Lecture 6 Objectives: After learning this material you will be able to: 1. Present the basic arguments concerning ethical egoism. 2. Understand Objectivist Ethics and its relationship to laissez-faire capitalism. 3. Discuss the differences between self-interest and happiness and their relationship to ethical self-understanding. 4. Understand the issues concerned with the theory of ethics called Utilitarianism 5. Compare and contrast utilitarianism and the moral community. 6. Reflect on the principle of utility in public policy. Welcome back! In the last lecture we presented some of the ideas that are leading us past relativism and toward universalism. We studied whether or not religion is necessary to morality and tried to understand the differences between natural law, divine command, and American civil religion. We also explored ideas concerned with conscience and moral development, compared the affective and cognitive sides of our conscience and reflected on what it means to be a morally mature person. In this lecture we will continue to explore some of the ideas that imply that morality and ethics are based on universal principles. Specifically we will study ethical egoism and utilitarianism to help us understand how these theories influence our understanding of ethics. What is Ethical Egoism? The first universal principle sounds like subjectivism, but it is not. It simply says that one ought to do what one perceives is in his or her own best interest. The universality comes from saying that all people ought to do this all of the time with no exceptions. “Ethical egoism differs from ethical subjectivism because it is concerned with a person’s best self-interest. Our best self-interests are those that are rational. Ethical subjectivism, in contrast, asks only what people desire or feel is right for them. The ethical egoist identifies happiness with the pursuit of rational self-interest. Egoism is not the same as egotism. An egotist is a person who is arrogant, boastful, inconsiderate, and self-centered. Egotistical behavior is not necessarily in one’s best self-interest because egotists tend to alienate others and, by doing so, limit their opportunities for happiness” (Judith A. Boss, Ethics For Life: A Text With Readings, Fourth Edition, [New York, New York: McGraw Hill, 2008] p. 238. Hereafter referred to as Boss.) I don’t really like this word “egoism” because it is so easily confused with egotism, but this is the word that comes down to us. The main thing to keep in mind is that egoism is rational and thus thoughtful, whereas egotism is immature and hasty and therefore not necessarily helpful. Egoism is really setting itself up as an alternative to altruism, where you put others before yourself. But this is not the same thing as ignoring others. Even on planes they remind us that in the case of an emergency we should put our own oxygen masks on first. We do this so that we can help others and not become a 1 burden to them. Egotism ignores the needs of others while egoism simply reorders needs so that you take care of yourself first. Even the great “Socrates acknowledged that it is morally acceptable for people to act in ways that benefit themselves. In fact, Socrates argues that being just benefits a person more than being unjust. However, he also argues that justice is good in and of itself, independent of its benefit to the just man. At this point, Socrates deviates from the position of the ethical egoist who claims that self-interest is the only moral reason for choosing one particular course of action. Most moral philosophers, like Socrates, agree that personal happiness is only one of several goods by which to judge the morality of an action. Elements of ethical egoism are found in many ethical theories, including those of Plato, Aristotle, Herbert Spencer, Jeremy Bentham, John Stuart Mill, and David Hume” (Boss, p. 238.) The question we will have to face in this lecture is whether or not egoism alone is enough of a foundation for a universal moral code. Some will say yes and some will say no. By looking carefully at the arguments you will become a more critical and deeper thinker. Egoism is not to be equated with a simple or shallow idea of happiness. There are times when we put off what would give us the most pleasure in order to work toward a goal that might be in our best interest. This is another example of how egoism is not egotism. Just as we saw there was a difference between cultural relativism and sociological relativism, so there is a difference between ethical egoism and psychological egoism. “There are two main types of egoism: ethical egoism and psychological egoism. Ethical egoism is a normative theory about how things ought to be. We ought to act in the way that is in our own best selfinterest. Psychological egoism, in contrast, is a descriptive theory about how things are (Boss, p. 240.) To describe how things are is not the same as saying how things should be. It is very easy to confuse this. Egoism seems to explain many of our actions, but it struggles with explaining our motivations, especially for actions that seem to be self-destructive. “On the surface, it may appear that psychological egoism is an airtight theory, but the problem is that psychological egoists will not allow any explanations that do not fit into their theory. No matter what happens, they explain it as an example of egoism: People are always motivated by self-interest; therefore, whatever people do must have been motivated by self-interest. Such circular reasoning, or begging the question, adds nothing to our explanation of human motivation” (Boss, p. 245.) Sometimes people do very self-sacrificing things such as putting their own life in danger to save the life of someone else. It is difficult to say that this is motivated by self-interest when the greatest interest we can be said to have is selfpreservation. Psychological egoists will say that even here we might be more interested in feeling good about ourselves than in helping another. They always find a way to bring it back to self-interest. Many times this makes sense but sometimes it seems like a bit of a stretch. 2 Psychological Egoism Psychological egoism gives an explanation that allows us to understand why some people do things to themselves that are actually harmful rather than in their own best interest. They do so because the immediate benefit seems to outweigh any future benefit. The correct way to change or modify destructive behavior according to egoists is to simply inform and educate. Once people understand where their good actually is, they will make the rational choice to change their behavior. This sounds correct, but we will see that there are actually problems with this, especially in regard to such things as egoism. It is very difficult to adequately understand motivation and inner movements of human will. We can look at outer actions and speculate, but it is much different to then speculate further with egoism as our only guide. “Our motives for performing an action and the consequences of that action are not always the same. People like Mother Teresa may derive great satisfaction from their altruistic actions, but this is not necessarily what motivates them to help others in the first place. It is even difficult to figure out our own motives sometimes! Consider how often you have replied, when asked why you did something, ‘I don’t know’” (Boss, p. 245.) When we are very little we see the world only in terms of ourselves. Psychologists can study this in child development. One of the things they look for is growth and development as a child matures. Egoism explains many of a child’s motivations. There is no question about that. The real question is whether or not it is an adequate explanation for adult motivation. Ayn Rand: Objectivist Ethics and Rational Ethical Egoism An American writer made ethical egoism popular. For example, you may have read her books The Fountainhead or Atlas Shrugged. “The current popularity of ethical egoism has been fueled by the work of American novelist, screenwriter, and philosopher Ayn Rand (1905-1982). Rand defended a version of ethical egoism that she called ‘objectivist ethics’” (Boss, p. 247.) Rand grew up in Russia under Communism and became disillusioned with its repressive form of government. She was a great admirer of American freedom and independence. She thought the freedom we enjoy to find success or failure was the best system under which to practice ethical egoism. While some people saw the American celebration of self-interest as a problem, she saw it as one of our crowning glories. Rather than a government that made people dependent on one another (her perception of communism) Rand wanted a government that left people free to make something of themselves or fall apart. When you hear “rags to riches” stories you can see her point. She was also wary of the role of religion in forming our ethics because religion pushes us toward altruism rather than egoism. Rand could not see religious values as part of the real world, rather they were imposed 3 on the world. “According to Rand, there is no source of values other than objective reality - hence, her term objectivist ethics. Rand maintained that we value that which helps us survive, and that which helps us survive is what is in our own self-interest” (Boss, pp. 247-248.) Religion was too idealistic for Rand. It seemed to deal with an imaginary world, not the world of survival of the fittest. As a philosopher she was not simply interested in raw self-interest, but in thoughtful, rational self-interest. This is her strong point and the most convincing part of her argument. “Rand adopted what first appears to be an Aristotelian view of human nature; she argued that reason sets us apart from all other species. According to both Rand and Aristotle, reason is essential for our survival as humans. Because reason is necessary for survival, reason has moral value for humans. Therefore, we ought to act in a rational manner. According to Rand, to behave irrationally is to behave immorally” (Boss, p. 248.) The universal value then is rationality rather than the relativism we studied earlier in this course. Humans are rational creatures and therefore our morality needs to be based on this inherent quality rather than on religious faith or on a “if it feels good, do it” mentality. Both of these alternative approaches are not rational according to Rand. But Rand did not follow Aristotle in his thinking about ethics. While they both agreed that humanity was rational by nature, Aristotle taught that we were also social creatures by nature and Rand did not agree with this. “Rand, in contrast, regarded humans as fundamentally solitary individuals, each pursuing his or her own personal self-interest. Unlike Aristotle, who views the state, rather than the individual, as a self-sufficient whole, she argued that ‘there is no such entity as society, only individual men.’ Her ideal society, or more accurately ‘collection of individual men,’ is an atomistic society where each of us must live and work only for ourselves and never for others. This type of society, she claimed, is the objectively real world - the only world in which we can prove our value and find rational happiness. Rand’s rational virtues, consequently, all involve the cultivation of individuality rather than social virtues. Her concept of rationality counsels us to 1. Be independent. Live by the work of your own mind. 2. Have integrity. Don’t sacrifice your convictions to the opinions of others. 3. Be honest. Don’t fake reality. 4. Be just. Neither seek nor give that which is unearned or undeserved. Rand assumed that any rational person would accept her list of virtues and what she called the supreme value of productive work” (Boss, p. 249.) We will see how each of these virtues plays very well into aspects of America, especially our economic system. One aspect of capitalism, for example, is the notion that if I work hard and make money for purely selfish reasons my wealth will still end up helping people, but it will do so indirectly rather than directly. Sometimes this is known as the trickledown theory of economics. Wealthy people 4 invest their money in a new business, this business provides work for people, which then allows them to advance in our society. Rand recognized that sometimes it was in our interest to help others, but only when they could help us in return. There had to be a fair trade. Anything less than a fair trade would not be just and thus would actually be an insult to the dignity of the other person. “Rand disagreed with sociobiologists that altruism can be compatible with our rational self-interests. Altruism involves self-sacrifice or giving without expectation of return, therefore, altruism is immoral. Christian ethics, in contrast, teaches us that selfishness and pride are the original sins and that altruism is a virtue. Rand turned this equation upside down. She maintained that centuries of being taught that we must live for others has eroded our sense of self-esteem and left us feeling guilty and full of self-hatred. For her, altruism is the equivalent of the Christian original sin, and selfishness is the greatest virtue. Altruism and compassion are vices, she argued, because all altruism is based on self-sacrifice and demands by others to give them something that they have neither earned nor deserve. Altruists are willing to sacrifice their lives and interests to benefit others. This attitude not only turns the giver into an object; it also turns the receiver into a parasite. For this reason, Rand referred to an altruist as a ‘second-hander’” (Boss, p. 251.) We have heard this argument in modern politics regarding programs such as welfare. Some people call welfare a handout while others call it a hand up. Laissez-Faire Capitalism We often think of ethics as very personal, that is, it has to do with our own personal choices and behavior. But this is not entirely true, because it is possible to analyze not just people but systems in regards to how moral they are. That is why colleges are offering courses in subjects such as business ethics. Ethicists are interested not just in how people treat one another but in how economic systems treat people. “Scottish economist and moral philosopher Adam Smith (1723-1790) laid out the foundations of laissez-faire capitalism in his book Wealth of Nations. The best society, he argued, is one where everyone is allowed the freedom to pursue their own self-interest in the marketplace. Smith’s book, which was published in 1776, had a profound effect on the founding fathers of the United States” (Boss, p. 251.) Capitalism is a great system of competition that plays right into the survival of the fittest mentality. Especially back in the early days of rapid industrialization, it was a very abusive system that was attacked by Karl Marx and other famous thinkers. Capitalism provided a way for the poor to become rich, but it also left a lot of people’s lives torn apart in the process. Marx did not imagine that capitalism could be self-correcting over time. For example, owners of factories did not hesitate in hiring children and paying them very low wages and then getting rid of them with no compensation if they were injured. But this changed with the birth of the labor movement and unions that gained for workers some rights such as 5 healthcare, pensions and worker’s compensation. In the process, some people would argue, capitalism became more moral. Would Rand agree? This is an important question, not just historically but in our modern world. We are still debating whether or not we can find a system of economics that does as much good for people in general as it does for specific individuals. “There is no doubt that capitalism, as an economic system, has produced massive wealth and technological advancement. However, because capitalism is successful in raising the overall wealth and productivity, does that mean it is moral? Both Marxist and liberation ethicists argue that it is possible to have a successful economic system that raises the gross national product and productivity but that is nevertheless unjust” (Boss, p. 254.) This is what we now will study. A Marxist Analysis of Laissez-Faire Capitalism Sometimes it is difficult to hear Karl Marx with an open mind because he is associated with the corruptions of communism. But he was not responsible for what people did with his ideas, which advocated socialism rather than communism and advocated a gradual process of change rather than a brutal suppression of people. It helps us hear him when we recognize that the capitalism we see around us today is much tamer than the capitalism that horrified him in the factory towns of England nearly two hundred years ago. Perhaps his criticism helped us adapt our own system to be a little gentler with people. “Karl Marx did agree with the capitalists that people can find fulfillment in productive work; however, he also believed, like Aristotle, that we are primarily socially productive beings. The egoism of capitalism, therefore, was to Marx one of its greatest evils. Marxists claim that, rather than promoting the interests of the majority, capitalism benefits only a few at the expense of the many. Ethical egoism, therefore, is not a philosophy of ‘humans qua humans,’ as Rand claimed, but, according to Marxists, a philosophy of the elite” (Boss, p. 254.) A trickledown theory says that everyone benefits from a system such as capitalism. But is it true? This is where we need our critical thinking skills and we need to search for the data and facts that either support such an assertion, deny it, or qualify it in some other way. Rand wrote that justice was a matter of trading. I scratch your back if you scratch mine. That is, we help others only when it is in our self-interest to do so. This means as human individuals we are traders. “Ethical egoists seem to assume that everyone is in a position to be a trader. They do not question the assumption that certain people deserve to control the wealth because of their socioeconomic status. Marxists, on the other hand, point out that people’s talents and their ability to trade skills and goods in a free-market economy vary enormously. Poverty, lack of access to resources, poor health, and social discrimination are only a few of the factors that place certain people at a distinct disadvantage. Women, in particular, have suffered in a capitalist system because much of women’s labor, 6 especially that which is based on caring and communal values, is unremunerated and undervalued. Patriarchal social structures also limit women’s opportunities and access to resources and high-paying jobs” (Boss, p. 255.) In an ideal world the trading system would work. But do we live in an ideal world? So much of ethical egoism comes down to trying to discern the nature of individual versus social responsibility. If you have studied history you know some of the problems of communism. One of the big issues has to do with motivation. For example, what motivates a person to work harder and do more difficult things if they cannot move ahead in their society and in their economic station? This problem was never solved. Rand was quick to pick up on this, and many of her criticisms of communism were as important as the Marxist critique of capitalism. “Both Rand’s theory of ethical egoism and the critics of capitalism offer important insights. Rand emphasized the importance of individual responsibility; Marxists and liberation ethicists remind us of the importance of social responsibility. However, an adequate moral theory must consider and integrate both the individual and social aspects of morality. Although capitalists are not necessarily greedy or exploitive, an egoist ethics offers no reason or incentive for people not to pursue their own ends at the expense of others. On the other hand, an ethical theory like Marxism, which for the most part ignores the individual, can just as surely create a sense of alienation by swallowing up individual interests and goals into the concept of the good of the community” (Boss, p. 258.) The problem with all of the great systems, whether in philosophy or economics, is that they tend to become insistent that their way is the only way. To solve the problems of our world we our going to have to find a middle way between such extremes. For example, some forms of socialism have not turned into huge systems of authoritarian government that takes away human freedoms, rights, and initiative. Some forms of capitalism have become much friendlier to people with generous benefit packages, adequate compensation, and profit sharing programs so that those actually producing the wealth can enjoy some of it as well. Egoism, Self-Esteem, and Moral Development Earlier I mentioned that child psychologists recognize the motivations of young children as being based on their own self-interest. A baby crying in the middle of the night does not care if you are tired or not! But we also hope children will expand their circle of moral concern to include not only their own interests, but the interests of others as well. Is this idealistic or is it based on the evidence of what it means to be human? It is true that we need enough egoism to care for ourselves and make the most of our lives. But is there more we can grow into? “By pointing out the importance of self-love, Rand provided an important corrective to moral ideologies that glorify 7 self-sacrifice and putting the needs of others first. However, by universalizing egoism as a moral principle - rather than seeing it as a stage in our moral development - we remain forever stunted at the preconventional level of moral reasoning. Indeed, most egoists are trapped in their own self-interest - shut away from the richness of the wider moral community. Egoism and concern for our own well-being become integrated into the higher stages of moral development rather than being discarded when we move on to later stages. Egoism, in other words, is not the goal of morality, as ethical egoists claim; it is the seed from which our moral community grows to become more and more inclusive” (Boss, p. 260.) The best image of this was used in an earlier lecture when we discussed the idea of moral communities and studied the process of how some people and animals are included in our moral community and some are excluded. One of the things we saw was that these circles seem to expand as we grow more mature and see the world with more wisdom. There is an alternative to communism and capitalism that is trying to offer another option when it comes to determining our moral community. It is called communitarianism. “The primary challenge to ethical egoism in the United States and the go-it-alone liberalism that it supports comes from a philosophy known as communitarian. While strands of communitarianism are found in many traditional moral philosophies, such as those of Aristotle and Confucius, modern communitarianism developed primarily as a response to the individualism of American liberalism. Libertarians, like ethical egoists, believe that the best society is one where people are free to pursue their rational self-interests. Communitarians, on the other hand, regard the democratic community as the basis of ethics. The human community - which encompasses community decisions, social conventions, and historic and religious traditions - rather than the individual, defines the moral community” (Boss, p. 262.) In order to make sense of this argument we have to answer one of the fundamental philosophical questions: What does it mean to be human? Are we basically loners or are we basically social creatures? How we answer this question determines to a great extent how we perceive our responsibility. Modern democratic societies have placed a great deal of emphasis on individualism. But there are alternative views. Many of the great mystical systems, for example, teach that our sense of being alone, individual and separate from others is one of the great delusions that needs to be overcome through spiritual practices such as meditation. Obviously this understanding would lead to a very different picture of the world. Too much community is almost as much a problem as too much individualism. Once again we see the problems of relying on extremes. “Substituting a sense of community for individual rights does not guarantee that everyone will be part of the moral community or even that those who are will be treated with equal respect. However, neither does ignoring community and defining the moral community purely in individualist terms assure that all people will be treated with 8 respect. Instead, we need a moral theory that can take both individual dignity and the value of community into account” (Boss, p. 262.) So we see that Rand and ethical egoism need to have a place at our ethical table, but at the same time we need to continue our search for universal values that are not so narrow. Before we move on to utilitarianism I want look at some specific problems that must be addressed by those who adhere to Rand’s philosophy. Critique of Ethical Egoism First, most philosophers agree that humans are all searching for happiness. What is in dispute is not happiness but the definition of happiness. “James Rachels argues that by having individual happiness as its only goal, ethical egoism becomes self-defeating. This phenomenon is known as the hedonist paradox. If we try to pursue only our own happiness, we are often left feeling frustrated and alienated. Individual happiness seems to be more often the byproduct of other activities than a goal in itself” (Boss, pp. 265-266.) It is one of the ironies of life that when we aim directly at happiness we often miss it. We also must address the issue that some of the happiest people are those who live lives of service to others, almost the complete opposite of what ethical egoism states. Next we face the problem of how we advocate a universal way of life that sets people up in competition with one another. “Ethical egoism cannot be universalized. If people want to maximize their self-interest, then it is not in their best interest to have ethical egoism universalized because their self-interest might conflict with someone else’s. Thus, ethical egoism cannot consistently be promoted as a universal moral theory” (Boss, p. 266.) If two people want the same thing, how do they both follow this dictate to follow their own self-interest? “Ethical egoism provides no guidelines for resolving conflicts of interest between people. In a world of limited resources and opportunities, people’s self-interests sometimes come into conflict. When this happens, ethical egoism is unable to provide any moral guidelines for resolving the conflict” (Boss, p. 266.) In other words, to arrive at an understanding of fairness you have to include others, otherwise it is simply each person for him or herself and there is nothing stopping individuals from using extreme measures to get someone “out of the way.” If everyone is suppose to follow their own self-interest then what makes my interests more important than theirs? “Ethical egoism is arbitrary. While it may be true, as Rand claims, that we cannot truly value others without first valuing ourselves, it does not follow from this that we should habitually put our interests above those of others. By doing so the ethical egoist violates the principle that all people have equal dignity” (Boss, p. 266.) If all people do not have equal dignity then why does anyone have it, including me? 9 On an even playing field competition can be fun and even helpful at times, but we know that in fact the playing fields of our world are not level. “Ethical egoism, like social Darwinism and ethical subjectivism, allows the powerful to exploit the weak. Ethical egoism, and the system of laissez-faire capitalism that it extols, may be attractive to those who are rich and have the power to pursue their own self-interest. The devastating effects of this ideology on the people and nations that are not in positions of economic power, however, are becoming more and more evident with the increasing accumulation of wealth and social goods in the hands of fewer and fewer people and the destruction of the environment in the name of economic progress” (Boss, p. 267.) We see this in modern politics being discussed when a company moves its jobs overseas to a cheaper labor market. This movement of jobs is happening more and more often in a global world. If I can get someone in another company to make my product for far less why should I not do it? There is almost no reason, if you rely on ethical egoism because you are only looking out for your own good rather than the good of others. Some even argue that it benefits the poor in other countries by providing them with jobs. But this too is not clear and that is why we need to ask good questions and listen to the evidence. What Is Beyond the Ego? What are we to do if the great religious and wisdom traditions are right that we are more than our ego? “Ethical egoism fails to take into account that we are social beings who exist only as part of a wider community. We do not exist as isolated individuals who can act independently of social constraints. There are times when self-denial may be called for, such as saving a drowning child without first negotiating to see what is in it for us. And it may sometimes be right to pursue our own self-interest. But, in general, the right path consists of choosing the medium between these two extremes. The association of the moral life and happiness with seeking the mean is also found in Aristotle’s philosophy. The idea that morality does not require putting our interests aside but balancing our needs with those of others is also a central theme in Carol Gilligan’s theory regarding moral reasoning and moral maturity” (Boss, p. 267.) The great wisdom traditions agree that we want happiness, but they all insist that our happiness depends on understanding what it means to be in right and harmonious relationship with other people as well as with nature. If it is true that we all start out as egos concerned only with ourselves, isn’t it also true that this is only a stage - the lowest stage - of our development? “Ethical egoism inhibits moral development. Rand believed that capitalism would encourage people to be their moral best. However, studies have shown that this is not the case. A business education in the United States and the socialization process within U.S. business firms actually tend to inhibit and even decrease a person’s level of moral reasoning rather than attract people of high moral integrity. Indeed, people who use higher levels of moral reasoning have a poorer 10 chance of rising to upper management positions in U.S. business firms” (Boss, p. 267.) There is a fallacy discussed in critical thinking called the wishful thinking fallacy. This means we take something as true because we wish it to be true rather than because we have evidence backing up its truth. Just because we want to believe capitalism brings out the best in people - or communism for that matter - we need to read and study and look at the evidence. Is it true? In a global world we become ever more aware of other religions and philosophies that are questioning the development of Western ethics. “Ethical egoism is based on a false premise regarding the source of happiness. In many Eastern philosophies, the moral life is not identified with denying the individual self or ego nor with pursuing rational self-interest or productive labor. Many schools of Eastern ethics, in particular, emphasize overcoming egoism and self-interest as a virtue and the path to true happiness. Moral maturity is viewed in terms of going beyond the self - the diffusing of the one or individual ego into the One, the I am into the I AM. According to these philosophies, we are all part of the same web of life - the same great ‘self’ - rather than separate, isolated beings” (Boss, p. 268.) Many native traditions are also telling us that the destruction of the environment is directly related to the human belief that we are separate. Always we have to ask ourselves if our assumptions about reality are true or not. All of these criticisms demonstrate that ethical egoism has some deadly weaknesses. That does not mean we cannot learn a great deal from it and how it sees the world. There is a great deal I admire about Ayn Rand. It is a good thing, it seems to me, to work hard to develop our talents and make the most of our lives and not simply wait around for someone to give it to us. There is a lot to be said for thinking for ourselves, making our own lives and not being so dependent on others to make us happy and fulfilled. All of this makes sense to me. I just don’t think it answers all of my ethical questions. I need more insight and wisdom! And one place we can look for more ethical wisdom is the tradition known as utilitarianism. Utilitarianism: Jeremy Bentham (1748-1832) Jeremy Bentham headed the utilitarians and was followed by a number of others, the most significant being John Stuart Mill. We will look at both of these philosophers. Bentham was an eccentric fellow who trained to be an attorney, but never practiced law. He spent most of his life in intense study and writing about legal reform, though he made little effort to publish what he wrote. When he died he left tens of thousands of manuscript pages. He also left a large estate to the newly established University College in London, which was contingent on his being able to attend all board meetings by being mummified upon his death. And until this day his mummified body still sits in a cabinet in a main corridor of the college! 11 What were the utilitarians trying to do? They wanted to apply the principles of empiricism (which worked so well in science), to ethical and political issues. Utilitarians “concluded that all theory, including moral and political theory, must be grounded in empirical fact. [Bentham] claimed that in the case of the human sciences this fact would have to be the primacy of the pleasure principle” (Donald Palmer, Looking at Philosophy: The Unbearable Heaviness of Philosophy Made Lighter, Fourth Edition, [New York, New York: McGraw Hill, 2006] p. 268. Hereafter referred to as Palmer). What does this mean? It means that when you look at all of the things that motivate us in our lives and break down these reasons as far as you can go, you discover that we are trying to find pleasure and avoid pain. The ancient Greek philosophy Epicureanism taught a similar theory, called hedonism, claiming that only pleasure should have value. However, Bentham’s contribution is that he taught “that hedonism doesn’t have to be egoistic; it can be social. That is, one can (and should) be motivated to act in the name of the pleasure of others as well as for one’s own pleasure. His social hedonism is reflected in his most famous maxim, “the greatest amount of happiness for the greatest number” (where “happiness” is defined in terms of pleasure” (Palmer, p. 268). Pleasure isn’t simply sensual enjoyment. Primarily it is the absence of pain and anxiety. Bentham also connected this with a democratic idea of each person having one vote, which means that we each have the chance to give our version of what brings us pleasure and happiness. It is interesting that this ethical theory is sometimes called “consequentialism” because the emphasis is on the consequences of our actions. It is the results that count, it is the results that make something morally right or wrong. This works out so that Bentham’s ethical theory is the exact opposite to Kant’s categorical imperative. For Kant the value of a moral act depended on the rational question of whether our acts could be made into universal laws for all people to follow all of the time. In other words, it was our intentions that counted, not the results of our actions. We will be looking at Kant’s theory of ethics in a future lecture. Both Kant and Bentham give us some important clues to how to make important decisions, but they also both leave problems. What we really need is an ethics that incorporates both views, which is, in fact, what most of us do whether we know it or not. For example, (to jump ahead) Kant taught that we have a moral duty to do only what we would have other people do and therefore we should not lie because we do not want others to lie. But what if lying could prevent more harm than not? Even then we had to follow the rule and not lie. This becomes a problem for some of us when the rule seems to take precedence over seeking the good, the whole reason for such moral rules in the first place. Here the utilitarians come to our rescue, because for them the key issue is the consequences. If our telling the truth will lead to the harm and unhappiness of others then we have the moral obligation to lie. 12 However, this doesn’t always work either. For instance, imagine that you were to visit a friend in the hospital and some doctors kidnapped you. They were going to kill you and remove your organs to save several people who would die without them. What then? Utilitarianism, looking at this from the point of view of “the greatest happiness for the greatest number” might conclude that your death would benefit the larger number and therefore it is O.K. We actually make these kind of decisions all of the time when it comes to sending soldiers to war, using a medicine that will benefit the many even though it may cause harm to a few. Yet most of us would not think a person should be killed to harvest his or her organs and our principle for this would not be utilitarianism, but Kant’s categorical imperative that we would not want all people killing each other to harvest organs because eventually there would be no one left! Bentham taught that utilitarian ethics could be looked at mathematically and he called this “The calculus of felicity.” One had to study pleasure scientifically and if one did then you would come up with seven questions representing seven categories: “1. Intensity: How intense is the pleasure? 2. Duration: How long does the pleasure last? 3. Certainty: How sure is the pleasure? 4. Proximity: How soon will the pleasure be experienced? 5. Fecundity: How many more pleasures will follow in the train of this pleasure? 6. Purity: How free from pain is this pleasure? And 7. Extent: How many people will experience the pleasure?” (Palmer, p. 270). By practicing this method one would find that the process becomes more intuitive as time goes on. Next time you don’t want to do something, think about these seven questions and see how it works! Anytime we go through the pros and cons of an argument we are doing a version of ‘the calculus of felicity.” How does it work with marriage? Bentham asked himself these questions about whether he should remain a bachelor or get married. He decided to get married. John Stuart Mill (1806-1873) John Stuart Mill was raised on Bentham’s philosophy because his father, James Mill, was Bentham’s follower and a fairly important utilitarian philosopher in his own right. His father, who kept John Stuart Mill away from boys his own age, educated him and kept him learning and focused on intellectual accomplishments to such an extent that he later admitted in his autobiography that his emotions and body were neglected and led directly to a serious breakdown when he was 21. He spent his life in an enormous intellectual labor writing many books and countless articles and reviews on many subjects in addition to philosophy. He had a long term and important relationship with a married woman named Mrs. Taylor who coauthored some of his writings. When her husband died they married in 1851. He was active in politics and advocated for women’s suffrage, the interests of the laboring class, and land reform in Ireland. 13 Having been raised on utilitarian ideas, Mill found some problems with them. For example, think about some of the things we in an ethics course hold of value, especially the study of philosophy. What if we asked the voters of a school district if they wanted to subsidize the study of philosophy or receive a tax break? Well, according to the one vote per person rule, the greatest happiness of the greater number might very well lead to the end of philosophy. Mill was very worried about this and thought we might as a society sink to the lowest common denominator. Mill came to the conclusion that some pleasures are more desirable and more valuable than others and only those who have knowledge of both will be allowed to vote. If someone were to propose that today, he or she would be accused of being elitist. This is a problem, but so is sinking to the lowest common denominator. Our own country is struggling with this issue today in terms of economic issues and debating how much to support certain social programs such as education, versus the need to cut the tax burden on people. Is it realistic to vote on all of these issues and is everyone’s vote, informed or not, of equal value? Quantitative to Qualitative Mill claimed that he was only changing the quantitative nature of utilitarianism to a qualitative measure. But he was accused of abandoning the pleasure principle, undermining the democratic principle, and becoming an elitist. “For what it is worth, Mill’s doctrine did leave us some questions to ponder: In a democracy, must the “one person, one vote” principle apply at all levels of decision making? And if so, are democracy and higher culture compatible?” (Donald Palmer, Looking at Philosophy, p. 273). If people will support football stadiums but not art galleries should we just accept that as the democratic way, or do we want to find another way of allocating funds? None of these are easy questions and their difficulty helps us understand why living in a democracy can be so tough. There are many competing demands! In Mill’s most famous book, On Liberty, he “outlined his doctrine of laissez-faire (hands off!). There were certain spheres where the government had no business interfering in the lives of its citizens. Mill’s “principle of liberty” states, “… the only purpose for which power can be rightfully exercised over any member of a civilized community, against his will, is to prevent harm to others” (Palmer, p. 273). Mill thought people should be as free as possible in their personal lives and only restricted in their public lives. This sounds good on the surface, but one does not have to go very deep before we see why society still struggles with these questions. For example, I do not ride motorcycles, but I thought it was kind of strange when the government said bikers must wear helmets. The same goes for seat belt laws. Why should the government tell me what chances I can take or not take? It 14 made no sense to me until someone pointed out that the injuries caused to people who don’t wear seatbelts and helmets end up costing tax payers a great deal of money in medical care and lost wages and productivity. And this is true of so many of our activities. The problem with Mill’s love of liberty is knowing where to draw the line between our public and private lives. You can see why I think ethics is the most difficult area of philosophy to apply, if not to study. Mill also influenced economics. His hands off policy basically said the government should stay out of regulation and control, unless required by some great good, and instead let the law of supply and demand take its natural course. Nevertheless, he did feel that there were some things not to be left to the marketplace, things that were for the overall good “the want of which is least felt where the need is greatest. This is peculiarly true of those things which are chiefly useful as tending to raise the character of human beings. The uncultivated cannot be competent judges of cultivation” (Palmer, p. 275). And there is the rub. How do we promote equality and at the same time only have the educated and the informed take part in the voting? And this gets to the heart of secrecy in government. To reveal secrets might bring great harm, and yet to keep secrets means that we, the average voter, cannot make a competent decision about things such as whether we should go to war or not. So what do we do? Reflections on Utilitarianism Utilitarianism can be criticized from a number of angles. If you push it too far, it seems to go against ‘common sense’ morality. By that I mean those things that seem obvious to us, such as the doctor not killing healthy people to harvest organs. Of course, there is a problem here too, which is that what seems like commonsense to me may not seem like commonsense to someone else. This is why we look for ethical rules in the first place. Another difficulty is in how we determine what happiness is. It seems that Bentham thought there might be a "calculus of happiness," some quantitative way to determine what is best, but John Stuart Mill and many others have shown that that is not possible. And what do we do if it gives someone pleasure to hurt others? Do they have that right or is that not fair? Then there is the problem of predicting consequences. We do have our past experience to guide us, but nevertheless the future is still unknown. Utilitarians might argue that they are not required to know exact consequences, but simply must make the best decision possible given the knowledge that they do have. There is also a problem with dealing only with consequences and not with intentions. What if someone intends to hurt others but mistakenly helps them? Does that make their action O.K.? When we train our children we teach them to follow our ethical values. But we are hoping that at some time their maturity will 15 be at such a level that they will buy into these ethics not simply to escape punishment, but because they care about how their actions affect us and others. One last example: What about human rights? If something like slavery or the torture argument we have been hearing about were to the benefit of the majority, utilitarianism would seem to give it approval. What is one to do? Utilitarians argue that justification of slavery or torture would require unrealistically high benefits to justify the direct and extreme sufferings of the victims. It also excludes the indirect impact of inhumane policies; for example, general anxiety and fear might increase for all if human rights are commonly ignored. Summary Utilitarianism does not work very well for me when it stands alone. But as discussed earlier regarding Rand’s ethical egoism theory, it works very well as one tool among many that we might want to use and have at our disposal. Having some quantitative questions to ask makes sense some of the time, but we want also to find a way to bring qualitative values into the picture. In our quest to find some universal values on which to build ethics we have looked at ethical egoism and utilitarianism. Both help fill out our picture, but it seems we need further help. In the next lecture we will study deontology and rights ethics, two more attempts to find a solution to solving ethical problems and living a virtuous life. In the meantime, see if you can define happiness! Bibliography: Judith A. Boss, Ethics For Life: A Text With Readings, Fourth Edition, [New York, New York: McGraw Hill, 2008] Donald Palmer, Looking at Philosophy: The Unbearable Heaviness of Philosophy Made Lighter, Fourth Edition, [New York, New York: McGraw Hill, 2006] Bertrand Russell, A History of Western Philosophy, [New York, New York: Simon and Schuster, 1945] Richard Tarnas, The Passion of the Western Mind: Understanding the Ideas That Have Shaped Our World View, [New York, New York: Harmony Books, 1991] Bruce Waller, You Decide! Current Debates in Contemporary Moral Problems, [New York, New York: Pearson, 2006] 16