Arendt and Bourdieu Between Word and Deed Keith Topper University of California, Irvine This essay investigates questions about the relationship between language, speech, and political institutions by examining two distinctive views of it: Hannah Arendt’s and Pierre Bourdieu’s. The essay’s first two sections sketch these perspectives, first explicating Arendt’s analysis of the connection between speech and identity disclosure, as well as its role in her conception of the public realm and what I call institutional form. Next I complicate this outlook by examining Bourdieu’s political sociology of language. Here I focus on the ways that linguistic competences valorized in particular institutional settings operate as mechanisms of silencing, subordination, domination, and exclusion. By subverting the principle of equal participation, these “symbolic violences” raise serious questions about the democratic pretensions of many political institutions. Finally, Arendt’s and Bourdieu’s insights are joined in a detailed investigation of a specific caseBAIDS activism. Examined in tandem, Arendt and Bourdieu complement and emend one another in surprising and illuminating ways. Introduction AWherever the relevance of speech is at stake, matters become political by definition, for speech is what makes man a political being.@ --Hannah Arendt1 AWords are also deeds.@ BLudwig Wittgenstein2 For many years now, students of social and political thought have been fascinated and perplexed by the idea that in some fundamental sense politics itself is a language system and language itself is a political system, that speech is often a form of action and action a mode of speech.3 Departing from the classical positivist and representationalist view that language is, or ideally should be, a neutral medium of communication, representation, or expression, contemporary social theorists have increasingly conceived of language and discourse as constitutive of both politics and identity. Speaking very broadly, two quite different lines of thought have emerged, each of which accents one or another aspect of the complex, inconstant, and promiscuous operations of language and speech. On the one hand, poststructuralists, postmodernists, and some feminist theorists have focused on the rhetorical, constitutive and power-laden dimensions of linguistic utterances. Thinkers as diverse as Michel Foucault and Catharine MacKinnon, for instance, have notoriously accented these aspects of language, albeit in very different ways and for very different purposes. Each has sought to highlight the manner in which language and discourse actively constitute and alter the very practices, institutions, and relationships they ostensibly describe and 1 represent. Politicizing Heidegger=s oft quoted assertion that Alanguage is the house of being,@ Foucault, in his account of discursive formations, and MacKinnon, in her reconceptualization of speech act theory, both conceive of language as a form of power that in varying degrees produces subjectivity while enacting domination, subordination, and exclusion.4 In short, Heidegger=s epigrammatic remark now reads rather differently, as something like Apower/language is the architect of the house of Being.@ On the other hand, Jürgen Habermas and other proponents of discourse ethics and deliberative democracy have sought to expose what they perceive as the performative contradictions and political dangers implicit in the former view. Frankly acknowledging the ways in which everyday linguistic exchanges are corrupted by manipulation, distortion, insincerity, and strategic intentBespecially in situations where power relations are unequal--Habermas sets out to reconstruct the normative basis of communication by identifying the pragmatic presuppositions of it. Thus, in his theory of communicative action Habermas looks to the Aideal speech situation@ as a universal normative standard for assessing the integrity of deliberative processes oriented toward understanding. In short, by locating imperatives built into the very nature of linguistic communication itself, Habermas aims to combat what he views as the irrationalist impulses of linguistic models such as those associated with Foucault and MacKinnon and to provide an ahistorical justification of the core values of democratic societies. While both of these approaches have attracted much scholarly interest, each is burdened by important limitations. Foucault=s account of discursive (or disciplinary) power, for instance, properly foregrounds the ways in which formal bodies of knowledge constitute and are constituted by relations of power, thereby installing modes of disciplinary control that escape the notice of juridical 2 theories of politics. At the same time, his Acapillary@ conception of power, which pictures power as a force that circulates throughout the social order, may impede or gloss over efforts to study systematically the politics of institutional structures. Ironically, Foucault=s conception of power/knowledge either makes the study of particular institutions misconceived (since modern power is dispersed through Ainfinitesimal mechanisms,@5 rather than concentrated in specific institutions and regions of social space), or too narrowly limits the scope of institutional analysis to an investigation of total institutions and the institutions of the modern human sciences. In contrast, by holding that pornographic speech and representations are performative, i.e., they are neither true or false statements nor reports of events but are types of conduct, MacKinnon=s radicalization of speech-act theory effectively foregrounds the very real psychic and physical injuries that these seemingly Aimmaterial@ utterances and images can cause. Nonetheless, MacKinnon=s account of the manner in which pornographic representations and speech figure women as sexual subordinates grants to speech acts a highly questionable ontological fixity and power. Pornography, MacKinnon argues, enacts subordination, depriving the addressee not just of what Judith Butler calls the power of resignification, but of the very power to speak at all. The pornographic speech-act, in other words, is both a sovereign and unilateral action, simultaneously imposing its own unequivocal meanings on women while silencing, reinterpreting and discounting the speech of those who seek to resist them.6 While MacKinnon is certainly right to highlight these instances of silencing, when they are woven into a general theory of language that deprives entire classes of utterances of equivocal or contestable meanings, something has clearly gone wrong. Indeed, reading MacKinnon=s account of injurious speech-acts, one senses that she has locked all the exits except her own and yelled Afire!@ 3 That is, having positioned the addressee in a structural relation that precludes the possibility of defusing, subverting, or deflecting the intended effects of pornographic words and images, MacKinnon advances legal prohibitions as the only viable response to them. As Judith Butler has summarized it, only the word of the law and the state, i.e., legal prohibitions, can effectively combat the power of injurious representations. Furthermore, due to her narrow analytic focus--in Only Words the analysis is limited to cases of hate speech, sexual harassment and pornography, that is, to what are often considered paradigm cases of intentional and overtly hostile and degrading forms of speech--MacKinnon=s insights into the operations of power in speech are less helpful for diagnosing forms of exclusion and domination that occur in more mundane everyday encounters, and often in the absence of any intention to exclude, subordinate, intimidate and the like. Finally, Habermas= effort to reconstruct the Auniversal-pragmatic infrastructure@ of all speech and action, however heroic, remains beset with important problems of its own. Apart from the deeply contentious question of whether Habermas= proceduralist and transcendental tack yields a normative standard that at best is too Athin@ to be of any real use, one might wonder whether he cedes too much to cognitivism and thus embraces, whether intentionally or not, something like a Platonic distinction between reason and rhetoric.7 Indeed, by excluding passion and rhetoric from the domain of communicative action and by discounting the productive role that agonism and discord play in politics, Habermas arguably deprives himself of critical resources for constituting shared experience and sustaining moral and political vitality. Moreover, by underestimating the role that the body plays in everyday communicative practice, Habermas fails to attend adequately to forms of exclusion and silencing that operate not through coercion, the denial of rights, covert manipulation and the like, but rather through a relationship between situated and embodied persons and particular 4 norms and social structures. To circumvent and overcome some of the difficulties accompanying these theoretical perspectives and to better explore the specific set of questions I want to raise in this paper, namely, questions about the relationship between language, speech and political institutions, in the following I shall bring into conversation two rarely linked thinkers, Hannah Arendt and Pierre Bourdieu. I do so because in spite of their superficial and at times not so superficial differences, each provides conceptual and analytical resources missing in the work of Foucault, MacKinnon, Habermas and others.8 Instead of restaging yet another confrontation between these thinkers, it may be instructive to examine the shared concerns and distinctive views that give form to Arendt=s and Bourdieu=s understandings of the relationship between language and speech, on the one hand, and political institutions, on the other. Not incidentally, such an investigation may also reveal important dimensions of Arendt=s and Bourdieu=s thought that are often neglected or obscured in the voluminous commentaries on their work. On the one hand, it may provide an alternative perspective on, and a challenge to, interpretations of Arendt as a type of anarchist who is at best uninterested in, and at worst hostile to, questions of what I call institutional form, that is, questions about the general structure and overall architecture of political institutions and their role in sustaining both political action and practices of political freedom.9 On the other hand, it may yield a deeper understanding of the significance of Bourdieu=s sociology of power for democratic theory today.10 More generally, Arendt is not only an important source of inspiration for Habermas= own thinking about language, speech and the public sphere, but in some ways provides a more compelling account of these relationships.11 Not only does Arendt display a fuller appreciation of the constructive role that rhetoric, agonism, and dissonance play in political discourse, but she also 5 provides a richer account of the links among public speech, action and identity-formation, one that anchors her spirited defense of the intrinsic value of a vibrant public sphere. In The Human Condition, for instance, Arendt holds that the very essence of politics is speech--public speech made possible by a shared language. Indeed, for Arendt, public speech and action are definitive of a human life in the sense that deprivation of them is literally the denial of human existence itself. Bourdieu, on the other hand, shares with Foucault the idea that language is a form of power, one that operates through social relations and inscribes itself in the very constitution of individuals. Like Foucault, he also recognizes that these operations are not just repressive but also productive. Unlike Foucault=s capillary conception of power, however, Bourdieu maintains that power often concentrates in particular institutional sectors and zones of social space.12 Thus, Bourdieu=s investigations of the politics of language are anchored in detailed sociological analyses of specific institutional domains--e.g., schools and universities--that are particularly crucial elements in the reproduction of economic and cultural capital and the subversion of democratic forms of life. At the same time, I want to suggest that reading Arendt and Bourdieu both with and against one another allows us to better grasp each writer=s peculiar strengths, tensions, and omissions. For instance, while Arendt provides what is arguably the most compelling modern account of the relation between speech, politics and human identity, one of the qualities which makes that account both so intriguing and elusive is its highly abstract mode of articulation. Indeed, Arendt is uninterested, at least in The Human Condition, in issues of how manipulation and domination operate concretely in language, how persons are rendered speechless even when they are not formally excluded from discourse and discussion, or how private and Asocial@ conditions affect one=s capacity for public participation. These, however, are precisely the issues that concern Bourdieu. In this essay I argue 6 that Bourdieu complicates Arendt=s views by examining concretely how power relations operate in actual linguistic exchanges. Bourdieu=s work on Asymbolic violence@ (an embodied but non-coercive, linguistic Aviolence@ that is exercised through misrecognition on the part of the participants of the meanings implicit in their speech) and the politics of language explores in detail the ways in which persons lacking the linguistic competences valorized in particular social and institutional domains are de facto excluded from participation in them. In such instances symbolic forms cease to operate as communicative links or modes of self-disclosure. Nor do they empower otherwise isolated and alienated persons, thereby preserving and augmenting the public realm and the peculiar freedoms it provides. Instead, these forms become sources of structured inequality which effectively dissolve the political realm as Arendt defines it. Moreover, these mechanisms of exclusion represent a unique and uniquely vexing challenge to students of political thought and political institutions. This is not only because what I term (slightly rewriting Judith Shklar) Aordinary violences@ are so inconspicuous and Agentle,@ but also because they defy the standard liberal dichotomies of freedom and constraint, will and coercion. Insofar as these violences fail to issue from overt force, conscious intention or the formal denial of consent, they appear categorically to be freely willed (or consented) and legitimate, although this is clearly a misleading formulation as well. If, however, Bourdieu=s notion of symbolic violence spotlights surreptitious mechanisms of domination and institutional exclusion which remain either under- or unexamined in Arendt, it is also the case that Arendt provides students of politics and institutions with important resources missing from Bourdieu=s conceptual vocabulary. Specifically, her normative construal of power as a collective property inhering in an Aability not just to act but to act in concert@13 supplements 7 Bourdieu=s detailed account of symbolic violence. Accenting the diverse ways in which agents are empowered through public speech oriented toward collective action, Arendt reveals the positive and productive potential of language and speech Ato establish relations and create new realities.@14 Thus, while individually incomplete, when viewed in tandem Bourdieu=s and Arendt=s accounts of language and speech emend and supplement one another, providing one both with important analytical tools, and insight into what constitutes a legitimately political form of public speech. I Arendt on Language, Institutions and the Ontology of Politics Notoriously, in recent years students of social and political life have rediscovered the timehonored truth that Ainstitutions matter.@ From the plethora of rational choice theories of institutional determinants to the sundry Ahistorical approaches@ to the seemingly countless proposals for new forms of deliberative democracy, the same idea constantly reappears: far from being mere arenas for the aggregation of individual and group interests, epiphenomenal effects of exogenous forces, or insidious mechanisms for stealing our most basic liberties, institutions are the precious and fragile mediums through which we secure those liberties. That this recent attentiveness comes at a time when large sectors of the public, as well as the elites of both major parties in the US, appear zealously eager to destroy, privatize or at a minimum dramatically Adownsize@ social and political institutions is of course an irony not easily missed. With politicians inveighing cynically against the very institutions that they are charged to protect and preserve, one cannot help but wonder if it is in part the imperiled status of institutions that has summoned the recent interest in them. If, however, one acknowledges the importance and distinctive value of institutions, a number of questions follow. If institutions matter, precisely how and why do they matter? How do and 8 should they function in democratic orders? If, as the Founding Fathers urged, institutions are necessary to Aestablish justice,@ to Asecure the blessings of liberty,@ and to Aform a more perfect union,@ then what kinds of institutions promote and procure these lofty goals? Is it not also true that institutions often subvert the very quest for justice and liberty they are designed to facilitate? Do they not, as Foucault has powerfully argued, normalize as well as enable, pacify as well as empower? While the possible rejoinders to these questions are myriad, one particularly provocative view is articulated in the writings of Hannah Arendt. In The Human Condition and elsewhere, Arendt proffers an account of politics that identifies speech and action as the primary modes of political activity, and political institutions as supplying the crucial framework for speech and action. Without this framework politics and the fragile space of political activity would literally disappear, expunged by both violence and the relentlessly expansive momentum of what she terms Athe social.@ And since, as she repeatedly insists, politics and political action are neither convenient outlets for the unalloyed pursuit of self-interest, nor burdensome if necessary civic duties, but are instead constitutive features of any uniquely human and humane existence, then the eclipse of politics simultaneously entails the disappearance of human existence as such. Arendt=s theory of politics and political action begins with the proposition that politics is a distinctive sort of activity, one that depends upon certain preconditions, and yields singularly human experiences and artifacts. According to Arendt, political life is possible only in a particular type of public space and community, one composed of distinct and equal citizens engaged in common deliberation with others and for the sake of all concerned. If citizens are unequal, then mutual understanding and common action are impossible. If they are identical, then politics would lose both its object and impetus. Deprived of plurality and the multiple perspectives it yields, political action 9 would lose its peculiar disclosive quality--i.e., its revelation of Awho@ as opposed to Awhat@ a person is--and could no longer function as a unique field in which one=s identity is disclosed to others and to oneself thorough others. Divested of shared objects viewed from a variety of different perspectives and in its different aspects, what Arendt terms Awordly reality@ would utterly vanish. This indeed is exactly what happens in totalitarian regimes, where the eradication of plurality and the consequent extirpation of the political realm yields not a common world but an atomized and lonely Aworldlessness,@ one in which all common referents, stable perspectives and sources of human solidarity are unmoored and eviscerated.15 In addition to the preconditions of equality, distinctness and commonality, political life for Arendt is distinguished by its peculiar content. Political existence, unlike the mundane and tedious preoccupations of the life process, is by definition free from the twin dictates of instrumental reason and biological necessity. Political action, Arendt controversially argues, aims not at objects or ends beyond politics itself, but rather is its own subject and object. When instrumental concerns, interest group bargaining and economic demands generally become the stuff of everyday Apolitics,@ then politics, which for Arendt is the sole activity in which humans distinguish themselves from nature, loses both its existential and ontological significance. Thus, quite unlike typical definitions of politics as a play of competing interests in pursuit of personal or group gain, or as Awho gets what, when, and how,@ both of which are in Arendt=s view paradigmatically nonpolitical activities, politics is precisely about the human creation and preservation of a space in which the natural impulses toward self-preservation and self-interest are throttled. What distinguishes politics and political action is its freedom from the relentless biological imperatives that humans share with all other animals, and its construction of an artificial arena within which all that is distinctive of the 10 human condition can flower unimpeded. As Arendt urges, it is only through speech and action in the public realm that one is able to disclose one=s unique identity, for only within an arena where one is Awith others and neither for nor against them@16 can one do rather than behave, persuade rather than coerce, know and be known rather than command and obey, initiate the new rather than confirm the probable. Given that humans are fragile creatures endowed with the burdensome knowledge of their own mortality, only the intense, meaning-giving activities of political speech and action can possibly vindicate the otherwise unendurable pain and anguish of this existential weight. Within this distinctive sphere with its singular content and redemptive possibilities, language and especially speech play an absolutely vital role. For Arendt, speech is the sine qua non of politics because it is the principal mode of political action. As the primary vehicle through which individuals express their intentions and announce their appearance and actions in the world, public speech and especially storytelling reaches beyond its typical function as a medium of communication or representation and becomes instead a necessary conduit to individual and collective self-disclosure. Finding the right words at the right time, for instance, involves something more than communicating discreet bits of information. It entails a sensitivity to audience, texture, and tone, an ability to express, illuminate, and even constitute that which is common (in the sense both of reestablishing contact with others and articulating common meanings that make such contact possible) in a world of distinct but related beings. For Arendt, therefore, public speech does not merely represent objects but is partly constitutive of the shared meanings which are simultaneously a precondition and product of it. Politics is literally sustained only through the revelatory powers of speech (which, Arendt reminds readers, is in such instances also action17), and where speech disappears so does the body politic and distinctive human identities. 11 Moreover, precisely because political life is defined by a shared commitment to adjudicate all issues Athrough words and persuasion and not through force and violence,@18 the capacity to speak and hence to listen, to persuade and be persuaded, becomes the preeminent political capacity. In its absence genuine mutuality disintegrates, with politics devolving into inegalitarian and prepolitical relations of ruling, commanding, administering and coercing, thus precluding any possibility of selfdisclosure. As George Kateb has aptly remarked: Those who use violence or force do not talk and hence do not reveal themselves; their victims are not revealed. Those who rule (and the rest) do what they do instrumentally, exploitatively, and manipulatively. They do not engage a world by which they come to be known or come to know others; and thus the speech embedded in those relations is not revelatory.19 The upshot of this brief discussion is fourfold. First, from Arendt=s point of view, speech and agency are ineluctably linked (though not identical), such that one who is rendered speechless is also dispossessed of all agency. As Arendt writes, ASpeechless action would no longer be action because there would no longer be an actor, and the actor, the doer of deeds, is possible only if he is at the same time the speaker of words.@20 Second, Arendt holds that public speech and action are uniquely definitory of a human life. To be deprived of speech and action, of Aword and deed,@ is to be deprived not of a political right but of a human identity. As she eloquently puts it, AA life without speech and without action ... is literally dead to the world; it has ceased to be a human life because it is no longer lived among men.@21 Third, Arendt places strict limits on the functions of political speech and hence the preconditions of politics. Most importantly, she maintains that public space and public speech exists and flourishes only to the extent that those within it seek not to manipulate, 12 deceive or dominate, but to persuade.22 For this reason, she argues that power, as opposed to force, strength or violence, Ais actualized only where words are not empty and deeds not brutal, where words are not used to veil intentions but to disclose realities, and deeds not used to violate and destroy but to establish relations and create new realities.@23 Finally, speech as the primary mode of political action is also linked closely with freedom, which Arendt terms Athe raison d=être of politics.@24 For Arendt, freedom, understood as the capacity to initiate new and unexpected projects and processes, is precisely what distinguishes the political from the social, where humans act in predictable, Aautomatic@ and causally stable ways. Indeed, like the physical and organic processes of nature, man-made, historical processes tend over time to become stagnant, routinized, natural and Aautomatic,@ thus hiding their origin in acts of human innovation.25 When this occurs, speech and action, both as modes of recalling and rejuvenating the Aunnatural@ sources of a now petrified political life and as unmined repositories of novelty and transformation, function as perhaps the most formidable bulwarks against the extinction of the often dormant faculty of freedom. Having delineated these affinities between speech, politics, identity disclosure, and freedom, we might now ask: how are they related to broad questions of institutional form and structure? In short, what role, if any, do institutions play in this account? At first glance they may appear to play virtually no role at all. After all, Arendt is often accused of constructing a conception of public space that is almost entirely bereft of institutional detail. Seyla Benhabib, for example, makes just this charge, arguing that Arendt=s conception of public space is Ainstitutionally unanchored, floating as if it were a nostalgic chimera in the horizon of politics.@26 While I would agree that there is some truth in Benhabib=s claim, especially if one focuses exclusively on The Human Condition, I believe that she overstates the case. At a minimum Arendt=s extensive writings on totalitarianism present a 13 richly detailed portrait of institutional forms that destroy systematically the public realm. Indeed, on Arendt=s view totalitarianism is distinguished in no small part by the creation of institutions that aim to eviscerate the very preconditions of a body politic, namely, the worldliness and plurality on which it depends. In addition, Arendt=s well-known criticism of the American founders for failing to establish an institution that preserved the Arevolutionary spirit@ of the founding implies that institutions are a vitally important aspect of political life.27 Thus, if only in this limited sense it cannot be said that Arendt disregards the role of institutions. Fortunately, Arendt=s view of political institutions is not articulated solely through the negative example of totalitarianism or inferential reasoning. Rather, Arendt=s discussions in On Revolution of various council systems and Jefferson=s ward system of government point clearly toward an institutional model in which public spaces of participation are multiplied dramatically, thus sustaining institutionally the experience of common deliberation and the fragile practices of public freedom. In contrast to centralized bureaucratic institutions--which Arendt denounces as Areally the rule by nobody@28--and the party systems that seek to organize them, the disparate experiments with councils aimed simultaneously to diffuse power and build it up from below.29 Such Aelementary republics@ would not, as some have supposed, entail the elimination of the more familiar institutions of representative democracy and the forms of citizenship they presuppose and sustain. Rather, they would function, among other ways, as instruments of resistance against the concentrating, bureaucratizing and homogenizing tendencies of modern political institutions and mass society.30 As seedbeds of grassroots politics and political participation, these diverse public spaces yield forms of political life that dramatically transfigure the political landscape and moral topography of mass society, interspersing among the mute dreariness and arid instrumentalism of the 14 private and social, living gardens of Apublic happiness@ and political freedom. Indeed, in a putative distillation of Jefferson=s views, Arendt sums up the political logic animating her own preferred institutional scheme: AThe basic assumption of the ward system ... was that no one could be happy without his share in public happiness, that no one could be called free without his experience in public freedom, and that no one could be called either happy or free without participating, and having a share, in public power.@31 It goes without saying that this sketch of an institutional form that sustains political freedom by multiplying the opportunities for active participation in public affairs leaves unresolved a breathtaking number of issues about the particular kinds of arrangements, rules, and procedures that should properly operate within specific institutions such as legislative bodies, the judiciary, and the like. I would argue, however, that this lack of specificity is not the result of an indifference on Arendt=s part to the challenges of constructing institutions of freedom or to an agonistic or anarchistic view of politics that inherently privileges extra-political forms of action that occur outside of all political institutions. Rather, it reflects an acute understanding of, and respect for, the implications of her own view. For Arendt, political institutions, no less than the political realm itself, possess no natural form or structure, but are instead artificial constructions of persons living together in particular cultural, political, and historical settings. Moreover, it is against the backdrop of these settings and the issues they raise that deliberations about the proper structure of political institutions must proceed. Political communities punctuated by a history of racial or ethnic subordination, for example, may construct legislative institutions that strive to insure representation of these subordinated groups, whereas other communities may not. In both cases, however, judgments about the type of institutional structures that a society needs must be informed by an 15 understanding of specific cultural, political and historical factors. Even more importantly, however, Arendt=s position entails that decisions about the proper structure of particular institutions must themselves be the product of public deliberation. Perhaps anticipating the charge that her description of the council system, as well Jefferson=s of ward government, fails to specify in sufficient detail the precise functions and modes of operation of this institutional arrangement, Arendt cites, and then supplements, Jefferson himself: A>Begin them only for a single purpose; they will soon show for what others they are the best instruments=--the best instruments, for example, for breaking up modern mass society, with its dangerous tendency toward the formation of pseudo-political mass movements, or rather, the best, the most natural way for interspersing it at the grass roots with an >élite= that is chosen by no one but constitutes itself.@32 This of course does not fully absolve Arendt of the accusation that her conception of the public realm remains institutionally vague, but it does draw attention to the paradox of specifying in advance institutional details that in her view must emerge from public deliberation taking place in specific cultural and historical settings. In Arendt=s mind, such efforts would undoubtedly represent yet another anti-political effort to import political Afoundations@ from outside of politics itself. While it is difficult not to be impressed by the sheer audacity of this political vision, it is equally difficult to avoid posing a number of perplexing questions about it. Many of these are no doubt familiar to Arendt=s readers. Questions, for instance, about the strict division between the private realm of necessity and the public realm of freedom, the ostensible exclusion of instrumental and strategic concerns from the political realm, and the durability and viability of an institutional form which Arendt herself concedes Anever was tried out,@33 are appropriate and clearly worthy of exploration in their own right. For the purposes of this discussion, however, I would like to return to 16 our original queries about the relationship between politics, language and institutions. If, as Arendt submits, it is only through speech and language that humans become both political and distinctively human beings; if, in some basic sense, our identities are constituted only through political speech and action; and if, as she also proposes, elementary republics counterpoise to the Amachinery of government@ diverse spaces for public speech and action, then how does one prevent social distinctions embodied in and expressed through speech from corrupting both speech and participation in these political institutions? If indeed this leakage occurs, does it not contaminate the public sphere that Arendt seeks heroically to reclaim? And if so, is it not also the case that Arendt=s account of the linguistic nature of political life requires concomitantly something like a political sociology of language? These are the questions that are addressed in Pierre Bourdieu=s analyses of linguistic competence and exchange. II Bourdieu and the Politics of Language As with Arendt, Bourdieu=s writings pivot around questions of language and politics. From his early analyses of gender relations in his native village of Béarn to his study of the multiple meanings and complex processes of euphemization and sublimation in Heidegger=s Being and Time, from his exegeses of the politics of academic discourse to his accounts of the political history of linguistic unification in France, from his investigations of the production and reproduction of legitimate language to his critiques of Chomskyian and Saussurian linguistics, Bourdieu=s varied inquiries exhibit what Isaiah Berlin might term a hedgehog-like ambition to delineate the social and political implications of defining human beings as language animals. Similarly, Bourdieu shares with Arendt the conviction that the specifically political functions and content of language cannot be 17 understood adequately by theories which regard it exclusively as a vehicle of communication, representation, or the exchange of information. What, however, clearly distinguishes Bourdieu=s views of language from Arendt=s is his acute focus on the ways in which modes of domination and exclusion are enacted and sustained through concrete linguistic exchanges. Thus, while Arendt exalts the disclosive and revelatory aspects of public speech, the ways in which public narratives both reveal a person=s identity and forge associative bonds that sustain a space in which such revelation is possible, Bourdieu focuses instead on different forms of Adistinction@ that operate in and through language, namely, those distinctions that work as unnoticed conduits of exclusion. While Arendt extols the way that words and public speech bond and constitute political communities, Bourdieu explores the ways in which they quietly wound and dissolve them. Bourdieu=s account of what he terms Alinguistic competence@ therefore begins from an assumption that may appear uncontroversial but which he argues is neglected by most linguists and philosophers of language--that language is not simply a medium of communication, but is also an instrument of distinction, domination and violence. As such, the ways in which language is used, the social relations of the speakers, the forms of speech, the setting of speech, and the style in which speakers speak--things that are irrelevant to those who construe language exclusively as a medium of communication--are all potentially crucial to an understanding of the meaning of linguistic exchanges. In elaborating his political sociology of linguistic or symbolic domination, Bourdieu deploys a variety of concepts that he has continually refined and enriched over many years, the most important of which is that of habitus. This concept, which the Scholastics used to translate Aristotle=s hexis, is revived by Bourdieu in an effort to describe the process through which Ahabits@ 18 become incorporated in the body in the form of Adurable, transposable dispositions.@34 As a system of Asocially constituted dispositions@35 lying at the intersection of social structures and practical activity, the habitus is the embodied product of an individual=s history, experience (and especially early childhood experience), and social location, becoming over time an ethos, a set of flexible and enduring Amental structures@ and Abodily schemas@ that serve to organize, orient and direct one=s comportment in private and public space. Initially, it is defined in terms of objective potentialities in which it is situated--i.e., Athings to do or not to do, to say or not to say@36--all of which are in turn shaped by objective structures of social existence, e.g., Ahierarchies of age, power, prestige, and culture.@37 As it is gradually modified in accordance with the ever-changing circumstances of one=s life, however, the habitus generates regular and immediate responses to a wide array of situations without necessarily being the product of either strategic calculation, or the methodical execution of rigid rules. If the habitus is Bourdieu=s conceptual vehicle for describing the genesis and generation of agents= practical sense (le sens pratique) and comportment in everyday life, Afield@ and Amarket@ are his preferred terms for describing and conceptualizing the specific settings and social contexts in which individuals act. According to Bourdieu, specific practices and individual acts are generated neither by an independent, unconstrained habitus, nor by deterministic external or environmental forces, but rather through the relation between the habitus and specific social contexts. These fields or markets are themselves conceived as semi-autonomous social spaces, each of which contains specific regulative principles and prescribes particular values. Moreover, breaking with analytically empty and abstract concepts such as Asociety,@ Bourdieu emphasizes that these spaces are neither uniform nor homogenous but rather are socially structured arenas of conflict,38 with each field or 19 market containing a variety of Asocial positions@ occupied by specific agents, i.e., individuals or institutions. These positions, as well as the relations among them, are determined by the degree of Acapital@ within each field or market. Importantly, for Bourdieu Acapital@ includes not just economic capital (material wealth of a type that is Aimmediately and directly convertible into money@39), but also social capital (social connections with prominent or influential persons), cultural capital (cultural knowledge or educational credentials) and symbolic capital (social honor and prestige). Moreover, these forms of capital, while not automatically Aconvertible,@ often can be converted. So, for example, middle-class parents lacking the economic or social capital requisite for securing certain types of lucrative jobs for their children often seek to send them to prestigious schools in order to convert that capital into highly esteemed, well paying jobs. Bourdieu=s purpose in making such distinctions is to permit an analysis of various social settings and institutions as differentiated, dynamic and mutable, without thereby embracing the untenable view that social and political space is essentially anarchic or mercurially fluid. By utilizing the concepts of field, market and capital, Bourdieu avoids the idea that all social and political relations obey a single logic or form part of a seamless totality, while nevertheless insisting that relations are structured and can indeed Aobey an economic logic,@ though not necessarily one based on Anarrowly economic interests.@40 Employing these central concepts in his analysis of Alinguistic exchanges,@ Bourdieu argues that just as the habitus inculcates a system of durable dispositions that govern our practice, so there is also a secondary, linguistic habitus that instills durable dispositions that govern our linguistic practices. As the product of a specific habitus, these dispositions are inscribed in the body as part of a Atotal body schema,@ one in which Aone=s whole relation to the social world, and one=s whole 20 socially informed relation to the world, is expressed.@41 Through various forms of linguistic-bodily discipline, individual agents develop what Bourdieu calls an integrated Aarticulatory style@ which reveals their class position, social position, and at times more specific group identities. While these distinctive and contrasting styles are revealed principally in accents, gestures, intonations and other bodily techniques for speaking, Bourdieu, for example, points out that in France they are also manifested in two different words for the mouth, each of which has its own cluster of popular usages. Members of the french lower classes, for example, typically speak with a large and open mouth (la gueule), which is associated with Amanly dispositions@ that rule out censorship (as well as Afeminine@ traits such as Aprudence and deviousness as well as >airs and graces=@), and valorize a virility that frequently manifests itself in verbal or even physical violence (casser la gueule, ferme la gueule--@smash your face in,@ Ashut your face@). By contrast, members of the bourgeois classes typically speak with a more closed, pinched mouth (la bouche), one that is Atense and censored, and therefore feminine.@42 Importantly, Bourdieu emphasizes that among the dispositions inculcated by the habitus is a sense of the value that one=s Alinguistic products@ will have in specific markets such as school or the labor market. He maintains that within particular social fields, differential values are accorded to linguistic products, meaning that although there may be no formal barriers to speech within a particular field, there are practical barriers to authoritative speech, i.e., speech that is recognized as legitimate and worthy of attention. As Bourdieu states, AA speaker=s linguistic strategies (tension or relaxation, vigilance or condescension, etc.) are oriented ... not so much by the chances of being understood or misunderstood (communicative efficiency or the chances of communicating), but rather by the chances of being listened to, believed, obeyed....@43 In other words, hierarchies of 21 linguistic legitimacy and authority (what Bourdieu terms Aa high or low acceptability level@44) informally regulate the operations of linguistic markets, privileging certain linguistic competences as Acorrect@ and Aacceptable,@ while censoring others. According to Bourdieu, agents lacking the linguistic competence valorized in a particular social or institutional domain are faced with essentially three possibilities. First, and least commonly, they can contest the legitimacy of the dominant language by refusing to recognize it, thus initiating what Bourdieu calls Alinguistic conflict.@45 Such instances, he asserts, are most likely to occur during Acrisis situations,@ where Athe tension and corresponding censorships are lowered.@46 Secondly, they might try to euphemize their expressions by casting them into the forms that are positively sanctioned by the market. These efforts, however, are typically futile, simply because linguistic competency involves not only grammar and diction, but Aall the properties constituting the speaker=s social personality.@47 Unlike articles of clothing, these Aproperties@--accent, pronunciation, bodily comportment--are inscribed in the body over the course of a lifetime and cannot be exchanged or jettisoned without great efforts of will. Furthermore, even in those instances where euphemization is possible, it is often achieved only by negating (or being perceived as negating) aspects of one=s own social or personal identity, or by narrowly circumscribing the range and content of what can be expressed.48 Finally, and most typically, speakers lacking the sanctioned forms of competence in a particular social domain may simply withdraw themselves from those domains, as in the case of the peasant who, Ain order to explain why he did not dream of becoming mayor of his village even though he obtained the biggest share of the vote, said (in French) that he >didn=t know how to speak= (meaning French), implying a definition of linguistic competence that is entirely sociological.@49 Less anecdotally, Bourdieu writes that 22 Speakers lacking the legitimate competence are de facto excluded from the social domains in which this competence is required, or are condemned to silence. What is rare, then, is not the capacity to speak, which, being part of our biological heritage, is universal and therefore nondistinctive, but rather the competence necessary in order to speak the legitimate language which, depending on social inheritance, re-translates social distinctions into the specifically symbolic logic of differential deviations, or, in short, distinction.50 What is so disturbing about these forms of censorship and exclusion is not only the fact that they raise difficult questions about the de facto and de jure basis upon which any shared or authorized language is constituted, and hence about the basis of politics itself, but also the fact that these exclusions and silences frequently operate in ways that escape conscious recognition on the part of those involved. As Bourdieu submits: The distinctiveness of symbolic violence lies precisely in the fact that it assumes, of those who submit to it, an attitude which challenges the usual dichotomy of freedom and constraint. The >choices= of the habitus ... are accomplished without consciousness or constraint, by virtue of the dispositions which, although they are unquestionably the product of social determinisms, are also constituted outside the spheres of consciousness and constraint. The propensity to reduce the search for causes to the search for responsibilities makes it impossible to see that intimidation, a symbolic violence which is not aware of what it is (to the extent that it implies no act of intimidation) can only be exerted on a person predisposed (in his habitus) to feel it, whereas others will ignore it. It is already partly true to say that the cause of the timidity lies in the relation between the situation or the intimidating person (who may deny any intimidating intention) and the person intimidated, or rather, 23 between the social conditions of production of each of them. And little by little, one has to take account of the whole social structure.51 In emphasizing the distinctiveness of this process--namely, the manner in which it operates causally and materially without being the product of overt force or conscious intention--Bourdieu draws attention to what I shall call a second dimension of violence. Stated tersely, the onedimensional view designates the standard social scientific construal of violence as involving above all an agent=s coercive use of physical force (either directly or through the use of various instruments).52 This view, which is evident in Max Weber=s influential definition of the state as Aa relation of men dominating men, a relation supported by means of legitimate (i.e. considered to be legitimate) violence,@53 defines violence expressly in terms of three basic elements: (1) a relation of domination, (2) a use of instruments of coercion or physical force directly on person=s bodies and (3) its instrumental, means-end character. Indeed, so common is this idea that even Arendt, who in AOn Violence@ criticizes almost all previous writers (including Weber) for their reluctance to distinguish adequately between violence and other terms such as power, authority, strength and force, includes in her definition two of these elements, differing only on a rather technical rendering of force as Athe energy released by physical or social movements.@54 Bourdieu, by designating as violent relations that involve neither instrumental calculation nor the use of physical force or instruments directly on person=s bodies, seeks to illuminate an inconspicuous mode of domination that operates effectively precisely because it is so Agentle.@ Such violations are not, as Bourdieu emphasizes, identical to the brute physical violence of torture or rape. Symbolic violence, as we have seen, lacks the intentional and instrumental quality of brute violence, and works not directly on bodies but through them. Nevertheless, symbolic violence shares 24 with ordinary usage not only an accent on relations of domination, but also on modes of domination or breaches of dignity that do not involve the use of overt physical force (as when we speak of being the object of Aviolent denunciations,@ of having been Adone violence@ or having had one=s trust Aviolated@). By extending the notion of violence to the symbolic realm, Bourdieu thus foregrounds an often unnoticed mechanism that generates and sustains relations of domination. And to the extent that such mechanisms go unnoticed, they are, as we have seen, also more difficult to combat. It is therefore in these ordinary violences which are neither simply consented to nor simply imposed that Bourdieu=s analyses become most pertinent politically. If, as Arendt argues, the denial of public speech is the denial of a properly human existence, then questions about the specific mechanisms of exclusion from public discourse (or the basis upon which one is included in that discourse) are political questions of the first order. As I have been arguing, they are also the questions that Bourdieu=s accounts of language, power and violence instructively address. III The Power of Speech Bourdieu=s signal contribution to the politics of language is his delineation of the diverse ways that systems of meanings and embodied speech sustain processes of exclusion and exploitation by masking socially valorized norms and hierarchies as natural or meritocratic. By showing how mechanisms of misrecognition prompt agents to unwittingly accept as legitimate that which is in fact arbitrary, Bourdieu uncovers a form of violence that is non-physical and therefore not categorically located in Arendt=s private realm. Indeed, as a form of violence that occurs in the absence of any conscious intimidation or consciousness of intimidation, the phenomena of symbolic violence escape Arendt=s specific strictures distinguishing political from pre- or non-political speech. Since these 25 strictures all focus on conscious intentions (to manipulate, misrepresent or coerce),55 they fail to address the peculiar features of symbolic violence. If Bourdieu=s political sociology of language exposes a dimension of language and speech that escapes Arendtian categories, it is nonetheless far from clear that his account, however rich and provocative, is not fully adequate either. For while Bourdieu=s studies of language and symbolic violence elucidate forms of domination and silencing inhering in and enacted through language, what he fails to provide is any positive account of language as a potent source of collective power, i.e., power as a capacity to accomplish things by acting together in the name of common ends. This absence of any articulation of the links between language and power in the paradigmatically Arendtian sense is in part due to the absence of any well-developed notion of political community in Bourdieu. As we have seen, Bourdieu conceives of social and political space not only as differentiated, dynamic and agonistic, but as a structurally unequal Abattlefield@ of forces. And while it is true that one of his central ambitions is to explore and identify the principal conditions of a Anon-violent communication,@56 or what Arendt would term the conditions of possibility of political speech, Bourdieu=s work contains few examples of such communication. Whatever the ultimate sources of Bourdieu=s neglect of this intersubjective conception of power, the political stakes of his omission are considerable. For unless one assumes that the mere exposure of arbitrary hierarchies and norms is sufficient for dramatically attenuating their effects or eliminating them altogether, then the alternatives to the Arendtian notion of power as something that Asprings up in between men when they act together@ would seem to be conspicuously limited. Standard interest group politics would seem to be of limited effectiveness, in part because success in such politics is usually premised on access to resources that dominated groups rarely possess in large 26 quantities. On the other hand, violence, as Arendt points out, can perhaps produce order and obedience, but never legitimacy, authority or power. To bring these issues into sharper relief, I would like to conclude with a brief examination of a concrete case of the politics of speech within a particular institutional setting. While there are many recent examples of groups attempting to modify or reappropriate the dominant languages of political discourse and their representation in that discourseBthe civil rights movement in the 1960s, the feminist movements of the 1970s and 1980s, various forms of identity politics in the 1980s and 1990s and most recently various evangelical and religious movementsBI will focus on a case that might initially appear to be anomalous, but which I have deliberately chosen because of its provocative nature. It is a case that allows us to see how Bourdieu=s analysis of linguistic competence and the ability to speak authoritatively might be allied with Arendt=s arguments about the disclosive aspects of political speech and speech as a source of collective power. The example revolves around an often heated set of controversies involving the efforts of AIDS activists to take Aa seat at the table@ of key scientific committees and advisory boards that regulated and funded AIDS research in the United States. This case offers a particularly rich example of how linguistic competences valorized in particular institutional settings structure processes of democratic inquiry and deliberation, operating, in effect, as informal barriers that limit the scope of democratic participation in issues of public concern. At the same time, it provides an opportunity to observe one distinctive way in which those barriers were at least partially overcome and what can happenBpolitically, morally, and epistemologicallyBwhen they are.57 The case involved an emergent public of those affected by AIDS and a set of institutions that were initially unresponsive to them. As biomedical researchers, pharmaceutical companies, 27 biotechnology firms, members of regulatory agencies, and AIDS activists struggled during the early 1980s and onward to identify the procedures and practices most likely to yield insight into the causes, treatment, and possible cure of AIDS, a number of increasingly intense disputes emerged. As one might expect, many of these disputes focused on distributive issues involving public funding of, and private investment in, AIDS-related research.58 Particularly during the early phase of the AIDS epidemic, many activists sought to focus public attention on what they viewed as grossly inadequate federal funding of AIDS research, treatment, prevention, and social services. Often charging the Reagan administration with severe neglect of the AIDS epidemic, activists and some prominent elected officials pressed for increased funding to address the crisis.59 By the late 1980s, however, activist attention was increasingly focused on the drug development process itself. And here a rather different set of issues arose, namely, issues about the proper direction, practice, and ethics of clinical research. Shifting their attention from the Food and Drug Administration (FDA) to the National Institute of Health (NIH), and, more particularly, to the bureaucratic entity charged with administering the network of publicly-funded clinical trials of AIDS treatmentsBthe AIDS Clinical Trials Group (ACTG) of the National Institute of Allergy and Infectious Diseases (NIAID)Bactivists pursued the lofty and highly improbable goal of inserting themselves directly into those ACTG committees that made critical decisions about research priorities and the proper conduct of research. Arguing simultaneously on two fronts, activists alleged, first, that the closed-door meetings of key committees violated basic democratic norms of openness and transparencyBone leading activist, Mark Harrington, frequently asserted that Athe ACTG acted as a secret society@60Band, second, that the ACTG was not, as its defenders maintained, a Aneutral advisory body.@61 Instead, activists viewed the ACTG meetings as Aa political field,@ 28 one in which Athe principal investigators who comprised its advisory committees all had vested interests.@62 Summarizing activists= objections, Steven Epstein writes: A>Card carrying virologists dominated the all-powerful executive committee that made final decisions behind closed doors about which studies to fund. The executive committee insured that the bulk of the resources went to the giant, high-profile trials of the antivirals, while researchers studying anti-infectives were starved for funds.@63 Largely eschewing the common strategy within many social movements of challenging the authority of some experts by enlisting other experts to speak on one=s own behalf, activists instead aimed to interject themselves as an alternative voice on these committees. In short, they began demanding Aa seat the table,@ that is, an opportunity to participate alongside scientific and governmental elites in those forums where deliberations and decisions about the practices and priorities of AIDS research occurred. Moreover, they insisted that their participation not be meaningless or token participationBactivists sought to obtain the same voting rights that the principal investigators themselves enjoyed.64 Although many of the researchers sitting on the ACTG committees were openly skeptical of these proposalsBas one key researcher remarked, AWhat are you going to do if you want to have a serious scientific discussion about a promising agent and you=ve got someone from the Provincetown PWA Coalition who thinks that [the drug] Peptide T is the greatest thing since sliced bread . . . ?@65BDr. Anthony Fauci, Director of NIAID, eventually agreed to activists= demands Aand forced the researchers to play along.@66 Importantly, these demands were not accompanied by a wholesale rejection of expert authority or of the cognitive division of labor. Rather, AIDS activists largely agreed that by its very nature scientific practice required both specialization and expertise.67 29 However, their acknowledgment of the legitimate role of specialization and expertise raised an important, and specifically Bourdieuian, issue: if effective activist participation in debates about biomedical research requires, among other things, an ability Ato speak in the language of medical science,@68 then how could the voices of lay activists possibly have authority within those institutions that oversee the conduct and direction of AIDS research? Within these deliberative forums, how could activist claims and challenges be taken seriously as claims, that is, as interventions that are recognized by others as having standing? In short, without some basic familiarity with Athe language of biomedicine,@69 how could theyBand why should theyBbe taken seriously by those they hoped to persuade? What is particularly significant in this context is that groups like Act-Up implicitly accepted the premise of this view, yet nonetheless proceeded to challenge experts on their own terrain, and not just in the wider political arena. Recognizing the credibility gap that separated themselves from officials and researchers in the NIH and FDA, treatment activists went about the hard task of acquiring credibility by Alearning the language and culture of medical science.@70 As Steven Epstein has remarked: AWhile activists have . . . insisted on the need to bring >nonscientific= language and judgments into their encounters with medical researchers, they have nonetheless assumed that the capacity to speak the language of the journal article and the conference hall is a sine qua non of effective participation.@71 Revealingly, when activists describe their initiation into the world of medical research, they often depict the process as akin to learning a foreign language or becoming familiar with the practices of an alien culture.72 Once armed with Aa working knowledge of the medical vocabulary@73 and detailed understanding of the arcana of clinical trial design, Atreatment activists@ or Alay experts@ were able 30 to spark debates about Aepistemic criteria and experimental validity,@74 raising issues about the design of clinical trials, the conditions under which patients could be expected to comply with study protocols, the criteria for inclusion in or exclusion from clinical trials, the value of a Apragmatic approach@ to clinical trials and a variety of methodological issues.75 They pushed, for example, Afor institutionalized mechanisms of >expanded access=@76 to experimental drugs, contending that orthodox policies of Arestricted access@ were at once Amorally offensive@ (in restricting the availability of experimental treatments exclusively to those persons who were selectedBon the basis of stringent entry criteriaBto participate in clinical trials77) and destructive of scientists= ability to conduct reliable clinical research (by making it increasingly difficult for scientists to enlist research subjects who would comply with study protocols).78 Activists also sought to transform the clinical trials themselves, both by diversifying the demographic characteristics of the participants in those trials and by making Athe trials more relevant, more humane, and more capable of generating trustworthy conclusions.@79 Finally, AIDS activists pressed the FDA for accelerated approval of promising drugs, maintaining that the very high standards of statistical validity that typically governed the drug approval process were inappropriate in cases of acute medical emergencies like the AIDS epidemic.80 More broadly, treatment activists challenged the dominant image of scientific inquiry as a pure and pristine activity, one that is cleansed of muddy ambiguities and insulated from the contaminating influences of practical exigencies, ethical demands and political pressures. Contending that this image of scientific purity was often deployed by mainstream researchers as a rhetorical device designed to entrench a single vision of the scientific enterprise as the only one that could rightfully be termed science, activists articulated a view of scientific inquiry that was grounded 31 in an appreciation of the striking Aimpurities@ of biomedical scienceBthe tensions, uncertainties, ironies, controversies, and contingencies that permeate the institutions and practices of biomedicine.81 This alternative conception, which they claimed more adequately represented the staggering complexities and Areal-world messiness@82 of AIDS research, focused on the needs and desires of patients as well as researchers, the dynamic interplay of ethical and epistemological claims, the knotty entanglements of power and knowledge, and the value of a pragmatic (as opposed to fastidious) perspective on the purpose of clinical trials.83 Moreover, in the view of most AIDS activists a recognition of these factors advanced rather than subverted the quest for good science.84 Although often sharp critics of various aspects of AIDS research, treatment activists were nonetheless able to forge over time cooperative relationships with epidemiologists, biostatisticians, bioethicists and other specialists. Indeed, one result of this process was the metamorphosis of treatment activists into what Steven Epstein has termed Aa new species of expert that could speak credibly in the language of researchers.@85 To be sure, many researchers were initially reluctant (to put the matter mildly) to include activists as participants in deliberations and decisions about the funding and conduct of biomedical research and the approval of new drugs. In addition to doubts about activists= grasp of the language and practice of medical science, activist efforts to achieve recognition as legitimate and credible participants in key decision-making bodies were complicatedBat least initiallyBby another factor that looms large in Bourdieu=s work: styles of embodied conduct that often violated implicit codes of proper dress, speech and behavior in formal scientific and governmental arenas. As Dr. Louis Lasagna, the chair of a special governmental committee formed to examine procedures regarding AIDS and cancer drugs, remarked, AIDS activists looked and acted in a manner that was strikingly different from other laypersons who spoke 32 about their illnesses. While the typical woman dying of breast cancer was Avery well behaved,@ Awell-dressed@ and spoke in measured tones about the need for new treatments and therapies, treatment activists were noisy, had a Apenchant for the dramatic@ and Acame dressed in any old way almost proud of looking bizarre.@86 Sometimes deploying a language and rhetoric that was more visual than verbal, activists would not uncommonly use highly theatrical modes of communication to challenge entrenched procedures and underscore their points. As Lasagna himself recounted, AAbout fifty of them showed up, and took out their watches and dangled them to show that time was ticking away for them.@87 It goes without saying that these dramaturgical forms of engagement often violated norms of discourse, deliberation and emotional expression within bureaucratic and scientific-medical institutions.88 Fortunately, activists= efforts were abetted by two distinctive factors. First, activists and researchers were bound together not just by shared aspirations but also by relationships of mutual need and dependence. While AIDS patients and activists undoubtedly needed researchers= highly specialized medical and scientific expertise, researchers needed patients who were willing to cooperateBto follow study protocolsBin clinical trials. Without a willingness on the part of people with HIV and AIDS to participate in trials and conform to study protocols, scientists= own goals were unachievable. Second, activists were able to leverage to their advantage other norms operating within the scientific field. Steven Epstein, for example, notes that Aexperts who maintained even nominal adherence to the notion that scientific arguments should be evaluated >without regard to person= have often found it difficult to dismiss such arguments simply on the basis of their >questionable= origin.@89 And here treatment activists= willingness to master the language of biomedicine while immersing themselves in the minutiae of scientific and clinical research was 33 critical to their success. Indeed, even Lasagna himself could not help but be grudgingly impressed: AI=d swear that the ACT UP group from New York must have read everything I ever wrote . . . And quoted whatever served their purpose. It was quite an experience.@90 Although often saturated with friction and discord, the long-term result of these interactions was a fairly startling shift of understanding among activists and experts alike. Over time, researchers and biomedical authorities revised their view of activists as well as themselves. Perhaps most significantly, they came to recognize and appreciate not only treatment activists= mastery of the languages and cultures of medical science, but also the distinctive repositories of knowledge, information, and expertise that activists possessed and they did not. Most notably, activists were able to draw on their links to gay communities and people with AIDS to provide an informed perspective on Awhat would work in the community,@ that is, on the conditions under which Apeople with AIDS and HIV would willingly participate in the trials and conform to the protocols.@91 In such cases, treatment activists= own Aimpure,@ hybrid identities (as persons positioned simultaneously inside and outside federal health bureaucracies and on both sides of the lay/expert divide) was a decided asset. It enabled them to complicate and realign conventional distinctions between experts and laypersons, while also providing them with insights, skills, and Asituated knowledges@92 needed to act as intermediaries (between various communities, cultures and constituencies) and translators (between, for example, political and technical languages, or the languages of the street and the languages of the meeting room). For their part, treatment activists were also changed by the experience. They developed a deeper understanding of the profound challenges entailed in bringing together ethical and epistemological commitments, in striking creative compromises between the competing demands of long-term and short-term goals, and in 34 attending properly to the opposing claims of those who advocated widely different entry criteria for inclusion in clinical trials. They also came to appreciate better the immense difficulties and labor involved in finding reliable answers to their questions. Seen from a specifically Bourdieuian point of view, many aspects of this process emerge in sharp relief. As Bourdieu=s analysis of linguistic competence suggests, activist efforts to become genuine participants in deliberations about the design and purpose of clinical trials required at a minimum Afamiliarity with the language of bioscience.@93 Absent some real competency in this language, activist interventions in biomedical debates would scarcely have been recognized as either credible or authoritative. Moreover, it is equally apparent that activist efforts to Ademocratize the practices of knowledge-making@94 were only partially successful. Just as Bourdieu argues that Aaccess to legitimate language is unequal,@95 so can one observe in the case of AIDS activism that the time and background understanding needed to achieve competence in the language of bioscience was not equally available to all. As studies of AIDS activism have shown, Agay communities possessed a relatively high degree of >cultural capital=B[that is to say,] . . . they had cultivated a disposition for appropriating knowledge and culture.@96 It is therefore not surprising, as Epstein notes, that Athe stars of the treatment activist movement were typically science novices, but ones who were unusually articulate, self-confident, and well educatedB>displaced intellectuals from other fields,= according to Jim Eigo, a New York City treatment activist with a background in the arts. Often these activists were able to parlay other social and personal advantages into a new type of credibilityBto convert their >capital= from one form into another.@97 In short, while treatment activism expanded the scope of participation on advisory committees, institutional review boards and community advisory boards, treatment activists themselves hardly constituted a representative 35 sample of people affected by AIDS. To the contrary, Astratification by gender, race, class, and education helped to structure access to the >lay expert= identity.@98 While Bourdieu=s theoretical perspective shines a spotlight on the kinds of barriers activists needed to overcome in order to gain access to, and participate effectively in, key forums where decisions were made and norms were set, it has much less to say about the rather astonishing transformations that occurred in the process of participation itself. Here, I would argue, Arendt has more to teach us. In the first place, the ways in which individual positions shifted and evolved through the process of spirited debate and discussion is perhaps best captured by Arendt=s distinction between interests, which in Arendt=s view are shared by members of a group and are the principal source of conflict in what we call interest group politics, and opinions, which are distinctive, individual positions reached by political agents Ain a process of open discussion@99 and debate. Although the discussions between treatment activists and members of the biomedical establishment were never, as I have noted, fully inclusive in the sense of being open to just anyone who wanted to participate, activists= success in finding a seat at the table of various committees and review boards transformed quite dramatically both the self-understandings of the participants engaged in those deliberations and the outcomes of them. On the one hand, through their deliberations both treatment activists and professional scientists developed what Arendt refers to as an Aenlarged mentality,@ that is, an ability to transcend one=s own local or personal perspective by taking into account where others stand. As Arendt suggestively states, ATo think with an enlarged mentality means that one trains one=s imagination to go visiting.@100 Judging by the accounts of the participants themselves and the evolution of their views over time, the often intense confrontation of different perspectives yielded, more often than not, just this kind of enlarged mentality. For instance, 36 Anthony Fauci, the Director of NIAID and the government=s AIDS research programs, remarked in a 1989 interview that AIn the beginning, these people [referring to AIDS activists] had a blanket disgust with us. And it was mutual. Scientists said all trials should be restricted, rigid, and slow. The gay groups said we were killing people with red tape. When the smoke cleared we realized that much of their criticism was absolutely valid.@101 Similarly, activists developed over time a deeper appreciation of the enormous challenges faced by AIDS researchers. While continuing to press for expanded access to various therapies, they also became increasingly wary of the Ahype cycle@ that often accompanied the introduction of new experimental drugs. Moreover, by 1992 many activists began taking a much longer range view of the problem and were advocating a new direction in AIDS research, one that would place much greater emphasis on basic research. On the other hand, the democratization of expert authority altered participants understanding of the community of researchers to include at least in principle all of those involved in the collective enterprise, which in this case included not only doctors and biomedical researchers, but also patients, activists and others affected by AIDS. Through their frequently agonistic yet also cooperative engagements, activists and researchers alike came to recognize the benefits (including epistemological benefits) of a more inclusive, polyvocal and democratic process of deliberation. Perhaps more than anything, however, the democratization of expertise yielded new forms of what Arendt calls Apower,@ that is, the power that is Agenerated,@ as Arendt puts it, Awhen people gather together and act in concert@ and Awhich disappears the moment they depart.@102 Power, in other words, is intersubjective: it names, as John McGowan has remarked, Athe creative, public side effects that attend political action.@ Moreover, it is Awhat keeps the public realm . . . in existence.@103 37 One of the most remarkable aspects of the emergence of these new forms of political power is their appearance in arenas and spaces that, from a conventional Arendtian perspective, are deemed non-political. As is well-known, Arendt viewed the advent of the administrative state, as well as the vast extension of bureaucratic structures and institutions, as both an index of the expansion of Athe social@ and a central factor in Athe disastrous shrinkage of the public realm.@104 Although not without their uses, Afully developed@ bureaucracies, Arendt believed, encourage dangerous forms of thoughtlessness, diminish a sense of responsibility for broader outcomes, and foster forms of inertia and automatic behavior that are inimical to political freedom and human spontaneity. Yet in the case we have just observed, a space of public speech and spontaneous action emerged from within a very large bureaucratic institution, namely, the federal health bureaucracy. Instead of acquiescing quietly to its rules and routines, however, activists used their seat at the table to disrupt and change them. And while it is true that both activists and researchers were deeply concerned about goals and outcomes, these concerns did not typically degenerate into an instrumentalist attitude the transforms flexible and provisional goals into fixed and nonnegotiable ends.105 To the contrary, activists regularly contested instrumentalist (in the strict sense that Arendt deploys this term) and technocratic modes of discourse, insisting instead that ostensibly technical and instrumental questions be recast and placed in a wider frame, one that includes neglected matters of ethics, justice, democracy and the public good. Ultimately, many activists came to see their contribution to these latter issues as constituting perhaps their most lasting legacy. As two leading treatment activists, Gregg Gonsalves and Mark Harrington, wrote in 1992: AIf AIDS activists ever leave any legacy other than their own bodies, it will be, among other things, a movement for national health care and the democratization of research.@106 While the goal of democratizing biomedicine has yet to, and may never fully, be 38 achieved, there is little doubt that the joint actions of AIDS activists and researchers have reshaped the institutions and practices of biomedical research, as well as the contours and boundaries of the scientific and medical fields. They have, in other words, introduced new and unpredicted principles and practices in the most unlikely of places. Thus, only something akin to Arendt=s notion of power is likely to provide both a vehicle and a legitimate normative basis for combating the various forms of exclusion and symbolic violence that Bourdieu so effectively exposes. In this respect the Arendtian conception of power serves as a necessary complement not only to Bourdieu=s work, but to the work of a wide variety of poststructuralist writers who adroitly unmask structures of domination and exclusion posing as natural, eternal or meritocratic relations. If, as I have argued, these undertakings are vital to any serious quest for a genuinely democratic future, it is questionable whether they alone are adequate for the task of constituting legitimate forms of public and political power. Indeed, as Sheldon Wolin has aptly remarked, Athe problem of the political is not to deny the ubiquity of power but to deny power uses that destroy common ends.@107 If Bourdieu eloquently reminds us of the first truth, Arendt does likewise with the second. 39 NOTES 1. Hannah Arendt, The Human Condition (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1958), p. 3. 2. Ludwig Wittgenstein, Philosophical Investigations (New York: MacMillan, 1968), 146e. 3. J.G.A. Pocock, AVerbalizing a Political Act: Toward a Politics of Speech,@ Political Theory 1 (February 1973): 28. 4. This is to say that for Foucault and MacKinnon language (and for MacKinnon speech in particular) is inextricably connected to conduct. For Foucault, this implies that language is a mode of government that designates Athe way in which the conduct of individuals or groups might be directed.@ See Michel Foucault, AAfterward: The Subject and Power,@ in Hubert Dreyfus and Paul Rabinow, Michel Foucault: Beyond Structuralism and Hermeneutics (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1983), p. 221. By contrast, MacKinnon draws on J. L. Austin=s theory of performative speech to argue that some forms of speech, notably, pornographic speech, Arequire understanding . . . more in active than in passive terms, as constructing and performative rather than as merely referential or connotative.@ These forms of speech can be, and often are also, actions. See Catherine A. MacKinnon, Only Words (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1993), p. 21. 5. Michel Foucault, Power/Knowledge, ed. Colin Gordon (New York: Pantheon, 1980), p. 99. 6. It is precisely this power of pornography to impose meanings and silence women that lends force to MacKinnon=s juridical prescriptions. Because the addressees of pornography cannot speak for themselves, it is necessary for the law to speak in and on their behalf. 40 7. On this point see, for example, James F. Bohman, AEmancipation and Rhetoric: The Perlocutions and Illocutions of the Social Critic,@ Philosophy and Rhetoric 21 (1988): 185-204; William Rehg, AReason and Rhetoric in Habermas=s Theory of Argumentation,@ in Walter Jost and Michael J. Hyde, eds., Rhetoric and Hermeneutics in Our Time (New Haven and London: Yale University Press, 1997), pp. 358-377; and Iris Marion Young, Inclusion and Democracy (New York: Oxford University Press, 2000), Ch. 2. 8. Although it would be a mistake to deny or underemphasize differences of intellectual and political context, narrative style, and theoretical orientation, it is equally important not to exaggerate these differences. Unfortunately, the disparaties in Arendt=s and Bourdieu=s thought are typically easy to spot, while the continuities are less readily identifiable. In this latter regard, it is worth noting that both thinkers share, among other things, an important, if also deeply ambivalent, intellectual debt to the thought of Martin Heidegger. In Arendt=s case, Heidegger was the most influential of her many distinguished teachers, a figure whom she described late in her life as Athe hidden king@ who Areigned therefore in the realm of thinking.@ See Hannah Arendt, AMartin Heidegger at Eighty,@ in Michael Murray, ed., Heidegger and Modern Philosophy: Critical Essays (New Haven, CT: Yale University Press, 1978), p. 295. While Arendt eventually became a severe critic of Heidegger=s philosophical politics, aspects of his thought continued to inform much of Arendt=s work, such as her theory of political action. For a thoughtful discussion of Heidegger=s influence on Arendt=s thought see Dana R. Villa, Arendt and Heidegger: The Fate of the Political (Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press, 1996). Similarly, Bourdieu has stated that Ain philosophy Heidegger was his >first love.=@ See Hubert L. Dreyfus, Being in the World: A Commentary on Heidegger=s Being and 41 Time, Division I (Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 1991), p. 9. Like Arendt, Bourdieu=s assessment of Heidegger=s thoughtBand his political thought in particularBwas hardly uncritical. See, for example, Pierre Bourdieu, The Political Ontology of Martin Heidegger (Stanford, CA: Stanford University Press, 1991). Nonetheless, both his phenomenologically informed view of social and political activity and his conception of the social field owe much to Heidegger=s work. See Dreyfus, Beingin-the-World, p. 9. In addition to the strong Heideggerian influence on their thought, Arendt and Bourdieu display striking affinities in their normative orientations. As I shall argue below, Bourdieu=s ideal of Anon-violent communication@ closely resembles Arendt=s account of the conditions of possibility of political speech. 9. For a view of Arendtian politics as anarchist, see Miguel Vatter, Between Norm and Form: Machiavelli=s Theory of Political Freedom (Dordrecht: Kluwer Academic Publishers, 2000). For a broader discussion of this issue, see Patchen Markell, AThe Rule of the People: Arendt, Archê, and Democracy,@ American Political Science Review 100 (February 2006): 1-14. 10. In the secondary literature on Bourdieu=s work, surprisingly little attention has been devoted to this topic. For one recent attempt to begin exploring Bourdieu=s views of democracy, see Loïc Wacquant, Pierre Bourdieu and Democratic Politics: The Mystery of Ministry (Cambridge, UK: Polity Press, 2005). 11. As Benhabib notes, Habermas= intellectual debt to Arendt is apparent in the opening pages of The Structural Transformation of the Public Sphere. It is also apparent in what is arguably his most important work of the past two decades, Between Facts and Norms. 42 See The Structural Transformation of the Public Sphere: An Inquiry in to a Category of Bourgeois Society, trans. by Thomas Burger with the assistance of Frederick Lawrence (Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 1991); and Between Facts and Norms: Contributions to a Discourse Theory of Law and Democracy, trans. by William Rehg (Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 1998). 12. See Loïc J.D. Wacquant, AOn the Tracks of Symbolic Power: Prefatory Notes on Bourdieu=s >State Nobility,=@ Theory, Culture & Society 10 (August 1993): 12. 13. Hannah Arendt, On Violence,@ in Crises of the Republic (New York: Harcourt Brace Jovanovich, 1972), p. 143. 14. Hannah Arendt, The Human Condition (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1958), p. 200. 15. Hannah Arendt, The Origins of Totalitarianism (New York: Harcourt Brace Jovanovich, 1979), pp. 475-476. 16. Arendt, The Human Condition, p. 180. 17. Ibid., p. 26. 18. Ibid. 19. George Kateb, Hannah Arendt: Politics, Conscience, Evil (Totowa, NJ: Rowman and Allanhead, 1983), p. 23. 20. Arendt, The Human Condition, pp. 178-179. 43 21. Ibid., p. 176. 22. Ibid., p. 200. 23. Ibid. 24. Hannah Arendt, AWhat is Freedom?@ in Between Past and Future (New York: Penguin Books, 1980), p. 146. 25. Hannah Arendt, AWhat Is Freedom?,@ pp. 168-169. 26. Sheila Benhabib, The Reluctant Modernism of Hannah Arendt (Thousand Oaks: Sage Publications, 1996), p. 198. Hanna Pitkin remarks similarly that AArendt was, on the whole, not much interested in institutional arrangements.@ See Hanna Fenichel Pitkin, The Attack of the Blob: Hannah Arendt=s Concept of the Social (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1998), p. 257. 27. As Arendt puts it: AThe failure of post-revolutionary thought to remember the revolutionary spirit and to understand it conceptually was preceded by a failure of the revolution to provide it with a lasting institution. . . . But in this republic there was no space reserved, no room left for the exercise of precisely those qualities which had been instrumental in building it.@ See Hannah Arendt, On Revolution (New York: Penguin Books, 1977), p. 232. 28. Hannah Arendt, AOn Hannah Arendt,@ in Melvyn Hill, ed., Hannah Arendt: The Recovery of the Public World (New York: St. Martin=s Press, 1979), p. 327. See also Arendt, The Human 44 Condition, p. 40; and Hannah Arendt, Eichmann in Jerusalem: A Report on the Banality of Evil, rev. ed. (New York: Penguin Books, 1976), p. 289. 29. Ibid. 30. This argument is developed in greater detail in Jeffrey C. Isaac, AOases in the Desert: Hannah Arendt on Democratic Politics,@ in Democracy in Dark Times (Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press, 1998), pp. 100-122. 31. Hannah Arendt, On Revolution, p. 255. 32. Ibid., p. 279. 33. Hannah Arendt, AOn Hannah Arendt,@ p. 327. 34. Pierre Bourdieu, The Logic of Practice (Stanford, CA: Stanford University Press, 1990), p. 53. 35. Axel Honneth et al., AThe Struggle for Social Order: An Interview with Pierre Bourdieu,@ Theory, Culture & Society 3 (1986): 42. For Bourdieu, the term Adisposition@ is employed because of its rich semantic content. As he explains, AThe word >disposition= seems particularly suited to express what is covered by the concept of habitus (defined as a system of dispositions). It expresses first the result of an organizing action, with a meaning close to that of words such as structure; it also designates a way of being, a habitual state (especially of the body), and, in particular, a predisposition, tendency, propensity, or inclination.@ See Outline of a Theory of Practice (New 45 York: Cambridge University Press, 1979), p. 214. 36. Ibid., p. 76. 37. Ibid., p. 25. 38. Here too there are striking similarities and differences between Arendt and Bourdieu. Just as Arendt views the Greek polis as an Aagonistic@ space or stage that provides an outlet for self-display and self-definition, so Bourdieu conceives social fields and markets as spaces of conflict and competition organized around a quest for distinction defined in terms of the Aprofits@ valorized in a specific field or market. The difference, of course, is that the agonism of the Greek polis was ideally oriented toward a fusion of personal distinction and the well-being of the political community, whereas Bourdieu=s concepts of field and market lack a similar orientation. 39. Pierre Bourdieu, AThe Forms of Capital,@ in John G. Richardson, ed., Handbook of Theory and Research for the Sociology of Education (New York: Greenwood, 1986), p. 243. 40. Pierre Bourdieu, The Logic of Practice, p. 50. 41. Pierre Bourdieu, AThe Economics of Linguistic Exchanges,@ Social Science Information 16 (6): 660. 42. Pierre Bourdieu, APrice Formation and the Anticipation of Profits,@ in Language and Symbolic Power, op. cit., pp. 86-7. 43. Pierre Bourdieu, AThe Economics of Linguistic Exchanges,@ op. cit., p. 654. 46 44. Ibid., p. 656. 45. Ibid., p. 664. 46. Ibid., p. 663. 47. Ibid., p. 655. 48. Bourdieu holds Athat each field draws the dividing line between the sayable and the unsayable (or unnameable) which defines its specificity. In other words, the form and content of discourse depend on the capacity to express the expressive interests attached to a position within the limits of the constraints of the censorship that is imposed on the occupant of the position, i.e., the required formality.@ Ibid., p. 657. 49. Pierre Bourdieu, Language and Symbolic Power, op. cit., pp. 68-9. 50. Ibid., p. 55. 51. Ibid., p. 51. 52. In this respect it contains affinities with what Steven Lukes calls Athe one-dimensional view of power.@ Like that view of power, the one-dimensional view of violence limits the scientific scope of the term to acts involving directly observable, manifest conflict. See Power: A Radical View (London and Basingstoke: Macmillan Publishers, 1984), pp. 11-15. 53. Max Weber, APolitics as a Vocation,@ in H. H. Gerth and C. Wright Mills, eds., From Max 47 Weber (New York: Oxford University Press, 1978), p. 78. 54. Hannah Arendt, AOn Violence,@ in Crises of the Republic (New York: Harcourt Brace Jovanovich, 1972), p. 144. 55. Hannah Arendt, The Human Condition, p. 200. 56. Pierre Bourdieu, AUnderstanding,@ in Pierre Bourdieu et al., The Weight of the World: Social Suffering in Contemporary Society (Stanford, CA: Stanford University Press, 1999), p. 608. 57. One might contend that this caseBfocusing as it does on the efforts of AIDS activists to attain entry into those committees, boards, and funding bodies that powerfully impacted the conduct and direction of scientific research into HIV and AIDSBis an awkward if not inappropriate vehicle for exploring Arendt=s views of speech and action. One might argue, for instance, that the very issues which AIDS activists sought to politicizeBissues of the body and of biological lifeBare precisely the kinds of social issues that Arendt excludes from the sphere of politics. From this perspective, AIDS activists= politicization of AIDS research might be seen as a distressing symptom of the modern tendency to blur, if not erase, critical distinctions between the private, the social, and the political spheres. While such a view is not entirely unwarranted, I believe it obscures important complexities and ambiguities in Arendt=s work and in the interventions of AIDS activists. Regarding Arendt=s work, I would contend that her distinctions between different spheres human activity are not most charitably or productively conceived as fixed and nonnegotiable ontological categories that facilitate a tidy compartmentalization of some issues, activities and classes of people as intrinsically suited for the public and political realm and others as not. Rather, I follow a number of scholarsBmost notably 48 Hannah Pitkin, Bonnie Honig, and Linda ZerilliBin arguing that Arendt=s distinction between the social and the political is not necessarily intended to debar all social concerns from the precincts of politics but, as Zerilli has put it, to warn Aagainst the introduction of the instrumentalist attitude that such concerns often carry with them. Insofar as expediency is held to be the highest criterion, the instrumentalist attitude treats democratic politics as a means to an end, which almost inevitably leads citizens to allow the actions and judgments of experts to substitute for their own. . . . There is neither a determinate group of persons nor a determinate class of objects that is by definition social, not political. Instead, there is a tendency to develop an anti-political sensibility . . . against which we need to be on our guard.@ See Linda M. G. Zerilli, Feminism and the Abyss of Freedom (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 2005), pp. 3-4. See also Hanna Pitkin, AJustice: On Relating the Public and Private,@ Political Theory 9 (August 1981): 342; and Bonnie Honig, AToward an Agonistic Feminism: Hannah Arendt and the Politics of Identity,@ in Bonnie Honig, ed., Feminist Interpretations of Hannah Arendt (University Park, PA: Pennsylvania State University Press, 1995), pp. 135-166. In this reading of Arendt, the key question regarding AIDS activism isn=t whether the issues activists sought to raise were inherently political or nonpolitical, but whether their attitudes, sensibilities, and modes of discourse were dominated by instrumental considerations, the criterion of expediency, and Aends@ rather than Agoals.@ The last of these factorsBends and goalsBis particularly salient, as Arendt insists that Aends are not the same thing as goals, which are always what political action pursues; the goals of politics are never anything more than the guidelines and directives by which we orient ourselves and which, as such, are never cast in stone, but whose concrete realizations are constantly changing because we are dealing with other people who have 49 goals. Only when brute force with its arsenal of means is introduced into the space between people . . . do the goals of politics become ends which are as firmly defined as the model on which any physical object is produced and like it determine the choice of means and justify and even sanctify them.@ See Hannah Arendt, AIntroduction into Politics,@ in The Promise of Politics, ed. Jerome Kohn (New York: Schocken, 2005), pp. 193. As this passage indicates, Arendt=s conception of politics and the political sphere places great emphasis on how practical purposes are pursued, that is, whether they are pursued in a flexible and open-ended manner or are guided by Afirmly defined,@ Aready-made formulas.@ The (or at least one) great danger to the vitality of political life and action, as Arendt understands it, consists in the atrophy of goals into ends and of action into execution. On the distinction between action and execution, see Arendt, On Revolution, p. 264. Consequently, it is not surprising that those moments of political ferment which Arendt most deeply admiresBfrom the revolutionary councils in Russia and Hungary to the anti-Nazi resistance movements during World War II to the non-violent wing of the anti-Vietnam War movement in the United StatesBare notable in part because those who participated in them were animated largely by the pursuit of goals rather than ends. As I will argue below, AIDS activists attempt to democratize scientific institutions evince a similar concern with goals rather than ends. 58. For a thoughtful, and Arendtian inspired, discussion of some of these issues, see Mark Reinhardt, AActing (Up) in Publics: Mobile Spaces, Plural Worlds,@ in The Art of Being Free: Taking Liberties with Tocqueville, Marx, and Arendt (Ithaca: Cornell University Press, 1997), pp. 142-178. While Reinhardt provides an insightful analysis of ACT UP=s activities outside formal governmental ans scientific institutions, he does not examine what is my primary concern here, 50 namely, treatment activists= participation in deliberations within biomedical institutions. 59. Although the first known cases of AIDS were reported by the Centers for Disease Control (CDC) in 1981, President Ronald Reagan remained conspicuously silent about the disease until asked about it by a reporter during a September 1985 news conference. Moreover, it has often been noted that Reagan failed to make any Aextensive public comments on AIDS until 1987,@ when he spoke on the eve of the Third International Conference on AIDS in Washington, DC. See Robin Toner and Robert Pear, AThe 40th President: The Opponents; Critics See a Reagan Legacy Tainted by AIDS, Civil Rights and Union Policies,@ New York Times, June 9, 2004. By that time more than 20,000 Americans had already died of AIDS. Indeed, perhaps the most memorable slogan associated with the AIDS movement in the United StatesBASilence=Death@Bwas inspired in no small part by President Reagan=s own conspicuous silence on the issue. Importantly, President Reagan=s reluctance to publicly acknowledge the AIDS pandemic was accompanied by a similar reluctance to fund adequately AIDS-related research. In a 1985 op-ed article, Congressman Henry Waxman excoriated the Reagan administration for cutting Aresearch budgets by millions of dollars, while the nation=s treatment costs have already run into the billions.@ See Henry A. Waxman, AFighting an Epidemic in the Absence of Leadership,@ Washington Post, September 4, 1985, H19, Health. On the failure to adequately fund fund AIDS research, see Epstein, Impure Science, p, 187; and Deborah Gould, ARock the Boat, Don=t Rock the Boat, Baby: Ambivalence and the Emergence of Militant AIDS Activism,@ in Jeff Goodwin, James M. Jasper, and Francesca Polletta, eds., Passionate Politics: Emotions and Social Movements (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 2001), p. 136. 51 60. Epstein, Impure Science, p. 285. 61. Ibid. 62. Ibid. 63. Ibid. Elsewhere Epstein submits: AAs activists saw it, the big names in AIDS anti-viral research . . . dominated the committees that voted, predictably, to fund the kinds of studies that these researchers did@ (p. 284). 64. Ibid., p. 286. 65. Ibid. 66. Ibid. 67. Ibid., p. 350. 68. Epstein, AThe Construction of Lay Expertise,@ p. 410. 69. Epstein, Impure Science, p. 231. 70. Epstein, AThe Construction of Lay Expertise,@ p. 417. 71. Ibid. 72. Epstein, Impure Science, p. 231. 52 73. Ibid., AThe Construction of Lay Expertise,@ p. 416. 74. James Bohman, ADemocracy as Inquiry, Inquiry as Democratic: Pragmatism, Social Science, and the Cognitive Division of Labor,@ Journal of Politics 43 (April 1999): 600. 75. Epstein, Impure Science, ch. 7. 76. Ibid., p. 228. 77. Since many demographic groups were significantly underrepresented in AIDS trials, this was not a trivial issue. In a 1989 exposé published on the front page of the Los Angeles Times, Robert Steinbrook reported that Ablacks, Latinos and intravenous drug users are substantially underrepresented in ongoing federally sponsored trials of new AIDS drugs. As of Aug. 28, 20.4% of the 7,659 patients who have been enrolled in National Institute of Allergy and Infectious Diseases (NIAID) trials were black or Latino. By comparison, about 42% of adult AIDS patients in the United States are black or Latino. In the trials, 11.3% of the enrolled patients were previous or current users of intravenous drugs. By comparison, 27.5% of all adult AIDS patients report previous or current intravenous drug use. Women represent 6.8% of the enrollees in the trials, compared to 8.9% of all adult AIDS patients.@ See Robert Steinbrook, AAIDS Trials Shortchange Minorities and Drug Users,@ Los Angeles Times, September 25, 1989, 1. In addition to the demographic issues, activists argued that the insistence on stringent entry criteria for clinical trialsBhowever understandable and well-intentioned they may have been in the abstractBproduced an incentive structure that was in some sense morally perverse. In the interest of insuring that studies were grounded in Aclean data,@ principal investigators often excluded persons 53 who were currently taking, or had previously taken, other medications. Additionally, Asometimes those enrolled in studies who took so much as an aspirin without explicit permission were threatened with expulsion.@ These criteria encouraged people with AIDS and HIV to avoid early treatment, since such treatment might disqualify them from inclusion in future studies that held more promise. As one AIDS activist, Terry Sutton, poignantly described the dilemma: AThe idea of clean data terrifies me, because it punishes people for trying to treat early. My roommate . . . has made the decision not to treat early because of the pure subject rule, What he says is >I want to be a pure subject so that I can get access to the best protocol once it starts to move.= You only get to be a pure subject once.@ As Epstein observes, these concerns led to an interrogation of Athe presuppositions of scientific >cleanliness.= Did clean data come only from >pure= subjects? Was >messy,= >impure= science necessarily bad science?@ See Epstein, Impure Science, pp. 254-56. 78. Martin Delaney, for example, contended that policies of restrictive access undermined scientists= ability Ato conduct clinical research. @ As he noted: AAIDS study centers throughout the nation tell of cheating, even bribery, to gain entry to studies; mixing of drugs by patients to share and dilute the risk of being on placebo; and rapid dropping out of patients who learn they are on placebo. . . . Such practices are a direct result of forcing patients to use clinical studies as the only option for treatment.@ See Martin Delaney, AThe Case for Patient Access to Experimental Therapy,@ Journal of Infectious Diseases 159 (March 1989): 416-419. 79. Ibid., pp. 228, 339. For an interesting analysis of the former issue, see Steven Epstein, 54 Inclusion: The Politics of Difference in Medical Research (Chicago: University of Cicago Press, 2007). Regarding the latter issue, activists challenged on ethical and pragmatic grounds what was widely accepted as the methodological A>gold-standard=@ in biomedicine, namely, randomized clinical trials (pp. 196-198). Here activists questioned, among other things, whether the use of Adouble-blind@ placebo controlled experiments were ethical in cases where the study=s research subjects suffered from a potentially fatal disease. They also questioned whether such controls were either possible or necessary (pp. 202-204). 80. Although activists= arguments for accelerated approval of experimental AIDS drugs ultimately prevailed, they were certainly not uncontroversial. Indeed, there was considerable disagreement among researchers themselves regarding the wisdom of an accelerated drug approval process, with some agreeing with activists= contentions that a quicker approval process was justified by the urgency and deadly nature of the AIDS epidemic, while others worried about the long-term implications of such a precedent, wondering if it might provide an incentive for pharmaceutical companies to push for approval in the absence of adequate data (pp. 276-279). Interestingly, activists= views also evolved over time. While the vast majority of activists remained committed to a policy of fast track drug approval, they also became increasingly concerned about the ways in which drug companies might abuse the policy. If accelerated approval ultimately yielded Amediocre drugs@ that were no more effective than currently available treatments, then it was difficult to understand how the policy could possibly benefit AIDS patients (pp. 315-318). Here, as in so many areas of AIDS research, the quest for easy answers was extraordinarily elusive. 81. Ibid., pp. 256-258. 55 82. Ibid., p. 257. 83. On the distinction between Apragmatic@ and Afastidious@ perspectives on the purpose of clinical trials, see ibid., pp. 255-256, 342. 84. Ibid, pp. 2, 235-264, 330-353. 85. Epstein, AThe Construction of Lay Expertise,@ p. 417. 86. Ibid, p. 232. Epstein cites other examples as well: ASusan Ellenberg, the chief biostatistician assigned to the ACTG trials at NIAID, recalled seeking out the ACTUP/New York document in Montreal in response to her own curiosity: >I walked down to the courtyard and there was this group of guys, and they were wearing muscle shirts, with earrings and funny hair. I was almost afraid. I was really hesitant even to approach them . . .=@ (p. 247). 87. Ibid., p. 232. 88. For an excellent discussion of the changing Aemotion culture@ within the AIDS movement in the United States, see Gould, ARock the Boat, Don=t Rock the Boat Baby,@ pp. 135-157. 89. Epstein, Impure Science, p. 335. As Epstein notes elsewhere, once activists demonstrated their competency in the language of biomedicine, they Adiscovered that researchers felt compelled, by their own norms of discourse and behavior, to consider activist arguments on their own merits@ (p. 231-2). 56 90. Ibid., p. 232. 91. Ibid., pp. 248-249. 92. Donna Haraway, ASituated Knowledges: The Science Question in Feminism and the Priviledge of Partial Perspective,@ Feminist Studies 14 (Autumn 1988): 575-599. In this influential essay, Haraway defines situated knowledges as Apartial, locatable, critical knowledges@ (p. 584). 93. Epstein, Impure Science, p. 231. 94. Ibid., p. 351. 95. Bourdieu and Wacquant, Invitation to Reflexive Sociology, p. 146. 96. Epstein, Impure Science, p. 12. 97. Ibid., pp. 229-230. 98. Ibid., p. 293. 99. Arendt, On Revolution, p. 268. 100. Hannah Arendt, Lectures on Kant=s Political Philosophy, ed. Ronald Beiner (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1982), p. 43. 101. Epstein, Impure Science, p. 235. As Epstein points out, researchers transformed view of activists is mirrored in activists own A transformed conception of the identity of the antagonist. In place of the charges of genocide that activists had used in the early days of ACT UP to frame their 57 critiques of the research establishment, these activists were now often inclined to acknowledge the good intentions of researchers@ (p. 328). 102. Arendt, The Human Condition, p. 244. 103. Ibid., p. 200. 104. Hannah Arendt, AOn Violence,@ in Crises of the Republic (New York and London: Harcourt Brace Jovanovich, 1969), p. 178. As Arendt asserts, bureaucracy Ais the most social form of government.@ See Arendt, The Human Condition, p. 40. 105. Garrath Williams captures nicely this aspect of Arendt=s worries about the logic of ends and means: Aan end trumps all other claims: in its absolute nature lies justification for the means of realization, and these, in turn, will tend to be destructive of human living and acting together.@ See Garrath Williams, ALove and Responsibility: A Political Ethic for Hannah Arendt,@ Political Studies 46 (December 1998): 941. 106. Gregg Gonsalves and Mark Harrington, AAIDS Research at the NIH: A Critical Review. Part I: Summary@ (Treatment Action Group, New York, 1992, photocopy), pp. 1-2, quoted in Epstein, Impure Science, p. 353. 107. Sheldon Wolin, AOn the Theory and Practice of Power,@ in Jonathan Arac, ed., After Foucault (New Brunswick, NJ: Rutgers University Press, 1988), p. 198. 58