Law and Heidegger's Question Concerning Technology: A Prolegomenon to Future Law Librarianship Paul D. Callister Introduction The German philosopher Martin Heidegger offers one of the most potent criticisms of technology and modern life. His nightmare is a world whose essence has been reduced to the functional equivalent of “a giant gasoline station, an energy source for modern technology and industry. This relation of man to the world [is] in principle a technical one . . . . [It is] altogether alien to former ages and histories.”1 For Heidegger, drawing upon his experience with Nazism, such a world would be driven toward a single end, and ultimately subjected to a single will (the antithesis of the rule of law). Furthermore, the technical relationship of humanity with its environment obscures the true nature of things, including the essence of law—which is transformative, rather than technological, in nature. Heidegger’s criticism of modern technology is an apt starting point to consider our own, modern legal information environment, which is increasingly technological in nature (particularly in the way Heidegger conceptualized “technology”). Furthermore, the nature of the threats revealed by Heidegger’s criticism bear not only upon questions about the future of modern librarianship, but underscore fundamental changes in modes of legal thinking, and ultimately jurisprudence itself. Indeed, the future of librarianship and law in the new information environment are intimately connected. This essay will first explain the nature of Heidegger’s criticisms of technology and modern life. Second, it will defend the appropriateness of application of Heidegger’s theory to the modern information environment, which is particularly necessary in light of Heidegger’s Nazi affiliations. Third, it will apply the criticisms to the modern legal information environment and stress the threats implicated by such criticism. Finally, the paper will explore “poetic thinking” as Heidegger’s prescription for modern life, including its application to legal thinking. It will conclude that the impact of the modern information environment on librarianship, law and legal thinking risks reducing law to an information resource to be “mined,” harvested, commoditized, exchanged, and ultimately exploited by various competing interests while at the same time reducing its potential transformative power as a guide for human conduct and social order. 1 Martin Heidegger, Memorial Address, in DISCOURSE ON THINKING 50 (John M. Anderson & E. Hans Freund trans., Harper Torch Books 1966) (1959). Heidegger’s Nightmare: Understanding the Beast Heidegger’s philosophy cannot be separated from his life and his experience with Nazism, a critique of which follows this section. In any event, Heidegger’s experience with Nazism becomes evident in his post-War writing, particularly on the subject of technology and language. Heidegger describes the threat to the modern world as based in the essence of thinking, which he describes as enframing,2 or “technological thinking.” Heidegger is very concerned about humanity’s conception of technology, which he describes as “instrumental and anthropological.”3 Heidegger notes two widely-held and interdependent beliefs about of technology: One says: Technology is a means to an end. The other says: Technology is a human activity. The two definitions of technology belong together. For to posit ends and procure and utilize the means to them is human activity. The manufacture and utilization of equipment, tools, and machines, the manufactured and use things themselves, and the needs and ends they serve, all belong to what technology is. 4 Note that Heidegger’s articulation of common understandings about technology apply equally well to information technologies, including legal databases. Databases are constructed as part of the human activity to serve various ends. True, it is hard to think of technology in any other way, but Heidegger actually views the failure to consider the essence of technology as a threat to humanity. The threat to humanity is expressed in two ways by Heidegger: First, humanity becomes incapable of seeing anything around them as but as things to be brought ready to serve as means to end (a concept he refers to as “standing reserve”). Humans are cutoff from understanding the essence of things, and consequently their surrounding world. Second, man has been reduced in his or her role to the “order-er” of things to some purpose or end, and at the same time risks becoming something to be ordered as well. Heidegger illustrates these concerns as follows: The forester who, in the wood, measures the felled timber and to all appearances walks the same forest path in the same way as did his grandfather is today commanded by profit-making in the lumber industry, whether he knows it or not. He is made subordinate to the orderability of cellulose, which for its part is challenged forth by the need for paper, 2 See William Lovitt, Introduction, in MARTIN HEIDEGGER, THE QUESTION CONCERNING TECHNOLOGY OTHER ESSAYS, at XXIX (Willliam Lovitt trans., Garland Publ’g 1977) (1955). . 3 See QUESTION CONCERNING TECHNOLOGY, supra note 2, at 5. 4 Id. at 4-5. AND which is then delivered to newspapers and illustrated magazines. The latter, in their set configuration of opinion becomes available on demand.5 In other words, the trees, the wood, the paper, and even the forester (may overlook the sanctifying value of the woods) are ultimately subordinated to the ultimate will to establish public opinion, which Heidegger cynically assumes will be, following the same pattern, placed in a set form, and presumably subjugated to a single will. The forester, in proverbial fashion, “cannot see the forest for the trees.” Instead of appreciating the majesty and mystery of the living forest, he sees only fodder for the paper mill, which will pay for his next meal. The same cynicism might be applied to legal publishing. Whole forests have given their lives to the publication of legal information, in order to provide a stable basis for society (“Law must be stable and yet it cannot stand still”)6--or, as our comrades from Clinical Legal Studies would put it: “to perpetuate the existing socioeconomic status quo.”7 Cadres of West editors (commonly referred to in generic fashion as human resources, ironically making them all the less human) work as feverishly as the scribes of any medieval scriptorium to digest points of law and assign 55,000 cases into a taxonomy with over 100,000 class distinctions,8 and all for the sake of predicable legal system and stable society. Id. at 18 (Heidegger also notes “current talk about human resources” and the “supply of patients” as evidence of humanity become just another part of the “standing reserve.”). Heidegger finds that man is never completely “transformed into mere standing reserve” because of his unique position as the “order-er” of every thing else. Id. 5 6 ROSCOE POUND, INTERPRETATIONS OF LEGAL HISTORY 1 (1923). BLACK’S LAW DICTIONARY 382 (7th ed., 1999). For a more thorough definition of Critical Legal Studies, see John Henry Schlegel, Critical Legal Studies, in OXFORD COMPANION TO AMERICAN LAW 202 (Kermit L. Hall ed., 2002). 7 8 See Paul Douglas Callister, 95 LAW LIBRARY JOURNAL 7, 21 (2003) (estimate of number of cases being published in West system in print. I learned that West’s taxonomy has over 100,000 in a conversation with Dan Dabney, West’s Senior Director for Research and Development, at an AALL convention [confirm]. Interestingly, Dabney has recently written: Large systems seem to encounter a limit to growth at about 100,000 items. There are relatively few indexing system that have grown so large as to encounter these effects, but most of the largest systems in use seem to grow more slowly once they approach six figures. This limit seems to affect both systems with a hierarchical structure like the West Key Number System and flatter systems like the Library of Congress Subject Headings. Perhaps something on the order of 100,000 is simply the limit of comprehension of a system even when it is used by dedicated specialists. Dan Dabney, A Brief Practical Introduction to Taxonomies (Thompson Legal Knowledge and Trends White Paper 7, available at http://www.thomson.com/cms/assets/pdfs/legal/westkm_Taxonomies.pdf (last visited Sept. 15, 2007). Apparently, humanity’s role as the order-er of things is “at capacity,” and is, presumably, in need of technological replacement. See supra note 5. For Heidegger, the threat is revealed in mankind’s perpetual quest to gain mastery over technology. “Everything depends on our manipulating technology in the proper manner as a means. We will, as we say, ‘get’ technology ‘spiritually in hand.’ We will master it. The will to mastery becomes all the more urgent the more technology threatens to slip from human control.”9 When Heidegger published these words (first in 1962, but based on lectures from 1949, and 1950),10 the implications of nuclear energy and atomic warfare occupied much academic discussion. Heidegger points out that the popular question of this period did not concern how to find sufficient energy resources, but “[i]n what way can we tame and direct the unimaginably vast amounts of atomic energies, and so secure mankind against the danger that these gigantic energies suddenly— even without military actions—break out somewhere, ‘run away’ and destroy everything?”11 The question is about mastery over technology, not about sufficiency of resources. Similar concerns are manifest with respect to information technologies, where the problem appears not to be lack of access, but too much access--for example, illegal music file swapping; the anti-circumvention provisions of the DMCA; the trends to use licensing to control and preserve economic value of information (and to prohibit otherwise lawfully competitive practices, such as reverse engineering); and with respect to the field of law and government; retraction of government documents; the Patriot Act; the furor over “nonpublished, electronic precedent; and the recent frenzy of e-discovery. Some seem to have liked things much better when resources were scarce. Universal access is destabilizing. Consequently, there is considerable interest in getting a “handle” on technology through legal sanction and yet additional technological innovation. Heidegger’s genius is that he recognizes that all the fuss about mastering technologies, although close to the mark, concerns the wrong issue. The more insidious threat is not nuclear fallout or economic devaluation of intellectual property, but the worldview of “calculative” thinking that accompanies rapid technological change. “The world now appears as an object open to attacks of calculative thought, attacks that nothing is believed able any longer to resist.”12 For Heidegger, humanity’s relationship to modern technology is unhealthy and is defined by calculative thought, which is not limited to the manipulation of machine code or numbers. Rather, the concept is grounded in “Machiavellian scheming” and the pursuit of the prospect of power. “Calculative thinking computes. It computes ever new, ever more promising and at the same time more economical possibilities. Calculative thinking races from one prospect to 9 Id. at 5. 10 Id. at ix. 11 Memorial Address, supra note 1, at 51. 12 Id. at 50. the next.”13 The threat Heidegger envisions to human thought is even more dangerous than nuclear warfare.14: Heidegger’s threat is based on the separation of man from his nature. By pursuing economic Machiavellianism, man is cut off from the transformative powers of his or her environment. In such a world, law does not have the capacity to educate, justify, and provide harmony (Plato’s vision in The Republic); rather, law like any resource must be employed to economic ends. The implication is that law must be subjected to a single will. While at the University of Illinois, I learned that a special mission of the Library of Congress had seized contents of Nazi libraries following World War II. Items were identified in other campus library, and with a little effort I was able to identify over seventy such items at the law library, and many other legal titles which traced their origin to Nazi Germany. As I made my way through some of the materials, I was struck by the fact that the Nazis did not simply ignore law, rather they systematically rewrote it to their own purposes. A Nazi legal academy complete with law professors sporting Nazi armbands reworked the law, defining the terms of “Jewish partnerships,” corporations and other organizations. Besides laws restricting interracial and ethnic marriages, special tax provisions discriminated among business. The Fuhrer, himself, became a legal concept. Ultimately, the law professor who served as director of the project, was executed at Nuremburg for his actions as governor of occupied Poland. Even law was put to the service of the great Nazi machine. Here I am, over 50 years after Heidegger introduced his novel criticism of the nuclear age, and the same concerns abound. 13 Id. at 46. Id. at 52 (“[A]n attack with technological means is being prepared upon the life and nature of man compared with which the explosion of the hydrogen bomb means little.”). 14 Essentially, the Enframing, which characterizes our time, means “all things are being swept together into a vast network in which their only meaning lies in their being available to serve some end that will itself also be directed toward getting everything under control.” Id. Heidegger calls the ordering of all things to some end (under the direction of will), “standing reserve.” 15 Heidegger’s relationship to the Nazis should, justifiably, make us wary of his philosophy. Heidegger made statements in favor of Hitler and benefited by succeeding _______ as the Rector of Freiburg University, who had resigned in protest to Nazi policies. 16 He also actively engaged in riding his university of non-conforming views. The most favorable evaluation of Heidegger is that in the late thirties and following the war, Heidegger began to recover from Nazism. A more critical evaluation is that Heidegger was merely disillusioned with the Hitler and the direction of the party, but never renounced anti-Semitism and forever distrustful of democratic institutions. Near the end of Otto Preminger’s film, Anatomy of a Murder, which explores the insanity defense, or “irresistible impulse,” the lawyer for the defense, Jimmy Stuart’s character, Paul Biegler, does something incompressible in the modern practice of law. Mr. Biegler, having recently won an important trial, actually chooses to spend his leisure time reading from case reporters—from Justice Holmes no less. For a practicing lawyer to find recreation in reading case reporters, let alone spend significant time to ponderously reading cases at all, immediately probably strikes most present-day attorneys as anachronistic, if not an outright Hollywood fabrication. However, there was indeed, such a time, when readings of cases (outside of the Reader’s Digest versions presented in the classroom), lay near and dear to the profession. As Professor Robert Berring has noted about one eminent 15 See id. 16 Martin Heidegger: Heidegger and Nazism, ENCYCLOPÆDIA http://www.search.eb.com/eb/article?tocId=3090 (last visited Oct. 31, 2005). BRITANNICA ONLINE, American attorney, “Daniel Webster probably read every case that was published by every American appellate court, and probably read English cases as well.” 17 17 Robert C. Berring, Collapse Of The Structure Of The Legal Research Universe: The Imperative Of Digital Information, 69 Wash. L. Rev. 9, 19 (1994).