HUMAN NATUREAND THE TRANSFORMINGSOCIETY A. ETZIONI Department of Sociology Columbia University T he essence of the question of what kind of society we may form-once we are freed from our past repressions and the hangover of our liberation feast-is what kind of material do we have to work with? As what we reshape is first of all ourselves, both as individuals and as a social combine, the question really is: What are humans like, what are they capable of, and what are their limitations? Is our present failure to act, i.e., to master our instruments and thus our fate, congenital or conditioned? Various theories that base their position on dynamic analysis of social, psychic, and historical forces, suggest alternative future views that range all the way from the retightened to oceanic abandonment. But does the "matter" which is being affected by these forces-human nature-set any limitations or indicate where we are headed? The questions are almost frightening in their scope, but it is a mark of the crisis that they are being asked. AUTHOR'S NOTE: This is part of a larger project entitled After Modern-What? carried out under the auspicesof the Center for Policy Research. International Journal of Group Tensions, Vol. 4 No.3, @1974 Sage Publications, Inc. [284] September 1974 Etzioni I HUMAN NATURE, TRANSFORMING SOCIETY [285] They cannot be avoided in the name of scientism, lack of sufficient data, or measurement difficulties. To be concerned with the human potential is not to deny that the historical conditions in which we find ourselves, as we experiment with new futures, are a significant factor. Obviously, it makes a great deal of difference whether we command an affluent economy or are on a starvation diet, reflect on a tranquil island or face the enemy at the gate, marshal nature's forces or are overwhelmed by them. Nevertheless, we are both the creature of our natural and social environment and its creator. If we do not find at hand the necessary tools for our purposes, we may make them. If the tools we have already made stand in our way, we can remove them. Hence it is insufficient to ask only about the historical conditions-"where we are at"; we must also assess our potential. Having defined our historical condition as regressive and hence as "open," removing all forms so that we will be able to reform, the question as to what our innermost capabilities are is more important than it would be under less pliable historical circumstances. How high can man rise? Are we at our best when we follow our natural inclination, each doing his own thing? Or is this anarchist's prospective not even an invitation to a Bacchanalian orgy but rather to a free-for-all of a quite different kind, that of a Hobbesian jungle? Is man "naturally" aggressive and selfish with society providing the necessary curb, or is the individual cooperative and sociable until the crooked society distorts him? Or are individuals highly pliable, largely reflecting forces above and beyond them, and subject to being made either selfish or altruistic, aggressiveor loving? [286] INTERNATIONAL JOURNAL OF GROUP TENSIONS HUMAN NATURE: THE LIMITS OF MALLEABILITY AND LIBERATION The debate as to what man is "really like" and what his potentiality is, is highly intricate. It has occupied intellectuals and citizens at large at least since Socrates walked the olive groves of Athens' academia. Scores of lines of argumentation have been advanced, challenged, qualified, extended. The debate's interwoven web threatens to entangle us and delay our main purpose. I hence shall try to cut through it as swiftly as possible, fully aware that I leave many knots still tied. PESSIMISTS VERSUS OPTIMISTS There are three basic views of human nature: negative, positive, and indifferent. As the list is logically exhaustive, leaving no other possibility, the ultimate answer must be a variant of one of these. The pessimists hold that human beings, in their natural, ungraced state, are beastly. What has commonly been referred to as the Hobbesian view of human nature, is that humans are inherently self-centered and aggressive: "man is wolf to man." Society, it follows, must set up and enforceconstra that keep human beings civil. Without taboos and authority, without social regulation, men would feast not with but on each other. Freudian theory, at least as it is commonly understood, has a strong Hobbesian foundation. The unsocialized human being is an instinct-driven animal, aggressive, destructive, fearful of death, in search of unrestricted sexual satisfaction. It is the sublimation of his destructive urges and the channeling of his unruly ones into less pleasurable but socially more acceptable outlets, that make it possible for humans to live together in aggregates. Regression to the natural base spells the end of civilization. Etzioni / HUMAI'J NATURE, TRANSFORMING SOCIETY [287] The optimists see human beings in the state of nature as graceful, cooperative, and loving. Competitiveness, aggression, and destructiveness are introduced by the society which imposes itself on them. John Locke is set up in civic high school classes as the opposite of Hobbes from this viewpoint, with Rousseau's "noble savage" also being referred to. And while Locke saw a need for a societal curb very much as did Hobbes, he did see the state of nature-the original society and natural humans as positive beings-corrupted by a few aggressive ones against whom associations of the good people must organize so as not to be bullied or cowed. That is, from much more optimistic premises, Locke reached the Hobbesian conclusion: societal regulation is vital. The most optimistic position, which provides the intellectual justification for the ideal of a non repressive society and the call for scrapping norms and authority, is the view that human problems are generated by the particular form a given society takes-or by societability in general-not by the members' (or some members') individual nature. If only the alienating conditions (specific societal structure or the societal bond) were to be abolished, if human beings were only left to their natural ways, their goodness would be manifest for all to see and share. Marx, whose discussion of human nature and the future society is anything but extensive or detailed, did foresee the possibility of a harmonious, conflictless society, one without the need for social order or personal curbs, one in which all would be like brothers and sisters, living happily together. Marcuse traced the aggressive nature of individuals, one of the two characteristics which worried Freud and Hobbes into accepting the societal curbs, to the capitalist arrangements. Aggression, he says, is generated by being caught in work that is not fulfill ing and trying to find satisfaction by chasing the ghost of false needs of consumerism, implanted by the market forces. As quoted in Kateb (1970), Marcuse states: [288] INTERNATIONAL JOURNAL OF GROUP TENSIONS The system reacts by stepping up the production of goods and services which either do not enlarge individual consumption at all, or enlarge it with luxuries. ...To the degree to which this sort of work appears as superfluous, senseless, and unnecessary, while necessary for luxury in living, frustration is built into the very productivity of this society, and aggressiveness is activated. Once people are freed to work only creatively and to pursue only authentic needs, this core of alienation would vanish. Similarly, once the societal limiting and channeling of sexual release, imposed by the capitalist society, were to be removed, and the innocent, free expression of sexuality restored, this second most important source of personal frustration and societal disorder would be eliminated. Fromm (1955) views man's raw impulses as "good," constructive, self-containing, and pro-social, among which his needs to relate to others and to overcome moral aloofness are paramount. He offers a design for a psychological utopia in TheSaneSociety. But neither would go all the way to suggest that human nature allows for a nonrepressive society in the sense of that undiluted nature suffices and no regulation is required. Marcuse moderates his optimism by recognizing that there may be some societal taboos that would still be needed, some unpleasant work that may have to be carried out. Although he focuses his discussion mainly on the surplus regressionthat unnecessary part generated by the particular societal format capitalism, which can be eliminated-he does see an element of irreducible alienation. He speaks of the "differential between phylogenetically necessary repression and surplus repression" (for a discussion of nonrepressive civilization, see Marcuse, 1955: 87; also 5 and 37). Marcuse accepts Freud's notion that the naive pleasure principle (id-like) needs to be moderated by a "reality principle" (ego and superego). However, Marcuse divides the task of the reality principle into two, that universal part which is reality (or ego-like) and the modern one" of "performance" (or Etzioni I HUMAN NATURE, TRANSFORMING SOCIETY [289] superego). The measure of surplus repression is all of that repression introduced by the modern forms of political and economic organization and can be done away with as they are undone, without sacrificing reality-testing. Marcuse does not divide the sea of repression into two equal parts. His mind is on the surplus repression, which is historically bound, and which the imminent revolution will abolish. Irreducible repression receives but a passing treatment, Marcuse assuming that most repression is "surplus" while irreducible repression is a small residual category. It looks like a small bone thrown to the Freudian aficionado; Marcuse sounds most of the time like an uitra-liberationist who calls for man to abolish repression. Nowhere is Marcuse's latent abolitionist tendency more evident than in his treatment of sexuality, a central subject for any Freudian theory of repression. Like Reich and Brown, Marcuse sees in sexual organization, both in terms of setting taboos on genital sexuality and in terms of the very organization of sexuality in genital terms, a core root of repression. The unifying process is repressive-that is to say, the partial instincts do not develop freely into a 'higher' stage of gratification which preservestheir objectives, but are cut off and reduced to subservient functions. This process achieves the socially necessary desexualization of the body: the libido becomes concentrated in one part of the body, leaving most of the rest free for use as the instrument of labor [Marcuse, 1955: 44] . Like Reich and Brown, he seesthe progression Freud signaled as the basis of civilization-from the generalized eroticism of early childhood to the genital focus of adulthood-as the psychic problem of our civilization. Marcuse favors what is called the polymorphous-perverse orientation, which embraces not only all sexual activities but the eroticization of all nonsexual acts (Marcuse, 1955: 183-184): [290] INTERNATIONAL JOURNAL OF GROUP TENSIONS With the emergence of a non-repressive real ity pri nci pie, with the abolition of the surplus-repression necessitated by the perform- ance principle, this process would be reversed. In the societal relations, reification would be reduced as the division of labor became reoriented to the gratification of freely developing individual needs; whereas, in the libidinal relations, the taboo on the reification of the body would be lessened. No longer used as a full-time instrument of labor, the body would be resexualized. The regression involved in this spread of the libido would first manifest itself in a reactivation of all erotogenic zones and, consequently, in a resurgence of pregenital polymorphous sexuality and in a decline of genital supremacy. The body in its entirely would become an object of cathexis, a thing to be enjoyed-an instrument of pleasure. True, Marcuse (1955: 211) does drop here and there some pessimistic asides on human nature: However, even if a maternal libidinal morality is traceable in the instinctual structure, and even if a sensuous rationality could make the Eros freely susceptible to order, one innermost obstacle seems to defy all prospect of a nonrepressive developmentnamely, the bond that binds Eros to the death instinct. The brute fact of death denies once and for all the reality of a non-repressive existence. However, his essential position is captured in this line: "the more sex, the freer." The ultimate radical position is left for Norman O. Brown and Wilhelm Reich. They (like Freud) are not so much concerned with the distortions caused by a particular societal format, but by societability. They see in regression the rejection of societal inhibitions and the return to nativity, the core solution of all problems in this and all societies. The uitra-liberationists, Reich and Brown at the head, favor regressing all the way and not coming out at all. Both hope to find salvation in elimination of sociability, in the naked biological act. They favor elimination of discipline, not only that invested in authority or taboos. but also in Etzioni / HUMAN NATURE, TRANSFORMING SOCIETY [291] interpersonal relations, reason, and even that involved in the organization of a self, or in the focusing of the sexual energy. Brown, who seeks "to uncover the promise of a non repressive civilization," finds Reich's prescription of more and better orgasms as too much of a focus, and strips further to "a return to the anarchic and total sexuality of early infancy; a truly non-repressive civiliation"-thus, undifferentiated eroticism. The homosexual is not the prophet of liberation, insofar as he challenges taboos (as Marcuse has it), but one more focused man who has not removed his own shackles; bisexuality would be a minimal admission ticket to the liberated circle. Playing on all sides-oral, anal, and genital, actually all nerve endings, the whole body, is the heaven. "The human body will become polymorphously perverse, delighting in that full life of all the body that it now fears" (Brown, 1959: 308). "Political and fleshly emancipation are finally one and the same; the god is Dionysus" (Brown, 1966: 225). And if this leaves any doubts: "All fulfillment is carnal" (1966: 222). A complete immersion, an oceanic, emotive level, in which the individual will lose (Brown would say, be freed from) any organization and, hence, also his capacity to direct his energy, is required. Not just society and super-ego are to be dissolved but also the self, because "egos are masks, specters, concealing our unity as body" (1966: 82; also 235). What hence has been referred to as ego-tripping might have better been called submersion in the id. He calls for abolishing the reality principle and ego, replacing it with the id, and a complete fusion. "Fusion: the distinction between inner self and outside world, between subject and object, overcome" (1966: 253). A more complete oceanic prescription could not be given. According to Brown, our central trauma is not any hidden desire to kill our father and make our mother (or Electra-Fy the mother and be made by the father), but the separation anxiety from mother. Life was innocent and good as long as [292] INTERNATIONAL JOURNAL OF GROUP TENSIONS we were in unity with mother (and, we had no identity, let alone guidability, of our own). As soon as we are weaned, we begin to suffer from a separation anxiety, the central neurosis of our civilization, which gnaws at its roots and browns its leaves. We engage in a variety of projects, all desperate attempts to reunite with our mother, and kill-the grand anxiety. But these flights are to no avail; projects and organizations will not do it; we must return to a free-floating, all-embracing sexuality. If we can be recharged and discharged by everything and anything, we may no longer miss mother, or any other ignis fatuus. Reich (1963: xxix) put it as basically as: "authoritarian social order and social sexual repressions go hand in hand, and revolutionary 'morality' and gratification of sexual needs go together"; and "in order to make natural instinctual gratification possible, one has to eliminate the repression and to liberate the instincts" (Reich, 1963: 12). Thus there is a clear link between one's view of human nature-the relation between the animal base and the civil overlay and what constitutes natural relations among individuals-and one's future view as to what needs to be done and how we shall come out, as to the human potential. The pessimists see human nature as forcing us to accept a tight-ordering societal structure and superego; the optimists see it assuring us we must remove those controls in order to bring to earth the kingdom of heaven. A SOCIAL SCIENCE CAVEAT Before one tries to set forth which view seems more valid, one must take into account that which so often happens when a debate such as this runs for centuries; that is, a third position arises which suggests that the wrong question is being asked. Over the last two generations, mainstream sociologists and psychologists have come to agree that both the pessimist and optimist positions are erroneous because Etzioni I HUMAN NATURE, TRANSFORMING SOCIETY [293] they rest on a false assumption, that individuals and society can be viewed separately. Actually-it is repeated by the collective wisdom of a professional choir-individuals and society are two sides of the same coin and exist by each other. "Human nature?"-mainstream sociologists and psychologists scoff-"Have you ever seen one?" Persons are found only in society, shaped by its culture and institutions. They see "man at birth as like a blank sheet of paper, on which the culture writes its text" (Fromm, 1966: 24). If people in society X seem to oppose one or more of its dictums, it is not because these are against their nature but because the objectionable prescriptions clash with the preferences the members of that society evolved in earlier experiences and during early childhood education-in society. Ruth Benedict's (1934) Patterns of Culture study proved to be the turning point. She says, in effect: look at different primitive tribes; in some, men are violently aggressive, bitterly competitive; in others, they are peaceful, cooperative; neither is their nature. Their nature is a set of needs which can be stated in one hundred and one ways; can be shaped, within very lax limits, at society's will. Rollo May uses the classical Greek concept of "daimonic" to refer to the human quality as neither creative nor destructive. The collective wisdom continues: even when you find a person before he is imprinted by society-a day-old infant, a feral child adopted by a wolf, an infant left locked in an attic-what do you see? A creature that crawls on all fours, baying at the moon, without any of the human qualities, even those of walking erect, of being able to make tools, absorb symbols, or speak. That is, even the most basic human features, let alone any particu jar shape, are socially and culturally provided, not inherent. Conclusion-there are as many "human natures" as there are cultures and societies. "Man's 'original nature' is seen largely in neutral terms, as neither good nor bad.. ..If it [sociology] does not quite treat him as a 'tabula rasa,' modern sociology, nevertheless, [294] INTERNATIONAL JOURNAL OF GROUP TENSIONS regards man as a flexible form which can be given all manner of content" (Inkeles, 1964: 50; see also Wrong, 1968). Geiger (1964: 188) saw a "nearly infinite adaptability and modifiability" of human nature. It was left to Edgar Z. Friedenberg (19: 3) to put the sociological bias more extremely: "Human life is a continuous thread which each of us spins to his own pattern, rich and complex in memory. There are no natural knots in it." In line with this prevalent position, antisocial conductaggressive tendencies, for instance-is itself the result of societal forces. It is said to be produced in one or more of three ways: (a) education is inadequate (e.g., because father left home for good and mother worked, hence moral upbringing was neglected); (b) subcultural influences are in conflict (middle-class values, represented by the public schoolteacher, frowning on violence, but violence glorified by movies and TV and often the neighborhood); or (c) schooling is out of gear with the rest of the society. It is hence argued that any given societal pattern, if it is well communicated via education and consistently rewarded by those candies society reserves for conformists, can be made to be as acceptable to people. And if education and rewarding are scrapped (regressed), man will be neither good nor bad, but his personality will be scrapped too; he will become animal-like (if he should survive at all, because without his culture he is a rather indifferent, unfit species). Thus, while the counterculture tends to see high hopes in regression and the Hobbesians see grave dangers, mainstream sociologists and psychologists view it as eliminating the subject matter; nothing is expected to be left to be either aggressive or pacific. They hold the impossibility of an unregulated society. It also follows from this social science viewpoint that no one society can be judged as more human or in any other moral sense "better" than any other, in any terms but the idiosyncratic preferences of whoever judges. If anything goes, Etzioni I HUMAN NATURE, TRANSFORMING SOCIETY [295] if man can be shaped to treasure equally a life in Sparta or in Athens, in Salem or in Sodom, what basis is there to value one's society more dearly than another other than one's personal tastes? No wonder mainstream social scientists see no third alternative to either a neutral descriptive science of man, or one based on outright value judgments (see Gouldner, 1970: 495 and throughout; Bredemeier, 1971). And, it follows, all societal arrangements command the same potential for the good society, as long as they are made internally consistent. We can do what we wish as long as we do it collectively. Individuals are malleable but societies have incontrovertible needs. We can change the society, it is written, as long as we keep the centrifugal forces in check. ("Take care of the functional requisites.") Regression must be stopped at the level where explosive asocial conduct will cease to be contained. Thus, while societal reformation is quite possible, not so a retreat to nature. Regression would eliminate individuals as it scraps societability. However, repression could be eliminated-if the individuals were to be completely fitted into the roles assigned for them by society. Here the ultramodern future view finds a congenial home; improved social engineering and control will provide the good society. THE NATURE OF INDIVIDUALS As I see it, the individual has a nature of his own, which affects and is affected by the societal needs, cultural heritage, economic opportunities, and the historical conditions he encounters. It is quite appropriately referred to as "human nature" because it is shared by all human beings, whatever culture, society, or historical age in which they live. This should not be so surprising aswe quite readily see a nature in other living things, from lions to rats, from olive trees to sunflowers. It is quite true that we never see, cannot even conceive of, a person outside society; but we find many other [296] INTERNATIONAL JOURNAL OF GROUP TENSIONS analytic concepts useful. Electrons are a case in point; one can discuss their attributes without being able to invite them for dinner (or even seethem). And to state that society is a prerequisite for human survival is not to say that all societal forms are equally responsive to their members' nature. Hobbes, Locke, Freud, and many contemporary social scientists focus on the condition of existence; Marx, Marcuse, Fromm, and Brown are concerned with disalienation. Attending to the society's needs is a prerequisite for collective and individual survival; it surely does not guarantee individual fulfillment. While all societies provide for survival, those which set unlivable conditions of course disintegrate. No two societies are shaped in the same way and no two societies are equally amenable to the underlying nature of the individual members. Some societies are highly repressive, others are less repressive, and still others quite responsive. Thus, one can accept that human nature requires a societal arrangement and still ask if it has to be repressive. If yes, to what extent, and in what ways? Or can repression be eliminated by finding a societal pattern that is truly adapted to the members, rather than adapting them to it? Social science, rather than ruling out the existence of human nature, would do better to make it its urgent business to establish the universal qualities of human beings. This may be achieved by comparative research, by examining the logic of the definition of the concept of humanity, by extrapolation from the biological base, and by a study of human genesis from barbaric infancy to mature membership in the human community. That there are universal human qualities stands out when we engage in precisely the kind of cross-cultural and cross-period comparisons that the man-has-no-nature school of social science used to justify its boundless relativism. We soon see that while people "adapt" to all societies, it is also evident that they do not adapt equally easily to all societal patterns. They adapt better, more easily, more happily, I suggest, to those closer to their nature. Etzioni I HUMAN NATURE, TRANSFORMING SOCIETY [297] To illustrate this point first rather informally, let us sharethe observation that in a great variety, of societies, in a very divergent set of social-cultural-economic conditions, attempts have been made to impose a severely austere and restrictiveregime. But in situations as different as those of Calvinist Geneva, Puritanical Salem, the early postrevolutionary USSR,the early kibbutzim, and the first Catholic orders, members soon pushed the system to untighten its rules, loosen the vows of poverty, and provide more comforts. What else-if not the human nature of their members-do all these societies have in common? There may have been somewhere a society that made its high austerity stick for more than a passing age, although I am not familiar with one. But I would predict, if one is ever found, it will also be established that this was "achieved" only at great cost to individual members and to the society, a sure sign of opposition. Opposition by whom? A dissenting mincrity? No, by the average member. And, to reiterate, what do these average members all share other thantheir humanity? One must hence conclude, until evidence to the contrary is presented, that it is natural for human beingsto seek basic comforts. To illustrate further our general thesis, let us focus on another universal human attribute. I n all the cultures I have examined that were highly prohibitive of sexual expressions,the pressure has been to reduce tight regulations; and all sooner or later (most of them sooner) at least partially untightened-or, "more commonly, their prohibitive norms lingered, but only as a facade behind which a lot of untying and unbuttoning occurred. Out of 148 societies surveyed by Murdock (1949: 265) 120 had a taboo on extramarital relations. '" n 4 of the remaining 28, adultery is socially disapproved but not strictly forbidden. It is conditionally permitted in 19 and freely allowed in 5," but only with specific categories of people. Murdock points out that the taboo is more honored in the breach than in observation. Textor lists 43 cultures in which [298] INTERNATIONAL JOURNAL OF GROUP TENSIONS extramarital activity is punished and 41 in which it is permitted under various conditions, which makes 84 societies in which extramarital relations are reported; there is no relevant information from the other societies.! Kinsey (1953: 437) reports that half of the American males and 26% of the American females "admitted" to extramarital experiences, back in the late forties. A Hopi man says, "There are times when a wife is not interested, and a man must find someone else or live a worried and uncomfortable life."2 A Navaho tells about his extramarital encounters and adds: "1 know everyone of you has been around with another man's wife. Nothing can be done about it." Tells a Kawakiute man, from Vancouver Island, "Sometimes when the husband is away from the village, we would make arrangements that I'll go and stay with her at night." And a Kainyang reports from Brazil, "Once a couple are married they do not drop the liaisons formed before marriage." The same story is told from Tikopia, Western Polynesia and Morngin, Australia. It is obviously a commonplace in all Western societies, widespread in Latin America and far from unknown in the socialist societies from the USSR to the kibbutzim. How is one to account for this universal-as far as we can tell-transgression? Does it make more sense to say that all the highly varied systems of education and reward have failed, or that man is not monogamous by nature? The desire for comfort and for sexual variety might be attributed to needs whose basis is biological and this, it might be said, explains their universality. There are enough significant differences in the ways animals seek comfort and sexual release as compared to human beings to suggest that these urges, which clearly have a biological foundation, have also a human and social layer. And, there are universal needs whose source could hardly be biological-for instance the need for recognition and for self-expression which agitates in all cultures we know against individual identity being swallowed up by the group or mob. Thus, kibbutz children, brought up Etzioni I HUMAN NATURE, TRANSFORMING SOCIETY [299] in a world of collectiveness, grab each others' toys, screaming "this is mine" although the toy is kib;butz property and the nurses and parents insist on indoctrinating them in the finer points of socialism. Soviet stress on teamwork has yet to prevent Soviet sportsmen from playing "solo" (to gain individual recognition), and reports that ancient tribes had no concept of self are very dubious. Moreover, thousands of attempts to provide extremely close-knit social groups, of the kind now offered by communes in America, all were either undone or redone, to be less tight. The untightened communities have varied from religious to socialist, from hippie to political; the only thing they have in common is human beings, who apparently cannot stand such demotion of self as all these subcultures prescribed. I cannot provide a definitive or even well-documented list of the un iversal attributes of human beings, if for no other reason that that the consensus of social science for the last two generations has been that there is no such nature to be studied, and hence there are few empirical studies of the effects or attributes of human nature. Also, to study one culture is demanding enough; cross-culture, cross-period studies, which would be needed to advance the thesis as suggested so far, are taxing in the extreme. Nor is our purpose here to evolve a full account of a largely unexplored terrain, hidden beneath layers of culture; it is rather to establish the value of recognizing the terrain's existence. As a highly tentative list, to work with until more research is done, I propose the following needs may be viewed as universal:3 (a) Need for basic physiological comfort (food. shelter, and so on); this need asserts itself most clearly whenever an attempt is made to impose or foster greater austerity than the objective conditions req~ire. [300] INTERNATIONAL JOURNAL OF GROUP TENSIONS (b) Ouest for security; protection from self-evident it hardly requires discussion. physical harm is so (c) Need for receiving affection (or love). (d) Need for recognition (or esteem). (e) Need for transcending the self. This last need comes into play chiefly after the other ones have been satisfied, at least to some degree, and is in this sense a higher need. It expresses itself in projecting oneself beyond the immediate condition, investing in the future, envisioning and moving toward it. To fully demonstrate that these are indeed universal needs, would require comparing those societies (or subsocieties) which provide fewer opportunities for the gratification of these needs with those offering more such opportunities, and finding that those which are less gratifying impose greater human costs (e.g., more nervous breakdowns, more psychosomatic illness); have greater education costs needed to fit people into the required roles (longer years of training to greater commitment of resources); have more policing to keep the people conform ing, and generate more pressure for change. Such a comparison would be demanding enough; it is further compl icated by the fact that people brought up in a repressive system may not immediately show a greater satisfaction when faced with a more liberating one. How long they must be free in order to overcome their old habits and how encompassing the liberation must be, is not known. Marxists refer to those as the problems of "bourgeois residues" and "islands of socialism"; that is, if workers in a postrevolutionary society still pursue false needs, this is due either to their upbringing in the prerevolutionary society or to the influences which penetrate from societies which have not yet been liberated. This would suggest that transformation may be a very long and difficult process. While such may well be the case, one would expect progress in the right Etzioni I HUMAN NATURE, TRANSFORMING SOCIETY [301] direction to set in once a whole society is liberated and a new generation is born, unless, of course, the postrevolutionary societal format should turn out no more, or even less, responsive than was the prerevolutionary. In any event, the need to take into account the time dimension and contextual factors severely aggravates the difficulties of studying human nature in this comparative way. Fortunately, the methodological difficulty in establishing what are the basic human needs via such comparative studies (that is, seeing individuals only in culture and hence having to laboriously derive their naked nature by establishing that which is common to all cultures) can be overcome by proceeding along a different route, by studying the genesis of individuals, focusing on the stage when they are at the threshold of society and in this sense are still outside it. If we ask where and how this human nature evolved, it is easier to ascertain what this nature is than to ferret it out through comparative studies. In part, human nature does rest in the biological inheritance man shares with other mammals. Nature seems to account for the very consequential desire for frequent gratifications of all the needs listed above. The preferences seems to hold all the way, except for very frequent gratification. That is, inasmuch as satisfaction is achieved by releasing a tension, unless some appetite is built up there is no satisfaction. Otherwise, frequent release is preferred over infrequent, unless cultural conditioning has introduced-in steps which can be readily traced in the education and social control processes-the opposite inclination, and even this kind of conditioning cannot go very far. Thus, people in various cultures differ as to how often they eat; some have no regular meals at all, just dip into the pot when they feel hungry, others have highly stylized meals; but in all cultures I informally surveyed (with the help of anthropologists) members appear to consume food more than once a day and the preference seems to be toward more than two-often, whenever hunger sets in. [302] INTERNATIONAL JOURNAL OF GROUP TENSIONS The reason seems to be that the physiological needs are such that the longer a human being (or other animal) defers gratification the more frustrated it becomes. A human being can train himself to eat lessoften, even go on a hunger strike; however, such infrequent consumption of food in all cultures will be experienced as a deprivation, feat, punishment, and even glory, but not as gratifying or pleasurable-that would be against nature. The same seems to hold for other abstinences. As all human beings start with the same basic physiology (warm blood, oxygen-processing lungs, cleansing kidneys, and so forth), physiology serves as one un iversal basis in determining how satisfactory a specific societal arrangement can be expected to be. Beyond this, however, there is a universal social source from which the infants attain their human features, and this also implants shared basic needs. For the infant to evolve so as to fit the definition of human-either a two-legged erect being without wings (the Aristotelian definition) or as a symbol-processing, speaking, hence culture-absorbing creature-it must be provided with a human parent. The parent, anthropologists keep reminding us, need not be the biological mother, much less the biological father, but a being already human, who will take care of the infant and teach it to walk and talk and the rest of the bundle of tricks which quite literally make the born animal into a human. I n the process the infant also acquires a dependency on the symbolic approval of significant others, the need for affection and esteem. How this happens has been often described and needs here only the briefest reminder. Children, as their specific needs for food and warmth are provided for by a parent, soon learn that the parent has the capacity to reduce their pain or discomfort, to increase their pleasure, and thus generalize some of this capacity to the nurturant person. So where originally only the mother's milk (or some other specific act by a parent) was gratifying, now the parent's generalized attitude, communicated through signs such as a Etzioni / HUMAN NATURE, TRANSFORMING SOCIETY [303] pat or a smile, is rewarding. Soon expressions of love are, by themselves, experienced as gratifying. The human need is established: the growing person may go elsewhere and may perform a variety of activities to gain the craved affection, but he will no longer be satisfied without a regular flow. Also, the human infant, unlike a lower-order animal, cannot rely on reflexes-which respond to a need with a biologically determined line of action. Even after this, his needs are implanted and specific patterns which will gratify them must be shaped. Adult guidance provides the pattern and the assurance that the pattern acquired is appropriate. Thus the need for approval is further reinforced. Other needs are similarly evolved.4 Marcuse attacks Fromm and other "F reudian revisionists" for "theoretical eclecticism"-which is to say that they plucked the concept of love from their ideological bags or thin air. While the two authors do not present or cite empirical evidence and their theoretical constructions surely are not ideologically neutral, there is from other sources a rich body of data and careful theorizing which makes the above conception of human needs about as "hard" as any could be. Maslow (1962: 37) is surely correct in stating that "the evidence that we 'need' love [and other social satisfactions] is of exactly the same type as the evidence that we 'need' iodine or vitamin C." If we are deficient in either love or vitamins, we suffer; if they are cut out altogether, we cannot function. The source of human nature is universal; the basic process is universal; hence the basic nature is universal. True, there are variations which the anthropologists played up for a while. However, what has been disregarded for too long is that all these are variations on a basic unchanging theme; there is in all these situations a parent (usually two) who is the agent of socialization, not a robot-like dispenser of food and diapers but as a source of affection and recognition. Hence, why is it so surprising that the persons which grow up have the same basic needs? [304] INTERNATIONAL JOURNAL OF GROUP TENSIONS If all human beings have these needs, how is one to explain the existence of repressive societies? First, the needs have no political power per se. Those who are frustrated because their needs are not fulfilled may withdraw (in liquor, drugs, apathy), strike out aimlessly, or hang new hopes on false and "undesirable" needs. Only when they understand themselves and act on this understanding, and do so collectively, can people remake society in their own true image. Second, subgroups can increase their own satisfaction by decreasing that of others; they will attempt this even though not all or even most desirable items are scarce, and many of those that are scarce could be made more abundant by cooperation rather than monopolization. Some highly significant sources of satisfaction are, especially in lean times, in a "zero-sum" condition. That is, whatever one group uses of them, others cannot. Hence, groups that command power because of their societal function (e.g., warriors) or symbolic status (e.g., priests) are tempted to use it to curtail the satisfaction of other groups and thus increase their own share of that which is to be had. The conditions under which all the needs of all the members acquire the same status as having effective claims on the resources to be distributed, must be left to be explored on another occasion. Here, my purpose is only to defend the theoretical status of the concept of basic inalienable individual needs and to point out the possibility, or principle, of evolving a society that could be responsive to these needs and hence not repressive. SUBLIMATION: A CONCEPTUAL HIGHLIGHT Sometimes exploring a single concept highlights a complicated issue. The study of sublimation offers such a light. Freud, who saw in human nature biologically rooted drives being converted into socially less destructive and more productive outlets (such as sex into work), held that the drives have a sticky quality; they cannot be wholly subli- Etzioni I HUMAN NATURE, TRANSFORMING SOCIETY [305] mated; there always remains underneath each sublimated pattern the primordial drive. Hence the frustration civilization entails, the need to maintain controls, and the impossibility of a wholly non repressive society. The social science approach reviewed above offers an alternative view which raises the possibility of complete sublimation (some refer simply to "rechanneling," like switching a river into a different bed), as the drives are assumed to be highly pliable-or better yet, there is nothing to sublimate, as the drives or needs people have are socially determined (love, for instance). And those needs which do have a biological origin are open-ended and can be specified into a large variety of outlets, whatever the society approves. Hence here it is assumed, at least in principle, a person can be made fully happy with his social role. If a substantial number of people are actually not happy, this is then attributable to deficient social engineering-either in the sense that ways of fitting them into the system have not been studied adequately or that the social engineers' advice has not been heeded. Successful engineering would provide that a 1984 kind of society, in which-through, let us say, stronger use of mass media and behavior modifying drugs-complete control and happiness could be generated. There is nothing in human nature as thus perceived to rule this out, precisely because there is nothing incontrovertible, nothing to sublimate, only so much psychic clay to be molded to society's specifications. As I see it, the needs people bring to the society have a considerable degree of specificity although they are not as predetermined as biological instincts or reflexes and, above all, are not inherently antisocial. Thus, people have a need for affection which can be satisfied in a variety of ways, but they cannot be drilled into substituting anything else for it (sublimation) or doing without it (rejection). And any two forms of serving this need (or any other) are likely to differ, at least marginally, in the extent of satisfaction they provide. [306] INTERNATIONAL JOURNAL OF GROUP TENSIONS Thus, people afforded fewer opportunities for its expression will find such a social system less satisfying than one which offers more frequent ones. Intense, encompassing affection IS more satisfying than superficial, transient contacts. That is, social patterns vary in the amounts and kinds of costs as against satisfactions they generate. A nonrepressive society is possible in principle, not by carefully and finely grinding the members to fit its pattern, but by fitting the societal pattern to the fulfillment of the members' needs. Will the people not have desires which are incompatible? To the degree that they will, organization and regulation will be necessary. But, in a world rich in things, the materialistic desires may be sated (we return to the question of their alleged insatiable quality below) and the satisfaction of the other needs is not governed by scarcity but by needs such as affection and recognition (love and dignity)-in principle, all members may award each other. Also, when people are emphathetic with each other, they will change their specific preferences out of respect for each other and the viability of the community, without a residue of frustration. Thus, a true friend is not frustrated because he cannot have the love of his friend's spouse. And a truly integrated member of a commune does not wish to use the one violin just at the time someone else is playing it, especially when there are plenty of other instruments around. This sounds, and is, idealistic because it presupposes that economic scarcity, social manipulation, and personal pathologies all have been removed and the social system opened to authentic participation, needed to make it responsive and harmonize members, for reasons discussed above. That it is idealistic only means it will not be easy to come by; nothing indicates that it cannot be approximated. And it does explain how one can both hold that sublimation of basic needs is not possible and maintain that in principle a nonrepressive system is possible (albeit not in the immediate offing). Transforming forces will be found in those movements which seek to adapt Etzioni I HUMAN NATURE, TRANSFORMING SOCIETY [307] the social system to the members rather than the other way around, and to foster a commitment to treat all members as purposes (needed if A is to truly accept inevitable limitations which B sets on his freedom), and which are tolerant of the reallocations necessary to reduce economic scarcity (because absence of want lessens interpersonal and intergroup tensions out of wh ich confl icts may arise). To make the transformation of society-by having it fit the needs of individuals-the central project of an attempt to abolish repression, is not to suggest that just any societal pattern dreamed up can be realized, that one can ignore the sociological laws of gravity. Just as architects are free to redesign buildings as they please, so long as the new design does not call for a building which is too tall, too narrowly based, the ratio of weight to structure violated, so the members of a society can reshape it-as long as its basic survival needs are not disregarded. I n the past, the needs of the nation (or the "economy") have often been used to justify the needs of those in power, and not real societal ones. The rebellion against societal demands reflects a backlash against this abuse. But its abuse suggests that rather than throwing out the concept, citizens must inform themselves so as to be able to differentiate false from authentic societal needs. The real societal ones cannot be ignored. But it is society that is flexible and adaptable, and there is nothing in its nature which does not allow, in principle, the satisfaction of all the basic human needs of all the members. There is a great confusion in this context between alienation that results from societability and from particular social structures. Sartre, for instance, sees in "the other" a jailor, and in the group, hell with no exit. However, if one seesthe other as a main source of some of one's most useful satisfactions, and oneself as a source of his, and that there is no individual need which cannot be truly satisfied in society, then we see the source of alienation not in our societal roots [308] INTERNATIONAL JOURNAL OF GROUP TENSIONS but in unresponsive formats; we see the way to fulfillment not in an anarchist abolition of society (beyond that of the state) but in the transforming of society. CONCLUDING NOTES All said and done, then, it seems quite unarguable that individuals and society go hand in hand and cannot be found one without the other, require each other like molecules and matter. It is hence senseless to ask if people could liberate themselves from society so as to reveal their natural goodness, because such a turn would mean restraining to ever more primary bases, falling back to the animal foundation. Recently it has become popular to depict the animal societies as more humane, pacific, and loving than human ones. A careful reading of the descriptions, though, reveals that animals will fight to kill, and not just ritualistically, when they are hungry and when their "turf" is invaded or they fear it will be. One or both of these conditions prevail most of the time. To return to the primal life is to return to the life of the jungle. The assumption of a human nature independent of societal shaping allows us to evaluate societies. Sorry indeed is a social science which cannot differentiate systematically-that is, on the basis of its concepts and premises-among a Nazi concentration camp, a Stalinist labor camp, a Danish cooperative farm, and a kibbutz in Israel, or can do so only on the basis of ad hoc, post hoc, personal value judgments. We need a social science that can help us anticipate which social arrangements would be more humane and just. Societies differ systematically in the extent to which they respond to the basic needs of their members. It should hence be possible to rank all societies, or compare periods in the life of the same society, as to how "good" they are, not from the standpoint of what an intellectual scholar, or one citizen sees Etzioni I HUMAN NATURE, TRANSFORMING SOCIETY [309] as significant, but from the vantage point of the society's own members, all of them. Thus observers whose personal preferences may vary greatly would agree that ancient Sparta and Stalin's USSR were lessresponsive to their members than ancient Athens or contemporary Russia. That is, there can be an agreed upon basis for a critical science. Robert Brownstein pointed out in a personal communication that you criticize the social science viewpoint for failing to provide a third alternative to either a neutral descriptive science of man or outright value judgments. I would argue that value judgments make up an intrinsic part of any effort to evaluate societies-even if the existence of basic needs is acknowledged. Knowing that basic needs exist does not automatically produce a means of coping with contradictions between needs (e.g., security and self-realization) or of indicating how needs should be limited in a scarcity situation, or of handling questions of distributive justice (should society guarantee everyone an equal amount of affection), or allocating priorities among non-basic needs. In fact, even if a need is natural, one can still argue whether it ought to be met. One might argue that the need for recognition interferes with independent and creat)ve innovation which is unpopular. This is all quite true. Nevertheless, the assumption that human needs are universal, shared by all-even pending empirical validation-provides an absolute anchoring point which no theorizing and evaluation can ignore, and thus breaks the back of relativism, and provides the essential basis for a scientific discipline-a shared, incontrovertible, empirical base. Thus, whatever value one may put on affection, one cannot ignore that all persons appear to need it and that all social systems which do not provide for it distort those individuals thus deprived. Finally, the facts about human nature are not neutral. A misanthrope may argue that a system which answers fewer human needs is better than one which answers more, but [310] INTERNATIONAL JOURNAL OF GROUP TENSIONS what basis could a social scientist have for putting his preferences before the real needs of all human beings? As to how priorities are to be set in a scarcity situation, the answer is-by the members, in a free give-and-take, which the social scientist may facilitate but dare not determine lest public policy not be truly responsive. Does this position deny the basic Marxist dictum that man is a creature of his social condition? that this fate is determined by the struggle between classesthat differ in their property base, a struggle within society, and not between him (his needs) and society (its unresponsive arrangement)? My position is consistent with Marx's, but not with the vulgarization of Marx's position-such as the one just cited, often attributed to him. Marx was quite aware that man has a nature of his own, that man acts on his historical condition as he i!) acted upon by it. I n an often cited statement he asserted (Marx, 19: I, lc, 668): one "must first deal with human nature in general, and then with human nature as modified in each historical period." This statement cannot be written off as coming from a young Marx, seen by the hard-nosed left as a soft romantic, because it was written by the old Marx. More significant, it is consistent with his position elsewhere, that man is active, that only "ultimately," in the last account, do technological economic forces prevail in history. Of course, he did not, like Nietzsche or Ayn Rand, focus on single "superior" individuals, able to shape history because each individual faces all others and their collective social expressions. But if by individuals one understands groups of people, like Marx I can see them joining hands to change their condition rather radically and to bring it closer to that which is responsive to their nature. What other fixed Archimedean point could there be? People can hardly be expected to act out a script a historian has conceived to rely on the outgoing, rejected society's prescriptions. The more they reject the outgoing pattern and open the society to recasting, the more they regress, the more they cannot but fall back on the one Etzioni / HUMAN NATURE, TRANSFORMING SOCIETY [311] remaining base-that which is in the constant, shared human nature. Along with these universal limitations on the freedoms of societal redesigning, each generation faces the sins of its predecessors. It cannot start from scratch, as if its members were a group of day-old infants, meeting to vote on which conditions to set up. Some-often much-of the available energy must be invested in opening up the societal and intrapersonal locks, in overcoming the present, in outgrowing the past. And the level of energy left for reconstruction is affected by historical conditions, of which material output and security are first. I n principle, though, the members of a society can join to fashion a society that is good for them. A study of human nature points to reconstruction and transformation, following temporary regression. Retreat from societability is not possible; to impose new repression is to prepare for a new crisis. NOTES 1. See Textor (1968: 155), who cites Ford and Benit (1951: 46, n. 4). 2. This and the following quotes are from Neubeck (19: 119ff.). 3. Other lists have been advanced by Kingsley Davis, Talcott Parsons, and Abraham Maslow. For additional discussion on how this list was derived and can be validated, see Etzioni (1968: ch. 21). 4. The details are extremely complex and are widely debated, but the general thesis is quite well documented. See any standard text on child development or socialization, for instance, Mussen et al. (19). REFERENCES BENEDICT, R. (1934) Patterns of Culture. Boston: Houghton Mifflin. BREDEMEIER, H. C. (1971) "Banfield, Gouldner, and social problems." Problems 18 (Spring): 562. Social [312] INTERNATIONAL JOURNAL OF GROUP TENSIONS BROWN, N. O. (1966) Love's Body. New York: Vintage. ---(1959) Life Against Death. Middletown, Conn.: Wesleyan Univ. Press. ETZIONI, A. (1968) The Active Society. New York: Free Press. FRIEDENBERG, E. Z. (n.d.) Coming of Age in America. FROMM, E. led.] (1966) Marx's Concept of Man (T. B. Bottomore, trans.). New York: Frederick Ungar. ---(1955) The Sane Society. New York: Holt, Rinehart & Winston. GEIGER, T. (1964) Social Order and Human Society. Chicago: Univ. of Chicago Press. GOULDNER, A. (1970) The Coming Crisis of Western Sociology. New York: Basic Books. IN KELES, A. (1964) What is Sociology. Englewood Cliffs, N.J.: Prentice-Hall. KATEB, G. (1970) "The political thought of Herbert Marcuse." Commentary 49: 55. KINSEY, A. G. (1953) Sexual Behavior in the Human Female. Philadelphia: W. B. Saunders. MARCUSE, H. (1955) Eros and Civilization. Boston: Beacon. MASLOW, A. H. (1962) Toward a Psychology of Being. Princeton: D. Van Nostrand. MURDOCK, G. P. (1949) Social Structure. New York: Macmillan. MUSSEN, P. H., J. JANEWAY, and J. KAGAN (1969) Child Development and Personality. New York: Harper & Row. NEUBECK, G. led.] (n.d.) Extramarital Relations. REICH, W. (1963) The Sexual Revolution. New York: Farrar, Straus & Giroux. TEXTOR, R. B. (1968) A Cross-Cultural Summary. New York: Human Relations Area File Press. WRONG, D. (1965) "Human nature and the perspective of sociology." Social Research 30: 300-318. ZWTTERBAUM, M. (n.d.! "Self and political order." Interpretation.