A SMALL STEP TO ERADICATING INFANT CIRCUMCISION Rebecca A. Ballard* Circumcision was introduced as a medical procedure in the late 19th century, and for more than half a century has strained to find a justification.1 Doctors endorsed routine circumcision as a cure for masturbation which they believed to be the cause of paralysis, hip trouble, sloth, moral laxity, spinal curvature, lameness, clumsiness, hysteria, malnutrition, and epilepsy.2 Circumcision was advocated as a precautionary measure, even in the absence of symptoms. Eventually circumcisions took on a more cultural role, becoming a marker of the family’s wealth, sophistication or religious affiliation.3 I. THE NON-THERAPEUTIC NATURE OF INFANT CIRCUMCISION Recent medical studies have not only called into question the medical benefits claimed by proponents of infant circumcision, but have also highlighted that adverse effects may be graver than generally realized. Claims of hygiene, prevention of urinary tract infections, genital cancer, and AIDS have been advanced as reasons for practicing male circumcision. * J.D./M.A. Candidate, 2006, Indiana University School of Law – Indianapolis; B.S., 1999, Southwest Texas State University, San Marcos, Texas. 1 Gregory J. Boyle, et al., Male Circumcision: Pain, Trauma and Psychosexual Sequelae, 7(3) J. OF HEALTH PSYCHOLOGY 329, 330 (2002). 2 Anonymous, Circumcision: A Serious Male Health Problem, 58 EVERYMAN (2000), available at 2000 WLNR 7502316, page 2. 3 Sarah E. Waldeck, Using Male Circumcision to Understand Social Norms as Multipliers, 72 U. CIN. L. REV. 455, 471 (2003). 1 A. For the Prevention of Urinary Tract Infections The foreskin can harbor bacteria, leading to the cause of diseases. Studies have indicated an association between uncircumicision and the risk of a urinary tract infection.4 However, urinary tract infections occur in only one or two percent of boys, and are conservatively treated with antibiotics.5 Because the incidence is low, coupled with the effective treatment by less invasive means, the prevention of urinary tract infections is not a persuasive justification for subjecting a patient to surgery. B. For the Prevention of Genital Cancer Penile cancer is a serious disease with a three-year mortality rate of 20 to 25 percent, with treatment options including penile amputation.6 Circumcised males, missing one-third to one-half of their penile skin, have a reduced surface area on which the cancer can develop.7 Such a conclusion resulted from the observation in 1932 that of the 1,103 cases of penile cancer none were observed in Jews, who routinely perform circumcision, with similar observations noted in Europe in Moslem populations.8 However, the American Cancer Society’s official website states: “The consensus among studies…is that circumcision is not of value in preventing cancer of the penis. It is important that the issue of circumcision not distract the public’s attention from avoiding 4 Waldeck, supra note 3, at 481. 5 Anonymous, supra note 2, at 2. 6 Edgar J. Schoen, The Relationship Between Circumcision and Cancer of the Penis, 41 CANCER J. FOR CLINICIANS 306, 308 (1991). 7 Waldeck, supra note 3, at 482. 8 Schoen, supra note 6, at 306. 2 known penile cancer risk factors – having unprotected sexual relations with multiple partners (increasing the likelihood of human papilloma virus infection) and cigarette smoking.”9 Even if circumcision has a protective effect in the prevention of penile cancer, it is a rare medical occurrence that does not warrant the use of prophylactic surgery.10 C. For the Prevention of AIDS Studies have linked non-circumcision with a risk for HIV infection.11 However, the validity of this data has been challenged as suffering from severe methodological defects because it utilized a high-risk subject pool from Sub-Saharan Africa and did not adjust for factors (like sexual behavior) that strongly correlate with HIV risk.12 The fact that the United States has both the highest rate of routine circumcision and also the highest rate of AIDS in the developed world calls into question this proposed link between circumcision and a reduction of HIV infection.13 D. 9 The Reality of the Procedure American Cancer Society, ACS Penile Cancer Resource Center, http://www.cancer.org/docroot/CRI/content/CRI_2_4_2X_What_are_the_risk_factors_fo r_penile_cancer_35.asp?sitearea= (last visited March 31, 2005). 10 Penile cancer affects 1,000 males annually. Schoen, supra note 6, at 308. 11 R.S. Van Howe, Circumcision and HIV Infection: Review of the Literature and Metanalysis, 10 INT’L J. STD & AIDS 8, 11 (1999). 12 Id. at 13 - 14. 13 Anonymous, supra note 2, at 2. 3 Circumcision of the male penis involves the insertion of forceps or other probes into the foreskin, audibly crushing the baby’s sensitive foreskin, and removing fifty percent (50%) of the penile skin containing thousands of specialized nerve endings aiding in normal sexual response.14 The wound site then becomes dried and keratinized or hardened, further desensitizing the penis leading to a progressive life-long loss of sensation affecting sexual functioning.15 As with every surgery, there are risks involved. It is estimated that some form of complication occurs in 1 of every 476 boys who are circumcised.16 A common problem is bleeding during and after circumcision, as well as the risk of an infection.17 Surgical error includes the removal of too much skin, lacerations to the penis, and, though extraordinarily rare, the amputation of the penis.18 When justifying the procedure of circumcision in the past, doctors were operating under the erroneous assumption that children were not yet sufficiently developed to feel pain. However, newborns have both the anatomical and functional components necessary for the perception of painful stimuli. Eight common expressions of extreme 14 Id. at 2 – 3. 15 Boyle, supra note 1, at 334 (reporting 84% of circumcised men surveyed reported impaired sexual functioning). 16 Dimitri A. Christakis, et al., A Trade-off Analysis of Routine Newborn Circumcision, 105 PEDIATRICS 246, 248 (2000). 17 Waldeck, supra note 3, at 480. 18 Id. 4 distress were observed during the circumcision.19 The vigorous crying and the altered behavioral states observed in infants post circumcision provide objective indicia of this fact.20 The harm inflicted by the procedure of male circumcision is not limited to the actual performance of the surgery, but has been shown to have prolonged effects. For example, researches have shown circumcised infants show an increase in pain scores to subsequent vaccinations than uncircumcised infants, leading to the theory that pain experienced during circumcision may alter infant’s central neural processing of pain stimuli.21 The development of post-traumatic stress disorder (PTSD) is also a speculated consequence of circumcision.22 Despite not being able to have conscious recall, infants do have the capacity to store information and experiences.23 Circumcision should not be validated on the grounds that circumcised males cannot retell the sensation of pain itself, but only the general experience. Various national medical associations, having studied the therapeutic rationales asserted on behalf of routine infant circumcision, urge against circumcision because it 19 Fay Warnock & Dilma Sandrin, Comprehensive Description of Newborn Distress Behavior in Response to Acute Pain (Newborn Male Circumcision), 107 Pain 242, 253 (2004). 20 Id. at 253 – 254. 21 Waldeck, supra note 3, at 479. 22 Boyle, supra note 1, at 335. 23 Id. 5 lacks documented benefit.24 From a utilitarian perspective, the benefits claimed are either so minuscule or non-existent that they do not ethically warrant the abrogation of the child’s autonomy and self-determinism. Therefore, circumcision fails the bioethical test of beneficence. In addition, great pain and psychological harm is inflicted, thereby violating the test of non-malfeasance. II. AN ASSAULT ON THE INFANT’S LEGAL RIGHTS The rudimentary legal principles governing the relationship of doctors to their patients are grounded in the tort law of battery and negligence.25 Negligence is committed when harm results from the doctor’s conduct falling below the accepted standard of care, which is the same whether the patient is an adult or child.26 A battery is “an intentional contact with the plaintiff’s body and that contact neither has been consented to nor is legally privileged.”27 Essential to the concept of an offense to one’s personal dignity is the infringement of one’s body without full and valid consent.28 This represents both the bioethical test of justice and the test of autonomy; respectively, the patient’s right to bodily integrity, and the right to self-determination. Both of these are violated in the practice of infant circumcision. 24 Id. 25 Robert H. Mnookin and D. Kelly Weisberg, CHILD, FAMILY, AND STATE: PROBLEMS AND MATERIALS ON CHILDREN AND THE LAW 26 Id. 27 Id. 28 Id. at 601. 6 600 (4th ed., 2000). Informed consent is justified by the ethical principles of self-determination and aids in the maintenance of bodily integrity. True self determination, from a Kantian account of autonomy, requires thoughtful and informed decisions, obligating the pursuit of all relevant information needed to make those decisions.29 Informed consent empowers the patient by granting control and access to information about one’s medical condition to the patient, serving to protect patients against depersonalized, authoritarian medical treatment.30 Respect for the power of a person to be a rational, self-determining, morally autonomous individual is the most influential reason for supporting the informed consent doctrine. III. A CHILD AS A PERSON Because a child lacks the capacity to provide consent for purposes of avoiding a battery, courts held that until children reach the age of majority, only a parent or legal guardian could give effective consent to medical treatment.31 Requiring parental consent for a minor’s medical treatment is consistent with the broad notion of family privacy, parental autonomy, and respect for familial bonds.32 However, the common law rule was justified under a narrower notion of parent’s being responsible for the care and support of 29 Rosamond Rhodes, Genetic Links, Family Ties and Social Bonds: Rights and Responsibilities in the Face of Genetic Knowledge, 23(1) J. OF MED. & PHILOSOPHY 10, 18 (1998). 30 Mnookin, supra note 25, at 601. 31 Id. 32 Id. at 602. 7 their children to protect parents from the possible financial consequences of unwanted medical treatment.33 A. Children Recognized as Persons Under the Law English common law treated children as “possessions,” and a father’s interest in custody was a right of property.34 John Stuart Mill, who championed the notion of individual rights, did not bestow this upon children. He believed limiting the freedom of children was necessary to protect children against “their own actions as well as against external injury” and “to protect society from the untutored.”35 The constitutionalization of a patriarchal notion of parental rights in both Meyer and Pierce has reiterated this notion of dominion and parental possession over their children.36 “The child is denied her own voice and identity and becomes a conduit for the parents’ religious expression, cultural identity, and class aspirations.”37 Explicit language in Meyer’s “right to control” and Pierce’s “high duty” of the parent to direct his child’s 33 See generally Lacey v. Laird, 139 N.E.2d 25, 30 (Ohio 1956) (stating that [the rule that parents must consent for minors] is not based upon the capacity of a minor to consent, so far as he is personally concerned… but is based upon the right of parents whose liability for support and maintenance of their child may be greatly increased by an unfavorable result from [a surgeon’s operation]). 34 Barry Nicholas, AN INTRODUCTION TO ROMAN LAW 65 – 68 (1969). 35 Mnookin, supra note 25, at 1. 36 See generally, Barbara Bennett Woodhouse, “Who Owns the Child?”: Meyer and Pierce and The Child as Property, 33 WM. & MARY L. REV. 995 (1992). 37 Id. at 1114. 8 destiny has shown a disturbing willingness to deny the integration of the child’s voice into an adult legal system.38 Mill did reject, however, the notion that parents have unfettered dominion over their children; rather the law should limit parental liberty when necessary for the good of the child or society.39 Progressive reforms through the women’s movement have been used to challenge the legally imposed limitation on a child’s decision making power.40 However, the analogy of age to race or sex as a determinate of a person’s legal autonomy ignores certain biological and economic reality of a child’s dependence on adults for articulation, assertion and enforcement of rights.41 Though a child’s dependence necessarily bestows an element of dominion over the child, it does not give an adult a license to ignore the moral dimension implicit in the respect for autonomy. Justice Douglas further states that “[c]hildren are ‘persons’ within the meaning of the Bill of Rights.”42 However broad the parental right to raise their children might be, the Court has begun to assert that it does have its limitations. One such limitation should be recognized in the context of non-therapeutic treatment. The World Medical Association’s (1949) code of ethics does not permit “weaken[ing] the physical or mental resistance of a human being except from strictly therapeutic or 38 Id. at 1116. 39 Mnookin, supra note 25, at 2. 40 Id. at 3. 41 Id. 42 Wisconsin v. Yoder, 406 U.S. 205, 243 (1972) (Justice Douglas, dissenting). 9 prophylactic indications imposed in the interest of the patient.”43 The broad parental discretion to consent on the behalf of the child typically enjoyed by the parent is sharply curtailed when a medical procedure has no benefit to the child.44 B. A Child Cannot Be Regarded as a Means to An End A core principle expressed by Immanuel Kant as the Formula of Respect for the Dignity of Persons directs that an individual may not properly be regarded as merely a means to an end, even if a legitimate end, but rather an individual must be regarded as an end in itself.45 This intrinsic, objective value inherent in an individual requires us to treat each other as “ends,” rather than merely as objects to be used solely to satisfy the desires of others.46 Society inevitably depends on our relation with others, so that we must use each other to a certain extent for our own ends, and in pursuit of our own happiness. However, this conduct becomes unethical when the dignity and worth of the individual is disregarded, such that the individual is reduced to a thing.47 43 Laine Friedman Ross, Children in Medical Research Balancing Protection and Access: Has the Pendulum Swung Too Far?, 47(4) PERSPECTIVES IN BIOLOGY AND MED. 519, 521 (2004). 44 Waldeck, supra note 3, at 487. 45 Donald L. Beschel, Kant’s Categorical Imperative: An Unspoken Factor in Constitutional Rights Balancing, 31 PEPP. L. REV. 949, 954 (2004). 46 Immanual Kant, Grounding For the Metaphysics of Morals 30, 35 (James W. Ellinton trans., 3d ed. 1993). 47 Beschel, supra note 45, at 967. 10 Relying on Kant, it could be argued the parent is using the child as the means to practice the parent’s culture. Parents subject their child to the painful ritual of circumcision, not because of any demonstrable health benefits, but because parents desire the boy to look like his peers and his father.48 Furthermore, religious considerations of the parents should not justify the parents electing a non-therapeutic procedure for their child. The Supreme Court has made it clear that while “parents are free to become martyrs, it does not mean they are free to make martyrs of their children.”49 Thus, infringement of the parent’s religious freedom is constitutional when there is clear and present danger to the child.50 IV. INFORMED ASSENT AS A MEASURED STEP TO ERADICATE MALE CIRCUMCISION It is the responsibility of parents to demonstrate that a non-therapeutic surgery is in the child’s best interest.51 Unless a medical procedure is necessary for the promotion of life or health, it should be postponed until the child is sufficiently mature to participate in the decision. “Where a child is mature enough to express potentially conflicting desires, it would be an invasion of the child’s right to permit such an imposition without canvassing his views.”52 In discussing its views on parents intentionally exposing a child to non-therapeutic experimentations the Court stated, “parents … have no more right to 48 Waldeck, supra note 3, at 492. 49 Prince v. Massachusetts, 321 U.S. 158, 170 (1944). 50 Id. at 167. 51 Debashis Singh, BMA says Non-therapeutic Circumcision Needs Consent of Both Parents, 326 BRITISH MED. J. 782, 782 (2003). 52 Wisconsin v. Yoder, 406 U.S. 205, 243 (Justice Douglas, dissenting). 11 intentionally and unnecessarily place children in potentially hazardous non-therapeutic research surrounding than do researchers. In such cases, parental consent, no matter how informed, is insufficient.”53 An informed assent approach, representing a more self-determinalistic approach rather than the nurturance approach, is perhaps best utilized for non-therapeutic treatments.54 This falls in step with Kantian principles of not using the child as mere means to effectuate the parent’s cultural and religious beliefs, in addition to respecting the child as a rational, self-determining, morally autonomous individual.55 V. CONCLUSION A purely academic analysis leads to the conclusion that infant circumcisions should be eradicated because it fails to satisfy the bioethical test of beneficence, nonmalfeasance, justice and autonomy. Others have suggested that circumcision is more properly construed as a violation of human rights or child abuse.56 An Equal Protection 53 Grimes v. Kennedy Krieger Inst., 782 A.2d 807, 814 (Md. 2001). 54 Mnookin, supra note 25, at 602. 55 Louis P. Pojman, Ethical Theory: Classic and Contemporary Readings 287 (4th ed. 2002). 56 Abbie J. Chesler, Justifying the Unjustifiable: Rite v. Wrong, 45 BUFF. L. REV. 555 (1997); William E. Brigman, Circumcision as Child Abuse: The Legal and Constitutional Issues, 23 J. FAM. L. 337 (1984). 12 Clause violation has been argued by equating male circumcision to female circumcision, which has long enjoyed a ban in the United States.57 Though commendable attempts have been made to highlight the inability to reconcile the legal and ethic dilemmas with the practice of infant circumcision, the fact is such attempts are out of step with popular sentiment. Today, an estimated of 650 million males alive are circumcised, so chances are members of the legal community are either circumcised themselves, have a partner who is, or have chosen to circumcise their own sons.58 A real change must progress in steps, beginning with the strengthening of the notion that a child is a person under the Constitution and continual affirmation of a child’s right to self-determination. Though circumcision as a practice may not be eradicated, at the very least, it should be postponed until the child can give informed consent to a non-therapeutic procedure. 57 Dena S. Davis, Male and Female Genital Alteration: A Collision Course with the Law?, 11 HEALTH MATRIX 487 (2001). 58 Boyle, supra note 1, at 330. 13