed.gov/nclb/overview/importance/difference/index.html (on file with the Columbia Law Review) (last visited Feb. 23, 2011) (providing information and statistics about curriculum standards under No Child Left Behind). 218. Margaret Placier, Michael Walker & Bill Foster, Writing the “Show-Me” Standards: Teacher Professionalism and Political Control in U.S. State Curriculum Policy, 32 Curriculum Inquiry 281, 294–96 (2002); see also Susan Ohanian, One Size Fits Few: The Folly of Educational Standards 76 (1999) (criticizing California state standards for systematically excluding terms such as enjoy or discover in favor of more banal terms like identify or use); Henry B. Maloney, The Little Standards that Couldn’t, Eng. J., Jan. 1997, at 86, 88 (1997) (criticizing national language arts standards for taking technical rather than personal or aesthetic approaches to literature or writing). 219. Placier et al., supra note 218, at 296. R R R R R R R \\jciprod01\productn\C\COL\112-3\COL303.txt 2012] unknown Seq: 34 REGULATING BENEFIT CORPORATIONS 19-MAR-12 16:45 611 no other discipline are professionals asked to define their jobs in language that is clearly understandable to the lay person at all levels.”220 Second, once the mission is defined, upward accountability can undercut service deliverers’ ability to achieve this mission. Specifically, organizations’ overriding interest in avoiding market-based sanctions produces a number of perverse incentives.221 For example, reporting requirements tied to sanctions give organizations the incentive to “[m]uddy[] their own informational environments,”222 which prevents them from identifying problems and “revealing and closely scrutinizing their mistakes”223: A comprehensive review of research on organizational response to threat . . . uncovered [a] dominant and often maladaptive pattern[] . . . . [R]ather than expanding their use of information to find solutions to the problem, threatened organizations and individuals actually restrict their information processing, relying instead on previously held internal hypotheses and expectations . . . . We can expect individual and system learning to be constrained under these conditions, as well as . . . examination of existing practice and assumptions.224 For example, a culture of blame in the healthcare industry led to “an epidemic of underreported preventable injuries.”225 In the nuclear power industry, “it took a decade of experience with problem reporting systems to realise that blaming individuals did not make the problems go away, but instead discouraged employees from reporting them.”226 Studies of upward accountability models in education similarly reveal a fairly unidirectional (top-down) flow of information throughout the system. . . . When information did flow the other way (from schools . . . up into the system), it focused on whether people were carrying out prescribed tasks. . . . [S]chools [were] 220. Id. at 294. 221. O’Day, supra note 157, at 312–13 (noting negative incentives in standards-based education reform focused schools’ attention “on getting off or staying off probation”); see also Langevoort, Internal Controls, supra note 119, at 966–67 (noting fear of shareholder suits and government audits can exert powerful influence over corporate behavior no matter how unlikely they are to occur). 222. Langevoort, Internal Controls, supra note 119, at 958; see also Sturm, supra note 210, at 317–18 (arguing targeting failures and mistakes for sanctions reduces comprehensiveness and quality of information organizations gather and use in decisionmaking). 223. Ebrahim, supra note 89, at 21. 224. O’Day, supra note 157, at 312–13 (citation omitted). 225. Paul Barach & Steven D. Small, How the NHS Can Improve Safety and Learning: By Learning Free Lessons from Near Misses, 320 BMJ 1683, 1683–84 (2000), available at http://www.ncbi.nlm.nih.gov/pmc/articles/PMC1127461/pdf/1683.pdf (on file with the Columbia Law Review) (stating “culture of blame and superficial analysis” causes “[f]ree lessons from near misses and more expensive ones from litigation [to be] largely lost”). 226. Carroll & Edmondson, supra note 178, at 52. R R R R R R R \\jciprod01\productn\C\COL\112-3\COL303.txt 612 unknown Seq: 35 COLUMBIA LAW REVIEW 19-MAR-12 16:45 [Vol. 112:578 reacting to directions imposed from above and outside the school rather than reflecting on internal practices.227 In short, “disclosure does not necessarily force introspection and internal change.”228 On the contrary, evidence suggests that disclosure requirements, when tied to market pressures or other threats of sanctions, can impede innovation and adaptation.229 As Alnoor Ebrahim put it, “[d]isclosure statements and reports . . . enforced through punitive threats . . . are of limited use for enhancing downwards accountability.”230 To the extent that combining disclosure requirements with performance-based sanctions does in fact encourage organizations to suppress information, focus on short-term results, and do the minimum necessary to comply with external requirements, they work to the detriment of the intended beneficiaries (“stakeholders”) of a social project.231 Adding quantitative performance metrics into the mix adds another wrinkle. When reporting requirements are not only tied to sanctions but are also—like B Lab’s—focused on easily quantifiable, short-term results, they discourage the pursuit of goals that are less easily quantified or that are not measured at all.232 Such reporting requirements may fail to capture the most meaningful aspects of a corporation’s social performance— all the more so because it is so easy for organizations to game the data disclosed to auditors or the public (i.e., by making cosmetic changes with227. O’Day, supra note 157, at 311. 228. Snyder, supra note 33, at 595, 599 (emphasis added). 229. O’Day, supra note 157, at 312–13; see also Jackson, supra note 21, at 103 (describing companies following “the bare minimum in terms of compliance with requirements foisted upon them by Western contractors”); Mulligan, supra note 15, at 2001 (arguing disclosure regimes “may lead to . . . the loss of freedom to make innovative decisions”); E. Rustique-Forrester, Exploring the Policy Influence of England’s National Curriculum on School Exclusion: A Dilemma of Intended Entitlement and Unintended Exclusion?, in The National Curriculum and Its Effects 121, 139 (Cedric Cullingford & Paul Oliver eds., 2001) (“Among the most deeply felt effects of the National Curriculum [in England] on schools and teachers is a climate . . . in which teachers . . . have few incentives and opportunities for attempting innovative, school-based solutions.”); Sturm, supra note 210, at 269–70 (arguing compliance accountability models discourage institutions from experimenting with creative solutions). 230. Ebrahim, supra note 89, at 12–13, 23 (emphasis added). 231. See A. V. Kelly, The National Curriculum: A Critical Review 49 (1990) (noting high score on external assessment system “need not reflect” that organization “is doing its best” for its intended beneficiaries). 232. See Tricia Connell, English: Meaning More, Not Less, in The National Curriculum and the Primary School: Springboard or Straitjacket? 15, 15–17 (Jeni Riley ed., 1992) (noting compliance with national curriculum in England may lead teachers to ignore “unspecified, but no less critical aspects of language . . . due to excessive concern for quantifiable outcomes”); O’Day, supra note 157, at 312–13 (noting under standardsbased reform policies, “schools exhibited an emphasis on strategies to produce immediate increases in test scores, often to the neglect of longer-term success”); Sturm, supra note 210, at 269–70 (noting external monitoring systems lead organizations to focus on easily quantifiable results); Ebrahim, supra note 89, at 25 (noting disclosures tend to focus on short-term results). R R R R R R R R R \\jciprod01\productn\C\COL\112-3\COL303.txt 2012] unknown Seq: 36 19-MAR-12 REGULATING BENEFIT CORPORATIONS 16:45 613 out any substantive improvements)233 and because, as discussed above, they have every incentive to do so. For example, an organization can easily change titles to make it look like it has more minorities in management positions.234 B Lab’s audits of benefit corporations lend themselves very much to this kind of manipulation: They are one-shot, short-term, occur only every few years, and rely on documentation provided by the benefit corporations themselves.235 In all of these ways, this accountability model may not only inhibit internal improvement, but may also, in some respects, cause a decrease in organizational effectiveness. For example, in the education context, the combination of quantitative performance metrics and negative sanctions has led teachers and schools to triage assistance to students nearest test score cut-off points,236 to expel students who might bring down test scores,237 to favor superficial rote learning over in-depth or individualized238 instruction, and generally “to teach in ways that [go] against their own notions of ‘good’ educational practice.”239 In these ways, “commercial competitiveness . . . cloud[s] professional judgment, the essence and prime motive of which is, or ought to be, a concern with the needs of the client (rather than the ‘consumer’).”240 III. AN ALTERNATIVE APPROACH TO MISSION ACCOUNTABILITY FOR BENEFIT CORPORATIONS Part III proposes revisions to the benefit corporation legislation that respond to the criticisms presented above. Part III.A presents an alternative theoretical model regarding for what benefit corporations should be accountable and to whom. Part III.B applies this theoretical model to the benefit corporation context. A. An Alternative to the SAAR Theoretical Model Part II.B critiqued the benefit corporation legislation for holding benefit corporations accountable (1) to an independent oversight body and the “market” (2) for attaining quantifiable and purportedly valueneutral standards for both process and outcomes. Part III.A proposes benefit corporations be held accountable as well (1) to self, professional peers, and the targeted beneficiaries of “specific public benefit” (2) for 233. See Sturm, supra note 210, at 266 (explaining results on external audits are easily manipulated). 234. Id. 235. See Become a B Corp, supra note 182 (describing B Lab’s auditing system). 236. O’Day, supra note 157, at 312–13. 237. See Rustique-Forrester, supra note 229, at 121, 125–26 (suggesting England’s National Curriculum “might provide possible explanations for the general rise” in expulsions and suspensions). 238. Id. at 121–22, 130, 143. 239. Id. at 136. 240. Kelly, supra note 231, at 49. R R R R R \\jciprod01\productn\C\COL\112-3\COL303.txt 614 unknown Seq: 37 COLUMBIA LAW REVIEW 19-MAR-12 16:45 [Vol. 112:578 maintaining “processes that can engender systematic critical reflection and adaptation.”241 Part III.A.1 explains this new “for what” framework; Part III.A.2 explains this new “to whom” framework. 1. An Alternative Framework for “Accountable for What”: Adaptive Learning. — An adaptive learning framework is concerned with assessing, first and foremost, an organization’s capacity for organizational learning.242 This requires not just regular monitoring of performance against mission,243 but also habits of observation, reflection, and analysis,244 a questioning attitude,245 proactive efforts to seek out hidden problems,246 the use of failures and mistakes as triggers for action,247 creativity and innovation,248 repeated trials and critical scrutiny of their results, acknowledgement of doubt, collaborative inquiry and mission development, conflict management, psychological safety,249 and robust communication across different levels of hierarchy and occupational specialties250 and across different peer organizations.251 Under this model, organizations are accountable not only for fixed results and fixed procedures, but also, first, for establishing and following processes for defining what those results and procedures should be and 241. Ebrahim, supra note 89, at 10. 242. See id. at 20–22 (describing concept of “adaptive learning”). 243. Id. at 21 (“As an accountability mechanism, adaptive learning focuses internally on organizational mission rather than externally on accountability to funders . . . .”). 244. See Carroll, supra note 209, at 702 (describing “four ordered learning processes” of observing, reflecting, creating, and acting). 245. Id. at 709 (describing root cause analysis). 246. Id. at 701 (describing need in high-hazard industries like nuclear power and chemical process plants to identify problems before they produce catastrophic consequences); see also Carroll & Edmondson, supra note 178, at 52 (“Safety and quality are enhanced by finding latent failures . . . .”). 247. See Sturm, supra note 210, at 295 (“Organizational catalysts at [the University of Michigan] create occasions for women and men concerned about gender to meet, . . . learn from mistakes, and take action . . . .”). 248. See Carroll, supra note 209, at 702 (describing “creating” as one of processes of ordered learning and defining it as “imagining, designing, planning, deciding”). 249. See Carroll & Edmondson, supra note 178, at 52 (“Organisations that value long term rather than short term performance . . . cultivate a variety of skills or disciplines to support learning, including acknowledgement of doubt, collaborative inquiry, personal and shared visioning, conflict management, team learning, and systems thinking.”). 250. See Carroll, supra note 209, at 700–01 (explaining “employees at different levels in the hierarchy . . . ‘know’ different things about how work is done,” especially in complex organizations where “no one person can know . . . both the ‘big picture’ and the details”); see also Carroll & Edmondson, supra note 178, at 55 (noting “powerful status differences” in healthcare organizations “inhibit open inquiry and collaborative learning”); Hopkins, supra note 185, at 217 (“The best companies have safety staff at several different points of the hierarchy . . . .”). For example, before the Moura coal-mine explosion, miners had reported detecting a “tarry” smell, an indication of coal burning. Management dismissed the reports and the burning coal eventually ignited a methane gas explosion. Hopkins, supra note 185, at 215. 251. See infra Part III.A.2.b (describing corporate accountability to individuals within organization and in peer organizations). R R R R R R R R R R \\jciprod01\productn\C\COL\112-3\COL303.txt 2012] unknown Seq: 38 REGULATING BENEFIT CORPORATIONS 19-MAR-12 16:45 615 how they should be measured and, second, for continuously adapting organizational efforts to achieve them. Instead of being “objective,” predominantly quantitative, and standardized, standards under this model are explicitly subjective; internally generated (in conjunction with peers, stakeholders, and regulators); justified on the basis of articulated reasons and research; and subject to continuous review.252 This approach recognizes that those attempting to address social problems “are unlikely to know how best to achieve their goals and what to measure along the way”253 and that they need to be adaptable not just in how they pursue their goals, but also in what specific goals they set— that they need “enough flexibility so that resources can be deployed away from social missions that are ineffective or no longer necessary.”254 It thus provides a framework both for developing performance targets that are better suited than SAAR to “[o]rganisations that value long term rather than short term performance and care about a wide[] range of outcomes (performance, safety, quality, environment) and stakeholders (shareholders, employees, customers, suppliers, community, society).”255 Because it is based on “capacity building” rather than compliance,256 this approach also better enables corporations to meet those targets than do the quantitative, results-oriented metrics of the SAAR model.257 This adaptive learning accountability framework has been implicitly or explicitly adopted in a range of other contexts, in the private, nonprofit, and government sectors. For example, in the private sector, analysis of the Three Mile Island (TMI) nuclear power plant meltdown revealed that information to prevent the . . . disaster was available from several sources—similar prior incidents at other plants, recurrent problems with the same equipment at TMI, and the critique of engineers that operators had been taught to do the wrong thing in particular circumstances—yet nothing had been done to incorporate this information into operating practices.258 252. Ebrahim, supra note 89, at 10. 253. Id. 254. Katz & Page, supra note 1, at 92–93; see also Sugin, supra note 93, at 920 (arguing for creation of “duty of fidelity” in nonprofit context that “would not prevent the board from amending its organizational documents” to respond to changing conditions). 255. Carroll & Edmondson, supra note 178, at 52. 256. See Ebrahim, supra note 89, at 24–25 (contrasting “[c]ompliance-driven accountability” with “strategy-driven accountability”); see also O’Day, supra note 157, at 311 (“[B]ureaucratic school accountability mechanisms . . . foster compliance . . . over system learning.”); Sturm, supra note 210, at 316–23 (describing “capacity building” approach). 257. See supra Part II.B.1.a (describing how quantitative measures alone may not provide information necessary to improve performance). 258. Carroll & Edmondson, supra note 178, at 52. R R R R R R R \\jciprod01\productn\C\COL\112-3\COL303.txt 616 unknown Seq: 39 COLUMBIA LAW REVIEW 19-MAR-12 16:45 [Vol. 112:578 As a result, “[l]earning [has become] a central activity in the nuclear power industry.”259 In the nonprofit sector, a recent report on “disturbingly high levels of preventable medical errors” in the National Health Service (NHS) in Britain attributed this pattern to the NHS being a “passive” rather than “active” learning organization, lacking the “structure, processes, and mindset” to rise to the next level of performance.260 The report called for “splic[ing] safety culture and learning into the organisational genome of the NHS,”261 concluding that the kind of standardization that is needed is not telling surgeons how to operate, but rather developing systems of communication and work practices.262 Similarly, in the government sector, recognizing the limits of safety management systems that rely on “compliance with various regulations and codes,” the Norwegian government has developed an approach to regulating petroleum companies that requires them to develop “safety cultures,” which they define as “a reporting culture, a just culture, a flexible culture, and a learning culture.”263 To create a learning culture, companies “must develop better mechanisms for detecting and responding to information about things that may be going wrong, or about to go wrong, and they must develop different styles of decision making.”264 The Norwegian regulators thus focus more on organizational design than on compliance with rules and regulations.265 2. An Alternative “Accountable to Whom” Framework: Internal Accountability, Professional Accountability, and Downward Accountability. — As argued in Part II.B.3, the benefit corporation model is driven primarily by upward accountability to external auditors, the courts, and “the market,” and does not provide sufficiently for three additional sources of accountability: (1) the corporation itself, (2) its professional peers, and (3) its intended beneficiaries. a. Internal Accountability. — Hess argues that the “primary goal” of the SAAR approach “is to ‘utilize the law to compel firms to behave “morally.”’”266 Research from psychology, economics, and other fields, however, suggests that “[t]he law can no more enforce success on charities 259. Carroll, supra note 209, at 701, 703 (explaining need in high-risk nuclear power and chemical process industries to “learn efficiently from precursors and minor incidents . . . due to the catastrophic costs of severe accidents” (citations omitted)). 260. Barach & Small, supra note 225, at 1683–84. 261. Id. at 1684; see also Carroll & Edmondson, supra note 178, at 51 (noting need for systems in hospitals that foster “cycle of action and reflection” to “increas[e] the capacity for effective organizational action through knowledge and understanding”). 262. Barach & Small, supra note 225, at 1683–84. 263. Hopkins, supra note 185, at 216–17 (emphasis added). 264. Id. at 217. 265. Id. 266. Hess, supra note 46, at 310 (quoting After Legal Instrumentalism? Strategic Models of Post-Regulatory Law, in Dilemmas of Law in the Welfare State 299, 320 (Gunther Teubner ed., 1986)). R R R R R R \\jciprod01\productn\C\COL\112-3\COL303.txt 2012] unknown Seq: 40 REGULATING BENEFIT CORPORATIONS 19-MAR-12 16:45 617 than it can enforce profits on business.”267 As a number of scholars have pointed out, “accountability has both an external dimension in terms of ‘an obligation to meet prescribed standards of behavior’ . . . and an internal one motivated by ‘felt responsibility;’”268 to be effective in the context of social goals, external accountability must align both with individuals’ intrinsic motivation269 and institutions’ internal accountability framework.270 Internal accountability is indispensable not just because humans are hardwired to perform best when their motivation is internal,271 but also for practical reasons. First, as explained in Part II.B.2.c, the most important “sources of learning” may be “analysis of an organization’s own experiences and internal debates rather than . . . benchmarking . . . or other external sources of information.”272 Second, no monitoring scheme can possibly be comprehensive enough, nor enforcement mechanism effective enough, to compel optimal social performance. For example, “[d]emands for permitting the unionization of garment workers . . . accelerated the outsourcing trend,”273 leaving American workers without any jobs at all; “[h]eightened emissions regulations pushed some manufacturers to the third world”;274 and noncompliance with federal nursing home standards “is the rule, not the exception.”275 b. Professional Accountability. — Individuals and organizations are governed not only by an internal sense of responsibility, but also by social 267. Sugin, supra note 93, at 920. 268. Ebrahim, supra note 89, at 3 (citations omitted). 269. Charles Abelmann et al., When Accountability Knocks, Will Anyone Answer? 16 (1999) (“Accountability in these schools boils down to individual teachers’ sense of responsibility. . . . [External] accountability structures exercised no effective influence over individual teachers’ sense of to whom and for what they were accountable.”); see also Langevoort, Internal Controls, supra note 119, at 971 (“Autonomy is a powerful motivator, for both individuals and groups.”); O’Day, supra note 157, at 304 (“Motivation must ultimately occur at the individual level.”). 270. See Abelmann et al., supra note 269, at 6 (“[H]ow a school responds to external accountability systems is largely determined . . . by the degree of alignment between the schools’ internal accountability mechanisms and the requirements of the external accountability system.”). 271. See Behn, supra note 89, at 11 (“‘[The] detailed regulation of public employees is not compatible with productivity, high morale, and innovation.’” (quoting Paul Volcker, former chairman of Federal Reserve Board, and William Winter, former governor of Mississippi)). 272. Carroll, supra note 209, at 701. 273. Chatterji & Richman, supra note 43, at 37. 274. Id. 275. Hovey, supra note 170, at 47–48; see also supra notes 231–240 and accompanying text (describing failure of quantitative performance metrics and punitive sanctions to improve organizational performance). R R R R R R R R R \\jciprod01\productn\C\COL\112-3\COL303.txt 618 unknown Seq: 41 COLUMBIA LAW REVIEW 19-MAR-12 16:45 [Vol. 112:578 and professional norms.276 In The Division of Labor in Society277 and Professional Ethics and Civic Morals,278 sociologist Émile Durkheim expounded a theory of “moral conduct . . . grounded in . . . networks of professional and personal ties.”279 He viewed “professional organizations and their historical forebears, the guilds and old corporations, as an important source of self-regulating economic institutions.”280 A number of industries rely on professional associations to define standards and peer review to ensure they are met.281 Recognizing the limits of external accountability, businesses developed “Smart Regulation,” a system of self-regulation and coregulation, after “it had become apparent that neither traditional command and control regulation nor the free market provides satisfactory answers to the increasingly complex and serious environmental problems which confront the world.”282 As a form of external accountability, professional accountability has a number of advantages that accountability to independent oversight bodies or the public at large does not have. First, professional accountability is better suited to preserving intrinsic motivation: In recent years, numerous social scientists have rediscovered the close relationships between communicative action, group ties, and the emergence of individual moral conduct. Contemporary philosophers . . . , social scientists . . . , and political scientists . . . have all offered distinctive and compelling arguments for the importance of interpersonal communication as a basic ingredient of sustained individual accountability.283 Second, professional accountability is better suited to generating valid metrics of performance. Because it involves members of the profes276. See Abelmann et al., supra note 269, at 3–4 (distinguishing “responsibility,” which is “personal and individual in nature and . . . stems from the values and beliefs of individuals,” from “expectations,” which “are collective in nature,” “shared,” and “formed out of relationships among individuals”); Furger, supra note 183, at 447 (describing “social rules, practices, and standards of accountability which at any given time characterize an industry and its members”). 277. Émile Durkheim, The Division of Labor in Society (1933) [hereinafter Durkheim, Division of Labor]. 278. Émile Durkheim, Professional Ethics and Civic Morals (1957). 279. Furger, supra note 183, at 447. 280. Id. For example, the American Bar Association sets standards of conduct for lawyers and accredits the schools that trains them; the National Fire Protection Association has established fire protection codes for over a century; and the Institute of Nuclear Power Operations spurred safety improvements in the nuclear power industry. Id. at 452. 281. Id. at 450; O’Day, supra note 157, at 315–16. 282. Neil Gunningham, Enforcement and Compliance Strategies, in The Oxford Handbook of Regulation 120, 131–35 (Robert Baldwin, Martin Cave & Martin Lodge eds., 2010). 283. Furger, supra note 183, at 449 (citations omitted); see also O’Day, supra note 157, at 317 (“[P]rofessional accountability expands the incentives for improvement, with particular emphasis on the intrinsic motivators that bring teachers into teaching in the first place, a commitment to students . . . and an identity as an educator.” (citation omitted)). R R R R R R \\jciprod01\productn\C\COL\112-3\COL303.txt 2012] unknown Seq: 42 REGULATING BENEFIT CORPORATIONS 19-MAR-12 16:45 619 sion assuming responsibility for defining standards of practice, it is adapted to activities “too complex . . . to be governed by bureaucratically defined rules,”284 like education, medicine, or environmental protection. As Durkheim argued, “neither political society in its entirety, nor the State can take over” the function of defining appropriate standards of professional accountability: “[E]conomic life, because it is specialized and grows more specialized every day, escapes their competence . . . . An occupational activity can be efficaciously regulated only by a group intimate enough with it to know its functioning . . . .”285 Third, professional accountability has certain advantages in helping an organization achieve those standards by promoting adaptive learning. Through norms of professional interchange, mentoring, and collective problem-solving, it can promote “the generation and spread of information.”286 Moreover, the information it produces is likely to be “more finegrained and immediate” and better suited to “meaningful interpretation[]” than information “accumulated at higher levels of aggregation.”287 c. Downward Accountability. — Finally, in addition to fostering accountability to self and to professional peers, an accountability framework for benefit corporations should provide accountability to those the corporation purports to benefit. In some respects, “downward accountability mechanisms remain comparatively underdeveloped,”288 though there have already been efforts to incorporate downward accountability in the corporate289 and government contexts.290 284. O’Day, supra note 157, at 315. 285. Durkheim, Division of Labor, supra note 277, at 5; see supra notes 215–220 and accompanying text (discussing how accountability to external parties can interfere with internal accountability). 286. O’Day, supra note 157, at 316–17. 287. Id. 288. Ebrahim, supra note 89, at 23. 289. See Hess, supra note 46, at 317–19 (describing stakeholder focus groups and surveys conducted by The Body Shop and Ben & Jerry’s). 290. For example, Pasi Sahlberg, a member of Finland’s Ministry of Education and Culture, attributes Finland’s exceptional performance on international assessments of student achievement to Finnish schools’ reliance on professional and downward forms of accountability (to teachers, students, and parents), rather than upward models of accountability. In Finland, neither external auditors nor externally imposed standardized tests are used to compare teachers or schools to one another. Instead, teachers, students, and parents “assess[] and . . . decid[e] how well schools, teachers, or students do what they are supposed to do.” Pasi Sahlberg, Learning from Finland: How One of the World’s Top Educational Performers Turned Around, Bos. Globe, Dec. 27, 2010, at A9; see also Broadfoot, supra note 133, at 161, 165, 229 (noting “the [French Ministry of Education] has so far resisted pressure for [student test] results to be made public and thus to provide for inter-school . . . comparisons. . . . [S]trongly held French belief[s] [about] . . . educational provision militate[] against the adoption of . . . market forces to stimulate” improvement). R R R R R R \\jciprod01\productn\C\COL\112-3\COL303.txt 620 unknown Seq: 43 COLUMBIA LAW REVIEW 19-MAR-12 16:45 [Vol. 112:578 B. Applying the Theory: An Alternative Accountability Framework for Benefit Corporations Disclosure, reporting, measurement, and external monitoring per se are not inimical to effective mission accountability. Many argue, for example, that they can serve to stimulate internal reflection and change.291 Part III.B proposes an alternative accountability framework for benefit corporations that—like the benefit corporation legislation—incorporates these tools, but—unlike the benefit corporation legislation—does so in such a way as to foster adaptive learning and internal, professional, and downward accountability. Specifically, this alternative framework reconceptualizes three components of the benefit corporation legislation: its use of assessment (Part III.B.1), external auditing (Part III.B.2), and incentives (Part III.B.3). 1. Reconceptualizing Assessment: Formative Evaluation. — One means to promote adaptive learning is through monitoring schemes that incorporate formative evaluation, which is a way to gather information to improve practices. Rather than, “Are you doing X?,” formative evaluation asks, “Is X working?” and, if you are not doing X, “How can you be helped to do X?” Like adaptive learning strategies, formative evaluation has been used in the private, nonprofit, and government sectors. In the private sector, for example, formative evaluation has become increasingly popular in the high-hazard nuclear power and chemical processing industries, where it is particularly important for firms to identify safety threats before regulators discover them. “[T]o identify problems, interpret the reasons for these problems, and select corrective actions,” firms in these industries have developed strategies like incident reviews and root cause analysis.292 Incident reviews involve “reporting, documenting, and analysing less serious incidents” to learn how processes can be improved.293 Root cause analysis involves assembling groups of employees from different levels of hierarchy, different functional specialties, and different plants to analyze selected problems. These types of exercises not only help understand causes and possible solutions better than summative evaluation; they also proactively uncover unrelated problems that can be addressed later.294 291. See Dorf & Sabel, supra note 149, at 331 (“[R]eporting requirements not only assure line-level accountability to management, but provide data that can be used to benchmark problem-solving teams and efforts against one another.”); E-mail from Barbara Schatz, Clinical Professor of Law, Columbia Law Sch., to author (Jan. 31, 2011) (on file with the Columbia Law Review) (explaining widespread belief that IRS’s recently added requirements that 501(c)(3) organizations report on document retention and whistleblower policies have prompted many organizations to adopt such policies, even though no sanctions attach for not having them). 292. Carroll, supra note 209, at 704. 293. Id. 294. Hopkins, supra note 185, at 214–15. R R R \\jciprod01\productn\C\COL\112-3\COL303.txt 2012] unknown Seq: 44 REGULATING BENEFIT CORPORATIONS 19-MAR-12 16:45 621 In the nonprofit sector, Minneapolis Children’s Hospitals and Clinics built learning mechanisms like blame-free event studies and safety dialogues as a means to improve patient safety.295 In the government sector, the U.S. Army uses After Action Reviews (AAR) immediately after training exercises or real events to give participants the opportunity to share observations and ideas in a blame-free discussion. Introduced after the Vietnam War, AAR “transformed the Army,” improving learning at both an individual and organizational level.296 The benefit corporation legislation, in contrast, relies primarily on a summative evaluation—that is, on measuring achievement of preset benchmarks. The “B” certification process emphasizes whether an organization has performed up to par, not why it might be falling short or how it can improve, or what “up to par” should mean.297 Summative assessment can be useful to compare efforts across benefit corporations with like missions and to suggest improvements. For example, in Finland’s school system, politicians and administrators learn about schools’ performance by conducting sample-based learning tests and research targeted to understanding how schools work.298 For summative assessment to be useful as a tool for adaptive learning, however, (1) it should not be tied to sanctions,299 (2) it should not rely exclusively on quantitative metrics, and (3) it should be complemented by formative evaluation. 2. Reconceptualizing the Role of External Auditor: Institutional Intermediaries and Organizational Catalysts. — Another means to promote adaptive learning in benefit corporations would be to reconceptualize the role of the third-party auditor. In particular, rather than require conformity to independently developed generic standards, the third-party auditor could foster more flexible adaptation to professionally developed industry-specific standards. How would the third-party auditor serve this function? Durkheim, who so vigorously defended the importance of professional standards of conduct in specialized industries,300 believed these standards developed and spread through “professional and personal ties,” “in face-to-face interactions,” and by “members of a certain group . . . interact[ing] regularly.”301 He worried, moreover, that “[u]nlike other professionals, mod295. Carroll & Edmondson, supra note 178, at 51. 296. Id. 297. See Ebrahim, supra note 89, at 25 (“[R]eporting requirements . . . biased in favor of easily measurable assessments of progress . . . undervalue adaptive assessments that are essential for understanding how a nonprofit might improve its work.”). 298. Sahlberg, supra note 290. 299. See Sturm, supra note 210, at 314–16 (describing use of assessments and evaluations as sources of information, not threats); see also supra notes 229–240 and accompanying text (discussing consequences of attaching sanctions to disclosures). 300. See supra notes 277–280 and accompanying text (discussing Durkheim’s view of role of professional standards). 301. Furger, supra 183, at 447. R R R R R R R \\jciprod01\productn\C\COL\112-3\COL303.txt 622 unknown Seq: 45 COLUMBIA LAW REVIEW 19-MAR-12 16:45 [Vol. 112:578 ern entrepreneurs were not embedded in networks of personal ties.”302 To encourage this kind of regular professional interaction, and to “drag [individuals], in this way, into the general torrent of social life,”303 scholarship suggests a combination of two institutionalized roles, one external to the benefit corporation304—what might be called an “institutional intermediary”305—and one internal to it—what might be called an “organizational catalyst.”306 a. Institutional Intermediary. — Like B Lab, an institutional intermediary serves as a source of external accountability for performance in relation to common metrics.307 An institutional intermediary is unlike B Lab, however, in three critical respects. First, unlike B Lab,308 an institutional intermediary’s role is less about “checking compliance with rules, and . . . more about encouraging the industry to put in place its own systems of internal control and management which are then scrutinized by regulators.”309 It thus preserves internal accountability more effectively than the SAAR model.310 Second, an institutional intermediary—as the name suggests—fosters professional accountability by pooling knowledge between members of an industry and “developing a community of practice to sustain . . . inquiry and learning.”311 In this way, the institutional intermediary does not just collect information from the regulated entity; it also provides information to that entity. Third, an institutional intermediary fosters adaptive learning by focusing on formative as well as summative evaluation. It asks not just about performance to date, but also vision, difficulties in implementing proposed activities, approaches to addressing the difficulties, and preliminary findings from self-evaluations. It encourages organizations “to ask more probing questions” about their own effec- 302. Id. at 447–48. 303. Durkheim, Division of Labor, supra note 277, at 28. 304. See, e.g., O’Day, supra note 157, at 318 (noting limitation of internal accountability in ensuring equality of provision across schools). 305. See Sturm, supra note 210, at 271–80 (introducing “institutional intermediary” concept). 306. Id. at 287–300 (introducing “organizational catalyst” concept). 307. Id. at 271–80. 308. In developing its standards, B Lab consults with “entrepreneurs, investors, thought leaders and academics.” Certified B Corp., How Was the B Impact Assessment Developed?, BCorporation.net, http://www.bcorporation.net/become/BRS (follow “How Was the B Impact System Developed?” hyperlink) (on file with the Columbia Law Review) (last visited Feb. 13, 2012). B Lab considers “performance standards and impact metrics” from sources such as the GRI, Wiser Business, and the Social Venture Network. Id.; see also supra note 144 (listing some of these earlier codes). 309. Gunningham, supra note 282, at 135. 310. See O’Day, supra note 157, at 311 (“[B]ureaucratic school accountability policies are insufficient to establish the patterns of interaction that might foster more information sharing in low-capacity schools.”). 311. Sturm, supra note 210, at 280. R R R R R R R \\jciprod01\productn\C\COL\112-3\COL303.txt 2012] unknown Seq: 46 REGULATING BENEFIT CORPORATIONS 19-MAR-12 16:45 623 tiveness312 and experiment with creative solutions.313 In sum, the institutional intermediary approach, which in effect tells the organization “you draw up a plan and we will inspect you against it,” involves “far more than passive compliance monitoring . . . . Rather it involves actively challenging the enterprise to demonstrate that its systems work in practice”314 and “encourag[ing] internal self-critical reflection about its regulatory performance.”315 It thus serves a capacity-building, or “reciprocal accountability,” function.316 Again, existing models for an institutional intermediary can be found in both the public and private sectors. In the government sector, an example of an institutional intermediary is the National Science Foundation (NSF), a federal agency that awards grants for scientific research.317 NSF recipients must commit to data-based decisionmaking, the use of formative evaluation, and creative and experimental approaches.318 They must clearly state the conceptual framework and research foundation for experimental approaches they use, suggest the benchmarks (both quantitative and qualitative) by which their efforts should be measured, show how data will be used as part of an ongoing change process, and detail a plan for sharing best practices.319 In the private sector, the U.S. nuclear power industry established the Institute for Nuclear Power Operations “to promote safety and reliability through external reviews of performance and processes, training and accreditation programmes, events analysis, sharing of operating information and best practices, and special assistance to member utilities.”320 Who should fill this role for benefit corporations? According to Durkheim, “occupational groups” are best suited for this role.321 Others, however, warn that the use of professional associations for this purpose 312. Hopkins, supra note 185, at 214. 313. See Sturm, supra note 210, at 271–80 (discussing how National Science Foundation adopts accountability approach that fosters creative experimentation in context of its ADVANCE grant program). 314. Gunningham, supra note 282, at 135–37 (referring to this approach as “meta regulation”). 315. Id. 316. Richard F. Elmore, Bridging the Gap Between Standards and Achievement: The Imperative for Professional Development in Education Accountability 5 (2002) (“For every increment of performance I demand from you, I have an equal responsibility to provide you with the capacity to meet that expectation. . . . This is the principle of ‘reciprocity of accountability for capacity.’ It is the glue that, in the final analysis, will hold accountability systems together.”). 317. Sturm, supra note 210, at 251. 318. Id. at 278. 319. Id. at 280–82. 320. Carroll, supra note 209, at 703. 321. See Durkheim, Division of Labor, supra note 277, at 28 (“A nation can be maintained only if, between the State and the individual, there is intercalated a whole series of secondary groups. . . . [O]ccupational groups are suited to fill this role, and that is their destiny.”). R R R R R R \\jciprod01\productn\C\COL\112-3\COL303.txt 624 unknown Seq: 47 COLUMBIA LAW REVIEW 19-MAR-12 16:45 [Vol. 112:578 presents the danger of collusion.322 To date, the “specific role” of professional and trade associations “as institutions that are particularly suited to develop and maintain standards of accountability has rarely been systematically explored.”323 As alternatives to professional associations, some suggest either a government entity or a third-party certifier, like B Lab, “that operate[s] independently of both the state and the relevant trade association.”324 A third-party institutional intermediary, however, would ideally make greater use of formative evaluation and more direct use of peer institutions to monitor and work with one another than does the current B Lab certification approach. b. Organizational Catalysts. — Emerging theories of regulation stress the importance of partnering external regulators with individuals within the organization.325 These “organizational catalysts” are ideally individuals who know the culture of the organization being regulated326 and, critically, possess “clout”327 in the organization—that is, someone with high status, high social and intellectual capital, sufficient resources, “direct lines of communication . . . [to] chief executives,”328 and who is otherwise strategically placed within the organization to mobilize learning and change by communicating with peers in their cultural/professional language.329 Organizational catalysts mobilize change by developing experiments, analyzing their effects, and reporting on them to the external regulator;330 cultivating “communities of practice” among individuals in the organization who might otherwise lack opportunities to connect; playing an ombudsman role, so people have someone to come forward to with 322. See Andrew A. King & Michael J. Lenox, Industry Self-Regulation Without Sanctions: The Chemical Industry’s Responsible Care Program, 43 Acad. Mgmt. J. 698, 713 (2000) (“Overseeing parties must be outsiders . . . . Trade associations are limited as enforcers both legally and practically, since they are ultimately governed by their members.”). 323. Furger, supra note 183, at 449; King & Lenox, supra note 322, at 699 (“[L]ittle research has addressed the potential for self-regulation by industry associations . . . .”). 324. King & Lenox, supra note 322, at 713; see also Sturm, supra note 210, at 328–30 (suggesting institutional intermediary could be government agency, accrediting body, nonprofit, professional association, or foundation). 325. Hopkins, supra note 185, at 215 (“Many studies have shown that these internally located . . . professionals are vital for organizational compliance.”); see also Sturm, supra note 210, at 251, 287–99 (“[I]nstitutional attentiveness can be . . . achieved by creating institutional roles that place people with knowledge, influence, and credibility in positions to influence practice . . . .”). 326. Sturm, supra note 210, at 287–99. 327. Hopkins, supra note 185, at 215. 328. Id. 329. Sturm, supra note 210, at 287–300; see also Hopkins, supra note 185, at 215 (noting external regulators can also contribute to organizational catalysts’ clout by lending support when organizational catalyst takes unpopular line). 330. Sturm, supra note 210, at 287–99; see also Hopkins, supra note 185, at 216 (“[A] safety culture is a reporting culture, a just culture, a flexible culture, and a learning culture.”). R R R R R R R R \\jciprod01\productn\C\COL\112-3\COL303.txt 2012] unknown Seq: 48 REGULATING BENEFIT CORPORATIONS 19-MAR-12 16:45 625 problems they have identified; and maintaining the momentum to act by continuously “destabiliz[ing] . . . organizational routine.”331 In this way, they contribute to adaptive learning and to both external332 and internal accountability. 3. Reconceptualizing Incentive. — In a study of Responsible Care, a “velvet glove” (i.e., sanctionless) approach to industry self-regulation instituted by the Chemical Manufacturers Association (CMA) to regulate environmental and safety performance, King and Lenox found that members of Responsible Care improved their performance more slowly than nonmembers.333 They concluded that, when it comes to accountability models, the “iron fist” of “explicit sanctions administered by informed outsiders may be needed to avoid opportunism” and poor performance.334 As robust as this finding about Responsible Care’s ineffectiveness may be, the hypothesis that the reason for this finding is the lack of external audits and explicit sanctions has no basis in King and Lenox’s empirical data. Nor does it have much basis elsewhere: There is still very little supporting the hypothesis that explicit sanctions are an effective regulatory tool. This hypothesis is still “just a presumption backed by common sense.”335 Rather than support this hypothesis, the available evidence on the relationship between sanctions and performance suggests instead that external sanctions actually undermine performance at both the individual and organization levels.336 An equally plausible explanation for the Responsible Care findings—but one that King and Lenox did not consider—is that Responsible Care is fundamentally a compliance-driven, rather than a capacitybuilding, approach. It is concerned with monitoring firms’ compliance with certain fixed inputs, not with fostering adaptive learning or internal accountability.337 That King and Lenox chose to attribute their findings instead to Responsible Care’s lack of sanctions may reflect what seems to 331. Sturm, supra note 210, at 287–99. 332. See Hopkins, supra note 185, at 216 (“The benefits [of internal change agents] are, of course, mutual. Inspectors who consult with company safety officers may be able to identify deficiencies in company systems far more quickly than if they have to identify these things for themselves.”). 333. King & Lenox, supra note 322, at 700, 711. The U.S. Chemical Manufacturers Association created the Responsible Care program “to improve the environmental and safety performance of CMA members and to thereby improve public perception of the industry.” Id. at 699. All CMA members are required to be part of the Responsible Care program, which includes ten guiding principles and six codes of management practices. CMA members must annually self-assess their progress toward implementation of the Responsible Care program’s code. Id. at 699–700. 334. Id. at 700, 713. 335. Moe, supra note 169, at 2. 336. See supra Part II.B.2.c (describing how external sanctions undermine organizational effectiveness). 337. King & Lenox, supra note 322, at 699–700 (explaining Responsible Care’s focus on ensuring firms’ compliance with inputs). R R R R R \\jciprod01\productn\C\COL\112-3\COL303.txt 626 unknown Seq: 49 COLUMBIA LAW REVIEW 19-MAR-12 16:45 [Vol. 112:578 be a popular bias in policy circles today toward accountability models based on external audits and sanctions.338 As a substitute for external sanctions, incentives are needed that can reduce the risks and increase the rewards associated with identifying problems, gathering data, and engaging in regular self-evaluation; that can increase the motivation deriving from a sense of personal responsibility and adherence to professional expectations; and that can, at the same time, effectively deter irresponsible conduct. Intrinsic motivation, an internal sense of civic responsibility, may be one such mechanism. Informal social regulation may be another: “[T]he few empirical investigations available indicate that the impact of informal social regulation within the professions may well have been underestimated.”339 Renée de Nevers argues that informal sanctions, like peer pressure and shaming (“management by embarrassment”), “can often push companies to adhere to normative standards,” since “‘none of us want to be viewed as a poor performer among our peers.’”340 A likely criticism of these internal and informal incentives is that they may work well enough when the corporation being “audited” is already pursuing its social mission in good faith and with a base level of competence, but that the whole point of “accountability” is to compel performance by those who lack such qualities. One way to address this concern might be an approach called “responsive regulation,” in which regulators start out by “assuming virtue (to which they respond with cooperative measures)” but switch, if their expectations are disappointed, to responding “with progressively more punitive strategies until the regulatee conforms.”341 The thinking is that “good regulation means invoking different responsive enforcement strategies depending upon whether one is dealing with leaders, reluctant compliers, the recalcitrant or the incompetent.”342 Another way to address possible gaps in intrinsic motivation could be to maintain a certification-based incentive system, but to base certification on qualitative assessments of performance against internal and industry-specific standards, rather than on externally imposed standards expressed in terms of quantitative outputs. The key is to decouple the lethal combination of sanctions and external standards.343 338. See supra Part II.A (describing popularity of accountability models that use threat of punishment as incentive). 339. Furger, supra note 183, at 450–51. 340. Renée de Nevers, The Effectiveness of Self-Regulation by the Private Military and Security Industry, 30 J. Pub. Pol’y 219, 224 (2010) (quoting Jospeh V. Ress, Hostages of Each Other: The Transformation of Nuclear Safety Since Three Mile Island 104–05 (1994)). 341. Gunningham, supra note 282, at 120–21. 342. Id. at 126. 343. See supra Part II.B.2.c (describing how external sanctions combined with quantitative performance metrics undermine organizational effectiveness). R R \\jciprod01\productn\C\COL\112-3\COL303.txt 2012] unknown Seq: 50 REGULATING BENEFIT CORPORATIONS 19-MAR-12 16:45 627 It is also possible that when intrinsic motivation and basic ability are lacking, nothing can compel high performance—particularly in a complex social or cultural endeavor.344 In such cases, the best remedy is probably just to make sure the organization in question gets out of the field— and this does not require extensive public disclosure or market pressure to accomplish. Bad apples can be identified by much less administratively burdensome—and less statistically questionable—means. 4. Putting It All Together. — There is still a place, then, for measurement, external auditing, and reporting in an effective mission accountability framework, but all need to be adapted to take into account the unique characteristics of corporations’ “public benefit” objectives. Instead of “top-down imposition of an independent standard by a disinterested third party, backed by the ability to impose stiff sanctions,”345 accountability for benefit corporations should rely more heavily on bottomup development of explicitly subjective standards, developed jointly by the organization itself, the industry as a whole, and key stakeholders, and backed by internal and professional sources of accountability. Such an accountability model would focus on measurement not just of fixed inputs or procedures, but also of structures and practices that foster adaptive learning; and it would rely on external regulators to fill a more capacity-building rather than compliance-driven role. CONCLUSION The idea of applying market-based solutions to social problems has a beguiling charm—especially, perhaps, for Americans, whose material prosperity has historically been built on success in industry. As we broach this new frontier of social enterprise, however, it is critical to reconsider pervasive assumptions about the appropriateness of applying businessmodel accountability techniques to the performance of social goals.346 Experience in the nonprofit and government sectors suggests that, to be effective, accountability for performance of social goals should emphasize adaptive learning rather than fixed procedures or outcomes, and should emphasize accountability to self, professional peers, and “clients,” rather than accountability to judges, “generalist” auditors from government agencies or nonprofits, or the market. 344. See supra Part III.A.2.a (arguing no monitoring scheme can possibly be comprehensive enough, nor enforcement mechanism effective enough, to compel optimal social performance). 345. Besmer, supra note 151, at 302. 346. See Sugin, supra note 93, at 894 (“We must analyze whether requiring—or even encouraging—conformity to a business model produces meaningful results for charitable endeavors.”). R R