draft of article for The International Encyclopedia of Ethics (Wiley-Blackwell) comments on content or style very welcome matthew.chrisman@ed.ac.uk EMOTIVISM 2667 words As a metaethical theory (see METAETHICS) about the meaning of ethical words, emotivism is typically seen as a form of non-cognitivism (see NON-COGNITIVISM) because it holds that ethical words and statements have a distinctive kind of emotive meaning, which distinguishes them from other words and statements, whose meaning is purely cognitive or descriptive. The theory had its heyday in the 1940s and 1950s, but traces back at least to Ogden and Richards (1923) and Russell (1935/1961) and receives its fullest treatment in Ayer (1936/1946) (see AYER, A. J.) and, initially independently, Stevenson (1937, 1944) (see STEVENSON, C. L.). Few philosophers today would call themselves emotivists, yet one can find more contemporary descendants in prescriptivism (see PRESCRIPTIVISM), expressivism, quasi-realism (see QUASI-REALISM). Ayer and Stevenson had different theoretical motivations for endorsing emotivism, and their respective versions of the theory are importantly different. For Ayer, the question of the meaning of ethical terms was important because it represented a potentially fatal objection to the version of verificationism he defends in his seminal 1936 book, Language, Truth and Logic. According to this, any synthetic statement, i.e. statement where the predicate is not contained in the concepts expressed by the subject, means what it does in virtue of what would count as verifying the statement empirically. This view helps Ayer to dismiss many puzzles of traditional metaphysics as mere “pseudo-problems”. These are puzzles about things like the existence of an external world, the fundamental nature of substance, or the possibility of free will. Ayer argued that these puzzles involve synthetic statements that are not empirically verifiable; and because of this, his verificationism allowed him to hold that these statements are (perhaps covertly or non-obviously) meaningless. The potentially fatal objection to this position is that ethical statements also seem to be synthetic claims that are not empirically verifiable. Yet ethical claims don’t seem to be meaningless, ethical puzzles don’t seem to be mere pseudo-problems. Ayer’s emotivist answer to this objection has two stages. At the first stage, he distinguishes between two uses of what are commonly thought to be ethical words, such as ‘right, ‘wrong’, etc. He suggests that, on one use of these words, they are used to make statements about what is acceptable or unacceptable to the moral sense of a particular community. As such, they are descriptive, and the claims they are used to make are sociological and so, in principle, empirically verifiable. On another use of these words, however, he holds that these words are used as “normative ethical symbols”, and here the objection has some bite, since the statements they are used to make do not seem to be empirically verifiable but they nonetheless seem to be synthetic and meaningful. At the second stage of Ayer’s response, he argues that while it’s quite right that his theory implies that normative ethical symbols have no factual meaning, that doesn’t preclude their having emotive meaning. According to him, the emotive meaning of words is a matter of “the different feelings they are ordinarily taken to express, and also the different responses which they are calculated to provoke”(1936/1946: 108). If Ayer is right, this means that the impression we have that synthetic ethical statements are meaningful can be explained in a way that is consistent with verificationism. Either these statements are descriptive claims about the moral sense of a particular community, in which case they have factual meaning even on his version of verificationism, or they are normative ethical statements, in which case they have no factual meaning but instead emotive meaning. That is, they are used and understood to express and provoke certain emotions, feelings, or sentiments, rather than to describe anything in the world. Ayer articulates several striking corollaries to his view about the meaning of ethical words and statements. First (and most famously), Ayer claims that because normative ethical statements are the expressions of feeling, “they do not come under the category of truth and falsehood”(108). In contemporary jargon, they are not truth-apt (see noncognitivism). Second, his emotivist view is different from the subjectivist view that ethical words are used to make factual statements about their authors’ state of mind (see SUBJECTIVISM, ETHICAL). However, third, it seems to face a similar objection to subjectivism; it makes moral disagreement look senseless. In response, Ayer argued that moral disagreement is senseless, unless it proceeds on the assumption of shared values, in which case it’s really a factual disagreement either about what the assumed values dictate or about the nonethical facts of a particular case. Fourth (and perhaps most implausibly), Ayer concludes that ethical philosophy consists in nothing more than noting that ethical words have no factual meaning, and the further task of describing the different feelings they are used to express is a matter for psychology. In contrast to Ayer, Stevenson was not motivated by a need to deflect an objection to verificationism but rather by commitment to a pragmatist or use-theoretic methodology in the philosophy of language. That is, he viewed language as first and foremost a set of instruments or tools that we use for various purposes. To explain the meaning of a word or statement, on this approach, is to explain how it is properly used or what purpose it can be properly used to pursue. In light of this, Stevenson suggests three broad desiderata on an account of the meaning of the word ‘good’ at least in its moral sense. First, it must make disagreements about whether something is good intelligible. Second, it must explain why ‘good’ has what he calls “magnetism” (1937: 16), which is the idea that if one recognizes that something is good one has ipso facto acquired a stronger tendency to act in its favor (see INTERNALISM, MOTIVATIONAL). Third, it must not treat goodness as verifiable solely by the scientific method. (Here, he appeals to Moore’s open-question argument (see MOORE, G. E., OPEN QUESTION ARGUMENT). A kind of theory which would go some way towards meeting the second desideratum is what Stevenson called “interest theories” which hold that statements about what is good are descriptions of the interests of a particular group or person (see subjectivism, ethical, RELATIVISM, MORAL). He claims that there is some element of description of interests in many ethical statements, but he thinks their core use is not to “indicate facts, but to create influence” (18). It is because of the interest theories failure to recognize this that they cannot meet Stevenson’s first and third desiderata. His emotivist strategy for doing better begins, in essence, with a sociological observation. He notes that a typical ethical statement, such as “Charity is good”, “has a quasi-imperative force which, operating through suggestion, and intensified by your tone of voice, readily permits you to begin to influence, to modify, [one’s] interests” (19). The idea is that, although one probably wouldn’t use this statement unless one favored charity or was speaking with a group which favored charity, one doesn’t fully grasp its meaning unless one appreciates that its primary use is to influence and modify interests not merely (or perhaps even at all) to describe them. To capture this distinction, Stevenson distinguishes descriptive uses of language from what he calls “dynamic” uses of language. The descriptive use of language is to record, clarify, and communicate beliefs. The dynamic use of language is to vent feelings, create moods, and incite people to action. He recognizes that most uses of language will involve some of both. For example, the statement “I want you to close the door” is plausibly thought to describe the speaker’s desire but also to get the audience to do something. So, the distinction is a theoretical idealization. However, in Stevenson’s view, a proper pragmatist theory of meaning will need to be sensitive to both aspects, and in some cases the dynamic aspect will dominate to the extent that one will not count as understanding the meaning of a claim without appreciating its dynamic penumbra to some extent. Stevenson doesn’t define “meaning” in such a way that the meaning of a sentence varies with dynamic use, since that would imply that, in each new situation where different dynamic purposes prevail, the sentence changes its meaning. As he recognizes, the notion of “linguistic meaning” is only useful if it is relatively stable across different situations of the use of a sentence. Because of this, Stevenson defines the notion of “emotive meaning” as something like the stable core of the dynamic meaning of a word. He writes, somewhat vaguely, “The emotive meaning of a word is a tendency of a word, arising through the history of its usage, to produce (result from) affective responses in people. It is the immediate aura of feeling which hovers about a word” (23). For example, the terms “Old Maid” and “Elderly Spinster” refer to the same kind of person, but, in Stevenson’s view, they differ in meaning and this is because they differ in their emotive meaning, i.e. their tendency, arising through the history of usage, to produce (and result from) affective responses in people. Stevenson uses this notion of emotive meaning to articulate his emotivist theory of the meaning of ethical terms such as ‘good’. To this end, he suggests, as a first approximation, that “X is good” means roughly the same as “We like X” when this latter sentence is used not to record, clarify, and communicate beliefs but to vent feelings, create moods, and incite people to action. He gives the example of a mother who says to her children, “We all like to be neat” as part of a campaign to get them to pick up after themselves. It may be quite clear that the children don’t really like to be neat, but the emotive statement is nonetheless apt. Indeed it seems to be just as apt as the statement “Being neat is good.” Generalizing this idea leads to the view that while ethical statements may have truthconditions, their primary use is not to assert these conditions to be satisfied or to express a belief that they are satisfied but rather to do something else that involves expressing feelings in an attempt to incite action. Insofar as one follows a pragmatist or use-theorist in accounting for the meaning of a statement by appeal to its correct use, one will take this fact about ethical statements to indicate an important difference with descriptive statements. This is the essence of Stevenson’s emotivism. Admittedly, in light of later developments in metaethics (see especially non-cognitivism) it is initially unclear whether Stevenson means to be asserting a hybrid view according to which ethical statements have both descriptive and emotive meaning where the latter is more important or a pure non-cognitivist view according to which ethical statements do not assert anything but deploy a relativistic content to purely emotive effect. In later work (1963: 210-214), Stevenson clarifies his position as the latter. In any case, he argues that his emotivism does better than interest theories at his three broad desiderata on an account of the meaning of ‘good’. First, it can make sense of the intelligibility of disagreement in judgments about what is good. Stevenson conceives of this not as a dispute about who is interested in what, or as a dispute about any factual matter, but rather as a dispute in interests themselves. Second, it can make sense of the “magnetism” of statements about what’s good. For, if these statements are meant to vent feelings, create moods, and incite people to action, then it should be unsurprising that they bear close connection to motivation to action. Finally, Stevenson’s emotivism does not treat statements about what is good as verifiable by the empirical method alone. This is because they are not seen as primarily expressing beliefs, which could be verified by the empirical method alone, but rather some admixture of affective states such as feelings, emotions, interests, etc. Although their motivations for the view are different and the exact articulations of the view differ in key respects, arguably Ayer’s and Stevenson’s versions of emotivism are similar enough to view them as versions of one theory. In any case, theirs is the theory that philosophers typically refer to as “Emotivism.” The fact that they reached their versions of this theory independently and from different theoretical backgrounds in the philosophy of language (verificationism and pragmatism) has perhaps led to lasting sympathy in some quarters, even where these theoretical backgrounds have been called into question. However, the view is widely viewed as deeply flawed in at least two respects. First, its rejection of the truth-aptness of ethical statements is a strong affront to ordinary usage. It’s quite common to say things like “It’s true that torture is evil” or, in response to an ethical statement one disagrees with, “No, that’s false.” This is inconsistent with emotivism. And this inconsistency with aspects of ordinary ethical discourse is only amplified by the fact that it’s quite common to use other expressions which imply the truth-aptness of ethical statements. For example, we say things like “I believe that democracy is good” and “She knows that what she did was wrong”; and believing implies taking to be true, and knowing implies truth. Emotivists may escape this problem by distinguishing between loose and strict senses of ‘true’, ‘believes’, and ‘knows’, but it is doubtful that this is a fully satisfactory rejoinder. Some expressivist heirs to emotivism (especially quasi-realists) argue that this problem can be escaped by reexamining the assumptions in the theory of truth which led emotivists to deny the truth-aptness of ethical statements. The second problem is more technical and influential in metaethics. This is the objection reached independently by Geach (1965) and Searle (1962), which is widely referred to as the “Frege-Geach Problem” (see FREGE-GEACH OBJECTION). There is some debate about the exact nature of the problem (consult the cross-referenced entry for more details), but the core issue has to do with the prospects for extending the emotivist theory of the meaning of ethical words as they appear in logically simple statements to a fuller account which accommodates their embedding in logically complex statements. For example, although the emotivist theory sketched above gives a relatively clear account of the meaning of “Tormenting the cat is wrong”, it’s far from clear what it would say about the meaning of the statement “If tormenting the cat is wrong, then getting your little brother to torment the cat is also wrong.” It’s not implausible to think that the bare ethical statement expresses a negative emotion or feeling about actions of tormenting the cat, in at least some sense. However, it’s highly implausible that the conditionalized statement expresses any particular emotion or feeling about actions of tormenting the cat or actions of getting one’s little brother to torment the cat. But the conditionalized statement seems to be an ethical statement, and so, according to emotivism, its meaning should be a matter of it’s expressing an emotion or feeling of some sort. Moreover, and more importantly, it’s a requirement of any plausible semantics that the meaning of the antecedent of the conditional (“Tormenting the cat is wrong”) have something systematically in common (what’s often called its “semantic content”) with the meaning of this statement when used to make a bare ethical statement. Although emotivism has been largely abandoned in contemporary metaethical debate, it has inspired a number of similar positions (mentioned above). This is probably because of the important advance emotivism makes over subjectivist theories. This comes down to the fact that, as Ayer writes, “…even if the assertion that one has a certain feeling always involves the expression of that feeling, the expression of a feeling assuredly does not always involve the assertion that one has it. And this is the important point to grasp in considering the distinction between our theory [emotivism] and the ordinary subjectivist theory. For whereas the subjectivist holds that ethical statements actually assert the existence of certain feelings, we hold that ethical statements are expressions…of feelings which do not necessarily involve any assertions.(op. cit: 109-10). SEE ALSO: Metaethics; Non-Cognitivism; Ayer, A. J.; Stevenson, C. L.; Prescriptivism; Quasi-Realism; Subjectivism, Ethical; Internalism, Motivational; Moore, G. E.; Open Question Argument; Relativism, Moral; Frege-Geach Objection References Ayer, A. J. 1936/1946. Language, Truth and Logic, first edition 1936, second edition 1946. London: V. Gollancz ltd. Geach, P. T. 1965. 'Assertion', The Philosophical Review 74: 449-465. Ogden, C. K. and Richards, I. A. 1923. The Meaning of Meaning: A Study of the Influence of Language upon Thought and of the Science of Symbolism. New York: Harcourt, Brace & World, Inc. Russell, Bertrand 1935/1961. Religion and Science, first edition 1935, reprinted 1961. New York: Oxford University Press. Searle, John 1962. 'Meaning and Speech Acts', The Philosophical Review 71: 423-432. Stevenson, C. L. 1937. 'Emotive Meaning of Ethical Terms', Mind 46: 14-31. Stevenson, C. L. 1944. Ethics and Language, New Haven and London: Yale University Press. Stevenson, C. L. 1963. Facts and Values, New Haven: Yale University Press. Further Reading Blackburn, Simon 1984. Spreading the Word, ch. 5-6. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Darwall, S, Gibbard, A., & Railton, P. “Towards Fin de siècle Ethics: Some Trends”, in Moral Discourse and Practice, Oxford: Oxford University Press. Finlay, Steve 2005. ‘Emotive Theory of Ethics,’ Encyclopedia of Philosophy, second edition (Donald M. Borchert, ed.). New York: MacMillan, 2005 Gibbard, Alan 1990. Wise Choices, Apt Feelings. Cambridge: Harvard University Press. Smith, Michael 1995. The Moral Problem, ch. 2. Oxford: Blackwell. van Roojen, Mark, 2009. "Moral Cognitivism vs. Non-Cognitivism", The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Fall 2009 Edition), Edward N. Zalta (ed.), URL = <http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/fall2009/entries/moral-cognitivism/>.