This article was downloaded by: [Betsch, Tilmann] On: 14 December 2010 Access details: Access Details: [subscription number 930559487] Publisher Psychology Press Informa Ltd Registered in England and Wales Registered Number: 1072954 Registered office: Mortimer House, 3741 Mortimer Street, London W1T 3JH, UK Psychological Inquiry Publication details, including instructions for authors and subscription information: http://www.informaworld.com/smpp/title~content=t775648164 Intuition in Judgment and Decision Making: Extensive Thinking Without Effort Tilmann Betscha; Andreas Glöcknerb a Department of Psychology, University of Erfurt, Erfurt, Germany b Max Planck Institute for Research on Collective Goods, Bonn, Germany Online publication date: 03 December 2010 To cite this Article Betsch, Tilmann and Glöckner, Andreas(2010) 'Intuition in Judgment and Decision Making: Extensive Thinking Without Effort', Psychological Inquiry, 21: 4, 279 — 294 To link to this Article: DOI: 10.1080/1047840X.2010.517737 URL: http://dx.doi.org/10.1080/1047840X.2010.517737 PLEASE SCROLL DOWN FOR ARTICLE Full terms and conditions of use: http://www.informaworld.com/terms-and-conditions-of-access.pdf This article may be used for research, teaching and private study purposes. Any substantial or systematic reproduction, re-distribution, re-selling, loan or sub-licensing, systematic supply or distribution in any form to anyone is expressly forbidden. The publisher does not give any warranty express or implied or make any representation that the contents will be complete or accurate or up to date. The accuracy of any instructions, formulae and drug doses should be independently verified with primary sources. The publisher shall not be liable for any loss, actions, claims, proceedings, demand or costs or damages whatsoever or howsoever caused arising directly or indirectly in connection with or arising out of the use of this material. Psychological Inquiry, 21: 279–294, 2010 C Taylor & Francis Group, LLC Copyright ISSN: 1047-840X print / 1532-7965 online DOI: 10.1080/1047840X.2010.517737 Intuition in Judgment and Decision Making: Extensive Thinking Without Effort Tilmann Betsch Department of Psychology, University of Erfurt, Erfurt, Germany Andreas Glöckner Downloaded By: [Betsch, Tilmann] At: 15:45 14 December 2010 Max Planck Institute for Research on Collective Goods, Bonn, Germany We claim that intuition is capable of quickly processing multiple pieces of information without noticeable cognitive effort. We advocate a component view stating that intuitive processes in judgment and decision making are responsible for information integration and output formation (e.g., preference, choice), whereas analytic thinking mainly guides input formation such as search, generation, and change of information. We present empirical evidence corroborating this notion and show that integration of information and preference formation works without cognitive control and is unconstrained by the amount of encoded information and cognitive capacity. We discuss the implications of our findings for the bounded rationality perspective and the multiple strategy approach to judgment and decision making. Finally we outline a connectionist framework for integrating intuitive and analytic thought processes. Seymour Epstein (2008) recently noted, “Intuition has been given so many different meanings . . . that it makes one wonder whether the term has any meaning at all” (p. 23). Even within psychology different concepts coexist. Intuition is conceived as a source of knowledge, a particular process or even a structure of the brain (Winerman, 2005). The field of judgment and decision making mainly resides with the process view yet proposes quite different mechanisms for the underlying process (Glöckner & Witteman, 2010b; Plessner, Betsch, & Betsch, 2008). Prominent approaches equate intuition with heuristic processing (Gigerenzer, 2007; Gilovich, Griffin, & Kahneman, 2002). According to this notion, individuals often make judgments and decisions by applying simple rules for information search and/or output-formation. These heuristics are assumed to rely on only a subset of available information (sometimes even only one piece). For example, people might base probability judgments mainly on the representativeness of an object for a certain category (representativeness heuristic: Tversky & Kahneman, 1974), or when deciding between two objects, they might choose the one that they recognize over the one they do not, while ignoring all other information (recognition heuristic: D. G. Goldstein & Gigerenzer, 2002). Compared to normative rules, for example, utility theory’s maximization principle or formal rules of probability theory, such heuristics substantially reduce cognitive effort. In some situations, however, they may lead to biased judgments and decisions (Kahneman, Slovic, & Tversky, 1982). In spite of this, they often help the actor quite well to maintain a relatively high level of accuracy in different choice and judgment tasks (Gigerenzer, Todd, & the ABC Research Group, 1999; see also Kahneman & Klein, 2009). The heuristic approach emphasizes effort reduction and selective information processing as key features of intuitive thought. For example, the lexicographic rule (LEX) is a simple analytic strategy that can be used in decision making. It says, Do not consider all information, rather start by comparing alternatives on the most important dimension. If they differ, choose the best and terminate further information search. There is ample evidence, both anecdotal and empirical, that people can successfully employ such a strategy of reduced information search. In this article we advocate a markedly different view on intuition. Note that we do not wish to discuss the usefulness of the heuristic approach. We do not deny that individuals may apply processes described by these heuristics, especially those that apply to search. We doubt, however, whether heuristics really cover the potentials of intuitive thought. Many of the heuristics described in the judgment and decision making (JDM) literature merely seem to be simplifications of analytic thought (see Betsch, 2008, for a discussion). They cope with cognitive limitations by leaving out effortful information processes, reducing the amount of information considered or, in short, by reducing complex judgments to simpler ones (cf. Tversky & Kahneman, 1973, p. 207). It is our conviction that there is much more to intuition than simply a reduction in task complexity. 279 BETSCH AND GLÖCKNER Our basic claim is that intuition is capable of dealing with complex tasks through extensive information processing without noticeable effort. We set out by explaining our concept of intuition in more detail. Then we present some empirical evidence substantiating our point of view. Finally, we discuss the limitations of intuitive thought as well as implications for bounded rationality and the multiple strategy approach in JDM. We close with a sketch of an integrative model and suggestions for future research. Downloaded By: [Betsch, Tilmann] At: 15:45 14 December 2010 The Nature of Intuition Processes of thinking are often sorted into two distinct categories. These categories have been given many different names (see Chaiken & Trope, 1999; Evans, 2008; Plessner, Betsch, & Betsch, 2008, for overviews). Henceforth we call them intuitive and analytic, but we do not overly comply with any specific label; more important is how we define them. In the following we present a sketch of intuition that is rooted in our theoretical approach to judgment and decision making (Betsch, 2005; Betsch, Plessner, Schwieren, & Gütig, 2001; Glöckner & Betsch, 2008a, 2008b). Intuitive processes operate autonomously and automatically, that is, they function without conscious control and cannot easily be accessed by introspection. Moreover, they can process multiple pieces of information in parallel. Analytic processes, in contrast, are performed step-by-step. The sequence and direction of these processes can be deliberatively controlled, and the actor is consciously aware of performing these processes. This definition overlaps conceptually with a number of other well known definitions in the literature (e.g., see Betsch, 2008; Glöckner & Witteman, 2010, for discussions). We assume that intuitive processes have the following main characteristics. First, in contrast to processes of deliberative construction and control (Glöckner & Betsch, 2008a), intuitive processes are only marginally constrained by cognitive capacity. Second, intuitive processes use all pieces of information that are momentarily activated from memory and salient in the environment (Betsch, 2005). As such, intuition processes encoded information in an extensive fashion irrespective of its origin (memory or environment). An important implication of this notion is that intuition relies heavily on prior experience. The stronger prior experience has been consolidated in memory, the more likely it will be activated by situational cues and, hence, feed input to intuition (Betsch, 2008). This is not to say that intuitive processes can only operate on prior knowledge, but prior knowledge will always be used if it is activated. Some (but not all) dual process models in cognition entertain an either–or view of mode application 280 (see Evans, 2008, for a recent review). Accordingly, judgments and decisions are made in either an intuitive or analytic mode. We do not see much merit in such a notion. Rather we believe that intuition and analysis share labor by performing different types of processes. We propose that intuitive processes handle output formation, that is, they are responsible for integrating input information and producing a judgmental or choice tendency (e.g., a preference). In turn, analytic processes are responsible for input formation, involving controlled search, generation and temporary change of information, which are only activated if necessary. We return to this component view later in the article. How Intuition Works: An Example From Outside JDM According to our view, intuitive processes are characterized by extensive thinking without effort. This notion is in opposition to mainstream views on intuition in the field of JDM. Cautiously speaking, such a notion may seem unrealistic from the viewpoint of a decision researcher raised in the tradition of bounded rationality. Those who point to the powers of the unconscious in decision making (e.g., Dijksterhuis, 2004; Dijksterhuis, Bos, Nordgren, & van Baaren, 2006) enter a field of harsh debate (e.g., Acker, 2008; GonzalezVallejo, Lassiter, Belleza, & Lindberg, 2008). In other areas of cognition, however, it is quite common to assume that extensive processing of information can easily be performed by the human mind. For example, in speech comprehension and production as well as pattern recognition and categorization, individuals are found to be capable of rapidly processing multiple pieces of information in an astoundingly narrow time frame. Consider, for instance, the case of understanding irony and sarcasm. Like other figures of humorous speech, the meaning of an ironic or sarcastic statement diverges from its surface meaning. In his famous tale “A Child’s Christmas in Wales,” Dylan Thomas (1968) described the following incident he experienced as a boy in his neighbor’s home: “Something was burning all right; perhaps it was Mr Prothero. . . . But he was standing in the middle of the room, saying, ‘A fine Christmas!”’ (p. 6) Understanding the latter statement properly requires the recipient to decide that the literal meaning of the sentence is not suitable to understand the intended meaning. This task involves complex processes such as encoding of the literal meaning, recognition and categorization of the context, and detection of incongruence between utterance and context. Nevertheless, individuals rapidly grasp the meaning of statements like the one in this example. Downloaded By: [Betsch, Tilmann] At: 15:45 14 December 2010 INTUITION IN DECISION MAKING Research on the understanding of irony in speech is evidencing that adult recipients simultaneously utilize even more stimuli such as prosodic-, mimic-, and gesture-related information (see Gibbs & Colston, 2007, for overviews). Nevertheless, comprehension is a very quick process in natural settings and can be performed in less than 600 to 800 ms (e.g., Schwoebel, Dews, Winner, & Srinivas, 2000). Remarkebly, increasing the amount of information (e.g., by providing contextual cues) can result in a faster detection of irony (Amenta & Balconi, 2008). This finding is attributed to parallel processing. Wang, Lee, Sigman, and Dapretto (2006) compared accuracy and speed in identification of irony in average and clinical patients. In the latter, the ability of parallel activation of brain regions was impaired. Whereas average participants showed simultaneous activation of different brain regions and were very quick to understand irony, the clinical patients had to engage in time-consuming deliberative thought to grasp the ironic intention behind the message. These and other findings led researchers to postulate that essential parts of speech comprehension are driven by holistic processes operating automatically and in parallel (e.g., Long & Graesser, 1988). We have chosen this example because speech comprehension and decision making share some important properties. In both domains, the individual must cope with uncertainty and utilize probabilistic cues to judge a distal criterion (speech: intended meaning; decision situation: future benefits of behavior). Speech and rational decisions are usually seen as manifestations of cognitive capabilities that are genuinely human. Regularly, we do not expect animals to understand irony or engage in anticipative waging of outcomes. Both domains involve conscious processes. In a standard communication situation, the recipient focuses her attention on the sender. Listening itself involves conscious awareness of the situation and the content of the message. Similarly, in standard settings used in decision research (e.g., the gambling paradigm), the individual intends to make a decision, focuses on the information given, and is consciously aware of alternatives as well as their respective pros and cons. It is our conviction that judgment and decision processes capitalize on the same potentials of the brain as speech comprehension processes do. According to our view, intuitive processes are devoted to information integration and the formation of judgmental or choice tendencies. These processes will immediately be instantiated upon activation or encoding of the information. They work in the background while analytic processes can set in to control or change further information search. In the following sections, we substantiate our claim with empirical evidence. Specifically, we show that extensive information processing without conscious control also guides judgment and decision making. Extensive and Uncontrolled Integration of Information in Judgment The experiments reviewed in this section show that extensive information integration can occur even if cognitive capacities are constrained by another task and the individual does not intend to form a summary evaluation of the target objects. In the experimental setting described next, participants were asked unexpectedly to evaluate shares. Prior to evaluation, they had encoded outcome information about these shares in a dual-task setting. As a distracting task (framed as the primary one), participants were asked to memorize the content of videotaped ads. Participants were told that the (ostensible) goal of the study was to assess memory performance under distracting conditions. In line with this cover story, reading outcome information about the shares was framed as a secondary task. Specifically, they were asked to read aloud information about shares scrolling across the bottom of the screen. Outcomes were return values produced by fictitious shares at the stock market over a period of several trading days (see Figure 1). A single return value (e.g., 32) represented the gain in Euro cent achieved by a particular share (e.g., “Pittler”) on a particular trading day. Return values were shown at a quick pace. Participants were asked to read all appearing return values and names of shares aloud to ensure encoding. They viewed up to 140 pieces of return values produced by up to eight different shares on 20 trading days. The presentation lasted up to 10 min. In sum, this procedure established a high level of information overload, constrained deliberate processing resources with a dual task procedure, and obscured the true intention of the study. Extensive pretesting showed that this procedure effectively prevented participants from consciously integrating return values and forming deliberate judgments of the shares. The distribution of return values was manipulated as a within-subjects factor. Specifically, the sum, average, frequency, and dispersion of return values were varied. In line with the cover story, participants were asked to recall information about the ads after the presentation. Subsequently, however, they were unexpectedly asked to spontaneously evaluate each share by adjusting a scroll bar representing an affective scale with endpoints labelled good and bad. Postexperimental interviews showed that participants indeed did not expect to evaluate the shares. Participants consistently reported that they had focused their attention on the ads and did not attempt to form evaluations of the shares. Moreover, a recall test following the judgments showed that participants were unable to reliably reproduce characteristics of the distributions of the return values. One key research question was whether return distributions covaried with evaluations in a systematic 281 Downloaded By: [Betsch, Tilmann] At: 15:45 14 December 2010 BETSCH AND GLÖCKNER Figure 1. Screenshot of stimulus presentation used in studies on integration of information without intention. Note. Attention-grabbing ads are shown in the background. Return values of shares are shown in the running caption at the bottom. fashion. If information integration occurred automatically during the encoding of return values, spontaneous judgments of the shares should systematically reveal influences of the properties of the given information. Across a number of studies, the astounding finding was that evaluative judgments consistently reflected the sum of return values. Figure 2 shows the results of the first experiment from this line of research (Betsch et al., 2001, Exp.1). Participants were presented with five target shares, each appearing with the same frequency. The sum of their return values, however, differed between 300 and 700 Euro cents. Evaluative judgments perfectly reproduced the actual variation of the sum of values. Accordingly, the 300-share was rated least positively, whereas the 700-share received the most positive rating. At the end of this study, participants were also asked to think carefully and rehearse the sum and av- erage of return values produced by each of the shares. In contrast to their spontaneous evaluative judgments, participants were unable to deliberatively reconstruct sums and averages of the return distributions. The results indicate that mere encoding of value laden information (monetary outcomes) was a sufficient condition for instigating the integration of this input information. Integration seemed to function without intention and deliberate control under conditions of information overload (dual task situation) and while participants’ attention was focused on another task (memorizing details of ads). A series of subsequent studies further substantiated the validity of these conclusions und ruled out alternative explanations of the results. For instance, we showed that the results could not be explained in terms of simple heuristics such as numerosity, peak-and-end Figure 2. Results from Betsch, Plessner, Schwieren, and Gütig (2001, Exp.1). Note. Evaluative judgments of five target shares differing with regard to sum of return values. Higher values indicate a more intense liking. 282 Downloaded By: [Betsch, Tilmann] At: 15:45 14 December 2010 INTUITION IN DECISION MAKING (Betsch et al., 2001), familiarity and ease of recognition (Betsch, Hoffmann, Hoffrage, & Plessner, 2003). Moreover, Plessner, Betsch, Schallies, and Schwieren (2008) demonstrated that the findings could be replicated in nonmonetary domains (e.g., political judgment and voting behavior). Of interest, the efficiency of extensive integration was impaired if participants attempted to control the process by deliberation. Intention and deliberation changed the pattern of results systematically. In contrast to intuitive integration, analytic inspection of the given information decreased the amount of information considered (Betsch et al., 2001, Exp. 3) and caused participants to consider other aspects such as the size of information sample as weighting factors. Specifically, the given information was weighted by the size of the sample (Betsch, Kaufmann, Lindow, Plessner, & Hoffmann, 2006) and its reliability (Kaufmann & Betsch, 2009). The latter results show that analysis can change the weighting of information in a fashion distinct to intuitive processing. We return to this issue later in the article when we discuss our connectionist model. Altogether, this brief review of studies provides evidence in support of the notion that information integration can be extensive and effortless at the same time. The underlying mental processes operate autonomously in the background while the individual focuses on another capacity-consuming task. Integration resulted in systematic preference formation. The only precondition for instantiating extensive accounting of information was that the information was encoded, that is, fed into the processing system (cf. Betsch, Plessner, & Schallies, 2004, for a discussion). Altogether, the results corroborate our claim that intuitive processes are characterized by autonomous (uncontrolled, unintentional) operation and extensive consideration of information. Thus far we have considered judgments and not decisions. Moreover, the experimental setting was designed in such a way that analytic processes were directed to another task. Recall, however, that we claimed that intuitive and analytic processes regularly interact in decision making (but are devoted to different types of processes). In the next sections, we present results from studies on choice among options using a standard paradigm from decision research. We show that extensive integration of information will also occur in deliberate decision making. In the experiments reviewed next, individuals use and integrate all available information within a remarkably narrow time frame when encoding is easy. Extensive and Effortless Integration of Information in Decision Making One of the most widely used tools for process tracing in deliberate decisions is the Mouselab (Johnson, Payne, Schkade, & Bettman, 1986). The Mouselab presents information in a covered Option × Attribute matrix. Individuals use the computer mouse to uncover information hidden in the fields, during which the computer program protocols search behavior, decision times, and choices. The introduction of the Mouselab was a significant advance in process tracing research. With help of this tool, decision strategies were identified on the basis of search behavior (e.g., Payne, Bettman, & Johnson, 1988). In Mouselab experiments it has been consistently observed that, under severe task constraints (e.g., time pressure), individuals change from complex to simple strategies that consider only subsets of information. These and corresponding results were interpreted as strong corroborations of the key assumptions of the bounded rationality approach and its offspring the multiple strategy approach to judgment and decision making (e.g., Gigerenzer, 2004; Gigerenzer & Selten, 2001; Payne, Bettman, & Johnson, 1993). The Mouselab, however, places constraints on information acquisition. It requires motor behavior (mouse movements) to uncover information hidden in the matrix. Moreover, if only one box can be open at a time and closes after another is opened, the tool places constraints on working memory, because pieces of information must be remembered until the search process is terminated. In the Mouselab, external constraints (e.g., time pressure) enhance the costs of information acquisition, making it reasonable to reduce search depth. As such, the observation of adaptive strategy change shows that the costs of information search and retention in working memory are indeed boundaries to information acquisition. This finding does not provide conclusive evidence, however, for the notion that information integration and calculation capacities are constrained by external factors. In a series of studies (Glöckner & Betsch, 2008b), we compared information consideration and integration under time constraints in hidden and open versions of the information board tool (Figure 3). In one condition we used the standard version of the Mouselab. Accordingly, participants were presented with a hidden information board so that they could access values in the matrix only serially by using the computer mouse. In another condition, we employed an open information board. All entries to the matrix were shown on the screen so that motor behavior was not necessary to access information and the entire stimuli set could be inspected directly and easily. In all conditions, the columns of the matrix contained three options representing different food producers. The rows contained binary predictions from three testers concerning the quality of products (values) represented by the symbols + (good) and – (bad). The probability of being correct (cue validity) differed between the testers. Their cue validities ranged between .60 and .95 and were 283 BETSCH AND GLÖCKNER Downloaded By: [Betsch, Tilmann] At: 15:45 14 December 2010 Figure 3. Information board with hidden and open cells used in the studies by Glöckner and Betsch (2008b). randomly assigned to the position of the testers (cues) in the matrix. The choice task was to select the best producer by clicking on the option’s number with the computer mouse. We varied the patterns of values systematically to allow for a choice-based measure of strategy identification (see Glöckner & Betsch, 2008b, p. 1060; for discussions of the procedure; cf. Glöckner, 2009). In a first step, we assessed whether findings typically observed in Mouselab experiments could be replicated in our decision domain. In line with results reported in the literature, the majority of our participants (90%) used lexicographic strategies when making decisions in the standard Mouselab (hidden information) under time pressure. Participant choices across the different patterns of values indicated that they considered only a few pieces of information on the most important dimension (the cue with the highest validity) and ignored the others. Therefore, they seem to rely on only a subset of the given information. The pattern of results dramatically changed when information was presented in an open information board. Even in a very narrow time frame (less than 1.5 s), more than 70% of participants’ choices reflected an extensive consideration and integration of information. Specifically, their choices indicated that all cue validities and all cue values were integrated in line with a weighted summation model. In a further study, we instructed participants to make their decision by deliberatively integrating information according to such a weighted additive rule. It took these participants almost 20 s on average to perform the task. The results add to the existing evidence. They demonstrate that integration of information can happen in an extensive fashion. Most important, integration is performed in substantially less time compared to conditions in which participants were asked to deliberatively perform the same operations (weighting and adding). Thus, we concluded that information integration can be performed intuitively without requiring conscious, rule-based operations of weighting and adding. The findings corroborate our notion that intuitive processes can integrate information with284 out considerable mental effort. Of interest, these processes seem to operate in the background of conscious thought, because all participants deliberatively dealt with the decision problems. In the next section, we stretch our argument to an extreme. If it is true that intuitive processes can integrate information without considerable mental effort, processing time should be unaffected by the amount of information to be integrated. The Power of Intuition: When More Information Is Processed Faster Than Less Before we present the study (Glöckner & Betsch, 2010), we need to go into more detail regarding our theoretical framework for modelling intuition. Further, we also outline a connectionist model of information integration. According to this model, intuitive processes consider all information contained in a working network in parallel. They attempt to find a solution (e.g., a preference) that coheres to constraints imposed by the entire pattern of information, especially their relations among each other. In line with this reasoning, we propose that intuitive processes have another important characteristic. They are sensitive to the holistic aspect of the information sample, namely, the coherence in the pattern (note that this assumption dovetails with Gestalt theory). In coherent patterns, judgments and decisions are easier to make than in incoherent patterns. For example, if all arguments favor one option and speak against another, the choice is easy. However, if pros and cons are associated with both options, the choice is more difficult, even if normatively one option dominates the other. There is ample evidence indicating that the degree of coherence covaries with the time needed to arrive at a judgment or decision (Glöckner & Betsch, 2008b; Glöckner, Betsch, & Schindler, in press; Glöckner & Bröder, in press; Glöckner & Hodges, in press; Hilbig & Pohl, 2009; Hochman, Ayal, & Glöckner, 2010). Taking this evidence into account, INTUITION IN DECISION MAKING Table 1. Decision Tasks Used by Glöckner and Betsch (2010). Cue Patterns 1 Downloaded By: [Betsch, Tilmann] At: 15:45 14 December 2010 v A 2 B Regular: Complete decision tasks 0.80 + – 0.70 + – 0.60 + – 0.55 – + Reduced I: Decrease in coherence 0.80 + – 0.70 + – 0.60 0.55 – + Reduced II: Increase in coherence 0.80 + – 0.70 + – 0.60 + – 0.55 3 4 A B A B A B + + – – – – + + + – + – – + – + + – + – – – – + + – + – + – – – – – + + – + – + – + + + – – + – – + – – + – – – + + – + Note. A, B = options; v = cue validity. we predict that decision time should vary as function of coherence but not as a function of the amount of information. Specifically, if additional information increases coherence of the entire pattern, than decision time should decrease (despite the fact that there is more information to be processed). Conversely, if additional information decreases overall coherence, then decision time should increase (despite the fact that there is less information to be processed). We tested this hypothesized interaction effect in the following task. We used an open information board similar to the one just introduced, with four cues of different validity (55–80%) and two options (Glöckner & Betsch, 2010). The most valid cue always differentiated between the two options. Accordingly, a consistent application of a simple lexicographic strategy would result in constant decision time on average. Moreover, one option was always better than the other with regard to their weighted-additive value. As in the previous studies, we used different value patterns within subjects in order to allow for choice-based identification of strategies (see Table 1). As another within-subjects factor, we varied the amount and coherence of the given information pattern. In the control tasks, participants received the entire set of eight values with a moderate level of coherence. In two other conditions, two pieces of information (values on the least valid cue) were removed from the matrix (reduction of amount of information). In one of these conditions, the reduction increased coherence (a piece of contradicting information was removed), whereas in the other the reduction resulted in an decrease in coherence (a piece of supporting information was removed). We instructed participants to make decisions as quickly as possible and measured decision time as the main dependent variable. How should these manipulations affect decision time? First, a null effect might occur if participants tend to use a simple search strategy such as LEX (i.e., focus only on the most valid cue) in reaction to the speed instruction. Accordingly, reaction times should not be affected by variations of amount and coherence of information because the most valid cues always differed between options. Consequently, such a simple strategy would relieve individuals from considering information on the other cues. Second, if individuals applied a more complex strategy, a main effect for amount of information could occur. This prediction follows from multiple strategy models, which assume that processing of more information consumes more cognitive resources. Accordingly, decisions should take longer if participants must weight eight pieces of values with the corresponding cue validity compared to six values. Third, according to our prediction, an interaction effect should occur. Specifically, reaction times should decrease with increasing information if coherence increases as well. Conversely, reaction times should increase with increasing information if this entails a decrease in coherence. Indeed, we found the predicted interaction effect: A reduction of the amount of information resulted in an increase in decision time when coherence decreased. When the reduction of information was accompanied by a decrease of coherence, less information was processed more slowly than in the control condition containing the entire set of information. Thus, the findings support our prediction that more information can be processed more quickly than less information. The reported study provides further evidence for the advocated notion of intuition. Information integration and preference formation seem to be largely unaffected by the amount of encoded information and cognitive capacity. This conclusion seems to be in opposition to the dominant view in JDM research, holding that capacity constraints require decision makers to use simple strategies for judgment and choice. In the remainder of this article, we present some suggestion on the conceptual and theoretical level to solve this puzzle. We begin by reconsidering the fundaments of simple strategies (heuristics), the bounded rationality approach. The Notion of Cognitive Effort in the Bounded-Rationality Approach The bounded-rationality approach focuses on analytic or deliberate processes. As A. Newell and Simon (1972) stated, “We are observing intentionally rational 285 Downloaded By: [Betsch, Tilmann] At: 15:45 14 December 2010 BETSCH AND GLÖCKNER behavior” (p. 55). This focus of research is deeply rooted in Western philosophy and Christian religion. In accordance with the Cartesian view, decision making has been considered one of the supreme disciplines of conscious thought. Even believing in God was conceived as an act of rational choice (see Blaise Pascal’s “wager”). The maximization principle of utility theory pushes to the extreme the notion that decisions require (intense) deliberation. Simon doubted, however, whether the maximization principle could serve as a descriptive model of human decision making. He suspected that individuals must have supernatural computational powers to implement this principle. He referred to utility theory as an “Olympic model” (H. A. Simon, 1982) and questioned its descriptive validity: “My first empirical proposition is that there is a complete lack of evidence that, in actual choice situations of any complexity, these computations can be, or are in fact, performed” (H. A. Simon, 1955, p. 104). In developing his bounded rationality approach, Simon suggested that individuals do not strive to make the best decision but rather employ simple rules or strategies that allow them to achieve a satisficing level of accuracy by minimizing computational or cognitive effort. This notion exerted a strong impact on the field of psychological decision research. It stipulated the rise of multiple strategy models (e.g., Beach & Mitchell, 1978; Gigerenzer & Goldstein, 1996; Payne et al., 1993; see Betsch, Haberstroh, & Höhle, 2002, for an overview). These models converge in assuming that individuals can choose among a variety of strategies (or heuristics) for judgment and decision making. These strategies differ with regard to effort and accuracy. Individuals are assumed to select strategies contingent upon environmental, task, and personal factors. This approach still dominates the field of judgment and decision making (e.g., Gigerenzer & Selten, 2001). One guiding research question is how individuals make an adaptive compromise between the cognitive effort and the (potential) benefits of deliberation and accuracy of a decision. Therefore, it is essential for this approach to quantify cognitive effort (Payne, Bettman, & Johnson, 1992, p. 112ff). A. Newell and Simon (1972) suggested that decision processes can be decomposed into units, the so-called elementary information processes (EIP). Examples of EIP are “reading information”; “comparing values”; “eliminating values”; and processes of calculation such as “subtracting,” “adding,” and “multiplying.” Over the past decades, research in this domain has identified a plethora of decision rules or strategies that reduce the number of EIP compared to utility theory’s weighted-additive rule. These strategies, such as the LEX, elimination by aspect, and equal weight, allow individuals to achieve or sustain a moderate to high level of decision ac286 curacy even under processing constraints (e.g., time pressure, fatigue, distraction). Most notably, however, these strategies are shortcuts to deliberation. The idea of cognitive effort is still central and undisputed simply because other processes are rarely considered at the level of specific strategies (although they are sometimes considered on a higher level of strategy selection, e.g., Payne et al., 1993). According to the notion that human judgment and decision making is constrained by cognitive capacity, one must predict that increasing the amount of information to be processed will result in an increase in cognitive effort. In other words, extensive thinking is only possible to the degree that cognitive resources are available. The empirical evidence presented in this article seems to run counter to this major tenet of the bounded rationality approach. We demonstrated that individuals can integrate multiple pieces of encoded information very quickly and even under cognitive constraints. On the other hand, we must acknowledge the bulk of evidence corroborating the bounded rationality approach. It is a robust and well-replicated finding that individuals can and do employ strategies that use only subsets of the given information, especially in situations that constrain cognitive capacity (Dawes, 1998; Gigerenzer, 2004). Solving the Puzzle of Contradicting Evidence: Three Assumptions to Start With Our approach rests on three main assumptions. The first states that intuitive and analytic processes are distinct. They obey to markedly different cognitive principles and, hence, should be considered to have emergent properties. One far-fetching implication of this proposition is that intuition is not a shortcut to deliberation but something different. According to our view, most of the strategies identified in research on multiple strategy models are not intuitive strategies but rather simplification of analysis (e.g., LEX, Peak-And-End Heuristic; see Betsch, 2008, for a discussion). They circumvent effortful processing by reducing the amount of information and avoiding weighting and integration procedures. As such they are still informed by the spirit of rationalism, which assumes that decision making is a deliberate process. However, focusing on the conscious side only may lead us to neglect the fact that thinking also involves genuinely different processes. These are not subject to introspection; function without cognitive control; and, most important, exploit the powers of the brain to process information automatically and in parallel. Second, due to their different nature, intuitive and analytic processes have different potentials and suffer from different constraints. The “two blades of the scissor” view of the bounded rationality approach is an appropriate metaphor to describe the bottleneck for Downloaded By: [Betsch, Tilmann] At: 15:45 14 December 2010 INTUITION IN DECISION MAKING analytic processes. Because these are performed in a step-by-step fashion, they consume processing time and, hence, are under the governance of working memory constraints and factors of the environment that strain cognitive resources (the two “blades”). With respect to intuitive processes, however, other boundaries seem to apply. Whereas processes of information integration and preference formation seem to be quite immune to variations in amount of information and task constraints, pattern characteristics of the given information do matter. In our studies, the ease and speed of information integration was bounded by coherence in the pattern of encoded information. We also briefly mentioned another factor. If the individual attempts to control and deliberately guide these intuitive processes, their efficiency can be impaired (e.g., Betsch, Plessner, et al., 2004). Similar results can be found in the literature on human error (e.g., Reason, 1992). As such, the notion of boundaries is an important and valid one. Acknowledging that boundaries are process specific, however, we must extend our catalogues by those types of boundaries that apply to intuitive processes. Third, and most important, we assume that intuition and analyses are component processes rather than different modes of thinking. According to this view, a judgment or decision is not made in either the intuitive or analytic mode. Rather, intuition and analyses are assumed to be responsible for guiding different types of subprocesses (components). This view converges with recent developments in the literature on dual process models. Granting substantial empirical evidence, Ferreira, Garcia-Marques, Sherman, and Sherman (2006) concluded that “judgment under uncertainty is neither an automatic nor a controlled process but . . . reflects both processes, with each making independent contributions” (p. 798). We suggested that information integration and output formation (e.g., preference, choice) is performed by intuitive processes, whereas forming the input to integration often requires analysis. These analytic processes may involve directed search for information (e.g., looking for the most valid cues, asking an expert for advice), making sense of given information (e.g., assessing how given consequences affect personal goals), anticipating future events, making inferences to generate information, and so forth. As such, we conceive a judgment or decision as the product of the collaboration of intuition and analyses. Whereas the depth of analysis can vary, we assume that intuitive processes always work in the mental background even if the individual deliberatively faces a judgment or decision task (see also the notion of default-interventionist models by Evans, 2008). Therefore, these intuitive processes are inevitable. Preferences evolve even if the individual does not intend to form a preference (an old notion indeed, cf. Wundt, 1907; Zajonc, 1980). Applying the Component Approach to Understanding Thinking Under Boundaries One of the key assumptions of the bounded rationality approach and multiple strategy models states that strategies or heuristics are tools of adaptation. They allow individuals to maintain mastery in changing contexts by making satisfactory or even good compromises between the costs of thinking and desired accuracy in judgment or choice (Beach & Mitchell, 1978; Gigerenzer et al., 1999; Payne et al., 1988). First, let us reconsider the goals the individual is assumed to pursue in strategy selection. The bounded rationality approach assumes that constraints foster application of strategies that reduce the number of EIPs needed to make a decision. A straight means to achieve this goal is selective search. Accordingly, simple strategies (e.g., LEX) focus on only a few important pieces of information (e.g., outcomes on the most important attribute or most valid cue). Selective search reduces not only the number of EIPs needed to form the input to the choice but also the number of EIPs needed to transform the input to an output (e.g., a choice). In our component approach we assume that input and output formation is guided by genuinely different processes, analyses and intuition, respectively. In line with the bounded rationality approach, we also assume that the costs for analysis covary with the number of deliberate processing steps (EIPs) because these processes are performed step-by-step. In addition, we postulate that the costs for intuition do not systematically covary with the number of processing steps, because they can be performed in parallel. Moreover, we postulate that intuitive processes are governed by different types of constraints than analytic processes, such as holistic aspects of the information pattern (e.g., coherence). The bounded rationality approach and multiple strategy models predict commensurate effects of constraints on processing. They converge in assuming that constraining processing time or cognitive resources (e.g., via load manipulation) would both bound input and output formation. For instance, severe time pressure should increase the likelihood that strategies are employed, which reduce the amount of information and/or complexity of the decision rule. Because constraints have commensurate effects on all steps, it is possible to allocate resources in a cost-compensating fashion. For instance, the individual may first attempt to search as much information as possible, but then apply a very simple rule that considers only a small subset of the encoded information when time runs out (or vice versa). 287 Downloaded By: [Betsch, Tilmann] At: 15:45 14 December 2010 BETSCH AND GLÖCKNER In contrast, our component approach predicts orthogonal effects for different types of constraints. Accordingly, distinct types of factors independently constrain input and output formation. Therefore, compensation of costs between input and output processes is neither possible nor necessary. Limiting processing resources (time, capacity) will constrain only input but not output formation. Consequently, we predict that only input formation will covary as a function of limited resources. One puzzling finding in the area of multiple strategy research is that individuals use simple strategies (such as LEX) far less often than expected theoretically. Even in environments that ideally favor the application of such simple strategies (e.g., time pressure in a Mouselab decision task), there is still a substantial proportion of participants integrating information in a complex fashion (Bröder, 2003; Glöckner & Hodges, in press; B. R. Newell & Shanks, 2003). This finding is not surprising from the viewpoint of our component model. Once information has been fed into the processing system, intuition will use this sample of information irrespective of amount and capacity. Individuals seem to have an intuitive understanding of the potentials of their intuition. They do not spare their mind but often seem to get as much information as possible. Applying measures for strategy identification based on choices, decision times, and confidence show that they regularly use and integrate the entire set of encoded information (e.g., Glöckner, 2009; Glöckner & Bröder, in press). What happens if we release boundaries on input formation so that information acquisition consumes only minimal resources? Recall that multiple strategy models still predict that costs will increase with increasing amounts of information, because integrating involves costly EIPs as well. In our decision studies, we created such an easy-access situation using an open information board. Outcome information was binary and depicted in symbols (+, –). Only cue validities were shown as numbers. For simplicity, assume that the costs for input formation are minimal in this case. Thus, processing time (as an indicator of cognitive effort) should vary only with effort invested in output formation. In contrast to this prediction of the multiple strategy models, we found no main effect for amount of information. Rather we found that processing time covaried with holistic pattern characteristics. This finding nicely corroborates the component model predicting that different factors constrain analyses and intuition in an orthogonal fashion. This brief discussion may illustrate how the bounded rationality approach can be fruitfully advanced by a component view assuming that intuition and analysis refer to different components rather than to different types of strategies. 288 Toward an Integrative Model of Judgment and Decision Making The literature on judgment and decision making hosts descriptions of a plethora of strategies and heuristics. Each strategy is a combination of processes, consisting of different rules for information search, comparison, integration, termination, and choice (so-called building blocks; Gigerenzer et al., 1999). The model outlined in the following starts with the assumption that there is only one all-purpose rule for integration and choice (for similar assertions of single strategy models, see Lee & Cummins, 2004; B. R. Newell, 2005) but that there are different rules for search, generation, and change of information. In other words, we assume that individuals use different strategies for input formation but that they apply a general, multifunctional mechanism for output formation. This mechanism is assumed to obey to the principles we described as the characteristics of intuition. It operates unintentionally and automatically, and it processes information in parallel. We suggest that this mechanism can be understood and formally described in terms of a connectionist model. This assertion, however, does not preclude that there might also be other automatic mechanisms involved in decision making (see Glöckner & Witteman, 2010a, for a discussion). Connectionist models have been applied to a variety of areas in cognition such as reading (McClelland & Rumelhart, 1981), explanatory coherence (Thagard, 1989), attribution (Read & Marcus-Newhall, 1993), stereotyping (Kunda & Thagard, 1996), and decision making (e.g., Glöckner et al., in press; Holyoak & Simon, 1999; Thagard & Millgram, 1995). In recent articles, we advanced a specific version of the connectionist approach, the parallel-constraint-satisfaction (PCS) model, to apply to multiattribute decision making (Betsch, 2005; Glöckner & Betsch, 2008a). In the following sections, we sketch the major assumptions of our advanced PCS model and discuss some implications and empirical predictions. Input: The Working Network The connectionist approach uses a network metaphor to model how information is represented in the mind (Holyoak & Spellman, 1993). Elements (nodes) and weights on the connections between the elements form the structure of the network. A working network represents the decision at stake. It contains features of the situation, options, goals, and outcome information (see symbolic connectionism; Holyoak, 1991). It may also contain other pieces of information that have been recently encoded or activated from memory. Connections between the elements can represent their learned relation reflecting, for instance, covariation, rates of reinforcement and punishment, logical INTUITION IN DECISION MAKING relations such as negation or causation, and so forth. Formally, these relations are expressed by positive or negative weights on the connections. When activation is passed through the network, a positive weight causes activation and a negative weight causes deactivation of a linked element. Downloaded By: [Betsch, Tilmann] At: 15:45 14 December 2010 Output: Application of the PCS Rule A decision is made by applying a PCS rule (see Read, Vanman, & Miller, 1997, for an excellent introduction). Information is passed in parallel through the network. The activations of the elements are simultaneously updated and constrained by the given structure of weights in the working network. By iterating this updating process, the PCS rule strives for a solution in which all elements optimally cohere with all other elements taking into account the constraints in the network in a parallel manner. This occurs in an iterative process of updating node activations. In most simple networks, activation of all nodes reaches an asymptotic level after a small number of iterations and the process is terminated. Activations of elements are used as the basis for judgments or decisions. In the case of decisions, the options with the highest activation will be chosen (see Betsch, 2005, for a variant of this rule). In the case of making a judgment about a single object on a certain criterion dimension, estimations reflect the strength of the element’s activation. Bottlenecks to the PCS Process Because the PCS rule attempts to maximize coherence, the effectiveness and speed of this process is mainly dependent on the holistic characteristics of the information pattern but not on the number of elements. If there is already a high level of coherence, the PCS rule needs only a few iterations to arrive at a solution. Accordingly, those decisions can be made very quickly regardless of the amount of information contained in the working network. On the other hand, if initial coherence in the pattern is low (e.g., because there is contradicting evidence activating and deactivating options at the same time), it will take the PCS rule more iterations to change the pattern in order to achieve coherence. On the phenomenological level, incoherence will manifest itself in extension of time needed to make a decision. Iterations in a PCS network have been proven to be a good predictor for decision times even on an individual level (Glöckner & Bröder, in press; Glöckner & Hodges, in press). In a network structure with a high degree of contradiction and/or high desired level of coherence (threshold θ ; Glöckner & Betsch, 2008a), PCS can fail to reach a solution of acceptable coherence. Under such condition the network must be restructured (see next). There are other bottlenecks that are due to analytic thinking. We noted earlier that trying to supervise intuition may decrease its effectiveness. In the experiments on implicit formation of preferences (Betsch, Plessner, & Schallies, 2004, for an overview), we found that trying to explicitly form a preference hindered participants from reproducing their intuitively formed pattern of preferences that so closely mirrored their actual experiences. Recall the assumed functioning of PCS. By parallel passing of activation, the activation of elements is changed to satisfy the characteristics of the entire pattern of interrelations among elements (the structure of weights in the network). The resulting activation of an element emerges within the network as a result of an iterative updating process. Analytic thinking is a process by which the focus of attention is directed to elements of the network. In terms of connectionist modeling, the focused element receives a dramatic change in activation from outside the network. These changes may help or hinder PCS to reach a solution. If the individual focuses pieces of information that, for instance, promote the dominating option, than PCS can jump toward termination. However, if the focused elements are those that need to be deactivated to achieve coherence, analytic thinking bugs PCS. In the case of our studies, individuals could not systematically access relevant characteristics of prior outcome distributions. Therefore, attentional focus (explicitly considering certain outcomes) may have varied randomly and diluted or even destroyed appropriate differences in the activations of the options. The Algebra of Intuitive Processing PCS employs a nonlinear rule for cue activation (i.e., a sigmoid activation function; McClelland & Rumelhart, 1981). Nevertheless, simulated distributions of the output of this process converge with those produced by a weighted summation (or weighted additive rule; cf. Glöckner & Herbold, in press; Glöckner & Hodges, in press). The results from simulation converge with empirical findings. For judgments it has been shown that they can be approximated well by a weighted linear model (see Brehmer, 1994; Hammond, Hamm, Grassia, & Pearson, 1987; Karelaia & Hogarth, 2008). We also found that evaluations reflect the sum of all values of prior experiences with the target object and not only their numerosity (e.g., Betsch et al., 2001). In our decision studies with an open information board, even decisions under time pressure showed that the pattern of choices mapped on the differences between the alternatives in terms of their weighted sum of values (Glöckner & Betsch, 2008a, 2008b, 2010). Furthermore, it should be mentioned that, in strong support of the PCS perspective, a coherence effect, that is, a systematic reevaluation of evidence in 289 BETSCH AND GLÖCKNER favor of the leading option in the decision process, has been demonstrated in many kinds of decision tasks (e.g., DeKay, Patino-Echeverri, & Fischbeck, 2009a, 2009b; Glöckner et al., in press; Holyoak & Simon, 1999; Russo, Carlson, Meloy, & Yong, 2008; Russo, Meloy, & Medvec, 1998; Russo, Medvec , & Meloy, 1996; D. Simon, Krawczyk, & Holyoak, 2004; D. Simon, Pham, Le, & Holyoak, 2001; D. Simon, Snow & Read, 2004, for similar earlier theoretical approaches; see also Montgomery, 1989; Svenson, 1992). Furthermore, recent findings indicate that arousal does indeed increase with decreasing coherence in decision tasks as suggested by PCS models (Glöckner & Hochman, in press; Hochman et al., 2010). Downloaded By: [Betsch, Tilmann] At: 15:45 14 December 2010 The Interplay of Analytic and Intuitive Processes PCS processes are assumed to function by default, regardless of whether analytic processes are used additionally (for an overview of other recent defaultinterventionist models, see Evans, 2008). According to the component view, intuitive and analytic processes serve different functions. We described the interplay between these processes in detail in a previous paper (Glöckner & Betsch, 2008a). We referred to analytic operations as processes of deliberate construction (DC). DC involves input formation such as active information search, generation, and change. In our PCS model, we assumed that DC is not a necessary condition for reaching a decision. Sometimes, salient information in the environment and accessible information from memory will provide an input sample of information that suffices to reach the necessary level of coherence for a judgment or decision to be made. This may be primarily the case for many routine decision situations that typically do not require additional information search and generation. In other situations, DC will always be involved. For example, in the Mouselab used in decision research, the options are unfamiliar to the participant and information is hidden in a matrix. Under such conditions, a working network must be actively formed prior to PCS processing. In the remainder of this section we outline two examples of how intuitive and analytic processes interact. An important potential of DC is to change information temporarily in an intended direction. Intuition, on the contrary, does not have such powers. Specifically, PCS processes can change only activations, not the structure of the network. Many aspects of the network stem from prior learning. For example, a strong positive weight on a relation between an option and a goal may reflect reinforcement history. Such weights provide the given constraints under which PCS must find a solution. If decisions were solely guided by PCS, individuals would have difficulty instantly adapting to changes in the world that render prior behavior obso290 lete. However, weights can be temporarily changed by DC (whereas lasting changes might require feedback learning). Assume an individual consciously realizes that a routine behavior is inappropriate under the given decision situation. This change in perceived instrumentality can be modeled as a change of the weights on the association between the goals and the behavior. Maintaining this change, however, requires cognitive control and, hence, cognitive effort. Factors that additionally consume cognitive resources reduce the likelihood that changes can be maintained during a decision. The lower the capacity for deliberative control over the representation of the decision problem, the higher the likelihood that weights will reach their prior state. Hence, one would predict that deviation from a decision routine under altered situational conditions requires DC processes to function effectively, a prediction that is strongly corroborated by the evidence (e.g., Betsch, Fiedler, & Brinkmann, 1998; Betsch, Haberstroh, & Höhle, 2004). This example shows how intuitive and analytic processes both have their specific powers. Their interaction and collaboration is necessary to promote adaptive decision making. By now, we have considered only situations in which the input (working network) allows for effective application and termination of PCS processes. What happens, however, if PCS fails to achieve an acceptable level of coherence in the network (i.e., coherence is below the aspired threshold)? In our PCS model, we assumed that failure to achieve coherence is an endogenous factor that instigates DC operations (Glöckner & Betsch, 2008a). We assumed that upon failure a secondary working network is constituted containing DC operations and strategies as options. Again, the PCS rule is applied to this secondary network to select a DC operation, which is then applied to change the primary network representing the original decision problem. Although these assumptions are not yet formally implemented in the model, they provide a starting point for theoretically modeling the selection of strategies for information search and change. Directions for Future Research The majority of studies on JDM still employ written descriptions of relevant information. For instance, the gambling paradigm (the “drosophila” of decision research, cf. W. M. Goldstein & Hogarth, 1997) provides individuals with stated probabilities and stated values. In this paradigm, encoding of information systematically involves only one channel. Moreover, the individual can rely only on the (new) stimulus information from the environment and not on prior knowledge. Conversely, in natural settings, decision information stems from multiple sources and can be simultaneously Downloaded By: [Betsch, Tilmann] At: 15:45 14 December 2010 INTUITION IN DECISION MAKING encoded via multiple channels (e.g., visual, auditory, memory). For example, assume you visit a restaurant with friends. The menu contains pictures of the different dishes and written description of their ingredients. Moreover, your friends comment on the menu, utter their own preferences, and may evoke examples of their prior experiences. You can additionally capitalize on your experiences with eating similar dishes that come to your mind easily in form of cognitive and affective representations. In such a situation, input information to the decision is fed through multiple channels (oral, visual, memory). Different types of information are encoded simultaneously. In a relatively effortless fashion, you are provided with a rich informational base for your decision. In these and similar situations that are encountered frequently in everyday life, intuition can reveal its powers. Integration and preference formation happens en passant. Unfortunately, multimodal situations are as of yet very rarely considered in decision research. The naturalistic decision-making approach must be mentioned as an exception (Klein, 1999; Klein, Orasanu, Calderwood, & Zsambock, 1993). Studies in this area are often conducted in the field yet suffer from insufficient experimental control. Change and development of research tools toward multimodal stimulus presentation is both a challenging and promising task for the future. The processes of intuitive thinking do not apply only to judgment and decision making. The connectionist approach views these processes as fundamental to many areas of cognition including, for instance, perception and speech comprehension. Accordingly, one should expect that extensive integration of information can be performed by decision makers from an early stage on. For example, preschool children who already do well in speech comprehension should be capable of applying the PCS rule to decisions without effort and instruction. Unfortunately, we still know little about how children make decisions. Most decision research with children is conducted and published in the field of developmental psychology (e.g., Davidson & Hudson, 1988; Gao, Li, Bai, Lin, & Wei, 2009; Knight, Berning, Wilson, & Chao, 1987; Schlottmann, 2001). Members of the JDM community only occasionally study child decision making (e.g., Levin, Weller, Pederson & Harshman, 2007; Reyna & Ellis, 1994). We see much merit in extending this line of research with a stronger focus on how children intuitively integrate information. We believe that valuable lessons about intuitions and analysis can be learned in this domain (cf. Jacobs & Klaczynski, 2005). The few studies that use functional measurement in nonadult participants provide first evidence in favor of our notion assuming that integration of multiple pieces of information can be easily performed even from an early age (e.g., Ebersbach, 2009; Schlottmann, 2001). For example, Ebersbach (2009) demonstrated that kindergarten children show remarkabe capabilities of spontaneously integrating three orthogonally varying stimulus dimensions in their judgments of volume. To drive this argument to the extreme, many studies show that even monkeys (Platt & Glimcher, 1999) and sticklebacks (Künzler & Bakker, 2001) make choices indicating an integration of information in a weighted compensatory manner. Research and theorizing in the field of judgment and decision making might benefit from acknowledging these findings. Conclusion According to the advocated approach to intuition, not all processes of thinking are constrained by limits of computational capabilities. We suggested that intuition can capitalize on the powers of autonomous, automatic, nonintentional processes that are characterized by parallel processing. These parallel processes are much less constrained by the amount of information. Extensive consideration of multiple pieces of information can happen in an astoundingly narrow time frame. We suggested that intuitive processes are responsible for transforming a sample of input information into an output (judgment, choice). We claimed that there are not two modes of thinking that can be used alternatively. Rather, we propose that intuitive and analytic processes are components that operate together to form judgment and decisions. Such a component view can be integrated in a connectionist model to decision making. We showed that such a model helps to advance the bounded rationality approach as well as our understanding of strategic adaptation to situational changes. Note Address correspondence to Tilmann Betsch, Department of Psychology, University of Erfurt, Nordhauser Strasse 63, D-99089 Erfurt, Germany. E-mail: tilmann.betsch@uni-erfurt.de References Acker, F. (2008). New findings on unconscious versus conscious thought in decision making: Additional empirical data and meta-analysis. Judgment and Decision Making, 3, 292–303. Amenta, S., & Balconi, M. (2008). Understanding irony: An ERP analysis on the elaboration of acoustic ironic statements. Neuropsychological Trends, 3, 7–27. Beach, L. R., & Mitchell, T. R. (1978). A contingency model for the selection of decision strategies. Academy Management Review, 3, 439–449. Betsch, T. (2005). Preference theory—An affect-based approach to recurrent decision making. In T. Betsch & S. Haberstroh (Eds.), 291 Downloaded By: [Betsch, Tilmann] At: 15:45 14 December 2010 BETSCH AND GLÖCKNER The routines of decision making (pp. 39–65). Mahwah, NJ: Erlbaum. Betsch, T. (2008). The nature of intuition and its neglect in research on judgment and decision making. In H. Plessner, C. Betsch, & T. Betsch (Eds.), Intuition in judgment and decision making (pp. 3–22). New York, NY: Erlbaum. Betsch, T., Fiedler, K., & Brinkmann, B. J. (1998). Behavioral routines in decision making: The effects of novelty in task presentation and time pressure on routine maintenance and deviation. European Journal of Social Psychology, 28, 861–878. Betsch, T., Haberstroh, S., & Höhle, C. (2002). Explaining routinized decision making—A review of theories and models. Theory and Psychology, 12, 453–488. Betsch, T., Haberstroh, S., Molter, B., & Glöckner, A. (2004). Oops, I did it again—Relapse errors in routinized decision making. Organizational Behavior and Human Decision Processes, 93, 62–74. Betsch, T., Hoffmann, K., Hoffrage, U., & Plessner, H. (2003). Intuition beyond recognition: When less familiar events are liked more. Experimental Psychology, 50, 49–54. Betsch, T., Kaufmann, M., Lindow, F., Plessner, H., & Hoffmann, K. (2006). Different principles of information aggregation in implicit and explicit attitude formation. European Journal of Social Psychology, 36, 887–905. Betsch, T., Plessner, H., & Schallies, E. (2004). The value-account model of attitude formation. In G. R. Maio & G. Haddock (Eds.), Contemporary perspectives on the psychology of attitudes (pp. 251–273). Hove, UK: Psychology Press. Betsch, T., Plessner, H., & Schallies, E. (2004). The value-account model of attitude formation. In G. R. Maio & G. Haddock (eds.), Contemporary perspectives on the psychology of attitudes (pp. 251–273). London, UK: Psychology Press. Betsch, T., Plessner, H., Schwieren, C., & Gütig, R. (2001). I like it but I don’t know why: A value-account approach to implicit attitude formation. Personality and Social Psychology Bulletin, 27, 242–253. Brehmer, B. (1994). The psychology of linear judgement models. Acta Psychologica, 87, 137–154. Bröder, A. (2003). Decision making with the “adaptive toolbox”: Influence of environmental structure, intelligence, and working memory load. Journal of Experimental Psychology: Learning, Memory, and Cognition, 29, 611–625. Chaiken, S., & Trope, Y. (Eds.), (1999). Dual-process theories in social psychology. New York, NY: Guilford. Davidson, D., & Hudson, J. (1988). The effects of decision reversibility and decision importance on children’s decision making. Journal of Experimental Child Psychology, 46, 35–40. Dawes, R. M. (1998). Behavioral decision making and judgment. In D. T. Gilbert, S. T. Fiske, & G. Lindzey (Eds.), The handbook of social psychology—Fourth edition (Vol. 1, pp. 497–548). Boston: McGraw-Hill. DeKay, M. L., Patino-Echeverri, D., & Fischbeck, P. S. (2009a). Better safe than sorry: precautionary reasoning and implied dominance in risky decisions. Journal of Behavioral Decision Making, 22, 338–361. DeKay, M. L., Patino-Echeverri, D., & Fischbeck, P. S. (2009b). Distortion of probability and outcome information in risky decisions. Organizational Behavior and Human Decision Processes, 109, 79–92. Dijksterhuis, A. (2004). Think different: The merits of unconscious though in preference development and decision making. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 87, 586–598. Dijksterhuis, A., Bos, M. W., Nordgren, L. F., & van Baaren, R. B. (2006). On making the right choice: The deliberation-withoutattention effect. Science, 311, 1005–1007. Ebersbach, M. (2009). Achieving a new dimension: Children integrate three stimulus dimensions in volume estimations. Developmental Psychology, 45, 877–883. 292 Epstein, S. (2008). Intuition from the perspective of cognitiveexperiential self-theory. In H. Plessner, C. Betsch, & T. Betsch (Eds.), Intuition in judgment and decision making (pp. 23–37). New York, NY: Erlbaum. Evans, J. S. B. T. (2008). Dual-processing accounts of reasoning, judgment, and social cognition. Annual Review of Psychology, 59, 255–278. Ferreira, M. B., Garcia-Marques, L., Sherman, S. J., & Sherman, J. W. (2006). Automatic and controlled components of judgment and decision making. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 91, 797–813. Gao, G., Li, H., Bai, J., Lin, C., & Wei, Y. (2009). Young children’s affective decision-making in a gambling task: Does difficulty in learning the gain/loss schedule matter? Cognitive Development, 24, 183–191. Gibbs, R. W., & Colston, H. L. (Eds.). (2007). Irony in language and thought: A cognitive science reader. Mahwah, NJ: Erlbaum. Gigerenzer, G. (2004). Fast and frugal heuristics: The tools of bounded rationality. In D. Koehler & N. Harvey (Eds.), Handbook of judgment and decision making (pp. 62–88). Oxford, UK: Blackwell. Gigerenzer, G. (2007). Gut feelings. The intelligence of the unconscious. New York: Viking. Gigerenzer, G., & Goldstein, D. G. (1996). Reasoning the fast and frugal way: Models of bounded rationality. Psychological Review, 103, 650–669. Gigerenzer, G., & Selten, R. (Eds.). (2001). Bounded rationality— The adaptive toolbox. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press. Gigerenzer, G., Todd, P. M., and the ABC Research Group (1999). Simple heuristics that make us smart. Oxford, UK: Oxford University Press. Gilovich, T., Griffin, D., & Kahneman, D. (Eds.). (2002). Heuristics and biases: The psychology of intuitive judgment. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press. Glöckner, A. (2009). Investigating intuitive and deliberate processes statistically: The Multiple-Measure Maximum Likelihood strategy classification method. Judgment and Decision Making, 4, 186–199. Glöckner, A., & Betsch, T. (2008a). Modelling option and strategy choices with connectionist networks: Towards an integrative model of automatic and deliberate decision making. Judgment and Decision Making, 3, 215–228. Glöckner, A., & Betsch, T. (2008b). Multiple-reason decision making based on automatic processing. Journal of Experimental Psychology: Learning, Memory and Cognition, 34, 1055–1075. Glöckner, A., & Betsch, T. (2010). Decisions beyond boundaries: When more information is processed faster than less. Manuscript submitted for publication. Glöckner, A., Betsch, T., & Schindler, N. (in press). Construction of probabilistic inferences by constraint satisfaction. Journal of Behavioral Decision Making. Glöckner, A., & Bröder, A. (in press). Processing of recognition information and additional cues: A model-based analysis of choice, confidence, and response time. Judgment and Decision Making. Glöckner, A., & Herbold, A.-K. (in press). An eye-tracking study on information processing in risky decisions: Evidence for compensatory strategies based on automatic processes. Journal of Behavioral Decision Making. Glöckner, A., & Hochman, G. (in press). The interplay of experiencebased affective and probabilistic cues in decision making: Arousal increases when experience and additional cues conflict. Experimental Psychology. Glöckner, A., & Hodges, S. D. (in press). Parallel constraint satisfaction in memory-based decisions. Experimental Psychology. Glöckner, A., & Witteman, C. L. M. (2010a). Beyond dual-process models: A categorization of processes underlying intuitive judgment and decision making. Thinking & Reasoning, 16, 1–25. Downloaded By: [Betsch, Tilmann] At: 15:45 14 December 2010 INTUITION IN DECISION MAKING Glöckner, A., & Witteman, C. L. M. (Eds.). (2010b). Foundations for tracing intuition: Challenges and methods. London: Psychology Press. Goldstein, D. G., & Gigerenzer, G. (2002). Models of ecological rationality: The recognition heuristic. Psychological Review, 109, 75–90. Goldstein, W. M., & Hogarth, R. M. (1997). Judgment and decision research: Some historical context. In W. M. Goldstein & R. M. Hogarth (Ed.), Research on judgment and decision making: Currents, connections and controversies (pp. 3–65). Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press. Gonzalez-Vallejo, C., Lassiter, G. D., Belleza, F., & Lindberg, M. J. (2008). “Save angels perhaps”: A critical examination of Unconscious Thought Theory and the Deliberation-Without Intention Effect. Review of General Psychology, 12, 282– 296. Hammond, K. R., Hamm, R. M., Grassia, J., & Pearson, T. (1987). Direct comparison of the efficacy of intuitive judgment and analytical cognition in expert judgment. IEEE Transactions on Systems, Man, and Cybernetics, 17, 753–770. Hilbig, B. E., & Pohl, R. F. (2009). Ignorance- versus evidencebased decision making: A decision time analysis of the recognition heuristic. Journal of Experimental Psychology: Learning, Memory, and Cognition, 35, 1296–1305. Hochman, G., Ayal, S., & Glöckner, A. (2010). Physiological arousal in processing recognition information: Ignoring or integrating cognitive cues? Judgment and Decision Making, 5, 285– 299. Holyoak, K. J. (1991). Symbolic connectionism: Toward thirdgeneration theories of expertise. In K. A. Ericsson & J. Smith (Eds.), Toward a general theory of expertise (pp. 301–336). Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press. Holyoak, K. J., & Simon, D. (1999). Bidirectional reasoning in decision making by constraint satisfaction. Journal of Experimental Psychology: General, 128(1), 3–31. Holyoak, K. J., & Spellman, B. A. (1993). Thinking. Annual Review of Psychology, 44, 265–315. Jacobs, J. E., & Klaczynski, P. A. (Eds.). (2005). The development of judgement and decision making in children and adolescents. Mahwah, NJ: Erlbaum. Johnson, E. J., Payne, J. W., Schkade, D. A., & Bettman, J. R. (1986). Monitoring information processing and decisions: The mouselab system. Unpublished manuscript, Center for Decision Studies, Fuqua School of Business, Duke University, Durham, NC. Kahneman, D., & Klein, G. (2009). Conditions for intuitive expertise: A failure to disagree. American Psychologist, 64, 515–526. Kahneman, D., Slovic, P., & Tversky, A. (Eds.). (1982). Judgment under uncertainty: Heuristics and biases. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press. Karelaia, N., & Hogarth, R. M. (2008). Determinants of linear judgment: A meta-analysis of lens model studies. Psychological Bulletin, 134, 404–426. Kaufmann, M., & Betsch, T. (2009). Origins of the sample-size effect in explicit evaluative judgments. Experimental Psychology, 56, 344–353. Klein, G. (1999). Sources of power. How people make decisions. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press. Klein, G., Orasanu, J., Calderwood, R., & Zsambock, C. E. (1993). Decision making in action: models and methods. Norwood, NJ: Ablex. Knight, G. P., Berning, A. L., Wilson, S. L., & Chao, C.-C. (1987). The effects of information-processing demands and socialsituational factors on the social decision making of children. Journal of Experimental Child Psychology, 43, 244–259. Künzler, R., & Bakker, C. M. (2001). Female preferences for single and combined traits in computeranimated stickleback males. Behavioral Ecology, 12, 681–685. Kunda, Z., & Thagard, P. (1996). Forming impressions from stereotypes, traits, and behaviors: A parallel-constraint-satisfaction theory. Psychological Review, 103, 284–208. Lee, M. D., & Cummins, T. D. R. (2004). Evidence accumulation in decision making: Unifying the “take the best” and the “rational” models. Psychonomic Bulletin & Review, 11, 343–352. Levin, I. P., Weller, J. A., Pederson, A. A., & Harshman, L. A. (2007). Age-related differences in adaptive decision making: Sensitivity to expected value in risky choice. Judgment and Decision Making, 2, 225–233. Long, D. L., & Graesser, A. C. (1988). Wit and humour in discourse processes. Discourse Process, 11, 35–60. McClelland, J. L., & Rumelhart, D. E. (1981). An interactive activation model of context effects in letter perception: I. An account of basic findings. Psychological Review, 88, 375–407. Montgomery, H. (1989). From cognition to action: The search for dominance in decision making. In H. Montgomery & O. Svenson (Eds.), Process and structure in human decision making (pp. 23–49). Oxford, UK: Wiley & Sons. Newell, A., & Simon, H. A. (1972). Human problem solving. Englewood Cliffs, NJ: Prentice Hall. Newell, B. R. (2005). Re-visions of rationality? Trends in Cognitive Sciences, 9, 11–15. Newell, B. R., & Shanks, D. R. (2003). Take the best or look at the rest? Factors influencing “one-reason” decision making. Journal of Experimental Psychology: Learning, Memory and Cognition, 29, 53–65. Payne, J. W., Bettman, J. R., & Johnson, E. J. (1988). Adaptive strategy selection in decision making. Journal of Experimental Psychology: Learning, Memory and Cognition, 14, 534–552. Payne, J. W., Bettman, J. R., & Johnson, E. J. (1992). Behavioral decision research: A constructive processing perspective. Annual Review of Psychology, 43, 87–131. Payne, J. W., Bettman, J. R., & Johnson, E. J. (1993). The adaptive decision maker. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press. Platt, M. L., & Glimcher, P. W. (1999). Neural correlates of decision variables in parietal cortex. Nature, 400, 233–238. Plessner, H., Betsch, C., &.Betsch, T. (Eds.). (2008). Intuition in judgment and decision making. New York, NY: Erlbaum. Plessner, H., Betsch, T., Schallies, E., & Schwieren, C. (2008). Automatic online formation of implicit attitudes towards politicians as a basis for intuitive voting behaviour. In H. Plessner, C. Betsch, &T. Betsch (Eds.), Intuition in judgment and decision Making (pp. 107–117). New York, NY: Erlbaum. Read, S. J., & Marcus-Newhall, A. (1993). Explanatory coherence in social explanations: A parallel distributed processing account. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 65, 429–447. Read, S. J., Vanman, E. J., & Miller, L. C. (1997). Connectionism, parallel constraint satisfaction, and Gestalt principles: (Re) Introducing cognitive dynamics to social psychology. Personality and Social Psychology Review, 1, 26–53. Reason, J. (1992). Human error. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press. Reyna, V. F., & Ellis, S. C. (1994). Fuzzy-trace theory and framing e?ects in children’s risky decision making. Psychological Science, 5, 275–279. Russo, J. E., Carlson, K. A., Meloy, M. G., & Yong, K. (2008). The goal of consistency as a cause of information distortion. Journal of Experimental Psychology: General, 137, 456–470. Russo, J., Medvec, V., & Meloy, M. (1996). The distortion of information during decisions. Organizational Behavior and Human Decision Processes, 66, 102–110. Russo, J. E., Meloy, M. G., & Medvec, V. H. (1998). Predecisional distortion of product information. Journal of Marketing Research, 35, 438–452. Schlottmann, A. (2001). Children’s probability intuitions: Understanding the expected value of complex gambles. Child Development, 72(1), 103–122. 293 BETSCH AND GLÖCKNER Downloaded By: [Betsch, Tilmann] At: 15:45 14 December 2010 Schwoebel, J., Dews, S., Winner, E., & Srinivas, K. (2000). Obligatory processing of the Literal meaning of ironic utterances: Further evidence. Metaphor and Symbol, 15, 47–61. Simon, D., Krawczyk, D. C., & Holyoak, K. J. (2004). Construction of preferences by constraint satisfaction. Psychological Science, 15, 331–336. Simon, D., Pham, L. B., Le, Q. A., & Holyoak, K. J. (2001). The emergence of coherence over the course of decision making. Journal of Experimental Psychology: Learning, Memory, and Cognition, 27, 1250–1260. Simon, D., Snow, C. J., & Read, S. J. (2004). The redux of cognitive consistency theories: Evidence judgments by constraint satisfaction. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 86, 814–837. Simon, H. A. (1955). A behavioral model of rational choice. The Quarterly Journal of Economics, 69, 99–118. Simon, H. A. (1982). Models of bounded rationality. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press. Svenson, O. (1992). Differentiation and consolidation theory of human decision making: A frame of reference for the study of pre- and post-decision processes. Acta Psychologica, 80, 143– 168. 294 Thagard, P. (1989). Explanatory coherence. Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 12, 435–502. Thagard, P., & Millgram, E. (1995). Inference to the best plan: A coherence theory of decision. In A. Ram & D. B. Leake (Eds.), Goal-driven learning (pp. 439–454). Cambridge, MA: MIT Press. Thomas, D. (1968). A child’s christmas in Wales. London, UK: J.M. Dent. Tversky, A., & Kahneman, D. (1973). Availability: A heuristic for judging frequency and probability. Cognitive Psychology, 5, 207–232. Tversky, A., & Kahneman, D. (1974). Judgment under uncertainty: Heuristics and biases. Science, 185, 1124–1131. Wang, A. T., Lee, S. S., Sigman, M., & Dapretto, M. (2006). Neural basis of irony comprehension in children with autism: the role of prosody and context. Brain, 12, 932–943. Winerman, L. (2005). Intuition [Special issue]. APA Monitor on Psychology, 36(3). Wundt, W. (1907). Outlines of psychology. Leipzig, Germany: Wilhelm Engelmann. Zajonc, R. B. (1980). Feeling and thinking: Preferences need no inferences. American Psychologist, 35, 151–175.