Karel Kleisner and Timo Maran 30 Visual communication in animals: Applying a Portmannian and Uexküllian biosemiotic approach Abstract: In modern biology, the appearance of organisms is largely understood as an adaptation serving the survival function. Here we advance a biosemiotic perspective inspired by the works of Adolf Portmann and Jakob von Uexküll. From this perspective, the visual dimension of every living being can be understood as a representation of the evolutionary experience of a species. In the study of animal displays, biosemiotics focuses on the qualitative perspective in both the logic behind the emergence of such signs as well as their perception and interpretation by perceiving animals. In this study, we claim that convergence of the animal surface patterns that stem developmentally from different ontogenetic precursors should be taken as evidence for congruence in biological meaning. As a specific example, the article discusses the development, perception, and evolution of semantic organs such as eyespots on butterfly wings and vertebrate eyes. 1 Diversity of visual communication in animals Studying visual communication in non-human animals always means taking a comparative perspective. Visual communication channels, i.e. organs of perception and expression, remain invariant in human visual communication; but between differing species, the specifics and effects of these can differ to a large extent. And so to focus on any singular trait, or even to build up a typology based on any single criterion, produces a simplified picture of animal visual communication. For this reason we claim in this chapter that the Portmannian and Uexküllian biosemiotic approach is potentially useful in studying animal visual communication as it provides a holistic understanding by incorporating several causal mechanisms, taking the specifics of living systems into account, and also including within it the animal’s subjective perspective. On a purely physical level, the range of perceivable light-waves differs between taxonomical groups: many birds and insects are able to perceive ultraviolet patterns whereas many reptiles sense infrared wavelengths. This means that human perception of the visual communication of other species may be biased due to our own physiological capacities. For instance, many differences or similarities that are significant to the members of other species remain outside our visual range. Thus, we do not sense the different coloring of the head cap of the male and female blue tits in UV, which is an important marker in their interspecific communication (Andersson et al. 1998), and it is easy for us to distinguish between Brought to you by | De Gruyter / TCS Authenticated | 66.31.11.14 Download Date | 5/6/14 7:27 PM 660 Karel Kleisner and Timo Maran the colors of orchid red helleborine and bellflowers, which are undistinguishable for certain bees for whom these form a mimicry of resemblance (Nilsson 1983). In addition to the simple range of wavelength, visual perception may differ for different animal species in many other aspects. It appears that we humans, as well as many other primates, have exceptionally good color vision when compared to other mammals, whereas other mammalian taxa, cats in particular, may have sharper eyesight in low-light conditions. Also, the ways in which animal eyes organize the color information can be rather different. Our visual apparatus consists of three types of retinal cells that distinguish between base colors – green, blue, and red – and renders all hues as a combination of these; birds have four types of color receptors (one of which is suited to perceive UV wavelengths) and accordingly, for birds, four base colors exist. When the many evolutionary pathways and the variety of anatomies of visual perception organs from simple unicellular structures capable of distinguishing light from non-light to the compound eyes of insects which have a large field of vision but relatively low resolution (though even here there are exceptions, as for instance dragonflies) are added to all the varieties of eyes in vertebrates, one can see that taking the comparative perspective to animal visual communication is a real necessity. Looking at visual signals themselves, one can distinguish between several types based on a formal criterion. One possibility would be to pose the question: how do colors emerge? This would allow a distinction between the visual signals of emitted colors (as in fireflies Photuris) and reflected colors, whereas the latter type could be further divided between embodied visual signals, those that exist within an animal’s body structure, and detached signals, which would include territorial markings, tracks, nests, feathers, and other environmental signs of the animal’s presence. Based on the physical mechanisms of color generation, embodied visual signals could in turn be divided between physical colors (blue, green, and metallic tones that are caused by color diffraction in the microstructures of body integuments) and pigmental colors (mostly brown, black, yellow and red tones that are caused by selective light absorption in chemical compounds). Finally, specific body structures exist through which messages of visual communication are expressed in animals, and which vary greatly (including outgrowths, spikes, outer ears, horns, feather structures, tales, among others). In addition to such purely formal description, any analysis of specific cases of visual communication in animals should pay attention to the spatial or temporal organization of the signals of a given species. Depending on taxonomical group, colors in animals can form patterns and specific indexical signs, for example the pale “follow-me” sign below the tail of many ungulates. Visual signals can also form repertoires of behavioral acts with a communicative function, e.g., the facial gestures or body postures of many group-living birds and mammals that are depicted in ethology as ethograms. In temporal means, visual signals can form specific sequences of ritual behavior, e.g., “wedding dances” and other forms of Brought to you by | De Gruyter / TCS Authenticated | 66.31.11.14 Download Date | 5/6/14 7:27 PM Visual communication in animals 661 courtship behavior. In their full species-specific complexity, animal signals can be dynamically employed in dialogic or polylogic encounters between the members of one and the same or different species, and they can be described as conveying meaning or function based on codes that organize specific acts of communication. A well-known example of spatially and temporally complex visual communication systems in animals is claw movements in signaler crabs, which are used in speciesspecific sexual and territorial communication. Another much studied case is the “dance language” honeybees use to communicate information about the position of a food source or other resource, relative to the bee-hive and the position of the sun. In its particulars, this appears to be a well-organized communication system that allows the conveyance of referential information about environmental objects (thus matching much of the criteria specific to human language e.g., Hockett 1960). Concerning the function of visual signals of animal communication, contemporary evolutionary biology mostly tries to establish that specific animal signals have selection value for the given animal species, thus contributing to its survival. Such outcome may relate to the effect of natural selection, for instance where the warning coloration of an insect species announces that it is unpalatable or poisonous. Alternatively, such an outcome can be related to sexual selection, as where vivid red and yellow colors in the plumage of the males of some passerine birds supposedly reveal their health and diet to the females. Given the variety of visual communication systems in animals, the function or meaning of a particular message can also be much more concrete. For instance, the German theoretical biologist Günter Tembrock (1971: 56) has described the basic categories of meaning that are transmitted in intraspecific communication as follows: (1) identity of the sender (species, group, age, sex, and individuality); (2) motivation (physiological status such as hunger and behavioral status such as intention to fly); (3) other living beings (dangerous and non-dangerous animals), things, territory, food, meteorological conditions. To present a typology does not mean to imply that all the colors in animal body surfaces necessarily have meaning or function. It is plausible to assume that there are also many aspects in animal body coloration that have no special meaning or function. In other cases, it is more adequate to talk about meaning complexes that can include several actualized or potential meanings, as we are about to show in the following semiotic excursion into animal appearances. 2 Introducing Portmannian and Uexküllian biosemiotics Biosemiotics generally studies the semiotic processes (e.g. recognition, communication, and interpretation) that are considered to exist in a variety of forms down to the simplest living organisms and to the lowest levels of biological organization. Brought to you by | De Gruyter / TCS Authenticated | 66.31.11.14 Download Date | 5/6/14 7:27 PM 662 Karel Kleisner and Timo Maran Biosemiotics can focus on codes and coding in biological systems, biological functions of semiotic processes, typology and evolution of sign usage, etc. (see Kull et al. 2008). Compared to mainstream Darwinian biology, the biosemiotic and especially Portmannian-Uexküllian biosemiotic approach is closer to many treatments of visual communication in the humanities and social sciences. This is because Portmannian-Uexküllian biosemiotics combines structural descriptions of the ecologies, physiologies, and development of animals with a subject-centered focus. Many of Uexküll’s basic concepts such as building plan (Bauplan), form-shaping rule, functional cycle (Funktionskreis), and counterpoint (Kontrapunkt) can be interpreted as tools of structural description; and both Portmann and Uexküll emphasize the subjective perspective by treating animals as perceiving, expressing, and communicating creatures (e.g. Uexküll’s analysis of animal Umwelten and Portmann’s concepts of self-representation and inwardness). It can be assumed that Portmannian-Uexküllian biosemiotics is more capable at describing qualitative aspects of the specific appearances in animal species. The Swiss zoologist Adolf Portmann (1897–1982, born and died in Basel) belongs in any list of the most original thinkers of twentieth-century biology. His originality was not founded by any new radical invention, but rather by elaborating the classical ideas of German romantic science. Portmann’s ideas were highly influenced by a tradition of continental speculative philosophy; perhaps this is why, with a few exceptions, philosophers and social scientists have appreciated his work, rather than biologists (see Gould 1977: 349). Adolf Portmann understood organic form as something of value in itself which should be studied as such. In his thinking, the external surface of an organism has its own formal value and a certain kind of autonomy over other life-sustaining functions. He was convinced that this outermost aspect of an organism informs us about the innermost dimensions as these surface manifestations reflect the inner self-experience of every living being. He stated that the only way to get closer to understanding the existence of other living creatures is by a sensitive interpretation of the outermost organic surfaces (Portmann 1960a, 1960b, 1965, 1969: 315). Though Portmann’s views may seem part of German idealistic biology, his approach does take animal appearance into account as a whole, making it very suitable for studying the complex visual patterns of an animal.1 This tradition of biology was common in German intellectual space, i.e. besides Germany it was especially common in Switzerland, Holland, Austria, the former Czechoslovakia, Estonia, and St. Petersburg in Russia, but some of its adherents also lived in France and England. Idealistic biology crystallized in the works of German Naturphilosophen towards the end of the eighteenth and beginning of the nineteenth century. It stresses the concepts of form, metamorphosis, and different kinds of holistic organization. Individual development (ontogeny) was often taken as co-logical with evolution. The rapid development of idealistic biology in the first half of nineteenth century was impaired by various subsequences of Darwin's appearance (1859), though in continental Europe it survived in various diasporas until the second world war. The foremost representatives of this intellectual line were L. Oken, J. W. Goethe, K. E. v. Baer, E. G. Saint-Hilaire, R. Owen, W. Troll, and A. Naef. Brought to you by | De Gruyter / TCS Authenticated | 66.31.11.14 Download Date | 5/6/14 7:27 PM Visual communication in animals 663 Jakob J. von Uexküll (born 1864 Estonia, died 1944 Italy) developed an original semiotic theory of nature that emphasizes meaning as the organizing force of animal physiology as well as individual relations with the living and non-living environment (Uexküll 1982). His work was inspired by the philosophies of Immanuel Kant and J. Wolfgang von Goethe and, in turn, influenced the latter ethological studies of Konrad Lorenz and Nikolaas Tinbergen. In the context of the present paper, we focus particularly on Uexküll’s notion that the specific form of an animal – its features and ontological development, the functional relations it has with others of its own species, especially its mates, but also with representatives of other species, physical forces etc – is interconnected by meanings. 3 Semantic organs The exposed surfaces of organisms play a crucial role in visual communication. It is largely through these that animals recognize each other’s species, sex and individuality, and these are the primary displays with which an animal can express its intentions and moods. Let organic appearances that may potentially enter the Umwelten of other living beings be called semantic organs (“semes” in short; Kleisner and Markoš 2005; Kleisner 2008b). In formal language, semantic organs can be defined as semiautonomous relational entities dependent on Umwelt-specific interpretation (Kleisner 2008a). It is remarkable that semantic organs can be defined neither by listing solely their anatomical, morphological, developmental or genetic components nor by unambiguous attribution of a particular signaling function. More precisely, every semantic organ exists at the interface between the expression of bodily features and their meaning within the Umwelt of a receiver. Semantic organs come into existence through semiotic cooption and semiotic selection. Semiotic selection occurs because semiosis literally operates through perception, interpretation and feedback, being thus an evolutionary derivative of Uexküll’s Funktionskreis (Maran 2008: 177; Maran and Kleisner 2010). Semiotic cooption happens when a trait expressed by an organism is recognized as meaningful by another organism (Kleisner 2011). It does not matter whether the co-opted trait was shaped to serve some specific function or had no function at all. In this respect, semiotic cooption is a kind of exaptation operated by the sensory channels and cognitive sphere of an organic subject (on exaptation, see Gould and Vrba 1982; Weible 2012). In our following exposition, we take eyespots as an example of semantic organs par excellence. Though eyespots take on immense diversity of form and color, still they bear something in common: the meaning of an eye. Eyespots are found in almost all kind of ecosystems whether underwater, in the air, or on terra firma. These iconic signs (i.e. signs based on resemblance) occupy the bodies of organism living nowadays as well as of those that were fossilized long before mammals first appeared. Brought to you by | De Gruyter / TCS Authenticated | 66.31.11.14 Download Date | 5/6/14 7:27 PM 664 Karel Kleisner and Timo Maran By focusing on this specific case, we hope to demonstrate the methodology and argumentation characteristic to the Portmannian-Uexküllian biosemiotic approach. Throughout the following exploration we highlight the complex nature of the visual appearances in animals that needs to be maintained to the final conclusions of our study. Our methodological approach is to analyze and finally synthesize the following aspects of animal appearance: 1. distribution and diversity across species and groups; 2. array of the possible functions of the phenomenon (eyespots in the present study); 3. evolutionary history of the particular appearance and the species involved; 4. developmental background of the individual; 5. behavioral activities of the animal (i.e. which behaviors are needed to make the appearance function as a message in the given communicative situation); 6. interpretations of appearances by other species (e.g. predatory species), their feedback and further effects. We address these methodological points in pairs in the following sub-chapters: 1 and 2 in “Eyespots – their distribution, morphological diversity and functions”; 3 and 4 in “Eyespots in evolution and development”; 5 and 6 in “Behavioral components do matter”. The following survey should lead us to a complex model of animal visual communication systems that is qualitative (e.g. by preferring the concept of appearance over signals, inter alia), sees the semiotic faculty (meanings and signification) as a main organizing force of communication, and highlights the interplay between meanings in communication and evolutionary history. 4 Eyespots – their distribution, morphological diversity and function Different spots and eyespots may be found in a number of animals of different phylogenetic origin such as squids, octopuses, turtles, sharks, rays, fishes, amphibians, reptiles, birds, and especially insects. The various eyespots on the surfaces of animals were traditionally considered representations of eyes. One may suggest this is only imaginative, resulting from subjective “anthropomorphic” projections that have nothing to do with modern science. Here we do not follow such an ultimate purification of the meaning of these iconic signs. We would rather ask whether the similarity between eyespots and eyes reflects a common principle that exceeds the range of human cognition and touches the other living beings in a similar way. In the most general sense, eyespots are mostly considered to be survival devices that deter enemies. Eyespots on the wings of butterflies especially represent the most intensively studied semantic system. The experimental approach is con- Brought to you by | De Gruyter / TCS Authenticated | 66.31.11.14 Download Date | 5/6/14 7:27 PM Visual communication in animals 665 tinuously perfected to bring more reliable results. There are two major explanations for the protective function of eyespots. The first represents an “intimidation” hypothesis according to which the function of the eyes is to deter predators, and prevent an attack. The usual reasoning here is that eyespots intimidate predators because they represent an imitation of vertebrate eyes: this is the “eye mimicry” hypothesis (Blest 1958). Recently, this hypothesis has been strongly criticized, especially by authors who perform field behavioral experiments (Stevens et al. 2007, 2009). In this view, eyespots serve an antipredation function, not because they are representations of eyes but because they are conspicuous. The fact that many of them resemble a vertebrate eye to a human observer arguably has nothing to do with their warning function. Eyespots effectively intimidate the predator’s attack because they are simply conspicuous and highly contrasting, not because they imitate vertebrate eyes. This understanding led Stevens et al. to abandon the term “eyespots” as anthropocentric while proposing the term “wingspots” for these structures in butterflies, “finspots” in fishes, etc. This hypothesis is based on the deflection of a predator’s attack away from the vital body parts, e.g. the head, to less vulnerable ones, e.g. the wing margins. Current support for the deflection hypothesis remains equivocal (Lyytinen et al. 2003; Hill and Vaca 2006; Vlieger and Brakefield 2007). Eyespots have yet other functions such as playing a signaling role in sexual selection. In the butterfly Bicyclus anynana (Nymphalidae), for instance, the dorsal wing pattern is supposed to partake in female mate choice whereas the ventral pattern serves a camouflaging and/or predator-deflecting role (Brakefield and Reitsma 1991; Lyytinen et al. 2004; Stevens 2005). Despite the current research progress in the behavioral ecology of antipredation signals, there are still some questions that transcend the focus of the mainstream adaptationist agenda. Our concern with eyespots occurs prior to formulating and testing a hypothesis. We assume that some pre-understanding to “what is an eye?” is always present when we approach objects that are conspicuous, circular, and concentric. One should ask: do eyespots enter the Umwelten of nonhuman animals as representations of an eye? May eyespots represent vertebrate eye mimicry? How has it come about that different circular objects are experienced as eyes? And, how have various representations of the eye come into existence?2 In the following, we will argue that neither the “eye mimicry” hypothesis nor the “conspicuous signal” hypothesis represents an appropriate explanation of the evolution of eyespots. Here, we propose a third perspective which differs from the previous “either … or” scenario and, at the same time, remains compatible with recent findings. For a more detailed application of the semiotic methodology to the study of animal communication, see Maran 2010. Brought to you by | De Gruyter / TCS Authenticated | 66.31.11.14 Download Date | 5/6/14 7:27 PM 666 Karel Kleisner and Timo Maran 5 Eyespots in evolution and development There are two major hypotheses on the evolution of eyespots in butterflies. The first proposes that eyespots originated from the undifferentiated row of elements (border ocelli) – each occupying a single wing compartment (or wing cell) – that became further individuated and diversified in number and morphology. According to the second scenario, eyespots originally appeared as single autonomized compartmental elements that were duplicated and repeatedly co-opted by other wing compartments (Monteiro 2008). Morphologically, the wings of satyrid and nymphalid butterflies often bear a row of eyespots that are homologous to the border ocelli within the generalized wing pattern of the nymphalid ground plan (Süffert 1927; Nijhout 1991); see Figure 1. By contrast, the eyespots on the hindwings of some sphingid moths originate from elements of the central symmetry system, that is, from a different part of the nymphalid groundplan. Inasmuch as the element of border ocelli consists of an array of eyespots, the whole system has a modular character similar to that of the vertebrate backbone. In the ancestral state, the eyespots were presumably highly coupled, both genetically and developmentally. However, during the course of evolution, acting adaptive forces led to their genetic decoupling, favoring individuation and independent diversification of single eyespots (Beldade and Brakefield 2003). Artificial selection Fig. 1: Generalized ground plan of wing patterns of family Nymphalidae according to Süffert (1927). Brought to you by | De Gruyter / TCS Authenticated | 66.31.11.14 Download Date | 5/6/14 7:27 PM Visual communication in animals 667 applied to eyespots had a rapid effect on size, location and color composition of the eyespots, whereas much lower heritability was reported for eyespot shape during selection for elliptical eyespots in the anteroposterior and proximodistal axes (Monteiro et al. 1997a; Monteiro et al. 1997b). As a result, it seems evident that when compared to other parameters, the circular shape of the eyespots is strongly constrained. This is probably because of developmental-mechanistic reasons during the formation of the eyespot such as the response of the surrounding epidermis to radial diffusion of a signal from a central focus point (Nijhout 1980, 1991; French and Monteiro 1994). However the same explanation can hardly be applied to instances where the eyespots do not originate from material homologous to border ocelli. The eyespots on the forewings of peacocks (Inachis io, Nymphalidae) represent a composite of neighboring elements of color pattern. The eyespots originated by fusion; integrations of different parts of a centrally symmetric system are frequent, for instance within sphinx moths, but also some mantids bear eyespots formed from spiralized stripes, etc. The suggestion of Stevens (Stevens et al. 2007: 526) that the high frequency of circles compared to the other shapes may be explained by “[…] the radial diffusion of a morphogen outward forming a concentration gradient, with the epidermal cells producing specific pigments depending on the morphogen concentration” is thus valid only for a limited number of eyespots, namely those derived from the marginal ocelli. But eyespots tend to be circular even when generated from noncircular precursors. Alternatively, “the circularity of these elements are favored because they increase the probability that the eyespots will be perceived as “eyelike” by a majority of possible receivers and thus attract the sight of predators” (Kleisner 2008a: 215). In other words, specific developmental mechanisms do not appear to fully explain the existence of generalized forms that are present in many species and groups. Within most studies, eyespots serve as a model system of development. Particular phenotypic changes in eyespot parameters provide information on the functioning of developmental mechanisms and genetic underpinnings. For such approaches, eyespots are an excellent experimental model, but this does not help us understand their close resemblance to vertebrate eyes. Again, one wonder how these eyespots became “eye-like” and how are they maintained as such during evolution. 5.1 Eyespots in fossils The role eyespots play in communication between and within species has a long evolutionary history. Eyespots are well evidenced from insect fossils. For example, members of the Eurasian family Kalligrammatidae were large insects from the Jurassic period that belonged to the order Neuroptera. Their conspicuously patterned wings, often with large eyespots on hind- and fore-wings, are well preserved in the fossil record. As nicely stated by Grimaldi and Engel: Brought to you by | De Gruyter / TCS Authenticated | 66.31.11.14 Download Date | 5/6/14 7:27 PM 668 Karel Kleisner and Timo Maran Kalligrammatids were the “butterflies” of the Jurassic. Their densely setose and patterned wings and bodies and their long palpi gave them the superficial appearance of large moths or butterflies, despite occurring 60–90 MY before the first papilionoid fluttered […] It is tantalizing to speculate how the eyespots of kalligrammatids served a similar function of startle defense. It is equally interesting as to what peculiar Jurassic vertebrates kalligrammatids might have been mimicking, perhaps some small, insectivorous reptile or even an archaeopterygid bird? (Grimaldi and Engel 2005: 347). Edmunds’ (1976) mention of eyespots found on the wings of the carboniferous insects from the order Protodiamphipnoa represents another example from an even older geological period. If these eyespots functioned as recent ones, the only possible vertebrate receivers of these signals would have been amphibians and/or reptiles (Komárek 1989). One should ask, however, whether or not these eyespots represented an imitation of the eyes of some particular animal group. The question whether there were any eyespots on the surfaces of animals from the period that preceded the evolutionary origin of the ventricular eye cannot be answered easily. Nevertheless, the eyespots found within the fossil record seem to be of the same forms and shapes as recent ones. The simplest explanation is that the eyespots probably did not represent an imitation of eyes, neither of a particular vertebrate species nor a vertebrate class. For now, we would rather say that eyespots generally do not imitate the eyes of any particular kind of vertebrate. 5.2 Eyespots underwater The different physical and physiological constraints of an aquatic environment do not prevent the communicational function of eyespots in inhabitants of marine and freshwater ecosystems. Various eyespots (or just spots) occur in many fish species. The most striking examples involve the presentation of the eyespots (finspot) on the caudal part of the body, while a dark band conceals the real eye, as seen in some species of butterfly fish (Chaetodontidae). As a result, the caudal part of the body fulfils the role of a false head. The entire effect is sometimes supported by movement opposite to body direction (backward in relation to real head). The coloration of the whole fish body, the concealed eyes and caudal fin-spots, together with associated behavior, together generates a context within which the spots carry the meaning of an eye and the caudal region that of a false head. The location of the eyespot and false head may be supposed to misdirect the attack of predator to less vital parts of the animal body as described by the misdirection hypothesis (Cott 1957; Neudecker 1989; Meadows 1993; Winemiller 1990). This hypothesis assumes that the eyespots should imitate the real eye in size and structural composition, while differing in position. Nevertheless, the caudal eyespots of many fish, for instance the four-eye butterfly fish (Chaetodon capistratus), markedly exceed the size of natural eyes. The larger size of the eyespots appears to refer to the presence of a larger animal, thus they would be more effective in Brought to you by | De Gruyter / TCS Authenticated | 66.31.11.14 Download Date | 5/6/14 7:27 PM Visual communication in animals 669 intimidating a predator (the intimidation hypothesis). The occurrence of dislocated and large sized eyespots may also be explained by the “reaction-distance hypothesis” which assumes that the larger size of eyespots may induce predators to initiate an attack from too great a distance, thus giving a temporal advantage to the prey and potentially thwarting the attack. According to this hypothesis, the predators use the angular extent of the eyelike pattern on their retina as a cue to trigger the attack. Moreover, the oval or elliptic shape of the eyespots may confuse the predator about its actual angle of approaching trajectory and thus misdirect the attack (Meadows 1993). These examples show that explaining the particular appearance of the eyespots may require taking into account the interpreter’s perceptual specifics and behavioral preferences.3 It would be extremely interesting to test these ideas in the context of insect eyespots, as we often find therein either a series or single eyespots of different sizes and sometimes spatially warped shapes. It is worth noting that the eyes themselves appeared to be a very conspicuous signal within the newly discovered red fluorescence of reef fishes. Red fluorescent eye rings were reported in 30 species from four families (Gobiidae, Tripterygiidae, Blenniidae, Syngnathidae). The frequent occurrence of this feature indicates that fluorescent eyes may potentially function as a presence indicator or deceptive gaze signal (Michiels et al. 2008). We return to the importance of the conspicuousness of the animal eyes in the final part of our discussion. 6 Behavioral components do matter In addition to the structural diversity and the developmental and evolutionary history of animal appearance, its dynamical and behavioral aspects must also be taken into account. The comparison of effectiveness of deimatic coloration in two models of butterflies shows that the behavioral component can play a crucial role.4 Vallin et al. (2007) performed an experiment in which hawkmoths (Smerinthus ocellatus) and peacocks (Inachis io) were subjected to attack by birds (great and blue tits). As a result, the birds killed more hawkmoths than peacocks. This is surprising because both species have similarly sized eyespots, which were suspected of having a similar intimidating effect on bird predators. Both peacocks and hawkmoths are palatable and non-poisonous. It is worth noting, that hawkmoths are a much larger prey item, which should be easier to attack than the smaller peacocks. However, when peacocks are disturbed not only do they open their wings with the eyelike ornaments, they also start to flick their wings and The recent research on coral reef fish Pomacentrus amboinensis also indicates the possible role of eyespots in social interactions (Gagliano 2008). The eyespots may take a role in rapid recognition of conspecifics, thus bringing a selective advantage to the species (Zaret 1977). Edmunds (1974) used the term deimatic behaviors for all forms of displays, postures and sounds taken up by prey with the apparent purpose of intimidating an attacking predator. Brought to you by | De Gruyter / TCS Authenticated | 66.31.11.14 Download Date | 5/6/14 7:27 PM 670 Karel Kleisner and Timo Maran allegedly turn around to follow the movement of the attacking bird (Vallin et al. 2007). The protective behavior of hawkmoths also involves “eyespots flickering” but this may seem especially impressive to human (mammalian) observers, while seen as more static and less frightening to birds. This is supposedly related to differences between the perceptual worlds (Umwelten) of humans and birds, the reaction times and temporal perception being generally much faster in the latter. A different species of hawkmoth, the tobacco hornworm (Manduca sexta), which has dorsal black and yellow bands on its abdomen, gives other example of correspondence between behavior and warning coloration. The abdominal pattern of Manduca somewhat imitates a wasp-like pattern. When Manduca sexta is irritated (attacked), it starts to move with its abdomen in a way that simulates the stinging behavior of aculeate hymenopterans (Evans 1983). The wasp-like coloration followed by an imitation of aculeate abdominal movements makes an overall expression quite intimidating for a potential receiver. The intimidating effectiveness of such deimatic displays thus depends on the behavioral repertoire of a bearer. Quite probably it could be the behavioral component that makes the eyespots a more effective anti-predation signal than the other conspicuous forms examined by the experimental design of these British behavioral ecologists. In other words, eyes and eye-marks should not be isolated as merely static displays, but considered in a way that emphasizes their dynamical and functional being – that is, within the context of activities such as looking, eye-blinking, head-turning, etc. However difficult it would be to test this possibility in the field, further research that integrates behavioral components with deimatic coloration is needed. 7 How a spot becomes an eyespot? Both theoretical arguments and experimental evidence have challenged the “vertebrate eye mimicry” hypothesis (e.g. Stevens et al. 2007). When we discard the concept of “eyespot” for the more or less neutral concept of “wingspot” – as suggested by Stevens and co-authors – we simultaneously abolish the question as to why some wingspots resemble eyes to us and perhaps also to other non-human receivers. Therefore, we should ask how wingspots become eyespots, or how a circular structure becomes an iconic sign that stand for an eye. Another source of criticism may point to the fact that experiments use an artificial design to examine the functioning of the anti-predatory role of eyespots – not butterflies themselves. This means that the possible active role of the prey in this prey-predator interaction is abandoned a priori. We have already shown that the behavior of the potential prey does influence a signal’s effectiveness, as probably do the specific features and capacities of the receiver, its response and co-action with the prey. We learn that different eyespots (wingspots, finspots) function because they are conspicuous, not because of their imitation of vertebrate eyes. It is also pos- Brought to you by | De Gruyter / TCS Authenticated | 66.31.11.14 Download Date | 5/6/14 7:27 PM Visual communication in animals 671 sible, however, that they refer to an eye as a general model, since the eyes themselves are usually conspicuous structures (as shown in the previous examples in fish).5 Therefore, we suggest that if the conspicuousness hypothesis attempts to explain the functioning of eyespots it should consider the question of why vertebrate eyes themselves are often conspicuous. Very likely, vertebrate eyes are mimicked because they are conspicuous structures marking the position of the animals’ heads. Vertebrate eyes are in fact headspots, to use Stevens’ (2005) vocabulary. But also the eyes of some vertebrate species became conspicuous secondarily, only after they have adopted a signaling function. Usually only conspicuous parts of other animals deserve to be imitated, as one can see in the frequent cases of partial mimicry (e.g. false heads, eyespots). It is in principle impossible to describe the evolutionary origin of complex eyespots on the wings of butterflies without any reference to the interpretative act (the signification) on the part of predator that gives a meaning of “vertebrate eye” to the primarily raw structures on butterfly wings. Only after such prospectively eye-like structures acquire the meaning of the eye in the Umwelt of the animal interpreter, can selection act to make them more and more similar to the representation of a vertebrate eye in a predator’s Umwelt, and thus ultimately become closely similar to real vertebrate eyes (Kleisner 2008b). Moreover, the morphological diversity of complex eyespots on the wings of insects may hypothetically be explained by differing Umwelt-specific interpretations of predators that have acted as selective agents. In this sense, one can also think about the attempt to infer the predator’s inner representation of an “eye” from eye-like ornaments exposed on the wings of his potential insect prey (Hinton 1977). In other words, if one wants to discover the meaning of an eye in the Umwelt of a particular interpreter it will potentially be helpful to look at the eyespots on the wings of its potential prey. We conclude this section with a couple of questions. Can conspicuousness partly explain the evolution of eyespots’ aversive function? Yes. Does conspicuousness suffice to elucidate the evolution of eyespots? No. Eventually we suggest that only wing spots, fin spots and other spots that are semiotically co-opted as representing eyes in the Umwelt of a particular animal interpreter should be named eyespots. Spots that are not so involved in any animal Umwelten should rather be considered as structures with an existing but yet-unrevealed semiotic potential. 8 Theoretical implication of semantic morphology One may question the need for new concepts such as semantic organs, appearance, co-option and others when contemporary biology already has such terms as signal “Mimicry of snakes by insects appears to be analogous to mimicry of vertebrate eyes by many species of insects. Many of these false eyes are very like the eyes of vertebrates: the incorporate Brought to you by | De Gruyter / TCS Authenticated | 66.31.11.14 Download Date | 5/6/14 7:27 PM 672 Karel Kleisner and Timo Maran and cue by which to label organic appearances. We insist, however, that the vocabulary of signals and cues, and the biological rationale underlying these terms, does not fit many of the situations that we find within the animal world. A sender emits a signal to directly affect a particular receiver, i.e. a signal is a sign that serves manipulative purposes. Cues, on the other hand, are not specific to living organisms and could also be present and perceived within inanimate objects. What is wrong with these terms is that the concepts of cues and signals are rather used to denote specific features of an animal body or an environment, and not the animal body as a whole. By contrast, when considering the whole surface of an organism as derived meaningfully in the function of a living body, and self-display as a revelation of the otherwise inaccessible innermost potential of an organism (i.e. as representation of organic inwardness, in Portmann’s terms), a new terminology is needed. These concepts should, on the one hand, describe animal appearances as meaningfully organized wholes and, on the other, make a clear distinction between living and non-living surfaces. The apparent feature of all exposed organic surfaces is their uniqueness in relation to other bodily structures. Everything that comes into being could be potentially perceived by someone, therefore being existent means being somewhat apparent. Being existent as animate supposes that appearance has inner causes, for organisms build themselves. If you remove the surface layer of a rock, you will usually find the same pattern beneath. This is because the appearance of a rock does not represent the result of activity stemming from the rock’s centrality, i.e. from the rock itself. Looking under the coat of a mammal produces a quite different experience. Although this basic fact is evident even to children, most of today’s biologists seems behave as if they are unaware of it. These differences between inner and outer lie at the core of the division between life/non-life. Living beings have an inwardness that can be interpreted in evolutionary terms as an evolutionary experience gathered by a lineage during the temporally vast period of evolutionary history. This deeply anchored dimension of living beings simply cannot be erased, forgotten, or overwritten. For the same reason, neither can it be wholly imitated. When thinking in terms of semantic organs, we simultaneously refer to these innermost dimensions of living. While a sign is a representation of something other, the semantic organs are self-representations of organisms (thus coming close to “proper names” in a semiotic typology of the signs). In identifiably particular ways, they reveal the evolutionary experience of a lineage and thus also their specificity and individuality. To talk about organisms in terms of semantic organs means to take their ontological wholeness into consideration. There is one important point stemming from the logic of semantic organs. One could admit that the exposed surfaces of an organism are often imitated, and eccentric circles and an apparently reflective high-light from a moist cornea. They can be astonishingly realistic, but they do not resemble the eyes of any particular vertebrate.” (Pough 1988: 81). Brought to you by | De Gruyter / TCS Authenticated | 66.31.11.14 Download Date | 5/6/14 7:27 PM Visual communication in animals 673 because many organic surfaces can be conceived as semantic organs, so too semantic organs must be subjects of imitation. Imitation is indeed ubiquitous in the living world, but semantic organs cannot be imitated easily. What we mean by this is that such an imitation would never be safe for the mimic (the imitating organism). As semantic organs are tightly related to organic inwardness (and living experience), changing a semantic organ will also change that being’s inwardness. We should now correct the former statement that “semantic organs cannot be imitated easily” to suggest that “semantic organs cannot be imitated ‘superficially’”. For example, take numerous cases of mimicry where a model is imitated by one or more mimic species. In the case of Batesian mimicry, the model is protected (unpalatability, sting, poison etc.), whereas the mimics have no protection. It is apparent that mimicking organisms gain a selective advantage by adopting the semantic organs (semes) of a model. In classical neo-Darwinian exposition, the story ends at this point. We suggest that advantage in survival is necessarily connected with a less apparent disadvantage in terms of self-representation. This is the loss of species-specific semes. This is what a mimic must pay for increased reproductive success, or in other words, for hiding behind a model. The most obvious example of this is the necessity for new types of intraspecific communicative mechanisms to arise, as imitating other species may cause previous speciesspecific communicative mechanisms to collapse. But this lead to crucial consequences as: […] self-representation of mimic does not longer stand for the presentation of the self, but it is the presentation of the semes of a model on the body of the mimic. In other words, bodies of the mimics serve as a projecting screen for the semes of the model. So, in fact, the display of a mimic represents the “self”-representation of the model (Kleisner and Markoš 2009: 305–306). By analogy from human society, losing face is also conceived as a dramatic event with non-trivial consequences for an individual. The other example can be seen when someone aims to ‘clear’ his or her family name; simply adopting a new “false” family name is usually not considered a satisfying solution. Some of the ideas presented in this chapter remain unacceptable in mainstream biological thought. However, without taking the “self” of living beings seriously as a representation of evolutionary experience gathered into a lineage by its unique evolutionary history, we will be in danger of erroneous reasoning about evolution. For the humanities and social sciences, biological treatment of communication may appear predominantly focused on evolutionary history and functionality in message conveyance. In this context, the Portmannian-Uexküllian biosemiotic approach attempts to introduce greater awareness about the historical and communicative contexts of meanings and the roles of the sender and the interpreter in bringing forth and shaping the messages in communication. Brought to you by | De Gruyter / TCS Authenticated | 66.31.11.14 Download Date | 5/6/14 7:27 PM 674 Karel Kleisner and Timo Maran Acknowledgments: We thank David Machin for the kind invitation to contribute to this volume. Karel Kleisner was supported by Czech Grant Agency project GACR P505/11/1459, and by Charles University in Prague project UNCE 204004, Timo Maran’s research was supported by European Union through the European Regional Development Fund (Centre of Excellence CECT, Estonia) and by Estonian Science Foundation Grant No 7790. References Andersson, Staffan, Jonas Örnborg and Malte Andersson. 1998. Ultraviolet Sexual Dimorphism and Assortative Mating in Blue Tits. Proceedings of the Royal Society of London B 265(1395): 445–450. Beldade, Patrícia and Paul M. Brakefield. 2003. Concerted Evolution and Developmental Integration in Modular Butterfly Wing Patterns. Evolution & Development 5(2): 169–179. Blest, A. D. 1957. The Function of Eyespot Patterns in the Lepidoptera. Behavior 11(2/3): 209–256. Brakefield, Paul M. and Nico Reitsma. 1991. Phenotypic Plasticity, Seasonal Climate and the Population Biology of Bicyclus Butterflies (Satyridae) in Malawi. Ecological Entomology 16: 291–303. Cott, Hugh B. 1957. Adaptive Coloration in Animals. London: Methuen Press. Edmunds, Malcolm. 1974. Defence in Animals. A survey in Antipredator Defences. Harlow: Longman. Edmunds, Malcolm. 1976. The Defensive Behaviour of Ghanaian Praying Mantids with a Discussion of Territoriality. Zoological Journal Of the Linnean Society 58(1): 1–37. Evans, David L. 1983. Relative Defensive Behavior of Some Moths and the Implications to Predator-prey Interactions. Entomologia Experimentalis et Applicata 33(1): 103–111. French, Vernon and Atónia Monteiro. 1994. Butterfly Wings: Colour patterns and now gene expression patterns. Bioessays 16(11): 789–791. Gagliano, Monica. 2008. On the Spot: The absence of predators reveals eyespot plasticity in a marine fish. Behavioral Ecology 19(4):733–739. Gould, Stephen Jay and Elisabeth S. Vrba. 1982. Exaptation – A missing term in the science of form. Paleobiology 8(1): 4–15. Gould, Stephen J. 1977. Ontogeny and Phylogeny. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press. Grimaldi, David and Michael S. Engel. 2005. Evolution of the Insects. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Hill, Ryan I. and Jarol F. Vaca. 2006. Differential Wing Strength in Pierella Butterflies (Nymphalidae, Satyrinae) Supports the Deflection Hypothesis. Biotropica 36(3): 362–370. Hinton, Howard. 1977. Mimicry Provides Information about the Perceptual Capacities of Predators. Folia Entomológica Mexicana. 37: 19–29. Hockett, Charles F. 1960. Logical Considerations in the Study of Animal Communication. In Wesley E. Lanyon, and William N. Tavolga (eds.), Animal Sounds and Communication, 392–430. Washington: American Institute of Biological Sciences. Kleisner, Karel. 2011. Perceive, Co-opt, Modify, and Live! Organism as a centre of experience. Biosemiotics 4(2): 223–241. Kleisner, Karel. 2008a. The Semantic Morphology of Adolf Portmann: A starting point for the biosemiotics of organic form? Biosemiotics 1(2): 207–219. Kleisner, Karel. 2008b. Homosemiosis, Mimicry, and Superficial Similarity: Notes on the conceptualization of independent emergence of similarity in biology. Theory in Biosciences 127(1): 15–21. Brought to you by | De Gruyter / TCS Authenticated | 66.31.11.14 Download Date | 5/6/14 7:27 PM Visual communication in animals 675 Kleisner, Karel and Anton Markoš. 2005. Semetic Rings: Towards the new concept of mimetic resemblances. Theory in Biosciences 123(3): 209–222. Kleisner, Karel and Anton Markoš. 2009. Mutual understanding and misunderstanding in Biological Systems Mediated by Self-representational Meaning of Organisms. Sign Systems Studies 37(1/2): 299–310. Komárek, Stanislav. 1989. Vorkommen, Morphologie und Evolution der Augenmuster in der Flügelzeichnung der Familie Sphingidae. Zoologische Jahrbücher. Abteilung für Systematik, Ökologie und Geographie der Tiere 116: 217–254. Kull, Kalevi, Claus Emmeche and Donald Favareau. 2008. Biosemiotic Questions. Biosemiotics 1(1): 41–55. Lyytinen, Anne, Paul M. Brakefield and Johanna Mappes. 2003. Significance of Butterfly Eyespots as an Anti-predator Device in Ground-based and Aerial Attacks. Oikos 100: 373–379. Lyytinen, Anne, Paul M. Brakefield, Leena Lindström and Johanna Mappes. 2004. Does Predation Maintain Eyespot Plasticity in Bicyclus Anynana? Proceedings of the Royal Society of London B, 271: 279–283. Maran, Timo. 2008. Mimikri Semiootika. [Semiotics of mimicry, Tartu Ülikooli doktoritöid]. Tartu: Tartu University Press. Maran, Timo. 2010. Semiotic modeling of mimicry with reference to brood parasitism. Sign Systems Studies 38(1/4): 349–377. Maran, Timo and Karel Kleisner. 2010. Towards an Evolutionary Biosemiotics: Semiotic selection and semiotic co-option. Biosemiotics 3(2): 189–200. Meadows, Dwayne W. 1993. Morphological Variation in Eyespots of the Foureye Butterflyfish (Chaetodon capistratus): Implications for eyespot function. Copeia 1993(1): 235–240. Michiels, Nico K., Nils Anthes, Nathan S. Hart, Jürgen Herler, Alfred J. Meixner, Frank Schleifenbaum, Gregor Schulte, Ulrike E. Siebeck, Dennis Sprenger, and Matthias F. Wucherer. 2008. Red Fluorescence in Reef Fish: A novel signalling mechanism? BMC Ecology 8: 16. Monteiro, Antónia, Paul M. Brakefield and Vernon French. 1997a. Butterfly Eyespots: The genetics and development of the color rings. Evolution 51(4): 1207–1216. Monteiro, Antónia, Paul M. Brakefield and Vernon French. 1997b. The Genetics and Development of an Eyespot Pattern in the Butterfly Bicyclus Anynana: Response to selection for eyespot shape. Genetics 146(1): 287–294. Monteiro, Antónia. 2008. Alternative Models for the Evolution of Eyespots and of Serial Homology on Lepidopteran Wings. Bioessays 30(4): 358–366. Neudecker, Stephen. 1989. Eye Camouflage and False Eyespots: Chaetodontid responses to predators. Environmental Biology of Fishes 25(1–3): 143–157. Nijhout, H. Frederik. 1980. Pattern Formation on Lepidopteran Wings: Determination of an eyespot. Developmental Biology 80(2): 267–274. Nijhout, H. Frederik. 1991. The Development and Evolution of Butterfly Wing Patterns. Washington: Smithsonian Institution Press. Nilsson, Anders L. 1983. Mimesis of Bellflower (Campanula) by the Red Helleborine Orchid Cephalanthera Rubra. Nature 305: 799–800. Portmann, Adolf. 1960a. Neue Wege der Biologie. München: Piper. Portmann, Adolf. 1960b. Die Tiergestalt. Studien über die Bedeutung der tierischen Ercheinung. Basel: Friedrich Reinhardt. Portmann, Adolf. 1965. Neue Fronten der biologischen Arbeit. In Günter Schulz (ed.), Transparente Welt. Festschrift zum 60. Geburtstag von Jean Gebser, 23–37. Bern: Huber. Portmann, Adolf. 1969. Einführung in die vergleichende Morphologie der Wirbeltiere. Basel: Schwabe & Co. Pough, F. Harvey. 1988. Mimicry of Vertebrates: Are the rules different? The American Naturalist 131: S67–102. Brought to you by | De Gruyter / TCS Authenticated | 66.31.11.14 Download Date | 5/6/14 7:27 PM 676 Karel Kleisner and Timo Maran Stevens, Martin. 2005. The Role of Eyespots as Anti-predator Mechanisms, Principally Demonstrated in the Lepidoptera. Biological Reviews 80(4): 573–588. Stevens, Martin, Elinor Hopkins, William Hinde, Amabel Adcock, Yvonne Connelly, Tom Troscianko and Innes C. Cuthill. 2007. Field Experiments on the Effectiveness of ‘Eyespots’ as Predator Deterrents. Animal Behaviour 74(4): 1215–1227. Stevens, Martin, Abi Cantor, Julia Graham and Isabel S. Winney. 2009. The Function of Animal ‘Eyespots’: Conspicuousness but not eye mimicry is key. Current Zoology 55(5): 319–326. Süffert, Fritz. 1927. Zur vergleichenden Analyse der Schmetterlingszeichnung. Biologisches Zentralblatt 47(7): 385–413. Tembrock, Günter. 1971. Biokommunikation: Informationsübertragung im biologischen Bereich I. Berlin: Akademie–Verlag. Uexküll, Jakob von. 1982. The Theory of Meaning. Semiotica 42(1): 25–82. Vallin, Adrian, Sven Jakobsson and Crister Wiklund. 2007. An Eye for an Eye? – On the generality of the intimidating quality of eyespots in a butterfly and a hawkmoth. Behavioral Ecology and Sociobiology 61: 1419–1424. Vlieger, Leon and Paul M. Brakefield. 2007. The Deflection Hypothesis: Eyespots on the margins of butterfly wings do not influence predation by lizards. Biological Journal of the Linnean Society 92(4): 661–667. Weible, Davide. 2012. The Concept of Exaptation Between Biology and Semiotics. International Journal of Signs and Semiotic Systems 2(1): 73–88. Winemiller, Kirk O. 1990. Caudal Eyespots as Deterrents against Fin Predation in the Neoptropical Cichlid Astronotus Ocellatus. Copeia 1990(3): 665–673. Zaret, Thomas M. 1977. Inhibition of Cannibalism in Cichla Ocellaris and Hypothesis of Predator Mimicry among South American Fishes. Evolution 31(2): 421–437. Brought to you by | De Gruyter / TCS Authenticated | 66.31.11.14 Download Date | 5/6/14 7:27 PM