Author: Marinus Schoeman Affiliation: Associate professor, Department of Philosophy, University of Pretoria, South Africa Email address: marinus.schoeman@up.ac.za Title: Overcoming resentment. Hannah Arendt on the virtue of forgiveness. Abstract: This paper explores Hannah Arendt’s view on the virtue of forgiveness. For Arendt a truly ethical or virtuous life is one that displays strength of character and greatness or generosity of spirit (magnanimity). As such it is the exact opposite of resentment and meanness of spirit. Forgiveness, together with trustworthiness (the capacity to make and to keep promises), constitute for Arendt the highest “principles” of action. The capacities of promising and forgiving do not only impart stability and durability to our actions, but they give us, in the first place, the confidence to act at all. Cultivating the capacities of promising and forgiving can thus be viewed as the highest expression of (and the most fundamental precondition for) virtue. According to Arendt, nothing on earth can be more ethical or more virtuous than helping to create a situation in which it becomes possible for people to go on with their lives, to make a fresh start in all candidness without being constantly plagued by feelings of guilt and remorse. For Arendt revengefulness is the opposite of forgiveness. It represents the worst of all vices, mainly because it is purely reactive, unable to initiate anything new or creative. Hence, the basic concern of Arendt is to devise strategies towards overcoming resentment and revengefulness. These strategies will be discussed in some detail, with particular attention to Arendt’s criticism of moral sentiments such as pity and compassion, as well as the egalitarian view of social justice. Keywords: Hannah Arendt, virtue, action, forgiveness, moralism, pity, compassion, resentment, revengefulness. ------------------This paper is about the German-Jewish born philosopher and political thinker Hannah Arendt (1906-1975) and her views on the virtue of forgiveness. For Arendt the term “virtue” applies only to the domain of action (in contrast to social behaviour and inner motives or dispositions). Virtuous actions are “great” in the sense that they are unique or extraordinary. Their meaning (ethical relevance) must also be understood in a performative (a-teleological) sense: it lies in the performance of the action itself, and not in its motives or consequences. Virtuous actions have their value or meaning in themselves, thus they should not be judged according to external norms such as moral prescriptions or utility. An action is virtuous if it is performed in a virtuosic fashion, hence it can manifest itself only in the public sphere, i.e. where others are present as spectators, as an audience, or as co-actors, and for Arendt this is the political sphere par excellence. This implies that no uniform or universal prescriptions for 1 virtuous actions can apply, because they are accomplished every time in a unique way (and within ever changing contexts) by exceptional individuals.1 According to Arendt, passions or sentiments of pity and compassion should never be taken as the spring or fountainhead of virtue, because they are too strongly associated with the moralistic view of virtue. This also applies to related passions or dispositions such as “love”, beneficence, kindness and brotherliness. Arendt insists that there can be no greater tyranny, no more serious a perversion of virtue, and hence nothing more unethical than the moralistic ethos of a forced brotherhood based upon compassion and “love of thy neighbour”. As Arendt showed so effectively through the figures of Billy Budd and Robespierre (in her book On Revolution), absolute goodness (in a moral sense) can lead to the most atrocious deeds and terror. And this is so because it destroys the public space – the space of freedom, plurality and worldliness – and along with that also the basic conditions for a truly virtuous, ethical existence. Arendt differs radically from traditional political theory (classical as well as modern), which always presupposed an identity between the political and the social, or between politics and morality, or a combination of both. For Arendt it is of utmost importance to maintain or to reinstate the autonomous status of the public sphere, the sphere of (political) action. Thus she fully agrees with Machiavelli when he insists that people who entered politics should first 11 Arendt’s position is particularly clear in this respect: “Excellence itself, areté as the Greeks, virtus as the Romans would have called it, has always been assigned to the public realm where one could excel, could distinguish oneself from all others. Every activity performed in public can attain an excellence never matched in privacy; for excellence by definition, the presence of others is always required, and the presence needs the formality of the public... [N]o activity can become excellent if the world does not provide a proper space for its exercise. Neither education nor ingenuity nor talent can replace the constituent elements of the public realm, which make it the proper place for human excellence.” (HC 48-49) “Unlike human behavior – which the Greeks, like all civilized people, judged according to “moral standards,” taking into account motives and intentions on the one hand and aims and consequences on the other – action can be judged only by the criterion of greatness because it is in its nature to break through the commonly accepted and reach into the extraordinary, where whatever is true in common and everyday life no longer applies because everything that exists is unique and sui generis... The art of politics teaches men how to bring forth what is great and radiant …; as long as the polis is there to inspire men to dare the extraordinary, all things are safe; if it perishes, everything is lost. Motives and aims, no matter how pure or grandiose, are never unique; like psychological qualities, they are typical, characteristic of different types of persons. Greatness, therefore, or the specific meaning of its deed, can lie only in the performance itself and neither in its motivation nor its achievement.” (HC 205-6; cf. BPF 153-54). For an excellent account of “action, freedom and performance” in Arendt and Nietzsche, see Siemens 2005. learn “how not to be good,”2 that is, how not to act according to Christian precepts or moral standards transcending the sphere of human action.3 According to Arendt, moral “goodness” is not fit to be shown in public; it is irrelevant within the sphere of political action where one must always reckon with the possibility of harmful or deleterious consequences. No action can ever pretend to be good in an absolute sense, and the desire to be good above anything else in the public sphere is totally misplaced. In fact, as Arendt states, “absolute goodness is hardly any less dangerous than absolute evil” (OR 82). Not (moral) goodness, but virtue is what we must try to achieve in political life: “Virtue – which perhaps is less than goodness but still alone is capable ‘of embodiment in lasting institutions’ – must prevail at the expense of the good man...” (OR 84). Virtues and vices are relevant in the sphere of the “worldly affairs of men”, but the same cannot be said of “goodness beyond virtue” and “evil beyond vice”, because they constantly wage war against the world. “[T]he absolute ... spells doom to everyone when it is introduced into the political realm” (OR 84). Absolute, uncompromising morality tends to become violent. It wants to eradicate all evil in this world, irrespective of what it costs (fiat iustitia, et pereat mundus!).4 That is why it is, like violence in general, essentially anti-political in nature: it has no respect for plurality and difference of opinion. It wants to overrule difference and plurality by 22 See Machiavelli, The Prince, chapter 15. 33 See OR 36, as well as Arendt’s remarks in HC 73-78, particularly the following: “The well-known antagonism between early Christianity and the res publica, so admirably summed up in Tertullian’s formula ‘no matter is more alien to us than what matters publicly’, is usually and rightly understood as a consequence of early eschatological expectations ... Yet the otherworldliness of Christianity has still another root, perhaps even more intimately related to the teachings of Jesus of Nazareth ... The one activity taught by Jesus in word and deed is the activity of goodness, and goodness obviously harbors a tendency to hide from being seen and heard... For it is manifest that the moment a good work becomes known and public, it loses its special character of goodness, of being done for nothing but goodness’ sake. When goodness appears openly, it is no longer goodness... Therefore: ‘Take heed that ye do not your alms before men, to be seen of them.’ Goodness can exist only when it is not perceived, not even by its author... Therefore: ‘Let not thy left hand know what thy right hand doeth’… Only goodness must go into absolute hiding and flee all appearance if it is not to be destroyed... Good works, because they must be forgotten instantly, can never become part of the world; they come and go, leaving no trace. They truly are not of this world... Goodness, therefore, as a consistent way of life, is not only impossible within the confines of the public realm, it is even destructive of it...” Cf. also OR 98 and BPF 137. 44 See Arendt’s critical remarks in this regard in BPF 228 and 245 passim. 3 proclaiming a single, univocal truth. It wants to establish a regime of moral perfection in a domain that can never satisfy such a demand. The (aristocratic) virtue of generosity (Greek: megalopsychia, Latin: magnanimitas) plays a pivotal role in the tradition of virtue ethics. Generosity is primarily associated with magnanimity, greatness and generosity of spirit. As the exact opposite of resentment and meanness of spirit, it can be viewed as the most basic virtue underlying a supra-moral (“außermoralische”) ethic. This also applies by implication to Arendt, although she never uses the term generosity as such. However, one can reasonably accept this, especially in light of her views on forgiveness, which together with trustworthiness (the capacity to make and to keep promises) constitute for Arendt the highest “principles”5 of action. The capacities for promising and forgiving do not only impart stability and durability to our actions, but they give us, in the first place, the confidence to act at all. Cultivating the capacities of promising and forgiving can thus be viewed as the highest expression of (and the most fundamental precondition for) virtue. According to Arendt, nothing on earth can be more ethical or more virtuous than helping to create a situation in which it becomes possible for people to go on with their lives, to make a fresh start in all frankness and without being constantly plagued by feelings of guilt and remorse.6 For Arendt revengefulness is the opposite of forgiveness and thus, by implication, it is the supreme vice. It represents the worst of all vices, mainly because it is purely reactive, unable to initiate anything new or creative. Hence, the basic concern of Arendt is to devise strategies towards overcoming resentment. Overcoming resentment means first and foremost to free oneself from the grip of moralism and the egalitarian view of social justice that usually goes hand in hand with it. In conclusion, I should like to consider briefly some of the criticisms levelled against Arendt. She is frequently portrayed by some of her critics as an elitist and an advocate of meritocracy rather than democracy. They suggest that this is mainly due to Arendt’s sharp distinctions 55 The principles governing action must, according to Arendt, be understood in a supra-moral sense. They have nothing in common with moral prescriptions or values. They are genuinely ethical principles because they are, unlike ordinary moral principles, immanent to action and not applied “from without” (HC 246). 66 “Without being forgiven, released from the consequences of what we have done, our capacity to act would, as it were, be confined to one single deed from which we can never recover; we would remain the victims of its consequences forever...” (HC 237). between the public and the private sphere, and between (political) action and (social) behaviour. However, it seems quite obvious that, by making these rigorous distinctions, Arendt did not intend to exclude certain individuals or groups from the public sphere. Rather, she wanted to point out the dangers inherent to certain mentalities or dispositions with regard to the public sphere. Where peoples’ actions are driven by the immediacy of, for instance, unbearable oppression or deprivation, they will lack the necessary freedom and “impersonal sociability” (civil friendship) which characterise genuine (political) action. The strong feelings and needs that motivate such desperate, often violent behaviour have very little in common with what Arendt calls “care for the world” – taking care for maintaining and securing the public space, that artificial space which is constituted by mutual political association. Care for this “space in between”, for the network of institutions with their respective rules and habits of association, is the benchmark of genuine (ethico-political) action. It is in this “worldliness” of human action that our freedom manifests itself, not in our “free will” or “self-expression”.7 This is precisely why Arendt insists on the worlddirectedness of the virtue of forgiveness. She takes it out of the “narrowly circumscribed sphere” of sentiments such as love, relating it rather to something like respect: Respect, not unlike the Aristotelian philia politiké, is a kind of “friendship” without intimacy and without closeness; it is a regard for the person from the distance which the space of the world puts between us, and this regard is independent of qualities which we may admire or of achievements which we may highly esteem. (HC 243) Arendt’s insists that in principle nobody should be excluded from participating in the public life of politics. But when persons indeed make their appearance in the public sphere, they are expected to demonstrate certain qualities, and quite rightly so. They are judged in terms of “their trustworthiness, their personal integrity, their capacity of judgement, often their physical courage”, as well as their commitment to matters of public concern (the res publica) and to excellence, “regardless not only of social status and administrative office but even of achievement and congratulation” (OR 274-75). Thus, participating in politics necessarily has 77 Both the voluntarist and the expressivist views of freedom (which lie at the root of the moralistic ethos) make the common, public world into a mere extension of the self, thereby destroying the integrity and relative permanence of the world. That is precisely why this is basically such a dangerous (unethical, defective) view, for the preservation of a common, public world and everything that Arendt associates with it is indeed a sine qua non for a genuinely virtuous (ethical) existence. Dana Villa very eloquently explains the anti-expressivist stance in Arendt’s work, especially in his excellent chapter on “Theatricality and the public realm” (in Villa 1999). 5 an “elitist” (i.e. “aristocratic” or self-perfectionist) dimension: Only those who exhibit exceptional qualities and a passion for public life should be “allowed” to appear in the public sphere. The demand that everybody must be allowed to participate, irrespective of their capabilities or commitment to the public interest, will eventually lead to the degeneration of political action and its corruption by extra-political issues and interests.8 These views of Arendt must nevertheless be seen together with her plea for the “right to have rights”, i.e. the right to belong to a political community where one can be seen and heard. This is the most basic, the most fundamental human right. It finds its purpose and legitimacy in itself, in the human condition of worldliness, natality and plurality. From an Arendtian perspective, a political community can only claim recognition and legitimacy if its members themselves respect the human conditions of natality and plurality. This, in turn, is what makes possible and sustains the public sphere, which is for Arendt the best guarantee for a dignified, genuinely human existence, fragile as it may be. Violating these conditions amounts for Arendt to a “law against humanity”. Genuine democracy requires a belief in equality and, where necessary, measures to maintain it. But this does not at all imply uniformity or homogenising of differences, which basically follows the logic of fabrication (social engineering). According to Arendt, this would lead to the destruction of the public sphere and genuine politics, leaving the door wide open for totalitarian rule or new forms of despotism. Bibliography 88 For Arendt’s remarks about elitism, see OR 275-280. She is adamant that “the political way of life has never been and will never be the way of life of the many” (OR 275). She has a strong interest in those structures and practices that could help to empower “those few from all walks of life who have a taste for public freedom and cannot be ‘happy’ without it” (OR 279). Like Jefferson, she believes that participation in “councils” on grass-root level could play an important role in nurturing “an ‘élite’ that is chosen by no one but constitutes itself”. Of this “elite” Arendt says the following: “Politically they are the best, and it is the task of good government and the sign of a well-ordered republic to assure them of their rightful place in the public realm. To be sure, such an ‘aristocratic’ form of government would spell the end of general suffrage as we understand it today; for only those who as voluntary members of an ‘elementary republic’ have demonstrated that they care for more than their private happiness and are concerned about the state of the world would have the right to be heard in the conduct of the business of the republic. However, this exclusion from politics should not be derogatory, since a political élite is by no means identical with a social or cultural or professional élite. The exclusion, moreover, would not depend upon an outside body; if those who belong are selfchosen, those who do not belong are self-excluded.” (OR 279-80) Arendt, H. 1958. The Human Condition [HC]. Chicago: Univ. of Chicago Press. Arendt, H. 1966 (1951). The Origins of Totalitarianism. New York: Harcourt Brace & Co. Arendt, H. 1968 (1961). Between Past and Future [BPF]. New York: Viking Press. Arendt, H. 1973a (1963). On Revolution [OR]. Harmondsworth: Penguin. Arendt, H. 1973b (1972). Crises of the Republic. Harmondsworth: Penguin. Arendt, H. 1973c (1955). Men in Dark Times [MDT]. Harmondsworth: Penguin Arendt, H. 1978. The Life of the Mind: Vol. 1 & 2. London: Secker & Warburg. Arendt, H. 1990. Philosophy and Politics. Social Research 57/1: 73-103. Arendt, H. 1994a. Some Questions of Moral Philosophy. Social Research 61/4: 739-764. Birmingham, P. 1995. Hannah Arendt’s Dismissal of the Ethical. In Van Haute, Ph. & Birmingham, P. (eds.), Dissensus Communis. Between Ethics and Politics. Kampen: Kok Pharos: 131-153. Dossa, S. 1989. The Public Realm and the Public Self. The Political Theory of Hannah Arendt. Waterloo: Wilfrid Laurier Univ. Press. Honig, B. 1988. Arendt, Identity, Difference. Political Theory 16/1: 77-98. Honig, B. 1993. Political Theory and the Displacement of Politics. Ithaca: Cornell Univ. Press. Kateb, G. 1984. Hannah Arendt: Politics, Conscience, Evil. Totowa: Rowman & Allenheld. Machiavelli, N. 1952. The Prince (transl. L. Ricci & E. Vincent). New York: American Library. Machiavelli, N. 1974. The Discourses (ed. B. Crick & transl. L. Walker). Harmondsworth: Penguin. Schoeman, M. 2008. Overcoming resentment. Remarks on the supra-moral ethic of Nietzsche and Hannah Arendt. H W Siemens & V Roodt (ed.), Nietzsche, Power and Politics. Rethinking Nietzsche’s Legacy for Political Thought, Berlin/ New York: Walter de Gruyter: 431-449. Siemens, H. 2005. Action, Performance and Freedom in Hannah Arendt and Friedrich Nietzsche. International Studies in Philosophy 37/3: 107-126. Villa, D. 1996. Arendt and Heidegger. The fate of the political. Princeton: Princeton Univ. Press. Villa, D. 1999. Politics, Philosophy, Terror. Essays on the thought of Hannah Arendt. Princeton: Princeton Univ. Press. Villa, D. (ed.) 2000. The Cambridge Companion to Hannah Arendt. Cambridge: Cambridge Univ. Press. [2686 words excluding abstract, footnotes and bibliography; 3310 words including abstract, footnotes and bibliography] 7