SCHMIDT ARTICLE FINAL MACRO FINAL FINAL (011409) 1/14/2009 4:58 PM ENDING THE MATHEWS V. ELDRIDGE BALANCING TEST: TIME FOR A NEW DUE PROCESS TEST Christopher J. Schmidt INTRODUCTION If the government was attempting to deprive you of your life, liberty, or property, do you know what United States‟ Supreme Court decision generally governs what “process” you are due? While your interest is probably not related to social security benefits, the governing decision involved social security benefits and that decision could determine what process you are due. The current due process test is from Mathews v. Eldridge;1 it “measures” three factors: the private interest affected by government action; the risk of erroneous deprivation of such interest; and, the government‟s interest, including the function involved and the burdens the government would face in providing greater process.2 The Mathews test has thus been described as an economic balancing test3 attempting to determine what process is due by weighing the legal parties‟ interests using language characterized as “social utility.”4 Another way some think of the test is as a cost-benefit analysis.5 The test requires a court to ask what procedures are required in the case before it by B.A., University of Maryland, 1998; J.D., Widener University School of Law, 2001; LL.M., Georgetown University Law Center, 2005. Member of the Pennsylvania Bar. 1. 424 U.S. 319 (1976). 2. Id. at 321. 3. Jerry L. Mashaw, The Supreme Court’s Due Process Calculus for Administrative Adjudication in Mathews v. Eldridge: Three Factors in Search of a Theory of Value, 44 U. CHI. L. REV. 28, 47-48 (1976); Stephen E. Gottlieb, The Paradox of Balancing Significant Interests, 45 HASTINGS L.J. 825, 841 (1994). 4. Mashaw, supra note 3, at 49-51; see also Gottlieb, supra note 3, at 841. 5. Michael J. Furbush, Constitutional Law: Procedural Due Process and Civil Commitment, 45 FLA. L. REV. 921, 923 (1993) (citing JERRY L. MASHAW, DUE PROCESS IN THE ADMINISTRATIVE STATE 103-04 (1985)). 287 SCHMIDT ARTICLE FINAL MACRO FINAL FINAL (011409) 288 S OU TH WES TER N LA W REVIE W 1/14/2009 4:58 PM [Vol. 38 determining procedures that would adequately protect the individual while not being too burdensome on the government; i.e., the cost-benefit analysis.6 Ultimately, the test is not designed to create a test with broad application to many other cases; instead, a unique procedure for each case may be created.7 Interestingly, my research revealed that Dean T. Alexander Aleinikoff of Georgetown University Law Center provided a thorough review of balancing tests.8 When one merges this review with the proposals of two textualist jurists—former Supreme Court Justice Hugo Black and current Justice Antonin Scalia—we have an eloquent historical review of balancing tests and a proposal for a new due process test. Part I of this article, which relies more on Dean Aleinikoff‟s writing, describes how balancing tests have little historical foundation and are ineffective at resolving due process issues. Part II, which relies more on Justices Black‟s and Scalia‟s view, analyzes the textual and historical foundation of the Due Process Clause and proposes a new due process test. I. EVALUATING THE MATHEWS BALANCING TEST The Mathews test has little historical foundation and it attempts to balance interests on a scale that cannot be measured and weighed like an inanimate object that has a specific weight. In section (A), I trace the evolution of balancing tests in legal decision-making, revealing that they are a relatively recent judicial concept. Next, in section (B), I illustrate the common sense critique of balancing tests that balancing only works in settings where a definite result, such as those in economics or mathematics, may occur. A. Little Historical Justification for Balancing Tests Dean Aleinikoff provided a chronological review of balancing tests. Obviously, the Bill of Rights (containing the Due Process Clause) was ratified before judges created any balancing tests to interpret it.9 In fact, it took a long time for balancing tests to come of age; they seem to first appear in the 1930‟s—long after the Due Process Clause came into effect in 6. Brock v. Roadway Express, Inc., 481 U.S. 252, 277 (1987) (Stevens, J., dissenting). 7. T. Alexander Aleinikoff, Constitutional Law in the Age of Balancing, 96 YALE L.J. 943, 979 (1987). 8. Id. 9. Id. at 948. SCHMIDT ARTICLE FINAL MACRO FINAL FINAL (011409) 2008] 1/14/2009 4:58 PM TI ME F OR A N E W D UE PRO CES S TES T 289 1791.10 Thus, the 1930‟s balancing tests were a new form of constitutional analysis from judges, not from the Constitution‟s text.11 And in the early balancing test opinions, there does not appear to be an explanation from judges as to why such tests were “a proper form of analysis.”12 In short, the use of balancing tests increased as the Warren Court guided constitutional analysis in the 1960‟s,13 and they were “commonplace” by the 1980‟s.14 Dean Aleinikoff provided an historical review revealing constitutional law opinions up to the 1930‟s did not use balancing tests in constitutional analysis.15 He found a close, linguistic review of the Supreme Court‟s opinions up to the 1930‟s shows it did not write opinions or analyze cases in terms of economic, cost-benefit, or social utilitarian balancing tests.16 Dean Aleinikoff explains the court did not even ask the parties what interests should be balanced or how those interests balanced against each other.17 The Court‟s failure to use balancing tests for about the first 150 years of its existence shows their use has little historical foundation. Further, the Constitution does not state balancing tests should be used to interpret it18 and one can see balancing tests are relatively recent judicial creations with little foundation.19 10. Id.; see also Frank N. Coffin, Judicial Balancing: The Protean Scales of Justice, 63 N.Y.U. L. REV. 16, 18 (1988) (determining the genesis of balancing tests to be 1939) (citing Schneider v. State, 308 U.S. 147, 161-65 (1939)). 11. Aleinikoff, supra note 7, at 949. 12. Id. at 948-49. 13. Coffin, supra note 10, at 18. 14. Id. 15. Aleinikoff, supra note 7, at 949. Dean Aleinikoff explained how well-known constitutional opinions of the era mentioned did not utilize balancing tests: Marshall did not hold for the Bank in McCulloch v. Maryland because the burden of the state‟s tax outweighed the state‟s interest in taxation. Webster‟s argument in Gibbons v. Ogden was not persuasive because he demonstrated that the interest of the national government outweighed the interests of the states in regulating interstate commerce. Nor were the purchasers of land in Fletcher v. Park entitled to keep their property because, on balance, the interest in security of transactions outweighed the interest of the State of Georgia in repealing corrupt legislation. Id. (internal citations omitted). 16. Id. at 950. For a review of language of well-known Supreme Court opinions prior to the 1930‟s that did not use balancing tests, see id. at 950-52 and accompanying footnotes. 17. Id. at 952. 18. See Konigsberg v. State Bar, 366 U.S. 36, 61-68 (1960) (Black, J., dissenting); Barenblatt v. United States, 360 U.S. 109, 138-39, 143-44 (1959) (Black, J., dissenting). 19. See Aleinikoff, supra note 7, at 949. SCHMIDT ARTICLE FINAL MACRO FINAL FINAL (011409) 290 S OU TH WES TER N LA W REVIE W 1/14/2009 4:58 PM [Vol. 38 B. Practical Problems of Balancing Interests As Dean Aleinikoff describes, the main problem with balancing tests is they have no set way to compare or “weigh” the interests before a court.20 Judges, therefore, are left trying to balance two distinct interests with different, yet usually very important reasons supporting why they have great “weight”; thus, it has been widely stated that balancing tests attempt to balance the proverbial apples and oranges.21 Dean Aleinikoff noted a court, such as Mathews, can frame a due process issue under a balancing test,22 but that framing of the issue is incomplete because balancing only provides an accurate answer when real, weighted items can be weighed and tip a real scale one way or another.23 Another scholar described it like this: a balancing scale is only an effective device when weighted items can be placed on it so it will tilt in one direction or another, thereby eliminating any human thought to control the result.24 Legal “interests,” such as an individual‟s cherished liberty versus the government‟s interest in detaining an individual dangerous to the public or themselves, are impossible to measure because there is no way to specifically “weigh” those interests and no scale where these interests can be weighed.25 With no scale, Dean Aleinikoff stated “legal interests cannot be translated into common currency for comparison.”26 Once we recognize no legal balancing scale exists, then we can seriously question if legal decisions using balancing tests actually reach a reasoned resolution.27 Another scholar thought of it this way: since balancing tests are not true mathematical or economic equations, there is no way to check or prove a court‟s answer as one can do in true mathematical problems and solutions.28 That is why, as Robert Bork described, economics “produces its best results with the behavior of persons in real markets, where dollars may be used as 20. Id. at 952. 21. See id. at 952, 975; RICHARD POSNER, ECONOMIC ANALYSIS OF LAW 581-642 (3d ed. 1986); Robert H. Bork, The Role of the Courts in Applying Economics, 54 ANTITRUST L.J. 21, 22 (1985) (determining that the notion that economics and cost/benefit analyses can be applied to all areas of law rests on the premise that there are no such things as apples and oranges); Gottlieb, supra note 3, at 841 (noting apples and oranges are incomparable when discussing flaws in balancing tests). 22. Aleinikoff, supra note 7, at 948. 23. Id. at 973. 24. See Gottlieb, supra note 3, at 839-41. 25. See Cass Sunstein, Incommensurability and Valuation in Law, 92 MICH. L. REV. 779, 796 (1994); Gottlieb, supra note 3, at 841; Aleinikoff, supra note 7, at 974-75. 26. Aleinikoff, supra note 7, at 973. 27. Id. 28. Gottlieb, supra note 3, at 842. SCHMIDT ARTICLE FINAL MACRO FINAL FINAL (011409) 2008] TI ME F OR A N E W D UE PRO CES S TES T 1/14/2009 4:58 PM 291 measuring units.”29 It has been widely determined then, that a court using a balancing test has to “„measur[e] the unmeasurable [and] compare the incomparable.‟”30 Dean Aleinikoff found this leads appellate judges and justices to reach opposite conclusions even though they agreed upon the form of analysis—a balancing test.31 The lack of consistent, unanimous adjudication of cases utilizing balancing tests shows how poor balancing tests are. If balancing can occur, then balancing should lead to a unanimous decision in every case it is used. Whatever interest tips the scale has to prevail.32 If interest A weighs 51 legal units and interest B weighs 49 legal units, then all justices would have to conclude interest A prevails.33 Because legal interests lack weights to balance, one can see that balancing tests are not actually balancing tests. As indicated earlier, a balancing scale is only an effective device when weighted items can be placed on it so it will tilt in one direction or another, thereby eliminating any human thought to control the result.34 Such legal “balancing” relies on what interests judges think are more important, not the actual weight of an interest.35 Since there is no real legal scale that judges can place weighted interests upon, many scholars found judges likely impute (either consciously or subconsciously) their own values into “weighing” the parties interests.36 This is especially troubling because legal balancing results in 29. Bork, supra note 21, at 22. 30. Laurent B. Frantz, Is the First Amendment Law? - - A Reply to Professor Mendelson, 51 CAL. L. REV. 729, 748 (1963), quoted in Aleinikoff, supra note 7, at 972; see also Bendix Auotlite Corp. v. Midwesco Enter., Inc., 486 U.S. 888, 897 (Scalia, J., concurring) (noting a scale is inappropriate since interests on the scale are incommensurate); Melissa Taylor, The VMI Decision: A Look at the Balancing Process in Equal Protection Cases, 60 U.M.K.C. L. REV. 393, 395-96 (1991) (discussing the argument that it is difficult to assign values to interests and subsequently compare them); Peter B. Edelman, Free Press v. Privacy: Haunted by the Ghost of Justice Black, 68 TEX. L. REV. 1195, 1213 (1990) (discussing the argument that it is difficult to assign values to interests and subsequently compare them). 31. Aleinikoff, supra note 7, at 975 n.204 (citing Dun & Bradstreet, Inc. v. Greenmoss Builders, Inc., 472 U.S. 749, 761, 785 (1985); INS v. Lopez-Mendoza, 468 U.S. 1032, 1050, 1052 (1984); United States v. Leon, 468 U.S. 897, 926-28 (1984); Hobby v. United States, 468 U.S. 339, 350 (1984); Mathews v. Lucas, 427 U.S. 495, 516-17 (1976); Branzburg v. Hayes, 408 U.S. 665, 709-10 (1972)). 32. E.g., Wayte v. United States, 470 U.S. 598, 618 (1985). 33. Id. 34. Gottlieb, supra note 3, at 839, 841. 35. Id. at 842. 36. Id. at 840 (citing IRVING L. JANIS & LEON MANN, DECISION MAKING: A PSYCHOLOGICAL ANALYSIS OF CONFLICT, CHOICE, AND COMMITMENT 174-75 (1977)) (stating SCHMIDT ARTICLE FINAL MACRO FINAL FINAL (011409) 292 S OU TH WES TER N LA W REVIE W 1/14/2009 4:58 PM [Vol. 38 increasing one party‟s interest, say the government, at the expense of another party‟s interest, say an individual.37 Or, obviously, an individual‟s interest can be improperly heightened and the government‟s interest improperly diminished.38 Thus, at least one scholar has concluded allowing judges to “balance” competing interests according to their own values is unacceptable.39 Many others have generally stated the legal balancing scale cannot consist of judges‟ personal views, unless constitutional law is to return to the “lochnerizing” era.40 Balancing tests, at worst, are an unacceptable form of constitutional analysis that should be eliminated.41 Balancing tests, at best, would sneak by as an acceptable form of constitutional analysis, but would still allow judges to essentially alter the scale to meet their values.42 Ultimately, former Supreme Court Justice William Brennan, one I did not expect to be aligned with my position, provided an apt summary of balancing tests by stating they are “not a neutral, utilitarian calculus, but an unanalyzed exercise of judicial will.”43 Justice Scalia, generally not of like-mind with Justice Brennan on contentious constitutional issues, explained “when a court weighs the that rational decisions require consideration of costs and benefits); JAMES W. LOEWEN, SOCIAL SCIENCE IN THE COURTROOM: STATISTICAL TECHNIQUES AND RESEARCH METHODS FOR WINNING CLASS-ACTION SUITS 95-114 (1982) (giving examples of the use of rank ordering in statistical assessments); Frantz, supra note 30, at 747-49 (concluding that quantification cannot be done). See also Gottlieb, supra note 3, at 842; see also Frantz, supra note 30, at 747-49 (asking how judges can keep their personal preferences off the balancing scale); Curtis E. Harris, An Undue Burden: Balancing in an Age of Relativism, 18 OKLA. CITY U. L. REV. 363, 400 (1994) (concluding “[b]alancing tests inevitably become intertwined with the ideological predispositions of those doing the balancing”) (citing John Hart Ely, Flag Desecration: A Case Study in the Roles of Categorization and Balancing in First Amendment Analysis, 88 HARV. L. REV. 1482, 1501 (1975)). 37. Bork, supra note 21, at 22-23. 38. Id. 39. David M. Beatty, The Forms and Limits of Constitutional Interpretation, 49 AM. J. COMP. L. 79, 119 (2001). 40. Aleinikoff, supra note 7, at 973 (citing John Hart Ely, The Wages of Crying Wolf: A Comment on Roe v. Wade, 82 YALE L.J. 920, 944 (1973)). The term “lochnerizing” comes from the Supreme Court‟s decision in Lochner v. New York, 198 U.S. 45 (1905). The widely rejected decision is commonly seen as a form of judicial activism wherein the Court struck down a state law limiting the number of hours an employee could work per week and per day under a substantive due process methodology. See, e.g., Lochner, 198 U.S. at 53. 41. Beatty, supra note 39, at 119 (citing RONALD DWORKIN, LAW‟S EMPIRE, CH. 5 (1986)); Aleinikoff, supra note 7, at 978-79. Balancing competing and non-quantifiable interests is not always an unprincipled and potentially illicit process in the workings of government. The task of balancing such competing interests is a traditional legislative task. See Erwin Chemerinsky, The Vanishing Constitution, 103 HARV. L. REV. 43, 68 (1989) (citing Aleinikoff, supra note 7, at 984). 42. Norman Viera, Unwarranted Government Disclosures: Reflecting on Privacy Rights, HIV and Ad Hoc Balancing, 47 WAYNE L. REV. 173, 197 (2001). 43. New Jersey v. T.L.O., 469 U.S. 325, 369 (1985) (Brennan, J., dissenting). SCHMIDT ARTICLE FINAL MACRO FINAL FINAL (011409) 2008] 1/14/2009 4:58 PM TI ME F OR A N E W D UE PRO CES S TES T 293 private interest against the [g]overnment‟s interest, it proceeds under the guise of the Due Process Clause to prescribe what procedural protections it thinks appropriate.”44 He further stated a court is not to prescribe what procedures it thinks is appropriate, but the procedures the law requires.45 Justice Black articulated the danger of allowing judges to determine what they think is appropriate: [U]nbounded authority in any group of politically appointed or elected judges would unquestionably be sufficient to classify our Nation as a government of men, not the government of laws of which we boast . . . I believe the only way to steer this country towards its great destiny is to follow what our Constitution says, not what judges think it should have said.46 Justice Black then describes who should decide what is fair: The rules set out in the Constitution itself provide what is governmentally fair and what is not. Neither due process nor equal protection permits state laws to be invalidated on any such nonconstitutional standard as a judge‟s personal view of fairness. The people and their elected representatives, not judges, are constitutionally vested with the power to amend the Constitution. Judges should not usurp that power in order to put over their own views.47 If we let five unelected justices decide what is fair, the Due Process Clause‟s protections could be eviscerated. Dean Aleinikoff mentioned balancing is also difficult because it is unclear if judges take into account all the parties‟ interests.48 This occurs because the Due Process Clause does not say anything about balancing interests, and judges, while probably trying their best, are not trained in balancing; so, courts likely identify some, but not all the interests of the government and an individual in a case before it.49 As a Supreme Court decision often establishes the final say on law in a particular area, the interests affected are broad and important. A Supreme Court decision can affect notions of equity, future legislative acts, future behavior of the citizenry and the government. Should not these interests be weighed and balanced as well? Since no truly weighted interests or legal scale exists, there is no 44. Hamdi v. Rumsfeld, 542 U.S. 507, 575 (2004) (Scalia, J., dissenting). 45. Id. at 575-76. 46. Boddie v. Connecticut, 401 U.S. 371, 393 (1971) (Black, J., dissenting). 47. Id. at 394. 48. Aleinikoff, supra note 7, at 977. 49. Id. at 988; Barenblatt v. United States, 360 U.S. 109, 144-47 (1959) (Black, J., dissenting). SCHMIDT ARTICLE FINAL MACRO FINAL FINAL (011409) 294 S OU TH WES TER N LA W REVIE W 1/14/2009 4:58 PM [Vol. 38 benefit to adopting the Mathews test;50 thus, courts should avoid it if possible.51 Ultimately, as Justice Brennan stated, the Supreme Court should provide some coherent framework to decide cases other than the Mathews test.52 II. DETERMINING AN APPROPRIATE DUE PROCESS TEST An appropriate due process test should conform to the Due Process Clause‟s text and its historical understanding. The clause‟s text shows it requires the government provide the procedure owed a person when the government attempts to deprive him of his life, liberty, or property.53 The source of this procedure must be found in a “law.” An historical understanding of the Due Process Clause verifies this textual conclusion. As Justice Black stated, an appropriate due process test provides the government must proceed according to the law of the land, that is, according to written constitutional and statutory provisions as interpreted by court decisions when attempting to deprive a person of life, liberty, or property.54 A. Understanding the Due Process Clause’s Text While the Due Process Clause may seem somewhat vague,55 it has to be defined in a constitutional analysis because the Constitution states the people “ordain and establish” the Constitution,56 and it is the supreme law of the land requiring judges to support it through oath or affirmation.57 As some described, since the Constitution‟s words are what the people ratified and believe is supreme,58 a constitutional analysis begins with the “constitutional text speaking to [the] precise question.”59 Even if a 50. See Bork, supra note 21, at 23. 51. See Laurence Tribe, Constitutional: Equal Justice or Economic Efficiency?, 98 HARV. L. REV. 592, 620 (1985), cited in Aleinikoff, supra note 7, at 992. 52. New Jersey v. T.L.O., 469 U.S. 325, 369 (1985) (Brennan, J., dissenting). 53. U.S. CONST. amend. XIV, § 1. 54. In re Winship, 397 U.S. 357, 382 (1970) (Black, J., dissenting). 55. Id. at 378. 56. U.S. CONST. pmbl.; Akhil Reed Amar, Foreward: The Document and the Doctrine, 114 HARV. L. REV. 26, 34 (2000). 57. U.S. CONST. art. VI, cl. 2. 58. Tome v. United States, 513 U.S. 150, 167 (1995) (Scalia, J., concurring); see also Amar, supra note 56, at 33. 59. Printz v. United States, 521 U.S. 898, 905 (1997); see also John Randolph Prince, SCHMIDT ARTICLE FINAL MACRO FINAL FINAL (011409) 2008] TI ME F OR A N E W D UE PRO CES S TES T 1/14/2009 4:58 PM 295 centuries old constitutional provision has not been specifically interpreted by the Supreme Court, the starting point of an analysis is with that provision‟s text.60 Even Richard Posner, the leading proponent of law and economics analysis, believes constitutional analysis begins with the constitutional text.61 Ultimately, courts should construe constitutional text in a reasonable, common sense manner.62 Although the Due Process Clause is not immediately clear, its meaning can be extracted from its text. It provides: “No person shall be . . . deprived of life, liberty, or property, without due process of law . . . .”63 Generally, the clause is read to require the government provide fair procedures before it deprives persons of life, liberty, or property.64 That basic interpretation is not as exacting as the meaning of “due process of law” requires. “Process” means “procedure.”65 Thus, the Due Process Clause requires a procedure.66 The question is whether “due” means a fair procedure is required or something else is required? “Due” relates more to what is owed, and less to what is fair. Due‟s meaning before the Constitution‟s enactment referenced something due as a Forgetting the Lyrics and Changing the Tune: The Eleventh Amendment and Textual Infidelity, 104 DICK. L. REV. 1, 17 (1999) (noting a court should start its analysis with an amendment‟s words, not with implicit principles). 60. Christopher J. Schmidt, An International Human Right to Keep and Bear Arms, 15 WM. & MARY BILL RTS. J. 983, 984-88 (2007) (starting Second Amendment analysis with amendment‟s text); District of Columbia v. Heller, 128 S. Ct. 2783, 2788 (U.S. 2008) (same). 61. Richard Posner, The Constitution as an Economic Document, 56 GEO. WASH. L. REV. 4, 33 (1987). 62. Christopher J. Schmidt & David A. Klinger, Altering the Posse Comitatus Act: Letting the Military Address Terrorist Attacks on American Soil, 39 CREIGHTON L. REV. 667, 675 (2006) (citing ANTONIN SCALIA, A MATTER OF INTERPRETATION: FEDERAL COURTS AND THE LAW 23 (1997)). 63. U.S. CONST. amend. V. 64. Christopher J. Schmidt, Revitalizing the Quiet Ninth Amendment: Determining Unenumerated Rights and Eliminating Substantive Due Process, 32 U. BALT. L. REV. 169, 188 (2003) (citing ROBERT H. BORK, THE TEMPTING OF AMERICA: THE POLITICAL SEDUCTION OF THE LAW 180 (Collier MacMillan 1990), cited in Bruce N. Morton, John Locke, Robert Bork, Natural Rights and the Interpretation of the Constitution, 22 SETON HALL L. REV. 709, 756 (1992)). 65. THE AMERICAN HERITAGE DICTIONARY OF THE ENGLISH LANGUAGE 1398 (4th ed. 2000). The modern day ordinary meaning of “process” includes: “[a] series of actions, changes, or functions bringing about a result,” “[t]he entire course of a judicial proceeding,” “[t]o put through the steps of a prescribed procedure,” “[t]o institute legal proceedings against . . . .” Id. See also THE WORLD BOOK DICTIONARY 1659 (1981); MERRIAM-WEBSTER‟S COLLEGIATE DICTIONARY 927 (10th ed. 1971); WEBSTER‟S NEW COLLEGIATE DICTIONARY 917 (1977); see OXFORD ENGLISH DICTIONARY available at http://www.dictionary.oed.com. 66. See THE AMERICAN HERITAGE DICTIONARY OF THE ENGLISH LANGUAGE, supra note 65, at 1398. SCHMIDT ARTICLE FINAL MACRO FINAL FINAL (011409) 296 S OU TH WES TER N LA W REVIE W 1/14/2009 4:58 PM [Vol. 38 debt or “due” as a right, being sufficient in that regard.67 The modern day meaning of “due” is remarkably similar. It includes: “[p]ayable immediately on demand;”68 “owed as a debt;”69 “[i]n accord with right, convention, or courtesy; appropriate . . . .”70 These meanings show “due” means that what is owed or payable on demand as a right. One may criticize the inclusion of the meanings of “due” as owed or payable on demand as irrelevant because no financial debt is in question. This critique is incorrect for two reasons. First, something that is “owed as debt” need not be financial in nature. This is true when the Constitution is thought of as a social compact or contract between the people and the government.71 Under this compact, the government is required to provide persons a process under law before depriving them of life, liberty, or property.72 Obviously, the process owed is not financial in nature, but it is still a debt the government owes persons when it attempts to deprive them of their life, liberty, or property. Second, courts, including the Supreme Court in Hamdi v. Rumsfeld,73 regularly frame due process questions as what process is constitutionally due, or more often, the “process due,” or the “process owed.”74 This placement of “due” shows courts attempt to determine what process a person is constitutionally owed when the government attempts to deprive him of his life, liberty, or property. The Hamdi plurality stated: “[M]r. Hamdi argues that he is owed a meaningful and timely hearing . . . .”75 With the definition of “due” including meanings referencing what is “owed” and the Supreme Court and multiple other 67. See OXFORD ENGLISH DICTIONARY, supra note 65. 68. THE AMERICAN HERITAGE DICTIONARY OF THE ENGLISH LANGUAGE, supra note 65, at 553. 69. THE WORLD BOOK DICTIONARY, supra note 65, at 649. 70. WEBSTER‟S NEW COLLEGIATE DICTIONARY, supra note 65 at 357. 71. Kevin W. Saunders, Privacy and Social Contract: A Defense of Judicial Activism in Privacy Cases, 33 ARIZ. L. REV. 811, 822 (1991) (citing Edward S. Corwin, The “Higher Law” Background of American Constitutional Law, 42 HARV. L. REV. 149, 383-98 (1928)); Citizens‟ Savings & Loan Ass‟n v. Topeka, 87 U.S. 655, 662-63 (1874) (concluding there are rights in every free government beyond the State‟s control that ensure the existence of the social compact); Calder v. Bull, 3 U.S. 386, 388 (1798) (finding a legislative act contrary to the first principles of the social compact); Chisholm v. Georgia, 2 U.S. 419, 455 (1793) (Wilson, J., concurring) (concluding states, like individuals, are bound by laws through a compact). I take no position as to whether the substantive decisions in cases invoking the social compact theory were correct or not. 72. See U.S. CONST. amend. XIV. 73. 542 U.S. 507 (2004). 74. Id. at 523 (emphasis added); Id. at 594 (Thomas, J., dissenting) (concluding “Hamdi thereby received all the process to which he was due under the circumstances”); see also Gilbert v. Homar, 520 U.S. 924, 931 (1997). 75. Id. (emphasis added). SCHMIDT ARTICLE FINAL MACRO FINAL FINAL (011409) 2008] 1/14/2009 4:58 PM TI ME F OR A N E W D UE PRO CES S TES T 297 courts recognizing this concept, one cannot effectively argue “owed” is not a relevant meaning of “due” when interpreting the Due Process Clause. Some may argue “due” means “fair”;76 thus, a “fair” procedure is required. The placement of due, again, defeats this position. If due meant “fair,” then the commonly used phrase “process due” would mean the “process fair.” Courts would then begin saying, for example, party A argues this is the process fair. That phrasing simply does not make sense. So, the placement of due in court opinions, just as much, if not more than its definition, shows what it means in regard to “due process of law.”77 Fairness is a principle of the Due Process Clause; that principle, however, is evidenced by determining what process is owed to an individual. The Constitution provides the meaning of what constitutes federal “law.”78 The Constitution declares itself the supreme law of the land.79 It describes how congressional legislation becomes “law.”80 It also describes how treaties are ratified and they are the supreme law of the land.81 While the Constitution does not specifically refer to judicial decisions as law, it is generally accepted they establish law.82 Since the Due Process Clause was ratified during the founding era, the common law of the colonists in existence at the time served as a source of “law” for determining what process was due as well.83 Those fundamental common law principles may also be a source of law. The Mathews test limits the meaning of “law” in the Due Process 76. See, e.g., supra note 65. 77. Hamdi, 542 U.S. at 531. 78. See U.S. CONST. art. VI. 79. Id. (“The Constitution . . . shall be the supreme Law of the Land . . . .”). 80. U.S. CONST. art. I, § 1 (“All legislative Powers herein granted shall be vested in a Congress of the United States, which shall consist of a Senate and a House of Representatives.”); U.S. CONST. art. I, § 7 Every Bill which shall have passed the House of Representatives and the Senate, shall, before it become a Law, be presented to the President of the United States; If he approves he shall sign it, but if not he shall return it, with his Objections to that House in which it shall have originated, who shall enter the Objections at large on their Journal, and proceed to reconsider it. If after such Reconsideration two thirds of that House shall agree to pass the Bill, it shall be sent, together with the Objections, to the other House, by which it shall likewise be reconsidered, and if approved by two thirds of that House, it shall become a Law. Id. 81. U.S. CONST. art. VI (“all Treaties made, or which shall be made, . . . shall be the supreme Law of the Land . . . .”). 82. Federal court decisions may not be a form of “law.” The Constitution does not describe court decisions as law. However, since federal court decisions are generally recognized as a form of law I will analyze them as such in this article. 83. Hamdi v. Rumsfeld, 542 U.S. 507, 555 (2004) (Scalia, J., dissenting) (concluding gist of the Due Process Clause is to force government to follow common law procedures traditionally required before depriving a person of life, liberty, or property). SCHMIDT ARTICLE FINAL MACRO FINAL FINAL (011409) 298 S OU TH WES TER N LA W REVIE W 1/14/2009 4:58 PM [Vol. 38 Clause to a court decision. Under Mathews, essentially the only “law” that can provide the procedure owed is a court decision because to determine what process is due, a court must undertake the Mathews balancing test.84 Under Mathews, essentially all other forms of law cannot determine what process is due; thus, courts will not specifically rely on the Constitution, statutes, rules, cases, etc.85 Mathews therefore excludes a tremendous body of law that should be referred to as the possible source for determining what due process of “law” is required.86 The Due Process Clause should be read to mean that a person whose life, liberty, or property is subject to government deprivation can demand a certain process that is owed to him as a right under a law. To identify what process is owed, courts should identify the sources of law that provide the procedure the government must follow for the scenario at issue. That is the process a person can demand the government provide them as a right. This methodology is not perfect. In difficult situations, where no specific law established the procedure to follow, judges may differ on what law may govern.87 This dilemma pales in comparison to the negative implications of using the Mathews test. Under this new test, at least we start and comply with the Due Process Clause‟s text. Courts would also return to the era beginning from the Constitution‟s ratification until the 1930‟s, a time in which balancing tests were not used.88 Ultimately, courts and lawyers would not have to deal with all the problems I described related to balancing tests.89 The application of the new test concerns identifying and analyzing laws that may provide a procedure that governs the circumstances before the Court. This process follows traditional, accepted legal research and analytical principles.90 84. Id. at 529 (citing Mathews v. Eldridge, 424 U.S. 319, 335 (1976)). 85. Aleinikoff, supra note 7, at 988. 86. See Mathews, 424 U.S. at 319. 87. Aleinikoff, supra note 7, at 948. 88. Id.; Coffin, supra note 10, at 18. 89. See supra notes 44-83 and accompanying text. 90. One may question whether my approach is essentially an equal protection analysis advanced under the guise of the Due Process Clause because this article is ensuring that each person receive the same process as a similarly situated person received before them. It is true that the concept of due process and the concept of equal protection are linked. Jane Rutherford, The Myth of Due Process, 72 B.U. L. REV. 1, 65 (1992). As far back as the Magna Carta the original idea of due process of law was inextricably entwined with notions of equality. Id. at 65, 68. Due process, in fact, hinged upon the notion of equality as one of the legitimating bases for the principle of due process to exist. Id. at 69. The critical distinction between the concepts of due process and equal protection is that one deals with procedures of law and one deals with the substance of law. Due process is about rules of procedure, not about the law at issue in the process. John Harrison, Substantive Due Process and the Constitutional Text, 83 VA. L. REV. 493, 542 (1997). A drafter of a law who wanted to convey a rule about the content of the law SCHMIDT ARTICLE FINAL MACRO FINAL FINAL (011409) 2008] 1/14/2009 4:58 PM TI ME F OR A N E W D UE PRO CES S TES T 299 B. Historical Understanding of the Due Process Clause As Justice Black stated, some think the Due Process Clause is too vague for its plain meaning to control its interpretation, but “any possible ambiguity disappears when the phrase is viewed in light of history and the accepted meaning of those words prior to and at the time our Constitution was written.”91 Justice Scalia provided a lengthy historical analysis of the phrase “due process of law” that I summarize below.92 Apparently, “due process of law” was first used in a 1354 English statute: “„No man of what estate or condition that he be, shall be put out of land or tenement, nor taken nor imprisoned, nor disinherited, nor put to death, without being brought in answer by due process of law.‟”93 The phrase “due process of law” in the statute has been equated with the phrase “Law of the Land” in the Magna Carta, which provided: No freeman shall be taken, or imprisoned, or be disseised of his Freehold, or Liberties, or free Customs, or be outlawed, or exiled, or any otherwise destroyed; nor will we not pass upon him, nor condemn him, but by lawful Judgment of his Peers, or by the Law of the Land. 94 It is commonly recognized that “due process of law” in American law is derived from the “Law of the Land” language from the Magna Carta. Legal scholarship95 and case law recognize this conclusion.96 would not talk about the activities through which that content is enforced, and not about the process of enforcement. Id. at 541. Due process does not include the requirement of equal protection in the substance of laws. Bork, supra note 21, at 83. Equal protection, on the other hand, is directly aimed at ensuring that the substance of a law does not deprive a person of equal protection. 91. In re Winship, 397 U.S. 357, 378 (1970) (Black, J., dissenting). 92. Pac. Mutual Life Ins. Co. v. Haslip, 499 U.S. 1, 28 (1991) (Scalia, J., concurring). 93. Id. (citing Due Process of Law Act 1354, 28 Edw. III, ch. 3). 94. Id. (citing Magna Carta, 9 Hen. III, ch. 29 (1225)). 95. See Peter Zablotsky, From a Whimper to a Bang: The Trend Toward Finding Occurrence Based Statutes of Limitations Governing Negligent Misdiagnosis of Diseases with Long Latency Periods Unconstitutional, 103 DICK. L. REV. 455, 479 n.102 (1999) (determining concept of procedural due process is derived from Magna Carta); Harrison, supra note 90, at 542-43 (stating a commonplace of 19th Century constitutional law was equivalence of due process and law of the land); Mark Kadish, Behind the Locked Door of an American Grand Jury: Its History, Its Secrecy, and Its Process, 24 FLA. ST. U. L. REV. 1, 7 (1996) (noting Magna Carta introduced procedural due process to English law); Rutherford, supra note 90, at 9 (noting notions of due process grew out of Magna Carta‟s “law of the land” language); THOMAS M. COOLEY, A TREATISE ON THE CONSTITUTIONAL LIMITATIONS WHICH REST UPON THE LEGISLATIVE POWER OF THE STATES OF THE AMERICAN UNION 175 (1st ed. 1868) (discussing the law of the land approach), cited in Harrison, supra note 90, at 523 n.85; Haslip, 499 U.S. at 29 (Scalia, J., concurring) (citing WILLIAM BLACKSTONE, 2 COMMENTARIES 133 (S. Tucker ed.) (1803), 2 J. KENT, COMMENTARIES ON AMERICAN LAW 10 (1827); 3 J. STORY, COMMENTARIES ON THE CONSTITUTION OF THE UNITED STATES 661 (1833)). SCHMIDT ARTICLE FINAL MACRO FINAL FINAL (011409) 300 S OU TH WES TER N LA W REVIE W 1/14/2009 4:58 PM [Vol. 38 Justice Scalia noted some colonial era state constitutions adopted “law of the land” language in provisions designed to protect against deprivations of life, liberty, and property.97 Obviously, these provisions mirror the Due Process Clause as life, liberty, or property could not be deprived but by the “law of the land.”98 Justice Scalia reviewed 19th century case law, verifying the Due Process Clause requires the government provide a procedure under the law of the land before it deprives a person of life, liberty, or property. In 1856, the Supreme Court stated: To what principles, then, are we to resort to ascertain whether this process enacted by [C]ongress, is due process? To this the answer must be twofold. We must examine the [C]onstitution itself, to see whether this process be in conflict with any of its provisions. If not found to be so, we must look to those settled usages and modes of proceeding existing in the common and statute law of England, before the emigration of our ancestors, and which are shown not to have been unsuited to their civil and political condition by having been acted on by them after the settlement of 99 this country. Justice Scalia noted that twenty years later, the Court reiterated the determination of whether a process is appropriate is if the process was “„according to the settled course of judicial proceedings. Due process of law is process due according to the law of the land.‟”100 Justice Scalia continued his review of case law, noting that eight years later, the Court dealt with the relationship between the founding era‟s common law principles and subsequent law enacted in the United States 96. In re Winship, 397 U.S. at 382 (concluding due process follows the principle of the Magna Carta that the rule of law governs); Haslip, 499 U.S. at 28-29 (discussing the historical understanding of due process as equivalent to the Magna Carta‟s “law of the land” language); see Davidson v. New Orleans, 96 U.S. 97, 101 (1887) (noting the equivalent of the phrase “law of the land” in the Magna Carta is found in the phrase “due process of law”); Walker v. Sauvient, 92 U.S. 90, 92-93 (1876) (determining due process of law is the process due according to the law of the land); Murray‟s Lessee v. Hoboken Land & Improvement Co., 59 U.S. 272, 276 (1856) (noting that the words “due process of law” conveyed the same meaning as the words “by the law of the land” found in the Magna Carta). 97. Haslip, 499 U.S. at 29. 98. Id. (citing N.C. CONST. art. XII (1976) (“No freeman ought to be taken, imprisoned, or disseized of his freehold, liberties or privileges, or outlawed, or exiled, or in any manner destroyed, or deprived of his life, liberty, or property, but by the law of the land.”); MASS. CONST., art. XII (1780) (“No subject shall be arrested, imprisoned, despoiled, or deprived of his property, immunities, or privileges, put out of the protection of the law, exiled or deprived of his life, liberty, or estate, but by the judgment of his peers, or the law of the land.”); see also Harrison, supra note 90, at 543 n.133 (determining that “law of the land” and “due process” in state constitutions are synonymous). 99. Id. at 30 (citing Murray’s Lessee, 50 U.S. at 276-77). 100. Id. (citing Walker v. Sauvinet, 92 U.S. 90, 92-93 (1875)). SCHMIDT ARTICLE FINAL MACRO FINAL FINAL (011409) 2008] 1/14/2009 4:58 PM TI ME F OR A N E W D UE PRO CES S TES T 301 when determining what source of “law” provides the process due.101 The Court concluded a process of law historically sanctioned in England and the United States would be due process of law, but historical process was not the only source of due process of law.102 Holding that only processes historically adopted satisfy due process muster “„would be to deny every quality of the law but its age, and to render it incapable of progress or improvement. It would be to stamp upon our jurisprudence the unchangeableness attributed to the laws of the Medes and Persians.‟”103 Ultimately, Justice Scalia concluded the English procedures brought to the United States help determine what due process requires.104 Justice Scalia found that complying with the idea behind the Due Process Clause makes the government follow common-law procedures before depriving a person of life, liberty, or property.105 But English common law of the 1600‟s and 1700‟s cannot be “fastened upon American jurisprudence like a straight jacket.”106 “If the government chooses to follow a historically approved procedure, it necessarily provides due process, but if it chooses to depart from historical practice, it does not necessarily deny due process.”107 Ultimately, Justice Scalia found a harsh or unwise procedure is not unconstitutional because judges personally think it is harsh or unwise,108 just as seemingly sensible procedures could violate the Constitution.109 C. An Appropriate Due Process Test Justice Black articulated the best test to incorporate the textual and historical understanding of the Due Process Clause.110 Therefore, the Due Process clause requires the government proceed according to the law of the land, that is, according to written constitutional and statutory provisions as interpreted by court decisions.111 Any deprivations of life, liberty, or 101. Id. at 31. 102. Id. (citing Hurtado v. California, 110 U.S. 516, 528 (1884)). 103. Haslip, 499 U.S. at 30 (citing Hurtado, 110 U.S. at 528-29). 104. Id. 105. Hamdi v. Rumsfeld, 542 U.S. 507, 556 (2004) (Scalia, J., dissenting). 106. In re Winship, 397 U.S. 357, 381 (1970) (citing Twining v. New Jersey, 211 U.S. 78, 100-01 (1908)). 107. Haslip, 499 U.S. at 31-32. 108. Id. at 39 (citing Corn Exch. Bank v. Coler, 280 U.S. 218, 223 (1930)). 109. Id. (citing Maryland v. Craig, 497 U.S. 836, 860-61 (1990) (Scalia, J., dissenting)). 110. In re Winship, 397 U.S. at 382. 111. Id.; see also Hamdi, 542 U.S. at 589. SCHMIDT ARTICLE FINAL MACRO FINAL FINAL (011409) 302 S OU TH WES TER N LA W REVIE W 1/14/2009 4:58 PM [Vol. 38 property must be lawful112 as the clause only imposes the rule of law.113 The government must provide the proceedings according to the law of the land as it exists at the time of the given proceeding.114 If no law directly applies, courts would apply existing law that most closely mirrors the circumstances at issue. Some may criticize this approach as making due process a meaningless protection. The argument could be that any process established under law would satisfy due process scrutiny, thus, no procedural protections could be struck down for violating the clause and the clause would be a tautological constitutional provision that would always be met. Professor John Harrison persuasively debunked this argument, noting many deprivations of life, liberty, and property were not done under law.115 For example, southern governments enacted the Black Codes,116 and making them provide procedures under law before depriving persons of their life, liberty, or property was a powerful legal requirement.117 The well documented governmental abuses in southern states showed the Constitution could not permit states to act without doing so under law.118 The requirement that a form of law establish the procedure the government must provide when attempting to deprive a person of life, liberty, or property is no small protection. A legally afforded process prevents arbitrary governmental action. Professor Jane Rutherford argued against the “law of the land” due process approach as too restrictive because it cannot encompass novel constitutional violations,119 and allows persons or groups with more political power to determine what procedures should be utilized.120 These arguments are unpersuasive. First, a law of the land due process approach is not rigid. As shown in this article, it is the textually and historically accurate approach. The Due Process Clause‟s meaning cannot be changed because some think it is too narrow a protection. The people, however, may change the Constitution by amendment if they wish to 112. Harrison, supra note 90, at 547. 113. Id. 114. In re Winship, 397 U.S. at 378; see also Lino A. Graglia, “Interpreting” the Constitution: Posner on Bork, 44 STAN. L. REV. 1019, 1045 (1992) (stating because due process must provide procedural regularity, the imposition of punishment through a deprivation of life, liberty, or property must be in accordance with pre-established law). 115. Harrison, supra note 90, at 550-51. 116. Id. at 551. 117. Id. 118. Id. 119. Rutherford, supra note 90, at 29. 120. Id. at 41. SCHMIDT ARTICLE FINAL MACRO FINAL FINAL (011409) 2008] 1/14/2009 4:58 PM TI ME F OR A N E W D UE PRO CES S TES T 303 provide broader constitutional protections.121 Those critics of a law of the land due process approach should stop trying to make due process what it is not and start making arguments for a constitutional amendment with language that would meet their position. Second, the argument that a strict application of due process magnifies the imbalance of power in society is without merit. Less powerful political groups will be less likely to get legislation passed that will provide the process they believe persons are due. But that is an “unavoidable consequence of democratic government, [which] must be preferred to a system in which each conscience is a law unto itself or in which judges weigh the social importance of all laws.”122 As Justice Clarence Thomas stated, leaving those less powerful groups at a political disadvantage could create a feeling that says: “Boy, I really need to do something. This just isn‟t right.”123 One may infer from Justice Thomas‟s remarks that the Due Process Clause does not allow judges to strike a lawful procedure because less powerful political groups did not get the procedure they wanted passed into law.124 Justice Thomas stated: “[I]t‟s like watching someone drowning 20 feet below and you only have 10 feet of rope.”125 Finally, one may criticize the law of the land due process approach as not protecting the notions of “fundamental fairness” in the Due Process Clause. This position generally is based on the notion due process requires “fundamental justice” or “fairness” in all cases.126 This argument is incorrect for two reasons. First, the nexus between what is the owed procedure and what is the fair procedure is the owed procedure is the fair procedure. Courts should not conclude what it thinks is fair,127 but conclude what procedure is owed by reviewing what procedure is afforded under existing “law.” Since the Constitution is the document the people ordained and established128 and judges swear to uphold,129 the document and laws passed in accord with it determine what process is fair. Justice Black articulated this principle: I realize that is far easier to substitute individual judges‟ ideas of 121. U.S. CONST. art. V (describing how Constitution may be amended). 122. Employment Div., Dep‟t of Human Res. v. Smith, 494 U.S. 872, 890 (1990). 123. Michael A. Fletcher & Kevin Merida, Jurist Embraces Image as a Hard-Line Holdout, WASH. POST, Oct. 11, 2004, at A10. 124. See id. 125. See id. 126. Pac. Mut. Life Ins. Co. v. Haslip, 499 U.S. 1, 33 (1991) (Scalia, J., concurring) (citing Snyder v. Massachusetts, 291 U.S. 97, 108, 116 (1934)). 127. In re Winship, 397 U.S. 357, 377-78 (1970). 128. U.S. CONST. pmbl.; Amar, supra note 56, at 34. 129. U.S. CONST. art. VI, cl. 2. SCHMIDT ARTICLE FINAL MACRO FINAL FINAL (011409) 304 1/14/2009 4:58 PM S OU TH WES TER N LA W REVIE W [Vol. 38 “fairness” for the fairness prescribed by the Constitution, but I shall not at any time surrender my belief that that document itself should be our guide, not our own concept of what is fair, decent, and right . . . As I have said time and time again, I prefer to put my faith in the words of the written Constitution itself rather than to rely on the shifting, day-to-day standards 130 of fairness of individual judges. Second, the fundamental fairness approach fails because it appears to be linked with another troubled approach to due process—balancing tests. The “fundamental fairness” approach apparently began in the 1930‟s,131 just when balancing tests began.132 Essentially, the concept of “fundamental fairness” is the inappropriate ends to the inappropriate means of balancing tests. Once again, Justice Black provided an eloquent critique: It can be, and has been, argued that when this Court strikes down a legislative act because it offends the idea of „fundamental fairness‟ it furthers the basic thrust of our Bill of Rights by protecting individual freedom. But that argument ignores the effect of such decisions on perhaps the most fundamental individual liberty of our people—the right of each man to participate in the self-government of his society. . . . The liberty of government by the people in my opinion, should never be denied by this Court except when the decision of the people as stated in laws passed by their chosen representatives, conflicts with the express or necessarily implied commands of our Constitution. 133 Leaving the determination of what meets due process muster in the hands of nine unelected justices could destroy the Due Process Clause. A rogue Supreme Court could undemocratically expand or contract what process is due in each circumstance before it. As Justice Black stated, unless we return to an analysis of the clause based on what it says, “liberty will likely be more honored in its breach than in the observance.”134 CONCLUSION Currently, if your life, liberty, or property was at stake, and a court was not sure what process you were due, you could have to wait and see how a judge or judges “weighed” your interests compared to the government‟s interests on some imaginary scale. How to weigh these interests is not taught, to my knowledge, at any law school. However, law schools 130. 131. 132. 133. 134. In re Winship, 397 U.S. at 377-78. Haslip, 499 U.S. at 33. Aleinikoff, supra note 7, at 948; Coffin, supra note 10, at 18. In re Winship, 397 U.S at 384-85. Barenblatt v. United States, 360 U.S. 109, 143-44 (1959) (Black, J., dissenting). SCHMIDT ARTICLE FINAL MACRO FINAL FINAL (011409) 2008] TI ME F OR A N E W D UE PRO CES S TES T 1/14/2009 4:58 PM 305 extensively teach students how to research the law. Law students become lawyers and lawyers become judges who decide due process cases. Adopting a “law of the land” due process test would allow these judges to decide due process case by using the research skills they are trained to use, as opposed to dusting off that imaginary Mathews scale.