Definition of an argument (in this handout we used the material form) http://terpconnect.umd.edu/~bschan/170/june3.pdf and http://www.philosophypages.com/lg/e11a.htm An argument (in the context of logic) is defined as a set of premises and a conclusion where the conclusion and premises are separated by some trigger word, phrase or mark known as a turnstile. For example: 1 I think; therefore I am. There is only one premise in this argument, I think. The conclusion is I am and the turnstile is therefore. 2 All men are mortal. Socrates was a man. So, Socrates was mortal. In this example there are two premises and the turnstile is so. This may also be written as: All men are mortal. Socrates was a man. ------------------------∴ Socrates was mortal. In general we will write an argument in either of the following two ways: p1 p2 p3 ⁞ pn Or ---∴q p1, p2, p3, …. , pn / ∴q Valid and Invalid arguments Of greater interest to the logician are valid arguments. A valid argument is an argument for which there is no possible situation in which the premises are all true and the conclusion is false. In other words an argument is valid if for all those situations which make all the premises true will also make the conclusion true. An invalid argument is an argument for which there is at least one situation in which the premises are all true but the conclusion is false. One way to check the validity of an argument is to use full truth-table method. In this method we draw a truth-table where the top row contains all the different sentence letters in the argument, followed by the premises, and then the conclusion. If an argument is valid, then every assignment where the premises are all true is also an assignment where the conclusion is true. P-1 But, if the table contains at least one row where the premises are all true and the conclusion is false, then the argument is invalid. We now study how to make use of full truth-table method to check the validity of an argument. Let us consider the following argument: P P→Q ----------∴Q To prove that it is valid, we draw a table where the top row contains all the different sentence letters in the argument, followed by the premises, and then the conclusion: Then using the same method as in drawing complex truth-tables, we list all the possible assignments of truth-values to the sentence letters on the left. In our particular example, since there are only two sentence letters, there should be 4 assignments: P T T F F Q T F T F P P→Q T T T F F T F T Q T F T F In the completed truth-table, the first two cells in each row give us the assignment of truthvalues, and the next three cells tell us the truth-values of the premises and the conclusion under each of the assignment. If an argument is valid, then every assignment where the premises are all true is also an assignment where the conclusion is true. It so happens that there is only one assignment (the first row) where both premises are true. We can see from the last cell of the row that the conclusion is also true under such an assignment. So this argument has been shown to be valid. More examples Show that the following argument is not valid: P→Q P ---------∴ Q Solution:- P Q P→Q T T F F T F T F T F T T P F F T T Q F T F T P-2 We know that an argument is invalid if there is at least one assignment where the premises are true and the conclusion is false. The third row of the table shows that this is indeed the case. When “P” is false and “Q” is true, the two premises are true but the conclusion is false. So the argument is not valid. Exercise:- Determine whether or not the following argument is valid: P→Q P ---∴ Q Another example: PQ (Q → P) ---------------∴ Q P Again we draw a truth-table for the premises and the conclusion: P Q T T F F T F T F P Q→P F F T T T T F T PQ T F T T (Q→P) Q P F F T F F T T F As you can see, there is no assignment where the premises are true and the conclusion is false. So it is valid. Reconsider validity: Now, it is probably clear to you why both a valid argument and an invalid argument can have (e.g.) true premises and a true conclusion. (Why? Hint: An actual case is only one row in the truth table.) Constructive dilemma In logic, a constructive dilemma is a formal logical argument that takes the form: 1a) P → Q. 1b) R → S. 2) Either P or R is true. Therefore, either Q or S is true. In logical operator notation with three premises In logical operator notation with two premises -----------------------------. In sum, if two conditionals are true and at least one of their antecedents is, then at least one of their consequents must be too. P-3 An example: If I win a million dollars, I will donate it to an orphanage. If my friend wins a million dollars, he will donate it to a wildlife fund. Either I win a million dollars, or my friend wins a million dollars. Therefore, either an orphanage will get a million dollars, or a wildlife fund will get a million dollars. Another example of constructive dilemma. If the statements “if it snows, then the schools close” and “if it is sunny, then Sam will go to the park” are true, and if it snows or is sunny, then it is also true that the schools close or Sam will go to the park. The constructive dilemma is the disjunctive version of modus ponens. 1st Premise 2nd Prem. Conc. Now let us show that the constructive P Q R S P→Q R→S (P→Q)(R→S) P R Q S dilemma is a valid argument by T T T T T T T T T construction the truth table. T T T F It is clear that the premises are true T T F T on lines 1, 3, 4, 9, and 13, and on T T F F each of these lines the conclusion is T T T F T T F T T T T T T T T T F TT F T F T T T T T F F F F F F F T T T T T F F T T F F F T F T F T F F F F T T T T F T T T F T T F F F T F T T T T T T T F F F T F T T T T F F F F F F F F T T F F T F T F T T T T T F T T T F T T T T F F T F T F also true. Thus, the argument is valid, and we can be sure that every argument that is a substitutioninstance of this argument form must be valid. Destructive dilemma In logic, a destructive dilemma is any logical argument of the following form: -------------------- ∴ P-4 The argument can be read in this way: 1. 2. 3. 4. If P, then Q If R, then S Not Q or not S Therefore, not P or not R In sum, if two conditionals are true and at least one of their antecedents is false, then at least one of their consequents must also be false. Here is an example of the destructive dilemma in English: 1. 2. 3. 4. If it rains, we will stay inside. If it is sunny, we will go for a walk. Either we will not stay inside, or we will not go for a walk. Therefore, either it will not rain, or it will not be sunny. The destructive dilemma is the disjunctive version of modus tollens. Exercise:- prove the validity of the destructive dilemma argument. Special case: Inconsistent premises will form a valid argument The following three arguments are all valid: P P ----∴Q P P -----------∴ ( P P) P P -------------∴( P P) All these arguments are valid because there is no assignment under which both P and P are true and Q / (P P) / (P P) are false. There is no such assignment simply because P and P cannot be true simultaneously. Here is the truth table to convince you the validity of above three arguments: P T T F F P F F T T Q T F T F P P F F F F P P T T T T Exercise: Use the full truth-table method to determine the validity of these arguments: Answer: 1. Invalid. 2. Valid (Notice that the first premise is true only under the 4th assignment. Once we have found out that the first premise is true only under the 4th assignment, we only need to calculate the truth-values of the second premise and the conclusion under the same assignment. There is no need to draw the rest of the truth-table. This means we can determine validity a lot faster.) P-5 Constructive Dilemma What is the proof of constructive dilemma in logic NOT with truth table if p is q and if r is s and either p or r is true therefore either q or s is true? In:Math [Edit categories] Business School Stylewww.thecambridgeadvantage.co.uk/Summer Programme for 15/16 yr olds to 'think-out-of-the-box'... Looking for Proof Perfect?www.Facebook.comFind Proof Perfect on Facebook. Sign Up Free Now! Ads Answer: Improve Wha?????! Please use the discussion area to explain this fascinating question Constructive Dilemma Proof: 1. ( A -> B ) Premise 2. ( C -> D ) Premise 3. ( A or C ) Premise 4. ( - B -> - A ) 1 , Contraposition 5. ( - A -> C ) 3 , Implication 6. ( - B -> C ) 4 , 5 Chain Argument 7. ( - B -> D ) 6 , 2 Chain Argument 8. ( B or D ) 7 Implication , Q.E.D. Read more: http://wiki.answers.com/Q/What_is_the_proof_of_constructive_dilemma_in_logic_NOT_with_truth_table_if_p _is_q_and_if_r_is_s_and_either_p_or_r_is_true_therefore_either_q_or_s_is_true#ixzz1lKSC6mpS Constructive dilemma From Wikipedia, the free encyclopedia Jump to: navigation, search P-6 This article needs additional citations for verification. Please help improve this article by adding citations to reliable sources. Unsourced material may be challenged and removed. (December 2009) Rules of inference Propositional calculus Modus ponens Modus tollens Modus ponendo tollens Conjunction introduction Simplification Disjunction introduction Disjunction elimination Disjunctive syllogism Hypothetical syllogism Constructive dilemma Destructive dilemma Biconditional introduction Biconditional elimination Predicate calculus Universal generalization Universal instantiation Existential generalization Existential instantiation v d e In logic, a constructive dilemma is a formal logical argument that takes the form: 1a) P → Q. b) R → S. P-7 2) Either P or R is true. Therefore, either Q or S is true. In logical operator notation with three premises . In logical operator notation with two premises[1] . In sum, if two conditionals are true and at least one of their antecedents is, then at least one of their consequents must be too. An example: If I win a million dollars, I will donate it to an orphanage. If my friend wins a million dollars, he will donate it to a wildlife fund. Either I win a million dollars, or my friend wins a million dollars. Therefore, either an orphanage will get a million dollars, or a wildlife fund will get a million dollars. The dilemma derives its name because of the transfer of disjunctive operants. [edit] Proof 1 . 2 . 3 . (addition ) 4 . (simplific ation) P-8 5 . (distribu tion) 6 . (DeMorg an's Law) 7 . (from assumpti on) 7 . And to once again restate the argument, one can turn this argument into a conditional, where if the first three premises, then not P or R: Note: An argument has the following form: (P1 ^ P2 ^ ... ^ Pn) C P-9