Journal of Psycholinguistic Research, Vol. 20, No. 3, 1991 A Sketchbook of Production Problems Kathryn Bock1 . Accepted February 5, 1991 This paper sets out five problems of language production that dominate current research in the area. Four of them are problems that the f o d a t o r must solve in order to carry out its functions. Consideration of these problems has spawned different theoretical perspectives on and a variety of empirical findings about how the formulator works, and these are briefly surveyed. The fifth problem is metatheoretical, and concerns the proper domain of production theory. The purpose of this paper is to identify some of the major themes in research on language production. Over the past 15 years or so, work in this area has rapidly made the transition from a psycholinguistic hobby to a central enterprise in the study of language performance. Although the focal problems are in many ways similar to those of language comprehension, there are important differences that help to make the study of production distinct. I will sketch five problems, starting with the one that serves as a major force in dividing the issues of production from those of comprehension, and briefly illustrate how these problems have been addressed in current theory and research. Four of the problems are This paper is adapted from a talk that introduced the Special Session on Language Production at the Third Annual CUNY Conference on Human Sentence Processing. 1 am grateful to the other participants in the session (Gary S. Dell, Merrill F. Garrett, W.J.M.Lcvelt. David D. McDonald. and Stcfanie Shattuck-Hufnageo for their contributions to this paper, and to Janet D. Fodor for making time stand still. Preparation of the manuscript was supported by grants from the National Science Foundation (BNS8617659) and the National Institutes of Health (R01-HD21011). ' Address all correspondence to Kathryn Bock, Department of Psychology, Psychology Research Building, Michigan State University, East Lansing, Michigan 48824-11 17. 141 0090.690519 1/0500-014 1106.50/0 0 1991 Plenum Publishing Corporation 142 Production P r o t Bock processing challenges that the production system must meet, and the last is a question about the domain of a production theory. Presenting the big problems requires a solution to a little problem of terminology. There is no very satisfactory label in general use for the cognitive apparatus that is responsible for producing language. The natural complement to the parser would seem to be the articulator, an apparatus that joins pieces together into systematic units. But that term is ambiguous and, in its dominant meaning, too toothy and lippy to adequately capture the higher-level linguistic processes that give rise to speech. As an alternative, I will refer to the formuiator, borrowing the term from Levelt's compleat introduction to the problems of production . - . . - -.-(Levelt, 1989). .--. THE FIVE PROBLEMS The five sections that follow present the five problems. In order, they are (1) getting the form right; (2) regulating information flow; (3) fluency; (4) coordination; and (5) type transparency. Regulating In) Getting the Form Right The goal of comprehension is to create an interpretation of an utterance. The goal of production-at least the speaker's immediate goalis simply to create an utterance. That utterance should be adequate to convey the speaker's meaning, but it must also meet a range of constraints that we think of in terms of the grammar. And that gives the production problem a different spin. As Garrett (1980) put it, "The production system must get the details of form 'right' in every instance, whether those details are germane to sentence meaning or not." So, a very general problem for a theory of production is to explain how speakers create linguistic structures at all levels. This difference between production and comprehension can lead to somewhat different evaluations of the role and the importance of structure in general, as well as structures in particular. Subject-verb agreement offers an illustration. This type of agreement carries little of the burden of interpretation in English, and in line with this, there are studies of comprehension which show that readers are all but oblivious to agreement violations such as Some shells is even soft at the same time that they are keenly aware of the problem with Sometimes the diamondback swims in the open sea but it usually lives in salt shakers and tidal rivers (Kilborn, 1988; Kutas & Hillyard, 1983). This tends to engender the idea that agreement is surprisingly st In several expi conditions knt ments 1 and 2 they could ha' In genera Tape-recorded prone than in fences, Deese yielding a rate sentences. Otl and word-leve of spontaneou ishingly low. ' of form right. \ Somewhi creating acce] leads to a pro1 like this: A s respect, has ey tures and inte The speaker r pretation. Thc creating a stn sequence, we Table I. Estirr the Deese (I! Corpus Deese (1984) London-Lund 2 Brian MacWhi for the speaker 143 production Problems agreement is all but irrelevant to the use of English. Yet speakers are surprisingly scrupulous in their observation of subject-verb agreement. In several experiments that were designed to elicit agreement errors under conditions known to predispose them. Bock and Miller (1991. Experiments 1 and 2) observed errors in less than 5% of the utterances in which they could have occurred. In general, speakers are very good at creating acceptable utterances. Tape-recorded corpora reveal that everyday speech is much less errorprone than intuition might suggest. In a corpus of nearly 15,000 sentences, Deese (1984) found just 77 that could not be parsed sensibly. yielding a rate of just five serious structural anomalies for each thousand sentences. Other errors are also rare. Table I gives the rates of soundand word-level errors per 10,000 words from two tape-recorded corpora of spontaneous speech. Though the rates differ slightly, both are astonishingly low. The production system does. in fact, tend to get the details of form right. Regulating Information Flow: The Full-Deck-of-Cards Paradox Somewhat strangely, speakers actually may be more successflil at creating acceptable forms than at conveying intended messages. This leads to a problem that I will call the full-deck-of-cards2 paradox. It runs like this: A speaker knows the communicative intention and. in that respect, has every advantage over comprehenders, who must piece structures and interpretations together from degraded and ambiguous input. The speaker merely has to create structures that convey a known interpretation. The paradox is that speakers can be simultaneously adept at creating a structure and inept at conveying an interpretation. As a consequence, we get a central fact about speech errors: They obey structural Table I. Estimated Rates per 10,000 Words for Sound and Word Errors from the Deese (1984) and London-Lund (Gamham. Shillcock. Brown, Mill, & Corpus - Dcese (1984) London-Lund Cutler. 1982) Corpora of Spontaneous Speech Estimated rates per 10.000 words Sound errors Word errors .1.3u e , . 3.20 2.50 5.10 . . .- . Bock Produ constraints at the same time that they egregiously violate the intended to m: flow One of the best-known structural constraints concerns form classes. The form-class constraint i s reliably illustrated in such errors as word exchanges, when two words transpose (e-g., The speakers of the minds of that community, in which minds and speakers traded places); semantic substitutions, in which a word that means something similar to the intended word substitutes for it (e-g., Until now, just do it, where now replaces the intended word then); and phonological substitutions, in which a word that sounds similar to the intended word substitutes for it (e-g., He's the kind of man that soldiers look up toand try to emanate, where emanate replaces emulate). None of the sample errors successfully conveys the speaker's intended meaning, but all of them obey syntactic constraints, because the words that interact in creating the errors represent the same form classes (for word exchanges, between 80% and 85% of spontaneous speech errors obey the form-class constraint, and for word substitutions, nearly 100% represent the form class of the intended word; Garrett, 1980; Stemberger, 1985). Errors that involve bound morphemes rather than full words (e-g., It'll get fast a lot hotter i f you put the burner on, when hot a lot faster was intended) likewise obey syntactic constraints as a result of affix stranding: Only the word stem moves (this is true for approximately 90% of such errors; Stemberger, 1985). In similar fashion, sound-level errors obey phonotactic constraints, creating acceptable phonological structures. So, analogous to the form-class constraint, there is a sound-class constraint on errors: Consonants interact with other consonants (e.g., Jashon and Josua when Jason and Joshua was intended), and vowels with other vowels (e.g., surplus accipital activity when occipital activity was intended) and originate in the same positions in words or syllables. The full-deck-of-cards paradox may be more apparent than real, though, because "playing with a full deck" may not be an especially good thing for a speaker who is forced by the constraints of the vocalauditory channel to say one thing at a time. If one knows, at some level, much more than one can conveyat a given moment, a great deal of work must go into not saying a lot of things, in order to say the right things at the right time. The availability of information other than that which is actually spoken and the deleterious potential of that availability are evident in the prevalence of contextual errors-errors more often than not have an identifiable source somewhere in the intended utteranceand in the predominance of anticipatory over perseveratory errors. So, begir flood rett's 1988 repre spon built item: func t (V)( this thou the 1 . ogic ,the 1 tern fransion 4 ! : 1 I ! , .. .I1 1 I I . gwe Dell retri I h an< inf is for int 19 ! P" an cl; fre ne [hi AI sa PC production Problems I I b i1 I 145 to mix metaphors, the full deck of cards gives rise to a torrent whose flow must be continuously regulated. But there are leaks. And those leaks, in the form of speech errors, begin to reveal the design of the machinery that ordinarily controls the flood. One influential analysis of errors is that of Merrill Garrett. Garrett's analysis motivates a model of the production process (Garrett, 1988) that is shown in Fig. 1. Briefly, there are three levels, the topmost representing the intended message. The remaining two levels are responsible for putting the linguistic pieces of utterances together. One builds the functional-level representation by assigning selected lexical items from the lexical set to syntactic functions within clauses; these functions are represented a s the slots in the functional structure ((V)(S(V)(N)(N))). The phonological forms of words are irrelevant to this assignment, as is the eventual order of the words in the utterance, though the form classes of words are critical. The second level creates the positional-level representation, where both word order and phonological forms are specified within phrases. Word forms are retrieved from the lexicon and their segmental and prosodic features are assigned to the terminal elements of the constituent structure or positional-level planning frame (see Shattuck-Hufnagel, 1979, 1987, for a more detailed discussion of how this second level might be o r g a n i ~ e d ) . ~ The levels of the model neatly explain the complex error, The skreaky p e a s e gets the wheel, which was observed by Garrett4 and analyzed by Dell (1989) in the following fashion. Initially, wheel and grease are retrieved from the lexical set and assigned the wrong syntactic functions I I have omitted a controversial set of processes that follow the assignment of segmental and prosodic structure. In Garrett's scheme these processes interpret and site node information (Ganett, 1988). that is, they insert the elements of the closed class. There is considerable disagreement about whether the phonological interpretation of these forms is different from that of the open class (see Dell. 1990). whether the forms are inherent in positional frames in the way that this mechanism seems to require (Bock, 1989). and whether the closed class constitutes a separable vocabulary of the language processor, as their peculiar vulnerability in aphasic disorders seems to suggest (aphasics are generally better at dealing with high- than with low-frequency words, but closedclass words are disproportionately absent from aphasic speech despite their very high frequencies of occurrence in normal speech; Garrett, 1990). Garrett (1990) presented new evidence from speech errors to counter the hypothesis that it is word frequency that is responsible for most of the differences between the open and closed classes. Among those word-exchange errors involving open- or closed-class words from the same frequency ranges, open-class errors predominated. ' Personal communication. November 1, 1988. J Production Problems Bock 7 Inferential processes Message representation of functional structures selection 1 { Lexical'assignment t Functional level representation \ . , Ñ Assignment of segmental and prosodic structure for words Positional level representation Fig. 1. A model of language production (slightly modified from Garrett, 1988). in the functional structure (wheel becomes the object and grease the subject). That functional error eventuates in the placement of grease in the same phrase wil frame, and sets up and HI. That excha This analysis rationalizing error 1 ambitious. It is als tion. The need to 1 and the model's ml this is achieved. Ji modularity (Fodor, modular, since it m are capable of exp many errors is enol far downstream. C severe restriction c that level are sensi A related rest Because everythin discrete stages of up influence f r o m retrieval side, one errors that have be and Levelt (1983) mother for wife, i phonological WOK catalog, consider4 rett, 1988). Like\ ological affinities (1981) and Marti occurrence of phc ceeds chance exp the levels of lexi of the lexicon in composition can thereby making 11 errors (for differ1 1991; Schriefers, Despite its i of lexical retriev that there are un the syntax and a Production Problems 147 the same phrase with and next to squeaky in the positional-level planning frame, and sets up the conditions for the sound exchange between /w/ and /r/. That exchange in turn yields sbeaky gwease. This analysis illustrates something about the theory's successes in rationalizing error patterns, but the model's goals are considerably more ambitious. It is also intended to explain the features of normal production. The need to regulate the flow of information is one such feature, and the model's modular design constitutes a strong proposal about how this is achieved. Jerry Fodor pointed out in a footnote to his essay on modularity (Fodor, 1983) that it makes little sense for production to be modular, since it must be open to the full range of information that people are capable of expressing. Sense aside, though, the weird semantics of many errors is enough to suggest that this openness does not extend very far downstream. Garrett's model proposes that, at each level, there is a severe restriction on the kinds of information to which the operations at that level are sensitive. A related restriction is evident in the direction of information flow. Because everything proceeds from the top down, there are relatively discrete stages of semantic and phonological retrieval, with no bottomup influence from the positional to the functional level. On the lexical retrieval side, one argument for this is found in the word substitution errors that have been discussed by Garrett (1980), Fay and Cutler (1977), and Levelt (1983): Semantic word substitutions (e-g., sword for arrow, mother for wife, listen for speak) show few similarities in form, while phonological word substitutions (mushmom for mustache, cabinet for catalog, considered for consisted) show few similarities in meaning (Garrett, 1988). Likewise, exchanged words d o not seem to have the phonological affinities that exchanged sounds do. However, Dell and Reich (1981) and Martin, Weisberg, and Saffran (1989) have shown that the occurrence of phonological similarities among semantic substitutions exceeds chance expectations, leading to questions about the strictness of the levels of lexical retrieval. Dell (1986) has proposed that the levels of the lexicon interact during retrieval, so that a word's phonological composition can affect the accessibility of its semantic representation, thereby making lexical processing a major culprit in the leaks that yield errors (for different perspectives, see Butterworth, 1989; Levelt et al., 1991; Schriefers, Meyer, & Levelt, 1990). Despite its differences from Garrett's model over the mechanisms of lexical retrieval, Dell's model shares with Garrett's the assumption that there are uniform levels of syntactic construction, thereby making the syntax and other structural processes the major regulators of infor- 148 Bock mation flow. If this assumption is right, supposed message-level features should have little effect on structural processes at the positional level. In line with this prediction, there are results which suggest that the processes that construct hierarchically and serially arranged sequences of words are not directly sensitive to the semantic or pragmatic burden of sentence constituents. Much of this evidence rests on a structural priming phenomenon which appears to reflect the process of creating constituent structures. The phenomenon itself is simply a tendency to produce sentences in structures similar to those of recently produced sentences. This tendency appears to persist regardless of changes in discourse structure (Estival,.. 1985), changes in the thematic roles of the sentence constituents (Bock & Loebell, 1990), changes in the semantic features of the sentence constituents (Bock, Loebell, & Morey, in press), and changes in the closedclass elements in the sentences (Bock, 1989). It disappears after a change in the constituent structures of the sentences involved (Bock & Loebell, 1990), even when metrical structures are held constant. The implication is that the processes that form the positional representation, building the bridge from the functional to the positional level, operate without the guidance of message features. This accords with the idea that the flow of information during production may be regulated by heavily restricting the access of processes to different types of information. The obverse of the problem of regulating information is the problem of fluency. Though it may be essential to restrict the top-down flow of information during production in order to reduce interference from extraneously or contemporaneously available information, it is also important to keep speech flowing smoothly, without long hesitations and interruptions (Clark & Clark, 1977). Speakers are not entirely successful at doing this, of course, but the rate at which speech is produced is nonetheless impressive. Levelt (1989) emphasizes just how big a feat it is: At a normal speaking rate, speakers select a word roughly once every 400 ms from a vocabulary that he puts in the range of 30,000 words. Because of the normal fluency of speech, it is natural to assume that the formulator is organized and operates in a way that meets the demands of creating utterances in time. This has the potential to conflict with the need to regulate information during production. On one side, the formulator must staunch the flow of information, and on the other, keep it moving. To see the problem, consider a possible implication for fluency of Production Problems , ! I I the organization of the model in Fig. 1. In order to ensure that only information which can be integrated into the developing utterance is passed to the next processing level, suppose that the functional representation of each utterance is fully formatted before positional processing commences, and the positional representation fully formatted before motor programming commences, and the motor program fully formatted before articulation commences. If so, speech might typically proceed in bursts punctuated by silence, as each utterance is formulated from the functional level on down. This violates the intuitions of both speakers and hearers. --- . . Part of the formulator's solution to the problem seems to be to specify progressively narrower windows or units at each level, creating a processing hierarchy. In terms of the model in Fig. 1, the units at the functional level are larger than those at the positional level, and so on down, allowing an utterance to be initiated without being fully prepared at every level. On the basis of speech-error evidence, Garrett (1988) proposed that the functional level spans about two clauses, while the positional level spans about a phrase. The error evidence is found in the typical scope of word exchanges, which is generally no more than two clauses, and the typical scope of sound exchanges, which is generally no more than a phrase. Since word exchanges seem to be consequences of syntactic-function misassignments and sound exchanges seem to be consequences of phonological-segment tnisassignments, the scope of such errors offers one index of the scope of the operations that normally perform these tasks (also see Ford, 1982; Ford & Holmes, 1978). Other evidence comes from experimental findings which show that the meanings of both the subject and the object of a to-be-spoken sentence may be active at a point in time when only the phonological form of the head of the subject noun phrase is active (O'Seaghdha, Dell, & Peterson, 1988). At lower levels, the processing windows may be narrower still. Stemberg, Knoll, Monsell, and Wright (1988) offer evidence from studies of planned speech that the stress group or metrical foot (a single stressed syllable and its accompanying unstressed syllables) is the basic unit of the motor program. Consistent with such a hierarchical arrangement, the units at different levels seem to interact differently with the realization of grammatical features. Bock and Cutting (1990) explored the occurrence of subjectverb agreement errors following phrasal vs. clausal subject-postmodifiers (e.g., The claim about the newborn babies. . vs. The claim that wolves had raised [he babies. . .) in which the lengths of the postmodifiers were equated in number of syllables. In these experiments, the task was simply . Production Problems Bock IS0 to produce a completion for each sentence fragment, and the dependent measure was the number of verb-agreement errors that speakers produced in their completions (see Bock & Miller, 1991). Extrapolating from find- . ings in comprehension (Caplan, 1972; Jarvella, 1971), the prediction would be that such errors should be more frequent after clauses than after phrases, due to a general tendency to forget the form of material preceding the most recent clause. The hierarchical formulation hypothesis predicts just the opposite. Grammatical agreement is defined over clauses and, on the assumption that clauses constitute a unit of formulation at the level at which agreement is implemented (the functional level, where subjects are specified), agreement should be relatively uninfluenced . .-. -by . .---material outside the clause in which a given verb occurs. The actual result was in line with the hierarchical hypothesis: Speakers made significantly more errors after phrasal than after clausal postmodifiers. Notice that the erroneously agreeing verb in The claim about the newborn babies were. . . i s in the same clause with the apparent source of the error, whereas in The claim that wolves had raised the babies were. . the erroneously agreeing verb is in a different clause, the matrix clause. If clauses constitute a formulation unit, such that the contents of constituent phrases within a clause are free to interact in a way that the contents of constituent phrases from different clauses are not, the agreement-error results follow. From a theoretical standpoint, the specification of such units is essential to meaningful contrasts between modularity and interactivity in production (or any fluid ability). In a modular system, processes are defined in terms of the vocabularies or information types to which they are responsive, and in a constructive modular system, one process must hinge on another, with one's product serving as the other's raw material. T o empirically distinguish such an arrangement from an interactive processing system, there must be some specification of the scope of each process that predicts the points at which different types of information come into play. . Coordination The coordination problem arises because production is, in fact, productive: The utterances we produce are rarely memorized sequences, but rather creative assemblies of elements within structures. Words must be put into place in syntactic structures, and sounds must be put into place within phonological structures. The problem is evident in the architecture of the model in Fig. 1: At the functional level the members of the lexical set must be assigned to the proper syntactic functions, and at the posi- tional level the phc into the right place The argumenl of coordination fir other elements of shows that words than other units su is that such eleme structures, are processing but system 1 t Another argi nomenon of accoi tures appropriate t rightly to bear th subject function. w e can rarely de when pronouns a; the world should rett, 1980). Sim tioned, they see environment. In tended; Fromkin 1 * iI i I .. . .'*' <r ' . ..- SENTENCE . PHRASI f '* .. . 2' fc 1 i " -> WORt MORPHEM' >SYLLABL g SYLLAEL  VCORC CLUSTE f PHONEN FEATUF Fig. 2. Percentage similar graph pres should be used foi 151 Production Problems tional level the phonological segments of the word forms must be slotted into the right places. The argument that words and phonological segments are the targets of coordination finds support in evidence that they are more likely than other elements of utterances to turn up in the wrong places. Figure 2 shows that words and segments are more likely to participate in errors than other units such as phrases or features or syllables. The implication is that such elements are not retrieved as pans of larger, more unitary structures, but are manipulated, placed, and misplaced as pieces by the processing system. Another argument for a coordination process comes from the phe-nomenon of accommodation, in which misplaced elements take on features appropriate to their environment. For example, something that ought rightly to bear the object function might be inadvertently assigned the subject function. Because English does not routinely mark case overtly, we can rarely detect case-marking accommodations, but they do occur when pronouns are involved, as in the error He offends her sense of how the world should be (when She offends his sense. was intended; Garrett, 1980). Similarly, if phonological segments are improperly positioned, they seem to take on the features appropriate to the new environment. In the error lumber s p a m (when slumber party was intended; Fromkin, 1973) a word-initial /p/ mistakenly follows the initial / . .. oe 0 >SYLLABLE SYLLABLE VCORCV SOUND UNITS -- FEATURE 0 I I I 10 20 30 40 PERCENTAGE OF ERRORS Fig. 2. Percentages of speech errors involving various linguistic units (modeled after a similar -graph . presented by Dell. 1987). The percentages are rough approximations and should be used for ordinal comparisons only. ' - - Production Problem Bock /sf, and the Ipf should no longer be aspirated. The implication here is that various structural positions or relations impose requirements on the elements that fill them, requirements that are not features of the elements ., themselves. T o solve the coordination problem, the formulator must know how to put the pieces of language into their proper places in utterances. Naturally, the pieces that have received the most attention in efforts to explain how the formulator solves this problem are those pieces that most obviously require coordination, words and sounds. Words themselves have two logically separable components, a meaning and a phonological form. As a result, we have the same meaning expressed in different phonological forms (e.g., pail a i d bucket) andm---different meanings expressed in the same phonological form (e-g., savings bank and river bank). If these components are represented separately as well, their coordination with the relevant structures may also be a twofold affair. Again in terms of the model in Fig. 1, abstract specifications of words (presumably including their semantic specifications, but not their phonological specifications) are hypothesized to b e linked to syntactic functions at the functional level, but the sound segments are not put into place until the positional representation is constructed. . ! One orediction that follows from dividing the coordination pioblem .iI up in this way is that variations in the states of preparation of the mean. '\ . . n g s of lexical entries should have a greater impact on the syntax of an utterance than variations in the states of preparation of the phonological . . ' forms of words. The prediction follows from the role of the functional representation in guiding the creation of a syntactic structure, via assignments to such syntactic functions as subject and direct object. This was tested in two experiments that compared the effects of semantic and phonological priming on the arrangements of words in sentences (Bock, 1986). The participants received priming words that were either semantically or phonologically related to various target words, under conditions that disguised the priming manipulation. T h e target words appeared as the subjects or objects of sentences that were extemporaneously created by the participants themselves to describe pictured events which followed the presentation of the priming words. For example, one speaker might have received the word thunder followed by a picture of lightning striking a church, while other speakers received the words worship, frightening, or search. The two target words were Zighming (semantically primed by thunder and phonologically primed by frightening) and church (semantically primed by worship and phonologically primed by search). The question was whether the subject and ' object assignment varied (and along on whether the a; The results s tion assignments mantically prime' an active or passi primed targets w were primed tha , meanings of woi differential prim , effect. This result ordination. Howl of the phonologi on functional as work (Bock, 191 reliable effect o assume, in line 1 effects on semar - " .. lexical errors, t - , activation of ph in the lexical se -- . tional structure. KT-'-proceeds in dis **. -Ç.-" * r.ff- form. 'Phonologi( .-..I 'ical o r phonolo; and some deba the phonologic: the odd fact th stored word fc should occur ( words). Why s I Shattuck-1 ! occurs because ! that transform are misplaced developing mt Evidence for t ences between 8 . , ' J ; ¥È ,.Ã̂ " I Production Problems 153 object assignments in the sentences that were produced by the participants varied (and along with them, the structures of the sentences), depending on whether the agent (lightning)or recipient (church) was primed. The results suggested that semantic priming affected syntactic-function assignments in a way that phonological priming did not. The semantically primed target reliably tended to serve as the subject of either an active or passive sentence, as appropriate, whereas the phonologically primed targets were not used as subjects reliably more often when they were primed than when they were not. So differential priming of the meanings of words may change their functional level assignments, but differential priming of the sounds of words did not have as strong an .- . . - -.-effect. This result is clearly consistent with the model's conception of coordination. However, the model also predicts that the state of preparation of the phonological forms of words should have no influence whatsoever on functional assignments, and this turns out to be too strong. In other work (Bock, 1987), I have found that phonological priming can have a reliable effect on sentence form. One way to accommodate this is to assume, in line with Dell and Reich's (1981) explanation of phonological effects on semantic substitutions, word exchanges, and other higher-level lexical errors, that such interactions are mediated by the lexicon: The activation of phonological forms affects the state of any affiliated items \ in the lexical set, which may in turn affect the determination of a functional structure. This requires weakening the view that lexical retrieval proceeds in discrete stages involving the access of meaning and then form. Phonological coordination, the problem of putting sounds into lexicai or phonological structures, is currently the object of intense scrutiny and some debate. Especially at issue is a question about the nature of the phonological planning frame, a question which follows in part from the odd fact that phonological segments move despite the existence of stored word forms which specify the order in which sound segments should occur (forms that allow us, among other things, to recognize words). Why should sounds move around at all? Shattuck-Hufnagel (1987; also see Levelt, 1989) suggests that this occurs because connected speech requires building a metrical structure that transforms the phonological segments in various ways. Segments are misplaced when they are copied from the stored template into the developing metrical structure, which incorporates the planning frame. Evidence for this view comes from experimentally demonstrated differences between errors that arise in the production of disconnected words Bock Product! and those that occur in connected speech (Shattuck-Hufnagel, 1987). In the former, there were a disproportionate number of word-onset errors relative to errors in other word positions, while in the latter, more errors appeared for non-onset consonants. Dell (1986) also proposed a coordination mechanism in which sound segments are associated with phonotactic frames, although the segmentretrieval mechanism was modeled as a process of spreading activation in a lexical network. Dell (1990), in contrast, has developed a paralleldistributed-processing model (similar to that of Jordan, 1986) in which frames are epiphenomenal, an emergent property of the features of the stored segments and the network in which they'are represented. According to this model, the frame-like regularities of errors are a product of the similarities and the sequential biases characteristic of segment combinations in English. This redefines the coordination problem, since segments sprout frames rather than having to be attached to them. Dell's (1990) new model is designed to simulate the qualitative and quantitative features of noncontextual sound errors, errors that have no obvious source in the immediate linguistic environment, and its performance on that score is impressive. It remains to be seen whether the same architecture is adequate to account for the more common contextual errors, whose distribution and features were the focus of Dell's earlier effort (1986). Dell (1990) suggests that the error types may, in fact, be disparate. If so, the coordination problem remains. tional distingi 154 Type Transparency . The question of type transparency (Berwick & Weinberg, 1984), applied to production, is whether the organization of the formulator mirrors the logical organization of rules and structures in the grammar. There seems to be an irrepressible desire on the part of many linguists and psycholinguists to equate the components of production models with the components of one or another syntactic theory, partly due to a confusion of the behavioral notion of generation with the mathematical notion of generation that is relevant to generative grammar. They are distinct. There are other divergences, too. Garrett (1980) noted that errorbased production models (including his own) are grounded in a type of data that is dramatically different from traditional linguistic evidence. For that reason, the model is agnostic about many things. T o take one example, the functional-level representation in Fig. 1 is not equated with any of the plausible candidates from linguistic theory (e.g., D-structure or S-structure in government-binding theory; f-structure in lexical-func- BI goals n linguis of inqi veridic vergen ticipatt (1985) error d similai dornai which media - 7 , betwe tions 1 manif theref ance There \ - aPPea poten & St( sake 1 perf0 sourc . the n prod1 the01 lang~ corn] Bevt nisrr tal 2 rece way anal doni Production Problems , 155 tional grammar), because the error data do not provide any grounds for distinguishing among them. But as Garrett (1980) also noted, the differences in methods and . goals make those similarities that do arise between production theory and linguistic theory all the more important. Whenever such disparate lines of inquiry converge on such similar pictures, one's faith in the picture's veridicality increases. Fromkin's (1971) classic paper detailed the convergences between the units of linguistic theory and the units that participate in speech errors. Fromkin (1971), Garrett (1975), Sternberger (1985), Dell (1986), and others have found that an explanation of the error data requires separating the domains of formulation along lines very. . . similar to the partitions found in most linguistic theories: There is a domain in which sentence structures are formed (a syntax), a domain in which sound structures are formed (a phonology), and a domain that mediates between the two (a lexicon or morphology). Though it is possible to construct much more fine-grained analogies between theories of production processes and theories of grammar, questions have been raised about how directly our knowledge of language is manifested in or adapted to our use of language (Chomsky, 1986) and therefore about how responsive a linguistic theory should be to performance data or, for that matter, a performance theory to linguistic data. There is no consensus about this in linguistics, though some linguists appear to regard the study of language processing as a relevant and potentially valuable source of evidence about language structure (Ades & Steedman, 1982; Bresnan, 1978; Bresnan & Kaplan, 1982). For the sake of consistency, at least, any linguist who regards children's language performance (almost always, children's language production) as a central source of evidence about how language is represented must acknowledge the relevance of adult language performance (including adults' language production). In psycholinguistics, there is considerable scepticism that linguistic theory will have anything to say about the fundamental mechanisms of language processing, in part due to the failures of earlier efforts to adapt competence theories to the domain of language performance (see Fodor, Bever, & Garrett, 1974, for a summary). Because performance mechanisms are beyond the reach of introspection and intuition, an experimental approach is required to tap processing in ongoing time. Still, the received view is that the processing system must be organized in such a way that i t yields the structural regularities that emerge from linguistic analyses (Fodor and Garrett, 1966). Although relatively little has been done by way of casting alternative linguistic construals of language struc- 156 Bock tures into production hypotheses (though see Bock et al., in press; Stemberger, 1990), it can be expected that linguistic theory will serve as an important influence on the development of models of the formulator. The obvious reason is that an explanation of structure is the focus of linguistic theory, and an explanation of the creation of structure is the focus of production theory. CONCLUSION The foregoing collection of sketches sets out some, but by no means all, of the focal problems in research on language production. These problems are sometimes judged to be either less open to solution or less interesting (or both) than the problems of language comprehension, and one purpose of this sketchbook has been to try to counter such impressions. The study of production has certainly been more trying than that of comprehension. It has gone forward thanks primarily to the tenacity and creativity of a few dedicated collectors of speech errors, who enjoy one advantage. Whereas the heavy industry of the study of parsing is devoted to the development of ingenious means for tapping into ongoing processes, formulation has the convenient property of wearing its ongoing processes on its sleeve: In both fluent and dysfluent speech, we have direct access to the final products of the formulator. Though w e assuredly do not have perfect access to the underlying details, either as introspective speakers or as curious investigators, w e often have readily observable indications of where and when in the development of an utterance things are proceeding smoothly and where and when they are not, and in errors, w e can sometimes detect the actual source of the disruption. But the successful construction and interpretation of processing models rests on the deployment of carefully targeted experimental methods. As valuable as the analysis of spontaneous speech errors has been in establishing the bedrock regularities of formulation, the enterprise is limited in its ability to evaluate competing hypotheses. The linguistic and extralinguistic contexts of natural errors may vary freely in ways that bear both on the occurrence of error and on the validity of different explanations, making some form of experimental control essential. That has been a sticking point in the development of research on language production, but pathways have begun to open with the invention of an array of methods for the study of phonological, lexical, and syntactic encoding. Despite the problems that it poses for the investigator, from the Bock >&emas an . The ist tic 1s of cans Tiese less and sresat of and one oted ises, sses cess , i ave kers ions prowe dels As tabited ex)ear )lahas iroray "g- the Production Problems 157 standpoint of the language user it may seem that production is inherently less challenging than comprehension. The fascination of the puzzle of comprehension comes from our mysterious ability to solve a problem with two unknowns: At the beginning of an episode that ends in understanding, the listener knows neither the meaning nor the form in which it will be conveyed, and the process of solving for both is extraordinarily vexed. The fascination of the puzzle of production comes from our mysterious inability to solve a problem that is, from a computational perspective, trivial (Ristad, 1990): Given a message to be conveyed, perfect forms can be generated by any of many different algorithms. Human speakers are, indeed, good at generating perfect forms. The mystery is that those forms can have annoyingly little to do with the intended meaning. The importance of a solution to this puzzle goes beyond its implications for our understanding of production itself. Explaining how the language processor works in a domain where structures can be formed on the basis of relatively rudimentary features of meaning may help in explaining how structures can be formed when the meaning is, in fact, unknown. In this sense, the explanation of production may contribute to an explanation of comprehension as well as to the development of a general theory of language performance. \ REFERENCES Ades, A. E.. A Steedman, M. J. (1982). On the order of words. UngwStics and Philosophy, 4 , 517-558. Berwick, R. C., & Weinberg, A. S. (1984). The grammatical basis of finguistic perfonnance. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press. Bock, J. K. (1986). Meaning, sound, and syntax: Lexical priming in sentence production. Journal of ExperUnental Psychology: Learning, Memory, and Cognition, 12, 575586. Bock, J. K. (1987). An effect of the accessibility of word forms on sentence structures. Journal of Memory and Language, 26, 119-137. Bock, J. K. (1989). Closed-class immanence in sentence production. Cognition, 31, 163-186. Bock, J. K., & Cutting, J. C. (1990). Production units and production problems in forming long-distance dependencies. Paper presented at the meeting of the Psychonomic Society, New Orleans, LA. Bock, 1. K., & Loebell, H. (1990). Framing sentences. Cognition, 35, 1-39. Bock, J. K.. Loebell, H., & Morey, R. (in press). From conceptual roles to structural relations: Bridging the syntactic cleft. Psychological Review. Bock, J. K., & Miller, C. A. (1991). Broken agreement. Cognitive Psychology. 23, 4593. Brcsnan. J. (1978). A realistic transformational grammar. In M. Halle, J. Brcsnan, & Bock 158 G. A. Miller (Eds.), Unguistic theory and psychological reality (pp. 1-59). Cambridge, MA: MIT Press. Bresnan, J., & Kaplan, R. M. (1982). Introduction: Grammars as mental representations ., of language. In J. Bresnan (Ed.), The mentalrepresentaticn ofgrammaticalrelations (pp. xvii-lii). Cambridge, MA: MIT Press. Butterworth, B. (1989). Lexical access in speech production. In W. D. Marsh-Wilson (Ed.), Lexical representation and process (pp. 108-135). Cambridge, MA: MIT Press. Caplan, D. (1972). Clause boundaries and recognition latencies for words in sentences. Perception & Psychophysics. 12, 73-76. Chomsky. N. (1986). Knowledge of language: Its nature, origin, and use. New York: Praeger. Clark. H. H., & Clark, E. V. (1977). Psychology and language: An introduction to psycholinguistics. New York: Harcourt Brace Jovanovich. - ----.Deese, J. (1984). Thought into speech: The psychology of a language.&g~&ood Cliffs, NJ: Prentice-Hall. Dell. G. S. (1986). A spreading-activation theory of retrieval in sentence production. Psychological Review, 93, 283-321. Dell, G. S. (1987, July). Phonological encoding in production. Lecture in the course "Language comprehension and production" (G. S. Dell & M. K. Tanenhaus, instructors), Linguistic Society of America Summer Institute, Stanford University, Stanford, CA. Dell, G. S. (1989. March). Languageproduction and connectionist models of the mind. Colloquium presented to the Department of Psychology, Michigan State University, East Lansing, MI. Dell, G. S. (1990, March). Frame constraints and phonological speech errors. Paper . presented at the CUNY Conference on Human Sentence Processing, New York, NY. Dell, 0.S. (1990). Effects of frequency and vocabulary type on phonological speech errors. Language and Cognitive Processes, 5,313-349. Deil, G. S., & Reich, P. A. (1981). Stages in sentence production: An analysis of speech . error data. Journal of Verbal Learning and Verbal Behavwr, 20, 611-629. Estival, D. (1985). Syntactic priming of the passive in English. Text, 5, 7-21. Fay, D., & Cutler, A. (1977). Malapropisms and the structure of the mental lexicon. Linguistic Inquiry, 8, 505-520. Fodor. J. A. (1983). The modularity of mind. Cambridge. MA. MIT Press. Fodor. J. A.. Bever. T. G.. & Garrett. M. F. (1974). Thepsychology of language. New York: McGraw-Hill. Fodor, J., & Ganett, M. (1966). Some reflections on competence and performance. In J. Lyons & R. J. Wales (Eds.), Psycholinyuticspapers (pp. 135-154). Edinburgh: Edinburgh University Press. Ford, M. (1982). Sentence planning units: Implications for the speaker's representation of meaningful relations underlying sentences. In J. Bresnan (Ed.), The mental representation of grammatical relations (pp. 797-827). Cambridge. MA: MlT Press. Ford, M., & Holmes, V. M. (1978). Planning units and syntax in sentence production. Cognition, 6, 35-53. Fromkin, V. A. (1971). The non-anomalous nature of anomalous utterances. Language. 47, 27-52. Fromkin, V. A. (1973). Speech errors as linguistic evidence. The Hague: Mouton. Production Probler Gamham. A.. ShiIIc Slips of the ton Cutler (Ed.), S Mouton. Garrett. M. F. (197 psychology of 1 Garrett, M. F. (19s (Ed-), Languor Garrett, M. F. (19 Linguistics: 77 aspects (pp. 6' Garrett. M. F. (19' presented at tl NY. Jarvella, R. J. (IS Learning and Jordan. M. I . (198 machine. Pro1 Society (pp. 5 Kilbom. K. (1988 behavioral an and granvruit cholinguistik, Kutas, M.. & Hill: and semantic W e l t , W. J. M. W e l t , W. J. M. MTT Press. M e l t , W.J. M-, J. (1991). Th naming. Psyi Â¥MartinN.. Wei: occurrence o of Memory a O'Seaghdha, P . ( resentations chonomic S( Ristad, E. S. (19' at the CUN' Schricfers, H., N lexical acce: Memory am Shaituck-Hufnag in sentence processing: Hillsdale, f Shattuck-Hufnag planning: F Production Problems 159 Garoham, A., Shillcock, R. C. Brown, G. D. A., Mill, A. I. D.. & Cutler, A. (1982). Slips of the tongue in the London-Lund corpus of spontaneous conversation. In A. Cutler (Ed.), Slips of the tongue and language production (pp. 25 1-263). Berlin: Mouton. Garrett, M. F. (1975). The analysis of sentence production. In G. H. Bower (Ed.), The psychology of learning and motivation (pp. 133-177). New York: Academic Press. Garrett. M. F. (1980). Levels of processing in sentence production. In B. Butterworth (Ed.), Language production (pp. 177-220). London: Academic Press. Garrett. M. F. (1988). Processes in language production. In F. J. Newmeyer (Ed.), Linguistics: The Cambridge survey, HI: Language: Psychological and biological aspects (pp. 69-96). Cambridge, England: Cambridge University Press. Garrett, M. F. (1990. March). Processing vocabularies in language production. Paper presented at the CUNY Conference on Human Sentence Processing, New York, NY. Jarvella, R. J. (1971). Syntactic processing of connected speech. ~ournaiof Verbal.. Learning and Verbal Behavior, 10, 409416. Jordan, M. I. (1986). Attractor dynamics and parallelism in a connectionist sequential machine. Proceedings of the Eighth Annual Conference of the Cognitive Science Society (pp. 531-546). Hillsdale, NJ: Erlbaum. Kilborn, K. (1988). A note on the on-line nature of discourse processing: Comparing behavioral and ekctrvphysiological m e a s w in I T ~ o ~ ~ I ofor M ~ semantic anomalies and grammatical errors. Unpublished manuscript, Max-Planck-Institut fur Psycholinguistik, Nijmegen, The Netherlands. Kutas, M., & Hillyard, S. A. (1983). Event-related brain potentials to grammatical errors and semantic anomalies. Memory & Cognition, 11, 539-550. Levell. W. J. M. (1983). Monitoring and self-repair in speech. cognition, 14, 41-104. Lcvelt, W. J. M. (1989). Speaking: From intention to articulation. Cambridge, M A : \ MIT Press. b e l t , W. J. M.. Schriefere, H.. Vorberg. D.. Meyer, A. S., Pechrnann, T., & Havinga, J. (1991). The time course of lexical access in speech production: A study of picture naming. Psychological Review, 98, 122-142. Martin, N., Weisberg, R. W., & Saffran, E. M. (1989). Variables influencing the occurrence of naming errors: Implications for models of lexical retrieval. Journal of Memory and Language, 28, 462485. O'Seaghdha, P. G.. Dell, G. S.. & Peterson. R. R. (1988. November). Indexing representations in language production. Paper presented at the meeting of the Pv chonomic Society, Chicago, IL. Rislad, E. S. (1990, March). Obstacles to efficient languageprocessing. Paper presented at the CUNY Conference on Human Sentence Processing, New York. NYSchriefers, H., Meyer, A. S., & b e l t , W. J. M. (1990). Exploring the time course of lexical access in language production: Picture-word interference studies. Jounml of Memory and Language, 29, 86-102. Shattuck-Hufnagel, S. (1979). Speech errors as evidence for a serial-ordering mechanism in sentence production. In W. E. Cooper & E. C. T. Walker (Eds.), Sentence processing: Psychoiinguistic studies presented to Merrill Garrett (pp. 295-342). Hillsdaic. NJ: Erlbaum. Shat~uck-Hufnagel.S. (1987). The role of word-onset consonants in speech production planning: New evidence from speech error patterns. In E. Keller & M. Gopnik 14 -. . -. ...-.. -.... . . ..--, . - -. . + .. - .. $4 . * * . . . . A , - - . Â¥ >.. .. v-...< ..,...., c$- t ..,.-,... ,. ,. 7. .- ,- -^;:.:,!.. ,.;**.., . '.;,,. .y ~^w^r . --'3.9$:--.: .:s -. ,',-a ,, +, ,.,- '-.', d c. !Â¥^i^,';y\. ..:..: .' -. -, .$i:~~,i$*,~.;~~.~:~-.. ^^.^ ..- . Â¥'" ":-<'*; . - ~(l+a;Ld.-,:.; X'G : :.:.x,+?:;$?.;y :+: ' c .W.L L.,+ .-;.-,d .w:.,.... -J?" --...- . .. .. ... . . ,.-, , 0% <. -,,,- ...... - . ,.: . . . .- ' Journal of P?c/ Bock Hillsdale, NJ: Erl(Eds,), Motor and sensory processes of lungtiage (pp. 17-5 baumSlemberger, J. P. (1985). An interactive activation model of language production. In A. Ellis (Ed.), Progress in the psychology of language (pp. 143-186). London: Erlbaum. Stemberger, J. P. (1990). wordshape errors in language production. Cognition. 35, 123- ~ 157. Sternberg, S., Knoll, R. L., Monsell, S., & Wright, C. E. (1988). Motor programs and hierarchical organization in the control of rapid speech. Phonetics, 45, 175-197. On the Evidenc Susana del Accepted Febn The present sn and phonologil the tongue in 5 effect 'on suble feedback-from meaning and ft to the hypotha production. F language proa processing-sta . !, There are f can be usec process tha one hand, 1 volving sut of phonoio: may lead u This rescan dc Investigi ryn Bock. Universida( Universidai Universida~ Address all sidad dc 0