Ecological Existentialism in a Deweyan Vein: Finitude, Heroism, and Prophecy A number of thinkers find fault with what they see as Dewey’s blindness to the existential realities of existence. Hilary Putnam claims that Dewey's vision falls short "when we try to apply it to individual existential choices,"1 William Caspary concurs, saying, “Dewey neglects the tragic dimension in which characters are caught up in the anguish and dire consequences of irresolvable conflict.”2 Kenneth Stikkers questions whether Dewey adequately understands that "Existence is not merely precarious...it is disastrous; life does not merely teeter on the edge of a cliff; rather, from the beginning, it hurls headlong onto the rocks."3 And William Barrett argues against Dewey’s inclusion as an existentialist thinker, despite Dewey’s recognition of the “‘negative’ and destructive side of philosophy” and presentation of the “image of man as an earth-bound and time-bound creature” because, for Barrett, Dewey never calls intelligence or the scientific method into question and “never goes past this [biological and social] context into that deepest center of the human person where fear and trembling start.”4 Sidney Hook, however, believes that Dewey’s work can be the basis for “existentialism without tears.”5 This paper will examine what resources are available within Dewey’s thought for addressing the irreconcilable, the tragic, and the disastrous and will argue that an ecological understanding of the individual must have the means for taking up these concerns, even if Dewey’s own thought too often falls short. 1 Hilary Putnam, Renewing Philosophy, (Cambridge: Harvard University Press, 1992), 190. William Caspary, Dewey on Democracy (Ithaca: Cornell UP, 2000), 129. (DOUBLE CHECK PAGE***) 3 Stikkers, 65. 4 William Barrett, Irrational Man: A Study in Existential Philosophy (New York: Double-Day/Anchor, 1958), 1920. 5 Sidney Hook, “The Quest for Certainty—Existentialism without Tears,” in Pragmatism and the Tragic Sense of Life (New York: Basic Books, 1974), 44-60. 22 1 Quite often, people dismiss Dewey as naive and overly optimistic. For instance, Stanley Cavell claims that for Dewey, "the relation between science and philosophy is unproblematic" and that the Deweyan (from an Emersonian perspective) is "apt to seem an enlightened child, toying with the means of destruction, stinting the means of instruction, of provoking the self to work."6 He claims that Dewey fits Tocqueville's characterization of the American, with his "lively faith in the perfectibility of man," and his assessment of "society as a body in a state of improvement, humanity as a changing scene, in which nothing is, or ought to be, permanent."7 Although this assessment is a caricature at best, Dewey himself notes in "Creative Democracy: The Task before Us" that he has "been accused more than once and from opposed quarters of an undue, a utopian faith in the possibilities of intelligence and in education as a correlate of intelligence" (LW 14:227). But despite his faith in human possibilities, Dewey is no utopian. Scott Russell Sanders' assessment of himself fits equally as well for Dewey: So I write always in the face of grief. I write about hope because I wrestle with despair. I describe glimpses of paradise as a measure of what we might aspire to and of the direction we might go. To write about the natural order that sustains us is not to ignore the human condition, but to insist on our most fundamental needs—for light and earth and water and air, for companions, for beauty, meaning, grace.8 Dewey, like Sanders, holds up a vision of the possible so that we can better see the actual in its light. 6 Stanley Cavell, Conditions Handsome and Unhandsome: The Constitution of Emersonian Perfectionism (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1990), 15-16. 7 Cavell, Conditions, 15, quoting Alexis de Tocqueville, Democracy in America, trans. Henry Reeves (New York, Vintage, 1945). 8 Scott Russell Sanders, The Country of Language (Minneapolis: Milkweed Editions, 1999), 38. 2 However, in Renewing Philosophy, Putnam argues that Dewey’s moral philosophy falls short when applied to “individual existential choices,” especially when “[i]ndividuality is at stake.”9 For Putnam, Dewey’s reliance upon scientific method and “intelligently guided experimentation” does not help, primarily because in making such a choice, the individual is attempting to authentically be what the individual already is or at least become what the individual will be.10 In questions of irreconcilable options, such as Sartre’s Pierre, who must choose between joining the French Resistance or staying home with his ailing mother, critical inquiry and the scientific method seem to be irrelevant. However, Putnam focuses too much on Dewey’s advocacy of experimentation and inquiry, and he overlooks the importance these and other elements of Dewey’s thought can have in making these types of decisions. Dewey does not have a specific answer for what Pierre should do with his life, because the particular individual must take up his/her life as a process of self-creation within a range of viable possibilities. For Dewey, such is the nature of moral inquiry: Moral theory can (i) generalize the types of moral conflicts which arise, thus enabling a perplexed and doubtful individual to clarify his own particular problem by placing it in a larger context; it can (ii) state the leading ways in which such problems have been intellectually dealt with by those who have thought upon such matters; it can (iii) render personal reflection more systematic and enlightened, suggesting alternatives that might otherwise be overlooked, and stimulating greater consistency in judgment. But it does not offer a table of commandments in a catechism in which answers are as definite as are the 9 Hilary Putnam, “A Reconsideration of Deweyan Democracy” in Renewing Philosophy, (Cambridge: Harvard UP, 1994), 190-191. 10 Ibid. 3 questions which are asked. It can render personal choice more intelligent, but it cannot take the place of personal decision, which must be made in every case of moral perplexity….the attempt to set up ready-made conclusions contradicts the very nature of reflective morality. (LW 7:166). Only a system that attempts to undermine the individual’s freedom of self-determination will specify the individual’s “proper” life path. Such a system runs the risk of promoting an ethical monoculture, something antithetical to the freedoms valued by Putnam. Dewey understands the precariousness of nature and realizes that individuals must pick their way through the options before them. His philosophy provides tools, critical inquiry and experimentation among them, to better enable this navigation. It is certainly distressing that none of us can be everything we want to be. Each of us faces moments of decision regarding self-creation which require leaps of faith. In order to live authentically, the individual must finally make that leap alone.11 Anything else means living life second-hand. However, Dewey’s philosophy does not leave the individual without methods of assessing options. But those methods are not replacements for the leap. Melvin Rogers, in responding to Putnam’s complaint, says: But the fact that Dewey does not spend a great deal of time on tragic conflicts, I think, does not point to an unwillingness to acknowledge them or inattentiveness to the pluralism conflicts imply….[H]e understands these moments to be a feature of our social and political world, rather than its exclusive feature….Recall [Dewey’s] earlier remark: ‘Sometimes a juncture is so critical that a person…feels that his future his very being, is at stake.’ But he continues on a Jamesian note, remarking that these cases are important for theoretical reflection because ‘some 11 This is meant in a functional sense, of course. The Deweyan individual is a creature of society, even while in isolation. See his discussion of Robinson Crusoe in “Individuality in Education,” MW 15:178-179. 4 degree of what is conspicuous in these momentous cases is found in every voluntary decision.12 Dewey’s understanding of the individual is such that every decision provides a means by which the individual takes up the process of self-development. Certainly the momentous decisions shape individuals, but the smaller, seemingly inconsequential acts do so as well. For instance, how often do people reach middle age to be startled by the appearance of health problems that have been slowly building throughout the course of their lives? So Rogers believes that Dewey does recognize the importance of individual existential choices, and that he extends the importance beyond momentous decisions to include those seemingly less important choices as well. But does his philosophy offer anything for the individual actually in the position of having to choose? For Putnam is correct: there are decisions that cannot be tested using the experimental method. Some decisions are irrevocable and must be made on the fly, while others must be made without the tools necessary for proper experimentation. And this is where Dewey’s focus on community and communication, as well as his idea of dramatic rehearsal become important. For Dewey does not believe that we make our irrevocable decisions in a vacuum. We make our decisions within a community, even as we struggle against living life second-hand by simply following social dictates. When we push for our own development, we do so in communication with those around us, including those who will push us to push ourselves. The moment of the existential leap, even if done alone, cannot be separated from the communicative events that inform it. Through communication, the individual can better unpack his or her values, desires, ambitions, and fears—all of which aid in making irrevocable decisions. 12 Melvin Rogers, The Undiscovered Dewey: Religion, Morality, and the Ethos of Democracy, (New York: Columbia UP, 2009), 188. 5 Dramatic rehearsal also provides a means of better approaching such decisions. It occurs when an individual uses imagination to explore “various competing possible lines of action….Thought runs ahead and foresees outcomes, and thereby avoids having to await the instruction of actual failure and disaster. An act overtly tried out is irrevocable, its consequences cannot be blotted out. An act tried out in imagination is not final or fatal. It is retrievable” (MW 14:132-133). Dramatic rehearsal allows us to project ourselves forward in our imagination in order to understand more clearly how we will embody and carry forward a particular action, whether “momentous” or ordinary. When the individual is understood as separate or alienated from nature and society, such a process seems fairly straightforward. But how does understanding the individual as ecological affect this process of making momentous as well as ordinary decisions? For one thing, we must look more closely at Stikkers’ critique. For Stikkers, Dewey’s philosophy “fails to address the endurance of suffering and thereby inadequately concerns the meaning of suffering.”13 But when we understand the individual as ecological—as inseparable from the biological and social communities of which we are a part—we are forced to recognize and address these very concerns, even if Dewey himself may not have sufficiently done so in his own works. Recognition of our embedment within biological and social contexts (all of which are shot through with suffering, danger, and irreconcilable choices) calls forth this existential fear. The child negotiating gang-land encounters and the biologist examining the current cascade of extinctions both recognize their embedment within a precarious and even disastrous context, and they must address the resultant existential fear and trembling. An ecological model that emphasizes our biological and social context, far from buffering us, instead emphasizes our condition as beings which exist within a precarious, disastrous, and all-too-often tragic milieu. 13 Stikkers, 72. 6 And Dewey’s presentation of the individual can be seen in just such an ecological way. Humans are embedded within a biological and cultural context, and because of this embedment—if we are to act with the critical intelligence Dewey continually calls for—we must examine our choices not only as they relate immediately to ourselves and those nearest to us, but also as they send ripples throughout the web of relations that form our existence. When we do this, we are forced to confront the extent and the “endurance of suffering.” Critical inquiry, far from allowing escape from the suffering, highlights its endurance and the precariousness not only of ourselves but of entire systems in which we exist. THE PRECARIOUS, TRAGIC, AND BANAL IN DEWEY’S WORKS: Although much of Dewey’s work calls for faith in the possibilities of human existence, he does not ignore the precarious, the banal, and the tragic. We see this in Experience and Nature, when Dewey claims: Man finds himself living in an aleatory world; his existence involves, to put it baldly, a gamble. The world is a scene of risk; it is uncertain, unstable, uncannily unstable. Its dangers are irregular, inconstant, not to be counted upon as to their times and seasons….Plague, famine, failure of crops, disease, death, defeat in battle, are always just around the corner, and so are abundance, strength, victory, festival, and song. Luck is proverbially both good and bad in its distributions. The sacred and the accursed are potentialities of the same situation; and there is no category of things which has not embodied the sacred and accursed: persons, words, places, times, directions in space, stones, winds, animals, stars. (LW 1:43) 7 For Dewey, there are possibilities for both disaster and triumph, and while hard work and critical intelligence may influence the outcome, there are features of existence which cannot be controlled. We live in a tychistic universe, in which our best laid plans all too often go awry. According to Dewey, individuals continually move through “phases in which the organism falls out of step with the march of surrounding things and then recovers unison with it—either through effort of by some happy chance” (LW 10:19). Growth occurs when these processes lead to a deeper enrichment. However, “If the gap between organism and environment is too wide, the creature dies. If its activity is not enhanced by the temporary alienation, it merely subsists” (LW 10:19-20). In this passage, Dewey does not address what occurs if the organism closes the gap only to find itself in a diminished or less secure position; however, in The Public and Its Problems, he speaks of the “weakening of vigor and…sapping of energy that emanate from the absence of constructive opportunity” (LW 5:80). As McDermott rightly claims, passages such as these call into question Dewey’s supposed optimism, for growth is by no means guaranteed: “A closer look, however, reveals that alienation and death present themselves in the course of events, and the line between the temporary alienation necessary for the enhancement of life and the gap of permanent alienation which spells death, physical or spiritual, is a thin one.”14 Dewey’s “The Lost Individual” captures just such alienation in his description of the fear, anxiety, and desperation so often felt by American workers: “individuals are confused and bewildered,” they “vibrate between a past that is intellectually too empty to give stability and a present that is too diversely crowded and chaotic to afford balance or direction to ideas and emotion” (LW 5:66, 67). They face insecurity that “cuts deeper and extends more widely than bare unemployment. Fear of loss of work, dread of the oncoming of old age, create anxiety and 14 John McDermott, [2 volume Dewey collection], xxix. 8 eat into self-respect in a way that impairs personal dignity. Where fears abound, courageous and robust individuality is undermined.” In place of confidence, we find “unrest, impatience, irritation and hurry” (LW 5:68). For Dewey, social conditions have produced a pathological state: “Feverish love of anything as long as it is a change which is distracting, impatience, unsettlement, nervous discontentment, and desire for excitement, are not native to human nature” (LW 5:68). But they are the conditions under which most Americans now live. Besides nervous anxiety there is a sense of colorlessness, banality, or what Dewey calls the anesthetic. Dewey speaks of the “colorless conformity” which is the mark of one type negative morals: “Its commonest form is the protective coloration of a neutral respectability, an insipidity of character. For one man who thanks God that he is not as other men there are a thousand to offer thanks that they are as other men, sufficiently as others are to escape attention….Conventional morality is a drab morality, in which the only fatal thing is to be conspicuous” (MW 14:6). But this colorlessness quite often extends into every aspect of an individual’s existence. Experience becomes anesthetic when “[t]hings happen, but they are neither definitely included nor decisively excluded; we drift. We yield according to external pressure, or evade and compromise” (LW 10:46). Unfortunately, the anesthetic becomes the norm, as most of life becomes either a “loose succession that does not begin at any particular place and that ends—in the sense of ceasing—at no particular place” or “arrest, constriction, proceeding from parts having only a mechanical connection with the other” (LW 10:47). Just as Dewey’s The Public and Its Problems captures the anxiety and bewilderment caused by alienation, so Art as Experience presents the anesthetic aspect of contemporary existence, appearing in “the humdrum; slackness of loose ends; submission to convention in practice and procedure[, r]igid abstinence, coerced submission, tightness on one side and dissipation, 9 incoherence and aimless indulgence on the other” (LW 10:47). For Dewey, most of experience has become anesthetic, and because such a condition has become the norm (LW 10:47), our cultural habits or character is likewise anesthetic. Aaron Smuts, in “Anesthetic Experience,” takes up this concern: “Dewey diagnoses a rarely recognized experiential ailment—what might be called the anesthetic malady. This illness generally results when experience is deprived of meaning due to the poverty of the predominant forms of activity available in one’s environment.”15 Although rarely recognized, the malady is certainly not rare, and the typical solutions address symptoms, not the underlying conditions. True solution would require radical reconstruction not only of the particular individual’s circumstances but a transformation of the broader environment—all the elements which undermine aesthetic possibility. For Smuts, “The diagnosis and alteration of those activities, situations, and structures that prevent experience from being an experience is a crucial task for philosophers concerned with identifying the optimum conditions for human flourishing.”16 Dewey’s writings, both academic and popular, fit this description and reflect his recognition of the banal or anesthetic qualities of existence. In addition to the precarious and the banal, Dewey also acknowledges the tragic as a central feature of human existence. In the original opening chapter to Experience and Nature, Dewey speaks of “moving fatally to tragic destiny” (LW 1:368) and the “fatal implication in the remote” (LW 1:369). Dewey, so opposed to supernatural explanations, frames tragedy and destiny in naturalistic terms and sees them as of our own making, for individuals as well as for communities. Each generation bequeaths a set of social and biological circumstances to the next, and that generation must take up those conditions in its attempt to flourish. In the process, we 15 16 Aaron Smuts, “Anesthetic Experience,” Philosophy and Literature 29, no.1 (April 2005): 97. Ibid. 10 create a sort of destiny for ourselves as these choices produce habits that form the basis of most of our behavior. Critical inquiry, communication, and dramatic rehearsal all aid us in this process, yet they are usually applied poorly, if at all. Destruction of rainforests, the biological and social consequences of factory farming, and the economic consequences of long-term U.S. banking practices all serve as examples of the fatal implication in the remote and of our moving fatally to tragic destiny. Our earlier choices have set up organic chains of events which have created the circumstances of today. As each set of practices has become more habitual and entrenched, they have become increasingly difficult to change. This is the only sense in which destiny has any meaning within a Deweyan scheme. Certainly there are opportunities for change, and “human desire and choice count for something” (MW 14:9); however, change must contend with the inertia within all systems. When we are forced to recognize the extent of the suffering and dangers surrounding us, it is all too easy for us to fall into despair, especially in light of our finitude. No matter what we do to mitigate the negative circumstances surrounding us, we continually find that it is too little and too late. Too often, people fall into either anxiety or depression in response to the precarious, the banal, and the tragic. Dewey’s philosophy, while acknowledging the existential realities we face, attempts to provide a way of responding to these circumstances in the hope of finding a means of amelioration and growth. WHAT ARE WE TO DO? DEWEY, THE HERO, AND THE PROPHET: While Dewey recognizes and understands the existential realities of suffering, destruction, and meaninglessness, he also knows that humans are not passive but actively take up elements of the world. Given the reality of suffering and death, as well as the lack of anything absolute to ground meaning, what are humans to do? For even if we ultimately are doomed to 11 failure, humans at least have the ability to carve out a personal meaning within their lived experience. Dewey’s instrumentalism, when paired with his aesthetic and religious views, provides a means of responding to suffering, not with the idea that we can escape the precarious nature of existence, but so we can better control those elements that can be controlled, better face those elements that cannot, and create meaning along the way.17 And this means taking up the project of living, regardless of the dangers or the banalities, for it is the process of living that allows us to deepen our experience and to truly live: Dewey urges us to live our lives on the qui vive, always alert to our surroundings as if with animal sensibility. The most perilous threat to human life is secondhandedness, living out the bequest of our parents, siblings, relatives, teachers, and other dispensers of already programmed possibilities. We should be wary of the inherited, however noble its intention, for it is the quality of our own experience which is decisive. Failure, deeply undergone, often enriches, whereas success achieved mechanically through the paths set out by others often blunts sensibility. We are not dropped into the world as a thing among things. We are live creatures who eat experience.18 But creatures who eat experience must struggle to overcome the lure of secondhand existence, as well as endemic despair and the banality. Dewey’s philosophy offers an alternative, and to the extent that it demands a struggle above and beyond mere existence and often in opposition to the easy answers offered by social habituation, it can be seen as “call to the heroic life,” as Murray G. Murphey has noted (MW 14:xix). 17 A non-theistic version of Reinhold Niebuhr’s Serenity Prayer might be appropriate: “God, give us grace to accept with serenity the things that cannot be changed, courage to change the things which should be changed, and the wisdom to distinguish the one from the other” (Bartlett’s 16th ed., p. 684). 18 John McDermott, The Culture of Experience: Philosophical Essays in the American Grain (New York: New York University Press, 1976), 140. 12 The Deweyan Hero In the introduction to Human Nature and Conduct, Murray G. Murphey claims that for Dewey, “moral choice is an effective agent in the world, and it is this fact which gives meaning and zest to life. Indeed, this is Dewey’s call to the heroic life, and for the possibility of genuine social reform” (MW 14:xix). The life dedicated to “genuine social reform” stands as an example of the heroic life because it is one that requires the individual to struggle toward an ideal despite opposition. Further, in taking up the heroic life, the would-be hero forsakes alternatives that do not require the degree of struggle and sacrifices that are part and parcel of the heroic life. Finally, the individual takes up the cause without assurance of success. Failure is a live option for the hero, and when the cause is genuine social reform, a partial victory is almost always the best possible outcome. In A Common Faith, Dewey claims that “Any activity pursued in behalf of an ideal end against obstacles and in spite of threats of personal loss because of conviction of its general and enduring value is religious in quality.”19 Properly employed, it is also heroic. But what would the heroic life look like for Dewey? Certainly it will be different from the way heroism appears in the times long past, yet there is a certain continuity at play. According to Will Durant, "To the Greek the best life is the fullest one, rich in health, strength, beauty, passion, means, adventure, and thought. Virtue is arête, manly—literally and originally, martial—excellence (Ares, Mars); precisely what the Romans called vir-tus, manliness."20 Michael Grant concurs, saying: The hero must use his superior qualities at all times to excel and win applause, for that is the reward and demonstration of his manhood. He makes honour his paramount code, and glory the driving force and aim of his existence. Birth, 19 John Dewey, A Common Faith, in John Dewey: The Later Works, vol. 9, ed. Jo Ann Boydston (Carbondale, IL: Southern Illinois University Press, 1986), 18. 20 Will Durant. The History of Civilization: 2, Life of Greece (New York: Simon and Schuster, 1939), 298. 13 wealth and prowess confirm the hero's title; his ideals are courage, endurance, strength and beauty. Enthusiastically confident in what he achieves and possesses, he relies upon his own ability to make the fullest use of his powers.21 Further, the hero falls between humanity and the gods, for "there is something about him which brings him not too far from heaven....human nature, far though it is from divinity, can yet come within reach of it...."22 The hero is able to "[shake] off primitive superstitions and taboos by showing that man can do amazing things by his own effort and by his own nature, indeed that he can almost rise above his own nature into strengths scarcely known or understood."23 Perhaps because of this, "an atmosphere of tragedy surrounds the Hero."24 As Grant says, "There is pathos in his struggle against his fellows and against fate; he fulfills himself in death, the last and most searching ordeal, the true test of worth."25 But the heroic form was no static structure. Just as Achilles must remember himself and fulfill the destiny he has chosen—for his choice is to secure a long life at the cost of renown or to live a brief, heroic life—so too must Odysseus remember himself and tear himself from the secret pleasures of Calypso’s arms so that he might find his way back home in order to fulfill his duties as husband, father, and king. Plato reworks the heroic ideal with Socrates as his model, the best of men and the truest exemplar of arête. Just as the Odyssey recasts the hero as presented in the Iliad, and as Plato transforms it with Socrates as the heroic exemplar, so too must the hero be reconstructed for Deweyan uses. 21 Michael Grant. Myths of the Greeks and Romans (New York: Mentor Book by New American Library, 1968), 45. Ibid. 23 Ibid., 46. 24 Ibid., 48. 25 Ibid. 22 14 Although he doesn’t use the term “hero,” Tom Alexander, in discussing spirituality in Dewey’s works, provides a hint as to why there is need for a heroic approach to existence and what that might look like. Alexander contrasts Dewey’s approach to world as an orientation toward possibility as such rather than an orientation toward actuality, or toward the secure and fixed. For Alexander: The former alternative requires a courageous and complex orientation of the self to existence, one that includes a surrender to the comforting notion that the ends of our aspirations and actions that give meaning to our lives are not guaranteed either in their existence or even in their meaning, much less that they are ultimately within our control. Spirituality in this mode requires that we undertake a degree of existential risk and accept the immanent possibility of tragedy, for even with the best of intentions, the final meaning of our actions may betray us. This requires a courageous orientation of spirit to existence, but it must be a resoluteness combined with humility, compassion and a certain ‘tragic wisdom’…[or] natural piety.26 The Deweyan hero in many ways will fit the Socratic exemplar as developed by Plato. There will be a focus on the wise life, with a particular emphasis upon self-cultivation (which also includes community cultivation). The Deweyan hero will be one who critiques the status quo, and will do so by means of communication, which will also be a key element to cultivation. Because the sense of the heroic develops in response to the existential realities faced by individuals, there must be an emphasis upon everyday courage and everyday inspiration. During the struggle to craft something better or to struggle toward ideals, the Deweyan hero will no 26 Thomas Alexander, “Imagination and Spirituality in John Dewey’s Philosophy and Life” (p. 12 of the 08-19-10 draft). 15 doubt often feel weak against the forces that work to undermine growth and thus will be able to identify with Keats’ “sick Eagle looking at the sky,”27 capable of imagining the ideal but incapable of finding the path or the strength to achieve it. But like Keats, the Deweyan hero “accepts life and experience in all its uncertainty, mystery, doubt, and half-knowledge and turns that experience upon itself to deepen and intensify its own qualities…” (LW 10: 41). This is the insight that breathes through all of Dewey’s writings and all his activities: educational, religious, political, and aesthetic, and it allows the Deweyan hero to face the realities of our precarious world but still find the strength needed for the struggle to create something better. In the process, it is easy to lose ourselves in the humdrum of daily existence, but Dewey’s “call to the heroic life” is one of remembrance of the interconnections which form us, recognition of the dangers surrounding us, and a courageous taking up of our lives in light of the possibilities of existence, despite our individual finitude and the impossibility of complete achievement. Courage must be tempered by humility and tragic wisdom to avoid the hubris which brings low those who forget themselves, who forget that they are finite and fallible, caught in a web of relations shot through with danger, sorrow, and loss. The Deweyan Prophet Closely tied to the hero is the prophet, and there is certainly a prophetic quality to Dewey’s work. The word Hebrew word for “prophet” is navi, and designates someone who is called by and speaks for God.28 According to Harris and Platzner, prophets “should be seen not as mere observers of or commentators on current events but as divinely appointed intermediaries 27 John Keats “On Seeing the Elgin Marbles” in The Complete Poems of John Keats (New York: Modern Library, 1994), 228. 28 Stephen L. Harris and Robert L. Platzner, The Old Testament: An Introduction to the Hebrew Bible (Boston: McGraw Hill, 2002), 215. 16 and even as active participants in an unfolding drama of judgment and redemption.”29 They note that the “primary task of an Israelite prophet was to be a truth-teller by declaring the word and the will of YHWH to his contemporaries, and the principle ‘truth’ that the prophets were summoned to proclaim was the true nature of the covenant relationship.”30 Although stripped of the explicitly Judea-Christian language, Dewey’s writings serve a similar purpose. Those who would take up Dewey’s heroic call must have prophetic eyes as well as a prophetic voice if they are to dedicate their lives to genuine social reform. They must be able to imagine a better future, be willing to act as spokesmen on behalf of that vision, and take on the often heroic task of working to make that vision a reality. The name most often associated with prophetic pragmatism is Cornel West. For West, pragmatism’s focus is the examination of cultural norms for the purpose of social transformation and amelioration: [P]ragmatism’s primary aim is to discern, delineate, and defend particular norms through highlighting desirable possibilities present in the practices of a specific community or society. The goal of reflection is amelioration, and its chief consequence is the transformation of existing realities. This process is guided by moral convictions and social norms, and the transformation is shaped by the interpretation and description of the prevailing communal practices.”31 But West thinks that pragmatism “is in need of an explicit political mode of cultural criticism that refines and revises Emerson’s concerns with power, provocation and personality in light of Dewey’s stress on historical consciousness and Du Bois’s focus on the plight of the wretched of 29 Ibid. Ibid., 220. 31 Cornel West, Prophesy Deliverance! An Afro-American Revolutionary Christianity, Anniversary Edition (Louisville: Westminster John Knox Press, 2002), 21. 30 17 the earth.”32 In particular, West’s prophetic pragmatism “understands pragmatism as a political form of cultural criticism and locates politics in the everyday experiences of ordinary people,” but “[u]nlike Dewey, prophetic pragmatism promotes a more direct encounter with the Marxist tradition of social analysis.”33 According to Jeffrey Ayala Milligan: Cornel West’s prophetic pragmatism [addresses] several shortcomings found in other forms of pragmatism. By embracing a progressive Marxism it overcomes deficiencies in pragmatism’s analysis of political and economic forces. Prophetic pragmatism is also more sensitive to issues of race and, supposedly, better appreciates that a deep sense of evil and tragedy must infuse the meaning of democracy. West’s version of prophetic pragmatism is Christological and believes that human beings are created in the image of God. Above all, the prophetic pragmatist is obligated to struggle toward values that transcend history because there are ideals that are, in a sense, ‘unattainable by historically defined individual human beings.’ Finally, prophetic pragmatist teaching places ethics, rather than knowledge, at the center of educational practice.34 While acknowledging the value of both West’s and Milligan’s prophetic pragmatism, Jim Garrison argues that Deweyan pragmatism can be prophetic and do so without turning to the supernatural.35 Further, Dewey (and thus the Deweyan prophetic pragmatist) is able to believe in the possibility of progress and amelioration without becoming a “naïve progressivist.” To Garrison’s mind, “One does not need to think things are getting better to do their best, or that there is some cosmic guarantee for success. Such is the attitude of the meliorist in contrast to the 32 Cornel West, “On Prophetic Pragmatism” in The Cornel West Reader (New York: Basic Civitas Books, 1999), 150. 33 Ibid., 151. 34 Jim Garrison, “The Crossroads of Poetry and Prophecy,” Philosophy of Education 1997 http://www.ed.uiuc.edu/PES-Yearbook /97docs/garrison.html 9/27/2010. 35 For a detailed critique of Garrison’s position see Dwayne Tunstall’s “Cornel West, John Dewey, and the Tragicomic Undercurrents of Deweyan Creative Democracy.” 18 optimist.” But it is Garrison’s connection of the poetic, the creative, and the prophetic—all within a strictly naturalistic frame—that distinguishes his version of prophetic pragmatism. For Garrison, “humanity is a participant in an unfinished pluralistic universe and…human beings are created creators poetically continuing the creation,” poetically in the “sense of poiesis, or calling into existence.” In fleshing out his views, Garrison claims that “[p]rophets are poets because they perceive beyond the limits of the actual into the possibility of unifying ideals that could heal our wounds,” and that our world is poorer because “[w]e live in destitute times wherein the gospel of greed and financial profit, not prophecy, answers our existential questions.”36 John McDermott, in addition to drawing attention to Dewey’s “secular liturgy” also describes Dewey’s critique of America in the 1930s as “a jeremiad worthy of his Puritan forebears” (LW 11:xxi). The phrase is apt and certainly captures the prophetic quality of Dewey’s writings: “As a people we are more eager than sturdy; more hasty in action than ready to reflect on what should be done; prone to snatch at nostrums and quack remedies in both physical and social ailments. The spirit of speculation has fallen in with the spirit of waste; together they have fostered reckless disregard of life itself and have encouraged recourse to crime” (LW 11:xxi, 232). However, Dewey does more than attack American failings, for he uses his critique as a call to do better by making democracy a way of life rather than simply a form of government. Dewey’s prophetic vision consists of seeing the actual in light of the possible, blinded not by fear, despair, or greed. It means recognizing the existential realities surrounding and penetrating us, and resolving to call others’ attentions to those realities in order to make them see. COMMUNITY AND THE TRANSMISSION OF MEANING 36 Garrison 19 Prophetic vision and heroic action take place within a specific setting, and the community becomes not only the locus of action but also a reservoir of meaning and funded experience, to use Dewey’s phrase. Individuals are born within social and biological networks, both of which exhibit qualities that can add to or detract from the individual’s possibilities for growth. A particular individual—even an extraordinary one—can achieve only a partial victory in his or her attempt to expand value and create a more just society. But in taking up the possibilities surrounding them, individuals are able to reshape their environments for good or ill, thereby leaving legacies that hopefully make their communities more sustaining than they were. We see Dewey’s hope, despite the dangers, banality, and tragic implications of existence in his closing of A Common Faith: We who now live are parts of a humanity that extends into the remote past, a humanity that has interacted with nature. The things in civilization we most prize are not of ourselves. They exist by the grace of the doings and sufferings of the continuous human community in which we are a link. Ours is the responsibility of conserving, transmitting, rectifying and expanding the heritage of values we have received that those who come after us may receive it more solid and secure, more widely accessible and more generously shared than we have received it. (LW 9:57-58) This is not a call to subsume one’s identity into the group, nor is it an attempt to deny the existential realities we face. Dewey understands that achievements crumble, civilizations fall, and that time gnaws away at everything we hold dear. Regardless, culture provides an opportunity for us to transmit our achievements, so that others may take them up, renew them, and perhaps transform them along the way. 20 DEWEYAN ECOLOGICAL EXISTENTIALISM When most people think of existentialism, they usually turn to thinkers in a particular tradition beginning with Kierkegaard. However, Lewis Gordon questions this approach, saying: The body of literature that constitutes European existentialism is but one continent’s response to a set of problems that date from the moment human beings faced problems of anguish and despair….Existential philosophy addresses problems of freedom, anguish, dread, responsibility, embodied agency, society, and liberation; it addresses these problems through a focus on the human condition.37 When William Barrett dismisses the possibility of American existentialism, saying that the “philosopher cannot seriously put to himself questions that his civilization has not lived,”38 he ignores exactly what America had lived through by the time of Dewey’s writings.39 Granted that Dewey himself did not speak often enough, or specifically enough, about existential concerns, what would Deweyan existentialism look like? It seems that it must include at least the following: First, it requires a belief that there is no ready-made, absolute truth, no ultimate guide to tell us what we are and how we should live. We exist in a world in which humans must create/carve out meaning, even when born into a “meaning full” culture. This is due to temporality and the precarious nature of existence. Our “stored meanings” are continually stretched and strained as times change and we find ourselves in novel situations. When we live 37 Lewis R. Gordon, Existentia Africana: Understanding Africana Existentialist Thought (New York: Routledge, 2000), 6-7. 38 Barrett, 20. 39 The horrors of the Civil War, both World Wars, as well as those of slavery and Jim Crow, of the massacres of Native Americans, and of the displacements during the Great Depression serve as a few examples of what America has lived. 21 “secondhand,” in a sense, we attempt to live out of time, or at least in denial of the temporality of everything, including our most favored cultural artifacts. Second, there needs to be a recognition that much of human malaise comes from just such an attempt to live life secondhand, whether by our following cultural ideals in an unthinking, lock-step fashion (such as is required by various types of fundamentalism) or by living life vicariously through fiction, sports, or even the lives of our loved ones, or by subsuming ourselves in a career that deadens our creativity and initiative. If individuals are to be actively engaged, they cannot rely upon ready-made answers. Even if their process of engagement results in recreating the wheel, “the value of a discovery in the mental life of an individual is the contribution it makes to a creatively active mind; it does not depend upon no one’s ever having thought of the same idea before” (LW 5:128). We must continually strive for authentic existence. Third, even when we are in irreconcilable, tragic, and disastrous circumstances, we must attempt to make sense of our particular circumstances. Too often we fall back upon ready-made answers and thus fail at the one distinctive, positive human contribution: our ability to create meaning. It is in actively taking up ourselves within this precarious and tragic milieu that we begin to live authentic lives, rather than allowing ourselves to be uncritically swept along by the cultural forces around us. Fourth, angst is an appropriate response to recognizing our existential status, as is the feeling of absurdity. However, in a Deweyan scheme, these should be phases of experience rather than conditions in which we remain. In doing so, one shifts from a determination that life has no meaning or a sense of "the ridiculous character of that habit, the absence of any profound 22 reason for living, the insane charatcter of that daily agitation, and the uselessness of suffering"40 to a recogntion that "even within the limits of nihilism, it is possible to find the means to proceed beyond nihilism."41 A fifth element is an acknowledgment that effects spill beyond the immediate situation, and we never return exactly to our previous state. Our legacies—large and small, for good or ill—may become lost in the buzz of existence, but individual existence transforms the relative whole of which it is a part. We ignore this fact at our own risk. Things wear down, wear out, stretch beyond their breaking point, and lose their spring. Systems have limits to the damage they can absorb and still remain capable of maintaining their viability. As individuals, we find ourselves within just such systems, and our viability is intimately connected with that of these systems. Critical intelligence demands that we take up our lived situation, but that very process drives home exactly how precarious our situation has become. Deweyan existentialism calls us to harness the resulting fear and trembling in order to live and to hopefully salvage that which can be saved. Sixth is the need to recognize that we exist within a community of co-sufferers and cocreators, not only with other humans but also everything within the biotic community, including the soil, plants, animals, mountains, streams, oceans, and weather patterns. Humans have a capacity these others lack, namely, critical intelligence. Unfortunately, we rarely cultivate this distinctive capacity and thus rarely take up our lived situation as proficiently as we otherwise could. Seventh, since everything within the ecosystem is intertwined, the precariousness of any component affects the relative stability of the rest. Because of this, our understanding of 40 41 Albert Camus, The Myth of Sisyphus and Other Essays. (New York: Vintage-Random House, 1955) 4. Ibid., Preface 23 individual actions must take into account the ways in which consequences are taken up within the larger biotic community. For instance, mercury levels in fish have risen not only in areas closest to large human populations but throughout the world’s waters. Our precariousness is such that possible demise might originate not only a world away, but in a form all but invisible. Finally, it recognizes that despite our best efforts, we continually make mistakes and at any moment we may fail in a catastrophic way. Growth requires a continual movement from the stable to the precarious to the stable once again. According to McDermott, for Dewey: [A]lienation and death present themselves in the course of events, and the line between the temporary alienation necessary to the enhancement of life and the gap of permanent alienation which spells death, physical or spiritual is a thin one. The blame for crossing it is placed not on nature, nor on civilization, nor on a deus ex machine, but on ourselves. In John Dewey’s philosophy, the task of overcoming personal and social alienation and reconstituting the processes of living within the flow of time is one which is laced with chance, happy and otherwise, but the responsibility is ours and ours alone.42 While Dewey might have been too much of a meliorist to count as a true existentialist, too hopeful of humanity’s capacity to become better, his philosophy is shot through with existentialist themes. If we are to take seriously an ecological understanding of the individual— in light of our current state of mass extinctions, environmental destruction, global warming, and willful ignorance about all of the above—we must also take up these themes and temper our hope with the realization that all our struggles for a brighter tomorrow may very well be in vain, and that the most we can ever hope for is a partial victory. But if we look closely at Dewey, underneath his faith in the common sense of the average citizen and his belief in science as the 42 McDermott, Culture, 142-143. 24 most secure means of progress, we find the recognition that despite (or perhaps because of) our intelligence and our ideals we still too often fall into mass suicide. As McDermott says, “The thought of John Dewey does not answer the question, Why Bother? in any peremptory or stentorian way. The question, however, pervades his life and work.”43 Understanding the individual as ecological strips away the various fictions we use to insulate us from the precarious nature of existence. When we recognize our ties to others—other humans, communities, life forms, ecosystems, even those non-living components of our environment—we are reminded of the various ways our actions intertwine and how tenuous our existence truly is. It is too easy for us to respond to our existential fears by grasping various monocultures to provide us with ready-made answers. Christianity, Islam, Capitalism, Marxism—all have fundamentalist contingents offering to provide a neat framework for selfunderstanding and a community of the like-minded. Although there is something tempting here, Dewey is correct: ready-made answers blunt our sensibility. If we are to grow and make meaning, we must acknowledge our existential status, harness our fear and trembling, and take up the project of self-cultivation, all the while knowing that, to quote McDermott, “The first, foremost, and permanent ontological fact of our human existence is that we are born to live but sure to die.”44 Dewey understands this and offers his philosophy as a means of taking up the project of living in the hope of “conserving, transmitting, rectifying and expanding the heritage of values we have received” (LW 9:57) but with the realization that “when all is said and done, the fundamentally hazardous character of the world is not seriously modified, much less 43 44 p. 282 “Why Bother,” 274 25 eliminated.”45 But for Dewey, it is this very fact which renders human meaning-making meaningful. 45 Experience and Nature, LW 1:45 26