Paper for the 2015 Philosophy of Management Conference David Silver Chair in Business and Professional Ethics, and Director W. Maurice Young Centre for Applied Ethics The University of British Columbia david.silver@ubc.ca ethics.ubc.ca Paper Title: Tax Ethics and Corporate Inversions Track submission: Philosophy of Management, Ethics and Economics, or Divers I. Introduction The recent merger between the U.S. fast-food giant Burger King and the Canadian coffee and donut chain Tim Horton’s renews questions concerning the ethics surrounding the paying of taxes by corporations. By headquartering the merged company in Canada, the company will save hundreds of millions of dollars in U.S. taxes. From another point of view, the U.S. Treasury will be deprived of several hundred million dollars due to a largely tax-motivated corporate merger. This merger is both legal and highly profitable. In this paper I explore the idea that this tax-motivated merger is nonetheless morally wrong. I begin noting that governments are morally necessary, and that in order to properly function, they require an effective scheme for taxation. All members of society thus have an obligation to comply with a fair tax system. This raises the question of what a “fair” tax system looks like, and what counts as “compliance”. I maintain that what counts as a fair tax system is a matter about which reasonable people may disagree, and that the resolution of this matter should be left to 2 a democratic system in which the interests of all citizens are treated equitably. It is not up to each corporation, or corporate managers to determine what is a fair system. Second, I maintain that when possible compliance with a tax code requires that taxpayers honor the spirit, and not just the letter of the code. It is not always possible, however, to follow the spirit of the tax code. This is because tax codes are based on presumptions about economic transactions that can cease to be true. For example, a historic premise of taxation has been that economic activity is location-bound. The emergence of intellectual property, however, has disrupted this assumption. By holding intellectual property in a low-tax jurisdiction, and charging for the use of the intellectual property, a company can transfer substantial profits away from high-tax jurisdictions. There are certain policy responses that jurisdictions can make in response to the upending of presumptions within their tax codes. They can lower their taxes to be competitive with low-tax jurisdictions, or they can change the tax code to attempt to tax a “fair share” of the economic activity. Both responses are problematic. Lowering taxes is problematic because it introduces a race to the bottom in terms of corporate taxation. Changing the tax code is usually a good idea but will often be ineffective when there is a widespread business culture that seeks all legal means to minimize paying taxes. This includes discovering loopholes, and lobbying against more effective regulations. I maintain that the inadequacy of these policy responses is rooted in the mistaken idea that corporations have no social responsibilities with respect to taxation other than compliance with the letter of the law. Instead, I argue that corporations have 3 an obligation to not take advantage of failures of the tax code; and, they have a positive obligation to work with tax authorities to fix these failures. II. The Business Purpose Test One response to the view I have just put forward is that businesses are morally free—or even morally required—to perform a tax-saving corporate inversion provided that there is some business purpose for doing so other than the avoidance of tax. This response is due to a bedrock feature of American tax law called the business purpose doctrine. It holds that a tax-sheltering transaction must have some legitimate business purpose other than the avoidance of taxes; otherwise it is disallowed for tax purposes as a ‘sham’ or ‘abusive’ transaction. The business purpose doctrine traces its origins to the 1934 case Helvering v. Gregory in which Judge Learned Hand ruled that tax-motivated transactions must be in accord with both the letter and the spirit of the tax code.1 Ironically, a quote from Hand’s opinion has become a bit of sacred text among promoters of various tax shelters and can be found widely on websites of companies marketing them. It states that: a transaction, otherwise within an exception of the tax law, does not lose its immunity, because it is actuated by a desire to avoid, or, if one choose, to evade, taxation. Any one may so arrange his affairs that his taxes shall be as low as possible; he is not bound to choose that pattern which will best pay the Treasury; there is not even a patriotic duty to increase one's taxes. Although this quote is typically offered as a defense of attempts to get around the spirit of the law this is exactly contrary to what Hand meant by writing it. All that the quote 1 69 F.2d 809 (2nd Cir. 1934) 4 states is that if a transaction is motivated by a desire to avoid taxes this does not as such make the transaction illegal, unpatriotic or immoral. It does not say that any transaction which is so motivated is legal, patriotic or moral.2 His point was that it wasn’t wrong to seek to lower one’s taxes so long as one was in conformance with the spirit of the law; however in no way did he endorse trying to lower one’s taxes by violating the spirit of the law. I will add that it comes as little surprise that those who have a disregard for the spirit and fairness of the law are similarly inclined to take Hand’s words out of context and use them in a way opposite to their intended meaning. The development of the business purpose doctrine within American tax law stands in contrast to a contemporaneous development in Britain. Shortly after the United States Supreme Court affirmed the Helvering decision the British House of Lords faced a similar set of facts in the Duke of Westminster Case. In that case the Duke of Westminster devised a scheme in which he deducted from his taxable income the wages he was paying to his servants. Normally, this would not be allowed; however, British law did allow deductions for the payments of annuities. Westminster’s scheme was to agree with his servants that he would pay them via an annuity instead of a regular salary for a period of seven years; he thereby claimed the annuity payments as a tax deduction. During that time the servants would be doing their 2 In a later case Judge Hand made the general case for a purposivist approach to the law: Of course it is true that the words used, even in their literal sense, are the primary, and ordinarily the most reliable, source of interpreting the meaning of any writing: be it a statute, a contract, or anything else. But it is one of the surest indexes of a mature and developed jurisprudence not to make a fortress out of the dictionary; but to remember that statutes always have some purpose or object to accomplish, whose sympathetic and imaginative discovery is the surest guide to their meaning. [Cabell v. Markham, 148 F.2d 737, 739 (2d Cir.), aff'd, 326 U.S. 404 (1945)] 5 normal duties even though the agreement stipulated that the annuity payments were technically not in exchange for them.3 The case was decided in favor of Westminster and it provided the key legal precedent for a “narrow, literal, pro-taxpayer approach which had dominated British and Commonwealth tax-avoidance law until the 1960s.”4 In the decision Lord Tomlin opined that "Every man is entitled, if he can, to order his affairs so that the tax attaching under the appropriate Acts is less than it otherwise would be". In doing so he echoed Lord Clyde’s lines from an earlier case: No man in this country is under the smallest obligation, moral or other, so to arrange his legal relations to his business or to his property as to enable the Inland Revenue to put the largest possible shovel into his stores. The Inland Revenue is not slow - and quite rightly - to take every advantage which is open to it under the taxing statutes for the purpose of depleting the taxpayer's pocket. And the taxpayer is, in like manner, entitled to be astute to prevent, so far as he honestly can, the depletion of his means by the Revenue.5 Unlike Hand’s statement these quotes really do support the idea that it is morally and legally permissible to engage in tax avoision. [Leo Katz’ term for evading the spirit of the law while adhering to its letter]. They portray tax payment and enforcement as an adversarial if not outright antagonistic process between the taxpayer and the tax collector. Tomlin argued that the approach to the law which the American courts had adopted which recognized the legal standing of the spirit of the law was wrong because it substituted “‘the incertain and crooked cord of discretion’ for the ‘golden and straight 3 I follow the description of the case from Likhovski 15. 4 (Likhovski, 14 cite) 5Ayrshire Pullman Motor Services & Ritchie v CIR ((1929) 14 TC 754) 6 metwand of the law’”. In so doing he was invoking the words of a seventeenth-century judicial opinion by Sir Edward Coke. Tomlin’s idea is that a literal, non-contextual reading of the law is clearer and fairer than a reading of the law which invites judges to use their discretion to discern a purpose to the law. This however is a distortion of the original use of the Coke’s words in favor of the “golden and straight metwand”. Coke was arguing that the law was to be judged by professional jurists (i.e. the golden and straight metwand) rather than by the legally untrained king (i.e. the incertain and crooked cord of discretion).6 He was thus not arguing against judges using informed judgment about the spirit of the law; rather, he was arguing against royal amateurs attempting to decide difficult matters of law, and as such was an early and brave defender of an independent and professional judiciary. Tomlin’s argument has another deep flaw aside from its misappropriation of Coke’s words. An approach to the law which takes into account its purpose or spirit can be “golden and straight” rather than “incertain and crooked” because it is often quite clear to a competent judge what the spirit of a given law is. These differing American and British legal decisions demonstrate the opposing ways that judges can interpret the relationship between the letter and the spirit of the tax code. This can be seen further in the ongoing development of the business purpose doctrine within the United States. While American courts have generally come to accept the business purpose doctrine this has not always guaranteed a continual close connection between the letter 6 Prohibitions del Roy (1607) Michaelmas Term, 5 James I. In Conference Before the King. First Published in the Reports, volume 12, page 63. [see p. 478-481 of text.] 7 and the spirit of the tax code. This is because there are many transactions which have a non-tax related business purpose but which violate the spirit of the underlying tax code. Indeed, it is often quite easy to come up with some non-tax-related business purpose for a tax-motivated transaction. Consider Accenture’s explanation for why it incorporated in the tax-haven country of Bermuda.7 Its official story was that its European and Asian partners could not stand its being headquartered in the United States, and its American partners did not want to be headquartered in an Asian or European capital. So according to Accenture lobbyist (and former Congressman) Robert Livingston “they picked a nice island, Bermuda.”8 As he put it, tax avoidance was merely a “minor factor”. While Livingston’s claims do not meet the laugh test this is beside the point here. There was at least some business purpose to incorporating in Bermuda other than the avoidance of tax and this is all that is required to formally satisfy the business purpose doctrine. Whether a court will accept a formal satisfaction of the business purpose test is a matter of continuing development within American tax law. Some judges give wide latitude as to what counts as a legitimate non-tax business purpose while others are inclined to follow Hand’s lead in examining transactions according to whether they are in accordance with the spirit of the tax code. 7 See this article in the American Prospect 8 Livingston was a former congressman from Louisiana who had nearly become Speaker of the House. Accenture had also hired “Bush family confidant Charlie Black. . .former senator Dennis DeConcini (DAriz.) and Reagan White House chief of staff Kenneth Duberstein” in their effort to turn back legislation which penalized Accenture for incorporating in a tax-haven country. The Washington Post, 9/24/2002. “Tax-Haven Firms Lobbying Hard Against Curbs” by Jonathan Weisman. 8 This highlights the fact that the relationship between the spirit of the law and how the law is interpreted by judges is continually subject to change. This in turn helps explain the push by the business community to get judges appointed who are likely to interpret the tax code in a way which allows businesses to get around its spirit. Regardless of the stance judges take towards the spirit of the tax code (and thus regardless of the actual state of the law) textualism has become the dominant legal philosophy of American tax practitioners. This is not only because it allows them to seek ways to formally satisfy the business purpose doctrine while violating its spirit. Given a textualist approach a lawyer can argue that the judicially-originated business purpose doctrine itself is legally suspect. A textualist might thus argue that it and any other judicially-originated doctrine meant to keep the letter of the law in accord with its spirit, “are the product of judicial activism and either should no longer be followed, or at a minimum should not be extended into new areas of the law.”9 This complaint of judicial activism is without merit. I have argued elsewhere that it is wrong for judges to substitute their own judgments about constitutional principles over the reasonably considered, but contrary judgments of elected legislatures. This is wrong because it is anti-democratic. It is hardly anti-democratic, though, for a judge to rule in a way that preserves the integrity of the democratically intended spirit of a law. The implausibility of textualism as either a descriptive or normative theory of the law raises issues of ethics on the part of accountants and lawyers who appeal to it and the businesspeople who seek out their advice. While it is the role of lawyers to serve as 9 (p. 2-3 of online version) “Textualism and Tax Shelters” Noel B. Cunningham James R. Repetti 9 advocates for their clients they also have duties which constrain their advocacy. For example, a lawyer may not advise a client to lie on the witness stand even if this would be in the client’s best interest. Similarly, lawyers have an obligation to render opinions on whether transactions will survive a legal challenge only if they have real grounds for saying so. Since textualism is not generally accepted by tax judges it is wrong for lawyers to opine as if this were the case. Businesspeople have a correlative duty not to rely on the tax advice of morally incompetent lawyers and accountants. It is thus not sufficient to hire a well-regarded lawyer when his reputation is based on a willingness to serve the interests of clients at the expense of his moral obligations. This means that corporate managers may not simply shop within the reputable legal community until they find the legal opinion they desire. Instead, they must evaluate the moral character of the lawyer—and by this I refer to his character insofar as he respects the letter and the spirit of the law. When businesspeople default on this obligation and simply find the lawyer or accountant with the most permissive reading of the law they set up a powerful incentive which can lead to the corruption of previously upright accounting and law firms. Accountants and lawyers have strong standards of professional ethics but are also in business. If the largest and most reputable corporations will only hire the most permissive accountants and lawyers who happen to have a good reputation, then soon more and more of those with a good reputation will deserve it less and less. It is my fear that this process is already well underway. This is easier to see in the case of accounting since just a few firms dominate the market for large corporate 10 clients. Arthur Andersen’s facilitation of several of the Enron-era scandals and its subsequent demise revealed a culture that had strayed far from the ideals of accounting. This is not to say, of course, that all the employees and partners of Andersen were morally corrupt. Indeed, it is quite a misfortune to be a morally upright professional in an organization with a corrupted culture. III. The Ethics of Corporate Inversions This discussion of the business purpose test shows that a corporate inversion is not morally acceptable simply because there is some business purpose for doing so other than the avoidance of tax. Going further, I propose that a tax-motivated transaction is wrong when its purpose is to remove business activity from the taxing jurisdiction of the state in which the activity occurs. Let me qualify this slightly. I am not saying here that it is wrong to move a business out of a given jurisdiction for tax purposes. For example, it may be morally permissible for a business to physically relocate to another state because of differential tax regimes. What I am saying here is that it is wrong to set up legal and accounting structures which remove a business activity from the taxing authority of the jurisdiction in which it occurs. The corporate inversion maneuver is a prime example. There is another tax maneuver which it is combined with that is equally wrong. This involves the use of intellectual property to transfer income from high-tax jurisdictions to low-tax ones. In this maneuver a company sets up a subsidiary in a tax-haven country and transfers key 11 intellectual property, including the brand name, to it. (Whether it does so at an armslength price is another matter). The subsidiary can then charge the parent company for the use of the intellectual property. This transfers income out of a high income country to the tax-haven. So for example, a company can sell a computer worth several thousand dollars in the United States; however, the U.S. company pays a royalty to its own subsidiary in the tax-haven and thus be assured of making little or no profit. 10 Eventually, this expatriated income is supposed to be returned and taxed in the US. The reality is that the income will only be repatriated for a fraction of the statutory rate. This is due, among other things, to patiently waiting for (and helping create) a once-in-a-generation “tax holiday” which allows companies to repatriate income at minuscule rates.11 It is completely trivial to come up with a non-tax related business purpose for setting up a subsidiary to hold and manage intellectual property.12 Nevertheless, I submit that it is wrong to do so as a strategy for removing business activity from the taxing authority of the jurisdiction in which it occurs. It is also wrong for the tax-haven state to engage in “tax poaching” in which it sets up a legal structure in which businesses can remove themselves from the taxing authority of the state in which it conducts business activity. They can do this by allowing companies to incorporate in the tax-haven, but pay vastly lower amounts of tax. It is 10 http://www.nytimes.com/2013/05/21/business/apple-avoided-billions-in-taxes-congressionalpanelsays. html?pagewanted=2&hp 11 “As companies’ earnings have accumulated offshore, many executives have been pushing more aggressively for a tax holiday that would allow them to bring back funds at lower tax rates.” 12 Apple executives disputed the characterization of Apple Operations International. “A.O.I. performs important business functions that facilitate and enhance Apple’s success in international markets,” the testimony states. “It is not a shell company.” 12 wrong for businesses to take advantage of tax-poaching opportunities both because it is wrong to exempt themselves from legitimate taxing authority, and because it is wrong to participate in the tax-haven’s poaching scheme. Apple Computer has recently demonstrated a heightened form of these maneuvers. Ireland has set up a tax-poaching scheme in which it permits companies to pay as little as 2% in corporate tax. A quirk (feature?) of Irish tax law, however, allows Apple to exempt some of its income from all taxation. While the US and other jurisdictions base taxing residency on where a company is incorporated, Ireland bases it on where they are managed and controlled. So, Apple’s intellectual property holding company that is incorporated in Ireland, but managed in California is a tax resident of nowhere. It produces what is dryly referred to as “ocean income”. The net effects are dramatic for just this one company: Apple Operations International has not filed a tax return in Ireland, the United States or any other country over the last five years. It had income of $30 billion between 2009 and 2012. By shuttling revenue between international subsidiaries, Apple was able largely to sidestep paying taxes. This situation is wrong for all the reasons I mention above; and it is additionally wrong as it shifts the national tax burden from businesses to wage earners. While this is not necessarily wrong in itself, it is wrong for companies to unilaterally make this policy change. IV. Business attitudes toward government and taxation There are many lines of reply available here. But let me anticipate one: the proper relationship between businesses and taxing authorities is adversarial—it is the 13 job of a business to push the limits of what it can get away with, and the job of governments to define and enforce limits. I think this is a seriously wrong understanding of the appropriate relationship between business and government. Businesses ought not to see themselves in an antagonistic relationship with legitimate governments, such as liberal democracies; rather, businesses should see the government as an important partner that creates the social conditions for fair and effective markets. As Judge Hand realized, this partnership does not require a company to pay any more than its moral minimum in taxes. But, businesses should not try to minimize their taxes by removing business activity from the taxing authority of the jurisdiction in which it takes place; and this is precisely what taxmotivated corporate inversions do. An adversarial view of taxation is not just unfair to those who must pay a higher share of taxes, or receive less of the benefits of government spending. It rejects the legitimacy of the state to tax business activity within its jurisdiction, at least with respect to business income. This may reflect a hostility to democracy itself. This is evident enough in the Westminster case where a Duke is judged by the House of Lords. They displayed a class solidarity against those who would dare threaten the privileges of the nobility. That particular class system may be all but extinct; however, the adversarial attitude towards taxation of the contemporary business community may reflect a class interest of a modern-day elite. The business leaders—both entrepreneurs and managers—may see themselves as the meritocratic lords of today. Their business success should be 14 celebrated—and not punished through taxation. This is not an anti-tax or antigovernment position. It is against governments that burden the people who deserve the fruits of their success.. This is all highly speculative, of course; but regardless of the psychology underlying business’ adversarial attitude towards governments and their taxing authority, it is a morally illegitimate attitude to hold. Taxes are morally necessary, and we all have an obligation to comply with a fair scheme of taxation. Businesses must not seek ways of avoiding taxation altogether; rather, they can work with governments to improve the efficiency and fairness of tax codes, while at the same time paying their fair share of taxes. Businesses can also show leadership by de-normalizing the adversarial stance to government and taxation. Finally, businesses can turn their limited managerial attention away from tax avoidance strategies, and towards creating value for all their stakeholders.