H F-XC A N GE H F-XC A N GE c u-tr a c k N y bu to k lic .d o m w o Possible Islands of Predictability: The Legal Thought of Hannah Arendt .c C m o .d o w w w w w C lic k to bu y N O W ! PD O W ! PD c u-tr a c k Jan Klabbers1 I Political theorists do not often comment on current affairs, let alone current legal affairs: one would be hard pressed to find a leading political theorist reviewing, say, the US Supreme Court’s Guantanamo opinion, or the trial against Saddam Hussein. 2 Hannah Arendt was different though. Some of her most well-known (some might say infamous) works were commentaries on current affairs3, both domestic and international, and some of these were explicit commentaries on important legal proceedings. The unauthorized publication of the Pentagon Papers, e.g., discussing the role of the US military in Vietnam, provoked a lengthy comment from her pen about lying in politics 4; she managed to offend a lot of people by her analysis of the follow-up to one of the US Supreme Court’s desegregation orders relating to schools in the southern US5; she devoted an entire book to the Eichmann trial, and even suggested that the trial of Socrates formed a pivotal turning point in the history of political thought, marking, as it does, the separation between philosophy and politics.6 In particular her attention for legal proceedings suggests that Arendt, unlike most political theorists, was well aware of the intimate and reciprocal relationships between law and politics. Where political theorists generally tend to treat law as the result of politics (and thus as somehow epiphenomenal, and of lesser importance7), for Arendt, so it seems, law was more than just the outcome of politics, or the reflection of politics, or the handmaiden of politics. Reflecting 1 Professor of International Organizations Law, University of Helsinki; Director, Academy of Finland Centre of Excellence in Global Governance Research. Many thanks to Larry May for his useful comments on an earlier version of this paper. 2 One of the few present-day public intellectuals who come to mind as someone who occasionally addresses such issues is Jürgen Habermas. 3 Despite, by her own admission, not understanding much about current affairs, as she wrote in playful French to Heinrich Blücher, who would become her second husband. See Hannah Arendt – Heinrich Blücher: Briefe 19361968 (Munich: Piper, 1999, L Köhler ed.), at 79. 4 See H. Arendt, ‘Lying in Politics: Reflections on the Pentagon Papers’, in H. Arendt, Crises of the Republic (1972) 3-47. The legal background and political manoeuvring within the US Supreme Court is well-sketched in B. Woodward & S. Armstrong, The Brethren: Inside the Supreme Court (1979) 5 See H. Arendt, ‘Reflections on Little Rock’, reproduced in P. Baehr (ed.), The Portable Hannah Arendt (2000) 231-246, as well as, in slightly different form, in H. Arendt, Responsibility and Judgment (2003, J. Kohn ed.) 193213. References will be to the former. 6 See H. Arendt, ‘Socrates’, in H. Arendt, The Promise of Politics (2005, J. Kohn ed.) 5-39, at 6. 7 This applies not just to political theorists, but to all who somehow occupy themselves with politics as a profession. For a brief overview of the skewed relationship between international lawyers and international relations scholars, see J. Klabbers, ‘The Relative Autonomy of International Law or The Forgotten Politics of Interdisciplinarity’, (2004/05) 1 Journal of International Law and International Relations 35-48. .c H F-XC A N GE H F-XC A N GE c u-tr a c k N y bu lic on legal trials and judgements made sense to her, precisely because of their political relevance.w k to .d o Law, to her, was an intrinsic part of political action and, as every activist will realize, often m o .c C m o .d o w w w w w C lic k to bu y N O W ! PD O W ! PD c u-tr a c k political action is geared to facilitate legal change. Typical for the attention Arendt bestowed on legal affairs is her acidic political interpretation of the “abysmal failure” of the Nuremberg trials: “The attempt to reduce the Nazi demographic policies to the criminal concepts of murder and per secution had the result, on the one hand, that the very enormity of the crimes rendered any conceivable punishment ridiculous; and, on the other, that no punishment could even be accepted as “legal,” since it presupposed, together with obedience to the command “Thou shalt not kill”, a possible range of motives, of qualities which cause men to become murderers and make them murderers, which quite obviously were completely absent in the accused.” 8 Arendt’s views on the relationship between law and politics were, quite obviously, dependent on her views on the two elements of the equation separately. While she wrote quite a bit on her concept of politics and set it out, with some coherence, in a single volume (The Human Condition, first published in 1958), a string of essays published in a single volume (Between Past and Future) and in a posthumously published work written a few years earlier (Introduction into Politics), her thoughts on law have always remained more sketchy and have, as far as I know, never been fully reconstructed by Arendt scholars. Perhaps the most obvious (or most wellknown) hint she dropped concerned the “right to have rights”: in thirteen brilliant pages in The Origins of Totalitarianism, the work which established her as a political theorist, she made clear, under the heading ‘The Perplexities of the Rights of Man’9, that human rights had little to offer those who were, as she herself had been for a long time, stateless.10 Human rights, so she argued, could only come to fruition in the framework of wider political communities 11: those who are not part of a political community (a state, typically) cannot count on any protection either: “Not the loss of specific rights, then, but the loss of a community willing and able to guarantee any rights whatsoever, has been the calamity which has befallen ever-increasing numbers of people. Man, it turns out, can lose all so-called Rights of Man without losing his essential quality as man, his 8 See H. Arendt, ‘Understanding and Politics (The Difficulties of Understanding)’, in H. Arendt, Essays on Understanding 1930-1954 (1994, J. Kohn ed.) 307-327, at 310. 9 See H. Arendt, The Origins of Totalitarianism (3d edn, 1979), at 290-312. Apparently, much of this was based on a text first published in 1949, in German, titled ‘Es gibt nur ein einziges Menschenrecht’. For an extensive discussion, see H. Brunkhorst, Hannah Arendt (1999). 10 The excellent standard biography is E. Young-Bruehl, Hannah Arendt: For Love of the World (2d edn, 2004). 11 Elsewhere she suggested that the universalism underlying human rights thought ran the risk of becoming a glorified Esperanto. See H. Arendt, ‘Karl Jaspers: Citizen of the World?’, in H. Arendt, Men in Dark Times (1983), 81-94, at 89. .c H F-XC A N GE H F-XC A N GE c u-tr a c k N y bu to k lic w .d o later she would point out that the only truly political rights happen to be the right to vote and the o .c m C m o .d o human dignity. Only the loss of a polity itself expels him from humanity.” 12 And a few years w w w w w C lic k to bu y N O W ! PD O W ! PD c u-tr a c k right to run for office, and those are typically not granted to resident aliens but only to nationals. 13 What is clear is that, to Arendt, law is itself intensely political; what is unclear is what this means. This essay (‘article’ being too big a word) is an attempt to reconstruct Arendt’s thoughts on law and its connections to politics, followed by a brief discussion of some of the issues in international law about which she had something of interest to say. As many will acknowledge, this applies to international criminal law and to human rights; her writings on these topics will be discussed in somewhat scattered form throughout the present piece, as they serve also to illustrate Arendt’s legal thought. Less obviously perhaps, she also had useful insights to offer on the currently popular idea of the constitutionalization of international law. It will be convenient to start with her views on politics, as these are inextricably linked to her legal thought. II During her lifetime, Arendt was typically treated with some disdain by those working in the same field; indeed, she consciously distanced herself from philosophy, preferring to think of herself as a political theorist instead.14 Professional philosophers would typically accuse her of being mistaken in her reading of classical Greece 15, of being perhaps intuitive rather than cerebral, of being rather aloof and haughty16 or insensitive17 and, after the Nazi regime, many 12 See Arendt, The Origins of Totalitarianism, supra note 9, at 297. Explorations include J. Isaac, ‘A New Guarantee on Earth: Human Dignity and the Politics of Human Rights’, in J. Isaac, Democracy in Dark Times (1998) 73-99; J. Klabbers, ‘Glorified Esperanto? Rethinking Human Rights’, (2002) 13 Finnish Yearbook of International Law 6377, and B. Cotter, ‘Hannah Arendt and “The Right to Have Rights”’, in A.F. Lang, Jr. & J. Williams (eds.), Hannah Arendt and International Relations: Readings Across the Lines (2005) 95-112. 13 See Arendt, ‘Reflections on Little Rock’, supra note 5, at 237. 14 See in particular the transcript of an interview first aired on German television, and reproduced under the title ‘”What Remains? The Language Remains”: A Conversation with Günter Gaus’, in The Portable Arendt, supra note 5. 15 See, .e.g., M. Ignatieff, Isaiah Berlin: A Life (2000), at 253. 16 In Laqueur’s words:, what is bothering about Arendt is “less the essence of what she said than the undue generalizations, the exaggerations, the violence and aggression in her attacks, the one-sidedness of her judgment.” See W. Laqueur, ‘The Arendt Cult: Hannah Arendt as Political Commentator’, in S.E. Ascheim (ed.), Hannah Arendt in Jerusalem (2001) 47-64, at 61. 17 Benhabib suggests that Arendt’s famous Eichmann study “exhibited at times an astonishing lack of perspective, balance of judgment, and judicious expression”, and finds that her comments on Eichmann’s prosecutor were “almost racist”. See S. Benhabib, ‘Arendt’s Eichmann in Jerusalem’, in D.Villa (ed.), The Cambridge Companion to Hannah Arendt (2000) 65-85, at 65. .c H F-XC A N GE H F-XC A N GE c u-tr a c k N y bu to k lic w 19 .d o former tutor and lover Martin Heidegger. To a large extent though, it would seem that the o .c m C m o .d o may have felt uncomfortable with her continued warm (but not uncritical18) feelings for her w w w w w C lic k to bu y N O W ! PD O W ! PD c u-tr a c k disdain found its cause in Arendt’s tendency to turn the regular academic philosophical approach on its head: whereas most philosophers first develop a view on the individual and, from there, extrapolate to capture the relations between individuals (social or political or both), thereby often suggesting that groups of individuals would merely be aggregates of the single stereotypical individual, Arendt worked the other way around. Her work during the 1950s and 1960s20, from The Origins of Totalitarianism via The Human Condition to On Revolution, is devoted to politics; it was only towards the end of her career that she started systematically to develop thoughts on individual faculties21, formulating (but never properly finishing) the Kant-inspired thesis that political judgment is related to aesthetic judgment. 22 In addition, Arendt was, and remains, difficult to categorize. She has been enlisted by conservatives and progressives alike23; feminist have been inspired by her work, as have both modernists (most prominently Habermas, perhaps24, but others as well25) and post-modernists. And Arendt herself was fairly ecumenical in where she drew her inspiration from: clear sources of inspiration are Aristotle and Kant, but then so are Heidegger and Nietzsche, not to mention Marx. 26 And while she generally held Christianity to be apolitical, favouring the contemplative life rather than the vita activa, she nonetheless drew on Christianity for inspiration as well, 18 Writing to Jaspers, she famously characterized Heidegger as lacking character, “in the sense that he literally has none and certainly not a particularly bad one.” See L. Kohler & H. Saner (eds.), Hannah Arendt – Karl Jaspers: Correspondence 1926-1969 (1992, Kimber & Kimber trans.), letter no. 93, 29 September 1949, at 142. 19 See the gossipy rendition in E. Ettinger, Hannah Arendt / Martin Heidegger (1995); a recent response of sorts is D. Maier-Katkin & B. Maier-Katkin, ‘Hannah Arendt and Martin Heidegger: Calumny and the Politics of Reconciliation’, (2006) 28 Human Rights Quarterly 86-119. 20 One hesitates to call this her earlier work, in that she had written the better part of two monographs already before The Origins of Totalitarianism, one doctrinally philosophical on St Augustine, and one (not quite completed at the time) on the salon of Rachel Varnhagen. Both are generally thought to already contain the seeds of some of her more overtly political work: she would return to Augustine to develop her politically relevant notion of natality (as will appear below), while Varnhagen stood model for the Jew as pariah, another significant Arendtian notion. See, e.g., R. Bernstein, Hannah Arendt and the Jewish Question (1996); T. Parvikko, The Responsibility of the Pariah (1996). 21 The key-word here is ’systematically’ for, as Bernstein makes clear, these also underlie her earlier work. See R. Bernstein, ‘Arendt on Thinking’, in The Cambridge Companion, supra note 17, 277-292. 22 Her work on judgment and its political relevance was posthumously published, in an edited version based on a series of lectures given in 1970, as H. Arendt, Lectures on Kant’s Political Thought (1982, R. Beiner ed.). It completed a trilogy, the first two parts dealing with thinking and willing. Those first two parts are published together as H. Arendt, The Life of the Mind (1978). 23 As Hauke Brunkhorst puts it: ”Arendt kann ebenso irritierend reaktionär sein wie sie – oft genug – verblüffend progressiv ist.” See Brunkhorst, supra note 9, at 138. 24 See Jürgen Habermas, Between Facts and Norms (1996, Rehg trans.). 25 A valiant attempt to formulate a left-wing politics on Arendtian foundations is Ph. Hansen, Hannah Arendt: Politics, History and Citizenship (1993). 26 Although she would also dismiss Marx, in quite sophisticated terms, as being “not interested either in freedom or in justice. (And he’s a terrible pain in the neck in addition.)” See Arendt-Jaspers Correspondence, supra note 18, letter no. 142, 13 May 1953, at 216. .c H F-XC A N GE H F-XC A N GE c u-tr a c k N y bu to k especially on the teachings of Augustine, to whom she had devoted her doctoral dissertation and w lic .d o who, she sometimes claimed, was Christianity’s only serious political philosopher. Having been trained in philosophy, her earliest forays into politics were less than surefooted, perhaps precisely because of difficulties in conceptualizing the individual in relation to the world. Typical is her early interpretation of Aristotle’s famous dictum that man is a political animal (‘zoon politikon’)27. In a fragment written in 1950, she suggests (without much argument except an unspecified reference to Hobbes) that this cannot mean that there is something essentially political about individuals. Instead, the individual him- or herself is a-political; politics is that what happens between individuals, and thus outside them personally. 28 Four years later though, in a lecture containing many of the seeds that would later come to fruition in The Human Condition, she had further developed this understanding, tracing politics back not so much, as political philosophers are wont to, to the necessity of living together in a pluralist world (although, as we shall see, she too embraced plurality as her starting point), but rather to the human capacity to act, including, in Aristotelian fashion, the capacity to communicate.29 And this would suggest that there is something inherently political about humans, thus adapting her earlier interpretation of Aristotle’s zoon politikon. Still, this sets her aside from others: for her, the relevant thing is that politics starts with plurality, and that this plurality signifies that different people function differently, have different ideas and opinions, and come to different judgments in political matters. Plurality, then, literally means plurality, not merely, as it often does to others, a single stereotypical human being in the aggregate. Arendt’s political theory can usefully be (and often is) summed up in a few sentences.30 For her, politics is not just about who gets what, when, and how; it is not just about power and the distribution thereof, as it is for most political theorists.31 It is also, and predominantly so, about how to organize our lives together, and how to debate and discuss our common future or futures. To this end, a pure version of politics (not entirely unlike Kelsen’s pure law) would be useful: a politics stripped of all attempts by individuals to promote their own interests. What 27 See Aristotle, The Politics (1992 edn., Sinclair transl.), at 59 (book I, ch. ii). ”... der Mensch ist a-politisch. Politik entsteht in dem Zwischen-den-Menschen, also durchaus ausserhalb des Menschen. Es gibt daher keine eigentliche politische Substanz. Politik entsteht im Zwischen und etabliert sich als der Bezug.” See H. Arendt, Was ist Politik? (1993, U. Ludz ed.), at 11. The English translation is published as ‘Introduction into Politics’, in The Promise of Politics, supra note 6, 93-200. The quote reads: “… man is apolitical. Politics arises between men, and so quite outside of man. There is therefore no real political substance. Politics arises in what lies between men and is established as relationships.” (at 95, italics omitted). 29 See H. Arendt, ’Concern with Politics in Recent European Philosophical Thought’, in Essays on Understanding, supra note 8, 428-447. 30 A brilliant and brief rendition is D. Villa, ‘Introduction: The Development of Arendt’s Political Thought’, in The Cambridge Companion, supra note 17, 1-21. Influential comprehensive studies of her Arendt’s political thought include M. Canovan, Hannah Arendt: A Reinterpretation of her Political Thought (1992), and D. Villa, Arendt and Heidegger: The Fate of the Political (1996). My reading of Arendt owes much to both. 31 For a useful overview (in Dutch, alas) on the meaning of politics, see M. Fennema & R. van der Wouden (eds.), Het politicologen-debat: wat is politiek? (1982). 28 m o .c C m o .d o w w w w w C lic k to bu y N O W ! PD O W ! PD c u-tr a c k .c H F-XC A N GE H F-XC A N GE c u-tr a c k N y bu lic politics stands for is discussion in the public sphere about public topics and ideals, about takingw k to .d o care of the world, and the main point of the discussion is not even to reach a result, but resides in m o .c C m o .d o w w w w w C lic k to bu y N O W ! PD O W ! PD c u-tr a c k the activity itself: it is only in politics that humans can express themselves fully to the world, and can excel in their own individuality. This then paints a strongly participatory picture: a picture of politics as a public activity in which all can participate, and where private economic and social interests and arguments, and even considerations of morality, should not be allowed to shine through.32 For as soon as this would happen, the political community would be “dissolved from within”: the social would come to “overwhelm” the republic. 33 Still, in particular given the capacity of humanity to destroy the world by means of nuclear weapons (she was living in the US when the bombs on Hiroshima and Nagasaki were dropped, and was thoroughly frightened by their potential), capacity for renewal assumes prime importance. Arendt found this in her concept of natality. In a literal sense, every new birth of every new child carries the potential for a new beginning for humankind; more metaphorically, natality signifies the political power of people to come together anew, to organize themselves anew, to form a new political community: hence her keen interest in the phenomenon of revolution, as exemplified in her book On Revolution. For her, revolution marked a new beginning, not merely, as so often, the overthrow of the ancien régime. 34 This politics, moreover, is the only possible way to guarantee freedom: “The meaning of politics is freedom.” 35 Only in politics can men and women be truly free; only in political action can they express themselves without having to worry about having to go to work in the morning, or having to worry about how to feed their children. While labour may be necessary for people to sustain themselves, and work may create useful and lasting artefacts, the political world revolves around a concept of action of which, in turn, speech is an important component.36 For, as Aristiotle had already suggested, it is the capacity of speech which makes men a zoon politikon.37 A political community then allows people to make the most of themselves. Peter Euben puts it well: “For Arendt, a political community as opposed to the ersatz politics of a Platonic city or a 32 Weltfremd as this may seem, it is probably not too far-fetched to suppose that Rawls based his veil of ignorance on similar considerations. See J. Rawls, A Theory of Justice (1973). 33 See Arendt-Jaspers Correspondence, supra note 18, letter no. 152, 21 December 1953, at 235-236. 34 “…the end of rebellion is liberation, while the end of revolution is the foundation of freedom.” And a few sentences later: “… there is nothing more futile than rebellion and liberation unless they are followed by the constitution of the newly won freedom.” See H. Arendt, On Revolution (1963), at 142. 35 See Arendt, ‘Introduction into Politics’, supra note 28, at 108. 36 This distinction between labour, work and action as separate concepts is set out most clearly in H. Arendt, The Human Condition (1958). See also the brief outline under the heading ‘Labor, Work, Action’, as reproduced in The Portable Arendt, supra note 5, 167-181. 37 See Arendt, Socrates, supra note 6, at 35. See also Aristotle, supra note 27, at 60. .c H F-XC A N GE H F-XC A N GE c u-tr a c k N y bu lic liberal state requires the contentiousness of strong-willed individuals who also appreciate how w k to the world they share makes their individualism possible.”38 .d o It is no surprise, e.g., then when called upon for jury duty in the mid-1960s, she thoroughly enjoyed herself, as she reported to Jaspers: “The whole business is really quite wonderful. You sit together with people from all classes, and the deliberations are very impressive, on the one hand because everyone takes the matter of justice very seriously and on the other because everyone is very happy to be there even if it means a significant loss of money and time for just about everyone. It is a duty of citizenship, and people are happy to assume it. And they perform it without any pretensions.”39 But how then to figure out which political expressions to adhere to or reject? How to figure out who would be right, and who would be wrong? At first blush, a politics for the sake of politics itself would require some way of delimiting true from false, worthwhile from useless, beneficial from harmful. One cannot just tell others that such-and-such is a bad idea; instead one needs to have some yardstick for judging these things, and this Arendt found in Kant’s doctrine of aesthetic judgment. As Benhabib puts it, in Kant’s doctrine “Arendt discovered a procedure for ascertaining intersubjective agreement in the public realm.” 40 In much the same way that we can meaningfully debate the beauty of a painting or a piece of music, we are also capable of debating political action and judging the wisdom or folly of past or prospective courses of action. 41 As a result, though, politics is necessarily a fragile activity, and prone to unpredictability. Indeed, on one interpretation (which would find a solid basis in parts of Arendt’s work42), politics in its true meaning is so fragile that it is hardly ever present; typically, it would only occur in revolutionary situations, where people are temporarily engaged with discussing their common futures before things become the routine of everyday partisan politics again. The US revolution of the 18th century was an example, as was the Hungarian uprising of 1956, however short-lived. She would no doubt also have embraced the enthusiasm with which eastern Europeans responded to the crumbling of the Soviet empire around 1990 as a true example of politics, but was clearly less impressed by the development of everyday politics into pre-cooked deals between locked-in interest groups. Her ideals were derived, as many have noted, from ancient Greece, although it would seem fair to suggest that hers was not a wistful nostalgia, but rather a search for historical inspiration, inevitable in any attempt to understand politics: “The 38 See P. Euben, ‘Arendt’s Hellenism’, in The Cambridge Companion, supra note 17, 151-164, at 156. See Arendt-Jaspers Correspondence, supra note 18, letter no. 414, 16 January, 1967, at 666. 40 See S. Benhabib, The Reluctant Modernism of Hannah Arendt (1996), at 189. 41 Arendt never fully elaborated this, and some commentators remain sceptical. See e.g. R. Beiner’s ‘Interpretive Essay’, in Arendt, Kant’s Political Thought, supra note 22. 42 See, e.g., her ’Introduction into Politics’, supra note 28, at 119. 39 m o .c C m o .d o w w w w w C lic k to bu y N O W ! PD O W ! PD c u-tr a c k .c H F-XC A N GE H F-XC A N GE c u-tr a c k N y bu lic Greek polis will continue to exist at the bottom of our political existence – that is, at the bottomw k to of the sea – for as long as we use the word ‘politics’.”43 .d o This connection of politics to revolution may, however, be too narrow a reading of Arendt’s conception of politics, for on other occasions she suggests that politics occurs wherever people relate to each other without being completely overwhelmed by their own interests: in the 1950s, she could still write that international politics was a proper example of politics precisely because it could not be reduced to bargaining about economic interests.44 And indeed, it would seem fair (and more fruitful) to regard Arendt’s conception of politics not as some vague reference to a past which may never have existed as such in ancient Greece to begin with45, but rather as developing a style of thinking about politics where individuals jointly, in all their plurality, take care of the world, and assume responsibility for it.46 Politics, then, to Arendt, is not (or not only) a matter of “who gets what, when and how”, as it is classically described. Neither is politics only a matter of acquiring and utilizing power in a more Foucauldian sense (I am not aware of Arendt discussing Foucault anywhere, but my guess is that she would look favourably at his work, not least for its maverick qualities), nor is it a means to reach agreement and accomplish certain goals, as modern discourse theory and deliberative democracy suggest. What sets Arendt apart (relatively speaking, of course47) is that, to her, politics is its own reward. This is difficult to grasp, for our tradition of political thought is immersed in thinking in terms of ends and means, whereby politics is often the means to a further, higher end, somewhere beyond politics: the Marxist workers’ paradise, the liberal rights heaven, what have you. To Arendt, by contrast, politics is its own reward, because it gives people the opportunity to excel and present themselves in public, to an audience, and in doing so 43 See H. Arendt, ‘Introduction: Walter Benjamin 1892-1940’, in W. Benjamin, Illuminations (1973), 7-55, at 53 (emphasis in original). 44 See H. Arendt, ‘What is Freedom?’, in H. Arendt, Between Past and Future (1977) 143-171, at 155: “Only foreign affairs, because the relationships between nations still harbour hostilities and sympathies which cannot be reduced to economic factors, seem to be left as a purely political domain.” Elsewhere though (and no doubt one reason why she has often been accused of being unsystematic), she seems to equate foreign policy with the nonpolitical. See, e.g., Arendt, Introduction into Politics, supra note 28, at 165. 45 Taminiaux argues cogently that however important ancient Greece may have been to Arendt, her conception of politics owes much to republican Rome as well. See J. Taminiaux, ‘Athens and Rome’, in The Cambridge Companion, supra note 17, 165-177. On the relevance of Roman political thought, see also Q. Skinner, Liberty Before Liberalism (1998). 46 One of the sources of her critique of bureaucratic governance was precisely that it ended up with no one being responsible for anything anymore: this would result in anonymous despotism. See Introduction into Politics, supra note 28, at 97. Some of this was based, quite obviously, on her reading of Kafka: see Arendt, ‘Franz Kafka: A Revaluation’, in Essays on Understanding, supra note 8, 69-80. 47 To some extent a kindred spirit though is the British philosopher Oakeshott: see M. Oakeshott, On Human Conduct (1975). A less than fully elaborated recent contribution underlining the idea of a transcultural conversation based on the liberal value of toleration is K.A. Appiah, Cosmopolitanism: Ethics in a World of Strangers (2006). Appiah is Arendtian in his rejection of the idea that this transcultural conversation should lead to some tangible results, but lacks the contrariness that characterizes both Arendt and Oakeshott. m o .c C m o .d o w w w w w C lic k to bu y N O W ! PD O W ! PD c u-tr a c k .c H F-XC A N GE H F-XC A N GE c u-tr a c k N y bu to k is our best chance to fend off evil. For evil can come about when people act in secrecy, and when w they stop caring for the world, only to care for themselves. 48 Arendt’s concept of politics has met with its fair share of criticism, of course. Chief amongst these is the suggestion that one can hardly take individual and group interests out of the equation, for what would be left to discuss? What would politics be about if not about such things as the price of milk, the salaries and working conditions of workers or the length of paid summer vacations? 49 On occasion, dubious stains on an intern’s dress may provide some political fodder or arouse people’s interest, but this too falls far short of Arendt’s standards of what makes politics an important activity. Indeed, some have posited that few people would actually be all that interested in a politics stripped of all things social and economic, resulting in mass apathy and a small class of interested people who would, by virtue of being interested, become specialists and in that way end up monopolizing politics, rather contrary to Arendt’s intentions. 50 III Either way, Arendt’s politics is a fragile affair. It needs constant protection and, no less important, left entirely to its own devices it might lead to unpredictability, in much the same way in which improvisational theatre might result in chaos if not supported by some form of structure.51 This structure, then, Arendt found in the law. The remedy for unpredictability, so Arendt learned from Rome, is the faculty (unique to humans) of making and keeping promises: pacta sunt servanda.52 It is no coincidence, so she points out, that political thought over the centuries has been dominated by contract theories. Indeed, the faculty of promising serves two immediate purposes. On the one hand, the fact that man is free means he can never be sure himself of what he will do tomorrow: this creates uncertainty. On the other hand, the fact of human plurality suggests that man not only does not know what he himself will do tomorrow, but also cannot be sure as to what others, and the community he is part of, will do tomorrow. 48 This is further explored in J. McGowan, Hannah Arendt: An Introduction (1998), esp. at 100-108. Most subtly, see H. Pitkin, The Attack of the Blob: Hannah Arendt’s Concept of the Social (1998). 50 See the fine study (in Dutch) by I. de Haan, Zelfbestuur en staatsbeheer: het politieke debat over burgerschap en rechtsstaat in de twintigste eeuw (1993). 51 The theatre metaphor is not entirely coincidental. See R. Sennett, The Fall of Public Man (1974). 52 “All political business is, and always has been, transacted within an elaborate framework of ties and bonds for the future – such as laws and constitutions, treaties and alliances – all of which derive in the last instance from the faculty to promise and to keep promises in the face of the essential uncertainties of the future.” See Arendt, ´What is Freedom´, supra note 44, at 164. 49 c u-tr a c k o .d o m lic .c C m o .d o w w w w w C lic k to bu y N O W ! PD O W ! PD .c H F-XC A N GE H F-XC A N GE c u-tr a c k N y bu to k Hence: promises (and thus contract); indeed, these form “the only alternative to a mastery which w lic relies on domination of one’s self and rule over others”.53 .d o m o .c C m o .d o w w w w w C lic k to bu y N O W ! PD O W ! PD c u-tr a c k Taken to the extreme, however, a life filled with promises ends up undermining itself: while promise is a means to come to terms with and protect freedom, at the extreme it could make freedom and politics impossible (this is, indeed, one of the paradoxes of constitutional theory54), so what Arendt ends up advocating in evocative, but perhaps less than fully clear terms, is the use of promises to create ‘islands of predictability’, or ‘guideposts of reliability’.55 The point as such is clear enough, even if her conclusion is somewhat surprising. To her, an overdose of promises means they lose their binding force: “The moment promises lose their character as isolated islands of certainty in an ocean of uncertainty, that is, when this faculty is misused to cover the whole ground of the future and to map out a path secured in all directions, they lose their binding power and the whole enterprise becomes self-defeating.”56 This does create one obvious problem though: how to determine that promises have taken over, and that the islands of predictability have turned into vast landmasses? Or can one pick and choose, and only set aside those promises one no longer feels attracted to? Arendt never, as far as I am aware, addressed the issue, and in not doing so provides further ammunition to her critics’ typical charge that she often refused to become sufficiently concrete. In addition to stressing the role of promising, Arendt picked up an even more important lesson from republican Rome about the key role of legislation. Legislation was not, as the Greeks had thought, somehow pre-political (what architecture is to building) 57, but itself a key element of political action.58 Telling is the following statement: “The crucial distinction … is that only for the Romans does legislative activity, and with it the laws themselves, belong to the realm of politics, whereas according to the Greeks, the legislator’s activity was so radically disconnected from the truly political activities and affairs of the citizens within the polis that the law-giver did not even have to be a citizen of the city but could be engaged from outside to perform this task, much like a sculptor or architect commissioned to supply what the city required.”59 Legislation itself, in the meantime, closely seemed to resemble contract. Indeed, Arendt had to maintain as much, in order to be considered consistent. If it is the case that force, domination and rule are not authentically political, then any attempt to bring legislation and 53 See Arendt, The Human Condition, supra note 36, at 244. See, in a somewhat different context, J. Klabbers, ’Constitutionalism Lite’, (2004) 1 International Organizations Law Review 31-58. 55 See Arendt, The Human Condition, supra note 36, at 244. 56 Ibid., at 244. 57 This, however, is the interpretation offered by Brunkhorst, supra note 9, at 125-126. 58 As Taminiaux puts it, for Arendt “the political genius of Rome consisted in remedying the deficiencies of the Greek political views.” See Taminiaux, supra note 45, at 174. 59 See Arendt, Introduction into Politics, supra note 28, at 179. 54 .c H F-XC A N GE H F-XC A N GE c u-tr a c k N y bu lic politics (in the Arendtian sense) together would have to stress the consensual nature of law, all w k to .d o law, including legislation. There is another element of consistency here though. Law, Arendt claims, brings people together; it establishes new relationships between men, perhaps even between former enemies. Yet, in order to do so without lapsing into domination of one sort or another, is has to be balanced towards all parties, and this, it would seem, is an implicit recognition that what matters is not so much the outcome, but the process: the content of the law is somehow less significant than the fact that parties can discuss and debate, and perhaps even agree on things.60 This also is why constitutions are of relevance. As Waldron puts it: “Like a promise, a constitution might appear to limit our freedom; but at the same time it creates something special – the power of a political community – whose importance consists precisely in mitigating the incalculability that human freedom gives rise to.”61 Probably for this reason, she was not at all enthusiastic about the bureaucratic state, in which government would proceed by means of administrative measures taken by faceless bureaucrats and in which, in the end, no one would be held responsible. Whereas for some this might be the ultimate image of a society based on law (the impartial application of higher norms, after all, is an important element of any description of the Rule of Law), Arendt saw it differently: for her, administration and law had fairly little to do with each other: law ought to keep the administration in check, but should not become its handmaiden. In a perfect bureaucracy, Arendt thought, law would be snowed under: “When Hitler said that a day would come in Germany when it would be considered a “disgrace” to be a jurist, he was speaking with utter consistency of his dream of a perfect bureaucracy.”62 What is important to realize though, is that for Arendt, the idea that law ought to keep the administration in check did not stem from any particular concern about the moral content of law; she was highly sceptical about the role of values and would clearly prefer to keep law and morality separate.63 Instead, or so it would seem, her thoughts on law and administration found their source in what she held to be the intimate connection between law and politics. Law is the form that political agreement typically takes, and is also the way in which politics can be protected. Bureaucratic administration, however, is anti-politics: faceless and irresponsible at best, downright totalitarian at worst. Moreover, totalitarian regimes typically invoke a higher 60 Ibid, at 180. Honig makes a similar point about law always being, by definition, the ’mongrel’ result of agreement between strangers. See B. Honig, Democracy and the Foreigner (2001), at 39. 61 See J. Waldron, ’Arendts Constitutional Politics’, in The Cambridge Companion, supra note 17, 201-219, at 212. 62 See H. Arendt, Eichmann in Jerusalem (1964), at 290. The words quoted are part of the postscript, written in 1964. 63 Arendt never, to my knowledge, discussed Fuller’s conception of the internal morality of law: the idea that legal rules bound to be morally acceptable as long as the law respects a handful of basis requirements: it should be published, non-contradictory, non-retro-active, et cetera. In short: proper procedure would lead to morally acceptable results. I would speculate that she would have some sympathy with this approach, but would be reluctant to share Fuller’s clearly non-positivist inspiration. See L. Fuller, The Morality of Law (rev. edn, 1969). m o .c C m o .d o w w w w w C lic k to bu y N O W ! PD O W ! PD c u-tr a c k .c H F-XC A N GE H F-XC A N GE c u-tr a c k N y bu to k lic .c .d o history; their defiance of positive law may, indeed shall, be excused in the name of the greater m w o form of legitimacy to justify themselves: they are executing what they claim to be the laws of C m o .d o w w w w w C lic k to bu y N O W ! PD O W ! PD c u-tr a c k good, the higher value. This in turn means, that totalitarian thought is, in the end, a species of the same genus as the type of thought which holds law to be infused by morality and which, in case of conflict, would not hesitate to give preference to morality: in both cases, a violation of positive law would be justified in the name of some (unverifiable) higher good.64 This, to Arendt, was quite a spectre: hence her insistence that the only law valid among humans, without denying the possible existence of natural law, would be positive law: a lawful government would be “a body politic in which positive laws are needed to translate and realize the immutable ius naturale or the eternal commandments of God into standards of right and wrong. Only in these standards, in the body of positive laws of each country, do the ius naturale or the Commandments of God achieve their political reality.”65 IV Admittedly, Arendt never was very clear on law, in particular on legislation. She lacked the legal background to completely capture some of the technicalities involved, and clearly looked at the law with the eyes of a political theorist, one trained as a philosopher, no less. And yet, in passing and almost without realizing it66, her work contains a few useful scattered insights relating to law in general, and international law in particular. Perhaps her most ‘legal’ works are her report on the trial of Adolf Eichmann and her discussion of desegregation in the American south. At any rate, these two pieces together combine to sketch a subtle picture of the position of law in relation to the world. The book on Eichmann, for all the controversy it sparked, has become justly famous for its shattering analysis of what happens when people stop thinking: Eichmann’s greatest crime, after all, resided not in any monstrous evil intentions, but in his incapacity to think 67; it resided literally in the thoughtlessness with which he could, with a stroke of his pen, condemn thousands 64 The links between liberalism and totalitarianism are explored in M. Halberstam, Totalitarianism and the Modern Conception of Politics (1999). 65 Arendt, The Origins of Totalitarianism, supra note 9, at 464 (emphasis in original). 66 It has been observed that those uninitiated in a certain academic discipline might be well-placed to identify some of its blind spots or even come up with innovations or breakthroughs. See T. Kuhn, The Structure of Scientific Revolutions (2d ed., 1970). 67 In the postscript, she put it in perhaps overly inflammatory terms: “He merely, to put the matter colloquially, never realized what he was doing.” See Arendt, Eichmann, supra note 62, at 287 (italics omitted – JK). The main analysis (e.g. at 48-55) is more subtle though, suggesting that he thought in clichés which, in turn, was partly the result of the totalitarianism prevailing in Nazi Germany. .c H F-XC A N GE H F-XC A N GE c u-tr a c k N y lic k to bu .d o form of punishment that could fit the crime. As early as 1946 (a decade and a half before m o .c C m o .d o to death.68 To Arendt, this presented a problem: for one thing, it would be difficult to think of aw w w w w w C lic k to bu y N O W ! PD O W ! PD c u-tr a c k Eichmann’s trial) she wrote to her erstwhile mentor Karl Jaspers: “The Nazi crimes, it seems to me, explode the limits of the law; and that is precisely what constitutes their monstrousness. For these crimes, no punishment is severe enough. It may well be essential to hang Göring, but it is totally inadequate. That is, this guilt, in contrast to all criminal guilt, oversteps and shatters any and all legal systems.”69 Moreover, and arguably more important still, following the biblical tradition, we tend to think of crime as inevitably resulting from evil intentions. 70 Our criminal laws, in other words, are based on the idea that evil intentions ought to be punished, even to the extent that people may be prosecuted for having attempted to commit crimes, without succeeding. In the absence of mens rea, however, things get decidedly more difficult: our traditions (legal, moral, philosophical) have yet to find a way of dealing with crimes without evil. 71 The point is not, of course, that no such attempts are being made: some branches of the law recognize strict liability, e.g. The point is, rather, that any attempt to fit ‘unintended’ crimes into the framework built upon traditional notions of crime is bound to raise questions, as has become more than visible in the recent attempts to establish international criminal tribunals. 72 Perhaps this means the law should focus on effects rather than intent – this is one possible interpretation of Arendt’s position 73; perhaps the law should at the very least, as recent commentators have suggested, show some humility when attempting to deal with the unspeakable, and realize that judgment may, on occasion, better be left to our moral sensibilities.74 68 The novelist Mary McCarthy, Arendt’s closest friend, suggested that the term “thoughtlessness” no longer carried the meaning which Arendt ascribed to it: McCarthy suggested that “inability to think” would have been better, as “thoughtlessness” could too easily be conflated with “neglect” or “forgetfulness”. See C. Brightman (ed.), Between Friends: The Correspondence of Hannah Arendt and Mary McCarthy 1949-1975 (1995), at 296. 69 See Arendt- Jaspers Correspondence, supra note 18, letter no. 43, August 17, 1946, at 54. 70 As Arendt explained to Jaspers, “… modern crimes are not provided for in the Ten Commandments. Or: the Western tradition is suffering from the preconception that the most evil things human beings can do arise from the vice of selfishness. Yet we know that the greatest evils or radical evil has nothing to do anymore with such humanly understandable, sinful motives.” Arendt-Jaspers Correspondence, supra note 18, letter no. 109, 4 March 1951, at 166. 71 “The trouble with Eichmann was precisely that so many were like him, and that the many were neither perverted nor sadistic, that they were, and still are, terribly and terrifyingly normal… This new type of criminal, who is in actual fact hostis generis humani, commits his crimes under circumstances that make it well-nigh impossible for him to know or to feel that he is doing wrong.” See Arendt, Eichmann, supra note 62, at 276 (emphasis in original). Some of the ramifications are explored in D. Villa, Politics, Philosophy, Terror: Essays on the Thought of Hannah Arendt (1999). 72 See, amongst others, I. Tallgren, ‘The Sensibility and Sense of International Criminal Law’, (2002) 13 European Journal of International Law 561-585. 73 See below, when discussing Eichmann’s punishment. 74 See M. Koskenniemi, ’Faith, Identity, and the Killing of the Innocent: International Lawyers and Nuclear Weapons’, (1997) 10 Leiden Journal of International Law 137-162. .c H F-XC A N GE H F-XC A N GE N y bu to lic .c .d o Eichmann not be said to have acted out of evil intentions as traditionally understood , part of what made his case fairly problematic was also the collective element involved. Eichmann clearly did not act alone; he was a cog (of intensely debated importance) in a larger machine. To what extent then is it fair, or even simply useful, to hold a single individual responsible for atrocities committed by, and in name of, a larger collective? And to what extent is it even possible to single out with some precision the role played by the individual? As Arendt complained, the trial of Eichmann was hardly a trial of Eichmann; instead, Nazi-Germany and the Holocaust were put on trial. 76 Not only did this take something away from the utility of legal proceedings in general, it also, paradoxically perhaps, undermined itself: precisely by focusing on the Holocaust, the proceedings suggested that crimes against humanity was a misnomer: “The crucial point is that although the crime at issue was committed primarily against the Jews, it is in no way limited to the Jews or the Jewish question.” 77 Arendt was also critical about the basis of Israel’s jurisdiction, although she eventually decided that to some extent, debates on the basis of jurisdiction were of no great relevance. Clearly, with Israel having been created only after the Second World War, traditional notions of territorial or national jurisdiction would be difficult to defend. Hence, it is no surprise that the prosecutors sought and found refuge in the idea of universal jurisdiction: Eichmann’s crimes were the sort of crimes outlawed all over the world, and therewith came within the scope of the principle of universal jurisdiction. This, however, Arendt found problematic, as universal jurisdiction taps into the universality of values but, as Arendt had it, totalitarianism had been extremely instrumental in highlighting that values are but fleeting feelings: it is about as easy to change values as it is to change underwear – she somewhat disdainfully spoke of an Ausverkauf der Werte78- and values (the word itself suggests as much) typically make sense only in an instrumental way: in a means-and-ends relationship.79 Values had not been able to resist the Nazis in Germany or, put differently, ordinary Germans had taken their earlier ideas on right and 75 As something of a second best solution, some have argued that he was, regardless of mens rea, a committed antisemite. See, e.g., Y. Lozowick, ‘Malicious Clerks: The Nazi Security Police and the Banality of Evil’, in Hannah Arendt in Jerusalem, supra note 16, 214-223. 76 See Arendt, Eichmann, supra note 62, at 6.This consideration may help explain the reluctance of some of the more powerful states to ratify the Statute of the International Criminal Court. On the oscillation between individual and collective responsibility in this context, see J. Klabbers, ‘The Spectre of International Criminal Justice: Third States and the ICC’, in A. Zimmermann (ed.), International Criminal Law and the Current Development of Public International Law (2003) 49-72. 77 See Arendt-Jaspers Correspondence, supra note 18, letter no. 277, 5 February 1961, at 423. 78 See H. Arendt, ‘The Crisis in Culture: Its Social and Its Political Significance’, in Between Past and Future, supra note 44, 197-226, at 204. 79 I discuss this at some length in J. Klabbers, ‘The Commodification of International Law’, in E. Jouannet & H. Ruiz-Fabri (eds.), International Law: Do We Need It? (Forthcoming). m w 75 o m o C k The Eichmann case also highlighted some other salient legal issues. Not only could lic C c u-tr a c k w w .d o w w w k to bu y N O W ! PD O W ! PD c u-tr a c k .c H F-XC A N GE H F-XC A N GE c u-tr a c k N y bu to k lic .d o behaviour; moreover, Eichmann was tried not so much for having offended against humanity, but for his crimes against the Jews.81 Instead of universal jurisdiction, Arendt would have preferred to base on something of a ‘spiritual jurisdiction’ basis82, and preferably not by an Israeli court but by an international tribunal. There is another element to this: one of the main characteristics of totalitarian regimes, her earlier analysis of totalitarianism had already suggested, was to turn values upside down: what might be recognizable as right and wrong in ordinary circumstances would become unrecognizable under totalitarianism. Faced with regimes intent on taking the ‘human’ out of humans, individuals lose their capacity to tell right from wrong. Under such circumstances, it might be all too easy to designate a few individuals afterwards and hold them responsible for doing something which, at the time, was not recognizably wrong, and may even have been in conformity with everyone’s expectations. It is not to difficult to occupy the moral high ground in ordinary times; in dark times, however, the high ground may be difficult to locate.83 This does not mean Arendt rejected all sorts of judgment altogether; indeed, her later work assigns judgment a central role in political action, and came to do so precisely because of the Eichmann trial. But it is important to realize that judgment should not turn into facile moralization: the spectator (doing the judging) should be able to place himself in the shoes of the accused, and seriously wonder whether he or she would have done things differently. 84 In this light, she also developed ideas (this is where Christianity comes in) on forgiveness: if we are not quite aware of what we are doing, then perhaps forgiveness becomes an option, all the more so as forgiveness facilitates beginning anew, with a clean slate. As Brunkhorst puts it: “Durch Akte des Verzeihens gewinnt die Kommunikation Macht über das Vergangene.” 85 In short, what the Eichmann trial was guilty of, in Arendt’s view, was in being guided by moral outrage. It was not an ordinary criminal trial of an ordinary criminal; the crimes were 80 A useful discussion is E.M. Meade, ‘The Commodification of Values’, in L. May & J. Kohn (eds.), Hannah Arendt Twenty Years Later (1996) 107-126. 81 See Arendt, Eichmann, supra note 62, at 261. 82 She captured this under the heading of territorial jurisdiction, but with a characteristic twist on the meaning of territory: “It relates not so much, and not primarily to a piece of land as to the space between individuals in a group whose members are bound to, and at the same time separated and protected from, each other by all kinds of relationships, based on a common language, religion, a common history, customs, and laws… No State of Israel would ever have come into being if the Jewish people had not created and maintained its own specific in-between space throughout the long centuries of dispersion, that is, prior to the seizure of its old territory.” See Arendt, Eichmann, supra note 62, at 263. 83 A thoughtful discussion is D. Barnouw, Visible Spaces: Hannah Arendt and the German-Jewish Experience (1990), esp. ch. 4. 84 See Arendt, Kant’s Political Thought, supra note 22. 85 See Brunkhorst, supra note 9, at 119. In English: “Communication gains power over the past through acts of forgiveness” (translation mine – JK). o w .c m C m o .d o wrong and replaced them by new ones. 80 Values then are an unreliable guide to human w w w w w C lic k to bu y N O W ! PD O W ! PD c u-tr a c k .c H F-XC A N GE H F-XC A N GE c u-tr a c k N y bu to k lic .d o difficult to fit Eichmann’s acts within the framework of criminal law to begin with. Precisely, or m o .c C m o .d o extraordinary, to such an extent that no real precedent existed86, and to such an extent that it was w w w w w w C lic k to bu y N O W ! PD O W ! PD c u-tr a c k so it seems, because the law was hardly able to deal with the crime under review, refuge was sought in morality: in claiming that universal values had been transgressed, in claiming that the idea of non-retroactive application of law was not all that relevant given the circumstances.87 Yet, Arendt felt, to rely on morality was wrong. A trial should be a legal proceeding, and law and morality are best kept separate.88 Indeed, politics, for her (and therewith law as well), had little to do with morality, with ‘doing the right thing’. 89 In fact, doing the right thing might often prove counterproductive, as was most clearly illustrated by the French revolution which, inspired by its attempts to alleviate the plight of the poor, ended up a nightmare of terror. Politics is not about right or wrong and, by extension, law is not about right and wrong either. Instead, politics is about common care for the world, is about being together and living together and finding common answers and solutions while respecting human plurality. There simply is no place for moral considerations in such a scheme, mostly because morality is a set of internal standards.90 The moral person might decide not to engage in activity X because, she feels, it might be immoral to do so. It does not follow, however, that this same person can prohibit others from not engaging in the same activity, or punish them if they do, unless those internal standards have become externalized, by agreement, into law. Those moral standards on their own might be all too easily subject to change and whim, and thus not be terribly reliable guides (in the external world, at any rate) for action.91 Arendt’s problem with morality was not so much that she denied that values could be universal, but rather that she felt them to be too fragile to serve any public purpose. 86 Nuremberg was not much help, as the IMT had focussed on the decision-makers and had paid much attention to illegal aggression, almost ignoring the Holocaust. Yet, Eichmann’s trial was, really, the trial of the Holocaust. For a brilliant analysis of these and other cases, see L. Douglas, The Memory of Judgment: Making Law and History in the Trials of the Holocaust (2001). 87 Akehurst once put the same thought well in respect of the Nuremberg proceedings: ”… anyone who thinks that justice demanded the acquittal of the men convicted at Nuremberg has a very peculiar idea about justice.” See M. Akehurst, A Modern Introduction to International Law (6th edn., 1987), at 280. 88 “The purpose of a trial is to render justice, and nothing else; even the noblest of ulterior motives … can only detract from the law’s main business: to weigh the charges brought against the accused, to render judgment, and to mete out due punishment.” See Arendt, Eichmann, supra note 62, at 253. 89 By way of illustration, she could subscribe to the view that Danish resistance against Nazism and for equal treatment of the Jews stemmed from political instincts, not from humanitarian sentiments. See Arendt, Eichmann, supra note 62, at 179. 90 It is for this reason, most likely, that she was not too convinced that Kant had been all that serious in his political writings, including the celebrated Zum ewigen frieden, which she held to be characterized by an “ironical tone”. See Arendt, Kant’s Political Thought, supra note 22, at 7. 91 In addition, there is a serious problem involved in relying on morality while the average ‘deskmurderer’ does not feel in charge in any way: given such a sentiment of powerlessness, the individual moralities of those involved are not likely to be ‘activated’. I derive the point from L. May, ‘Socialization and Institutional Evil’, in May & Kohn (eds.), note 80 above, 83-105. .c H F-XC A N GE H F-XC A N GE N y bu to lic w .d o being put on trial as such – not even with him receiving the death penalty. She felt that his trial o m o .c m C k Somewhat surprisingly at first sight, Arendt had no particular problem with Eichmann lic C c u-tr a c k w w .d o w w w k to bu y N O W ! PD O W ! PD c u-tr a c k rightfully should have been done by an international tribunal and on the basis of existing international law, but did not reject him being tried to begin with. Likewise, she supported the verdict of the death penalty although, it seems, without the liberal gloss some put on it, suggesting that penalizing war crimes and crimes against humanity might help deter or even might help create an accurate historical record. Instead, for her, the punishment was its own justification: Eichmann’s crimes had been unspeakable, and therefore he deserved to die. This is puzzling of course: if she truly felt his greatest crime had been his thoughtlessness, then this would hardly add up to deserving the death penalty. One way to make sense of her position, though, is to suggest that in applauding Eichmann’s death penalty, she ended up judging him by the effects of his actions rather than by his intentions. And that, all of a sudden, seems rather consistent with her general views that criminal law, with its focus on mens rea, has not been able to accommodate crimes such as those of which Eichmann was accused. Or, if not consistent, then at least compatible: where mens rea is absent but the effects are nonetheless atrocious, perhaps it becomes justifiable to take the level of atrocity into account. This may also account for her earlier comment, in a letter to Jaspers, that it might well be essential to hang Göring.92 While she was happy with Eichmann being subjected to law (or would have been had the law been more appropriate, perhaps), she was unhappy with the attempt, in the US, to force desegregation of schools by legal means. This, she notoriously found93, was aiming to use the legal process to make a political point and, most ironically, doing so over the backs of the most immediate victims: the black school children who all of a sudden were taken out of their familiar environments and thrust into white settings: “…this was to burden children, black and white, with the working out of a problem which adults for generations have confessed themselves unable to solve.”94 The point Arendt tried to make, it seems, was this: discrimination is a social phenomenon, and as such, there is nothing particularly wrong with it, as long as it remains limited to the social sphere: after all, it is merely a matter of making distinctions. Its opposite, equality, has no role to play in social matters, but is a fundamental political principle: “…equality not only has its origin in the body politic; its validity is clearly restricted to the 92 I am indebted to Larry May for his help in getting me to articulate this. Her piece on Little Rock has met with truck loads of criticism. Even those who are fairly sympathetic to Arendt in general suggest she was dead wrong in opposing the desegregation orders; that doing so clearly was a mistake. See, e.g., J. Bohman, ‘The Moral Costs of Political Pluralism: The Diemmas of Difference and Equality in Arendt’s ‘Refelctions on Little Rock’’, in May & Kohn (eds.), note 80 above, 53-80. An exception is the more positive appraisal in J. Kristeva, Hannah Arendt (2001, Guberman trans.), at 113-114. 94 See Arendt, Reflections on Little Rock, supra note 5, at 236. 93 .c H F-XC A N GE H F-XC A N GE c u-tr a c k N y bu to k lic .d o matter, on issues which are not strictly political but nonetheless belong to the public domain m o .c C m o .d o public realm.”95 In other words: where discrimination appears in all matters political or, for thatw w w w w w C lic k to bu y N O W ! PD O W ! PD c u-tr a c k (think, e.g., of seating arrangements in public transport), it should be fought tooth and nail. In social affairs, however, discrimination is perfectly at ease, and it would be fruitless to fight it: people should be at liberty to invite whoever they want to their birthday parties, the open question that remains being the question what exactly counts as private settings, and what as pubic settings. What remains worth fighting though (she called this a “crucial point”96, highlighting how relevant she thought it was) is the legal enforcement of discrimination. Surely, having a law on the books which holds that black children are only allowed to attend black schools is wrong. Yet, equally wrong would it be to force these same children to attend white schools against their wishes or those of their parents. This would turn education from the social matter that it inherently is into something else: as soon as governments aim to control education and take it out of the realm of free association, one descends down a slippery slope towards the tyrannical: the rights of parents to decide where to send their children to school “are challenged only by dictatorships.”97 The more general point to emerge is that her thoughts on law seemed to revolve around the idea of law as a guarantor of the political or, perhaps better, as a guarantor of the dividing lines between the public, the private and the social, the latter embodying something of an intermediary between public and private. The political needed to be protected by means of legislation: a positive obligation, to adopt the language of human rights advocacy. With respect to the social (and by the extension, it would seem, the private), something else would apply: “While the government has no right to interfere with the prejudices and discriminatory practices of society, it has not only the right but the duty to make sure that these practices are not legally enforced.”98 It is one thing to strive to get rid of laws prohibiting children from attending schools they wish to attend; this is something the law is well-equipped to do. It is something else entirely though to try to force children to attend schools they may not wish to attend – the law ought not to be used for this sort of purpose. As she had written almost a decade earlier, “… the greatness, 95 Ibid., at 237. Ibid., at 235-236. The crucial distinction between a social phenomenon and its legal enforcement would appear to have been too subtle for some of Arendt’s more vocal critics. 97 Ibid., at 245. 98 Ibid., at 240. Note, incidentally, that Arendt was fairly sanguine about the role of prejudice: prejudices are useful in everyday life, as abridgments of past experiences, as long as the bear any resemblance to those past practices. See Arendt, Introduction into Politics, supra note 35. The idea of prejudices as useful abridgments is echoed (inadvertently it seems) in later jurisprudential work on the properties of rules, suggesting that rules release people from the obligation to make their own decisions on the numerous issues confronting them on an every day basis, such as how fast to drive, on which side of the road to drive, et cetera. See in particular Frederick Schauer, Playing by the Rules (1991). 96 .c H F-XC A N GE H F-XC A N GE c u-tr a c k N y bu to k lic .c .d o never what one should do.” Arendt’s pure politics, it seems, was accompanied by a fairly pure law. Law might well be inspired by moral concerns but, in the end, should be kept separate from it. Law might also well be inspired by lofty social motives – alleviating the plight of the poor, improving education for all – but, Arendt felt, would not be quite suitable for reaching social goals. To those familiar with the modern welfare state, this may seem curious, as much legislation in the welfare state is (or used to be, perhaps) precisely, social legislation, aimed to achieve certain social goals. Yet, the demise of the welfare state (its relative failure) would not have come as a surprise to Arendt, for two related reasons: the welfare state, with its concomitant need for the application of technical and detailed regulations, would invite the sort of faceless bureaucracy she abhorred, with administration taking the place of politics. Second, witness her Little Rock piece, she would be sceptical about its chances of achieving its goals without slipping uncomfortably into bureaucracy: one should not expect the law to accomplish what has proved unattainable in the body politic, and social issues are almost by definition unsuitable for law – and for politics. That leaves us with a bit of a puzzle for, as many of her critics have suggested, such things as the duration of the working week, or the level of education of national minorities, social as they are, would seem natural candidates for political debate and discussion and, eventually, for some kind of legislation as well. In the absence of social (or socio-economic) issues, there is not much left for politics to be about, and neither, it would seem to follow, would there be a great need for law. That is, in itself, perhaps a salutary sentiment: not to have all sorts of laws on the books that, by definition, will prove unsuccessful; the insight that not everything can be subjected to legal regulation is, no doubt, a useful insight; whether all socio-economic issues can be excluded is a different question altogether. V The above has already suggested that Arendt continues to be of relevance for international politics (in fact, it is only recently that her relevance to international relations has started to be explored 100), and to international law as well. Human rights theory may derive useful insights from her thoughts on the locally embedded nature of at least the classical political rights (the right to vote and the right to be elected), which has some impact on the universal nature of human rights. While her thoughts on the “right to have rights” have been thoroughly criticized 99 See Arendt, The Origins of Totalitarianism, supra note 9, at 467. See generally Lang and Williams (eds.), supra note 12. 100 m w 99 o but also the perplexity of laws in free societies is that they only tell what one should not, but C m o .d o w w w w w C lic k to bu y N O W ! PD O W ! PD c u-tr a c k .c H F-XC A N GE H F-XC A N GE c u-tr a c k N y bu lic for ignoring the internationalization of human rights protection and for not being able to definew k to the status of this basic right to have rights (it could hardly be a positivist right)101, the critique .d o m o .c C m o .d o w w w w w C lic k to bu y N O W ! PD O W ! PD c u-tr a c k seems to bypass Arendt’s point. For, in Arendt’s view, politics was the only way in which humans could come to full fruition, could fully develop their potential in the public realm. 102 And if this is so, then public happiness comes to depend on a right to participate in political life, both through being to vote and to run for office.103Yet, as domestic legislations show, this still depends on recognition through positivist law: these political rights are still locally legislated. 104 In addition, Arendt’s scepticism with respect to the possible contribution of law to social or economic goals suggests that one should not be overly optimistic about changing the plight of people by means of adding ever greater numbers of economic and social rights, and it is quite possibly no coincidence that these rights, to the extent they materialize at all, tend to materialize in highly procedural fashion: social and economic rights tend to be re-conceptualized as bundles of procedural rights, for, as Arendt would no doubt acknowledge, it is only in this way that the law can accommodate them.105 By the same token, her study of the Eichmann trial still offers much valuable insights to those engaged in the creation of international criminal law. At the very least, one could argue, international criminal lawyers ought to be aware that assertions of universal jurisdiction are not always unproblematic; that it might be difficult at times to disentangle individual culpability and group responsibility106 and, perhaps most of all, that neither political crimes (some emanations of terrorism comes to mind, as do large scale human rights violations) nor what Arendt famously (or infamously) termed the ‘banality of evil’, can easily be captured in traditional categories of criminal law. 107 Indeed, inspired by such considerations, Drumbl has coined the term ‘law of atrocity’ and fleshed out some of its characteristics.108 101 See in particular Brunkhorst, supra note 9. Perhaps Arendt-inspired, Douzinas has noted that human rights are injunctions to people to love each other. This, however, cannot work: one cannot be ordered to love thy neighbour. See C. Douzinas, The End of Human Rights (2000). Arendt would add, moreover, that love belongs properly to the private sphere, not to the public realm. 103 It is surely no coincidence that convicted felons are often disenfranchised: they are deemed to be not worthy of political participation, affecting the “purity of the ballot box”. For a critical discussion, see N.V. Demleitner, `Continuing Payment on One’s Debt to Society: The German Model of Felon Disenfranchisement as an Alternative´, (2000) 84 Minnesota Law Review 753-804. 104 Even within the European Union, the right to vote in national elections is reserved to nationals only; permanent residents are still not granted the right to take part in national elections, although they may vote and run for office in municipalities and for the European Parliament. See Article 19 TEC. 105 I have argued elsewhere that much the same applies to the right to self-determination. See J. Klabbers, ‘The Right to be Taken Seriously: Self-Determination in International Law’, (2006) 28 Human Rights Quarterly 186-206. 106 On the connections between the two see, e.g., L. May, Sharing Responsibility (1992). 107 A fine study along similar lines is M. Osiel, Mass Atrocity, Ordinary Evil, and Hannah Arendt: Criminal Consciousness in Argentina’s Dirty War (2001). 108 See M. Drumbl, ’Collective Violence and Individual Punishment: The Criminality of Mass Atrocity’, (2005) 99 Northwestern University Law Review 539-610. 102 .c H F-XC A N GE H F-XC A N GE N y bu to to bu y N O W ! PD O W ! PD k lic .c .d o insights regarding constitutionalism in international law. This currently popular notion comes, m o o c u-tr a c k C m C lic k What is perhaps somewhat less obvious though is that Arendt may also offer some useful w w w .d o w w w c u-tr a c k roughly, in two shapes. First, some discuss, in more or less limited fashion, the constitutionalization or possible constitutionalization of individual international organizations. This occurs, most obviously, with respect to the EU109, but also takes place with respect to other organizations, most notably the WTO perhaps (if nothing else, this signifies considerable unhappiness with the acts and styles of the WTO110). Typically (if not invariably), such studies end up suggesting that the organization at issue should be (and is) subjected to general international law; should be (and is) subjected to judicial review, and should be (and is) subjected to human rights. Much of this is based on the idea, more fully developed in the second strand to be discussed, that there are universal, more or less absolute values in international politics, which ought not to be cast aside, not even by international organizations and for the sake of international cooperation.111 The second strand is more ambitious still, and insists that the international legal order as a whole is undergoing some process of constitutionalization. Based on the notion that humanity shares a few universal values, all action on the international plane should be judged in light of those values. These have overcome the debilitating role of state consent in their transmogrification from morality to law, and take the form of jus cogens norms and erga omnes obligations. As possibly its most enthusiastic protagonist puts it, the international constitutional order denotes “a system in which the different national, regional and functional (sectoral) constitutional regimes form the building blocks of the international community (´international polity´) that is underpinned by a core value system common to all communities and embedded in a variety of legal structures for its enforcement.”112 Those core values, in turn, are universally shared, and have acquired a special hierarchical standing, and would obviously be norms with “strong ethical underpinnings”113 such as human rights and international criminal law, but may also come to encompass norms such as sustainable development, democracy, and possibly even trade liberalization. 114 109 The best comprehensive discussion remains J.H.H. Weiler, The Constitution of Europe (1999). For a sustained discussion, see D. Cass, The Constitutionalization of the World Trade Organization: Legitimacy, Democracy, and Community in the International Trading System (2005). 111 A different, more modest strand, would hold that instead of subjecting international organizations to constitutionalization pur sang, it might be more advisable to use the label constitutionalization to describe a process of increasing control – legal and political – over the acts of international organizations: a constitutionalist paradigm rather than the traditionally dominant paradigm of functionalism. For a discussion, see J. Klabbers, ‘Introduction’, in J. Klabbers (ed.), International Organizations (2005). For a more concrete elaboration, see J. Klabbers, ‘Checks and Balances in the Law of International Organizations’, (2006) 12 Ius Gentium (forthcoming). 112 See E. de Wet, ‘The International Constitutional Order’, (2006) 55 International and Comparative Law Quarterly 51-76, at 53. 113 Ibid., at 57. 114 Ibid., at 62-63. 110 .c H F-XC A N GE H F-XC A N GE N y bu to .c lic .d o the first), for a variety of reasons. On a superficial level, she would probably hold that neither of m o o c u-tr a c k C m C lic k Arendt would, no doubt, be fairly critical of such propositions (the second more so thanw w w .d o w w w k to bu y N O W ! PD O W ! PD c u-tr a c k the values singled out in constitutionalization debates are self-evident as to their contents, and perhaps for the better.115 The one possible exception would be democracy but democracy, she suggested, was difficult to reconcile with, e.g., respect for human rights, or review of political action by courts. Indeed, many others have made the same point, often referred to as the ‘counter-majoritarian difficulty’: what if a democratic decision is taken to cast an established human right aside? One either respects the democratic nature of the decision (in which case the human right turns out to be nothing more than contingent), or one keeps the right in place, therewith undermining democracy. One might even go so far as to posit a tension between constitutionalism itself (as government constrained by law) and democracy (as government by the people).116 Hence, lumping together a number of values and proclaiming the arrival of a constitutional order comprising them would fail to convince. Still, there are a few other points worth addressing. The first of these is that, as hinted at above, Arendt would not be able to muster much enthusiasm about speaking in terms of values to begin with. To her mind, the very term value denoted a means-ends type of rationality: something is of value with a view to accomplishing something else: indeed, being closely connected to the term exchange-value says it all, really, and this in turn provokes two questions. First, what then is it that the constitutional values are expected to accomplish? And second, this higher value (for it can only be higher value) would itself have to be grounded somehow and, ironically, remain subject to yet higher values, in what can only be an infinite regression. There is, in the end, nothing absolute about values; they are by definition relative; and if they were absolute, they would be heavily competing with each other. Second, there is the moralization associated with thinking in terms of values: those values, with their “strong ethical underpinnings”, suggest and infusion of morality into law. Arendt, as noted, would favour keeping law and politics separate, which not only casts some doubts on the sources of the supposed universal values but, what is more, might also point into a different direction. It is not, of course, the case that Arendt rejected any role for morality: she would readily accept that people can “do the right thing” simply for the sake of “doing the right thing”. But instead of capturing this in values, it is not implausible to suggest that, without being nostalgic, she would rather resurrect Machiavelli’s old notion of virtù to give effect to moral 115 She was sceptical about any truth claims (other than factual truths) in politics, for a claim that something is true tends to be an intolerant claim: it cannot tolerate discussion, and therewith stifles political debate. See H. Arendt, ‘Truth and Politics’, in Between Past and Future, supra note 44 , 227-264. 116 For a useful discussion, see F. Michelman, Brennan and Democracy (1999). .c H F-XC A N GE H F-XC A N GE c u-tr a c k N y bu to k lic .c .d o would bother Arendt. Additionally, the absolutism of the full-fledged constitutionalist mode would probably have her worried. One cannot argue with or about absolutes, yet without positing the world community’s core values as absolutes, the entire constitutionalism project would dissipate. And then there is the practical matter that such a world community would almost by definition lead to centralization, to something akin to a world government (in itself something to worry about118) and most likely one without any real kind of politics, where the application of the posited core values ends up in the hands of bureaucrats, applying norms coming out of nowhere, based not on agreement between political actors but on someone’s conception of what the world needs, and without any system of accountability. She would have been more sympathetic to the idea of judicial review, provided that the idea would remain limited to testing, indeed, whether legislation and administrative action had come about in the right manner, and provided there would be a clear constitutional mandate. She said kind words about the US Supreme Court which, while powerless, exercised great authority, and did so in a purely legal function.119 While she does not seem to have given the matter much attention, it seems likely that she would not be overly optimistic about the capacities of courts to either protect the political process or to function as a useful check on the exercise of political power.120 And as noted earlier, the idea of getting judges to solve political debates or fix political outcomes under the heading of judicial review would run into serious difficulties; and it is of course a sobering thought that often, this is precisely why judicial review is being advocated in the international law literature on constitutionalization.121 As an alternative, and in light of her general (neo-)republican outlook122, it is likely that for Arendt, constitutionalism would take a more modest form, emphasizing a more or less proceduralist outlook.123 Starting from the premise of human plurality and the crucial importance 117 Machiavelli’s virtù relates to virtuosity, in particular in performance. To Arendt, in turn, participation in politics was largely a matter of performance, of excelling in public, and would involve such things as courage. Indeed, freedom itself (the meaning of politics) would involve virtù. This would, tentatively, seem to establish some link between politics and morality (courage, after all, having a certain moral quality). Hints to this effect can be found in Arendt, What is Freedom, supra note 44, at 153. 118 See her essay on Jaspers, supra note 11: “The solidarity of mankind may well turn out to be an unbearable burden…” (at 83). 119 See Arendt, On Revolution, supra note 34, esp. at 200. 120 A useful historical illustration of how 17th century English courts time and again sided with the King, against Parliament, is A. Tomkins, Our Republican Constitution (2005). 121 For an overview, see J. Klabbers, ‘Straddling Law and Politics: Judicial Review in International Law’, in R.St.J. MacDonald & D.M. Johnston (eds.), Towards World Constitutionalism (2005) 809-835. 122 Arendt is plausibly sketched as a republican of sorts in Canovan, supra note 30. For a spirited defence of republicanism (and, not accidentally, of Machiavelli), almost amounting to a manifesto, see M. Viroli, Republicanism (2002, Shugaar trans.) 123 This derives in part from Klabbers, ’Constitutionalism Lite’, supra note 54, and Klabbers, Straddling Law and Politics, supra note 121. m w 117 o sentiments: morality and law being different things, their conflation under the guise of values C m o .d o w w w w w C lic k to bu y N O W ! PD O W ! PD c u-tr a c k .c H F-XC A N GE H F-XC A N GE c u-tr a c k N y bu to k of political debate and action, in combination with respect for different viewpoints and opinions, w lic .d o one would hardly expect her to be enthusiastic about absolutist value claims. Instead, she would, m o .c C m o .d o w w w w w C lic k to bu y N O W ! PD O W ! PD c u-tr a c k one imagines, advocate rights and possibilities relating to political participation. That is well reconcilable with a rights-based focus, as for instance Jeremy Waldron has suggested: the political process requires protection by means of political rights, and political debates are best left to political processes. 124 Obviously, the right to vote and run for office are of relevance here, but so are such rights as those relating to freedom of expression and association. VI Reading Arendt can be quite infuriating. As her critics have noticed, the writing, however elegant, is not always lucid, and is definitely not always systematic. Indeed, as Canovan notes, she never set out to be systematic. Writing, for Arendt, was not so much a process of communication, but rather an attempt at understanding things and, more fundamentally, she was suspicious of thought systems to begin with: “Authentic political thought necessarily arose, she thought, out of real political events, and had to be rethought in response to them.”125 Indeed, it is fully possible that her thoughts on the right to have rights, to take one example, emerged not only from being stateless herself but from also seeing stateless or near-stateless Spanish fighters, having helped liberate occupied France in 1944, being threatened by the new De Gaulle regime with having to enlist in the Foreign Legion or report to mandatory labour battalions. 126 Either way, her attitude to political thought as responsive to actual events may help explain why she wrote, in contrast to many political theorists, a good deal about current events: these were, in the end, the heart and soul of politics: never fully stable, always fluid. At her best, though, Arendt’s writings are thought-provoking and immensely powerful. She was opinionated (in the good sense of the term), extremely erudite and outspoken, and will offer the receptive international lawyer much food for thought on a variety of topics, including issues not or hardly covered in the present piece, from the utility of truth and reconciliation commissions to the role of non-state actors, and from the use of force to the study of federalism. 127 Infuriating and frustrating as her writings may on occasion be, it also has a strangely seductive quality, in part no doubt the result of her refusal to be pigeonholed. The 124 See J. Waldron, Law and Disagreement (1999); see also his The Dignity of Legislation (1999); for a brief overview, see Waldron, Arendt’s Constitutional Politics, supra note 61. 125 See Canovan, supra note 30, at 5. 126 She published a comment on this in German in 1944 under the title ‘Die Entrechteten und Entwürdigten’, which is cited, in relevant part, in S. Courtine-Denamy, Three Women in Dark Times (2000, Goshgarian trans.), at 185. 127 On non-state actors, see, e.g., A.F. Lang, Jr., ‘Governance and Political Action: Hannah Arendt on Global Political Protest’, in Lang & Williams (eds.), supra note 12, 179-198; on use of force, see, e.g., J. Klabbers, ‘Off Limits? International Law and the Excessive Use of Force’, (2006) 7 Theoretical Inquiries in Law 59-80. .c H F-XC A N GE H F-XC A N GE c u-tr a c k N y bu to k consequence (and this is something to celebrate rather than to deplore) is that Arendt is best used w lic .d o not as a fount of wisdom, as providing the right answer to any concrete political problem, but rather as a source for inspiration. Since Arendt did not care too much about being systematic and perhaps even enjoyed being difficult to pigeonhole during her lifetime, there would be something inherently paradoxical (and therewith hampering professional commentators) in trying to systematically address her legal and political thought and turn it into an –ism. There is, to fall back on Arendt’s own terms, something inherently paradoxical in trying to frame and systematize the thoughts of the one thinker who advocated thinking without banisters. 128 128 This is how she herself described her attitude as an independent thinker, as quoted in Canovan, supra note 30, at 278. The German phrase ‘Denken ohne Geländer’ is sometimes also translated, somewhat less evocatively, as ‘thinking without railings’. See, e.g., U. Ludz (ed.), Hannah Arendt and Martin Heidegger: Letters 1925-1975 (2004, Shields trans.), letter no. 120, 12 March 1970, at 167. m o .c C m o .d o w w w w w C lic k to bu y N O W ! PD O W ! PD c u-tr a c k .c