A JURISPRUDENTIAL ANALYSIS OF CIVIL DISOBEDIENCE IN SOUTH AFRICA by CHRISTOFFEL HENDRIK HEYNS MA LLB (Pret) LLM (Yale) Thesis submitted for the degree Doctor of Philosophy Faculty of Law University of the Witwatersrand Supervisor: Professor J D van der Vyver B Com LLB BA Honns (PU for CHE) LLD (Pret) Dip1 Int'1 s Comp L Hum Rts (Int'1 Inst Hum Rts, Strasbourg) Pretoria, October 1991 ACKNOWLEDGMENTS I wish to thank the following people and institutions for their support in writing this thesis: - The Human Sciences Research Council, which provided financial assistance. - My philosophy and law teachers at the University of Pretoria and Yale Law School, who stirred and shaped my thoughts over the years. - My colleagues in the Faculty of Law, University of Pretoria, and especially my departmental colleagues, who have contributed to the eventual product. I am particularly grateful to Johann van der Westhuizen, for stimulating discussions, and Isabeau de Meyer, who did most of the typing, as well as the assistants at the Centre for Human Rights Studies, and especially Helen Fourie, Isiah Methlape, Ellen Nicol and Villiers Terblanche, who helped with the administrative aspects. The personnel at the Merensky Library also provided a friendly and efficient service. - Professor J D van der Vyver, my supervisor, who, with his encyclopedic knowledge of law, philosophy and politics, opened up new avenues of research and saved me from more mistakes than I care to remember, while still allowing me to take my own chances. Ek wi1 ook my familie bedank: my pa, vir sy voorbeeld van kritiese betrokkenheid, asook my vrou, kinders, ma, broers en skoonma, vir die ryk en verweefde lewensomstandighede waarin iets soos die voltooiing van ‘n proefskrif betekenis het. Aan hulle, en danksy hulle, kan ek nou se: "Dit is klaar!" Christof Heyns CONTENTS ACKNOWLEDGMENTS 2 CHAPTER ONE: INTRODUCTION 12 CHAPTER TWO: DEFINING CIVIL DISOBEDIENCE: ITS ELEMENTS AND MANIFESTATIONS 19 I. 22 THE ELEMENTS OF CIVIL DISOBEDIENCE A. ILLEGALITY 22 B. NON-VIOLENCE 31 C. OPENNESS 38 D. MOTIVATED BY CONVICTION 40 E. POLITICAL ACT 42 II. COMBINATIONS OF THE DIFFERENT TYPES OF CIVIL DISOBEDIENCE 45 III. CAN CIVIL DISOBEDIENCE HAVE REVOLUTIONARY OBJECTIVES? 47 IV. DIRECT AND INDIRECT CIVIL DISOBEDIENCE 49 A. CONSIDERATIONS RELATING TO THE LAWS OBJECTED AGAINST 49 B. CONSIDERATIONS RELATING TO THE TARGET OF THE RESISTANCE 50 V. THE TERM "CONSCIENTIOUS OBJECTION" VI. SCHEMATIC SUMMARY 52 54 CHAPTER THREE: HISTORICAL SURVEY OF THE DEVELOPMENT OF CIVIL DISOBEDIENCE 56 I. 56 THE ORIGINS OF ILLEGAL RESISTANCE TO AUTHORITY II. THE ORIGINS OF CIVIL DISOBEDIENCE 58 A. AN INTERPRETIVE FRAMEWORK FOR THE HISTORY OF CIVIL DISOBEDIENCE 59 B. DEFENSIVE CIVIL DISOBEDIENCE 63 C. INDIVIDUAL, RESULT-ORIENTED CIVIL DISOBEDIENCE 64 D. PLICATION 70 III. A. THE MODERN DEVELOPMENT OF MASS, RESULT-ORIENTED CIVIL DISOBEDIENCE CIVIL DISOBEDIENCE IN SOUTH AFRICA 75 76 (1) Early forerunners of civil disobedience 76 (2) Gandhian civil disobedience in South Africa 78 (a) Indians in South Africa in the late Nineteenth Century 79 (b) Legal resistance 1894 - 1906 83 (c) Illegal resistance 1907 - 1914 95 (i) Phase one: Refusal to register (1) (ii) Phase two: Refusal to register (2) (iii) (iv) (d) (3) 95 97 Phase three: Unsuccessful negotiations 99 Phase four: Satyagraha on a grand scale 103 Evaluation Civil disobedience in South Africa after Gandhi 105 107 (a) Phase one: The period before World War II 108 (b) Phase two: The 1940's 118 (c) Phase three: The Defiance Campaign of the 1950's 124 (i) Prelude to mass civil disobedience (ii) Rationale of the Campaign (iii) (iv) Consequences of the Campaign 132 137 152 - Reaction of the white establishment 152 - Reaction of the black community 158 - International consequences 163 Evaluation of the Defiance Campaign 166 - Civil disobedience in the African context. 167 - Weaknesses in the way in which the Campaign was conducted 167 - Nature of the adversary 168 (v) (vi) (d) The Defiance Campaign 125 Black politics in the wake of the Campaign Phase four: The violent underground struggle starts 169 179 B. (e) Phase five: External and internal resistance 180 (f) Phase six: Prospects of reconciliation and new resistance 186 GANDHIAN CIVIL DISOBEDIENCE IN INDIA (1) Campaigns conducted by Gandhi Phase one: The Non-co-operation Campaign of the 1920’s 190 (b) Phase two: The Salt Tax Campaign 1930 195 (c) Phase three: The “Quit India” Campaign 198 Gandhi's philosophy of Satyagraha 201 (a) The sources of Satyaqraha 203 (b) Central features of Gandhi’s political thought 206 CIVIL DISOBEDIENCE IN THE UNITED STATES OF AMERICA 212 (1) Civil disobedience by native Americans 212 (2) Religious civil disobedience 212 (3) Anti-slavery resistance 213 (4) Henry David Thoreau 214 (5) The Womens’ Rights Movement 216 (6) The Civil Rights Movement 217 (7) D. 189 (a) (2) C. 188 (a) The Montgomery Bus Boycott 1955-1956 218 (b) Little Rock 1957 220 (c) The lunch-counter sit-ins 1960 220 (d) The freedom rides 1961 221 (e) Birmingham 1963 222 (f) The March on Washington 1963 224 (g) The Mississippi Summer Project 1964 224 (h) The Civil Rights Act 1964 224 (i) Martin Luther King 225 The anti-Vietnam protests of the 1960’s SOME OTHER INSTANCES OF MASS, RESULT-ORIENTED CIVIL DISOBEDIENCE CHAPTER FOUR: CIVIL DISOBEDIENCE UNDER THE SOUTH AFRICAN POSITIVE LAW 228 232 235 I. IMPLICATIONS OF THE CRIMINAL LAW FOR CIVIL DISOBEDIENCE 235 A. THE “PRIMARY OFFENCE” 236 B. SECONDARY IMPLICATIONS OF THE CRIMINAL LAW 237 (1) Sentences imposed for crimes of protest (a) Statutory provisions for increased penalties 237 (b) The sentencing policy of the courts 240 (i) The era of white against white conflict (ii) C. 254 (3) Civil disobedience as a substantive crime 254 TERTIARY IMPLICATIONS OF THE CRIMINAL LAW Incitement of civil disobedience 256 257 (a) Incitement to commit any offence 257 (b) Incitement to commit a political offence 258 (c) Proclamations prohibiting the incitement of “natives” 265 Assistance of those engaged in civil disobedience OTHER CRIMES 265 269 (1) Treason 270 (2) Sedition 284 (3) Terrorism 288 (4) Subversion 289 (5) Sabotage 291 (6) Defeating or obstructing the course of justice 291 EXECUTIVE POWERS AND CIVIL DISOBEDIENCE A. 243 Attempt to commit an act of civil disobedience (2) II. The era of black against white conflict 241 (2) (1) D. 237 EXECUTIVE POWERS RELATING TO STATE SECURITY (1) Non-emergency powers (d) Detention (i) (ii) 292 292 292 293 "Banning" of organizations 294 "Banning" of -individuals 294 (iii) (2) "Banning" of meetings Emergency powers 294 295 (e) "Macro emergencies" 295 (f) "Micro emergencies" 296 B. CENSORSHIP AND STATE SECURITY 297 C. EXECUTIVE LENIENCY FOR POLITICAL OFFENDERS 301 III. CIVIL DISOBEDIENCE OF MEMBERS OF THE LEGAL PROFESSION 305 A. THE GENERAL IMPLICATIONS FOR LEGAL PRACTICE OF EARLIER CONVICTIONS 306 B. CONVICTIONS FOR POLITICAL OFFENCES 310 (1) (2) IV. Political crimes in general 311 (g) The era of white against white conflict 311 (h) The era of black against white conflict 313 Civil disobedience CONSCIENTIOUS OBJECTION TO MILITARY SERVICE 315 324 A. THE LEGAL SANCTION OF COMPULSORY MILITARY SERVICE 327 B. ILLEGAL CONSCIENTIOUS OBJECTION 328 C. LEGAL CONSCIENTIOUS OBJECTION 331 D. EVALUATION 340 CHAPTER FIVE: CLASSICAL VIEWS ON POLITICAL AND LEGAL OBLIGATION AND RESISTANCE 343 I. 344 WESTERN POLITICAL THOUGHT A. B. C. THE BIBLE 346 (1) The Old Testament 347 (2) The New Testament 347 GREEK PHILOSOPHY 352 (1) Socrates and Plato 352 (2) Aristotle 358 (3) Stoicism 362 ROMAN JURISPRUDENCE 364 D. GERMANIC JURISPRUDENCE 373 E. AURELIUS AUGUSTINE 374 F. JOHN OF SALISBURY 378 G. THE RE-EMERGENCE OF ROMAN LAW AND THE GLOSSATORS 381 H. THOMAS AQUINAS 383 I. CANON LAW 387 J. PHILIP OF LEYDEN 388 K. BARTOLUS OF SASSOFERRATO 388 L. THE PROTESTANT REFORMATION 392 (1) Martin Luther 393 (2) Jean Calvin 396 (3) The Vindiciae contra tyrannos 401 M. THE REVIVAL OF THOMISM 402 N. JEAN BODIN 404 O. GROTIUS 405 P. THOMAS HOBBES 410 Q. SAMUEL PUFENDORF 416 R. JOHN LOCKE 420 S. ULRICH HUBER 425 T. GERARD NOODT 426 U. CHRISTIAN WOLFF 426 V. JEAN-JACQUES ROUSSEAU 427 W. WILLIAM BLACKSTONE 431 X. IMMANUEL KANT 433 Y. JEREMY BENTHAM 437 Z. GEORG W F HEGEL 438 AA. ANARCHISM 439 (1) William Godwin 441 (2) Pierre-Joseph Proudhon 442 (3) Michael Bakunin 442 (4) Peter Kropotkin 442 (5) Leo Tolstóy 443 BB. MARXISM 443 CC. THE AGE OF REVOLUTIONS 445 DD. THE NATURAL LAW - POSITIVE LAW DEBATE 448 EE. CONTEMPORARY POLITICAL THEORY 451 II. (1) The social contract 452 (2) Utilitarianism 454 (3) The "duty of fair play" 456 (4) The "natural duty to obey the law" 457 (a) The "natural duty to support just institutions" 457 (b) Obedience based on necessity 459 (c) Respect for officials exercising authority 459 (d) An underived obligation to obey the law 460 THE CHRISTIAN CHURCHES IN SOUTH AFRICA 460 A. THE 1914 REBELLION 461 B. APARTHEID 462 III. TRADITIONAL AFRICAN SOCIETIES 471 A. THE "RITUALS OF REBELLION" 474 B. REBELLION AND REVOLUTION 475 IV. CONCLUSION 479 CHAPTER SIX: THE STATE AND CIVIL DISOBEDIENCE 482 I. 482 INTRODUCTION A. THE TERM "DEMOCRACY" 483 B. THE "ORIGINAL POSITION" 486 II. THE RECOGNITION IN PRINCIPLE OF A STRONG RIGHT OF RESISTANCE 488 III. THE CONDITIONS OF LEGITIMATE CIVIL DISOBEDIENCE 502 THE SUBSTANTIVE STANDARD: BASIC HUMAN RIGHTS 504 A. (1) The primary criterion: the boni mores 504 (2) The secondary, alternative criterion: The types of convictions involved 506 (a) Integrity-based civil disobedience 507 (b) Anti-exploitation civil disobedience 509 (c) Policy-based civil disobedience 511 (3) B. C. IV. Application 515 FORMAL CONSIDERATIONS 517 (1) The question whether other reasonable alternatives have been exhausted 517 (2) The extent of political participation 518 (3) Proportionality of means and ends 519 (4) The chances that civil disobedience might worsen the situation 520 (5) State security 520 (6) Approach of the protesters regarding punishment 524 (7) The level of coercion involved 526 (8) Repetition of acts of civil disobedience 526 (9) The question whether or not the protesters are members of a well-established social group 527 CONCLUSION 527 THE LAW AND LEGITIMATE CIVIL DISOBEDIENCE A. THE NECESSITY DEFENCE AND CIVIL DISOBEDIENCE (1) United States law 528 532 533 (a) Relative severity of harm 534 (b) Reasonable alternatives 535 (c) Imminent harm 535 (d) Direct causal relationship 536 (2) South African law (a) Legal interest endangered 538 538 B. (b) Threat commenced or imminent 540 (c) Necessary for the accused to avert the danger 540 (d) Proportionality of means and ends 540 (e) Duty to face the danger 541 CONSTITUTIONAL PROTECTION OF FREEDOM OF SPEECH 542 (1) Civil disobedience as a form of "symbolic speech" 547 (2) Advocacy of civil disobedience 552 CHAPTER SEVEN: CONCLUSION 559 BIBLIOGRAPHY 565 SYNOPSIS 600 SAMEVATTING 602 CHAPTER ONE: INTRODUCTION There is a apartheid, certain but dialectical also civil logic in disobedience the as fact an that not only of mass instrument political mobilization, originated in South Africa. It was here, at the beginning of the century, that a pervasive and perverse system of racial domination gave rise to the emergence of a new and powerful tool of political resistance, when Mohandas Gandhi led the first campaign of mass civil disobedience in history against the South African government. Eventually, civil disobedience would prove itself to be one of the major forces responsible for the demise of apartheid. As the century is drawing to a close, it is dear that mass civil disobedience has become a global phenomenon. It has been widely applied in liberation and civil rights struggles, and to exert leverage in respect of issues as diverse as the environment, the military and nonmilitary use of nuclear power, university policies and the conduct of foreign wars. What is surprising, however, in light of the important role which civil disobedience played in the history of South Africa, is the scant intellectual reflection that this form of protest has generated in its country of origin. In a 1939 essay, Gandhi’s main political rival in South Africa, Jan Smuts, described how Gandhi had achieved "a successful coup" against the South African government with a method that was "novel ... in political warfare". Smuts went on to say: "I think the phenomenon is deserving of careful study." 1 However, virtually no serious attempt has been made to provide a conceptual framework within which civil 2 is evaluated. It disobedience in this in regard South that Africa this can thesis be aims placed to and make a contribution. Political resistance and its concomitant, political obligation, raises fundamental 1 and universal issues. Human J C Smuts "Gandhi's political Archives, J D Pohl Collection 3. 2 life method" reflects University the tension of Pretoria The most notable exceptions in this regard are Du Toit Staatsgesag en burgerlike ongehoorsaamheid; Wink Jesus' third way and Villa-Vicencio Civil disobedience and beyond. The primary focus of all three works, however, is theological. between obedience and disobedience of different demands - mundane and transcendental, personal and social, those emanating from the id and those imposed by the super-ego. All these tensions, however, find their most visible manifestation in the relationship between the citizen and the state. What are the limits of individual autonomy? Does the individual have an obligation to obey the state, and if so what are the nature and limits of that obligation? To whom or what do we owe our most basic loyalty when we are confronted by a conflict between the demands of personal conviction and those of the state? These questions bring one to the intersection of some of the main preoccupations of the human spirit: politics, philosophy, religion and law, and it is in this wider context that civil disobedience has to be seen. What is needed disciplined from discourse the South which will African place perspective civil is a disobedience, multias it manifests itself here, in this bigger context. No single study can of course hope to achieve this. This thesis will attempt to establish the outlines of the relevant wider considerations, but will do so primarily with a view to the jurisprudential perspective in the South African context. The central question is: How should the South African state and more particularly the South African law treat civil disobedience? In addressing this question, however, the ultimate aim is not only to arrive at some conclusions regarding civil disobedience in South Africa, but also to gain a better understanding of civil disobedience as such. In fact, it could be argued that in order to understand the phenomenon of civil disobedience, an understanding of its role in South Africa is indispensable. There can be little doubt that the most developed body of jurisprudence on the topic of civil disobedience can be found in American literature. The method established by Gandhi in South Africa and India was soon taken up in other countries, but nowhere can his legacy be seen more clearly than in the United States of America, where Martin Luther King modeled the Civil Rights Movement on the Gandhian example. This campaign and others prompted a deep and sustained national debate, in which lawyers and philosophers played a leading role. The question should, however, be posed as to the extent to which the circle can be completed - that is, the circle from South Africa to India; from there to the United States and then back to South Africa. Can American jurisprudence provide the necessary insights in understanding and evaluating civil disobedience in South Africa? It will be submitted that in significant respects it can not. American thinking on the subject was developed in a largely democratic society, where the rule of law is respected, and to a significant extent American perspectives are applicable to those conditions only. If South Africa is going to be a thriving democracy where people are to be ruled by the law and by the law only, direct comparisons with the United States might be appropriate. However, realism cautions that for a long time to come our society might still be one in which an ebb and flow of freedom and oppression will prevail. A more open approach to the - issue is needed. A "flexible" theory of civil disobedience must be developed which can be applied to less democratic as well as more democratic societies. In this regard it should be noted that the conventional wisdom that a right to resist exists in an undemocratic society, but not in a democratic setting, might be correct in abstracto, but it has little practical value because it is such a gross oversimplification. It will be argued that democracy entails two elements: universal franchise and the protection of individual rights. Because these elements are often contradictory, no society can be entirely democratic. At the same time it will be very difficult to find a state which is completely undemocratic. The American situation, consequently, represents only one point in this spectrum. A flexible theory of civil disobedience should make allowance for the whole range of possibilities. Any theory of civil disobedience has to address at least two questions: in the first place, what the definition of civil disobedience is, and in the second, under what circumstance civil disobedience can be justified: When does one have "a right to resist" by means of civil disobedience? Before these questions can be considered, however, the term, a "right to resist", requires clarification. A distinction may be drawn between having a "right to resist" in the weak and the strong sense of the word. 3 One has a right to resist in the weak sense when, given one's position, a certain protest action is "the right thing to do" but there is no corresponding duty on one's adversary to recognise and give effect to that right. One might think, for example, that it is "the right thing to do" for a prisoner of war to try to escape, but there is no duty on the warders to allow him to 3 See Dworkin Taking rights seriously 188fff do so. Much of the discussion of civil disobedience applies on this level only. The issue is not whether there is a duty on the authorities to treat the resistor with leniency. It is natural to ask whether someone has a right to resist in the weak sense if one approaches the issue of civil disobedience from the perspective of the agent - the person who has to decide whether or not to engage in this form of resistance. Our perspective will be different. Civil disobedience will - instead be seen primarily from the perspective of state officials who have to evaluate such acts and determine what the response of the state should be. Our concern will be to establish the circumstances in which one has a right in the strong sense of the word to engage in civil disobedience. The recognition of such a right of resistance implies that there is a corresponding duty it will be called a "duty of leniency" - of the authorities to allow that resistance or at least to tolerate it to some extent. The aim is to establish some guidelines which will enable legal decision-makers the legislature and judicial officers who shape and administer the law - to evaluate acts of civil disobedience and help them to determine how lenient or severe their response should be. The present situation in South Africa is particularly conducive to an investigation into the legitimacy of political resistance. In most instances when this issue is considered, there is a natural inclination to make one's conclusions dependent on one's own particular interests. Almost inevitably people endorse a wide right of resistance if their own views are in opposition to those of the government, while those who in general benefit from the status quo entertain a restrictive view in this regard. At the moment, however, South Africa is almost in, what might be called, a Rawlsian "original position" - no one knows who is going to rule in five years' time, and whether he or she will be in the camp of the resistors or the resisted. In considering the question of justified resistance, one is therefore forced into the (in some ways unenviable) position where one cannot hold a brief for anyone, and, as far as this is possible, cannot help but to be "objective". And indeed, that win be the central point of departure of the present analysis: It will be argued that in order to arrive at a fair and just notion of what the nature and limits of political obligation are - and by implication when resistance would be justified - one has to ask what the view of rational agents should be if they had to answer that question from behind a "veil of ignorance", shrouding from them their own special interest in the matter. It will be argued that people in such a situation will not require blind obedience to all political sovereigns. Participants in the original position would insist on some aspects of their lives being placed beyond the reach of government - for example, they would insist on a high degree of autonomy in respect of their religious convictions. On the other hand, it should be equally obvious that not everyone should be allowed to break the law whenever he wants to, even if he passionately believes that his conduct is justified ": at least not in a society as divided as our own. Those in the] original position would not want to live in an ungovernable society. How should the balance then be struck between anarchy and state absolutism? Evidently no rules of thumb can be given for answering such a complex question. There are simply too many variables which are impossible to quantify with any degree of precision. What is the level of respect for law in the particular society? How much individual autonomy and disobedience can the social fibre accommodate without suffering serious deterioration? What is the level of injustice of the prevailing system -that is, how deserving is the legal system of respect? At most one can hope to develop distinctions provide the between some conceptual different general tools kinds guidelines necessary of on civil how to make useful disobedience, those kinds and of to civil disobedience, comparatively speaking, should be evaluated. There can be little doubt as to the relevance of such an inquiry for South Africa. We live in a society which is likely to remain divided for many more years to come. Divergent interests, and consequently also different values, frames of reference and indeed different realities, are bound to clash. Irrespective of who will be in power, it is inevitable that a large percentage of the population is going to be politically frustrated. It is a sad prospect that much of the resistance against the state might be violent. But, if the country can manage to avoid an all-out state of anarchy and civil war, it seems clear that civil disobedience will be a permanent feature of the political processes. It is no exaggeration to say that the future of the country will to a significant degree depend on the ability of those in power to find legitimate ways of managing dissent, expressed, interalia, through acts of civil disobedience. The inquiry chapter, the will proceed term "civil along the following disobedience" will lines: be In the defined second and its essential elements win be set out. Aspects that are not essential but which are often associated with that form of protest will also be discussed. Different manifestations or forms of civil disobedience will be identified. disobedience” The and relationship between "conscientious the objection” notions will of also "civil receive attention. The purpose of this chapter is by and large to develop the vocabulary necessary for a nuanced view of civil disobedience. The third chapter contains a fairly detailed overview of the historical development regarding of the civil way disobedience in which civil with a view disobedience to bringing manifests clarity itself in practice. The different uses to which civil disobedience has been put since its earliest inception are considered, and an attempt is made to establish what the most pertinent developments reveal about the nature of this form of protest. The question is posed why certain types of civil disobedience were practised under some circumstances but not under others. Particular attention is paid to the question why mass civil disobedience only developed as a political tool in this century, in South Africa. The campaigns conducted in South Africa, India and the United States, and especially their legal implications, are discussed. As far as could be established, this chapter contains the first comprehensive historical account of civil disobedience in South Africa. The South African campaigns of Gandhi, as well as the later campaigns of the liberation movements, are recounted in some detail, especially with a view to their legal ramifications. Extensive use has been made of newspaper clippings of the time, since such clippings are often the only available source of information on the particular periods of history under consideration. The lengthy historical survey might seem disproportionate in a jurisprudential inquiry, but it is considered necessary to fully canvass the "raw material" basic to the philosophical investigation into the present subject matter. In the fourth chapter the South African positive law relating to civil disobedience comes into the spotlight. The implications in respect of acts of civil disobedience of the criminal law and the powers of the executive are considered, as well as the effect of participation in acts of civil disobedience on a person's legal competence to practice law. The legal provisions relating to conscientious objection to compulsory military service are also discussed. Chapter five deals with the perceptions regarding political obligation and resistance of some of the most important contributors toward the shaping of Western and South from the African culture. The message emanating Bible, some perspectives from the Roman and Roman-Dutch law, the views of the great philosophers - political and otherwise - and of religious leaders, the approach scientists and main South the of some African contemporary churches, and political some of the practices of traditional African society in this respect, will receive attention. In chapter six the question how law should respond to civil disobedience is directly addressed. This inquiry comprises three parts. In the first place the question is considered whether, and if so on what basis, recognised. a strong Assuming circumstances, the right that crucial of resistance there is question such is should a in right then principle under asked be certain what those circumstances are. On the basis of a critical appraisal of some ideas of Ronald Dworkin, a model is proposed which, it is believed, is more flexible and intuitively more acceptable than most other approaches. Thirdly, the issue is addressed what mechanisms legal decision-makers can use to bring relief to those who have engaged in civil disobedience, in cases where it has been established that a strong right to engage in civil disobedience should be recognised. In chapter seven a summary of the most important conclusions is given and their interrelationship and wider implications are considered. CHAPTER TWO: DEFINING CIVIL DISOBEDIENCE: ITS ELEMENTS AND MANIFESTATIONS Some of the many activities loosely referred to as civil disobedience, have been practised for many centuries. However, it is only since the last century that the term "civil disobedience” has come to be used. 1 Although there might be an intuitive understanding of what the term implies, no general consensus exists amongst persons usually regarded as practitioners of civil disobedience, 2 political philosophers, 3 1 The term "civil disobedience" could probably be traced to the legacy of Thoreau. His essay "Resistance to civil government" (1848) was published - and became famous - post-humously under the title "On the duty of civil disobedience". According to MacGuigan The Canadian Bar Review 1971 222 at 256 the word "civil" In "civil disobedience" refers to i) the fact that it is practised by a citizen as citizen (of the Afrikaans "burgerlike ongehoorsaamheid"); ii) the fact that military methods (force) is not used and iii) the conscientious base and hence the civilized nature of such protest. 2 See on the views of Thoreau infra chap three III C (4); Gandhi infra chap three III B (2) and King infra chap three III C (6)(1). 3 According to Zinn Disobedience and democracy 32, civil disobedience is "the deliberate, discriminate, violation of law for a social purpose." Cohen Civil disobedience 39 defined it as "an act of protest, deliberately unlawful, conscientiously and publicly performed." Rawls A theory of Justice 364 saw it as "a public, nonviolent, conscientious yet political act contrary to law usually done with the aim of bringing about a change in the law or policies of the government." It was stated by Hugo Bedau The Journal of Philosophy 1961 653 at 661 that "anyone commits an act of civil disobedience if and only if he acts illegally, publicity, nonviolently, and conscientiously with the intent to frustrate (one of) the laws, policies, or decisions of his government." For Martin Ethics 1969/70 123 at 126 "[c]ivil disobedience is the deliberate and public violation of the command of an authorized and accepted political superior on the ground that this decree is unjust, immoral, unconstitutional, contrary to good public policy, etc." (Original emphasis.) See also Weingartner Columbia University Forum 1966 38 at 39. According to Christian Bay "Civil disosobedience" in the International Encyclopedia of the Social Sciences vol 2 473 at 473 the term refers to "any act or process of public defiance of a law or policy enforced by established governmental authorities, insofar as the action is premeditate understood by the actor(s) to be illegal or of contested legality carried out or persisted in for limited public ends and by way carefully chosen and limited means." Schuyt Recht, orde en burgerlijke ongehoorzaamheid 311 regarded the following as the basic elements civil disobedience: "1) de handeling is illegaal 2) de sociologists 4 and jurisprudes 5 who considered the issue as to what the essential elements necessary to give of civil definition disobedience of what is are. It is consequently meant by the term "civil disobedience". What are the necessary elements which, taken together, give sufficient description of the phenomenon? However, a clear definition of the general concept of civil disobedience is not the only tool needed in order to be in position to evaluate individual cases of civil disobedience. There are many different manifestations of civil disobedience, each with its own characteristics that might affect the acceptability of the conduct in question. various kinds of The civil terminology disobedience necessary will to distinguish consequently have to the be developed. This chapter, then, will aim at defining civil disobedience and handeling gewetensvol 3) er is betekenissamenhang tussen bekritiseerd object gekozen handelwijze 4) de handeling is weloverwogen 5) de handeling geschied openlijk 6) men werkt vrljwillig men aan arrestasie vervolging 7) men aanvaardt net risiko van een straf 8) men heeft te voren lega1e midelen geprobeerd 9) geweldloosheid 10) rechten van andti worden zoveel mogelljk in acht genomen." Closer to home, according Esterhuyse Broers buite hoorafstand 22, civil disobedience is” nie-gewelddadige protesstrategie op morele gronde, en verteenwoordig ‘n vorm van doelbewuste wetsoortreding." 4 Gene Sharp, in his seminal work The politics of nonviolent action part 2 The methods of nonviolent action 315, described civil disobedience as "a deliberate, open and peaceful violation of particular laws decrees, regulations, ordinances, military or police instructions, and the like which are believed to be illegitimate for some reason. One the most drastic forms of noncooperation, civil disobedience is expression of the doctrine that there are times when men have a moral responsibility to disobey 'man-made' laws in obedience to 'higher' laws.” 5 Few lawyers have actually attempted to define civil disobedience MacGuigan The Canadian Bar Review 1971 222 at 256 saw it as “a public, nonviolent act which is either actually illegal or likely to be treated as illegal by the governmental authorities, performed for a no purpose, with a willingness to accept the legal penalty attached to breach of the law." See also Freeman Indiana Law Journal 1965/66 221 231; Van den Haag Rutgers Law Review 1966/67 27 at 27 and Katz UCLA Review 1985 904 at 905. Edwin Cameron "Civil disobedience and passive resistance" in Corder Essays on law and social practice In South Africa 219 at 221 put it as follows: "Civil disobedience occurs when a law publicly violated for moral reasons as a deliberate protest." See a Christa van Wyk Wetenskaplike Bydraes van die PU vir CHO 1990 97 at 109. identifying its different manifestations. A later chapter will deal with the question as to the possible justification of acts of civil disobedience. It is justification, as decision-maker must important far as in that possible, the first the be place issues dealt be of with able definition and separately. The to identify in as neutral a manner as possible which form of protest is at stake, and then, secondly, proceed to evaluate it. If definition and justification are conflated, one is forced to make an evaluation without being granted the opportunity of independently considering with an open mind the merits of the case in question. 6 Consequently we shall attempt to establish, what disobedience; 7 is called, a "minimal" definition of civil that is, a definition which in the barest possible terms identify the phenomenon, without signifying any moral judgment as to its propriety. What are the criteria according to which the essential elements of civil disobedience are to be established? It. if submitted that the basic criteria are convenience and common usage. In the first place, the elements identified mud describe a range of actions which is sufficiently narrow to allow meaningful generalisations regarding the way in which they are to be evaluated, but at the same time this range of actions must be wide enough to be politically significant. 8 The 6 Zinn Disobedience and democracy 48 and Cohen Civil disobedience 24 confused the definition and the justification of civil disobedience. They argued that because it might under certain circumstances be necessary to use force in order to protect human rights, civil disobedience should not be regarded as necessarily nonviolent. Few people would disagree with this premise, but the conclusion does not follow. Only complete pacifists would argue that coercion, and particularly violent revolution, can under no circumstances be justified, but it does not follow that such actions should be regarded as acts of civil disobedience. All actions which can be classified as acts of civil disobedience are not automatically justified, and those which are not thus classified are not automatically unjustified. See also K Nielsen "Remarks on violence and paying the penalty" in Beauchamp Ethics and public policy 162 at 165 and E Cameron "Civil disobedience and passive resistance" in Corder Essays on law and social practice in South Africa 219 at 222. 7 8 See Du Toit The Black Sash May 1973 6 at 9. Brown The Journal of Philosophy 1961 669 at 680 remarks, with reference to some examples of protest actions which he believes will commonly be called acts of civil disobedience: "Call them what we will, there is a class of illegal acts which differ characteristically question must be asked which elements would highlight the truly unique nature of civil disobedience, without rendering that concept too isoteric. At the same time, the technical meaning of the term civil disobedience should as far as is possible accord with the popular understanding of the term. It was stated earlier that an objective of this study is b develop a "flexible theory" of civil disobedience, in the sense of rendering the concept useful in more and less democratic situations. It will be argued that the definition of civil disobedience which finds support in the main stream of American jurisprudence is in a number of respects only applicable under American conditions. In order to be relevant in a wider range of social settings, a number of important adjustments or modifications need to be made, and it will be argued that at least in one respect American jurisprudence is misguided, even for American purposes. I. THE ELEMENTS OF CIVIL DISOBEDIENCE In this study conduct will be regarded as civil disobedience if it is: - illegal (in the wide sense of the word, as will be explained later on), - non-violent (or at least not highly coercive), - open, - motivated by conviction, and - political. The significance and meaning of these elements will next be considered. A. ILLEGALITY The first element of civil disobedience which writers usually emphasise is the fact that only wrongful actions can qualify for this kind of resistance. 9 Civil disobedience involves a special kind of “disobedience” to the state. The civil disobedient acts outside the scope not only of what the authorities consider acceptable but also of what they regard as tolerable behaviour. Actions which might be deeply resented by the state, such as demonstrations, strikes and picketing, ... from typical acts of law-breaking ... which pose very peculiar problems about justification." 9 See Rawls A theory of justice 364 and Cohen Civil disobedience 4. whereby the government is openly defied, attacked or ridiculed, are not acts of civil disobedience if they are not also unlawful. The mere fact that one’s act offends a social taboo is not sufficient - the civil disobedient must also render himself liable to the wrath of the powers that be. Terms such as "passive resistance", "non-cooperation" and the Afrikaans notion of violent "lydelike methods of verset", protest, which are should often be used to signify non- from civil distinguished disobedience. Those concepts have a wider meaning: they include both legal and illegal acts of (non-violent) resistance. These forms of resistance might be, but are not necessarily, unlawful, while acts of civil disobedience are essentially illegal. Whether this approach is acceptable for our purposes depends upon the interpretation given to the term "illegality". It is submitted that only if the widest possible meaning is attached to the notion of illegality, in two crucial respects can it be regarded as an essential element of civil disobedience. The first respect in which this should be done becomes apparent when the difference between a society in which the rule of law is observed and a society in which that is not the case is considered. Conduct is "illegal" in the narrow or technical meaning of the word if a publicly established legal norm, for the breach of which the state has prescribed a specified sanction, is transgressed. According to this interpretation of the word "illegal", one’s conduct has to constitute a crime before it can be considered an act of civil disobedience. 10 Insofar as the rule of law is observed in a particular society, there can be no problems with this approach. The argument can be explained in the form of a syllogism: Civil disobedience involves subjecting oneself to the wrath of the state. Where the rule of law pertains, one can only be subjected to the wrath of the state if one has committed a crime. Consequently, in such a society the commission of a crime must be an essential element of civil disobedience. It should be evident that a narrow interpretation of the requirement that conduct must be "illegal" in order to qualify as an act of civil 10 Christa van Wyk Wetenskaplike Bydraes van die PU vir CHO 1990 97 at 106 regarded the requirement "dat 'n wet oortree moet word" as a universally accepted element of civil disobedience. disobedience serves societies where the rule of law is being well observed. It is therefore not surprising that American authors find this approach acceptable. We are, however, interested in a more flexible theory of civil disobedience, which applies not only to societies in which the rule of law obtains. The question must accordingly be asked what the position would be in a society where the rule of law is not observed. The fact that the rule of law is not upheld means that the coercive power of the state may be unleashed on a subject even if he does not, in the technical sense of the word, act illegally. This may occur in primitive societies where law, morality and religion are fused, as well as in more modern societies where the executive has far-reaching discretionary powers. In such cases the question whether someone has subjected himself to the coercive powers of the state cannot be answered simply by asking whether he has technically broken the law. Someone who sets out to participate in a demonstration against the government, knowing that the police will in all likelihood arrest and detain him indefinitely without trial, clearly challenges the state at least as fundamentally as someone who does the same under circumstances where his conduct constitutes a crime. It is consequently submitted that inasmuch as the rule of law does not obtain, a wide interpretation should be attached to the term "illegality". All actions that are likely to provoke use of the state’s coercive powers, whether it technically constitutes a crime or not, should be regarded as "illegal" for the purposes of defining civil disobedience. This brings us to the second problem concerning the interpretation of the term "illegal". In situations where the rule of law - is observed and the identify technical civil - interpretation disobedience the the question term "i1legal" arises how is used narrowly to this criterion should interpreted. When exactly in such circumstances can certain conduct be described as "illegal” in the technical sense the word? In most cases the answer to this question raises few problems, at least for those with some legal knowledge. If unambiguous and uncontroversial Act of Parliament states that it is an offence to demonstrate within the proximity of the Houses of Parliament, it is clearly illegal to do so. A problem will arise, however, in cases of so-called "doubtful law" 11 - that is in cases where the question whether certain conduct which is prima facie illegal is in fact to regarded as illegal, can be the subject matter of a bona fide debate between reasonable lawyers. In the event uncertainty regarding the illegality of certain conduct, question will arise as to whether or not such conduct co be described as "illegal" for purposes of the definition civil disobedience. At least three situations in which the problem of “doubt law" might arise, should be distinguished: - In jurisdictions where a justiciable Bin of Rights in operation, legislation and administrative acts which are prima facie legal may be declared invalid if they violate any provision of the Bill of Rights; - Subordinate legislation may be invalidated in terms the directives of administrative law (for instance such legislation is found to be ultra vires unreasonable); and Acts which are prima facie illegal may be shown to be legal on - the basis of one of the grounds of justification of the criminal law (for example necessity or consent). For purposes of a definition of civil disobedience, one could approach the question as to transgressions of "doubtful" laws from different perspectives. If a narrow interpretation of the term "illegal" were to be preferred, it would mean that transgressions of doubtful laws will not constitute civil disobedience, whereas a wide interpretation of that concept might lead to the opposite conclusion. According to the narrow approach, which is preferred by most American writers on the subject, civil disobedience involves an extra-legal appeal to morality, not an intra-legal appeal to a stronger rule of positive law. 12 The civil disobedient makes the claim that his conduct is legitimate, not that it is legal. Transgression of "doubtful laws" consequently does not qualify as “illegal" conduct for the purpose of the definition of civil disobedience. Seen from 11 12 this perspective, the idea of "legally justified civil See Dworkin Taking rights seriously 208. See W L Taylor "Civil disobedience: Observations on the strategies of protest" in Bosmajian Dissent 86 at 87 and Arendt Crises of the republic 53 disobedience” is a contradiction in terms. Civil disobedience is by definition unlawful, and if one’s conduct is sanctioned by more basic norms of the legal system, that conduct is ultimately legal. Civil disobedience cannot be lawful, because “the law logically cannot permit law-breaking." 13 To state the same proposition in different terms: whenever an act of protest which seems illegal turns out in fact to be legal, it can no longer be regarded as an act of civil disobedience. Obviously this approach has far-reaching consequences regarding the way in which a campaign of civil disobedience, such as the Civil Rights Movement, should be seen. In that particular campaign nearly all the infringements of local and state segregation laws were justified on the basis that those laws violated the federal constitution, and in particular the Bill of Rights. It may consequently be argued that these protests should not be regarded as acts of civil disobedience properly so-called, but rather as "assertions of rights". 14 Instead of dealing with civil disobedience, we are here concerned with civil obedience since the disobedience to the weaker law is, as it were, trumped by obedience to the stronger law. 15 Following this line of argument. Burke Marshall posed the question whether "the federal system does not in effect make the theory of civil disobedience movement." wholly inapplicable to the efforts of the protest 16 Martin Luther King needed only to appeal to the law: He should not have saddled himself with the difficult task of proving that an appeal to 13 See Cohen Civil disobedience 7; Cohen Rutgers Law Review 1966 1 at 7 and Alien University of Cincinnati Law Review 1967 1 at 3 n 5. See also Arendt Crises of the republic 51 at 53. Art 20(4) of the German Basic Law, since 1968, provides as follows: "All Germans shall have the right to resist any person or persons seeking to abolish the constitutional order, should no other remedy be possible." For a discussion of this controversial provision, see Kaufmann New England Law Review 1985/6 571 at 573. Du Toit Wetenskaplike Bydraes van die PU v1r CHO 1985 1 at IS argued that "'n [p]ositiewe regsorde kan geen reg van verset (lydelik of aktief) verdra nie, omdat dit dan homself dualisties sou maak of sy eie opheffing sou herberg." 14 See Black Texas Law Review 1965 492 at 496. 15 One of the leaders of the Civil Rights Movement called their actions "civil obedience". See Freeman Indiana Law Journal 1965/66 228 228. 16 Marshall Virginia Law Review 1965 785 at 795. conscience justified the acts of protest, because in the majority of cases he was in fact not breaking the law. The legality of his acts was clearly established in subsequent Supreme Court cases. In similar vein, Charles Black argued that much of the defiance of segregation ordinances in the Civil Rights Movement merely had the "flavor of disobedience". Because the illegality evidently appeared from the constitution, "the of the ordinances defiance of law was all on the other side." According to him the leaders of the Civil Rights Movement preaching were and too "engaged practising and was busy" not to civil note that disobedience what at they all. were Black maintained that if at any given time doubt prevails as to the legality of certain actions and as long as "there is an element of claimed legal right", there would be "an implied submission to, rather than defiance of, the order of law." 17 The views of these authors regarding the element of illegality can be interpreted and applied in two different ways. The first possibility is that the question as to the illegality of certain conduct should be answered from an objective, ex post facto perspective. Only after an authoritative, final verdict has been given by the highest possible court declaring that the conduct in question was in fact illegal, can it be stated with certainty that the act of protest was in fact a matter of civil disobedience. This approach conflates the issues of definition and justification, since identification of certain conduct as a manifestation of civil disobedience would in this instance require an authoritative verdict concerning its legality. This approach also proceeds from the mistaken assumption that one can arrive at a final authoritative judgment as to the precise legal position. In reality a lower court can be overruled by a higher court, or a court may in future overrule its own earlier judgments. 18 To make the question whether one is dealing with civil disobedience dependent on an authoritative judgement regarding the legality of the conduct in question, could therefore mean that the 17 18 Black Texas Law Review 1965 492 at 496. See Dworkin Taking rights seriously 211. The most famous United States example in this regard is probably Brown v Board of Education 347 US 483 (1954), in which Plessy v Ferguson 163 US 537 (1896) was overruled. See also the "Flag salute" cases, discussed infra chap three III C (2). answer to the question whether or not one is dealing with civil disobedience is relegated into infinity. This manifestation of the narrow interpretation of the term "illegal" is consequently not conducive to developing an approach to the question of civil disobedience that would allow the decision-maker to evaluate events as they occur. In fact, what would be required if this approach were to prevail, would be to wait until the conduct has beer evaluated before one could acquire the conceptual tools needed to evaluate it. The other possible way in which to apply the narrow approach is to regard the ex ante. subjective beliefs of the people involved in the protest as whether the or decisive factor. This not certain conduct is entirely to disobedience" would in bi mean fact that the qualifies determined with a as view question "civil to the understanding of the people concerned of their legal position. If they themselves were to justify their prima facie illegal actions on the basis that those actions are sanctioned by law they would not commit civil disobedience; if they seek to legitimise their action on moral grounds only, those actions can properly be defined as instances of civil disobedience. The eventual finding of the courts would then be irrelevant. Judging from the remarks of Charles Black quoted above; this appears to be his view. The problem with this approach is that in the heat of the battle, people seldom juridical justified clearly legality. by additional some problem distinguish They higher that simply believe principle might between - arise be moral that it from their legal an legitimacy and actions or entirely moral. are 19 An subjective approach, is that people’s beliefs concerning the legality of their actions are often highly unreasonable. Why should the conduct of someone who holds the mistaken belief that he is acting illegally be regarded as an act of civil disobedience, while that of another person who holds the totally unwarranted belief that he is acting legally would not qualify as civil disobedience? All manifestations of the narrow approach consequently seem unacceptable. It is consequently submitted that the narrow interpretation of the term 19 Barkan Protesters on trial 56 pointed out that in most cases members of the Civil Rights Movement took the decision to go to court only after the acts of civil disobedience occurred. It was not their intention to create test cases. “illegal” is wrong. In order to avoid the above-mentioned problems, a wider interpretation of the term "illegality" should be followed. All acts of protest ought to be regarded as illegal if juridical provisions officially in force at the critical time have been violated, irrespective of whether, subsequently, those provisions are likely to be declared disobedience invalid one's or inoperative. conduct must be In order "illegal" constituted transgression of a legal provision to in qualify the as sense civil that it which at the time of the conduct was clearly valid or at least not clearly invalid; that is, where at the critical time it has not been revoked or declared invalid. The possibility, or rather the "risk", of illegality, the breaking of a legal proscription, would suffice to constitute civil disobedience. The point is subjects state. that a himself protester to the who runs possibility the of risk of provoking breaking the wrath the law of the 20 When this wider approach is followed, it becomes clear that one is not making a self-contradictory claim when stating that civil disobedience can be legally justified. From an ex ante perspective, such a claim boils down to the assertion that a possibility exists that, what now appears to be illegal, might in future be declared legal. From the ex post facto perspective it means that, even if the conduct is now viewed as legal, there was a risk at the critical time that it was not. To argue that the fact of prima facie illegal conduct eventually being vindicated in court implies that we were all along not dealing with civil disobedience, is similar to arguing that because Sir Edmund Hilary returned safely from Mount Everest his journey was in reality not dangerous. Although the narrower approach should consequently not be followed as far as the definition of civil disobedience is concerned, it is nevertheless useful to recognise that two different manifestations of civil disobedience can be identified on the basis of the distinction outlined above: - Legality-based civil disobedience, or acts of civic disobedience in respect of which the claim is made that they are legally justified. 20 The idea is to create test-case if necessary. An See also Blackstone Georgia Law Review 1969 679 at 684. MacGuigan The Canadian Bar Review 1971 222 at 225 included cases of contested legality in his definition of civil disobedience. appeal is made to the highest norms of the positive law. These are the "assertion of rights"-cases, prevalent in the Civil Rights Movement and which some American commentators now deny the status of acts of disobedience. 21 civil This type of civil disobedience will probably become more evident in South Africa once a Bill of Rights has been introduced. It may, of course, in principle already occur in South Africa, insofar as it might be claimed that the grounds of justification of the criminal law apply, or that subordinate legislation is invalid in terms of the provisions of administrative law. Legitimacy-based - civil disobedience or those cases of civil disobedience where only the claim of its moral justification is made. Here an appeal is made not to the positive law, but to the conscience of the nation or the world, to reason, to natural law, or to God himself. This is the traditional form in which civil disobedience occurred in countries such as South Africa and India. According to the American writers referred to above, this is the only form which, in reality, civil disobedience can take. There are instances in which these two types of conduct overlap. The important point for the moment is, however, that both these types of action should be regarded as “illegal" for purposes of the definition of civil disobedience. Having completed the discussion on how wide or how narrow the term "illegal" should be interpreted, it remains to allude to the different ways in which illegal acts can manifest themselves. An important distinction between different types of civil disobedience can be drawn on the basis of the type of actus reus involved 22 - the distinction between, what disobedience. might be called, positive and negative civil 23 21 The United States Supreme Court does not approve of the practice of "asserting rights" or creating test cases, even in the dear cases: "No one, no matter how exalted his public office, or how righteous his private motive, can be judge in his own case." United States v United Mine Workers 330 US 258 (1946) at 308. 22 See also the distinction made by Bedau The Journal of Philosophy 1961 653 at 654. 23 The terms "active" and "passive" civil disobedience would have been more accurate, but are bound to cause confusion because of prevalence of the term "passive resistance" which, as illustrated In the case of positive civil disobedience the illegal action takes on the form of a commissio. A negative legal provision or a proscription is violated through a positive act. A typical example in this regard would be participation in public demonstration prohibited by law. Negative civil disobedience involves an illegal act in the form of an omissio. A positive legal provision or prescription is violated through a negative act or inaction- a refusal to comply. A typical example of this form of civil disobedience would be the refusal to pay taxes as a means of protest. It is the element of illegality which makes civil disobedience a radical form of resistance, at least comparison with other forms of resistance. It will be argued that this element, when it is combined with the other characteristics of civil disobedience, such as openness, brings into question the respect with which law is normal treated in society. 24 B. NON-VIOLENCE Most, but not all, commentators regard non-violence to be an essential element of civil disobedience. 25 It is, as indicated earlier, primarily a matter of terminology and convenience. 26 It is probably not "wrong" to define civil disobedience so as to include both Gandhi and the berserk political murderer in the public square who after the event surrenders himself to the police. Their conduct in both instances could be classified as illegal political acts about which some very general observations could be made. However, there is such a vast qualitative earlier, has a distinctly different meaning. 24 On the reasons why law is normally obeyed in society, apart from compulsion, see Sharp Power and struggle 8ff. 25 For writers who regard non-violence as an element of civil disobedience, see Bedau The Journal of Philosophy 1961 653 at 656; Sibley Journal of the Minnesota Academy of Science 1965 67 at 71; Thalberg Scientia 1966 436 at 438; Martin Ethics 1969/70 123 at 132; Weingartner Columbia University Forum 1966 38 at 38; MacGuigan The Canadian Bar Review 1971 222 at 241 and Rawls A theory of justice 364. For writers who do not regard non-violence as essential, see Zinn Disobedience and democracy 32 and Keeton Texas Law Review 1965 507 at 508. As to South African writers who hold the latter view, see Du Toit The Black Sash May 1973 6 at 10 and E Cameron "Civil disobedience and passive resistance" in Corder Essays on law and social practice 1n South Africa 219 at 222. 26 See also Cohen Rutgers Law Review 1966 1 at 3. difference between the two cases that a further subdivision seems imperative. If the term "civil disobedience" is not to be used to denote the less coercive category of conduct, then another term will have to be found to distinguish that conduct from the category of more violent acts. These two categories of conduct clearly involve different consideration pertaining to their possible justification. On what basis, exactly, should the distinction between the different types of conduct described above be made? Various possibilities present themselves in this regard; most notably the coercion/non-coercion and the violence/non-violence distinctions. In order to establish which one of these distinctions will best serve our purposes, the terms involved must be circumscribed. A political act can be seen as "coercive” if it involves changing the incentives of the adversary to the extent that he has no choice but to change his behaviour. The opposite is "non-coercive" or "persuasive" action, whereby the opponent is brought to see for himself that he should mend his ways. 27 "Violence" involves the use or the threat of physical force against the person or property of one’s adversary; "nonviolence" entails the absence of such use or threat of force. 28 Non-violence is consequently the wider term and can encompass noncoercive as well as certain coercive acts. 29 Someone who blocks the entry to a building, slows down the traffic, sails into a nuclear testzone or stages a sit-in in someone’s office is not using violence, but his actions can nevertheless be highly coercive. 30 Non-coercion, on the other hand, necessarily involves the absence of violence. Should, then, "non-coercion" or "non-violence" be regarded as an element of civil disobedience? The distinction coercion/non-coercion 27 See the discussion by Fried Harvard Law Review 1964 1258 of what he called "moral causation". E P J Corbett "The rhetoric of the open hand and the rhetoric of the closed fist" in Bosmajian Dissent 71 also discussed the nature of persuasion through civil disobedience. 28 Perhaps best-known in this regard is Bondurant's model for describing a non-violent programme. See Bondurant Conquest of violence 73ff. For a discussion of the meaning of the terms "violence" and "non-violence", see Sharp The Journal of Conflict Resolution 1959 41. 29 30 See also MacGuigan The Canadian Bar Review 1971 222 at 271. On non-violent coercion, see Sharp The dynamics of nonviolent action 741ff. certainly appears to be more basic to our inquiry, since it signifies the two fundamentally different ways in which one can move an opponent to change: that is, through persuasion and compulsion. From the purist’s point of view, it would probably be correct to say that, if one intends isolating a completely unique form of political resistance under the name of civil disobedience, non-coercion should be regarded as an essential element. Civil disobedience, so defined, would then entirely be compulsion aimed present, at persuasion; one would no and if longer there be is any dealing element with of civil disobedience. Non-violent but coercive acts, like blocking the entry to a building, could then be grouped together with acts of violence as non-persuasive or coercive tactics. Both blocking an entry and throwing a bomb involve coercion; the only difference is the level of intensity of the coercion. 31 There is also historical support for this approach. According to Gandhi, for example, civil disobedience had to be noncoercive. 32 The problem with this purist approach, however, is that very few acts of political resistance do not involve some form of coercion. In South Africa, with the Defiance Campaign in 1952 and the Positive Action Campaign in 1960, the objective of many participants was to flood the jails and law courts, and in so doing to make the system unworkable by clogging it. Clearly, that involves an intention to coerce, even if the coercion occurs on a relatively low level. In other cases of nonviolent resistance, the compulsion is more subtle - less physical and more moral. Nevertheless the coercion in such cases might in fact be 31 M Cohen "Civil disobedience in a constitutional democracy" in Beauchamp Ethics and public policy 145 at 148 regarded the conduct of someone who sails into a nuclear testing area to prevent such tests as coercive, and argued that such conduct crosses the line from civil disobedience to other forms of resistance. Bedau The Journal of Philosophy 1961 653 at 657 called such acts "non-violent obstruction". 32 Gandhi regarded blocking the way of an opponent as "sheer compulsion", contrary to the spirit of Satyagraha. Gandhi Non-violent resistance 201. See also in the same work 334. He maintained that "(t]he appeal is never to [the] fear [of the adversary]; it is, must be, always to the heart. The Satyagrahi's object is to convert, not to coerce, the wrong-doer." Gandhi Non-violent resistance 87. To Gandhi Satyagraha was the direct opposite of compulsion. See Chatterjee Gandhi's religious thought 91. For an exposition of the coercive forms of protest that have been practised under the name of Satyagraha in post-Gandhian India, see Bayley The American Political Science Review 1962 663. more intense. By voluntarily undergoing suffering, one might not change the physical incentives of the opponent, but the moral manipulation could be hard to resist. 33 Gandhi, near the end of his life, expressed his regret at having coerced people through his fasts. 34 What is more (as will be demonstrated in the historical overview), acts of political resistance that involve no direct coercion almost always indirectly entail coercion. Civil disobedience in most cases is not directly aimed at bringing about a change of heart in the opponent himself. Invariably the target is, what win be called, a "benevolent background force" - a third party (for example another country or the United Nations) which may use its leverage to change the opponent’s behaviour. Inciting such indirect pressure, which can be highly coercive, was the preferred strategy of most of the people regarded as classic proponents of civil disobedience, including Gandhi. 35 The moral component of civil disobedience should consequently not be overrated. If all cases where an element of coercion is involved either physical or moral, direct or indirect - had to be disqualified as civil disobedience, this category of protest would be so small as to render it insignificant. Moreover, it might be true that the difference between "blocking the way" and "throwing a bomb" is one of degree (both involve coercing the opponent). However, it should also be noted that this difference in degree is nevertheless extremely significant. In practice, it seems appropriate to speak of a "blocking of the way" and an "illegal, peaceful demonstration" in the same breath; more so than 33 Consider the case of the person who sails into a nuclear testing site in order to frustrate experiments in the area. Is he physically or morally manipulating his adversary? If they can stomach it morally, they may be able to proceed with their tests. 34 35 See Gandhi Non-violent resistance 291. A careful study of some of the civil rights protests in the United States has suggested that the conditions for the success of such forms of "direct action" are the following: There must be a "dilemma", in the Gunnar Hyrdal sense of the word. That is, there must be some gross direct conflict between social reality and the generally professed values and goals of society. In order to activate people - to bring them to appreciate the dilemma and to make it a matter of priority - a crisis must be created. This can be done by causing disorder. Civil disobedience, without direct coercion, can serve this purpose. The elite's fear of disorder then moves them to action. See Von Eschen et al The Western Political Quarterly 1969 309 at 322ff. would be the case with "blocking the way" and "throwing a bomb". It is submitted that the more practical approach is to regard noncoercion and coercion as two extremes, where the tangent point between these extremes represents different combinations of coercion and persuasion. On the one side of the spectrum persuasion prevails, in the middle ground they are of equal significance, whereas on the other side coercion dominates. Civil disobedience, then, is located on that side of the spectrum where the acts are either completely non-coercive or at least primarily persuasive. The further one moves away from the pole of non-coercion, the less relevant would the considerations which apply to civil disobedience become. Civil disobedience could consequently be either coercive of non-coercive. This can perhaps best be explained by using terms popularised by Marx. Marx believed material spiritual that history conditions aspects of of is driven living. living is The by the base-structure super-structure entirely determined or by or the the more the base- structure. Civil disobedience in its purest form proceeds from exactly the opposite premise, namely the belief significantly influence the material. that the spiritual can 36 It is therefore submitted that civil disobedience involves little or no coercion. As a practical measure, the category of actions on the one side of the spectrum can be described with reasonable accuracy by using the term “non-violence", and indeed, as has been mentioned earlier, most commentators on civil disobedience use this criterion. Whether the coercive as opposed to the persuasive element of protest strategies is in fact predominant in a given case is a matter to be determined realistically and with practical wisdom. If someone sails into a certain area to protest against nuclear testing that is about to take place, his actions might be coercive in the able to cause Nevertheless, the if his postponement actions in of the test practical sense of him being for terms a still few hours. leave those engaged in the testing free to choose whether or not to continue with their business after the protester has been removed, it can practical purposes be regarded as an act of civil disobedience. primary aim of such conduct is what Bertrand Russell 36 See infra chap five I BB. 37 See Bedau The Journal of Philosophy 1961 653 at 657. 37 for The calls "propaganda", 38 directed at an acquiescent or uninformed public. In reality, the objective is to persuade and very little coercion is used. It should also be borne in mind that during campaigns of political resistance passions often run high and spontaneous violence at the instance of the disobedient or their sympathisers can erupt, especially if demonstrations unforeseen transform although are incidents an act subdued of of by violence civil force. or The coercion disobedience outbreak does into a not of minor necessarily violent uprising, the possibility of violence should be discounted by those who choose to embark on acts of civil disobedience. 39 The fact that the use of violence by the security forces is foreseen by the protesters (for example if they make provision for the availability of first-aid for such an eventuality 40) also does not imply that violence is an element of the conduct violence of the perpetrated by protesters the - state. the The foreseen violence requirement of is then non-violence applies only to the conduct of the protesters and to acts of those whom the protesters can reasonably expect to side with them. Another factor actions might worth not considering involve actual is the fact violence. that For highly example, coercive the (non- violent) blocking of a city’s highways might disrupt the community more than would the (violent) sabotage of the city’s electric lines. At a certain point such conduct should no longer be regarded as acts of civil disobedience, consequently remain although sensitive no to violence the fact is that used. if One the should compulsion exceeds certain limits of coercion, non-violent actions could no longer be regarded as acts of civil disobedience. It should be noted that not all acts involving physical damage qualify as acts of violence. As will appear from the historical overview, there have been many cases where passes, registration certificates, flags etc have been destroyed as signs of protest. Where the property destroyed was that 38 of the protesters themselves (or was issued to them See Russell "Civil disobedience" in The New Statesman Feb 1961 245. 39 In response to the question whether Satyagraha will lead to violence, Gandhi answered: "It may, though I am trying my best to prevent any outbreak of violence." Gandhi Non-violent resistance 229. 40 See the discussion of the campaign at the salt-works in India, infra chap three III B (1)(b). personally) the person or property of the adversary was not attacked, and such acts should, for practical purposes, be treated as acts of non-violent resistance. Given these provisos, however, it is submitted that the requirement of non-violence generally provides the most workable criterion. The implications of the requirement of non-violence (or a low level of coercion) are far-reaching. By putting the conflict on this footing, the protesters can effectively disarm the government or render its superior forces useless. Effective government depends upon a mixture of control (or authority protesters compulsion, (or inter legitimacy). can in a very By alia through acting dramatic the use non-violently way raise of force) and themselves, the questions about the authority or legitimacy of the conduct of the opponent. In the case of a government which is largely dependent on control, the direct effect might be small, but where authority plays a meaningful role, the legitimacy of the government (both in its own eyes and in the eyes of the public) can be seriously threatened if the government is seen to respond excessively on the level of control. Civil disobedience, as one protester according to evidence in a court case during the 1952 Defiance Campaign in South Africa stated, can be very effective to put the government in a position where it either has to change or expose itself as a dictatorship. 41 Through the non-violent actions of the protester, such a government is compelled to respond on the level on which - it might be the weakest, namely that of morality. 42 41 42 See infra chap three III A (3)(c)(ii). To put this point more technically: Governments as well as their opposition usually depend for their effectiveness on a mixture of authority and control; legitimacy and coercion. (On the multiplicity of legal systems in society, see Pospisi1 The Journal of Conflict Resolution 1967 2.) The less the authority at the disposal of any one of these institutions, the more it will be compelled to depend on control in order to achieve its goals. There is, consequently, a direct inverse relationship between authority and control within each grouping. There is, however, also a direct relationship between the control exercised by one institution and the authority of the other. The more excessive the violence of the state becomes, the more the legitimacy of its opposition would increase, and vice versa. Civil disobedience by the opposition alms precisely at inciting the government to use excessive force, whereby the legitimacy of the opposition can be increased. For this reason civil disobedience is sometimes described as a form of "moral or political jiu-jitsu". See To conclude this part of the discussion, it should be noted that someone like Thoreau was often said not truly to have been a civil disobedient, violence. because 43 in certain cases he propagated the use of It is true that he did not consistently propagate non- violence. This, however, does not detract from the fact that what he propagated in other cases was the method of civil disobedience. A distinction should be drawn between those, like Gandhi, who propagate civil disobedience as an article of faith, 44 and others - like Thoreau and the leaders of the Defiance Campaign - who use civil disobedience as one of several strategies. Insofar as their actions are non-violent and meet the other requirements, they are practising civil disobedience. Rawls noted that "by taking part in civilly disobedient acts one does resistance." 45 not foreswear indefinitely the idea of forceful Surely, the opposite is also true. There might of course be practical advantages for protest leaders who intend keeping their campaigns non-violent in taking a strongly principled and even religious stand against violence. In a campaign where the ideal of non-violence is not evident, the masses could on the spur of the moment resort to violence and hence relinquish the high moral ground of the campaign at a time when the protest movement is possibly not ready or willing to engage in other forms of protest. As we shall see, this happened to some extent in the case of the Defiance Campaign, while Gandhi, on the other hand, had considerable successes in keeping his campaigns disciplined and non-violent. However, this is a practical matter of strategy. C. OPENNESS An illegal, non-violent act must furthermore be executed in the open that is publicly or overtly - in order to qualify as an act of civil disobedience. The element of openness, it is submitted, has three essential components: Sharp The dynamics of nonviolent action 657. According to Gandhi Nonviolent resistance 57, "[t]he might of the tyrant recoils upon himself when it meets with no response, even as an arm violently waived in the air suffers dislocation." 43 See Infra chap three III C (4). 44 See Gandhi Non-violent resistance 223. 45 J Rawls "The justification of civil disobedience" in Beauchamp Ethics and public policy 132 at 139. - the illegal deed must be committed in the "public forum" (the streets, parks, etc 46); or it must at least be intended to be visible to the public through the media; 47 - by a person whose identity is revealed; and - who does not attempt, at least not through illegal means, to evade being held responsible for the act. Openness is in many ways one of the most crucial components of civil disobedience, which gives it its distinct character. It affords to this form of protest its sharp edge, its dramatic impact. The authorities are defied for all to see, and while no attempt is made to conceal it. Civil disobedience consequently carries with it the risk of undermining respect for the law. At the same time the openness of the transgression renders the perpetrator vulnerable and exposed, and provides her - and her opponent morality. The -with an incentive not to abandon the dictates of 48 element of openness helps to ensure that civil acquires the disposition of a two-sided communication act. disobedience 49 Of course, clandestine acts of terror also convey a message, but in such cases the "communication" is intended to be mainly one-sided. It is the openness of civil disobedience that makes it a civic becomes part of the community’s public life. 50 act, something which By acting openly the civil disobedient communicates his message to members of the community, and then places himself, as it were, in their hands. The element of openness, 46 it will be argued, gives civil disobedience a basically See Alien University of Cincinnati Law Review 1967 1 at 5. 47 Cheating with taxes because one disagrees with its application can consequently not constitute civil disobedience. 48 This does not imply that clandestine acts cannot be consciencebased. See the example of the illegal abortion performed for purely altruistic reasons, discussed in Wasserstrom The Journal of Philosophy 1961 641 at 645. 49 As to the communicative aspect of civil disobedience, see HA Bailey "Confrontation as an extension of communication" in Bosmajian Dissent 181. 50 See Bedau The Journal of Philosophy 1961 653 at 655 and Cohen Civil disobedience 16. Because the Boston Tea Party was carried out under cover of darkness, it cannot be classified as an example of civil disobedience, as was suggested by Cohen Civil disobedience 37. See also Bedau The Journal of Philosophy 1972 179 at 183. democratic character, in the sense that an appeal is made to the body politic to reconsider its position. The self-imposed adversary to vulnerability elevate consciousness. The of their question the civil conflict here is disobedient to not the who forces level is of his moral physically the strongest, but instead who is morally more powerful. Hence Rawls saw civil disobedience as "a political action which addresses the sense of justice of measures majority protested dissenters honored." The the the and in to conditions order warn of to urge that in social reconsideration the firm opinion co-operation are of the of the not being 51 element disobedience of openness that the makes it protester part should of the not definition actively try of civil to evade punishment, at least not through illegal means such as escaping or concealing evidence. This does not mean, however, that he must insist on being punished. It win later be argued that behaviour such as pleading guilty and asking for the maximum sentence to be imposed could enhance the justification of civil disobedience and might also make civil disobedience more effective. That, however, does not affect the definition of civil disobedience. 52 D. MOTIVATED BY CONVICTION The interest which the civil disobedient attempts to advance through his actions are his convictions. An act of civil disobedience is consequently not simply motivated by narrow self-interest or by cruelty or other similar manifestations of spiritual deformity, as is the case as far as the conduct of the common criminal is concerned. The term "conviction" carries a wide and not necessarily a precise meaning. In essence it involves convictions concerning the way the world is seen to be or evaluated, as opposed to more mundane personal aspirations. 53 One’s convictions greater or lesser are, of extent course, often determined, influenced, by one’s or own even to a self-centred interests. In fact, most of the participants in the classic examples of 51 J Raw1s "The justification of civil disobedience" in Beauchamp Ethics and public policy 132 at 132. 52 See also Dworkin A matter of principle 115. 53 On the meaning of the term "conscience", see Burger JCRDL 1991 512. civil disobedience that will be considered in the historical section, had a personal interest in the positive outcome of their respective campaigns. Nevertheless, as civil disobedients they also maintained that their aims were objectively and morally justified, and not merely subjectively convenient or desirable. disobedient to act on behalf of a group. It is typical of the civil 54 The fact that conduct is motivated by conviction does not, of course, carry with it any guarantees of its acceptability. Convictions that lead to breaking of the law can be good or evil. It will be argued later on that it might in many cases be extremely difficult to find an acceptable criterion for distinguishing the "good" from "bad" convictions, precisely because one is here dealing with basic values. In such cases it might be more feasible to distinguish different acts of disobedience on the basis of the type of conviction involved. 55 With a view to a sliding scale of importance to the individual concerned, one could distinguish convictions which form part of one’s i) integrity; ii) opinion on the question whether those in power exploit those without power, and iii) convictions in respect of matters of policy. 56 On basis of his distinction three different types of civil disobedience can be identified: - Integrity-based civil disobedience, which is motivated by the belief that compliance with a particular law or system of laws would seriously damage or even destroy what one might call one’s "moral wholeness", for example by requiring one to commit sin or to be an instrument of injustice. Disobedience in this case is regarded as the only means of preventing the moral catastrophe which compliance would entail. This is the category of one's most deeply held beliefs "ultimate concerns". 57 - conscience par excellence or one’s As will be demonstrated hereafter. Western thinking for a very long time professed that only religious values could be of such importance in people’s lives. However, the modern understanding of freedom of conscience brought with it 54 See Weingartner Columbia University Arendt Crises of the republic 76. 55 See infra chap six III A. 56 See Dworkin A matter of principle 102. 57 See infra chap four IV C. Forum 1966 38 at 39 and greater recognition of the basic role which secular beliefs can play in people’s lives. On this basis we can further distinguish between religious and secular integrity-based civil disobedience. As will be demonstrated later on, this distinction is of particular importance in the field of conscientious objection to military service. 58 Insofar as the beliefs that prompted acts of civil disobedience have not acquired the status of an "ultimate concern", one can also distinguish justice-and policy-based civil disobedience: - Anti-exploitation civil disobedience is premised on the belief that those who rule are oppressing or exploiting those subject to their rule. The claim is made that those in power are benefiting themselves at the expense of the powerless. The exploitation that may occasion this kind of disobedience can take on one of two possible forms: - It can involve suppression of the majority by the minority (as in apartheid South Africa), or - it can involve suppression of the minority by the majority (as in the United States as far as the Civil Rights Movement was concerned). - Policy-based civil disobedience does not involve the claims that the government is compromising integrity, or that it is exploiting those who are ruled. Instead, it is alleged that those who are in power are misguided in acting in a certain way. E. POLITICAL ACT Certain acts of protest are illegal, non-violent, open and motivated by conviction, but, nevertheless, can not be described as instances of civil disobedience in the ordinary meaning of the word. A case in point would be that of someone who breaks the speed limit to take an injured person to hospital. 59 What is lacking in that case, and in many others where the traditional grounds of justification of criminal law apply, is a political dimension. An act of civil disobedience is political in the sense that it challenges the authority of the government - either 58 See infra chap four IV. 59 Compare the facts of S v Pretorius 1975 2 SA 85 (SWA). because the disobedient believes that the government leaves him no choice but to ignore its enactments, or because he exerts himself to challenge the government. Politically motivated acts can be either defensive, in the sense that the person concerned refuses to comply with a particular legal requirement because he considers that requirement to be wrong, but he has no intention of bringing about any changes; or they can be resultoriented, in the sense that the objective sought to be achieved by one's protest is to bring about changes in the social system." 60 In the first instance the disobedient person’s objectives are, so to speak, "private" or "internal"; in the second they are "public" or "external". On basis of this distinction one can differentiate between, what may be called, defensive and result-oriented civil disobedience. In the case of defensive civil disobedience there is no intention to confront the authorities (even if that is the eventual consequence of one’s act). 61 The perpetrator does not "go out of his way" to break the law and to seek confrontation. The motivation is deontological, in the sense that the person who acts illegally does so irrespective of any possible consequences. 62 He simply wants to avoid the moral debasement of compliance. A good example in this regard is the position taken by the Jehova’s Witnesses in respect of military service, which has been characterised as follows: "Ons neem niemand kwalik wat wel mititere diens doen nie; ons opponeer ook geen regering se militere aktiwiteite nie; ons wil ook niemand afraai om militere diens te doen nie - maar vir ons is dit sonde." 63 This type of civil disobedience can also be called "non-cooperational". In the case of result-oriented civil disobedience, the illegal action involves a deliberate choice on the part of the protester to break the 60 See Smith Fordham Law Review 1968 707 at 719. Gandhi used the terms "defensive" and "aggressive" civil disobedience. See Gandhi Nonviolent resistance 175. 61 There is, so to speak, at the most dolus indirectus to confront the authorities. 62 MacGuigan The Canadian Bar Review 1971 222 at 272 called obedience not aimed at results, "expressive" civil disobedience. This seems too strong a term, since the person involved might not even want to "express" himself, but might simply see detection to be unavoidable. 63 See Potgieter & Munnik Militere dienspllg en dienswelering 13. law in order to make a statement. He, so to speak, "goes out of his way" to "seek confrontation". 64 The action is consequentialist; it is aimed at bringing about a specific social effect. Any one of the major campaigns of civil disobedience that will be discussed could serve as an example of this type of civil disobedience. Gandhi rejected the term "passive resistance" as a description for his own acts of defiance, because he regarded his approach as active and confrontational. 65 His civil disobedience was consequently result- oriented. Two types of result-oriented civil disobedience may be distinguished on the basis of the mechanism through which change is primarily affected: sacrificial and symbolic civil disobedience. Sacrificial civil disobedience depends for its effectiveness on martyrdom. By willingly placing his life, freedom or possessions on the line, the protester legitimises his cause as something which is worth such a sacrifice. Traditionally most instances of civil disobedience took this form. To Gandhi, for example, civil disobedience was "a terrifying synonym for suffering". 66 Civil disobedience can also challenge and change the system simply because the person who defies the state is seen as a normal and respected member of society - he is "one of us". The ritual of the criminal trial is designed to bring about "reality reparation" - that is, to reconfirm to society what its values are. 67 It identifies to the dominant group who the "good guys" and the "bad guys" are. In this sense the criminal trial reveals more about those who conduct it than about those who are being tried. If a normal member of society is branded as an outlaw, the security which this mechanism normally provides is undermined. If such a person is on the other side of the 64 As to the meaning of the term "confrontation" in this context, see R L Scott SDK Smith "The rhetoric of confrontation" in Bosmajian Dissent 170. 65 See Gandhi "The theory and practice of passive resistance" in Golden number of "Indian Opinion" 1914 9. 66 67 Gandhi Non-violent resistance 69. See R A Ball "A theory of punishment: restricted reprobation and the reparation of reality" in Brantingham & Kress Structure, law, and power 135 at 143. The same can be said of war. See Reisman Folded lies 24. fence, either we are not as good as we thought, or there must be something wrong with the fence. Even if the actual punishment is negligible, civil disobedience can consequently be deeply disturbing and may provide those in power with a strong incentive to change the system. Resistance which provokes, or attempts to provoke, this type of reaction will be called non-sacrificial civil disobedience. II. COMBINATIONS OF THE DIFFERENT TYPES OF CIVIL DISOBEDIENCE Both defensive and result-oriented civil disobedience can in principle be either integrity-, justice- or policy-based, and in each case it could manifest itself as positive or as negative civil disobedience. In practice, as should be evident from the historical overview, positive civil disobedience is typically result-oriented (as is the case for example with participation in illegal demonstrations), but it can also be defensive (for example someone like Daniel in the Old Testament who prays to his God even though disobedience, on the other it is prohibited). Negative civil hand, will mostly be defensive (as was the case with Daniel's friends who refused to bow to strange gods when ordered to do so), but it can also be result-oriented (as in the Defiance Campaign of 1952, when black South Africans refused to carry passes as prescribed by law). Although it is not entirely clear, since there is no generally accepted terminology in this regard, it seems that a number of writers (i) only regard, what we have called, positive civil disobedience as disobedience proper, while others (ii) confine its meaning to what was termed neither result-oriented of these civil limitations disobedience. 68 of the It meaning is of submitted the term that "civil disobedience" should be applied. Limiting the definition of civil disobedience to those cases where one positively does impracticable and something which unwarranted. It is prohibited by is impracticable law is because, both as is generally accepted in criminal law and the law of delict, a watertight distinction between a positive and a negative act cannot always be 68 See eg Thalberg Scientia 1966 436 at 438 and Van den Haag Rutgers Law Review 1966 27 at 28, 35. Douma Metenskaplike Bydraes van die PU vir CHO 1986 1 at 2 required civi1 disobedience to be "dwingend", in the sense that it annoys the authorities. drawn. 69 Does it, for example, constitute a positive or a negative act to go into an area where one is required to have a special permit without such a permit? The limitation is also unwarranted, because it is clearly counter-intuitive not to regard the actions of those South Africans who refused to carry passes as acts of civil disobedience. Should it then be required that only result-oriented disobedience can qualify as civil disobedience? 70 acts of It is submitted that, although this requirement seems more feasible, it should ultimately also be rejected. It is also both impracticable and unwarranted. It is unworkable because it is often very difficult in real situations to identify with sufficient clarity the motive of an act of disobedience of the law. In reality, the motives in most cases are mixed. It often happens that someone breaks the law to protect himself from moral corruption, but at the same time she acts in a manner that could possibly indicate an attempt to persuade others to follow suit or to exercise pressure on the government to change its behaviour. It is almost impossible in such cases to establish whether that person has crossed the line between defence and offence. More importantly, however, the limitation is also unwarranted. From the perspective of the evaluator of such conduct, there does not seem to be a sufficiently significant qualitative difference between defensive and result-oriented present the disobedience state with to justify essentially the such a distinction. same problem, They namely open defiance state with the problem of a breach of its laws whereby its authority is challenged, irrespective of whether or not that was in fact the intention. It is consequently submitted that, while it is useful to make a loose distinction between positive and negative civil disobedience, and between result-oriented and defensive civil disobedience, the basis of these distinctions cannot be used to define civil disobedience as such. These distinctions differentiation should between rather different be types regarded or as the manifestations basis of of civil disobedience. 69 See Snyman Criminal law 42. See also, in respect of delict. Van der Merwe & 01ivier Die onregmatige daad in die Suid-Afrikaanse reg 29. 70 See eg Raz The authority of law 264, who claimed that civil disobedience must be "designed to have a public effect". In conclusion it should also be noted that all these different types of civil disobedience can be practised either by individuals, in which case it will be called individual civil disobedience, or by groups, in which case it will be called mass civil disobedience. III. CAN CIVIL DISOBEDIENCE HAVE REVOLUTIONARY OBJECTIVES? Up to this point, the elements included in the definition of civil disobedience have been discussed. It is now necessary to highlight a possible element which thus far has not been considered. A considerable number of writers, especially in the American tradition, has argued that civil disobedience as a matter of definition must have the limited aim of only protesting against a certain law or laws. According to, what can for the sake of convenience be called, the American approach, protest directed against the legitimacy of "the existing system as a whole" cannot be civil disobedience, and, because it is revolutionary, should instead be regarded as a different type of political action. 71 Civil disobedience cannot be aimed at, what Thoreau called, a "peaceable revolution"; 72 that is, insofar "revolution" is used to signify qualitative change. as the term 73 If the American approach is correct and applied uncritically to other societies, it would mean that neither Gandhi in his protest against the British Raj in India, nor those engaged in the struggle against apartheid in South Africa, or those who practised civil disobedience against Hitler, would qualify as civil disobedients, because in all these cases defiance of the law was aimed at protesting the existing system as a whole. 74 It would be strange, however, if a form of protest 71 See Dworkin A matter of principle 105 and Rawls A theory of justice 363. See also Keeton Texas Law Review 1965 507 at 508 who required the civil disobedient to stay "within the framework of the prevailing form of government." According to Blackstone Georgia Law Review 1969 679 at 680, "[a] civil disobedient is distinguished from those who advocate rebellion or revolution in that he [does not advance] the overthrow of existing authority." 72 See infra chap three III C (4). 73 The distinction between revolution, which is aimed at replacing the existing system, and rebellion, which is aimed at replacing the personnel of the system, was first drawn by Aristotle The politics 8.1. For other definitions of this term, see Calvert Revolution 16 and Friedrich Revolution 5. 74 It will later be demonstrated that while he was in South Africa, were to be circumscribed in such a way as to exclude some of its most well-known examples. 75 Alternatively, it could be said that application of the American approach to these circumstances would have required those who used civil disobedience first to accept the legitimacy of their opponent’s rule. That is clearly absurd. It is submitted that such conclusions would reflect a confusion regarding the meaning attached by the American writers to the term "the existing system" transferred as a uncritically whole. to American other jurisprudence jurisdictions where cannot be different circumstances prevail. What American writers mean when they say that the civil disobedient must remain loyal to "the existing system" is that he must continue to uphold the basic values of democracy, which to these writers describe their (the Americans’) "existing system". They do not intend to convey that protesters in undemocratic countries can only engage in civil disobedience if they remain loyal to their (the foreigners’) undemocratic systems. 76 Having cleared up this confusion, and accepting that what these writers really meant was that civil disobedients must be loyal to basic democratic values, the fact remains that the question of loyalty to any value system can only affect the justification of such acts and not the definition of civil disobedience. Civil disobedience is a morally neutral tool and can be resorted to for good or bad purposes; to achieve democratic or undemocratic objectives. Two types of resultoriented civil disobedience can be distinguished with a view to the range of the laws objected against: 77 - Reformatory civil disobedience, which is aimed against a particular law or laws or an aspect of the social system. The Civil Rights Movement is an example of this type of civil Gandhi accepted the basic legitimacy of the system of white domination. See chap three infra III A (2)(b). Later he saw civil disobedience as "a symbol of revolt against the state". See Gandhi Non-violent resistance 175. 75 See Arendt Crises of the republic 77. 76 See A Cox "Direct action, civil disobedience, and the constitution" in Cox et al Civil rights, the constitution and the courts 2 at 12. 77 See Sharp The methods of nonviolent action 316. See also Martin Ethics 1969/70 123 at 125 and Macfarlane Political Studies 1968 335 at 335. disobedience, as well as Gandhi’s campaigns in South Africa. The changes envisaged in this instance might even include a change in government if the basic structure which upholds that government is accepted. - Revolutionary civil disobedience, which is directed at the basic structure and laws of the existing political dispensation. Gandhi’s campaigns in India, and the Defiance Campaign of 1952 as well as the Positive Action Campaign of 1960 in South Africa, are examples of this type of civil disobedience. Two types of revolutionary civil disobedience can be distinguished: Anarchistic - civil disobedience, which rejects the legitimacy of all laws, or the idea of law itself. - Non-anarchistic civil disobedience, which aims at replacing the existing structure with another system of law and government. As will be pointed out later on, the occurrence of anarchistic civil disobedience would be very rare - logically there seems to be little reason for someone committed to anarchy to act openly, since he rejects the legitimacy of anything that might, as a result of his actions, be done to him. Whether any of these types of civil disobedience is justified in a particular case, is an entirely different matter and will be addressed later. IV. DIRECT AND INDIRECT CIVIL DISOBEDIENCE Civil disobedience can be used either as a direct or as an indirect tool of political resistance in two different ways. A. CONSIDERATIONS RELATING TO THE LAWS OBJECTED AGAINST Direct civil disobedience in the first sense of the word occurs when the agent violates a law because he believes that particular law to be unjust. Such civil disobedience can either be positive or negative, defensive or result-oriented. Indirect civil disobedience, on the contrary, takes place when the agent breaks a law, not because he believes that particular law to be unjust, but because by doing so he objects against another aspect of political life, such as another law or laws, certain governmental policies, the entire governmental structure, etc. Indirect civil disobedience requires "going out of one’s way" and will inevitably be result-oriented. It can take the form of either negative civil disobedience (for example if one refuses to pay tax in protest against a non-related aspect of government policy) or positive civil disobedience (for example if one takes part in an illegal demonstration aimed at a bill pending in parliament). Indirect civil disobedience in this sense of the word is the only type available when the wrong being protested is the absence of governmental action. 78 As far as the definition of civil disobedience is concerned, there need not be a relationship between the issue giving rise to the civil disobedience and the illegal act itself. This issue will again be addressed when the justification of civil disobedience is considered. 79 B. CONSIDERATIONS RELATING TO THE TARGET OF THE RESISTANCE Civil disobedience can also be direct or indirect in another respect, to which brief reference has already been made. Firstly, however, the dramatis personae disobedience will "disobedient" disobedience "target". or her The should be be called explained. the "protester". conduct target can is be The "civil In person practising disobedient" the case directed at, what either (i) the of or civil simply the result-oriented we will direct call, her adversary or "opponent"; the person, people or institution whose behaviour in the first place caused the civil disobedience, (ii) the potential followers of the protester, whose support she wants to mobilize, or (iii) it could be a congenial third party which is in a position to change the behaviour of the adversary. Such a third party may be called a "benevolent background force". The civil disobedient can address his adversary directly or indirectly in the following way: directly addressing the opponent occurs when the 78 See Cohen Rutgers Law Review 1966 1 at 4 and Weingartner Columbia University Forum 1966 38 at 39. Katz UCLA Law Review 1985 904 at 906 wrongly described the lunch-counter sit-ins of the Civi1 Rights Movement as an example of direct civil disobedience. As will be demonstrated, the only crime possibly committed during the sit-ins was trespassing, while the demonstrations were directed against de facto segregation practices. See infra chap three III C (6)(c). 79 See infra chap six III B (2). aim of civil disobedience is primarily to bring about a change of heart in the opponent without any outside interference. Indirectly addressing the opponent occurs when civil disobedience is primarily aimed at mobilising supporters or persuading a "benevolent background force" to in a positive way exercise its leverage with the adversary. 80 Protesters often make use of indirect civil disobedience aimed at a benevolent background force, operate a imminent success, as on form of exposing the because civil critique: difference it between disobedience is can dependent, pretense only for and its reality, between the values the target professes to adhere to and his actual deeds. Civil disobedience works like Plato’s idea of education - it can only awake and arouse that which is, at least latently, already there. It cannot create humanity in an opponent where there none. 81 is Consequently, civil disobedience has very little chance of success if used directly against a ruthless opponent. Since the opponent in cases where legal resistance is no longer considered feasible is often ruthless, it is only natural that the indirect address system would be the most common manifestation of civil disobedience. An appeal through civil disobedience to a benevolent background force can take many forms: it can be Gandhi who mobilises British opinion against Smuts (in the case of South Africa) or world opinion against Britain mobilise (in the the case of electorate India); against it his can be direct Thoreau who opponent, wishes the to American government, or it can be Martin Luther King attempting to activate public opinion and the federal government against his opponents, the Southern local authorities. It will be argued that mass civil disobedience in this century was in most cases also aimed at mobilising the world community, as a type of global "benevolent background force", against the more direct opponents, namely the national governments. Although the third party might ultimately act coercively against the direct opponent, the protester’s actions essentially remain persuasive in the sense that the third party is persuaded and not coerced into 80 81 See Sharp The dynamics of nonviolent action 659. Ndabaningi Sithole observed in 1966: "Nonviolence is an appeal to the moral conscience. If the 'powers that be' have no moral conscience, nonviolence is left without any power whatsoever." See his observations contained in Davis & Baker Southern Africa in transition 240. acting against the opponent. V. THE TERM "CONSCIENTIOUS OBJECTION" To conclude this chapter, the meaning of the term "conscientious objection" and the way in which it is related to "civil disobedience" will be considered. In some cases where people are placed under a positive legal duty to do something which some of them might find particularly objectionable, provision is made for exceptions from direct compliance. This normally takes the form of an alternative way of complying with that particular law. The most obvious example in this regard is the provision made in many societies for alternatives to mandatory military service. 82 In such cases those who qualify for exceptional treatment have a legal alternative to civil disobedience. Often, however, only a limited number of those who find compliance with the law unacceptable qualify for alternative service. The alternative option provided for by law is consequently not open to them. They have to choose between compliance and civil disobedience. The question then arises in respect of which category of persons refusing to comply the term “conscientious objection” be applied. A variety of different approaches are proposed by writers on the subject. - Some commentators restrict the term "conscientious objection" to the actions of those who do qualify for exemption - that is, in the case of military alternative service. 83 conscription, those who qualify for Seen in this way, conscientious objection does not amount to civil disobedience, since such action is legal while civil disobedience is per definition illegal. - Other writers only use the term "conscientious objection" to refer to the actions of those who do not qualify for exemption, and who then act illegally and -at least in the case of military 82 On conscientious objection to compulsory military service in South Africa, see infra chap four IV. In Britain special legal provisions are made for those who object to joining a trade union on religious grounds. See Lloyd Introduction to jurisprudence 146 n 24. 83 Cohen Civil disobedience 41 regarded the term "conscientious objection" as a special expression, generally observed for "acts entirely within the protection of the law". conscription - end up in prison. 84 If this approach were to be followed, "conscientious objection" would be a form of civil disobedience. Conscientious objection would then in fact simply be another name for negative civil disobedience. - The third approach is to distinguish civil disobedience and conscientious objection on the basis that, while both involve illegal action, civil disobedience is always result-oriented while conscientious objection is defensive. If this approach were to be followed, civil disobedience and conscientious objection would be parallel and mutually exclusive terms. The term "civil disobedience" would then be used to refer to, what was termed, "result-oriented "conscientious civil objection" disobedience" would "defensive civil disobedience". then only, cover, and what reflect objection". In the common ordinary was term called, 85 It is submitted that all three approaches are too narrow properly the usage of the term discussions we regard and do not "conscientious as conscientious objectors those who qualify for alternative military service (who are excluded by the first view) as well as those who do not qualify for alternative service and are imprisoned or otherwise punished (who are excluded by the second view). It also seems strange (as is done by those who adhere to the third view) not to regard someone who refuses to do military service for reasons of conscience as a conscientious objector on the grounds that his intention is to make a political statement and to put the government under pressure. In this study the term "conscientious objection" will be used to refer both to those objectors who qualify and those who do not qualify for exemption, irrespective of the question whether they intend through their actions to have a political effect. The actions of those who qualify for exemption win be referred to as "legal conscientious objection", while the actions of those who do not qualify win be called "illegal conscientious objection". Only the last category qualifies as civil disobedience proper, but, for reasons which will appear in due course, both categories of conscientious objection will be considered in this study. 84 See Bedau The Journal of Philosophy 1972 179 at 181 n 3. 85 This approach was considered supra chap one II. VI. SCHEMATIC SUMMARY CIVIL DISOBEDIENCE ("cd") Elements of cd Mainfestations Legalimacy-based cd Legality-based cd Illegality Positive cd Negative cd Coersive cd Non-violence Non-coersive cd Openness Religious Integrity-based cd Secular Motivated by conviction anti-exploitation cd Policy-based cd Defence cd Political act sacrificial Result-oriented cd Non-sacrificial Other manifestations of cd Reformatory cd Anarchic cd Revolutionary cd Non-anarchic cd Direct and indirect cd: Direct cd, which involves a direct breach of the laws objected against Consinderations regarding the laws objected against Indirect cd, objection through is which expressed against certain laws by means of breach of unrelated laws Cd which directly addresses the adversary Considerations regarding the target Cd which address adversary indirectly, by mobilizing one’s own constituency through or a background force” CONSCIENTIOUS OBJECTION (“co”) Illegal co (a form of cd) Legal co (not a form of cd) the by working “benevolent CHAPTER THREE: HISTORICAL SURVEY OF THE DEVELOPMENT OF CIVIL DISOBEDIENCE In this chapter the historical development of against the background of the origins civil disobedience, seen of illegal resistance to authority, will be considered. In accordance with the general focus of this study, the emphasis will be on the development of civil disobedience as an instrument of mass political mobilisation during this century. I. THE ORIGINS OF ILLEGAL RESISTANCE TO AUTHORITY The origins of illegal resistance to authority can be traced to our constitutive represents myths our - the entangled understanding of web our of fact origin. and fiction Irrespective which of the question of their objective validity, these myths, because they reflect the workings of the human spirit in an uninhibited setting, should be taken seriously. They reveal much about the way in which we understand our world and consequently about our deepest nature. 1 Myths have been described as "the common source of morality and religion"; "the most powerful statement of values to which any society commits itself" 2 and "nothing less than a cloak for abstract thought." 3 In many ways myth is the early manifestation of ideology. "Illegality" was earlier defined as attending conduct which is likely to provoke the wrath of the state or the ruler. ancient times, when law, morality, custom and religion were largely fused, transgression of most of the taboos of society was likely to have this effect. It is consequently the myths regarding such actions that are the most pertinent to our inquiry. 1 See Jung Man and his symbols 78; Smith & Weisstub The Western Idea of law v11, 122, 148; Reisman Folded lies 15 and Marti-Ibanez Tales of philosophy 41. By using the term "myth" to describe a particular historical exposition, no opinion is expressed about the question whether it is regarded as true or not - the intention is to signify that reference is being made to an account of facts which might be true or untrue, but which is nevertheless believed by many to be highly significant in their lives. 2 3 Smith & Weisstub The Western idea of law 120. H Frankfort & H A Frankfort "Myth and reality" in Fankfort et_al Before philosophy 11 at 15. Few other subjects have generated so much interest through the ages as authority and humankind’s relationship to it. 4 Obedience and resistance are, for example, the central themes of both religion and politics; the one on a divine and the other on a secular level. It is therefore only to be expected that our most important constitutive myths would centre upon this theme. And indeed, the myth of the disobedient representative human being plays a pivoted role in Christian and Greek portrayals of the sources of human civilization. According to the Christian tradition, human civilization as we know it today started with an act of defiance of God himself, when .humanity’s earliest ancestors broke God’s command not to eat from the tree of the knowledge of good and evil. As punishment for having transgressed this commandment and having attained this knowledge, human beings, according to the Bible, were banished to a life of toil, misery, and eventually death. 5 Similarly, in Greek mythology, civilization, Prometheus from Zeus, stole the fire, supreme the god. basic For Prometheus was subjected to the most severe pain. requirement having done for this, 6 Several observations flow from a consideration of the above. In the first place, both traditions recognise the crucial role that resistance plays in our earthly existence. According to these myths, resistance coincides conceptually, if not chronologically, with authority. Resistance must play a central role in the earthly life of humans, if the archetypical human being will defy what he perceives as the highest authority, namely God, even though this subjects him to the imposition of the highest penalty, namely death. There can be little doubt that a very powerful message about the consequences of disobedience is being portrayed. At the same time, one should be careful not to deduce from the Bible’s portrayal of the events in paradise that any resistance to authority should be seen as "wrong" or "sinful". It is resistance to God which is cast in this light. In paradise God was the only authority, but it belongs to the essence of human life as we now know it that we are subjected to a wide 4For an in-depth discussion of the psychological dimensions of obedience and resistance, see Mitscherlich Society without the father. On the famous Milgram experiments, see migrant Obedience to authority. 5 Genesis 2 & 3. 6 Aeschylus Prometheus bound. See the introduction by G Murray at 9ff. variety of appeals to our obedience. Where the demands of the state, the church, our peer group and our conscience conflict, one often does not have the choice whether to disobey, but simply whom to disobey. Obedience to one order often entails disobedience to the others. In this sense disobedience is an inevitable and central feature of the human condition. Perhaps the most important message emerging from these myths is the fact that, although Adam and Eve and Prometheus tempted divine authority, their actions did make considerable human progress possible. Adam and Eve gained the knowledge of good and evil, which lies at the basis of an ethical society; while Prometheus gave his society the gift of fire, one of the preconditions of civilization. For this progress they did, however, pay dearly. The "moral" seems to be that it is possible to make progress by deviating from the established norm, but only if one is willing to "pay the price". In the dialectical process which characterises human development, disobedience to a particular order can have a charismatic effect, in the sense that the old order can be relativised and a new order can be legitimised. A new right and a new wrong can be created. The precondition for this, however, is suffering. 7 The notion of the creative force of suffering, which lies at the heart of the most common manifestation of civil disobedience as a political instrument, will namely presently be sacrificial, discussed in result-oriented more detail. civil For the disobedience, moment it is intended merely to point out that this notion can be traced to our most fundamental understanding of human origin. II. THE ORIGINS OF CIVIL DISOBEDIENCE It was argued earlier that two main types of civil disobedience should be distinguished: defensive and result-oriented civil disobedience. As will be demonstrated in this chapter, defensive civil disobedience has been practised by individuals and groups throughout history. Resultoriented civil disobedience has a much shorter history and was practised initially only by a small number of extraordinary individuals. It was 7 See eg Gandhi's observation that civil disobedience is a "terrible synonym for suffering" (infra chap three III B (2)(b)) and Lutuli's comment: "No cross, no crown" (infra chap three III A (3)(c)(ii)). only at the mobilised beginning to engage of in this century that result-oriented the civil masses could disobedience. be These historical developments will now be traced. It will be argued that the differences in the developmental patterns of defensive and result- oriented civil disobedience, as far as the numbers of people who were willing to engage in these different forms of protest are concerned, can largely be explained in terms of differences between these forms of resistance. A. AN INTERPRETIVE FRAMEWORK FOR THE HISTORY OF CIVIL DISOBEDIENCE From our ex post facto perspective on history, events from the past often seem either inevitable or wholly contingent; the result either as a manifestation of a predestined master plan for the universe, or simply the outcome of the contingent passions of the moment. The extent to which much of history is the result of rational choices by the individuals involved at the time, based on the facts of the situation as they saw them, is not always taken into consideration. "Rational choices” in this context mean choices which are calculated to attain the maximum fulfilment of the agent's objectives at the minimum personal cost. These choices can still make sense if the conditions under which they were made are properly taken into account. The historical patterns according to which individuals or groups adhered to defensive or result-oriented civil disobedience, when and where they did, can largely be explained in terms of such rational choices, made by people throughout history who had to establish the feasibility of particular forms of protest in their circumstances. The two crucial factors which affect people’s willingness to engage in certain types of resistance are the personal risk to which such actions expose the resister and the likelihood of success. The higher the risk and the lower the prospects of achieving one’s goals, associated with a particular form of protest, the less attractive such protest becomes. The fact that defensive civil disobedience has been practised throughout history by groups and individuals, but mass result-oriented civil disobedience was practised in this century for the first time, can be explained in terms of this truism. It was noted earlier that civil disobedience is a form of immanent critique which can only be effective against a morally sensitive target. Insofar as the objective is to change the behaviour of the adversary, it follows that practising this form of protest only makes sense in a situation where the target is susceptible to moral pressure. Defensive civil disobedience is mostly encountered where the objective is to preserve one’s “ultimate concerns" or integrity. The fundamental nature of this concern implies that the issue of personal risk is often considered to be of secondary importance. In order not to betray their deepest convictions, people are often even prepared to die. Moreover, since the resistor’s goal is not to change the prevailing social circumstances, but merely to avoid the moral pollution of compliance, the moral sensitivity - or lack of such sensitivity - is irrelevant. "Success" for the resister lies simply in saving his own integrity through non-compliance. The conduct of the defensive resister is consequently not as dependent on the response which it is likely to provoke as is the case with the result-oriented resister. In this sense defensive civil disobedience is ahistorical. It could be expected to be engaged in throughout history, by any number of people who consider their basic convictions to be sufficiently threatened. Different considerations arise in respect of result-oriented civil disobedience. The objective of this form of disobedience is typically to protest against alleged exploitation and policy decisions of the government. Because the objectives pursued are not as fundamental as is the case with integrity-based disobedience, personal risk becomes more relevant. But perhaps more importantly, the intention with result- oriented disobedience is indeed to bring about social change, which means that the political circumstances in which this type of civil disobedience is practised could become highly relevant to the rational agent concerned with a view to his prospects of success. The use of result-oriented civil disobedience would to a large extent be determined by prevailing political circumstances, and particularly by the question how morally sensitive the target is. If the target is perceived to be susceptible to moral appeals, resultoriented resistance becomes attractive, because the chances of "success" in bringing about the envisaged change might then become big enough to offset the personal cost, namely the punishment likely to be imposed. Conversely, if the prospective target is considered ruthless, result-oriented civil disobedience becomes unattractive. This form of resistance is consequently historically determined. The term "success" in the above exposition should be given a wide meaning. Since we are dealing with political resistance, which often takes the form of attempts to have one set of values prevail over another, it is submitted that not only immediate positive results should count as success, but also the setting into motion of a process that will probably eventually bring about change, even if that change is not witnessed by the agent himself. In this context, even martyrdom might be regarded as "rational" if the person concerned considers change as sufficiently crucial and martyrdom is a likely way in which it can be effected. How, then, does the historical outline of the development of resultoriented civil disobedience reflect such rational choices made by the people involved? It is submitted that in antiquity result-oriented civil disobedience was not practised because of the limited prospects of bringing about moral conversion of the opponent through illegal action. Illegal resistance of any kind was inevitably viewed by the rulers as tantamount to treason, and the penalty would mostly be death. Death of the disobedient was also unlikely to exercise a positive influence on the opponent, either immediately or later. The rulers of the time were ruthless and insensitive to outside moderating influences. Because of their likely reaction, they were either resisted by the use of force or disobeyed in secret, or both. Only when visionary individuals at the beginning of our year count perceived the emergence of a new, kinder order, would they engage in result-oriented civil disobedience. The isolated instances of disobedience, exemplified by the actions of a Socrates or the heroes of Christianity, indicates that such conduct must have been rare indeed. Such persons often had to pay the highest toll without witnessing the eventual success of their ideals. Not surprisingly, the masses could not be persuaded to do the same. Given the strength of their convictions, it was “rational" for these individuals to engage in civil disobedience, even if they were to pay the highest price. To the less idealistic masses the chances of success, measured against the likely punishment to be imposed, were still too remote. Result-oriented civil disobedience became a realistic option to the proverbial person in the street in the Twentieth Century. It is submitted that only in this century people like Gandhi and King could mobilise ordinary people with family and other commitments to engage in non-violent protest, because, due to the new emphasis on human rights and the development of enforcement mechanisms, the prospects of success of civil disobedience became significantly higher, and the probable punishment less extreme. At least in two respects there was a dramatic increase in the global human rights culture and the level of moral activism in the Twentieth Century. In universal the first franchise place, and this century meaningful saw the introduction of protection of institutional individual rights. Inevitably, the more liberal governments were the ones confronted sufficiently with morally civil disobedience sensitive to render campaigns. the They practice of were result- oriented civil disobedience feasible. At the same time, important events also occurred on the international front. In village" this or century, for international the first community time was in history, established. a "global This was manifested in the emergence of structures such as the United Nations Organization. In an increasingly interdependent world, it would become more necessary as well as easier for the international community to involve itself in what was traditionally considered to be the domestic affairs of nations, namely their human rights practices. This process was greatly assisted by the powerful role which the international media started to play. Injustice now started to lose its localized nature and the adagium became popular that "human rights know no boundaries". It is only natural that, once the world was locked into a single moral unit, norms could be established that would aim at some consistency and hence equality in the way in which people were treated, and that international pressure would be exercised in that direction. Although often hesitatingly, the emergent world community itself would act as a type of universal benevolent background force to which protesters who were not likely to succeed on a national level could appeal. Only in this century would indirect civil disobedience, whereby a protester aims his civil disobedience at the international community who in turn then pressurises the direct opponent or national government, have the prospect of success. Of course, injustice remains rife. Many conflicts exist in which the use of civil misplaced. widespread disobedience Nevertheless, goodwill exists would at to probably least in make civil be some naive cases, disobedience and totally sufficiently on a fairly widespread level feasible and likely to obtain results. As win be illustrated, it was only when the opportunities offered by these new developments were pointed out to the masses by people like Gandhi, that mass civil disobedience was practised. With this overview interpretative of the framework development of in mind, the a general different historical types of civil disobedience will next follow. B. DEFENSIVE CIVIL DISOBEDIENCE Although illegal political resistance in antiquity (and in fact throughout history) was often violent and motivated by narrow selfinterest, it is interesting to note that the oldest example of resistance to secular authority known to us, which comes from Judaism, was non-violent and motivated by conviction. 8 Pharaoh, during the time of the Diasphora, ordered the Hebrew midwifes to kill all the Jewish male newborns immediately on delivery. According to the Bible "the midwifes, however, feared God and did not do what the king of Egypt had told them to do." 9 When asked about the boys who lived, the midwifes lied to Pharaoh and their fives were saved. 10 As was the case when the first acts of resistance were considered, a parallel may again be found in the Hellenistic tradition. In the Fifth Century, Sophocle’s Antigone -considered by many to be the archetype of civil disobedience 11 - defied King Creon’s prohibition on the burial of her brother, whom Creon regarded as a traitor. In the dark she threw sand on the body of her brother. Antigone, however, was caught and brought before Creon. She showed few signs of repentance and told Creon: I didn’t suppose your decree had strength enough, or you, who are human, to violate the lawful traditions the gods have not written merely, but made infallible. These laws are not for now or for yesterday, they are alive forever; and no one knows when they were shown to us first. 12 8 For an account of the origins of political revolution in Egypt, see Calvert Revolution 16ff. 9 Exodus 1.17. 10 Exodus 1.19. 11 See eg Cover Justice accused 1. 12 Sophocles Antigone lines 555-561. In these acts of non-violent political resistance we have, in embreotic form, the origins of civil disobedience in both the Judaist and in the Hellenistic traditions. These myths, however, portray instances of defensive rather than result-oriented resistance. Result-oriented civil disobedience would involve the introduction of an additional element, namely open confrontation. C. INDIVIDUAL, RESULT-ORIENTED CIVIL DISOBEDIENCE The non-violent actions of the midwives and of Antigone would later be echoed, in their respective traditions, in the conduct of persons such as Daniel and his friends and the heroes of the New Testament on the one hand, and events surrounding the death of Socrates on the other. What was new in this development was the introduction of the element of deliberate and open confrontation, aimed at bringing about a new order. In essence the idea was now introduced that martyrdom - which more often than not was the inevitable result of open confrontation - could be used to bring about social change. 13 This idea was described earlier as the core idea of sacrificial result-oriented civil disobedience. The effect which acts of civil disobedience that resulted in martyrdom played in the development of Western civilization is indeed remarkable, as is the extent to which those who engaged in it were "successful" in promoting their persuasions. Civil disobedience is often seen as a form of destructive protest established legal and which only serves to undermine respect for political institutions, while its role can in fact be highly constructive. Sacrificial civil disobedience, involving martyrdom, has served to establish some of the most crucial pillars of the modern world order. Martyrdom entails the normally regarded as sacrifice an for unqualified a certain human cause good, such of as something liberty, freedom, health or life itself. The fact that someone is willing to "pay the highest price" - to sacrifice his life - in the pursuit of a certain ideal, affords to that ideal the quality of highest value. The sight of blood that is spilled for a certain cause affects the human mind at its deepest levels of consciousness. 14 It is difficult to 13 In Greek "martyr" means "witness". For a discussion of the proper translation, see Vivian St Peter of Alexandria 216. 14 See Reisman Emory Law Journal Weisstub The Western idea of law 129. 1983 499 at 519 and Smith & discard a cause for which someone died, for to tantamount to discarding the value of life itself. do so could be 15 Two types of martyrs and martyrdom should be distinguished. In the first place there are those who do not take the final decision to bring the ultimate sacrifice themselves. Although such an occurrence can make a great contribution toward mobilising loyalty for their cause among their followers, they should, to the extent that they declined to take a final decision to make the sacrifice themselves, be regarded as victims rather than true martyrs. 16 The true martyr is the person, like Socrates or Christ, who takes the final decision to pay the highest price himself. It is to this second category that the sacrificial civil disobedient, who decides to break the law knowing that the consequences to himself would be serious, belongs. At crucial junctures in the history of Western civilization, prophets of a new order peacefully, but also openly and deliberately, defied the demands of older, more exclusive orders to which they were subjected, in obedience to new, more inclusive orders, fully realising that they will pay with their blood for such defiance. By bringing this sacrifice, they relativised the older orders and legitimised the new orders which they propagated. Through their defiance they created a new right and a new wrong. Seen on a purely secular level, the phenomenon of result-oriented, sacrificial civil disobedience is particularly visible in the JudeoChristian tradition. At a time when the tribes of Israel were dispersed and without a common loyalty, Abraham defied the claims which his family and his own immediate happiness made on him. In obedience to "the God of Israel" he agreed to sacrifice his son. 17 After his absolute obedience to God had been demonstrated in this dramatic way, it was no longer necessary to actually bring the sacrifice. The point had been made - the supreme position of the God that would unify Israel had been established. Throughout Jewish history, Abraham served as an inspiration and a reminder that one’s ultimate loyalty should be to 15 See Heyns Die Suid-Afrikaan April 1989 43 at 43. 16 In the South African context people like Steve Biko were victims rather than martyrs. 17 See Genesis 22. Jop1e Fourie and that which unifies the group and not to one’s own parochial interests. 18 In time, as the world developed and became more populated, the order of Israel would in turn become too restrictive and exclusive. The time had arrived for a new world order which would transcend existing barriers. This most inclusive order would be brought into existence through the greatest possible sacrifice: a double, divine sacrifice. Through Christ’s defiance of the dictates of the church and the establishment of his time, and his consequent death on the cross. God the Father would sacrifice his Son, and God the Son would sacrifice himself in pursuit of such a new world. This most dramatic event in Western spiritual life would inspire much of the world with a world-view in which all people are linked to each other as the children of one God. This new world order would be founded on the idea of love that transcends all differences - also the distinction between Jew and Muslim, freeman and slave - now and to eternity. That is, after all, the ideal for which Jesus died. The disobedience of Christ to the dictates of the more restrictive order in obedience to a higher order, and his subsequent martyrdom on the cross, is the central pillar of strength of the Christian faith and Christian values. 19 The Judeo-Christian tradition constitutes what is traditionally considered to be the more mystical side of Western civilization, which to some extent might explain the role which martyrdom played in this tradition. What is remarkable, though, is that the same phenomenon also played a crucial role in the legitimation of new orders in the Hellenistic tradition, which is normally considered the more rational side of Western civilization. One of the most influential aspects of the legacy of Greek philosophy is Plato’s account of the events surrounding the death of Socrates, as portrayed in the "Apology", "Crito" and "Phaedo". 20 In "Crito" the scene is described where Socrates, having been sentenced to death, is visited 18 See Reisman Emory Law Journal 1983 499 at 517. 19 For interpretations of the meaning of the martyrdom of Christ, see Horbury & McNeil Suffering and martyrdom in the New Testament 9, 70, 118. 20 For an analysis of the meaning of these events, see Reisman Emory Law Journal 1983 499; A D Woozley "Socrates on disobeying the law" in Vlastos The philosophy of Socrates 299 and Woozley Law and obedience. by one of his best friends, Crito. Although he was charged with crimes such as corrupting the youth, it is widely agreed that Socrates was convicted and sentenced to death because of his political unpopularity, which was the result of his relentless examination of all aspects of life and his exposure of what he considered to be false certitudes. Crito begged Socrates to escape from prison and from Athens - something that could be arranged and which apparently would not be against the wishes of the authorities, who simply wanted to get Socrates out of the way. Crito argued that Socrates owed it both to his family and his friends to escape. Crito reminded Socrates of the opportunities he had missed to avoid his eventual predicament. The first possibility had been to escape from the city before the trial (as many people who faced the prospects of a similar fate had done 21); the second possibility had been conducted to have his trial differently (Socrates inter alia claimed in the course of the trial that he should be granted a pension by the city of Athens as a reward for his good work). Now Socrates was offered a third opportunity, namely to escape execution - an opportunity which, according to Crito, he should not allow to pass by. 22 In a seminal statement on the importance of conscience, Socrates told his friends: "I cannot ‘mind my own business’." What he was convicted for - his examination of truth and goodness - "is really the very best thing that a man can do, and ... life without this sort of examination is not living." 23 worth He could consequently not comply with the dictates of the state. However, he could also not escape. Socrates argued that he could not do this, because "one ought not to return a wrong or an injury to any person, obedience whatever to the the state provocation and all is." 24 its He laws, argued since that "any one owes Athenian, on 21 Aristotle for one would do this when he later face essentially the same charges as Socrates. His explanation was: "Athens must not sin a second time against philosophy." See Strauss & Cropsey History of political philosophy 64. 22 See Plato's Socrates 44 B. 23 "Crito", reprinted See Plato's "Apology", Socrates 71 at 72. 24 Id 48 E. in reprinted Plato in The Plato last The days last days of of attaining to manhood and seeing for himself the political organization of the state and ... its laws, is permitted, if he is not satisfied with [it] to take his property and go away wherever he likes." 25 To escape would have involved the breach of a covenant with the state to obey all its disadvantage. laws, even when occasionally they work to one’s Consequently Socrates asked Crito: Suppose that while we were preparing to run away from here ... the laws and constitution of Athens were to come and confront us and ask the question: "Now Socrates, what are you proposing to do? Can you deny that by this act which you are contemplating you intend, so far as you have the power, to destroy us, the laws, and the whole state as well? Do you imagine that a city can continue to exist and not be turned upside down, if the legal judgements which are pronounced in it have nullified and destroyed by private persons?" no force but are 26 In a scene, the drama an ethos of which is surpassed only by that of the cross, Socrates, surrounded by his friends, then drank the hemlock and died. 27 This portrayal of the last hours of Socrates has become one of the most important images of Western civilization. Socrates has become the doyen of both obedience to the law and civil disobedience. 28 The crucial factor which makes this seemingly impossible combination tenable to many, was Socrates’ willing acceptance of the punishment meted out to him. It was through his willing acceptance of martyrdom that he managed to preserve not only his own convictions but also the idea that law should be respected. By "paying the price" for disobedience Socrates reaffirmed his respect for the law. Socrates looms large as the archetype of the Western concept of the citizen. In Socrates’ refusal to deny his conscience on the one hand 25 Id 51 D. 26 Id 89. 27 This is described in the concluding pages of Plato's "Phaedo", reprinted in Plato The last days of Socrates 99. The impact of the closing scenes of Socrates' life on later generations is discussed by F C Doherty in his introduction to Plato The martyrdom of Socrates 1. 28 See also, however, Du Plessis SALJ 1980 423 and Olsen Georgia Law Review 1984 929 for more critical views. and his decision to drink the hemlock on the other, the two spheres of political life are portrayed: the private sphere of conscience, which is beyond the control of the state, as well as the public realm, which recognises the binding power of political obligation. The way in which Socrates’ death was portrayed has in an especially powerful way legitimised the idea of obedience to the state. As Michael Reisman observed, Plato’s description of Socrates’ death is an outstanding example of political propaganda, which operates primarily on the emotional level. 29 If subjected to analysis, Socrates’ arguments are less than compelling. In the first place, continued residence in the country of one’s birth seems to be flimsy ground on which to base an obligation to obey all its laws. As Adam Smith observed: To say that by staying in a country obedience to government is just the ship and after he is at a distance being in the ship he had contracted a man agrees to a contract of same as carrying a man into a from land to tell him that by to obey the master. 30 Moreover, a single instance in which the legal system is circumvented is hardly likely to bring about the downfall of the entire legal system. According to Michael Reisman, that idea "seems to be animated by the primitive notion that infraction of sacred rites even by a mild deviation will consequences." 31 anger the gods who will let loose the gravest Indeed, this aspect of the portrayal of Socrates' death leads one to suspect that what Plato, as a political artist and as an opponent of democracy, tried to convey was that political obligation was as stringent as religious obligation. Obviously Socrates’ point could not have been that individual laws should never be disobeyed. He himself broke the law, and during his trial he made it clear that he would break the law again if necessary. What Socrates did argue, and for which he sacrificed his life, was that although the individual must remain true to his own conscience, at the same time the authority of the state has to be accepted. Disobedience was acceptable only if one was prepared to be punished for it. The fundamental message of "Crito", then, is that the laws of a political 29 See Reisman Emory Law Journal 1983 499 at 509. 30 Quoted id 514 n 18. 31 Id 515. community should be the object of one’s highest and ultimate earthly loyalty. Socrates lived institution and was Plato still in wrote at strong a time when competition, the for the state as an individual's highest loyalty, with smaller social units to which the individual belonged, such as the family and the tribe. Plato’s political objective was to assure the position of dominance for the state. As Reisman put it: Could this be made more dramatic than by having the wisest of men sacrifice himself to vindicate the authority of [the] state and the effectiveness of its laws even when they are wrong? Plato, who was committed to this super-ordination of the state over the older formations, thus uses the dialogue as political art to reinforce commitments to the city-state. 32 Consequently, the death of Socrates served to promote the idea of the legitimacy of the state as a more inclusive order vis-a-vis the older, more restricted social groupings. Socrates’ self-sacrifice was transformed by Plato into one of the most powerful instances in history where disobedience and consequent martyrdom was used to bring about social change. Given the circumstances of the era (and his own political biases), it is perhaps understandable that Plato chose to convey the message of the need for obedience in such strong terms. The enormous scale and impact of the idea he tried to establish could have necessitated the device of martyrdom in order to be effective. However, it will later be argued that martyrdom is by no means a requirement for legitimate civil disobedience. D. PLICATION The above sets out, by means of the most dramatic examples available, the role which acts of sacrificial, result-oriented civil disobedience played in shaping history and legitimising new orders. It remains to account for the absence of the element of open confrontation in the early cases of the Hebrew midwives and Antigone, and its presence in the later cases of Christ and Socrates. What prompted the switch from defensive to result-oriented civil disobedience? According to Daube, a pattern can be identified in the instances of the 32 Id 516. (Original emphasis.) Hebrew midwives and Antigone which cannot be accidental, since both occurred in completely distinct civilizations. 33 At a time when men were by far the dominant actors, the agents committing these first acts of political disobedience were women, and the opponents, in fact, were men. Consequently, he regarded non-violent, conscience-based resistance to threats to one’s conscience as essentially female. They are anticonfrontational, anti-war, life-preserving. 34 and In short, the contention is that the midwives and Antigone avoided open confrontation because they were women. Conversely, the main actors in the later introduction of the element of open confrontation - Socrates and Christ - were males, and confrontation and martyrdom is seen as typically male pursuits. If this is correct, synthesis result-oriented of suppression. civil characteristically The element of disobedience female and non-coercion can male is be seen as responses female, a to that of confrontation is male. The idea of there being an essentially female element at the heart of civil disobedience someone like perceived a resistance. 35 does find Gandhi, who more female component some than in support two his in the thousand own observations years non-violent later of also political At the same time, Gandhian civil disobedience was largely rejected in the male dominated African society, in favour of a more 33 Daube Civil disobedience in antiquity 5. 34 Id 18. 35 Fischer remarked that Gandhi combined the masculine and the feminine. He often compared himself to a mother, and wrote to a friend: "I hope you have not missed the women in me." See Fischer Gandhi 129. In his Freudian study of Gandhi's youth, Wolfenstein The revolutionary personality 144, 157 indicated that Gandhi modelled himself after his mother and thought of himself in feminine terms. Wolfenstein regarded non-violent resistance as essentially female. On Gandhi’s desire to find a way to express motherly love, see Chatterjee Gandhi's religious thought 89. See also Gandhi Non-violent resistance 325. Martin Luther King's father told him: "Well you didn't get this non-violence from me, you must have got it from your mama." See "The Martin Luther King no one knows" The Washington Monthly October 1988. As win be Indicated later, the Civil Rights Movement in the United States was introduced by a woman and the first Instance of African mass civil disobedience in South Africa occurred when women protested against the pass laws in 1913. militant approach. 36 Although there is a certain intuitive plausibility in this view, the stereotype of female passivity versus male aggression and inclination towards martyrdom seems too crude, without further unpacking, to carry the full weight of what it tries to explain. Why, as rational actors, would the women concerned have preferred not to act confrontational, while the men were willing to do so and engage in martyrdom? Perhaps some cue can be gained by asking whether this difference of approach can be identified only by comparing the conduct of men and women, or can it also be accounted for in other contexts? It should be noted that a marked difference of approach in this regard also exists between the people of the Old and the New Testament; between Judaism and Christianity. As a general rule, open, non-violent confrontation and consequently martyrdom is much more prominent and acceptable in the New Testament than is the case in the Old Testament. 37 Judaism is a martyr-religion only in the limited sense of the word of its inspiring its adherents to engage, where necessary, in bearing witness to their faith in what we have described as defensive civil disobedience. To Christianity, martyrdom, however, is also a way to do missionary adherents. work 38 and to evangelize - that is, to win over new Christian civil disobedience is more result-oriented. The heroes of Judaism, with its emphasis on both the spirit and the body, were typically survivors. 39 This was evident from the history of 36 See Infra chap three III A (3)(c)(ii). 37 Perhaps the most famous words on the role of martyrdom in Christianity are those of Tertullian: "The blood of martyrs is indeed the seed of the church. Dying we conquer. The moment we are crushed, that moment we go forth victorious." Quoted in Workman Persecution In the early church 143. The trials and the last words of the early martyrs were recounted in great detail in the early church, where it served as an inspiration. For an investigation of some of these trials, see Bisbee Pre-Decian acts of martyrs and commentarii. The central role of martyrdom in the Christian faith is discussed by various commentators in Horbury & McNeil Suffering and martyrdom in the New Testament. See also Pillay Wetenskaplike Bydraes van die PU vir CHO 1990 113. 38 See the fascinating discussion of this theme by G W H Lamps "Martyrdom and inspiration" in Horbury & McNeil Suffering and martyrdom in the New Testament 118. 39 See Daube Civil disobedience In antiquity 79. Abraham, who eventually found a ram to slaughter in the place of Izak. 40 Daniel, who came closest to direct confrontation and to sacrificing his life for his religious convictions, eventually survived. This, however, was not because his willingness to die changed the heart of his opponent, but occurred only through a deus ex machina. Judaism also rejected Christ the martyr. Judaism avoided martyrdom as far as possible, and was not premised on the idea of the creative force of suffering - or at least not to the same extent as Christianity. Consequently, the figures of the Old Testament either acted illegally in secret, or resorted to violence. The traditional heroes of Christianity, on the other hand, with its strong emphasis on the spirit, were martyrs who sacrificed the flesh. This was the Christians. 41 case not only with Christ, but also with the first Christianity had drawn heavily on the Greek tradition, where the voluntary death of Socrates served as the ultimate model of the price a citizen had to pay if he wanted to bring about change in his society. How should it be understood, then, that result-oriented civil disobedience is traditionally uncommon amongst women and Jews? Is there a mean denominator between the circumstances of these two groups which can provide a rational answer to this question? It was suggested earlier disobedience throughout reference the to that the history prospects of can use of result-oriented largely success. It is be civil understood submitted that with the explanation of why women and Jews in antiquity largely eschewed resultoriented or confrontational civil disobedience, lies in the ruthlessness of their traditional enemies, who were unlikely to be moved by their martyrdom. The Hebrew midwives stood very little chance of shaking the absolutism of the Pharaohnic regime; hence they lied when detected. For her part, Antigone, as a woman, was an unlikely counter for Creon, whom she defied in secret. Similarly, the world of the Old Testament was one of an eye for an eye in the Pythagorean 40 41 Genesis 22. See B Lindars "The persecution of Christians in John 15.18-16.4a" in Horbury & McNeil Suffering and martyrdom In the New Testament 48 and T Baumeister "Martyrdom and persecution in early Christianity" in Metz & Schillebeeckx Martyrdom today 3. sense, where mercy played little or no role. 42 In contrast, Socrates’ actions were informed by a world-view in which the good ultimately won, in which no person was intentionally evil. He spent his life on the streets of Athens, where he experienced through the force of his massive intellect the continued susceptibility of people to persuasion. Christianity for its part has as its most basic assumption the brotherhood and sisterhood of all people through a common father. Clearly, such a world-view would be congenial to the prospects of moral persuasion, and consequently to civil disobedience. In short, traditionally the prospects of success of women and Jews, were they to engage in result-oriented and consequently confrontational civil disobedience, were too small to make it a feasible option, even to the most outstanding individuals. Defensive civil disobedience, which, as stated earlier, is independent of political determination, would be practised in essentially unchanged form throughout history. Result-oriented civil disobedience, once established, would be practised on the basis of the persuasive power of martyrdom by individuals with strong convictions. Initially the values pursued through such actions would predominantly be religious, with the most visible example of open defiance emanating from the early Christians who resisted the pagan government in Rome. The early Christians movement in the West. represented 43 the first mass civil disobedience Part of their strategy was to win new adherents, but it was not their prime objective to bring about political change. Only with Gandhi do we find the first instance of mass result-oriented civil disobedience, used as a political tool. The Roman religion, Catholic dominated Church, the after Western Christianity spiritual and, became to a the state considerable extent, also the political world until the Sixteenth Century. Again on the basis of religious conviction, the authority of the Roman Catholic Church would be challenged through open defiance by reformers such as Martin Luther and John Calvin. 42 See, for a sympathetic discussion of the violent history of the Old Testament, E J Crowley "The Old Testament" in Culliton Nonviolence 11. The basis of political power in Biblical Israel is discussed in Weber Power 47ff 43 See C Bay "Civil disobedience" in International Encyclopedia of the Social Sciences vol 2 473 at 473. The emergence of the powerful understanding of the world which modern science, that came with the Renaissance, offered, would fundamentally challenge traditional religious notions, and in a sense became the new religion. New perceptions of reality were established, and, even though some scientists like Galileo were prepared to retract their views when they came into conflict with the prevailing ideas of the time, others, like Bruno, were prepared to die for their convictions. 44 Civil disobedience, however, insofar as it was practised, was still confined to a small number of brave individuals. III. THE MODERN DEVELOPMENT OF MASS, RESULT-ORIENTED CIVIL DISOBEDIENCE The first indication of a new era where not only individual but also mass civil disobedience would be viable was the work of Henry David Thoreau. Writing in Nineteenth Century America, the pioneer of modern democracy, Thoreau saw the possibilities which this new commitment to the value of freedom offered. Calling for mass jail-going by "all just men", he was perhaps the first to express the belief that people could be persuaded on a wide scale to confront the government peacefully and openly in order to secure change. 45 Nevertheless, it seems that the circumstances were not yet conducive to mass protest. Thoreau's appeal would remain a call in the wild. It did not change the present, but it did herald the future. It would only be in the next century that this new approach to the problems of mankind would be followed on a wide scale. Thoreau’s conduct signalled a very important and closely related change which was taking place. Whereas the outstanding earlier examples of civil disobedience almost without exception constituted acts of sacrificial civil disobedience, Thoreau’s conduct can best be described as an example of non-sacrificial civil disobedience. His real impact did not lie in his “suffering" - he spend only one reasonably comfortable night in jail. The force of his conduct lay rather in his message that the decent place to be when the government had passed a certain threshold of unacceptabi1ity, was in prison - and that under 44 On the trial and execution of Bruno, see Boulting Giordano Bruno 262ff. The famous image of Galileo's recanting of his scientific beliefs before the Italian Inquisition is critically discussed by De Santillana The crime of Galileo. His trial is discussed at 237ff. 45 Weber Civil disobedience in America 26. such circumstances it was being out of prison which required explanation. Clearly, if it was possible at least in some societies to engage in civil disobedience without necessarily being martyred, civil disobedience in those societies was becoming a more widely acceptable option. In a word, result-oriented civil disobedience was becoming a more feasible instrument to be used by the masses, because the likely sacrifice was becoming smaller and the prospects of success more real. It has been pointed out that mass result-oriented civil disobedience was first developed in South Africa, after which Gandhi introduced it in India. It has since then been employed in a number of societies, most notably in the United States. The history of civil disobedience in these countries will next be considered in some detail, while a number of other cases will be considered more superficial1y. Particular emphasis will be placed on the conditions which made this development possible - the role of the international community and of morally sensitive targets. A. CIVIL DISOBEDIENCE IN SOUTH AFRICA Three different periods in the history of civil disobedience in South Africa may be distinguished: pre-Gandhian, Gandhian and post-Gandhian. (1) Early forerunners of civil disobedience The Bantu-speaking peoples migrated to the southern part of Africa somewhere between ten and fifteen centuries ago. 46 A great number of separate political societies developed, some of whom had sophisticated social structures and powerful rulers who built vast empires. 47 From the middle of the Seventeenth Century colonists from Europe settled in the southern part of Africa. Through access to superior weapons, effective white control over the area now known as South Africa was established two centuries later, and has been maintained to this day, although there is every reason to believe that major change is now under way. 48 African political resistance, both against black and white rule, has 46 See Davenport South Africa 3ff. 47 Id 57. 48 Id 22ff. traditionally taken the form of violent beginning of the Twentieth Century, uprisings and war. 49 Since the however, the method of civil disobedience came to play a significant role in the political processes of the country, and particularly in the black liberation struggle. The question arises to what extent civil disobedience (as opposed to other forms of resistance) has historical roots in African society. In a later chapter it will be argued that the notion of "Illegal" resistance to traditional political African authority society. voluntary acceptance underlies the of important 50 is But suffering category to what ensures of some about extent the ultimate sacrificial accepted idea that salvation, civil in the which disobedience? Although this idea is not entirely foreign in African culture, it has neither a long nor a happy early history in South Africa. The most outstanding examples in this regard are the history of the legendary figures of Makana and Nongqause. The Xhosa prophet, politician and soldier, Makana (or Makanda or Nxete) is today regarded as one of the heroes of the early struggle against the establishment of white hegemony in the country. At the beginning of the last century, during the border wars in the Eastern Cape, he unsuccessfully tried to capture Grahamstown as part of his attempt to establish a powerful empire. While under hot pursuit by the colonists, Makana one day, to the astonishment of his opponents, appeared in the English camp and gave himself up. He said: "People say that I have occasioned this war. Let me see whether delivering myself up to the conquerors win restore peace to my country." He in effect decided to sacrifice himself for the cause of his people. The effects were not positive. He was sentenced to life imprisonment on Robben Island and 49 On the early history of black political resistance in South Africa, see J C Mbata "Race and resistance in South Africa" in Paden & Soja The African experience vol 1 210; Karis & Carter From protest to challenge vol 1 3ff; Villa-Vicencio Civil disobedience and beyond 14ff; Daniel Radical resistance to minority rule in South Africa 24ff; Hell A history of the ANC 1ff and Davenport South Africa 123ff. See also Walshe The Journal of Modern African Studies 1969 583. For a discussion of the uprisings of slaves at the Cape, see Roux Time longer than rope 27ff. See also Van Jaarsveld De Kat 1989 66. T Emmett "Popular resistance in Namibia, 1920-1925" in Lodge Resistance and ideology in settler societies 6 at 14 refers to an observation by an Otjiwarongo magistrate that he was confronted by a "passive resistance campaign". 50 See infra chap five III. died while trying to escape. The border wars continued unabatedly. 51 The history of the Xhosa diviner, Nongqause (or Nongqawuse), is even more intriguing. In 1856, as a young girl, Nongqause convinced her uncle and eventually the paramount chief, Kreli, that in order to drive the English from the land all the cattle were to be killed and no one was to cultivate the land. On a certain day food would appear in abundance, the sky would fall and the white people would be crushed. Two camps developed - those who believed her and did as she directed them to do, and those who did not. According to reports of the time, 300 000 to 400 000 cattle were killed. Nothing out of the ordinary happened on the specified date. In the ensuing famine between 25 000 and 50 000 out of 150 000 Xhosas died. 52 As indicated above, these instances of non-violent, sacrificial resistance were, however, very rare, and for the greater part Africans exercised a choice between submission and violent resistance. However, for more than two centuries the dominant feature of black resistance to white rule in South Africa, where it occurred, was that it was unsuccessful and in most cases led to even greater misery. Force failed to secure freedom, and led to greater repression. Perhaps this fact more than any other explains the popularity of the method which Gandhi used with so much success against Smuts in the later liberation struggle in South Africa. (2) Gandhian civil disobedience in South Africa In 1893 Mohandas Gandhi, aged 23, arrived in Durban, in what was then the British colony of Natal. 53 Having studied Roman law and Common law in London, Gandhi was called to the bar in the Inner Temple. His exposure to British life, institutions and values made a lasting and largely favourable impression on Gandhi. 54 Gandhi failed at legal practice both in Rajkot and Bombay in India. 55 Hired initially as counsel of an Indian firm in a civil suit in South 51 See Roux Time longer than rope 16ff. 52 Id 47ff. 53 On Gandhi's earlier history, see Gandhi An autobiography 3ff and Kytle Gandhi 18. 54 See Hancock Smuts 323. 55 Fischer Gandhi 20. Africa, Gandhi became involved in local politics and would eventually spend most of the next 21 years in the country. 56 Here, personally at the receiving personally end of subjected what to became racial known as humiliation, 57 apartheid Gandhi and often developed a powerful new way of confronting the country’s harsh injustices. It must be noted, however, that during his career as lawyer cum politician in South Africa, Gandhi was a reformer, not a revolutionary. His quarrel was not with the system of racial discrimination: at this stage he still accepted and in fact advocated its legitimacy. What he objected to was the position which the Indian community occupied on the social ladder. In fact, Maureen Swan’s probing study suggests that his loyalties were even more limited and were for the main part of his career in South Africa not aimed primarily at improving the position of the Indian community as a whole, but were designed to do so only insofar as this was in the interests of the elite - the merchants and the traders. 58 What can be described as Gandhi’s revolutionary phase would commence after he had returned to India, when he rejected the system of British domination in toto and in fact also eventually rejected racism and other forms of elitism. (a) Indians in South Africa in the late Nineteenth Century When Gandhi arrived in Durban, immigrants from India -indentured labourers and later merchants - had settled and were settling mainly in 56 The literature available on Gandhi in South Africa is discussed in the recent contribution of J D Hunt "Gandhi in South Africa" in Hick & Hempel Gandhi's significance for today 61. For Gandhi's own account of his political struggle in South Africa, see Gandhi Satyagraha in South Africa 21ff and, for a useful summary, see "The struggle and what it has meant" in Golden Number of "Indian Opinion" 1914 13. For Afrikaner views on Gandhi, as expressed in the popular press of the middle of this century, see "Vredesapostel uit die land van die Himalayas" Die Ruiter 13 Feb 1948 and P J Cillie's "Gandhi mistikus, profeet en dinamiese politieke leier" Die Huisgenoot 20 Feb 1948. See also "Ek het Gandhi geken" Die Brandwag 20 Feb 1948. 57 The famous incident where Gandhi was pushed off a train in Pietermaritzburg is recounted in Gandhi An autobiography 111. On another unpleasant experience, see "When a police chief sang to save Gandhi from a Durban mob" The Nongqai Feb 1948. His career as a lawyer in South Africa is discussed by Sachs Justice in South Africa 205ff. On the difficulties he encountered to be admitted as an advocate, see Spiller De Rebus Oct 1985 517. 58 Swan Gandhi 270. the colony of Natal, with a smaller Indian community deve1oping in the Zuid-Afrikaansche Republiek ("ZAR") or Transvaal. 59 Indians were not allowed to settle or trade in the Orange Free prohibited from owning land in that republic. 61 State 60 and were In the Cape Colony, traditionally more liberal in racial matters, Indians, at least in theory, had the franchise. 62 The major events concerning the development of Gandhi’s peculiar form of protest occurred in the Transvaal and in Natal, and consequently the discussion will centre upon the situation in these two territories. Indians living themselves in Natal subjected to at the time extensive de of Gandhi’s facto arrival found discrimination. 63 The indentured labourers lived in conditions which can only be described as slavery, while, at the same time, some merchants had vast economic interests. Indians There before was little responsible legislation government, dealing and specifically Indians, as with British citizens, in theory qualified for the franchise if they met the wealth requirement. 64 However, the tide started turning against them when responsible government was granted in 1893 - thirty-three years after the first indentured Indians had arrived in South Africa. 59 In Natal, In 1896 there were 51 000 Indians, 50 000 whites and 400 000 Africans; in the ZAR 5 000 Indians, 120 000 whites and 650 000 Africans. Fischer Gandhi 23, 24. For the approach in the ZAR to the immigration of Indians into the territory, see Volksraadsbesluiten. art 41, 9 May 1888. 60 Art 1, chap 33 of Wetten, contained 1n the Wetboek van den Oranje-vrijstaat 1891, determined that Indians could settle 1n the Orange Free State for more than two months only if they had special permission. Art 8 of the same chapter prohibited the State President from granting Indians trading or farming rights. 61 Section 8, Ordinance 29 of 1890, "Wet tot tegengaan van de Instrooming van Aziatische kleurlingen, en tot verwijdering van blanke misdadigers van elders in deze staat komende". See also Ordinances 5 of 1876 and 1 of 1865. 62 In practice, however, most Indians were barred from the vote by s 4(c) and s 6 of the Franchise and Ballot Act 9 of 1892, which raised the property requirement for the franchise from £25 to £75 and posed an educational requirement. See Huttenback Gandhi 98. 63 64 For an overview, see Gandhi Satyagraha In South Africa 26ff. Section 11 of the Natal Charter of 1856 provided that every man over the age of 21 who owned Immovable property to the value of £50 was entitled to a parliamentary vote. See also Pachai The International aspects of the South African Indian question 2. Shortly after Franchise Indians Amendment to Parliament. symbolic, responsible 66 the 65 Bill, government aimed parliamentary at was the granted abolition franchise, was to of Natal, the introduced right in the the of new Although the significance of the proposed act was largely the symbolism was important. It reflected for the first time official legislative antagonism aimed at the "Asiatic races" eo nomine, and was a significant departure from what Chamberlain had called "the tradition of the Empire", which at least in theory made "no distinction in favour of or against race or colour". 67 An extensive assault on Indian interests in the colony had begun. Any act accepted by the Natal parliament, however, had to be approved by the colonial office before it would have the force of law. Upon Gandhi’s arrival in the country, the acceptance of the Franchise Amendment Act was still pending. In the ZAR, behoorende rights of Law tot 3 een of der citizenship 69 1885 68 provided, inter inboorlingrassen (including the van alia. Azie" franchise) that were and "personen, denied the right the to acquire land (although this provision did not have retroactive force). 70 Law 3 provided that all Asians who wished to reside in the Transvaal had to register and upon registration had to pay £3. 71 This law also gave the government the power to determine that Indians had to reside 65 The Bi11 provided that only those members of the Asiatic races who already had the franchise before the introduction of the Act would in future have the right to vote. See Swan Gandhi 45. See also Pachai The International aspects of the South African Indian question 10 and Huttenback Gandhi 18, 74. The underlying idea was not to affect vested interests, but also not to grant any new rights. 66 Less than 300 Indians exercised the right to vote in 1894. Swan Gandhi 45. 67 Quoted in Pachai The International aspects of the South African Indian question 11. 68 "Omtrent Koelies, Arabieren en andere Aziaten", as ammended by Volksraadsbesluit art 1419 of 12 Aug 1886, published in the Bijvoegsel tot de Staats-Courant der Zuid-Afrikaansche Republiek 2 Feb 1887. For a discussion of Law 3 and its effects, see Pillay British Indians In the Transvaal 1ff. 69 Section 2(a). 70 Section 2(b). 71 Section 2(c). Initially the amount was fixed at £25. This was changed to £3 by the 1886 amendment. in locations which could, in terms of a 1886 amendment, be allocated for reasons of health. 72 The Transvaal authorities used this provision to also restrict Indian trade to these areas. A dispute arose as to whether the Transvaal government had the right to subject the Indians to such discriminatory legislation, and especially whether Law 3 could be used to restrict Indian trade to the locations. 73 The British government had, through the Pretoria Convention of 1881, conceded the Transvaal "complete self-government subject to the suzerainty of Her Majesty". Hereafter the London Convention of 1884 was promulgated in order to increase the Transvaal’s jurisdiction over its own affairs. British subjects - including Indians - could gain entry into Transvaal. The British government would in later years base much of its claim to protect the rights of Indians on its position as suzerain in terms of the Pretoria Convention. However, on the basis that no mention was made in the London Convention of British suzerainty, the ZAR claimed that it no longer applied. Even if it did not, however, both conventions stipulated that "all persons other than natives, conforming themselves to the laws of the South African Republic" had the right to reside in any part of the Republic 74 and to carry on commerce. 75 At the same time the 1858 Grondwet van de Zuid-Afrikaansche Republiek proclaimed that people of colour could not receive the same treatment as white persons. 76 Clearly the legal position was far from certain. Which provision(s) had to take precedence? To complicate matters even further, the British Colonial Office did give permission for ZAR legislation which would make special provisions applicable to "coolies". By using the term "coolies" the Colonial Section 2(d): "De regering zal het regt hebben straten, wijken en locaties ter bewoning aan te wijzen." hun bepaalde 72 73 Swan Gandhi 39. See also Huttenback Gandhi 102 and Pi11ay British Indians in the Transvaal 2ff. 74 the London Convention and a 22(a) of the 75 the London Convention and a 22(c) of the Article 14(a) of Pretoria Convention. Article 14(c) of Pretoria Convention. 76 Article 9 provided that "[h]et volk wil geene ge1ijkstelling van gekleurden met blanke ingezeten toestaan, noch in kerk noch in staat." Also, according to art 31, "[g]een gekleurden, nocht bastaarden zullen toegelaten worden in onze vergaderingen." Office, however, meant Indian "workers", but the Transvaal State Secretary took it to mean all Asians, and consequently Law 3 was framed in such wide terms. 77 Law 3 was assented to by the British government only after an 1886 amendment, which provided that locations could be allocated for sanitary reasons, was accepted. The question then arose whether this acceptance implied that the British government agreed to the allocation of locations not only for the purposes of residence, but also for the purposes of trade. The dispute intensified when an 1888 Transvaal High Court judgment interpreted Law 3 to mean that the Transvaal authorities could also restrict Indian trade to these "locations". 78 Although the measures were in practice not always enforced, the situation for Indians in the Transvaal was increasingly uncertain when Gandhi arrived in Natal. Gandhi’s political career can be divided into two distinct phases. From 1894 to 1906 he participated in and eventually became the most prominent leader of legal protest against measures adversely affecting the Indians in South Africa. During the period 1907 to 1914 he supplemented legal protest with campaigns of illegal protest. Since the issues at stake during this latter period - the period most pertinent to our inquiry - developed during the time of legal protest, a brief overview of this phase will first be given. (b) Legal resistance 1894 - 1906 The phase of legal resistance can be subdivided into the period 1894 to 1897, when Gandhi’s energies were directed at an unsuccessful attempt to block the imposition of detrimental laws proposed in both Natal and in the Transvaal, and the period 1897 to 1906, when attempts were made to mitigate the effects of these laws. The anti-Indian measures in Natal and Transvaal can be classified into two main categories: those directed against the interests of Indians already in the particular territory (the removal of Indian franchise, requirements 77 78 for registration, the imposition of taxes, etc) and See Swan Gandhi 39. Ismail Suleiman & Co v Landdrost of Middelburg (1888) 2 SAR 244. The question at stake was whether the town of Middelburg could refuse a trading licence to an Indian outside a "location". The Court held that it could. measures aimed at preventing more Indians from entering the territory (immigration laws). In Natal the initial protest against the proposed Franchise Amendment Act took the form of a petition signed by 9 000 people, which Gandhi presented to the Colonial Secretary in 1894. 79 He further wrote letters of protest to political figures and newspapers in South Africa, Britain and India, and also drew attention to the plight of Indians in South Africa during a 1896 visit to India. Gandhi was instrumental in the formation of the Natal Indian Congress ("NIC") 80 in 1894, of which he was elected the first Honorary Secretary. 81 "Congress", as this body was called, was to co-ordinate much of the Indian protest in Natal in the years to come. At this stage the political activities of Gandhi and of the NIC were directed only at furthering the limited cause of the merchant classes in the Indian community. 82 On the one hand, he based his claim to equal rights for Indians on the fact that they were British subjects in terms of the Royal Proclamation which followed the usurpation of crown rule in India in 1858. On the other hand, while not expecting all Indians to be granted the full rights and privileges of citizenship by the Natal government, he pleaded on behalf of those "respectable" Indians who deserved "the just place of the better class". He made it clear that he did not intend to pave the way for "coolies” (meaning the working class) to vote. What was at stake, Gandhi explained, was not the political power of the Indian people but protection of this "better class." 83 In 1896 the Colonial Office approved what became known as the Franchise Amendment Act 8 of 1896, 84 which was more in line with the British policy of the time and was a little more subtly worded than the 1894 version. Only people not of European origin who came from a country in 79 Swan Gandhi 61. 80 See Id 49ff, where the romanticised picture often painted of Gandhi at this early stage of his career is placed into perspective. 81 See Gandhi Satyagraha autobiography 148ff. in South Africa 82 See Swan Gandhi 50. 83 Id 63. 84 "To amend the law relating to the franchise." 46 and Gandhi An which they did not enjoy the franchise, were disqualified from voting in Natal. 85 Although Indians were not named specifically in this Act, in practice they were the ones to be disenfranchised. This came in addition to the Indian Immigration Amendment Act 17 of 1895, which imposed an annual £3 tax on all ex-indentured workers 86 and which was designed to induce Indians to leave the colony after expiry of their contracts. Indeed, the fear of the Indian leadership that the Franchise Amendment Act was the thin end of the wedge by which a major assault was made on Indian interests in Natal was proved to have been well-founded. In 1897, The Immigration Act", 87 Restriction Act 1 of 1897, or the "Natal was passed, requiring all intending immigrants to posses some written knowledge of a European language. 88 This was followed by what became known as the Dealers Licenses Amendment Act 18 of 1897, 89 which made it possible for the Natal administration to deny wholesale and retail licences to Indians on the alleged grounds of insanitation. 90 In accordance with British policy, none of these statutes, which in reality were aimed at the Indian community, directly referred to Indians, or in so many words took away existing rights. Consequently, those enactments were not vetoed by the British government. This barricade of anti-Indian laws largely broke the spirit of resistance in Natal until 1906. Gandhi moved to the Transvaal after his return from a brief visit to India in 1902, and the activities of the NIC in the meantime consisted mainly of court actions that challenged 85 Section 2. 86 Section 6. This Act was approved of, however, by the Indian government of the time. See Huttenback Gandhi 45. 87 “To place certain restrictions on immigration." 88 Section 3(a). A prospective applicant had to be able to write out an application to immigrate in a prescribed form in "any language of Europe". Act 2 of 1897, "To amend the laws relating to quarantine", which provided for the prevention of people from infected areas from landing in Natal, was seen as another legislative strategem designed to prevent Indians from entering Natal. 89 Indians were also required to carry passes by Act 28 of 1897, "To protect uncovenanted Indians from arrest in mistake for absconding indentured Indian servants." 90 Section 8. the implementation of the aforementioned laws in specific cases, such as the refusals to renew licences and denials of permission to transfer licensed businesses to new premises. 91 Although Gandhi only moved his base to the Transvaal in 1902, he had often visited the Transvaal before that. Here, as mentioned earlier, Indians also faced considerable official hostility. The main source of resentment was the fact that the government claimed the right to use Law 3 of 1885, as amended and approved by Britain, to confine Indian merchants to designated locations for the purpose of residence and of trade. Early in 1895 the dispute between Britain and the ZAR on the question whether the imposition of such restrictions was legal, was referred for arbitration to the Chief Justice of the Orange Free State - a state, as was suggested earlier, not known for its positive disposition towards Indians. Chief Justice Melius de Villiers held that the ZAR had the right to interpret the law as it saw fit, and effectively endorsed the ZAR’s anti-Indian stance. 92 Gandhi led the protest against the "Bloemfontein award", as the outcome of the arbitration came to be called. The validity of the finding was challenged by the Indian community, inter alia through petition. As in Natal, Gandhi claimed equal rights for Transvaal Indians on the basis that they were British subjects. In the ZAR, however, because Indians were discriminated against eo nomine, he did not attempt to dissociate the elite as a class from the workers. Instead he sought to dissociate Indians as a race from the "natives". Gandhi expressed himself on the matter of Indians and blacks staying in the same residential area in no uncertain terms: "About this mixing of the Kaffirs with the Indians, I confess I feel most strongly. I think it is very unfair to the Indian population and it is an undue tax on even the proverbial patience of my countrymen"; and on another occasion he said: "If there is one thing which the Indian cherishes more than any other, it is the purity of the type." 93 Gandhi indicated his acceptance of the broad legitimacy of the system 91 See Swan Gandhi 68. 92 For a full discussion, see Pillay Transvaal 25. See also Swan Gandhi 81. 93 Quoted in Swan Gandhi 112, 113. British Indians in the of white domination in so many words in a remark made in 1903: "We believe also that the predominating race." In spite of white race in South Africa should be the provisions and 94 extensive Indian protest against the application of Law 3, the British government endorsed the Bloemfontein award later in 1895, and the Indians also lost a subsequent test case, heard in the High Court of the ZAR. 95 During the next four years, however, very little happened in terms of the practical implementation of Law 3. Before Indians were removed to locations, the country was at war. One of the causes of the Second Anglo-Boer War cited by Britain was the infringement of the rights of (white and) Indian British subjects by the ZAR government. 96 During the Second Anglo-Boer War, Gandhi organised an Indian ambulance corps, serving on the British side in an attempt to demonstrate that Indians were desirable and loyal British citizens. 97 After his active participation in the War ceased in 1900, Gandhi returned to India, in general disillusioned with Indian politics in South Africa. He made an unsuccessful attempt to enter Indian politics. When he was asked by the NIC to return to South Africa after the end of the War in 1902, he again set sail for South Africa, hoping for a more liberal approach to the Indians under British rule, inter alia because 94 Id 133 n 163. Switzer Journal of Ethnic Studies 1986 122 at 126 also came to the conclusion that Gandhi's interests in South Africa never expanded beyond the needs of the Indian community. See also Huttenback Gandhi 44. 95 Tayob Hajee Khan Mohamed v The Government of the South African Republic (F W Reitz. NO) (1898) 5 SAR 168. In his judgment Esser J declared: "There is not and never was an equality between whites and persons of colour, and we are bound to accept, as a principle, that every right possessed by the white man can only be exercised to a limited extent, or not at all, by the person of colour." Laws should be interpreted "in the case of any doubt or ambiguity, against the person of colour for whose benefit the law was enacted". (At 178.) 96 Pachai The International aspects of the South African Indian question 18. 97 He did the same during the "Zulu uprising" in 1906. See Gandhi An autobiography 214ff, 313ff. See also Marks Reluctant rebellion 214, 239. of the pro-British stance of the Indians during the War. 98 In reality the situation of Indians would further deteriorate. As mentioned earlier, the period immediately following the War found Gandhi settled in the Transvaal, where he established the British Indian Association ("BIA") early in 1903, which in many respects was to be the Transvaal equivalent of the NIC. The new High Commissioner for South Africa and Governor of what was now the Crown Colony of the Transvaal, Milner, who had supported Indian rights in the ZAR as far as possible in order to assert British authority over the region, now favoured implementing of as much of the legislation of the former Republic as was possible, in pursuit of the ideal of reconciliation with the Transvaal whites. 99 In fact, in one of its first major acts after the War, the British Government gave notice that Law 3 of 1885 would be used to restrict Indian trade to Indian locations, now called "bazaars". The new government adopted an even more aggressive policy of restricting both the residential and the trading rights of Indians to these "bazaars". 100 Gandhi tentatively started mooting the idea of civil disobedience in The Indian Opinion in 1904. He stressed the important role of suffering in the course of human progress, and cited the examples of Christ and Joan of Arc. He propagated the idea that the suffering which was required of Indians to improve their situation in South Africa would not be excessive because of the benevolent role which Britain played in South African affairs: "We have given these illustrations [of Christ and Joan of Arc] to draw a contrast between the very little that the Indians as individuals have to sacrifice so that the community may gain a great deal, and the much that had to be sacrificed in the instances quoted required by to us"; and: "Nor is there any heroic the communities living under the British rule." 98 See Gandhi Satyagraha in South Africa 81. 99 Swan Gandhi 94. 100 sacrifice 101 Government Notice 356, Transvaal Government Gazette 1 May 1903, and often referred to as the "bazaar notice". The notice contained the proviso that Indians whose "intellectual attainments or social qualities" appear so to entitle them, could be granted the right to reside outside the "bazaars". The Transvaal Executive Council, through Resolution 97 of 1902, also reaffirmed Law 3. See also Huttenback Gandhi 133. 101 “Self-sacrifice" The Indian Opinion 21 Jan 1904. Gandhi was promoting the idea that civil disobedience had become a viable option to the ordinary person or, in the terms used earlier, that mass option. result-oriented civil disobedience had become a rational 102 In Britain the Colonial Office found miner’s new approach increasingly difficult to justify to the British parliament and to the government of India. Especially the reversal of British policy regarding the trading rights of Indians caused controversy. It became even more of a problem when, in a test case brought in the Transvaal Supreme Court in 1904, 103 Milner’s 1903 instructions were in fact declared illegal. In his judgment the Chief Justice, Sir James Rose-Innes, said that "it does strike one as remarkable that, without fresh legislation, the officials of the Crown in the Transvaal should put forward a claim which the Government of the Crown in England has always contended was illegal under the statute, and which in the past it has strenuously resisted." 104 This decision, while bringing clarity as to the question of trading rights, placed further pressure on Britain to reassess its general position on Indians in the Transvaal. It also vindicated the Indian community’s earlier claims. As a direct consequence of the Court's decision, the field was left open for Indian merchants to enter into competition with white business people - a fact which caused much agitation from the colony’s white population. Various fresh attempts from the Transvaal authorities to limit the number of Indian licences to trade, however, now failed to receive the sanction of the Colonial Office. 105 In 1904 the Colonial Secretary, Lyttelton, formulated a new policy, in line with the one followed in Natal, for the Transvaal. An immigration act would block further Indian immigration into the Transvaal while, in return for this, the vested commercial and other interests of Indians in the colony would be protected. This policy was not acceptable to the white colonists. They agreed with the restrictions on immigration but were not willing to ease the other restrictions - in fact they wanted 102 See supra chap three II D. 103 Habib Hotan v Transvaal Government 1904 TS 404. The earlier decisions in Suleiman and Tayob were disapproved. 104 At 412. 105 See Huttenback Gandhi 152ff. to increase it. After the War, entry into and residence in the Transvaal in general was regulated under the Peace Preservation Ordinance 5 of 1903, 106 which required everyone who wanted to enter the colony to have a special permit. In practice, very few Indians were granted permits. Although they were not legally required to do so, the Indians already resident in the Transvaal agreed to and did voluntarily. 107 re-register Nevertheless, unauthorized entry into the Colony took place on a large scale and the Ordinance was considered inadequate by many white Transvalers, who believed that the concession that ex-residents could return after the War was being abused. In 1905 the "Lyttelton Constitution", which provided for the establishment in Transvaal of an elective legislative assembly, was promulgated. 108 government. solution Soon With which the the would Transvaal intention allow the of would be providing British awarded at responsible least a to ride government temporary out the remainder of Crown rule, Lord Selbourne, Milner’s successor, introduced two draft ordinances. 109 It provided for the compulsory (re- )registration of all Indians lawfully resident in the colony by means of fingerprinting. Further immigration into the Transvaal would be prohibited - only temporary permits would be made available for Indians to visit the Transvaal. Failure to (re-)register would constitute a crime. However, at least the £3 tax would be scrapped. Gandhi and the unfavourably rest to of these the Indian developments, leadership which reacted amounted to strongly the and proposed introduction of a "pass" system for Indians. They set themselves the task of measures persuading and the the Transvaal British legislature Government to not to withhold accept Royal these assent. 106 To amend the Peace Preservation Ordinance of 1902", which amended the Indemnity and Peace Preservation Ordinance 38 of 1902. See s 2. See also, for an apparently ineffectual attempt to make these provisions applicable specifically to Indians, Government Notice 229, The Transvaal Government Gazette 22 Feb 1907. 107 See Gandhi Satyagraha in South Africa 94 and Huttenback Gandhi 158. 108 Letters patent providing for the constitution of a legislative assembly in the Transvaal, and the Transvaal Constitution Order in Council, 1905." 109 Huttenback Gandhi 162 and Swan Gandhi 100. Especially the fact that all Indians were forced to register by means of fingerprinting was seen as humiliating, because it meant that Indians were treated like criminals. The Selbourne Ordinances would reduce Indians, Gandhi said in a letter to The Times, "to a level lower than the Kaffirs". 110 On 11 September 1906, 3 000 people, gathered at a meeting in Johannesburg, pledged to resort to passive resistance and go to jail if the ordinances gained the force of law. 111 Since this date might well be described as the birth date of civil disobedience as an instrument of mass-mobilisation, 112 it seems fitting to quote at some length Gandhi’s description of the events: The old Empire Theatre was packed from floor to ceiling. I could read in every face the expectation of something strange to be done or to happen ... The most important among the resolutions passed by the meeting was the famous Fourth Resolution, by which the Indians solemnly determined not to submit to the Ordinance in the event of its becoming law in the teeth of their opposition and to suffer all the penalties attaching to such non-submission. I fully explained this resolution to the meeting and received a patient hearing ... The resolution was duly proposed, seconded and supported by several speakers one of whom was Sheth Haji Habib. He ... was a very old and-experienced resident of South Africa and made an impassioned speech. He was deeply moved and went so far as to say that we must pass this resolution with God as witness and must never yield a cowardly submission to such degrading legislation. He then went on solemnly to declare in the name of God that he would never submit to that law, and advised all present to do likewise. Others also delivered powerful and angry speeches in supporting the resolution. When in the course of his speech Sheth Haji Habib came to the solemn declaration, I was at once startled and put on my guard. Only then did I fully realize my own responsibility and the responsibility of the community. The community had passed many a resolution before and amended such resolutions in the light of further reflection or fresh experience ... Amendments in resolutions and failure to observe resolutions on the part of persons agreeing thereto are ordinary experiences of public life all the world over. But no one ever imports the name of God into such resolutions... Full 110 of these thoughts as I was, possessing as I did much Oct 1906. 111 See Swan Gandhi 102 and Pachai The international aspects of the South African Indian question 33. 112 See Anonymous The Round Table 1952 130 and Meer Africa South 1959 21. experience of solemn pledges, having profited by them, I was taken aback by Sheth Haji Habib’s suggestion of an oath. I thought out the possible consequences of it in a moment. My perplexity gave place to enthusiasm. I [explained the consequences of the suggestion to the audience] and resumed my seat. The meeting heard me word by word in perfect quiet. Other leaders too spoke. All dwelt upon their own responsibility and the responsibility of the audience. The president rose. He too made the situation clear, and at last all present, standing with upraised hands, took an oath with God as witness not to submit to the Ordinance if it became law. I can never forget the scene, which is present before my mind's eye as I write. 113 It seems that by making a pledge two objectives were achieved. In the first place, divine authority, which is often seen to support governmental authority, was invoked on the side of those who resisted government. In the second place, the disobedience, which was essentially anti-exploitation, through the pledge assumed the status of being integrity-based. The terms used in the Fourth Resolution accepted at the meeting are interesting - the new measures were called "gulling, tyrannous, and UnBritish". 114 Clearly the opportunities which British liberalism offered for the imminent critique of civil disobedience were perceived. In spite of Indian opposition, the draft ordinances were replaced by a single ordinance, the Asiatic Law Amendment Ordinance 29 of 1906 which was even more comprehensive. Only Indians who were already "lawfully resident" in the Transvaal would qualify for registration 115 and the definition of the circumstances under which someone would be regarded as "lawfully resident" was severely restricted. 116 Although Gandhi was already in 1904 prepared to cross the line from legal to illegal resistance, these developments opportunity to mobilise mass support. 117 provided the first Before he would actually do this, however, a deputation was sent by the BIA to England to protest against the new measures. The Asiatic Law Amendment Ordinance still had 113 Gandhi Satyagraha in South Africa 102-107. 114 Quoted in Huttenback Gandhi 166. (Emphasis added.) 115 Section 3(1). 116 Section 3(2). 117 See Swan Gandhi 117. to gain royal assent, and Indian efforts were directed at preventing this. British public opinion was aroused against the measures. The British government anticipation of withheld the their introduction acceptance of of responsible the proposals government in in the Transvaal. It would be left to the new government to decide how they wanted to deal with the proposed ordinance - and with the threat of passive resistance. As it turned out, the new government had little doubt about what they wanted to do. On 1 January 1907 the Transvaal was granted responsible government. 118 Two days after the formal opening of the new parliament the Colonial Secretary, General Smuts, introduced the Asiatic Law Amendment Bill, which was to amend Law 3. Accepted unanimously as the Asiatic Law Amendment Act 2 of 1907, and often referred to simply as "Act 2", its provisions were essentially Amendment Ordinance of 1906. the 119 same as those of the Asiatic Law Act 2 was called the “Black Act" by the Indian community. In terms of Constitution the reservation Letters Patent clause 1907, the contained British in the Governor, Transvaal after the granting of responsible government, had the right to reserve for Royal assent any bill whereby "persons not of European birth or descent may be subjected or made liable to any disabilities or restrictions to which persons of European birth or descent are not also subjected or made liable." 120 Consequently, the avenue of an appeal to the British Government was still open to the Indian community. They used every available channel to prevent Britain’s acceptance and the implementation of Act 2. Resolutions condemning the Bill were submitted to the colonial office by various organizations representing Indian interests in the Transvaal, Natal and in England. A deputation waited on Smuts, and an unsuccessful attempt was made to see Botha. Numerous objections were raised in the press. 121 Gandhi even attempted to forge a compromise by proposing voluntary registration if the Act was scrapped. This was rejected. On the basis of non-interference in the affairs of 118 The Transvaal Constitution Letters Patent 1906. 119 In terms of s 4(1), as read with schedule "B" of Government Notice 716 The Transvaal Government Gazette, 28 June 1907, a full set of ten fingerprints had to be supplied by every applicant. 120 Section 39(a). 121 See Swan Gandhi 141. the Transvaal government. Act 2, however, eventually acquired Royal assent. Gandhi’s appeals for Indians not to register were carried in the pages of his newspaper, the Indian Opinion. Indian resistance, under the leadership of Gandhi, would now turn from legal to illegal forms of protest. The Selbourne Ordinances provided a catalyst for an intensification of a growing resistance in the Indian community which slowly matured and spilled over into action. One fact contributing towards the pot eventually overcooking was Britain’s failure to live up to the expectations it created in the Indian community, namely that after its victory in the Anglo-Boer War, Britain would be more liberal minded than the ZAR. On the contrary, additional repressive measures were introduced. Arguably community the most towards important illegal reason action for was a the shift change or in the Indian development in Gandhi’s own political thinking, which in turn resulted in a change in the leadership he provided. At the beginning of the century, through a process with which we need not detain ourselves here, Gandhi became deeply impressed by the work of a number of proponents of non-violent resistance, discussed below. 122 As the position of Indians deteriorated, he gradually became convinced that conditions were right to implement this new weapon on a wide scale. In Natal and in the Transvaal the issues of immigration to these colonies, and restrictions on residential and trading rights of Indians already there, permeated in 1907 into the most important causes of friction between the Indian communities and the authorities; with the additional problem of compulsory registration in the Transvaal. It was against this last-mentioned, most visible form of discrimination that the campaign was initially directed - which means that it started in the Transvaal. It must be remembered, however, that the registration requirement only formed one part of a wider web of discrimination. In a very real sense, South African Indians at the beginning of this century were fighting for their survival in the country. Smuts received strong admonitions from British advisers not to alienate British opinion by taking too hard a line in its relations with, India 122 See infra chap three III B 2(a). On Gandhi's transformation during this time, see Kytle Gandhi 64ff. spiritual which would embarrass the Imperial Government. That, he was warned by Cape Prime Minister John X Merriman, "will above all furnish a pretext for a great deal of mischievous interference in native matters." 123 Also impressed upon Smuts was the emergence world-wide of respect for the dignity of people who were previously "inferior". 124 considered In effect, Britain was warning Smuts that it would act as a benevolent background force and exercise pressure on Smuts if moved to do so by the plight of South African Indians. It was under these circumstances that mass civil disobedience in its new, modern form was first practised. (c) Illegal resistance 1907 - 1914 The period of illegal resistance by Gandhi to which we now turn, can be subdivided into four different phases. During this time three major campaigns of civil disobedience were conducted. (i) Phase one: Refusal to register (1) The first phase started in Pretoria in April 1907 when the September 1906 passive reaffirmed. 125 resistance resolution, aimed against Act 2, was Mass meetings at which the decision not to register was confirmed, were held all over the Transvaal under auspices of the BIA. Although pickets operated on a dissuading wide scale, would-be there applicants were from virtually no registering reports of intimidation and violence. At the end of the (extended) deadline for registration, only just more than 500 applications had been received out of the possible 7 000. 126 Gandhi explained his motivation for leading the campaign of civil disobedience in a letter to The Star: It is because I consider myself to be a lover of the Empire for what I have learned to be its beauties that, seeing, rightly or wrongly, in the Asiatic Law Amendment Act seeds of danger to it, I have advised my countrymen at all costs to resist the Act in 123 See Hancock Smuts 332 ff. 124 Id 322. 125 See Pachai The international aspects of the South African Indian question 38. 126 Swan Gandhi 142, 154, 155. Hancock Smuts 331 put the last figure at approximately 9 000. the most peaceful, and I shall add, Christian manner. 127 Gandhi also described the effect of the Asiatic Act as the "ruination of a whole people" and stated: I claim, too, that the method of passive resistance adopted to combat the mischief is the cleanest and the safest, because, if the cause is not true, it is the resistors, and they alone, who suffer. I am perfectly aware of the danger to good government, in a country inhabited by many races unequally developed, in an honest citizen advising resistance to a law of the land. But I refuse to believe in the infallibility of legislators ... It is no part of a citizen’s duty to pay blind obedience to the laws imposed upon him. 128 In Britain public opinion was turning against the British government’s allowing the Transvaal government to treat the Indians in this way especially in the light of the likely effect which this would have on Britain’s position in India. 129 The first person to be arrested for not registering was Pandit Ram Sunder of Germiston. He was sentenced to a month’s imprisonment. 130 By the end of January 1908 almost 2 000 Indians who had refused to register, had been jailed. This included Gandhi. At his trial Gandhi asked the received magistrate only a two for month the maximum sentence. 131 sentence To use of the six terms months but introduced earlier, this first campaign of mass result-oriented civil disobedience was legitimacy-based, negative, non-coercive, anti-exploitation, sacrificial and reformatory. After eight months, however, the movement was running out of steam. This was due to a variety of circumstances, such a the lack of a welldeveloped organizational infrastructure the absence of proper communication between leaders am followers, and fear of the hardships of imprisonment. Since January 1908, Indians who failed to register faced not only prison sentences but also the threat of losing their 127 "Indian trouble" The Star 30 Dec 1907. 128 Ibid. 129 See eg The Times of London 7 Jan 1908. 130 See Pachai The international aspects of the South African Indian question 39. 131 The trial is recounted in Gandhi Satyagraha in South Africa 148ff. See also Huttenback Gandhi 184. trading licences. 132 Gandhi and others then concluded a compromise with Smuts. In terms of this compromise Indians would register, but they would do so voluntarily and not as a result of compulsion. According to Gandhi, Smuts agreed to repeal Act 2 once such registration was completed. With this truce in January 1908, the first phase ended, and voluntary registration - in the most cases accompanied by fingerprinting - took place. It is ironic to note that voluntary registration is exactly what Gandhi proposed as a compromise before the campaign. In the meantime, the Immigrants Restriction Act 15 of 1907 was passed. This Act provided, inter alia. that any person (that is Indian or otherwise) unable to write out in "characters of an European language" an application immigrant". 133 to enter the colony, would be deemed a "prohibited This provision was certain to block a substantial portion of Indian Immigration into the Transvaal. In effect the immigration of all non-indentured Indians, whatever their social status or educational attainments, was halted by a further provision that "any person who at the date of his entering" the Transvaal is "subject to ... any law which might render him liable ... to be removed from ... this Colony", was also deemed a prohibited immigrant. 134 Because non-compliance with Act 2 rendered Indians liable to deportation, immigration and registration were effectively conflated into a single issue. The by now familiar British way of discriminating against Indians without mentioning them by name was used with deadly effect by the Transvaal legislature. 135 (ii) Phase two: Refusal to register (2) In May 1908 it became clear that Smuts did not intend to repeal Act 2, 132 See Swan Gandhi 161. 133 Section 2(1) "prohibited imigrant". 134 Section 2(4) "prohibited imigrant". See also Huttenback Gandhi 186. 135 The government also issued curfew provisions, sidewalk restrictions and limitations off the use of trains and trams by Indians. See Huttenback Gandhi 187. See also the classification of Indians as "Coloureds" for the purposes of Act 35 of 1908, "To consolidate and amend the law relating to prospecting and mining for precious metals and base metals and to provide for matters incidental thereto." but in fact would on pain of criminal sanction, Asiatics Registration Amendment Act 36 of 1908, 136 by means of the require all Indian residents who were absent during voluntary registration to register. The fact that Act 2 was not repealed did not on the whole seriously worsen the plight of Transvaal Indians, since most of them had already registered. What was objected to most strongly was the retention of the element of compulsion and what Gandhi described as Smuts’ breach of faith. 137 Extensive notice that the campaign of civil disobedience was about to be resumed was given. When the ensuing negotiations broke down, it was decided that the campaign of Satyagraha. as Gandhi was now calling the form of resistance he used, was to be resumed this time aimed also at securing the residence rights of an former bona fide residents. An ultimatum was presented to the government which threatened that a large number of Indians would burn their (voluntarily obtained) registration certificates if Act 2 was not scrapped. Another important issue was the ban on immigration into Transvaal. The BIA only asked permission for six highly educated Indians each year to be admitted into the followed. On 16 Transvaal. 138 Various abortive attempts at negotiation 139 August 500 trade licences were burnt in front of a crowd of 3 000 at Fordsburg. 140 At the same Transvaal time a 1908, number 1 300 of registration Indians from certificates Natal entered and the illegally and openly, and were arrested. Approximately 1 500 people, including Gandhi and the other leaders of the movement, were placed in custody for crossing the border, or reporting to the police station 136 The voluntary registration which resulted from the compromise, illegal in terms of Act 2 of 1907, was legalised, but Act 2 Itself was not repealed. 137 A chapter of Gandhi's book Satyagraha in South Africa is, somewhat tentatively, entitled "General Smuts' breach of faith (?)". No certainty exists as to what was really agreed upon. See also Hancock Smuts 336. 138 See Huttenback Gandhi 197. 139 Some test cases were also being brought. See "The struggle and what it has meant" Golden Number of "Indian Opinion" 1914 13 at 15. 140 See Swan Gandhi 171. stating that they did not have registration certificates. 141 By the beginning of 1909 it became clear that pursuance of the movement’s methods was exacting too high a toll from its members. Many people who had been in jail were not willing to again suffer such humiliation, and the financial position of those who were imprisoned was seriously prejudiced. Over the objections of Gandhi, who was now out of jail, a deputation under his leadership was sent to England which, as it turned out, achieved nothing. The resistance had run out of steam. By February 1909, 97% of the Transvaal Asians had taken out registration certificates. 142 On this despondent note the second phase ended. A deputation to India, however, raised considerable public awareness and the Indian government persuaded the British government to implore the Transvaal to cease to deport Indians from the colony. 143 The movement, Transvaal, was which at showing this its stage was vulnerability largely to confined increased to the governmental pressure. It had, however, also shown that civil disobedience could be used to mobilise people. What had not been proved was that it could change the behaviour of the government. The campaign was also much localised. It was directed mainly against registration, and registration was only required in the Transvaal. Civil disobedience had not spread to the other provinces. (iii) Phase three: Unsuccessful negotiations The third phase began when Gandhi returned from London at the end of 1909, after the movement had virtually collapsed. With the creation of the Union of South Africa on 31 May 1910, however, issues which were previously considered regional, automatically became national. The 141 See Kytle Gandhi 95 and Swan Gandhi 174. There is no account of these large-scale arrests in Huttenback Gandhi 193, 201 et passim. Gandhi refused to produce his registration certificate and was convicted by the magistrate of Volksrust with having violated s 9 of the regulations framed under Act 36 of 1908. He was sentenced to a £25 fine or two months' imprisonment. Characteristically he chose the latter. He was again arrested and convicted in Volksrust at the beginning of 1909. He was now sentenced to three months' imprisonment, which he chose over the alternative of paying a £50 fine. See Huttenback Gandhi 195, 202. 142 143 See Swan Gandhi 174. See "The struggle and what "Indian Opinion" 1914 13 at 16. it has meant" Golden Number of prime centre of action would, however, for the time being remain in the Transvaal. Hopes were raised again that the new administration would be more tolerant. Dominating this phase would be the approach of the new South African government to Indian immigration. 144 Gandhi’s main adversary remained Smuts, who was now Minister of the Interior of the Union. During this phase, Gandhi would virtually retire to Tolstoy Farm, outside Johannesburg. On 7 October 1910 the British government sent a dispatch to the Union government, urging the repeal of Act 2 and the removal of the racial bar on immigration. It was suggested that Indian immigration could be limited to a minimum by posing an education test. The Union government responded favourably to the suggestions. 145 In February repealing 1911 Act 2 an and Immigrants Restriction consolidating and Bill, 146 replacing which the aimed at immigration measures of the different provinces - not only in respect of Asians, but in respect of all other immigrants - was introduced in the Union Parliament. abroad. 147 It established Immigration into an educational any province, test for however, regulated by decrees of that particular province. 148 immigrants could from still be This last measure was severely opposed by Gandhi, inter alia on the basis that the Bill recognised the right of the Free State to continue excluding Indians altogether. 144 In Chotabhai v Union Government (Minister of Justice) and Registrar of Asiatics 1911 AD 13 the Appellate Division, overruling a Transvaal Provincial Division decision, held that although Act 36 of 1908 provided only for the registration of minors resident in the Transvaal at the commencement of the Act or born within its boundaries, it did not follow that minors entering lawfully after that date could not register as provided for in Act 2 of 1907. 145 See Huttenback Gandhi 27ff and "The struggle and what it has meant" Golden Number of "Indian Opinion" 1914 13 at 16. 146 Entitled "Bill to consolidate and amend the laws in force in the various provinces of the Union relating to restrictions upon 1 iron igrat ion thereto, to provide for the establishment of a Union Immigration Department and to regulate immigration into the Union or any province thereof". Government Notice 35, Union Gazette Extraordinary 25 Feb 1911. 147 Section 4(1) (a). The Australian model of requiring the applicant to write out 50 words in the language selected by an immigration officer was followed. See Huttenback Gandhi 275. 148 Section 7. After negotiations between Gandhi and Smuts - the latter being under heavy pressure from Free State members of parliament who refused to abandon the old republican discriminatory measures - it became clear that an agreement could not be reached during the 1911 parliamentary session. They agreed on a “provisional settlement". Smuts stated his intention to fulfil the demands of the protesters during the 1912 session of parliament; Gandhi to bring passive resistance to a halt. The first Immigration Bi11 was not passed although the government administered the law as if it was in operation, and exempted a number of educated Indians. 149 Smuts asked Gandhi to have a national "Bill of Rights" (as it was called) drawn up, which -in truly retroactive fashion would reflect the sum total of Indian grievances. Smuts clearly wanted to prevent Gandhi from later reopening the campaign of passive resistance with ever widening demands. In addition to the familiar grievances, the issue of the yearly £3 tax on Indians in Natal was now listed as a matter of priority and eventually dissatisfaction. 150 became one of the leading causes of A second Immigration Bill was rejected in 1912 for a variety of reasons and the provisional settlement was extended for another year. 151 In October 1912, Gopo1 Gokhale, President of the India National Congress in India, visited South Africa. He ha talks with Premier Louis Botha and with Smuts, after which he told Gandhi that the causes of most of their grievances would be removed, including Act 2 of 1907 and the £3 tax in Natal When a year later this had not happened, it was once more regarded by Gandhi as a breach of promise which strengthened the moral basis of his case. Gokhale’s visit British link with both South Africa and India. also highlighted the 152 At this time a shift in Gandhi’s approach became evident. He had become more and more intent on exploring the use of Satyagraha as an instrument of mobilisation on a national level. Gandhi’s traditional 149 See Huttenback Gandhi 284 and Swan Gandhi 230. 150 See Swan Gandhi 213, 226. 151 Huttenback Gandhi 289. Section 28 of the Bin reintroduced all the stipulations in the previous Bill which the Indians had found objectionable in respect of the Orange Free State. 152 See Gandhi Satyagraha in South Africa 259ff. See also Hancock Smuts 341. focus on the more pressing but also more localised grievances of the different communities widened. He found in the endorsement of racial bars on interprovincial migration contained in the Immigrants Restriction Bill a cause that was of sufficient concern to inspire countrywide support, but which at the same time would probably not be met with the same vehement opposition from the government, if broken, as was the case with some of the other issues. Gandhi no longer upheld the belief that numbers were irrelevant. As would happen so often in his career, Gandhi, the deontological moralist, had to make room for Gandhi, the consequentialist politician. His commitment to the interests of the elite now gave way to a commitment to the interests of the Indian community as a whole. All that was needed before Gandhi would appeal to Indians nationwide to resist the measures to which they were now all being subjected, was that the political temperature would raise a few degrees. This happened due to a number of causes. One was the fact that the Cape Division of the Supreme Court, in a 1913 judgment, found that the wife in a marriage celebrated in accordance with rites which recognised polygamy, even if there was only one wife in that marriage, did not have the right to emigrate to South Africa. 153 Gandhi concluded that all Hindu and Muslim wives already living consequently lose their right to live there. in South Africa would 154 The third phase of post-1906 Indian resistance, during which time civil disobedience was prevented by the provisional settlement, came to an end when the third Bill dealing with Indian immigration was passed in 1913, and became law in the form of the Immigrants Regulation Act 22 of 1913. 155 The Immigrants Regulation Act repealed Transvaal Act 2 of 1907 in its entirety, except insofar as it related to minors. 156 Immigration into the Union and between provinces was formally made dependent on the ability of the person concerned to read and write a European 153 Esop v Union Government (Minister of the Interior) 1913 CPD 133. 154 Gandhi Satyagraha in South Africa 276. 155 Later renamed the Admission of Persons to the Union Regulation Act. 156 Schedule 2 language. 157 However, the marriage question was not resolved to the satisfaction of the Indian community, and the £3 tax remained unrepealed. Since negotiations with the government had not secured the required results, they were broken off, after a last attempt had been made to mobilise British support. (iv) Phase four: Satyagraha on a grand scale The fourth (and final) phase, during which time the effectiveness of Satyagraha as a form of mass political mobilisation on a nationwide scale would be subjected to its most severe test yet, began in 1913. The prime focus of the campaign at this stage would be the polygamous marriage and £3 tax questions. Gandhi’s belief that the Immigrants Regulation Act should be met with passive resistance was repudiated in Natal and received only guarded support in the Transvaal. His opposition to the £3 tax in Natal, however, found support among the Natal Indian coal miners. Since this tax was not abolished a year after Gokhale’s visit, it provided the immediate grievance which, in conjunction with the general harshness of their living conditions, would move the workers in Natal to strike. Within two weeks after a call by Gandhi to strike, the appeal was heeded by between 4 000 and 5 000 Indian coal miners in Northern Natal. 158 The government followed a policy of non-intervention and did not arrest the strikers. In order to elicit a confrontation, Gandhi led a group of strikers and their dependents, which eventually totalled 4 000, on what was later called the "Great March" - a trek by foot towards the Transvaal, where they intended crossing the border illegally and getting arrested. 159 Smuts nearly managed to turn this mass exodus into a disaster for Gandhi when he refused to arrest the marchers, even when they illegally 157 Section 4(1)(b). Section 4(1)(a) also added the provision that "any person or class of persons deemed by the Minister on economic grounds or on account of standard or habits of life to be unsuited to the requirements of the Union or any particular province thereof" was a prohibited immigrant. 158 159 Swan Gandhi 247. For Gandhi's own account of these events, see Gandhi Satyagraha in South Africa 297. See also “That wonderful march" Golden Number of "Indian Opinion" 1914 21. crossed into the Transvaal. As Smuts’s biographer, Hancock, observed. Smuts also acquired some Gandhian skills in ensuring that those under his command refrained as far as possible from using violence. 160 The marchers as well as their funds were fast becoming exhausted, and they were demoralised by the anti-climax of not being arrested. Then the strike in Northern Natal spread spontaneously to the south of Natal, and the movement was saved. The government now had a major, spontaneously growing expression of open defiance on its hands which it could no longer ignore. 161 As was to be expected, because the strike in the south of Natal was much less disciplined and without strong leadership, violent clashes with the police occurred. The proportions of the strike forced Smuts to intervene. Mass arrests were ordered, and both the march and the strike were suppressed, often by violent means. The imprisoned marchers were returned to Natal by train and confined to the compounds of their own mines, which now had been cordoned off with barbed wire and were declared outposts of the Natal prisons. When attempts were made through whippings and beatings to force the strikers back to work, and this was portrayed in the media, South African and world public opinion was outraged. Britain was subjected to international criticism, particularly from India, and this criticism was brought to bear on the South African government. 162 Gandhi’s moral victory was complete when he called the campaign off in 1914 when white railway workers also began striking. He stated that opponent’s misfortunes. one should not take advantage of one’s 163 Gandhi rejected the composition of a government-appointed commission of 160 Hancock Smuts 340. 161 Swan Gandhi 251. 162 According to Bishop A technique for loving 57: "Public opinion outside South Africa had become too strong to be ignored any longer, and South Africa's position within the empire rendered it amenable to pressure from Britain and India." Lord Hardinge, the British Viceroy in India, chastised the South African government for its actions. This criticism violated an established tradition that one part of the Empire would not criticise another. Nevertheless, it elicited much support in the Empire. 163 Woodcock Gandhi 42 and Huttenback Gandhi 324. This aspect of Gandhi's approach was particularly resented by Simons Class and colour in South Africa 161. Simons, who wrote from a Marxist perspective, saw this as a naive squandering of opportunities. inquiry into the causes of the strike and the march, because it contained no representative from the Indian community, and refused to testify before it. He nevertheless held private discussions with Smuts and others. The recommendations of the “Indian Inquiry Commission” were given the force of law by means of the Indians Relief Act 22 of 1914. A number of important concessions were made: Indian marriages were recognised as valid 164 and abolished. 165 the £3 tax on the ex-indentured workers in Natal was In other respects, however, the battle was far from over: no provision was made to guarantee the right of South African-born Indians to migrate from one province to the other, or to provide for a more just administration of the laws affecting Indian interests. 166 However, in correspondence with Gandhi, Smuts undertook on behalf of the government to carry through the administrative reforms not covered by the new Act. 167 (d) Evaluation For Gandhi, however, the battle in South Africa was over. In the eyes of the world he had won. His international reputation was established, and he went back to face India’s much larger problems with the still novel, but by now tested, tool of Satyagraha. Gandhi and Smuts had come to respect each other, but when he left. Smuts wrote: "The saint has left our shores, I sincerely hope for ever." 168 And so it was. But Gandhi’s ideas were yet to exercise a profound influence on the history of both South Africa and the world. In his 1939 essay on Gandhi's political method, Smuts wrote that Gandhi had revealed “a skeleton in our cupboard". 169 The skeleton would be dressed by later governments in the clothes of a beauty queen. It continued to haunt South Africa and would again be revealed for what it was - not 164 Sections 1 and 2. 165 Section 8. 166 For a discussion of the later history of Indian immigration, see Corder Judges at work 169ff. 167 See "The struggle and what "Indian Opinion" 1914 13 at 17. 168 169 it has meant" Golden Number at J of See Hancock Smuts 345. See J C Smuts "Gandhi’s political method" Collection, University of Pretoria Archives. 2, D Pohl least through civil disobedience. Some important characteristics of Gandhi’s approach are evident at this stage: - His protest was aimed mainly at making a moral appeal on the British sense of fair-play. In turn he trusted the "benevolent background force", would that Britain, as then change the behaviour of his primary opponents, namely the authorities in South Africa. There is evidence that Britain indeed played this role. - He used civil disobedience as an instrument of immanent critique, as a device which could exploit hypocrisy: the tension between words and deeds. More than once, his protest would be expressed in the indignant tone of someone who was the victim of a broken promise. In particular, he exposed the conflict between the ideals which Britain professed and the realities of her South African territories. - Gandhi tried all alternative channels of resolving the dispute before he engaged in civil disobedience. He also continued to explore legal possibilities, even after the campaign had started. - The need for discipline in the campaign became manifest when violence erupted in the south of Natal. It was clear that strict organization would be needed in future to ensure that the purpose of making a moral statement is not defeated. Gandhi viewed absolute non-violence in this respect as indispensable. - Gandhi believed that civil disobedience should be aimed at easily identifiable injustices, to which a large section of the community could relate - even if these were not the greatest injustices. - The idea of martyrdom, of suffering, was already playing an important role in Gandhi’s understanding of the working of civil disobedience. The pattern of inviting the harshest possible penalty was set. - Gandhi’s focus gradually shifted away from the more exclusive interests of a particular grouping to become more inclusive, more universalist. The genius of Gandhi lay -in the fact that he perceived and used the opportunity posed in early Twentieth Century South Africa to develop non-violent resistance as a powerful form of resistance with appeal to the masses. (3) Civil disobedience in South Africa after Gandhi The precedent which Gandhi set of a "non-white" person standing up for his rights against the white rulers left a deep impression on the world at large and on the people of the country where this first happened. Gandhi had in the first place challenged the white rulers in a fundamental way and managed not to get crushed in the process, which was in itself a novel feat. Moreover, he managed to bring about actual social change; something which was previously unheard of for a person who was not white, dearly, here was something new and promising. It would, however, be several years before the country once again saw crowds reminiscent of those inspired by Gandhi, pursuing political change through non-violent, illegal action. Political resistance against white domination in South Africa after Gandhi would mainly be initiated by the African section of the population, with one dominant strand of this group widening to include members of all races who opposed the racially exclusive basis of the government, and the other strand being more preoccupied with the African cause. The dominant organizations representing the interests of these two formations, the African National Congress ("ANC" or "Congress") and the Pan Africanist Congress ("PAC"), would in turn sponsor mass campaigns of civil disobedience, before they were both outlawed and turned to violence. The period under consideration, from more or less 1912, when black resistance started to become organised, to the present time, can be divided into six phases. 170 - During the first phase, from 1912 until the outbreak of World War II, black opposition operated within the paradigm or non-activist or "reactive" liberalism. - During the second phase, the 1940’s, the politicising of the black community took place on an unprecedented scale, preparing the ground for the imminent confrontation when legal protest could be supplemented by illegal resistance. 170 A similar division in respect of the earlier periods is used by Lodge Black politics in South Africa since 1945 viii. See also Davis & Fine Journal of Southern African Studies 1985 25 at 27. - In the 1950’s, during the third phase, the developing political disquiet boiled campaigns of over passive into action, resistance, which took particularly the in the form of form of civil disobedience. With the escalation of action, the tensions underlying the process of politicising that took place in the previous decade came to the surface, and a rift occurred between those who were more susceptible to European influences and those who were more Africanist oriented. - The fourth phase was initiated - and largely determined - by the ban imposed on the main vehicles for black political expression in the early 1960’s. There was a shift in strategy from nonviolent to violent illegal action, initiated mainly from positions outside the country. - In the seventies and eighties the actions of the armed underground was combined with the activities of a reconstituted mass overground. - The sixth and present stage started at the beginning of 1990, when the major political opposition groups were unbanned and a process of negotiations was initiated. In this period civil disobedience and threats of civil disobedience would come from the liberation movements as well as from right wing whites. During the last two phases, sporadic incidents of civil disobedience occurred, but never on the same scale as in the 1950’s. During the whole period under consideration, civil disobedience would never be practised with the same commitment to non-coercion as under Gandhi and it would have much less success. As will be demonstrated, however, even if the method of civil disobedience was new to many of those who participated in the liberation struggle and was practised mostly for reasons of strategy, it did have a considerable influence on the struggle itself and on the system of apartheid. (a) Phase one: The period before World War II With the formation of the Union in 1910, black expectations of greater political participation were not accommodated. The issue of the right of Africans to vote for parliament was simply sidestepped when each province was allowed to retain the franchise system that existed before Union. Consequently, blacks and coloureds voted together with whites in the qualified franchise dispensation of the Cape, but in the other provinces only whites were enfranchised. 171 Black protest against white domination throughout this phase of resistance was characterised by its mild and guarded nature. It mostly took the form of public comments, critical of measures introduced by the government, which were made by a small number of politicised blacks. Because the initiative remained in the hands of the government, black opposition reactive. during Resistance at this this period stage can was at aimed best not be at described replacing as the existing structures of government, or even the personnel who manned those structures, but merely at making them more responsive to black needs. As Felt put it, the appeals of the leaders of the ANC at this time "were directed not to the Africans, but to the whites". 172 In 1912 the South African Native National Congress, which changed its name to the Bloemfontein. African 173 The National formation Congress of background of the enactment of the the in ANC 1923, took was place founded against in the Black Land Act 27 of 1913, which in effect represented the equivalent of the nationalisation of by far the largest part of the country by whites. Pixley Seme, the convener of the conference in Bloemfontein, in his address to the delegates described as follows the situation which had to be redressed: Chiefs of royal blood and fellow Africans, we have discovered that in the land of our birth we are treated as hewers of wood and drawers of water for the white race. The white people of South Africa have formed a union of their own; which does not recognise us as its integral part. In this union, the Africans have no say in the making and no part in the administration of the laws of the country. 174 171 See Davenport South Africa 247ff. 172 Felt South Africa 1. 173 On the formation of the ANC, see Meli A history of the ANC 34ff; Karls & Carter From protest to challenge vol 1 61ff; De Villiers Die "African National Congress" en sy aktiwiteite aan die Witwatersrand part 1 23ff; Benson The African patriots 25ff and Esterhuyse & Nel Die ANC 9ff. See also R V S Thema "How Congress began" Drum July 1953 and his series of articles "Towards national unity" Bantu World 19, 26 Sept; 3, 10, 24, 31 Oct; 14, 28 Nov; 5, 12, 19, 26 Dec 1953; 9, 23 Jan; 20, 27 Feb and 24 April 1954. 174 Quoted from R V S Thema "Towards national unity" Bantu World 26 The most direct and visible legacy of Gandhi and his movement to the broader liberation movement in South Africa is to be found in the first constitution of the ANC. 175 Under the heading, "Methods or Modus Operandi", the constitution provided that "the work of the Association [that is, the ANC] shall be affected or advanced ... by passive action or continued movement." 176 In practice the organization at this stage would mainly use "constitutional" - and futile methods, such as sending deputations to the Prime Minister and to London to voice its protests. In essence the ANC at this stage constituted an exclusively black elite which pursued its own narrow self-interest strictly within the confines of what was acceptable to the white rulers. 177 To a large extent the political vision it represented was confined to a plea for a return to the qualified vote system of Cape liberalism. John Dube, the first President of the ANC, expressed his "hopeful reliance in the sense of common justice and love of freedom so innate in the British character" to bring relief to the position of blacks where needed. 178 The ANC in fact remained a small and largely ineffectual organization until the Defiance Campaign of 1952. Before that date civil disobedience - and any other form of political resistance - would only be practised on a limited scale by individuals or small groups. Some of the more widely published incidents will now be discussed. The pass laws, which were an integral part of white rule in South Sept 1953. 175 The first constitution of the ANC was approved in 1919. Extracts from the constitution are reprinted in Karis & Carter From protest to challenge vol 1 76ff. In 1912 the rev Z R Mahabane, later twice President of the ANC, warned that taxation of Africans without representation would lead to "such a condition of despair" that they might be "compelled to adopt the Gandhian policy of 'non-cooperation'." Karis & Carter From protest to challenge vol 1 296. 176 Id 78. It is not clear what the words "continued movement" signify. 177 The elitist nature of the movement in its early years was reflected in remarks such as those of Professor D D T Jabavu (later the first president of the All African Convention), who expressed the resentment felt by African leaders at the fact that "the more decent native" had to share transport facilities with the "rawest blanketed heathen". See Karis & Carter From protest to challenge vo1 1 122. 178 38. Quoted in Walshe The rise of African nationalism in South Africa Africa for a very long time, provided a constant source of friction between black and white, and were a natural focusing point for acts of civil disobedience. 179 In 1913 black women of the Orange Free State engaged in civil disobedience on a large scale in protest against the extension of these laws by municipalities to also cover women in that province. Women on a large scale refused to carry passes and hundreds went to prison. In Winburg the prison became so full that the authorities were powerless to deal with the resistors. Eventually the authorities were forced to withdraw the pass laws women. 180 for This is the first recorded example of mass civil disobedience by Africans in South Africa and one of the few instances where immediate success was achieved. 181 Again women took the lead. Both the harshness of the conditions of third class travel, which Africans were compelled to use, and the desire to get away from what he called "uncivilised" and "uneducated" people, prompted S M Makgatho, President of the Transvaal branch of the ANC, to break convention by travelling to Pretoria in a second class rail coach, which was reserved for white passengers. As an "educated African" he in fact had a letter of exemption from the operation of certain laws and regulations which discriminated against Africans, 182 but he wanted to test its applicability. After serious arguments with railway officials regarding the question whether he could use second class facilities, and after having presented his letter of exemption, he was assaulted by a white passenger. In a subsequent court case the assailant was convicted and sentenced to pay a fine of one shilling or to be detained until the 179 For the history of the now abolished pass laws, see Dugard Human rights and the South African legal order 75 and Simons Africa South 1956 51. See also the detailed discussion of the early days of the pass system in R v Detody 1926 AD 198. 180 See Roux Time longer than rope 125. 181 The campaign was halted when South Africa entered the First World War on the side of Britain, but revived afterwards, and continued at least until 1920. For an account of the campaign, and the role of Sol Plaatje and Louis Botha in it, see Benson South Africa 33. 182 Such letters were issued under the Coloured Persons' Exemption (or Relief) Proclamation 35 of 1901 (Transvaal) to blacks who were ministers of Christian denominations, or who have attained certain educational qualifications, etc. rising of the court. 183 The case was taken up by the ANC and received wide publicity. According to R V S Thema, it "became a topic of discussion around glowing fires at tribal kgotlas in the rural areas, and in the slums of urban locations." 184 In 1917, at Evaton, a number of Congress leaders, including R V Selope Thema, were arrested when they sat on the only bench on the station and refused to get up when told by the station foreman that the bench was not to be used by "Kaffirs". They were arrested and held in custody for a short time. Their claim against the state for damages resulting from an unlawful arrest (much to their disappointment) was settled out of court by their attorney. Each one received £10. Separate facilities for blacks were then provided on the station. 185 Encouraged by these events, other Congress leaders courted arrest by openly using sidewalks in Johannesburg which were reserved for the use of whites. 186 They were subjected to much abuse from white pedestrians and eventually forcibly arrested. In court they then produced their letters of exemption. In this way they established the applicability of these letters to a wide range of discriminatory practices. 187 Illegal industrial action was also developed as a tool during this 183 See R V S Thema "Towards national unity" Bantu World 12, 19 Dec 1953. See also Lodge Black politics in South Africa since 1945 2, who presumably refers to the same incident. 184 See R V S Thema "Towards national unity" Bantu World 19 Dec 1953. 185 See R V S Thema "Towards national unity" Bantu World 28 Dec 1953. When those arrested were told that a woman had to stand because they refused to get up from the bench, Thema asked whether they were arrested for a breach of etiquette. For an account of an analogous incident which occurred in Britain, where an ANC delegation called on Lloyd George and were thrown off their ship, see "Kontrese loe Hsediseng" The Bantu World 8 Oct 1949. (Translated from Sotho for the author by Isiah Methlape.) 186 The bylaw under which they were charged was issued in terms of s 42(50) of the Municipal Corporations Ordinance 58 of 1903 (Transvaal), as amended by s 26(e) of the Municipal Corporations Amendment Ordinance 41 of 1904 (Transvaal), which authorised municipalities to prohibit "the use of sidewalks of any public street by natives not holding letters of exemption ... and by coloured persons who are not respectably dressed and well conducted." 187 See R V S Thema "Towards national unity" The Bantu World 28 Dec time. 188 In 1919, Africans disobedience in campaign. the 189 Transvaal Thousands engaged of in Africans an anti-pass marched to civil the pass office in Johannesburg, where they turned in their passes. Speakers made statements such as: "We count for nothing in Parliament" and “[w]e have a right to be heard, and will be heard." The need for non-violence was emphasised. collected, All "Rule, weapons Britannia" in the was hands sung, and of those the present British were King, the Governor General and President Woodrow Wilson were cheered by those participating in the protest. When the leaders were arrested women collected passes from Africans throughout the city. Thousands of passes were destroyed and about 700 Africans were arrested. They were told by the police that they would be punished for their "traitorous actions". Some were charged with disturbing the peace, others with inciting workers to leave their employment. Eventually violence erupted. A subsequent commission of inquiry recognised to some 190 extent the legitimacy of the protests, but its recommendations (which amounted to a simplification government. The of the campaign pass system) achieved were very not little, accepted both in by the terms of changing the behaviour of the government and in terms of mobilising the masses politically. With the colonial occupation of Africa by the European powers still firmly in place, the outside world could not be moved. Two incidents thereupon ruthless attitude to religious group called commonage, non-violent the Queenstown, which underscored opposition. "Israelites" to In the 1920 assembled celebrate on government’s members the the passover. See De Villiers Die "African National aktiwiteite aan die Witwatersrand part 2 255. Congress" 188 near occurred of a Bulhoek 191 When en sy 189 See "Native menace" The Star 31 March 1919. For a discussion of the campaign, see Roux Time longer than rope 125ff and De Villiers Die "African National Congress" en sy aktiwiteite aan die Witwatersrand part 2 258. One pass resister said he was engaging in civil disobedience because he had "always been taught in his boyhood days that the British government was the most liberal and freedomloving of a11 governments." Quoted in Karis & Carter From protest to challenge vol 1 107. 190 See Walshe Black nationalism in South Africa 15. 191 They believed the New Testament was a fiction of the white man's instructed to do so, they refused to leave, claiming that they had been ordered there by Jehovah to await the end of the world. In May 1921, after protracted attempts to have them leave, soldiers opened fire, killing 163 people. 192 In the following year the Bordelswarts in the then South West Africa refused to pay certain dog taxes levied by the South African government, which controlled the territory under a League of Nations mandate. Jan Smuts subdued this revolt by sending in soldiers with machine guns and bomber planes, killing more than 100 people. 193 number of strikes by especially white workers were also suppressed. A 194 In October 1920, 23 Africans were killed in Port Elizabeth when panicstricken white civilians fired into a crowd of demonstrating against refusals to raise minimum wages. The non-violent resistance of the Transvaal blacks who were 195 Native Congress (later called the ANC (Transvaal)), through the intervention of the courts, met with some success. In 1921 it challenged the validity of a poll tax imposed on black people by the Transvaal Provincial Administration. It was argued that the ordinance under which the tax was levied was ultra vires in terms of the statutory powers of the administration. After the leadership had a consultation with Smuts, in which he agreed with their point of view, two members of the organization created a test case by refusing to pay the tax. Upon conviction, a nominal fine was imposed by a Johannesburg magistrate. On appeal the conviction was set aside by the Provincial Division, which ruled that the Provincial Administration lacked the power to impose the tax. When the Provincial Administration appealed, the Appellate Division also ruled that the ordinance was ultra vires. 196 imagination and they had to worship on the model of the Israelite patriarchs who were liberated by Jehovah from the yoke of oppressive rulers. 192 See Roux Time longer than rope 143ff. 193 Id 149ff. The treason case R v Christian 1924 AD 101 arose out of these events. For a discussion, see Corder Judges at work 74ff. 194 Id 151. 195 Walshe The rise of African nationalism in South Africa 72. 196 See Transvaal Provincial Administration v letanka 1923 AD 102. The case is discussed by De Villiers Die "African National Congress" en sy aktiwiteite aan die Witwatersrand part 1 48. In 1921, members of Congress were under the impression that they had gained a sympathetic ear from the mayor of Johannesburg regarding the inadequacy of transport facilities for blacks. When a year later nothing had been done, a member of Congress (apparently acting on its instructions) boarded a tram reserved for whites. He was forcibly removed from the bus and succeeded with a claim for damages against the city council. A separate tram service for blacks was then introduced. 197 In spite of these small and ambivalent "victories", however, it became obvious at the beginning of the 1920’s that the central leadership of Congress was out of touch with demands of the masses. Black working class aspirations at this stage found better expression in the shortlived, but immensely popular. Industrial and Commercial Workers’ Union ("ICU"), which was founded Kadalie as its secretary. Party of South Africa 198 in 1922 with the charismatic Clements Some Africans also joined the Communist ("CPSA"), which, at the time, was the only political organization in the country of which the membership was open to all races. 199 In August 1926, Kadalie, having been refused a permit to go to Natal, nevertheless attended some meetings in Durban. Upon his return to Johannesburg he declared that the best way to deal with the pass laws was to defy them. He was arrested, brought back to Durban and charged before the local magistrate. Although he was convicted, he appealed and succeeded on a technical point. 200 At a turbulent conference in April 1927 the ICU, after being referred to Gandhi’s use of civil disobedience in India, rejected Kadalie’s idea of a national day of prayer as too mild. A motion was passed which envisaged the organization of "a passive resistance movement throughout the Union." 201 In 1927, in the Orange Free State the local chairperson of the ICU, Johannes Mogorosi, refused to pay "certain location rates and charges" 197 See De Vi11iers Die "African National aktiwiteite aan die Witwatersrand part 2 265. Congress" 198 en sy The ICU was the first modern mass movement of black people in South Africa. See Meli A history of the ANC 63ff. 199 Renamed the South African Communist Party in 1953. 200 See Roux Time longer than rope 167ff. 201 Id 179. in contravention of the "Location Regulations", which rendered such conduct an offence. His aim was to create a test case to establish whether such conduct was not ultra vires. He was convicted and his appeal was dismissed in the Supreme Court. 202 A subsequent attempt by members of the ICU to incite a general boycott of the rates and charges was flouted when the ANC leadership encouraged people to "render unto Caesar that which is Caesar’s" and to use established channels for negotiation. 203 In the same year the ICU also took the initiative in creating test cases to challenge the validity of proclamations enforcing segregated living areas in Johannesburg. 204 In two cases taken to the Supreme Court the relevant proclamations were declared ultra vires. 205 At the 1929 ANC congress a proposal that the pass laws should be met with a campaign of civil disobedience was rejected. 206 In 1930, the CPSA planned a nationwide campaign of pass-burning on 16 December, claiming that "[y]ou cannot imprison millions." The campaign was opposed by the ANC and by Kadalie, who warned that the government would find space in gaol for the law breakers. Eventually the campaign was observed almost nowhere except in Durban, where it was most brutally suppressed by the police. As the protesters were forming a 202 See R v Mogorosi 1927 OPD 293. 203 See De Vi11iers Die "African National aktiwiteite aan die Witwatersrand part 1 75. Congress" en sy 204 Id part 2 267. 205 See R v Hodos & Jaghbay 1927 TPD 101 and R v Zock 1927 TPD 582. 206 See De Villiers Die "African National Congress" en sy aktiwiteite aan die Witwatersrand part 1 81. In 1925 the ANC sponsored an appeal of a black woman who was arrested for not carrying a night pass in contravention of s 3 of the Transvaal Ordinance 43 of 1902, which required all "natives" to carry night passes. In a split decision the Appellate Division ruled that the provisions were not applicable to women. See R v Detody 1926 AD 198. For a discussion of the circumstances leading up to this case, see De Vi11iers Die "African National Congress" en sy akt1w1te1te aan die Witwatersrand part 1 63 and for a discussion of the case itself, see Corder Judges at work 141. On the ANC's failed campaign of civil disobedience that would have been aimed against night pass laws which were made applicable to black women in 1931, see the account of De Villiers at 270. procession and collecting passes in bags, the police arrived and broke up the meeting with assegais, pick handles and revolvers. Four men were killed; twenty were seriously wounded. Nevertheless the campaign continued until virtually all the leaders were arrested. Thirty-two were subsequently charged and convicted of “incitement to violence”. Black communists were charged with being “idle, disorderly” persons and deported to their country homes. dissolute or 207 Kadalie, however, now followed a policy of hamba kahle (go carefully) and chose not to offend the government. After some strike action was orchestrated by Kadalie, the ICU - one of the most powerful black political organizations the country has ever known - faded from and Smuts existence. In 1936, commonly regarded as a watershed year, Hertzog managed to push through two acts which were supposed to provide the "solution to the native problem". 208While the Development Trust and Land Act 18 of 1936 added marginally more land to the black reserves, it also prohibited blacks from owning land outside the "native reserves". The Representation of Blacks Act 12 of 1936 abolished the Cape common voters’ roll. In future African interests would be "represented" by whites who were separately elected. The Native Representative Council, an advisory body, was to be established. In reaction to the prospect of these provisions coming into force, the A11 African Convention ("AAC"), an umbrella body which included the ANC and other organizations, was established in 1935. 209 Their opposition, however, amounted to little more than verbal rejection of the status quo. The more activist members were contained by the conservatives. The only recorded example of the use of civil disobedience by the AAC occurred in 1936, when one of -its members (apparently under orders from the AAC) boarded a tram reserved for whites, and refused to disembark when ordered to do so. He was charged with contravention of the Johannesburg Tramways by-laws, which stated that the City Council 207 In terms of s 17 of the Blacks (Urban Areas) Act 21 of 1923. See also Roux Time longer than rope 256ff and L Kuper "Nonviolence revisited" in Rotberg & Mazrui Protest and power in black Africa 788 at 796. 208 Walshe Black nationalism in South Africa 12. 209 See Me1i A history of the ANC 84. could set apart any car or portion of a car for the exclusive use of members of a particular race group. 210 The prosecutor did not press for a conviction and the accused was acquitted on the basis that there were no trams for blacks in service at the time on the same line, and the conductor had a wide discretion as to whom to allow travelling on the tram. 211 In 1936 a case reached the Appellate Division in which a coloured man was convicted of contravention of a railway regulation, 212 which had reserved certain benches others for "non-Europeans". on 213 Kimberley station for "Europeans" and The appellant had been sitting on a bench marked "Europeans only" when he was asked to move, and he refused to do so. According to the appellant, he belonged to an association of coloured persons who desired to test their right to use the benches marked "Europeans only". 214 The appeal was dismissed on the ground that the statute in question authorised such reservation of facilities for the exclusive use by particular races. 215 These acts of resistance did little to impress either the government or the outside world, or, with the exception of the activities of the illfated ICU, to mobilise the masses. The outbreak of World War II ended the first phase of resistance. 216 (b) Phase two: The 1940's After the Second World War, industrialisation and urbanisation took place on an unprecedented scale in South Africa. The African population nearly doubted between 1932 and 1952. 217 The inevitable politicising which consequently ensued, coupled with the poor living conditions of 210 Section 33. 211 See De Villiers Die "African National aktiwiteite aan die Witwatersrand part 2 275. Congress" en sy 212 Regulation 19(d) of the General Railway Regulations, framed under s 4(6) of the Railways and Harbours Regulation, Control and Management Act 22 of 1916. 213 See R v Herman 1937 AD 168. 214 At 169. 215 For a discussion, see Corder Judges at work 148. 216 0n African and Indian opposition to, as well as participation in, the War, see Roux Time longer than rope 3l0ff. 217 See Lodge Black politics in South Africa since 1945 11. the majority of Africans, found expression in two early campaigns of non-violent resistance: The Alexandra Bus Boycott and the Johannesburg Squatters’ Movement. Between 1940 and 1945 increases in bus fares from the freehold suburb, Alexandra, to the centre of Johannesburg were boycotts that lasted for various lengths of time. 218 met with sporadic At times up to 20 000 people walked to work, which meant that some had to get up at 03:00 and arrived at home only after 21:00 in the evening. The boycott eventually met with success when the Council agreed to sponsor the fares, but the initiators of the boycott (the ANC and the CPSA) lost credibility because of ineffective organization and lack of positive leadership. 219 More important for the struggle as a whole was the fact that the effectiveness of the mass boycott action as a weapon in the hands of Africans had been emphasised. The protest was still legal, but this would soon change. Between 1944 and 1947 thousands of families illegally moved into open land near the established townships outside Johannesburg, where they built shelters with whatever was at hand. The movement was spontaneous and was aimed at securing physical survival rather than at expressing political resistance. It occurred with little if any encouragement from organizations such as the ANC. Eventually the shelters of the squatters were destroyed by the government, and they were absorbed in the massive complex of housing estates around Orlando. The Johannesburg Squatters’ Movement signalled a willingness on the part of black people openly and non-violently to take the law into their own hands when deemed necessary. The treatment to which they were subjected, however, also demonstrated an inclination on the part of the government to intervene with force and to impose its own perception of law and order on the black community. 220 The ANC began developing into something resembling a national movement with a modern branch structure in the 1940’s when Dr Xuma was President General. 221 Structures developed in these years would prove to be vital in the process of mass political mobilisation which was to take place 218 Id 13. See also Roux Time longer than rope 325ff. 219 Id 15. 220 Id 16. 221 Walshe Black nationalism in South Africa 26. in the next decade. The approach followed in the forties was more assertive than before, and the initiative was no longer left entirely in the hands of the government. Inspired in part by the Atlantic Charter of 1941, a major policy statement called “African Claims in South Africa” was issued by the ANC in 1945 after long consultation. A "Bill of Rights" was outlined, which now for the first time provided for a "one person one vote" system of franchise and direct representation of Africans in parliament. 222 The "meritocratic" ideals of earlier were abandoned. In 1946, Dr Xuma would ask the Native Representative Council to disband. As Oliver Tambo later put it: "[T]he Africans, heartened by the Allies’ promise of a postwar world in which the fundamental rights of all men would be respected, became increasingly impatient with their lot." 223 The fact that their objectives and aims were spelled out provided a basis for a more assertive approach. In 1943, Smuts, by now a prestigious international figure, was returned to parliament with an increased majority. Black hopes for a better deal were reinforced by black participation in the War, and by the description by Smuts’s Secretary of Native Affairs of the policy of "separate development" as an illusion. 224 These changed circumstances, both at home and abroad, would directly affect the nature of black politics in South Africa. The hope that the South African government would voluntarily meet these expectations was relinquished when Smuts refused an interview requested by Xuma, and rejected the ANC’s application of the Atlantic Charter to the situation of Africans in South Africa. It became clear that white hegemony was not about to disband; on the contrary, there could be little doubt that if left to itself, the white government would only increase its hold on the future of the black population. At the end of 1943, Congress declared the pass laws “enemy number one”. An Anti-pass Council was established by the ANC and the SAIC. Anti-pass conferences were held and several demonstrations followed. In June 1945, after an unsuccessful attempt to meet with Acting Prime Minister 222 See Karis & Carter From protest to challenge vol 2 209. 223 See O Tambo "Passive resistance in South Africa" in Davis & Baker Southern Africa in transition 217 at 219. 224 See Walshe Black nationalism in South Africa 28. J H Hofmeyr, an unlawful demonstration was held outside the Houses of Parliament. The leaders of the demonstration, including Dr Dadoo and R V S Thema, procession. were arrested and fined for leading an unlawful 225 In April 1944, members of the ANC established the Youth League under the leadership of Anton Lembede. 226 Rejecting the traditional elitist nature of the ANC and its negative strategy of reaction, the Youth League set itself the objective of infusing the national liberation movement with "the spirit of African self-determination". 227 They would take organised African politics African from opposition a mind into frame of the streets, protest into and one transform of active resistance. When they presented their manifesto to Dr Xuma, the leaders of the Youth League stated as one of their criticisms against the ANC the fact that "there was no programme of action - no passive resistance or some such action." 228 Clearly, they felt that African opposition had to go on the offensive. The orientation of the new generation was distinctly Africanist; their approach confrontational. Various factors accounted for the increase in the political awareness of the black community at this time. On the home front there was an increased dissatisfaction with the unyielding white rule and the deteriorating living conditions. On the international front, reference has been made to the influence of the Second World War. Since 1945, the United Nations ("UN") for the first time also provided an international forum which would take an active interest in the domestic affairs of countries. In the aftermath of Nazism and the devastating consequences it had for world peace, racism would be regarded in a far more serious light than before. In India the precedent of a third world country breaking the hold of a European power was established. The ANC established contact with other African leaders for the first time in many years when its representatives attended the 1945 meeting of the Pan-African Congress in Manchester. The congress, attended by many of Africa’s young leaders like Kwame Nkrumah and Jomo Kenyatta, 225 Roux Time longer than rope 328ff. 226 See Meli A history of the ANC 108. 227 See the "Congress Youth League Manifesto", reprinted in Karis & Carter From protest to challenge vo1 2 300 at 306. 228 See Lodge Black politics in South Africa since 1945 25. endorsed Gandhian civil disobedience as persuade alien rulers races. to respect the the only effective rights of unarmed way to and subjected 229 In 1946, a major strike was organised by the "African Mine Workers Union", which was terminated only when the police shot and killed at least nine people. 230 In 1946, a two year "Passive Resistance Campaign" 231 was launched by members of the South African Indian Congress ("SAIC"), which to some extent acted in alliance with the ANC. It was the first initiated campaign in the country since the days of Gandhi. 232 IndianThis was to protest against the Asiatic Land Tenure and Indian Representation Act 28 of 1946, commonly known as the "Ghetto Act". 233 In terms of this Act, the Indians were awarded communal representation, at the price of restrictions on their rights to land and property. 234 229 230 See Benson The African patriots 117. See De Villiers Die "African National aktiwiteite aan die Witwatersrand part 1 154. Congress" en sy 231 This term is usually used to distinguish this Campaign from the 1952 Campaign. 232 ln 1939, Indians clashed violently with each other on the question of the use of civil disobedience, and nothing came of it. See Simons Class and colour in South Africa 507. The correspondence between Yusuf Dadoo and Gandhi, since 1939, when the former asked Gandhi's advice on a passive resistance campaign in South Africa, is reprinted in Dadoo South Africa's freedom struggle 293. For his statements during the Campaign, see id 34. 233 Lodge Black politics in South Africa since 1945 25, 38. See also Kuper Passive resistance in South Africa 97, Meli A history of the ANC 96, Benson South Africa 95 and Simons Class and colour in South Africa 551. A pass-burning campaign planned for 1946 by the ANC failed to materialise. See De Villiers Die "African National Congress" en sy aktiwiteite aan die Witwatersrand part 1 146. 234 The history of this Campaign is vividly portrayed in the pages of Flash, something between a newsletter and a flyer which was brought out by the Passive Resistance Councils of the Natal Indian Congress and the Transvaal Indian Congress during the Passive Resistance Campaign, 21 June to 14 August 1946. It ran reports on more than 47 batches of resistors that were arrested. In the first month, 287 people were imprisoned. See Flash 26 July 1946. The accused typically pleaded guilty and then proceeded to address the court at length on their reasons for transgressing the law. Many of these statements were also published in Flash. The accused used the opportunity to describe their poor living conditions and the injustice of the laws they The Campaign took the form of Hartals (economic boycotts), illegal crossings of provincial borders, and the occupation of selected sites in “white” areas of Durban. By 1948, some 2 000 protesters had been convicted and had served terms of several months’ imprisonment with hard labour. The Campaign, in terms of its immediate objectives, met with no success. It did, however, increase the membership of the Natal Indian Congress from a few hundred to 35 000. 235 The Campaign also provided the leadership of the ANC with an example of how people could be mobilised. It stimulated an appetite in the African community to express their grievances in a more forceful way. Especially younger African nationalists, such as Nelson Mandela, were impressed by witnessing this type of protest action. 236 in Later, Professor Z K Matthews would describe the Passive Resistance Campaign as the “immediate inspiration” for the ANC’s 1949 decision to employ civil disobedience. 237 Direct confrontation between the government and a majority of the population was inevitable when, in the 1948 elections, the National Party ("NP") gained power on the apartheid ticket. The Nationalist victory heralded an era of increased legislative and administrative racial suppression and a decreasing liberalising outside influences. openness of the government to 238 The decrease of legitimacy of the government directly increased the legitimacy of resistance. The exclusive white nationalism of the NP had the inevitable effect of eliciting black nationalism and “non-white” solidarity. The example which the white nationalists set in respect of objected to. Some mentioned the legacy of Gandhi as their direct inspiration. See eg Flash 1 Aug 1946. For an overview of the Campaign, see De Villiers Die "African National Congress" en sy aktiwiteite aan die Witwatersrand part 1 152ff. See also K A Moodley "South African Indians: The waivering minority" in Thompson & Butler Change in contemporary South Africa 250 at 260. 235 Meli A history of the ANC 99. 236 Mandela was a dose friend of Ismail Meer, one of the organisers of the Passive Resistance Campaign and editor of its journal. The Passive Resister. See Benson South Africa 95. 237 238 See Karis & Carter From protest to challenge vol 2 103. What can be called the "dosing of the South African government's mind" would be epitomised by the declaration of a Republic in 1961 and the South African departure from the Commonwealth in the same year. the means which can be used to pursue one’s goats was one of no holes barred - also in respect of obedience to the law. Reacting to the Smuts government’s declaration of war on behalf of the Union on the side of Britain, Or Malan stated at the NP 239 Conference at Cradock in 1940: “Daar rus op ons nie die minste plig om te voldoen aan die Verdedigingswet nie. Daarom se die Party aan die Afrikaners: As julle geen gehoor wil gee nie, gee dan geen gehoor nie, want julle handel binne julle reg.” 240 Reacting to the prospect of banning of the (then still non-violent) Ossewabrandwaq. Malan said the following: As die regering daartoe oorgaan, se ek dat dit tyd is om halt te roep, dat die Afrikaner geen gehoorsaamheid aan die regering verskuldig is nie. As die hou van ver-gaderings belet is, sal ek my voile morele steun gee aan passiewe ongehoorsaamheid. Ek is bereid om suike ver-gaderings by te woon en deel daaraan te neem - laat die gevolge wees wat dit wil. 241 After its assumption of power, the NP would show blatant disregard for the rule of law, as evidenced by the way in which the coloureds were removed from the common voters’ roll. 242 Now safely in power, however, it would expect the most fastidious obedience to its laws from all those under its rule. Against this background the third phase of the liberation struggle, during which time widespread illegal activity would take place, commenced. (c) Phase three: The Defiance Campaign of the 1950's 239 Or, more correctly, the Reunited National Party, as the party was called until 1951. 240 Quoted from "Or Malan vertolk wi1 van nuwe Afrikanerdom" Die Burger 31 Oct 1940. 241 Ibid. On the subsequent history of the relationship between Malan and the "Ossewabrandwag", see Van der Schyff Die Ossewabrandwag 58ff. It is interesting to note that John Vorster, later Prime Minister and State President of South Africa, when he was placed under house arrest in the Cape during the Second World War, simply ignored the order and moved to the Transvaal. The Smuts government in turn ignored him. See "Civil disobedience" Business Day 24 Aug 1989. See also, on the history of violent and non-violent resistance by Afrikaners, Piet van der Schyff's "Verset deur Afrikaners" Bee1d 17 May 1991 and "Verset kom 'n lang pad" Beeld 21 May 1991. 242 For a discussion of this history, see Forsyth In danger for their talents 61ff. When the Nationalists came into power in 1948, they started erecting the cornerstones of "Grand Apartheid", including the Prohibition of Mixed Marriages Act 55 of 1949, the Population Registration Act 30 of 1950 and the Group Areas Act 41 of 1950. The Immorality Act 5 of 1927 was also amended to extend the ban on sexual intercourse between “Europeans” and “natives” to prohibit intercourse between “Europeans” and all “non-Europeans”. 243 (i) Prelude to mass civil disobedience The Youth League argued in favour of a passive resistance campaign in response to these developments. 244 When Dr Xuma tried to block this strategy, he in 1949 was replaced as President-General of the ANC by the more militant (but nevertheless still elitist) Or Moroka. Youth Leaguers who were now elected to the national executive of the ANC were Nelson Mandela, Oliver Tambo and Waiter Sisulu. 245 In December 1949, at its annual conference. Congress adopted a statement of policy, entitled the "Programme of Action", 246 backed by the Youth strike[s], strategies. League, [and] 247 It in which civil would, the use disobedience” however, of, inter were take endorsed some “boycott[s], a1ia, time as acceptable before civil disobedience would be implemented in practice. Various experiments with campaigns of resistance were now conducted by the ANC. In 1950, three major demonstrations took place. 248 The first was a “Freedom of Speech Convention”, over which Dr Moroka presided. Secondly, it was announced that May Day would be marked by a stay-away from work. Because of the involvement of the CPSA in arranging the May Day stay-away, many of the Youth League leaders refused to endorse it. Nevertheless, the demonstration went ahead and was widely observed, 243 This was done by means of the Immorality Amendment Act 21 of 1950. 244 When train apartheid was announced on 13 Aug 1948, the Communist Party convened a large meeting in Cape Town, also attended by a number of other parties. A largely unsuccessful attempt was made to fill whites-only coaches. See Lodge Black politics in South Africa since 1945 40. 245 See Lodge Black politics 1n South Africa since 1945 27. 246 Reprinted in Karis & Carter From protest to challenge vol 2 337. 247 Id 338. 248 See Kuper Passive resistance in South Africa 98. especially on the Reef. It is difficult to establish who was to blame, but there were clashes between the protesters and the nearly 2 000 members of the police who were placed on duty. Violence erupted, and a number of people were killed when the police opened fire. 249 The third demonstration, held on 26 June, was a “Day of Protest” against the Group Areas and the Suppression of Communism Bills, 250 and a day of mourning for Africans who had lost their lives in the struggle for liberation. No surprisingly, the demonstration was not successful in term of preventing the passing of these bills, but the date would become historic as “South African Freedom Day” to commemorate the first attempt at a political strike on a national level by the black people of the country. 251 Also in 1950, the (still predominantly white) CPSA strengthened its ties with Congress by accepting the notion of a two-stage revolution, according to which a nationalist revolution would have to precede a socialist revolution. In the same year, the Internal Security Act 44 of 1950, or the “Red Act” as it came to be called, was passed, which outlawed the Communist Party. 252 This Act also made it an independent crime to attempt to bring about any political, industrial, social or economic doubly 249 change through outlawed: first unlawful in the acts. sense Civil that disobedience civil was now disobedience per Lodge Black politics 1n South Africa since 1945 34. 250 The latter Act was considered necessary as a result of the poor success record which the state had in prosecutions under section 29 of the Black Administration Act 38 of 1927. Section 29. the so-called "hostility clause", made the promotion of "feelings of hostility between natives and Europeans" an offence and was often used against communists who advocated social change. Prosecutions under this clause were eventually supplemented by the implementation of the procedures under s 1(12) of the Riotous Assemblies and Criminal Law Amendment Act 27 of 1914, which gave the Minister of Justice power to order any individual to leave any magisterial district for a period not exceeding one year if in the opinion of the Minister his presence there could lead to the creation of "feelings of hostility" between black and white. See in general ss 1(4)-(16), which were introduced by s 1 of the Riotous Assemblies Act 17 of 1956. See also Roux Time longer than rope 211, 235ff. 251 252 See Karis & Carter From protest to challenge vol 2 406. The CPSA officially dissolved itself in anticipation of the implementation of these provisions on 20 July 1950 and went underground. However, the Act was made applicable retrospectively in 1951 to everyone who had previously subscribed to communism. definition involved the breaking of some law, and, secondly, because its motive In 1951, also placed such action within the ambit of the Red Act. 253 the struggle broadened and a greater measure of anti- government unity was established, as an increasing flow of legislation implementing Nationalist policy emerged from parliament. 254 A sense of solidarity developed between Africans, coloureds and Indians since they were a11 threatened by the rising gulf of apartheid. When coloureds formed the Franchise Action Council (“FAC”) to oppose the Separate Representation of Voters Bill 255 whereby coloured voters would be removed from the common voters’ roll, they received some support from Africans and Indians, as well as from the largely white War Veterans’ Torch Commando. In July 1951, a Joint Planning Council was appointed by leaders of the ANC, the SAIC and the FAC, in order to co-ordinate the efforts of Africans, Indians and coloureds in a mass campaign for the repeal of some of the most obnoxious laws. 256 The Council comprised James Moroka, Walter Sisulu and J B Marks of the ANC, and Yusuf Dadoo and Yusuf Cachalia of the SAIC. Both Dadoo and Cachalia were leaders in the 194648 Passive Resistance Campaign. In its report, the Joint Planning Council proposed a strategy of the use of joint mass action in the form of civil disobedience. 257 Under the heading "Plan of Action" they stated: We recommend that the form of struggle for securing the repeal of unjust laws be the DEFIANCE OF UNJUST LAWS based on non-cooperation. Defiance of unjust laws should take the form of committing breaches of certain selected laws and regulations which are undemocratic, unjust, racially discriminatory and repugnant to the natural rights of man. Rather than submit to the unjust laws we should defy them deliberately and in an organised 253 For a discussion of these provisions, see infra chap four I B (3). 254 See Lodge Black politics 1n South Africa since 1945 40. 255 Later enacted as the Separate Representation of Voters Act 46 of 1951. 256 See Kuper Passive resistance In South Africa 99. See also Karis & Carter From protest to challenge vol 2 412. 257 See the "Report of the Joint Planning Council of the ANC and the South African Indian Congresses", reprinted in Karis & Carter From protest to challenge vol 2 458. manner, and be prepared to bear the penalties thereof. Defiance of Unjust Laws should be planned into three stages although the timing would to a large extent depend on the progress, development and the outcome of the previous stage. Participation in this Campaign will be on a volunteer basis, such volunteers to undergo a period of training before the Campaign begins. Three stages of Defiance of Unjust Laws:(a) First Stage. Commencement of the struggle by calling upon selected and trained persons to go into action in the big centres, eg, Johannesburg, Cape Town, Bloemfontein, Port Elizabeth and Durban. (b) Second Stage. Number of volunteer corps to be increased as well as the number of centres of operation. (c) Third Stage. This is the stage of mass action during which as far as possible, the struggle should broaden out on a countrywide scale and assume a general mass character. For its success preparations on a mass scale to cover the people both in the urban and rural areas would be necessary. 258 This “Plan of Action” was accepted by the ANC at their December 1951 national conference. The result was the “Defiance of Unjust Laws Campaign”, or as it came to be known, the “Defiance Campaign” of 1952. Civil disobedience in South Africa would now be confronted with its most difficult test. On a nationwide scale an attempt would be made to mobilise people to confront the apartheid state, by transgressing the laws which were regarded as the “most obnoxious and which are capable of being defied”. The immediate objective of such action was the repeal of a selected number of laws and regulations; 259 the ultimate objective 258 259 Id para 8. (Original emphasis.) The law? and regulations of which the repeal was demanded were the Pass laws (.restricting the movement of blacks); the stock limitation regulations (limiting the size of the herds of cattle which could be kept in relation to the size of the land on which they are kept); the Internal Security Act 44 of 1950 (giving the government draconian powers In the name of state security); the Group Areas Act 41 of 1950 (providing for racially segregated living areas); the Black Authorities Act 68 of 1951 (granting official approval to traditional tribal authorities, which prepared the ground for the establishment of "homelands") and the Separate Representation of Voters Act 46 of 1951 (used to remove the coloureds from the common voters role). It was also stated in the report that the government was "preparing the - the end of white political hegemony. 260 It was suggested by the Joint Planning Council that because of the different effects which apartheid had on the various sections of the community, each racial group should concentrate on transgressing a different aspect of apartheid legislation, except in the Cape where “a strong possibility” was perceived of mixed units. The ANC was primarily to transgress the pass laws; the SAIC was to concentrate on breaking the ban on crossing inter-provincial borders, segregation in public facilities and the Group Areas Act, and the FAC had last two. What was envisaged, therefore, was to focus on indirect the civil disobedience, in the sense that the laws transgressed were not the only laws of which the repeal was demanded. 261 Formally, the Campaign was to be orchestrated by the National Action Council, which comprised four Africans and three Indians. In practice, however, organization was largely decentralised. 262 Nelson Mandela was appointed “National Volunteer-In-Chief” or “National Co-ordinator”. 263 machinery for the enforcement of the Population Registration Act. This Act is repugnant to a11 sections of the people and the Campaign must pay particular attention to preparing the volunteers and instructing the masses of the people to resist the enforcement of this Act." Id para 12. 260 The report of the Joint Planning Council also stated that: "Full democratic rights with a direct say in the affairs of the government are the inalienable rights of every Individual - a right which in South Africa must be realised [in the lifetime of the present generation]." Id para 7. The words in square brackets appear in the version of the same document handed in as exhibit "A" in R v Sisulu & others, unreported ease no 1417/52 W 2 Dec 1952, but not in Karis & Carter From protest to challenge vo1 2 461. 261 For a discussion of this type of indirect civil disobedience, see supra chap two IV A. 262 See N Carter "The Defiance Campaign - A comparative analysis of the organization, leadership and participation in the Eastern Cape and the Transvaal" in Institute of Commonwealth Studies Collected Seminar papers on the Societies of Southern Africa in the 19th and 20th centuries 76 at 79. 263 Lodge Black politics in South Africa since 1945 42. He was also called "General Officer Commanding". See "No strike planned for June 26" The Bantu World 21 June 1952. Although a statement "We defy" appeared under Mandela's name in African Drum Aug 1952 inviting whites to join the campaign, Mandela later denied having written it and dissociated himself from the contents. See "Mr Mandela's statement to Spark" Spark 5 Sept 1952. Nevertheless, Schadeberg Nelson Mandela 43 The fact that the protest groups had a racially based composition was largely the responsibility of Walter Sisulu, the former Africanist, 264 who was also the first to elaborate a civil disobedience strategy. 265 When asked about the attitude of the ANC towards "other non-Europeans", Or Moroka stated that the ANC, as an African organization, wanted “to retain our identity. We wish to co-operate fully but not to combine.” 266 No doubt, the bloody fighting which broke out between Africans and Indians in Durban in 1949 also contributed to this decision. 267 After adoption of the report of the Joint Planning Council in December 1951, the ANC sent a letter to the government demanding the repeal of the six specified government was laws given before notice 29 of February the 1952, intended failing campaign which of the civil disobedience which was to start with demonstrations on Van Riebeeck Day, 6 April. 268 In its answer to the letter, the Malan government described the claims as an attempt to secure “privileges” (not rights) which were not due. The differences between races were “permanent and not man-made”. The Campaign was labelled “subversive” and the Prime Minister gave notice of the state’s intention to “make full use of the machinery at its disposal” to quash the Campaign. 269 A subsequent letter to the government from the ANC, stating that still attributed the statement to Mandela. An apparently authentic message from Mandela was published as "Youth leader's call to youth" Spark 6 April 1952. See also Mokoena The South African Outlook 1952 180 and Robertson Liberalism In South Africa 71. 264 See Lodge Black politics in South Africa since 1945 41. Mandela had to be convinced by Sisulu that other races were in the first place to be invited to participate. Mandela initially feared that Africans would be dominated by other races. See Benson South Africa 137. Perhaps this explains the confusion regarding his Drum article, referred to in the previous footnote. 265 See Benson South Africa 134. 266 Drum interview, reprinted in Schadeberg Nelson Mandela and the rise of the ANC 30. 267 See Lodge Black politics in South Africa since 1945 60 and Me1i A history of the ANC 99. The government's commission of Inquiry into these riots listed the bad precepts from Indian passive resistors as one of the causes of the disaster. See Benson South Africa 125. 268 The letter is reprinted In Kuper Passive resistance In South Africa App B at 233. 269 Reprinted id 235. For the ANC's response, see "Dr Moroka answers Malan" Spark 29 Feb 1952. Africans were “striving for the attainment of fundamental human rights in the land of their birth” and that they “have explored other channels without success” and had “no alternative” disobedience, was not answered. 270 but to engage in civil A letter from the SAIC, explicitly linking the Campaign to the name of Gandhi, also failed to elicit a response from the Prime Minister. 271 On 6 April 1952 (coinciding with the climax of the Van Riebeeck tercentenary festival), public meetings were held in the major urban areas around the country, with thousands of people attending meetings in Johannesburg, Cape Town, Port Elizabeth and Kimberley. 272 the At these meetings Congress made its plans for the Campaign known to its followers. 273 In May a number of leaders of the intended Defiance Campaign were served with notices by the government, ordering them not to engage any further in the activities participating in the envisaged Campaign. 274 of the organizations In a prelude to the Defiance Campaign, and as a morale-booster, these orders were defied by a number of the leaders. 275 They were tried, convicted and sentenced to between four and six months’ imprisonment. 276 On 25 June 1952 a night of prayer 270 Reprinted in Kuper Passive resistance in South Africa App B at 239. 271 Reprinted Id 242. 272 See Benson South Africa 143. See also "'Save South Africa from fascism'" The Guardian 3 April 1952, "Thousands pledge to defy unjust laws" The Guardian 10 April 1952 and "Duisende betogers besluit: Sal wette begin trotseer" Die Transvaler 7 April 1952. 273 See "Or Moroka outlines new phase of ANC Campaign" The Bantu World 3 May 1952. See also the flyer issued by the ANC "April 6: People's protest day", reprinted in Karis & Carter From protest to challenge vol 2 482. 274 See "Militant reaction to Swart's letters' and swart cannot crush us" The Guardian 22 May 1952; "Swart gags people's leaders" Spark 23 May 1952 and "Seven Africans have received letters" The Bantu World 31 May 1952. 275 J B Marks, Transvaal President of the ANC, and a number of other people were arrested when (under orders from the leadership of the Defiance Campaign) they defied these orders. When he was arrested, Marks said: "This is the hour now. I am being crucified and I feel the weight of the cross." See "Moving scenes as Harks is arrested" The Bantu World 14 June 1952 and Karis & Carter From protest to challenge vol 2 418. 276 See Schadeberg Nelson Mandela 34. was held. 277 On the following day the Campaign started. (ii) Rationale of the Campaign A variety of interpretations of why and how the Campaign of civil disobedience was to be conducted was given by those in decision-making positions and by those who explained the Campaign to the masses. While the immediate objective of the Campaign was stated as being the elimination of the laws listed, it was generally accepted that the ultimate objective was equal political status for whites and blacks. 278 In South African terms this would amount to a revolution. Anarchy, however, was rejected. Albert Lutuli and others made it clear that those who were behind the Defiance Campaign were not proposing the indiscriminate breaking of the law, rejection of “a particular kind of law”. but wanted to signify their 279 The basis of the claims for the repeal of the laws and the ending of the apartheid system was in some cases advanced in the language of natural law and human rights. The Joint Planning Council, for example, said they African”. However, 280 were claiming “the inalienable rights of every South Lutuli asked the Question “Shall we obey God or man?” there were differences in approach to the use 281 of the instrument of non-violent resistance. Some adhered to non-violence on a principled basis. For this approach they drew inspiration, inter alia, from their Christian beliefs or from the teachings of Gandhi. The majority, however, saw non-violence as a temporary strategy. Lutuli (who, incidentally, had visited India some years earlier) was motivated, at least at this stage of his life, by a principled belief 277 See Benson South Africa 146. 278 See Karis & Carter From protest to challenge vol 2 414. See also Kuper The British Journal of Sociology 1953 243 at 254. Compare also Sisutu's observation that a limited franchise would not appeal to the "great majority of non-whites". Karis & Carter From protest to challenge vol 2 423. 279 See Luthuli Let my people go 110. His book was published under the name "Luthuli", but he spelled his name "Lutuli". See Karis & Carter From protest to challenge vol 4 62. 280 Karis & Carter From protest to challenge vol 2 461 para 7. 281 Id 488. in non-violence, often clothed in strong religious fervour. 282 Looking back on the Defiance Campaign, Lutuli would later observe that June 26 marked "the acceptance by the African people of the fact that the road to freedom is sanctified by martyrs: in other words. ‘No cross no crown’." 283 Lutuli’s justification for the use of civil disobedience was strongly reminiscent tried to show of Gandhi’s idea of “truth-force”: “[W]e have what the realities are in the hope that the whites could see the imperative need to conform to them.” 284 Several leaders perceived that civil disobedience could be used, as it was used by Gandhi, as a powerful tool of immanent critique, forcing the white rulers to reconsider the true implications of their own professed Christianity. Or Moroka, for example, said that there was an ongoing need to evangelise the Europeans. 285 Dr Njongwe described the Campaign as a fight against the destruction of “faith in Christianity as a way of life”. 286 According to a statement attributed to one of the accused in a trial during the Campaign, it was envisaged that “[i]f the policy of noncollaboration is successfully carried out by the masses it will leave the herrenvolk with two roads open to them - capitulation or open dictatorship.” 287 One of Gandhi’s disciples in South Africa, Nana Sita, saw the Campaign as a manifestation of Satyaaraha, and declared: “By suffering we shall march forward with this weapon” - the weapon being civil disobedience, which he declared was “stronger than the atomic bomb”. 288 Nevertheless, the dominant approach was less idealistic. A number of ANC leaders, like Z K Matthews, justified their decision not to engage 282 See Karis & Carter From protest to challenge vol 2 425. See also Hendricks From moderation to militancy 193, where Lutuli's legacy 18 discussed in some detail. 283 See Lutuli's observations "What June 26 means to African people" New Age 27 June 1957. 284 See Luthu1i Let my people go 102. 285 Benson South Africa 144. 286 Id 146. 287 See "'Democracy or open dictatorship'" People's 1952. 288 See Kuper Passive resistance in South Africa 120. World 9 Oct in violence on the pragmatic basis that the use of violence leaves bitterness, as was evident from the aftermath of the Anglo-Boer War. 289 When asked whether the envisaged Campaign was to be conducted with methods similar to those used by Gandhi, Dr Moroka was also not dogmatic about it: “Yes, along those lines. Passive resistance is the most effective method open to us.” 290 As Lodge observed: It is unlikely that many subscribed to Gandhi’s notion of Satyagraha in which the suffering of those punished for disobedience was supposed to activate the inherent goodness of the rulers. More conceivably, a large number of those who eventually participated in the Campaign probably hoped that their actions would succeed in disorganising authority by filling the prisons and the courts to capacity. 291 Some leaders described civil disobedience to the people as a manoeuvre which would throw the police off balance: “But what will they say now? ‘Hoe gaan ons werk, kerels, die mense baklei nie.’ You must give them that headache.” 292 ANC leaders like Oliver Tambo, while accepting the method of non- violent resistance, explicitly rejected Gandhi’s belief in the creative power of suffering. Tambo’s approach was explicitly coercive. According to him: Mahatma believed in the effectiveness of what he called the ‘soul force’ in passive resistance. According to him, the suffering experienced in passive resistance inspired a change of heart in the rulers. The [ANC], on the other hand, expressly rejected any concepts and methods of struggle that took the form of a selfpitying, arms-folding, and passive reaction to oppressive policies. It felt that nothing short of aggressive pressure from the masses of the people would bring about any change in the political situation in South Africa. As a countermeasure to Mahatma Gandhi’s passive resistance, the ANC launched, in 1952, the Campaign for the Defiance of Unjust Laws. 293 289 See Benson The African patriots 175. 290 Interview by Drum magazine, reprinted in Schadeberg Nelson Mandela and the rise of the ANC 30. Before the Campaign Moroka studied Gandhi's writings. See Benson South Africa 140. 291 Lodge Black politics in South Africa since 1945 41. 292 Quoted in Kuper Passive resistance in South Africa 119. 293 O Tambo "Passive resistance in South Africa" in Davis & Baker Southern Africa In transition 217 at 217. Fatima Meer responded to To Tambo, “[n]on-vio1ence was ... a political tactic that could be changed according to the demands of the political situation at any time.” 294 Sisulu was also not a Gandhian and wanted the Campaign to be “typically South African and militant”. 295 Even the choice of the name “Defiance Campaign” as opposed to “Passive Resistance Campaign”, Yusuf Dadoo later said, was intended to signify the militant nature of the Campaign. 296 According to Mandela, “[a]partheid had to be disorganised and made unworkable.” 297 He described the Defiance Campaign as 298 (In “extremely dangerous to the stability and security of the state”. the later Treason Trial, however, Mandela testified that he had expected the government, when the Campaign reached the stage of mass defiance, either at its own accord to “remove an discrimination” or to do so under pressure from the voters. 299) Meli regarded the philosophy underlying violence. 300 the Defiance Campaign as “broader” than Gandhian non- Both Z K Matthews and Lutuli, in their testimony at the this observation by saying, "Tambo has clearly misunderstood Gandhian passive resistance and is wrong in thinking that there was any difference between the Indian and African approach in using it. Whereas the philosophical content of Satyagraha remained crucial to Gandhi, the Indian masses in India and South Africa rarely understood that content or subscribed to it." See F Meer "African nationalism some inhibiting factors" in Adam South Africa 121 at 154 n 19. See also Meer Africa South 1959 21. 294 O Tambo "Passive resistance in South Africa" in Davis & Baker Southern Africa In transition 217 at 221. 295 See Benson South Africa 137. 296 See the interview with Dadoo published as "The role of the Indian people in the S African revolution" Sechaba (Special Issue) March/April 1969 14. 297 See "Debates at ANC conference" The Guardian 27 Dec 1951. 298 See Mandela's "No easy walk to freedom" address, reprinted in Mandela The struggle is my life 34 at 34. When later questioned about this statement, Mandela said he envisaged that when the third stage of the Campaign was reached, "we should have created a position whereby the government would not be able to administer certain laws." See S v Adams & others, unreported case no 1/58 SCO 1961, reasons for judgment of Bekker J at 52. For an interview concerning their objectives with the Campaign, see "Mandela re-states defiers' call" People's World 2 Oct 1952. 299 See S v Adams & others, unreported case no 1/58 SCC 1961, at 15794. 300 Meli A history of the ANC 99. Treason Trial, described the Campaign as coercive. 301 Others propagated civil disobedience as a necessary step towards violence. 302 In general, it seems that adherence to non-violence in the Defiance Campaign was largely a matter of expediency. 303 A clear vision of what the Defiance Campaign would achieve came from the talented journalist and politician, Jordan Ngubande, who described the rationale behind the Campaign, inter alia, as to create a climate for white democrats to cross the line against white supremacy, to teach Africans and Indians collaboration and to awaken world opinion to the dangers apartheid. 304 of Lutuli would later state that the objective of the Campaign was “to politicise the African people.” had the objective consciousness.” of “awakening the native to first 305 It political 306 Looking back, it seems that the objectives of the Campaign can be described as follows: Insofar as the Campaign was result-oriented or aimed at bringing about social change, it had both direct and indirect objectives. As far as the direct objectives vis-a-vis the government were concerned, there were two different approaches: one, adhered to by the Gandhians and those who were expressly motivated by Christian convictions, was the notion that the South African government could be brought to see the error of its ways through the Campaign; the second was the belief that the Campaign, even though a relatively low level of coercion was involved, could force that government to change by making its laws impossible possibility of to directly administer. affecting Another the group conduct of discarded the the government altogether, and relied entirely on its indirect effects. The indirect objectives of politicising the of Campaign encompassed prospective both supporters the and possibilities of mobilisation of international support. 301 See S v Adams & others, unreported reasons for judgment of Bekker J at 9. 302 case no 1/58 SCC 1961, Meli A history of the ANC 120. 303 See L Kuper "Nonviolence revisited" in Rotberg & Mazrui and power in black Africa 788 at 792. Protest 304 See Walshe The rise of African nationalism In South Africa 402. 305 See Karis & Carter From protest to challenge vol 2 426. 306 See "Chief addresses ANC" The Friend 11 Nov 1952. At the same time, it also seems fair to note a defensive component in the Campaign. Irrespective of its likely results, civil disobedience provided a relatively safe way of expressing feelings which people had to express simply in order to retain their own dignity. Whatever the underlying philosophy, the Campaign dearly struck a cord. Unlike many earlier attempts that had failed, this new initiative at least initially received fairly widespread support. At meetings around the country the following pledge was read out and accepted by the crowd by a show of hands: We, the oppressed people of South Africa, do hereby solemnly pledge to carry on a relentless struggle for the repeal of the unjust laws, as specified in the ‘Plan of Action’ of the African National Congress, the Franchise Action Council, the Indian Congress and freedom-loving peoples. We shall do all within our power, to the utmost limits of our endurance and sacrifice, to carry out the Congress call to fight against the unjust laws, which subject our people to political servility, economic misery and social degradation. From this day onwards we vow to act as disciplined men and women and dedicate our lives to the struggle for freedom and fundamental rights. 307 It is perhaps worth noting that no mention was made of non-violence. (iii) The Defiance Campaign The Defiance Campaign was officially launched on 26 June 1952, peaked in August to October, and was largely over in December of that year. 308 307 Quoted in "Non-European plan for 'mass defiance'" The Cape Times 7 April 1952. 308 On the history of the Defiance Campaign, see Houser Nonviolent revolution In South Africa in general; Benson The African patriots l75ff; De Villiers Die "African National Congress" en sy aktiwiteite aan die Witwatersrand part 1 186ff & part 2 291ff; Benson South Africa 140ff; Felt South Africa 27ff; L Kuper "Nonviolence revisited" in Rotberg & Mazrui Protest and power in black Africa 788ff; Walshe The rise of African nationalism in South Africa 40lff; N Carter "The Defiance Campaign - a comparative analysis of the organization, leadership and participation in the Eastern Cape and the Transvaal" in Institute of Commonwealth Studies Collected seminar papers on the societies of Southern Africa in the 19th and 20th centuries 76ff; Kuper Passive resistance In South Africa 122; Daniels Radical resistance to minority rule in South Africa 145ff; R Standbridge "Contemporary African political organizations and movements" in Price & Rossberg The apartheid regime 66 at 72; Hendricks From moderation to militancy 227ff; Lodge Black politics In South Africa since 1945 33ff; Dercksen Lyde1ike verset as metode van swart politieke deelname in Suid-Afr1ka 67ff; Meer Higher than hope 59ff; Holland The struggle In accordance with the plans for the first stage of the Campaign, groups of apartheid volunteers regulations resisted under in public auspices places of the trained pass laws leaders. 309 and The intention was to concentrate on localised incidents in large centres across the country. It was made clear at this stage that only selected volunteers were to defy the law - it was not to be a mass movement (at least for the time being) in the sense of country-wide defiance of laws by all those who identified with the cause. 310 Only people “who have been called upon by the Action Committee” of those congresses involved in organizing the Campaign, were to transgress the laws in public places. These people were “trained to remain disciplined” and were to act in units under the leadership of an appointed marshal. Other people were urged not to defy the law. 311 The non-violent character of the Campaign was also emphasised on a number of occasions, inter alia by Or Moroka who stated “We do not want the Mau Mau spirit to come here.” 312 73ff; Davenport South Africa 366ff and Schadeberg Nelson Mandela 34ff. See also Hatch Jewish Frontier March 1953 19; Kuper The British Journal of Sociology 1953 243; Anonymous The Round Table 1953 88; Anonymous The Round Table 1953 130; and Olivier Koers 1987 512 at 534ff. See also the summary of the facts relating to the Campaign by Bekker J in S v Adams and others, unreported case no 1/58 SCC 1961, at 47ff of his judgment. For a vivid account of the start of the Campaign, see "The story of 'defiance'" Drum Oct 1952 9. See also "Democrat's diary" Advance 1 Jan 1953. 309 The only laws directly broken were the pass laws. For the rest apartheid regulations were transgressed, mainly on the railways. 310 Dr Moroka stated: "What we are doing is to put into the field only specially selected people trained for this Campaign; those who are not chosen should carry on as usual, and avoid provocative incidents." According to him, the ANC was "selecting only those people intelligent enough to understand the whole purpose of this move." See "No strike planned for June 26" The Bantu World 21 June 1952. See also the report of Sisulu's address in this regard, published as "5 000 met at protest gathering in Fordsburg" The Bantu World 5 April 1952. See also "Non-violence is keynote of unjust laws campaign" The Bantu World 28 June 1952. 311 See "Only volunteers will fight '.unjust' laws" The Friend 25 June 1952 and "Net sekeres mag wet uittart" Die Burger 25 June 1952. 312 Quoted from "We want no Mau Mau spirit to come here" The Bantu World 25 Oct 1952. See also "Dadoo explains civil disobedience" The Cape Times 9 April 1952 and "Non-Europeans are ready to start By all accounts, the Campaign started on a high note. The first groups of 28 defiers were arrested when they used the “Europeans only” entrance at the New Brighton railway station. The leader was eventually sentenced to thirty days’ imprisonment and the others to fifteen. 313 In Boksburg a group of 52 protesters, including Walter Sisulu, SecretaryGeneral of the ANC, and Nana Sita, President of the Transvaal Indian Congress, set out to enter the black township without the necessary permission. 314 Mandela and Cachalia took a letter to the magistrate of Boksburg, informing him of what they intended doing. 315 The resistors (excluding location. awaiting Mandela They were trial. “conspiracy convicted 316 to on and Cachalia) not In the incite the granted were bail ensuing public alternative arrested and trial violence”. counts the spent 24 they were 317 under at They the Boksburg days prison charged were pass in with eventually laws and the location regulations and sentenced to a fine of £1 or seven days’ imprisonment. Nearly all chose to serve terms of imprisonment. 318 Mandela and Cachalia were arrested that evening with a group of resistors who had broken the curfew regulations in Johannesburg. They were arrested on charges of having aided and abetted those in the group to break the law. They were granted bail 319 and eventually withdrawn, due to a lack of evidence. other accused, it transpired that the 320 the charges were In respect of the protesters, when they were 'Defiance Campaign'" Rand Dally Hall 2 June 1952. 313 See Benson South Africa 147. 314 See "Full list of arrested volunteers" and "Sisulu arrested in Boksburg" The Bantu World 27 June 1952. 315 The report "136 arrests on first day of 'Defiance' Campaign" Natal Mercury 27 June 1952 mentions only Cachalia in this regard; the report "Non-Europeans open defiance bid In the Union" Rand Daily Mail 27 -June 1952 mentions only Mandela. See also Kuper Passive resistance In ?uth Africa 125, where the letter that was delivered is reprinted. 316 See "Aansoek om borgtog geweier" Die Volksblad 30 June 1952 and Sisulu and Sita jailed" Spark 25 July 1952. 317 See "Conspiracy charges levelled against volunteers" Spark 4 July 1952. The charges were presumably levelled in terms of s 7 of the Riotous Assemblies and Criminal Law Amendment Act 27 of 1914. 318 See "Sentenced for 'defiance'" The Argus 21 July 1952. 319 See "Freedom battle begins" Spark 4 July 1952. 320 See "52 Naturelle Transvaler 26 July 1952. van 'protes'-veldtog vrygespreek" Die arrested, were asked as a group whether they had passes, to which they answered as a group “no”. Since it could not be proven that each one individually had answered “no”, no conviction could be obtained. 321 In urban areas, especially in the Eastern Cape but also on the Rand, groups of protesters entered waiting rooms reserved for Europeans, walked the streets without curfew passes, and went into locations for which they did not have permits, in order to invite arrest. 322 In some cases the protestors were unsuccessful to secure arrest the first time when they defied laws and they had to repeat their actions. 323 By and large the resistors acted with self-restraint, and the Campaign was free of violence. The first woman participant was arrested in July. 324 The Campaign picked up momentum in August 325 and was extended to Cape Town. 326 In September it spread to Bloemfontein 327 and to Durban. 328 In the first four months, 6 880 volunteers were arrested. 329 The second stage of the Campaign had commenced, with the increase of volunteers and centres of operation. During the initial stages of the Campaign it was repeatedly emphasised that the actions were directed against unjust laws, not against the whites. 330 The aim was stated as black equality, not superiority. 331 Or 321 See "52 Rand 'defiers' acquitted" The Cape Times 26 July 1952. 322 See "30 Bantoes reeds aangekeer" Die Vaderland 26 June 1952; "20 volunteer at Langa for 'defiance'" The Argus 27 June 1952; "Protesveldtog voortgesit" Die Burger 27 June 1952 and "'Resistors' act in three centres" The Cape Times 27 June 1952. 323 See "Scorpion", "Arrested" succession" Flash 25 Nov 1952. and "Curfew for second night in 324 See "33 native women arrested" The Argus 24 July 1952. See also Walker Women and resistance in South Africa 131ff. 325 See "Defiance Campaign is gathering momentum" The Friend 19 Aug 1952. 326 See "First city 'resistors' arrested" The Cape Times 4 Aug 1952. 327 See "Defiance Campaign in Free State" The Friend 23 Sept 1952. 328 See "Defiance in Durban" Drum November 1952. 329 the Eastern Cape, 306 from the Western 116 from the Transvaal, 152 from Natal See "Defiance Campaign now in second Friend 22 Oct 1952. 330 See Sisulu's remarks as reported in "Organisers urge volunteers Of these, 5 269 came from Cape, Mafeking and Kimberley, 1 and 147 from the Free State. stage: More will take part" The Malan understood and expressed this aim well: “[d]at die blankes as voogde van die nie-blanke meet abdikeer”, 332 although the merits of this demand did not strike him as obvious. The progression of the Campaign saw a steady increase in the severity of the sentences imposed. At the beginning, the typical sentence imposed for the minor crimes committed was a fine of £1 or ten days’ imprisonment. 333 After warnings of an impending increase in sentence, fines of £8 or 40 days’ imprisonment, half of which was suspended, were imposed. 334 This was later raised to £10 or two months’ imprisonment, 335 and eventually to £15 or 90 days’ imprisonment. 336 From April 1953, convictions under the Criminal Law Amendment Act 8 of 1953 were handed down. The first person so convicted was sentenced to twelve months’ imprisonment and eight lashes. 337 As a general evidence crime. 338 rule, admitted the formal resisters compliance pleaded with not all guilty the but elements then of in the The resistors took the opportunity to address the court on their views of the legislation at stake, and on the inadequacy of the “proper channels” for the expression of grievances to which they were inevitably referred to. 339 It was made clear that South Africa was a society in which there was “no constitutional platform for dissent to show restraint" The Friend 23 June 1952. 331 See "Op gelyke voet in die parlement" Die Burger 24 June 1952. 332 See "Teen die witman" Die Vaderland 2 Sept 1952. 333 See "Trotseerders van wette gestraf" Die Burger 23 July 1952. See also "Sentenced for 'defiance'" The Argus 10 July 1952. 334 See "Swaarder gestraf" Die Burger 25 July 1952. 335 See "Swaarder straf vir versetters" Die Vaderland 19 Aug 1952. See also "Fines increased at Port Elizabeth from £6 to £10" Rand Daily Man 19 Aug 1952. 336 See "Uittarters swaarder gestraf" Die Transvaler 26 Sept 1952. 337 See "First conviction under anti-defiance Act" The Bantu World 4 April 1953. 338 See eg "Sentenced for defiance" The Argus 10 July 1952 and "151 go to jail in East London" The Friend 26 July 1952. 339 See, for example, the address to the court of one Mr S Mokena, the leader of a group of resistors, published as "How painful are these restrictions" The South African Outlook 1 Dec 1952. except the court dock.” 340 The General Secretary of the Natal Indian Congress, Debi Singh, who had led a group of resistors to defy Railway Apartheid Regulations, told the court: There is nothing in our common law which lays down that differential treatment should be meted out to people of colour. In some countries it is indeed a criminal offence to discriminate on racial grounds. Thus it is correct to say that the crime with which I have been charged is a crime to which there attaches no moral guilt ... When there are marked and pronounced contradictions between thee (sic) law of nature and man-made law a very painful duty devolves on all enlightened members of our society. 341 In this case Singh regarded it as his duty to obey “natural law”. 342 The protesters gave due notice of any intended acts of civil disobedience, and almost without exception refused to pay fines imposed and went to prison. 343 In doing this, at least the outward form of Gandhi’s campaigns of Satyagraha was observed, even if there was no certainty was. 344 to the as to what the exact philosophy underlying the Campaign In order to counter the fact that some prisons were later filled brim, courts implemented the provisions of the Criminal Procedure and Evidence Act 31 of 1917, which made allowance for the seizure of the property of a convicted person in order to pay his fine. 345 As a consequence, people were turned out of gaols against their will. 346 In an especially controversial move, courts later began imposing whippings, in accordance with the provisions of the Criminal 340 MacFarlane Political studies 1968 335 at 342 used this phrase to describe a system of permanent colonialism. 341 See "Veteran leader Debi Singh leads defiance batch into action" Spark 14 Nov 1952. 342 Ibid. 343 See Kuper Passive resistance in South Africa 127. For an account of some of the arrests and trials, see Karis & Carter From protest to challenge vol 2 421. 344 345 See Robertson Liberalism in South Africa 78. Section 346. See Vaderland 28 Aug 1952. 346 "Tronk reeds tot oorlopens toe vol" Die See "'Defiance' natives expelled from gaol by order" Rand Daily Mail 25 July 1952 and "Heldedom deur tronkstraf" Die Burger 28 July 1952. Law Amendment Act. 347 Especially pertinent to the question how the law should respond to civil disobedience, and revealing in the light of what is today commonly referred to as the legitimacy crisis of the South African legal system, are the comments made by magistrates from all over the country who presided in Defiance Campaign cases, as reported in the newspapers of the time. 348 An accused called Mhlaba stated in a Port Elizabeth court that by defying a railway station segregation notice he was defying an “unjust law which was against God’s rule”. The magistrate told the accused that he was not going to allow political speech. The proceedings continued: “Mhlaba: If the law is oppressive, what is one to do? The magistrate: There are constitutional means by which you can try to have th1ngs amended. When it comes to deliberate defiance of the law this court will see that the persons responsible are properly punished.” 349 Passing sentence in another case on 21 Africans who broke apartheid regulations, a Johannesburg magistrate remarked: It is quite clear that the law has been deliberately flouted. The laws are made to be observed, whether we like them or not. There are some laws which I also do not like - they hit me rather hard. The Income Tax Act for example, is one I do not like. Just the same, I must obey it, as, just the same, you must obey these laws. 350 He also maintained that it was quite clear that there was no partiality or inequality in the apartheid regulations which were broken. None of 347 See "Jong versetters kry lyfstraf" Die Burger 7 Aug 1952; "Die werklike gevaar" Die Burger 13 Aug 1952; "Rottang vir versetters" Die Transvaler 18 Aug 1952; "Soek 'vryheid' 1n stasie: Kry slae" Die Vaderland 20 Aug 1952; "Cuts, fines or gaol for 18 more under rail apartheid law" Rand Daily Hall 21 Aug 1952; "Appeal not to whip 'defiers'" Cape Times 25 Aug 1952 and "Brutal flogging proposed for defiers" Advance 5 Feb 1953. 348 Before the Campaign, Sam Kahn, Communist Party HP, had warned a meeting of the organizations participating in the Campaign: "Do not place reliance in the courts, which apply every apartheid law passed by the government." See "April 6 meetings" The Guardian 10 April 1952. 349 Quoted from "Natives in court in Port Elizabeth" The Cape Argus 10 July 1952. 350 Reported in "21 go to gaol for 'defiance' at station" Rand Daily Mail 28 Aug 1952. the accused’s rights, he said, were taken away or interfered with. 351 In sentencing the group of resistors who, under the leadership of Sita and Sisulu, had defied the Boksburg “location regulations”, the magistrate stated that he could not concern himself with any of the political aspects of the case. He said: “My duty is to apply the law as I find it.” 352 In another case, after hearing that nine out of a group of 29 resisters who transgressed the pass laws were unemployed, the magistrate remarked: Julle moot nie die feit uit die oog verloor nie dat die staat julle dikwels van hongersnood en epidemies gered het. Julle lewe nou in ‘n soort van weelde, met baie voedsel en baie werkgeleentheid. Dit sal nie altyd aanhou nie. Ek wil vir julle dit se: Dit help julle niks om jul koppe teen ‘n muur te stamp nie - die muur sal nie seer kry nie. 353 One magistrate said to an 87 year-o1d defier: “An old man like you should have more sense. If you think I shall let you make a martyr of yourself you are mistaken - go home.” 354 The sentiment that Africans were the helpless and incapable victims of others, and that they themselves would never have had the initiative to embark upon civil disobedience, was reflected in the words of a magistrate who sentenced a number of offenders who participated in an illegal demonstration: “Ek betreur mense, wie se Intel ligensie nie dit dat bale hoog hierdie betreklik jong is nie, gewerf word om aan versetpleging en wetsoortreding deel te neem, en dat hulle nou met hulle vryheid daarvoor moet boet.” 355 At the 351 trial of Dr Conco, Lutuli's second-in-command in the Natal Ibid. 352 Quoted from "Sentenced for 'defiance'" The Cape Argus 21 July 1952. See also "Many resistors arrested: Cape Native fined for contempt" The Friend 16 Sept 1952. 353 Quoted from "Muur sal nie seer kry!" Die Volksblad 11 Sept 1952. 354 Quoted from "Defier (87) not allowed to be a 'martyr'" The Argus 1 Oct 1952. 355 Quoted from "'ANC vernietig sy jeug'" Die Burger 1 Oct also the seemingly bizarre case described in "Magistrate defiance men - frees them" Rand Daily Mail 7 Oct 1952. version of the facts of the case was given in "Congress Vereeniging magistrate" People's World 16 Oct 1952. 1952. See sorry for The ANC's reply to African National Congress, the magistrate was urged by the defending lawyers to refuse to administer unjust laws. He imposed the maximum sentence and told the accused: The legislature has seen fit to pass these laws. It behoves all citizens to obey them. I am not concerned with your motive for breaking the law. There has been far too much of this deliberate transgression ... My advice to you is to obey and respect the laws of the country before you ask for other privileges. 356 In dealing with an application for bail of the first racially mixed group of defiers, the magistrate remarked, with reference to the Defiance Campaign in general: “We are dealing with a race that is primitive, easily led and easily on the emotional side raised to a pitch who win, under emotion, act as they would otherwise not do under calmer reflection.” 357 Nevertheless, bail was fixed at £50 for “Europeans” and £20 for “non-Europeans”. During the latter part of 1952, the magistrates’ courts in the areas affected by the Campaign were at times swamped with cases resulting from the Campaign. Some days more than 400 people were sentenced in courts across the Union. 358 By far the majority of cases involved the transgression of apartheid provisions at railway stations, and to a lesser degree transgressions of the pass laws. 359 In August, Supreme Sisulu, Court with Mandela, the Moroka crime of Internal Security Act 44 of 1950. and others contravening 360 were charged section 11(b) in the of the According to the indictment they 356 See Flash 6 Nov 1952. 357 Quoted from "First victims of Swart's new order" Advance 18 Dec 1952. 358 See eg "413 Naturelle gister gevonnis" Die Transvaler 19 Aug 1952. 359 Some people were also tried with Illegally collecting money to support the movement. See "'Defiance' collection test case" The Cape Times 14 Aug 1952. 360 See "14 charged under anti-red Act" The Argus 13 Aug 1952; “Eleven Defiance Campaign leaders arrested 1n Johannesburg" Mercury 13 Aug 1952; "Leaders to appear in Supreme Court on November 17" The Bantu World 1 Nov 1952. In another trial under the Internal Security Act which followed in the wake of the violence in Port Elizabeth, Or Njongwe and 14 others were convicted. See "No violence in Defiance Campaign" People's World 2 Oct 1952 and "PE accused's view of Defiance Campaign" People's World 9 Oct 1952. Before being sentenced, Dr Njongwe cited as his inspiration for having taken part in the Campaign advocated and encouraged the achievement “communism” as defined in the Act. 361 of the objectives of The charge was based on their role in organising the Defiance Campaign. The reports of the Joint Planning Council, as well as the letters to Malan, were used as supporting evidence by the state. Several of the accused, including Sisu1u and Mandela, addressed the court on their reasons for having participated in the Campaign. 362 Giving judgment in the case of R v Sisulu others 363 and in the Witwatersrand Local Division, Rumpff J held that the actions of the accused were covered by the provisions, and convicted them of what he called “statutory communism”, commonly known as communism.” 364 which was different from “what is In passing sentence the judge observed: “It is not for me to judge the wisdom of legislation. That is the province of the legislature. I have to interpret the law and to apply it to the facts before me.” 365 He continued: “I have decided to impose a suspended sentence. I have done so because I accept the evidence that you have consistently advised your followers to follow course of action and to avoid violence in any shape or form.” An appeal dismissed. against 367 the conviction to the Appellate a peaceful 366 Division was Among other things, the court held that even if it was assumed that the Campaign was intended to “move the legislators by pity or a realisation of the justice of the cause” and not at moving them the "historical example of Ghandi (sic)" who, if he were in South Africa at that moment, "could even technically be regarded as a communist". See "Dr Njongwe's statement to court" Advance 9 April 1953. 361 See the discussion of the offence infra chap four I C (l)(b). 362 See "'Nat government desperate - crown has World 11 Sept 1952. 363 no case'" People's Unreported case no 1417/52 W 2 Dec 1952. 364 During the trial, Mr Justice Rumpff asked the prosecutor "whether a party of European women who sat down in the street and refused to leave when ordered to do so because they had decided on a plan to obtain a change in regard to the rules of jury service, would be guilty of communism." The prosecutor replied: "The scope of the Act is very wide." See "Defence case in Jo'burg trial" Advance 4 Dec 1952. 365 At the first unnumbered page of the reasons for sentence. 366 Ibid. 367 Reported as R v Sisulu and others 1953 3 SA 276 A. Judgment by Greenberg A C J. through a “threat that was intended to produce terror in the legislators” (that is, even if the Campaign was entirely persuasive and involved no coercion), it would nevertheless still have constituted a contravention of section 11(b). 368 Given the formidable legal apparatus at the disposal of the state, and the intention of the protesters to commit crimes, it is not surprising that only a small number of cases resulted in acquittals. Where this did occur, it was either due to the insufficiency of the evidence in the particular case or the result of lacunae in the legal system. Charges against 54 black protesters who used the section of a post office counter reserved for whites were withdrawn and 19 others were acquitted when it was discovered that the post office regulations did not make provision for such an enforcement of apartheid. 369 Similar cases followed in respect of purported breaches regulations in other courts, with the same result. of post office 370 In another case, a number of white defiers used seats in a post office reserved for “non-Europeans”, as a result of which a crowd of between 250 and 300 people gathered around them. Since there were no valid post office apartheid regulations making provision for racially defined reservation of seats, they were charged with causing an obstruction. It was argued on behalf of the accused that the real reason for the obstruction was the conduct of the crowd, not that of the accused. Counsel for the accused asked the captain who made the arrests whether he would have detained Elizabeth Taylor if she had walked into the post office and a crowd gathered around her. 371 The accused were acquitted. In a crude reversal of the normal sentiment in such cases 372 the magistrate told the accused: “You have committed a moral crime, but 368 At 290. 369 See "Charges of 'resisting' fail: 54 freed" The Argus 21 July 1952 and "Postal apartheid" The Cape Times 22 July 1952 370 See "'Defiers' are found not guilty at Worcester" The Argus 25 July 1952. 371 See "Blanke versetplegers deur hof ontslaan" Die Burger 20 Dec 1952. 372 See eg the observations the magistrate in the "Great Trial" made regarding Gandhi, quoted infra chap three III B (1)(a). fortunately for you not a legal one.” 373 In contrast to the situation regarding the post offices, the railway regulations made specific provision for segregation at stations. The validity of the” railway apartheid regulations was attacked on the basis that the regulations. rights However, magistrates’ courts. of this blacks were contention diminished was not through upheld these in the 374 Much attention centred upon the case of R v Lusu, which acquired the status of a test case and was eventually decided in the Appellate 375 Division. The case originated in August 1952 when the accused, a black man, as part of the activities of the Defiance Campaign, entered the “European waiting-room” at the Cape Town railway station, and refused to leave when requested to do so. He was charged with having contravened the Railways Management Act 22 of 1916. and 376 Harbours Regulation, Control, and Section 7(bis)(1) of this Act authorised the South African Railways and Harbours Administration, inter alia. to reserve railway premises for the use of members of a particular race. In terms of section 36(b) it was a crime to knowingly enter a place so reserved for use by members of other races. The trial magistrate found that the facts alleged in the charge sheet had been proved, but acquitted the accused on the ground that the administration had reserved substantially inferior facilities for “nonEuropeans” as compared to those reserved for Europeans. On the basis of R v Abdurahman, 377 this action of the administration was declared void. An appeal by the state to the Provincial Division was dismissed. In a further appeal to the Appellate Division, it was not contested by the state that the "non-European" facilities were indeed inferior. What was 373 See "No legal basis for PO apartheid" Advance 25 Dec 1952. 374 See "42 Oortreders skuldig bevind; 1 kry rottang" Die Transvaler 20 Aug 1952. 375 The Appellate Division decision was reported as R v Lusu 1953 2 SA 484 (A). See the discussion of this case by Van der Vyver Seven lectures on human rights 9 and Forsyth In danger for their talents 97ff. See also "Resisters challenge railway regulations" People's World 21 Aug 1952. 376 377 Read with regulation 20(a) of the General Railway Regulations. 1950 3 SA 136 (A). For a discussion of this case, see Forsyth In danger for their talents 95. argued, however, was that the Railway Administration had "unfettered discretionary rights" to treat different races unequally and partially if it desired to do so. Centlivres C J, writing for the majority of the Appellate Division, argued that: If the crown’s contention were correct, it would follow that the Administration could, under section 7(bis)(1). reserve conveniences on railway premises for members of a particular race only and provide no conveniences for members of any other race. This could not, in my opinion, have been the intention of Parliament. 378 Consequently the appeal was dismissed. In terms of the British case of Kruse v Johnson, 379 if facilities were to be separate, they at least had to be equal. To the great dismay of both the white press and the presiding officers, there were cases where singing, shouting and other interruptions of the court occurred. 380 proceedings The trial of Sisulu and others was adjourned at one stage for 15 minutes to allow Sisulu to address the crowd outside the courtroom. Upon his request they left immediately. 381 The Campaign was Intensified in October when India successfully moved that the Assembly. in situation 382 Durban in South Africa be debated at the UN General A so-called “United Nations Rally” was held at Red Square and attended by more than 10 000 people. The rally “unanimously passed by acclamation” a message which was sent to the Secretary-General of the UN. After expressing solidarity with the values embodied in the Charter of the UN, the message proceeded: We are of the considered opinion that one of the most disturbing factors in the world today is the practice of racial discrimination, a practice which has within it the seeds of another world war. Because we believe in the peace of the world and in the creation of peace fu1 (sic) conditions in our own 378 At 491 of the report. 379 [1898] 2 QB 91 at 99. 380 See "85 'Resisters' in court" The Argus 23 July 1952; "Court was cleared" The Argus 27 Aug 1952; "Rumoerige tonele by Randse verhore" Die Burger 27 Aug 1952; "U1t die hof gejaag" Die Burger 28 Aug 1952; "Resisters warned of contempt" Mercury 9 Sept 1952 and "Native crowd outside court dispersed" The Argus 21 Oct 1952. 381 See Houser Nonviolent revolution 1n South Africa 25. 382 See Lodge Black politics in South Africa since 1945 44. country, we look forward to the United Nations to take a positive stand on this vital question. The future of the new world organization born in the struggle against Fascism depends on its ability to give the oppressed peoples of the world a clear lead on racial discrimination which like a cancer is eating into all that we hold dear in human relationships. In sending our greetings to you we hope that the democratic nations of the world will not allow any further impairment of world peace by allowing herren-volkism to hold sway in any part of the world. 383 A number of so-called “UNO batches of resistors” were now arrested. 384 Four months after the beginning of the Campaign, the ANC in the Transvaal was considering the extension of the Campaign into the rural areas. 385 Just as the Campaign was about to move into its third stage preparation for nationwide mass civil disobedience - rioting broke out on a large scale. The first outbreak of mob violence occurred in New Brighton, Port Elizabeth, in October. When a white railway constable tried to arrest two Africans suspected of stealing a drum of paint, some bystanders came to their assistance. Reinforcements for both sides arrived on the scene. Eventually a crowd of 2 000 to 3 000 were stoning the station and other buildings in the vicinity. The police opened fire. Four whites were killed by the mob, and nine (according to some reports seven) black people were shot dead by the police. 386 Similar incidents occurred at Denver and in Kimberley, also sparked off by trivial incidents. 387 Particularly the killing of a white nun who was sympathetic to the African cause during riots in a black township sent shock waves through the country. In total, 26 blacks and 6 whites died 383 Quoted in "Message to the United Nations" Flash 14 Oct 1952. 384 See "Defiers' first 'UNO batch'" Cape Times 6 Oct 1952. 385 See "Extension of defiance" The Cape Times 13 Oct 1952 and "'Defiance' to spread to platteland" Rand Daily Mail 13 Oct 1952. 386 See Kuper Passive resistance in South Africa 133. The incident sparked an outcry in the white press. See eg "Onluste in Port Elizabeth" Die Volksblad 20 Oct 1952; "Towards a stage of siege?" Pretoria News 20 Oct 1952; "Horror at Port Elizabeth" The Natal Mercury 21 Oct 1952; "New Brighton riot" The Star 20 Oct 1952 and "Call off the 'defiance'" The Star 21 Oct 1952. 387 The court case resulting from the incident at discussed by Kuper Passive resistance 1n South Africa 135. Denver is in these uprisings. 388 Whether or not it was in fact agents provocateurs who had instigated these riots, as has been alleged, 389 the masses were drawn into them, and the disciplined, non-violent nature of the Campaign, together with much of its grounds for claiming moral superiority, were compromised. The ANC denied responsibility for the violence and refused to call the Campaign off. 390 In response to a call from Congress, some white resistors now also joined the Campaign. Among the new resistors was Patrick Duncan, son of a former Governor-General of South Africa, 391 as well as Manilal Gandhi, son of the Mahatma. 392 However, fewer resistors 388 389 Olivier Koers 1987 512 at 535. See Kuper Passive resistance in South Africa 138 and Let my people go 115. Luthuli 390 See "ANC statement on PE riots" People's World 23 Oct 1952 and "Defiance leaders' call to their people" Advance 20 Nov 1952. It should also be noted that no participation In this violence by the ANC was alleged by the state during the Treason Trial. 391 For Duncan's own account of his participation In the Campaign, see Duncan Africa South 1956 78. The news of the participation of Duncan and the other white resistors In the Campaign received considerable publicity in the white press. See eg "Police arrest seven Europeans In defiance episode" Rand Daily Mail 9 Dec 1952; "Blankes neem deel aan verset" Die Burger 10 Dec 1952; "Staat sluit sy saak at" Die Vadarland 28 Jan 1953 and "Patrick Duncan in die getulebank" Die Volksblad 4 Feb 1953. See also "White resisters 1n action" Advance 11 Dec 1952. They were charged with "inciting Natives to break the law" in terms of regulations which wm be discussed later. A fine of £100 was Imposed. See "Duncan kry £100 boete" Die Burger 5 Feb 1953. Duncan told the court that he (as a white) joined the Defiance Campaign because liberty was Indivisible; It was the duty of every citizen to fight injustice, whether he was personally affected or not. He also wanted to demonstrate that some whites were prepared to work with the congresses Involved. See "Evidence by Duncan in location case" The Argus 3 Feb 1953. The young Gandhi stated that "[w]e can submit to these laws or submit to the penalties Imposed by these laws; we have decided to submit to the penalties because the laws are unjust. We do not ask for mitigation of sentence." Quoted from "Duncan and 7 fined for incitement; to appeal" Rand Daily Mail S Feb 1953. They withdrew an initial appeal and went to prison. See "'Defier' to withdraw his appeal: will 90 to jail for 100 days" The Star 29 June 1953. 392 See Lodge Black politics in South Africa since 1945 62. Manilal Gandhi attracted worldwide attention by going on a fast before the Campaign, expressing his doubts that the leadership of the Campaign was sufficiently disciplined to carry on the movement in a non-violent spirit. Apparently his opinion on the matter later changed. See Houser were prepared to come forward, and the Campaign started grinding to a halt in December, with only a few arrests in 1953. 393 In total, 8 057 civil disobedients were arrested during the six months of the Campaign. A serious handicap to the Campaign was the naming of 500 people under the Internal Security Act. 394 These orders were largely defied - a fact which resulted in renewed arrests. 395 (iv) Consequences of the Campaign It was stated earlier that the Campaign was aimed at changing the behaviour of the South African government, either through coercion or non-coercion, politicising blacks, and mobilising international support. It was also mentioned that the Campaign provided an outlet for oppressed people to retain their dignity. The question must now be considered to what extent these objectives were achieved. - Reaction of the white establishment The most important immediate effect of the Defiance Campaign was a dramatic increase in the polarisation of the South African society. 396 The reaction of the governing establishment was one of threatened hostility and panic. The Campaign was perceived as an attack on the very basis of white survival. 397 The open defiance of laws was regarded as treason, subversion, sedition and mutiny, 398 on the basis (the argument that patent violations of the law inevitably cause general Nonviolent revolution In South Africa 25. 393 During December, the number of resisters dropped to 280. Kuper Passive resistance in South Africa 143. 394 See Benson South Africa 146. 395 See "ANC will continue to fight Nat dictatorship" Advance 4 Dec 1952. 396 This theme is thoroughly discussed in Horrell Action, reaction and counteraction 6ff. The legislative consequences are discussed in Horrell Legislation and race relations 48ff. 397 Calling for white unity. Die Transvaler described the Campaign as the beginning of a "terugsinking in die barbaredom". Sea "Hulle is verenig - en ons?" Die Transvaler 4 June 1952. See also "Trotsering van wette" Die Burger 27 June 1952. Cabinet minister, Eli Louw, stated that the future of the "white civilisation" was at stake. See "Louw warns of strong action" The Friend 17 Dec 1952. 398 See "Defiance Campaign is mutiny, says Donges (sic)" The Friend 10 Dec 1952. lawlessness. 399 The Campaign was also portrayed as defiance of the valid laws of a lawful authority and hence as an attack on the authority of God. 400 The government described the term “unjust laws” as perceived in the Campaign as a misnomer, insisting that the apartheid laws were in the best interest not only of white people but also of black people. 401 Consequently, it denied the Campaign the status of being anti- exploitation, and treated it as policy-based. Not surprisingly, the ANC rejected this assumption as one of hypocrisy, and emphasised its conviction that what it was striving for was recognition of the basic right of the people not to be exploited. 402 The Defiance government Campaign stated its met with intention stern to reproach ensure that in Parliament. law and order The was maintained “irrespective of opposition, irrespective of criticism.” 403 No government “worth its salt” can sit still while being threatened with intentional violations of the law. The Minister of Justice stated: “We cannot tolerate that, and if a few heads are split open in the process, then I am very sorry, but it cannot be helped.” 404 The attendance by two members of Parliament of a meeting addressed by Solly Sachs in defiance of an order served on him, urging people to take part in defying the law, caused consternation in Parliament. 405 The Minister of Justice said: “Even if the policy of this government is wrong it is still the law and no one may violate it.” 406 399 See Kuper Passive resistance in South Africa 154. 400 The "Sinodale Kommissie van die Ned Herv of Geref Kerk" stated its conviction "[d]at alle vorms van geweldpleging en verontagsaming van bestaande wette of die wettige gesag van die land veroordeel moet word as strydig met die Woord van God." See "Die spanning tussen rasse-groepe in SA" Die Voorligter Jan 1953. 401 See "Dr Eiselen gives his views on the unjust laws campaign" The Bantu World 20 Sept 1952. 402 See "Dr Moroka again denies allegation that ANC has political link" The Bantu World 9 Aug 1952 and "ANC replies to Dr Eiselen" The Bantu World 27 Sept 1952. 403 Debates of the House of Assembly 20 June 1952 col 8759. 404 Id 20 June 1952 col 8758. 405 Id 26 May 1952 col 6319ff. 406 Id 26 May 1952 col 6327. At the beginning of 1953, in his “opening speech” in Parliament, the Governor-General of the Union announced that Parliament would be asked by the government effectively” with for any additional further acts powers of to defiance deal of “swiftly the law. 407 and The government held the opposition parties responsible for the Campaign because of its support for those engaged in breaking the law. 408 The United Party, seen as the bastion of liberalism, was singled out for particularly severe criticism in view of the fact that, although it eventually government. opposed 409 the Campaign, it refused to side with the For its part, the opposition lay the blame squarely at the door of the government which it was argued, created the conditions which led to the Campaign. 410 The United Party press reminded Or Malan of his own earlier endorsement of the method of passive resistance 411 and accused the government of setting a precedent of lawlessness by overruling the Appellate Division in coloureds from the common voters’ roll. their effort to remove the 412 The Campaign was portrayed by the white press and by the government as inspired by communists and Indians. 413 Africans were often viewed as the helpless pawns of instigators who did not realise that apartheid was in 407 Id 23 Jan 1953 col 4. 408 Id 27 Jan 1953 col 120. 409 In other words, they refused to be drawn into a "laager" with the government. See "Mostert na die maal" Die Volksblad 25 Aug 1952; "Die uittarters en hulle vriende" Die Transvaler 26 Aug 1952 and "VP en versetveldtog" Die Burger 11 Sept 1952. See also "Verset gemik teen blanke, nie teen NP" Die Vaderland 27 Oct 1952. On the views of the United Party and its supporters in this regard, see "A dual responsibility" The Friend 21 April 1952; "Dangerous defiance" The Cape Argus 3 June 1952 and "Danger ahead" Mercury 19 Aug 1952. For Alan Paton's views, see "Paton gives warning to white common-front" Mercury 19 Sept 1952. 410 Id 27 Jan 1953 col 89. 411 See "The chickens come home" The Cape Times 24 Sept 1952. 412 See "Premier must set an example" The Friend 4 Sept 1952. 413 According to cabinet minister Or T E Dönges, the Campaign could be labelled "Made in Russia or India". See "Dönges sees mark of Moscow" The Argus 22 Nov 1952. See also "'n Siniese spel" Die Volksblad 26 June 1952; "Agter die versetveldtog" Die Burger 12 Aug 1952 and "Leiding van Moskou" Die Volksblad 15 Dec 1952. The approach accorded with the fact that civil disobedience was regarded as an "act of communism" in terms of the Internal Securuty Act 44 of 1950. the blacks’ own best interest. 414 When it seemed that some prisons were approaching their capacity, it was suggested that those arrested for participation in the Campaign should be housed in concentration camps 415 or taken to road camps, where they could assist in the construction of roads. 416 It was also suggested that they be banned from certain areas. 417 In practice, the envisaged breakdown of the legal system, due to flooded prisons, never materialised. As the Campaign progressed, the call from the enfranchised population for the restoration of law and order increased. The government was quick to respond by announcing that orders had been given to the police to take whatever steps were necessary, 418 and the introduction of new, harsher legislation was promised. 419 From the outset, the government ruled out the possibility of any negotiations, arguing that negotiation would be useless because it was not prepared to concede the protesters’ 414 See "'Unjust laws' is complete misnomer" Pretoria News 18 Sept 1952 and "Versetplegers is onkundig oor wette" Die Burger 18 Sept 1952. 415 See "Konsentrasiekampe vir versetleiers" Die Burger 22 Nov 1952. 416 See "Padkampe vir versetters" Die Volksblad 4 Aug 1952. 417 See "Verbanning van belhammels?" Die Volksblad 9 Dec 1952. At one time there was also the suspicion that deportation would be used. See "Defiers to be deported?" People's World 2 Oct 1952. 418 See "Nats will use force to keep order" The Friend 16 June 1952; “Regering sal nie swig voor uittarters" Die Transvaler 26 Sept 1952; "Regering sal dit onderdruk, sê Min Schoeman" Die Transvaler 27 Oct 1952 and "Police will shoot - Swart" Rand Daily Mail 3 Nov 1952. One aspect of the strong arm tactics of the government in this regard was the raiding of homes and offices of the leaders of the Defiance Campaign. See "Union-wide raids by CID" The Cape Argus 30 July 1952. 419 See "'Versetters' sal kortgevat word" Die Burger 2 Aug 1952; "Straks nuwe wette teen moedswillige oortreders" Die Transvaler 4 Aug 1952; "Tydige waarskuwing" Die Vaderland 5 Aug 1952; "Cabinet believed to have discussed 'defiance'" Rand Daily Man 15 Aug 1952; "Versetveldtog sal 'gebreek' word" Die Volksblad 29 Sept 1952; "Vra dalk meer magte teen uittartery" Die Transvaler 20 Oct 1952; "Gooi tou om die horings" Die Vaderland 21 Oct 1952; "'Panic laws' final symptom of the government's failure" The Friend 8 Dec 1952; "Noodmagte teen terrorisme" Die Burger 9 Dec 1952 and "Maatreëls teen wetsverbreking byna voltooi" Die Vaderland 11 Dec 1952. This provoked heated resistance at the instance of the ANC. See eg "Protest meetings call for withdrawal of bills" The Bantu World 14 Feb 1953. requests. 420 As far as the establishment was concerned, the high moral claims of the Campaign were effectively neutralised through the publicity given to acts of violence that had occurred. During the Defiance Campaign the liberation movement in Kenya was in the news, and white people tended to see the spirit of the Mau Mau in the Campaign, rather than that of the Mahatma. The violence which erupted also provided a pretext for discounting the morality of the cause underlying the Campaign. Commentators like Desmond Tutu 421 and Gwendolyn Carter 422 have expressed the opinion that the Defiance Campaign had practically no effect in awakening sympathy among whites. It certainly achieved little in terms of persuading legislation. government the In to intellectuals underestimated. government fact, it initiate and 423 did more to the repeal very oppressive religious any opposite of and legislation. leaders should, the offensive prompted Its the effect however, on not be Eventually, these people would play an important role in the liquidation of apartheid. 424 Executive harsh. and During legislative the response Defiance to Campaign the the Campaign were swift Governor-General and issued a proclamation which made “the incitement of natives” by either whites or blacks a criminal offence. 425 White resistors, like Patrick Duncan, who joined the Campaign at the end were charged and convicted under this proclamation. Many leaders of the Campaign were also tried, restricted or banned in a variety of ways under the Riotous Assemblies and 420 See "Difficult to 'stamp out' Defiance Campaign" The Friend 11 Oct 1952. 421 See 0 Tutu "Persecution of Christians under apartheid" in Metz & Schillebeeckx Martyrdom today 63 at 67. 422 See Robertson Liberalism in South Africa 85. 423 See Karis & Carter From protest to challenge vol 2 426. 424 One small manifestation of this can be seen in the fact that under the impetus of the Campaign liberals in the United Party split away to form the Liberal Party, which introduced a "one person one vote" platform into white politics. See Gerhart Black power In South Africa 8. 425 This proclamation is discussed infra chap four I C (1)(c). Se also "Heavy penalties under new proclamation" The Bantu World 6 Dec 1952 Criminal Law Amendment Act 27 of 1914 426 and the Internal Security Act 44 of 1950. 427 Instead of bringing about abolition of the Pass Laws, the year of the Campaign saw its expansion. The Blacks (Abolition of Passes and Coordination of Documents) Act 67 of 1952 was introduced which, in mockery of its name, made provision for the state to require all black persons not previously required to possess passes to carry reference books. In terms of the Black Laws Amendment Act 54 of 1952 black women could in future also be required to carry such “passbooks”. 428 Early in 1953, in response to a general outcry from the white public concerning the Defiance Campaign, the Public Safety Act 3 of 1953 and the Criminal Law Amendment elsewhere in more detail, 429 Act 8 of 1953 were enacted. Discussed it can briefly be mentioned that the Public Safety Act provided to the introduction of a state of emergency. The Criminal Law Amendment Act made provision for increased penalties which could be imposed for crimes of protest. It also created the crime of incitement to civil disobedience and rendered punishable the offer or acceptance of material support for such acts of protest. 430 In response to those cases in which loopholes in the apartheid legislation were discovered in the course of prosecutions resulting from the Defiance Campaign, the Reservation of Separate Amenities Act 49 of 1953 provision was for introduced segregation to consolidate of public regulations facilities. which This made new Act specifically excluded the requirement of equality between “European” and “non-European” facilities posed by the courts. 431 Consequently the decisions in R v Lusu 432 and the post office cases 433 were effectively 426 Mandela was banned for six months under this Act. See Meer Higher than hope 59. 427 See eg R v Ngwevela 1954 1 SA 123 (A), where it was held that the audi alteram partem rule must be observed in this regard. 428 See Joseph Africa South 1959 20. 429 See infra chap four I, II. 430 For a discussion of this period in South Africa's legal history, see Brookes s, Macaulay Civil liberty in South Africa 77ff. 431 See s 3. 432 1953 2 SA 484 (A). 433 These cases are discussed supra chap three III A (3)(c)(iii). neutralised. The effect of the Campaign on the white community, at least on the short term, was consequently overwhelmingly negative. Insofar as its aim was to underwrite a moral appeal, the Campaign resulted in a clenched fist rather than a softened heart. The long term results are more difficult to evaluate, but were perhaps more positive. - Reaction of the black community Views in the black community regarding the Defiance Campaign were, as was to be expected, not consistently favourable. From the conservative side, opposition to the Campaign by Mr Bhengu (who was later convicted on unrelated charges of fraud and theft) of the pro-government Bantu National Congress was the most vocal. 434 The latter’s claim to have any meaningful following among Africans was repudiated by the ANC. 435 Selope Thema of the National-minded Block in the ANC now also took an anti-civil disobedience stance. 436 Most chiefs either rejected the Campaign or remained neutral. 437 The exception was Lutuli, who participated actively and as a result lost his chieftainship. 438 Lutuli’s famous defence of his stance was to ask: “Who will deny that thirty years of my life have been spent knocking in vain, patiently, moderately and modestly at a closed and barred 434 Kuper Passive resistance in South Africa 150. See also the pamphlet "Danger! Danger! Danger!", issued by the Bantu National Congress and contained in the W A Kleynhans collection at the UNISA library archives. The main thrust of the attack of the Bantu National Congress on the Campaign was levelled against the dominant role of its Indian leadership. Some workers asked for police protection as against pressures to strike. See "Bantoes vra beskerming by polisie teen leiers" Die Vaderland 6 Aug 1952. For an account of dissension in ANC ranks, see "Msimng attacks ANC campaign" The Guardian 17 Jan 1952. 435 See "Chief A Luthuli speaks of march to freedom" The Bantu World 18 Oct 1952. 436 On the approach of Selope Thema and the National-minded Bloc, see Benson South Africa 145. See also N Carter "The Defiance Campaign - A comparative analysis of the organization, leadership, and participation in the Eastern Cape and the Transvaal" in Institute for Commonwealth Studies Collected seminar papers on the societies of Southern Africa In the 19th and 20th centuries 76 at 87. 437 See "Bantu Chiefs warn followers against passive resistance" Rand Dally Man 8 Sept 1952. 438 See Luthuli Let my people go 111. door?” 439 National Party newspapers also tried to expose – apparently not entirely without justification leadership of the Campaign. - black resentment at Indian 440 The reaction of the radical Non-European Unity Movement, on the other side of the spectrum, was interesting. It declared that “there is only deception and self-deception in dealing with ‘Malanazis’ as though they were ‘democrats’ and ‘Christians’ who will suffer pangs of conscience because certain non-white ‘leaders’ are in gaol.” 441 These comments were clearly aimed at those who thought that civil disobedience could bring the government to reconsider the morality of its position. The underlying assumption is that civil disobedience is an instrument of immanent critique, and consequently it was not suitable to be used against the South African government. By using civil disobedience, one is suggesting that the opponent possesses the 439 439See his statement: "The road to freedom is via the cross", reprinted in Karis & Carter From protest to challenge vol 2 486. 440 440See "Bantoes raak sat vir Indiër-base" Die Vaderland 23 Aug 1952. These newspapers also took obvious delight in the case of one protester who told the court that the explanation of a police witness that only apartheid could maintain good order at the train station convinced him that apartheid was necessary. See "Verstaan nou waarom daar apartheid is" Die Transvaler 21 Aug 1952. 441 Quoted from the editorial of the movement's journal. The Torch 10 June 1952. On 19 Aug 1952, the editorial stated: "ImperialismHerrenvolkism has no 'conscience' or 'soul or 'sense of decency'. It is not moved to pity or reform by the misery and suffering of the oppressed and exploited people. It causes and lives off this oppression and exploitation, of which poverty, tyranny and suffering are Inevitable and inseparable parts. It has no respect for those who seek to end Its regime of oppression and exploitation. In fact, it passes laws against, builds jails for, and generally hounds and persecutes those who seek to liberate the impoverished, rightless and voiceless mass which is the foundation of I Imperialism-Herrenvolkism. It never repents, because repentance would mean suicide. It never parts with anything voluntarily. It gives up on1y. what is forced from it. It never departs from the scene of its own accord. It fights with every means at its disposal. It disguises itself when and where it can. It uses any agency or person it can, and in the end, it has to be beaten to its grave by the active, unified, organised, principled and militant struggles of the oppressed and exploited people.' The same attitude was expressed by W M Tsotsi, president of the A11 African Convention. See "Native condemnation of passive resistance" The Friend 17 Dec 1952 and "Naturelle-leier slinger ander verwyte toe" Die Transvaler 18 Dec 1952. See also "Tabata and Co get some of their own medicine" People's World 2 Oct 1952. morality needed to change. To them, civil disobedience was an unwarranted compliment to the humanity of the government. The indirect and eventually perhaps more important goals of the Campaign were, however, ignored. Some African newspapers gave their full support to the protest and lashed out at the government for the way in which it handled the Campaign. 442 As time progressed, African newspapers which were initially sceptical became increasingly supportive of the Campaign. This largely due to the support which the Campaign received from abroad. was 443 It is difficult to establish what the role of religion was in the black community in respect of the Campaign. 444 Kuper indicated that Christianity was viewed with ambivalence by many blacks. On the one hand, Christian Christianity was values seen legitimised as resentment of suppression. 445 a plot resistance; whereby on whites the other hand, appeased black The black churches played a relatively low-key role in the Campaign. It is perhaps revealing that the Native Affairs Department, at the end of the Campaign, threatened to withdraw “certain privileges” from ministers participating in the Campaign. 446 A number of church leaders did, however, participate or provide some support, 447 and a national day of prayer was held during the Campaign. 448 442 See eg "Public Safety Bi11 means political terrorism" Advance 5 Feb 1953. 443 See eg "Sooner is better than later" The Bantu World 31 Jan 1953. See also "Attitude to 'unjust laws' campaign" The Friend 30 June 1952 and "Danger of resistance movement" The Friend 29 Sept 1952, as well as Benson South Africa 150. 444 For a consideration of some of the studies conducted on the religious dimensions of African protest, see Jeeves International Journal 1973 511 at 518. 445 See Kuper Passive resistance in South Africa 116ff. 446 F See "Ministers' comment on political ban" The Bantu World 3 Jan 1953. 447 See "African churches back Defiance Campaign" The Clarion 14 Aug 1952; "Make religion a living force" The Bantu World 23 Aug 1952; "Their call is 'no violence'" The Argus 21 Oct 1952; "Kerkmanne betuig meegevoel" Die Burger 23 Jan 1953 and "Ernstige aanklag teen Strauss" Die Burger 26 Feb 1953. 448 See "Defiance day of prayer" The Mercury 11 Aug 1952; "They prayed for defiance men" The Argus 18 Aug 1952; "Hundreds of Natives ready to defy law" The Friend 18 Aug 1952 and "'Make religion a living At a meeting of nearly seventy ministers of religion of many different denominations and all races to discuss the role of the church in the Campaign, the clergy were urged to give moral but not active support to the Campaign. 449 Civil disobedience also had far-reaching effects on the nature of the liberation movement in the country. It fulfilled an important function in making African opposition articulate and robust at a time when other strategies were simply not available and, it is submitted, in this sense helped to make the retention of black dignity possible. According to Mandela, “[i]t inspired and aroused our people from a conquered and servile community of yesmen to a militant and uncompromising band of comrades-in-arms.” 450 This aspect is closely related to a further consequence of the Campaign for the liberation movement: One of the stated objectives with the Defiance Campaign, at least insofar as the ANC was concerned, alluded to earlier, was to increase its membership. The Campaign certainly served to mobilise the masses and was an inspiring demonstration of black ability. 451 Paid-up membership of the ANC increased during the Campaign from approximately 7 000 to 100 000 - and paid-up members gave only a small indication of the movement’s wider support. 452 After the Campaign, the ANC was for the first time truly a mass movement. It lost much of its élitism and became more sensitive to the needs of the workers and the less privileged. 453 It was this change in force' says rev Nkabinde" The Bantu World 23 Aug 1952. See also "2 000 pray in rain for defiance 'volunteers'" Rand Daily Mail 23 June 1952. See also N Carter "The Defiance Campaign - A comparative analysis of the organization, leadership, and participation in the Eastern Cape and the Transvaal" in Institute of Commonwealth Studies Collected seminar papers on the societies of Southern Africa in the 19th and 20th centuries 76 at 83. 449 See "Clergymen discuss Defiance Campaign" The Bantu World 21 Feb 1953. 450 Mandela "No easy walk to freedom" in Mandela The struggle is my life 34 at 34. 451 See "Civil disobedience Argus 31 July 1952. campaign a continuing struggle" The 452 See Walshe The rise of black nationalism In South Africa 402. See also Gerhart Black power in South Africa 89, whose figures are slightly different. 453 Mandela, in his "No easy walk to freedom" address to the ANC focus which resulted in the rejection of the more aloof Dr Moroka 454 in favour of the man of the people, Albert Lutuli, who was elected to the position of President-General of the ANC in December 1952. 455 The Defiance Campaign also seems to have affected those involved in the liberation struggle in another way. While the different racial groups went into the Campaign along racially divided lines, the ties between them were considerably strengthened during the Campaign. 456 In the decade after the Defiance Campaign there was a strong movement among Africans toward interracial co-operation, which reached its climax in the adoption of the Freedom Charter with its non-racial ideals. 457 White people would now also be accommodated in the ANC. 458 Oliver Tambo put it as follows: “Following the lessons of the Defiance Campaign, the need was felt for an organization through which the ANC and other nonEuropean bodies could make contact with those whites who were prepared (Transvaal) Conference in 1953, stated: "The general political level of the people has been considerably raised and they are now more conscious of their strength. Action has become the language of the day. The ties between the working people and the Congress have been greatly strengthened." See Mandela The struggle is my 1ife 34 at 39. 454 During the R v Sisulu and others trial (see supra chap three III A (3)(c)(111)), in which he was also an accused, Moroka betrayed his organization by distancing himself from the other accused. He engaged separate counsel in spite of an earlier agreement not to do so. In mitigation of sentence, his lawyer argued that his ancestors had helped the Voortrekkers. See Robinson Liberalism in South Africa 101 and Me1i A history of the ANC 122. The disagreement between Moroka and the others was partly the result of his objection to the inclusion of (former) communists among the lawyers assisting the ANC. See Benson South Africa 155. Especially the Africanists would later cite this incident as proof that the Defiance Campaign was prematurely called off, not because violence erupted but because the ANC leadership had developed cold feet. See Gerhart Black power in South Africa 230. 455 456 See Robertson Liberalism in South Africa 102. See and power 122. See Vaderland Mercury 2 L Kuper "Nonviolence revisited" in Rotberg & Mazrui Protest in black Africa 788 at 795 and Meli A history of the ANC also "Nie-blankes organiseer terwyl blankes 'skerm'" Die 28 June 1952 and "Appeal for unity to non-whites" The Natal July 1952. 457 See L Kuper "Nonviolence revisited" in Rotberg & Mazrui Protest and power in black Africa 788 at 791. 458 Lutuli emphasised the fact that the target of the Campaign was the system and not a race. See Luthuli Let my people go 105. to join the non-Europeans in their fight for freedom and democracy.” 459 While many other factors also had an influence in this regard, it was inevitable that the high moral ground of non-racialism on which the Campaign was premised, made it difficult for those participating to practise apartheid in their own ranks. Even if the use of civil disobedience did not convince its direct opponent to mend its ways, it contributed towards changing the people who practised it. 460 The irony of the Defiance Campaign was that it changed those who used it for the better, but those against whom it was targeted for the worse. The Defiance Campaign no doubt made a significant contribution towards mobilising support for the liberation movement and towards fostering black self-respect. Even if still oppressed, Africans gained some control over their own 1ives. - International consequences Coming soon after the Second World War, the Campaign also served to arouse world government. 461 opinion against the policies of the South African Eliciting a negative world response to the South African government was one of the objectives of the Campaign, 462 and something the government tried to avoid. 463 International sympathy with the 459 See "ANC stands by the alliance with Congress of Democrats" New Age 13 Nov 1958. 460 The same happened during the campaigns conducted by Gandhi. See infra chap three III B (1)(b). 461 For an overview of the Immediate world reaction to the Campaign, see Kuper Passive resistance In South Africa 165. For the views of Professor Z K Matthews on this topic, see foreword in Houser Nonviolent revolution in South Africa 3. See also "Humanity's conscience outraged by apartheid" The Clarion 7 Aug 1952, for an overview of some of the reactions of the foreign media. 462 Right at the beginning of the Campaign, Sisulu assured those who intended participating that they had the support of the world. See "Free State Natives to defy 'unjust' laws" The Friend 23 June 1952. See also "Steun uit die buiteland" Die Burger 18 July 1952 and "Beskrywing van uittartery oor BBC gegee" Die Transvaler 22 Sept 1952. The protesters were later also assured: "You have the whole world on your side." See "Duncan addresses Rand crowd" The Cape Times 9 Feb 1953. 463 463For example, when the United Party asked for a commission of inquiry into the riots at New Brighton, the government refused, saying that it was an attempt to provide the protesters with the opportunity Campaign was much cherished by the participants and leaders. 464 In various ways funds were set up in countries around the world, aimed at providing assistance to the resistors. 465 Especially the Indian government provided widespread moral support 466 and raised the issue in the UN. A commission was consequently appointed by the UN to study the effects of apartheid legislation 467 - a move which was deeply resented by the Nationalists interference in their country’s domestic affairs. as 468 direct international onslaught on apartheid as such. an unwarranted It was the first 469 The UN played a significant role in the thinking of those leading the to say to the outside world how they were being suppressed. See "Oorsake van die onluste sal uit die hofsake blyk" Die Transvaler 22 Nov 1952. 464 See eg "The world is with us" Spark 6 April 1952; "World action against SA mooted" The Clarion 7 Aug 1952; "World press lines up against South Africa" People's World 11 Sept 1952 and "ANC replies to Dr Eiselen" The Bantu World 27 Sept 1952. 465 Early on, the "Congress of Racial Equality" in the United States offered financial support. See "Non-European leaders outline plan" Rand Daily Mail 9 April 1952 and "Dadoo explains civi1 disobedience" Cape Times 9 April 1952. See also "Geldoproep vir uittarters uit Indië" Die Transvaler 15 Sept 1952 and "Congress motion calls for financial aid for passive resistors" Rand Dally Mail 15 Sept 1952. In Britain, a "Christian Action" group established an assistance fund which was administered in South Africa by a group under the chairmanship of Alan Paton. See "Fund opened in London for dependants of 'resistors'" The Star 29 Oct 1952; "Misplaced zeal" The Star 31 Oct 1952; "Distress fund group" The Argue 17 Dec 1952; "Geld van oorsee vir 'slagoffers van rassestryd'" Die Transvaler 18 Dec 1952; "Openbare fonds vir uittarters in Brittanjt gestig" Die Transvaler 2 Feb 1953; "Versetfonds van Britte" Die Volksblad 2 Feb 1953; "London fund for native resistors" The Friend 2 Feb 1953 and "London meeting to aid 'defiers'" The Cape Times 3 Feb 1953 466 See "India issues a report on 'unjust laws' campaign" The Friend 4 July 1952; "Nahru (sic) loof die Gandhi-manier" Die Volksblad 16 Aug 1952; "Indiese premier oor uittarters" Die Transvaler 6 Oct 1952; "Nehroe vra wereld: Steun uittarters" Die Transvaler 19 Jan 1953 and "Beroep om steun vir versetters" Die Volksblad 19 Jan 1953. 467 See "Wil VVO op versettery in SA wys" Die Transvaler 25 Aug 1952; "Indië steun versetters" Die Vaderland 25 Aug 1952 and "Versetplegers en die VVO " Die Burger 25 Aug 1952. 468 See "Huigelary ken geen perk in die VV, sê Min Dönges" Die Vaderland 22 Nov 1952. 469 See Benson South Africa 153. Campaign. 470 The defiance leaders (and a number of foreign governments), for example, claimed that the conduct of the police in raiding the houses of the participants violated the UN Charter. 471 As mentioned earlier, UN attention to the issue of apartheid led to an intensification of the Campaign. In Britain, assistance, government churches 475 the Defiance also from led the Campaign, to strong press, and politicians. 472 the apart from criticism radio, 473 attracting of the the trade financial South African unions, 474 the 476 In the United States, the New York Times commented that the Malan government’s policies were responsible for the disrespect which was shown for the law. 477 Eleanor Roosevelt, widow of the former American president and one of the principal authors of the Universal Declaration of Human Rights, wrote a letter of support to the leadership of the Campaign. 478 Voices against the South African system were also raised in 470 For an account of Dr Xuma's petition to the UN in 1946, see Benson South Africa 111. See however also "SA & US govts tried to bully prof Matthews" Advance 4 Dec 1952. 471 See "Versetters sê hu11e kry baie steun" Die Burger 4 Aug 1952 and "India attacks race policy of S Africa" Rand Daily Mail 15 Sept 1952. 472 See "Net een antwoord moontlik" Die Volksblad 29 Aug 1952 and "British periodicals comment on Defiance Campaign" Rand Daily Mail 30 Aug 1952. 473 See "Beskrywing van uittartery oor BBC gegee" Die Transvaler 22 Sept 1952 and "SA defiers described to Britain" Mercury 22 Sept 1952. 474 See "Britse vakbondkongres se besluit" Die Volksblad 4 Sept 1952. 475 See "Prediker sê Dr Malan sleg in St Paul-katedraal" Die Volksblad 9 Sept 1952; "Resistance campaign supported" Mercury 9 Sept 1952. See also, on a report in the Church of England newspaper, "British Christians' interest in Defiance Campaign" The Star 29 Oct 1952. 476 See "Apartheid - the shadow over Africa" The Friend 4 Feb 1953. 477 See "New York paper's view of 'unjust laws' campaign" The Friend 15 July 1952. 478 After reading the letter to a protest meeting in Durban, Mr Ashwin Chondree, vice-president of the Natal Indian Congress, told those present: "I offer this letter to Dr Malan. It is not a letter from Stalin, whom he dislikes. It is a letter from the world's greatest democracy, which buys our gold." See "Mrs Roosevelt on countries such as Canada 479 and even by the government Nepal. 480 of Clearly, apartheid was now on the international agenda. Although at the time no immediate action was taken against South Africa by the international community, the global quicksand which later threatened to engulf the country was starting to build up under its feet. The implementation and lack of concrete results of civil disobedience would later be an important argument advanced to justify to the world community the use of violence in the struggle, and to bring foreign countries to isolate South Africa in a number of ways. Given the extent of the eventual pressure from the international community on the South African government and the effect this would have on the country, this aspect of the Defiance Campaign might well eventually prove to be one of its most meaningful consequences. 481 The Defiance Campaign consequently contributed towards making apartheid an international issue. (v) The Evaluation of the Defiance Campaign successes of the Defiance Campaign should, however, not be overestimated. Was it worth the sacrifices of the people involved, and was the maximum possible mileage obtained from the use of this strategy of protest? The Campaign failed to reach its primary objectives, at least in the short term. Instead of reducing oppression, it elicited more. It was abandoned by the people before it was called off by the organisers. Given the number of potential resistors, the figure of 8 000 odd people who participated is also not particularly impressive. Relatively speaking, Gandhi was much more successful in his campaigns against Smuts and against Britain. The mobilisation of support for the liberation movement was significant, but it was only a start. Apartheid endured for at least forty more years. In short, the Campaign did not live up to the expectations of those who initiated it. Why not? Several reasons can be advanced in this regard. They relate to the defiance" Cape Times 15 Sept 1952 and "Eleanor se brief aan Natal se Indiërs" Die Transvaler 16 Sept 1952. 479 See "Kanadese is geskok" Die Burger 21 Aug 1952. 480 See "Nepal betuig meegevoel met SA se versetters" Die Vaderland 18 Sept 1952. 481 For an overview of United States economic pressure against South Africa, see Heyns CILSA 1989 269. compatibility of civil disobedience as an instrument of political resistance with African culture, the way in which the Campaign was conducted, and the attitude of the adversary. - Civil disobedience in the African context. According to Kuper, “the technique of civil disobedience seemed alien to the ardor.” African 482 masses and failed to fire them with revolutionary At least two aspects of the type of resistance practised during the Campaign possibly did not fit well into African culture. In the first place, as will be pointed out, the idea that suffering is a creative force is an integral part of the culture of India, 483 but it is not to the same extent indigenous to Africa, where the traditional methods of settling serious disputes are either amicable, legal means or force. 484 The “spirit of Nongqausi” does dwell in Africa, but she is not as dominant here as in some other societies, and in any case she did not have a good track record. In the second place, the female component of civil disobedience, also discussed earlier, was bound not to go down well in the traditionally male-dominated African society. - Weaknesses in the way in which the Campaign was conducted As indicated earlier, no coherent philosophy existed of what was to be achieved through the Defiance Campaign. Nor was the Campaign associated with a charismatic leader such as Gandhi or King. Mandela, who is perhaps the only person who could have played that role, was not nearly as prominent then as ha would become later. In the absence of a principled commitment to non-violence, the fact that participants in the Campaign resorted to violence or were drawn into it was not altogether surprising. Through this, much of the moral high ground was lost. Participation in the Campaign became singularly unattractive once the protection of a non-violent record was lost. As we already know, the Gandhian practice of notifying the authorities beforehand of an intended Campaign and going to prison voluntarily was adhered to during the Defiance Campaign. Whether this was necessary, 482 L Kuper "Nonviolence revisited" in Rotberg & Mazrui Protest and power In black Africa 788 at 795. 483 484 See infra chap three III B (2)(a). According to Kuper Passive resistance in South Africa 92 "[p]urification by voluntary suffering is an integral part of Hindu culture, in contrast to Bantu culture." given the particular circumstances of the Defiance Campaign, is open to doubt. As Kuper observed: From a purely expedient point of view, the resistors might have elected not to notify the authorities of their plans, nor to invite arrest. It would have been sufficient, for example, that more and more Africans should cease to carry their passes. Nor would the refusal of the police to effect an arrest have created a problem. But, in terms of Satyagraha, the courting of arrest and the willing submission to punishment are the essential means for conversion of the rulers. 485 It is revealing to note that, eventually, it was precisely the fact that Africans simply ceased to carry passes without drawing specific attention to it, that made the system unworkable. 486 The outward form of Gandhian protest was adopted during the Campaign without considering its applicability to the particular needs of the protest movement. Gandhian civil disobedience was designed to bring about suffering, and arguably a precise Campaign resulted adherence in a to his situation methods where too during much the was Defiance asked of prospective protesters, with too remote prospects of success. It also seems that the laws targeted failed to arouse order to be sufficient enthusiasm to sustain resistance. - Nature of the adversary It has been stated repeatedly that, in successful in weakening the resolve of the opponent, civil disobedience requires a target which has a commitment to “fair play”. The direct opponents of the Defiance Campaign had a three-hundred years history of what they regarded as a struggle for survival, which indeed resulted in a ruthless attitude. Instead of recognising that their Christian values were supposed to support the demands made upon them, they used those values to legitimise their own power base. 487 As is evident from the observations of the Non-European Unity Movement quoted above, a vocal group in the black community saw civil disobedience as simply not worth the sacrifice, in view of the nature of the opponent. A campaign which involves the deliberate and open violation of laws for the transgression of which millions of people were being punished every 485 Kuper Passive resistance in South Africa 125. 486 See infra chap three III A (3)(e). 487 See on the role of religion in legitimising apartheid Infra chap five II. year, was bound to encounter a problem. 488 legitimacy Clearly, the government had few scruples in applying the laws objected against. And indeed, the ruthless suppression of the Campaign by the government was one of the major reasons why it ran out of steam. In fairness it should be pointed out that the challenge which civil disobedience in post-World War II South Africa posed to the rulers, seen from their perspective, was more formidable than the challenge posed by Gandhi in South Africa and in India, and by King in the United States. In all three of these last-mentioned cases there were circumstances which mitigated the challenge. Either the opponent was foreign or the objective was not its overthrow. In Gandhi’s South Africa, the opponent was local, but the aim was not to overthrown the existing system. In India the aim was to overthrow the government, but the officials of the government were foreigners, which meant that they did not perceive their existence to be under threat. In the United States, as in Gandhi’s South Africa, the opponent was a domestic government, but the aim was not its overthrow. One could consequently expect a more lenient approach in all of these cases. In the South African case in the 1950’s the opponent was a domestic government whose overthrow was the ultimate aim. As a result, a harsher response by the government was to be expected. In consequence of a combination of the above factors, there was “an insufficient stimulus to launch the revolution, stimulus to strengthen the counter-revolution.” (vi) but a sufficient 489 Black politics in the wake of the Campaign After the Defiance Campaign, very little in the line of civil disobedience emerged from the ANC. Only in 1958 did the ANC again - and rather ambivalently this time - encourage civil disobedience, when women in Johannesburg protested against the pass laws. Eventually the half-hearted campaign had to be called off. 490 For the time being, the ANC restricted itself to forms of protest within the confines of the law. Only in 1960, not to be outdone by its own offshoot, the PAC, would the ANC again engage in acts of civil disobedience. The events 488 See L Kuper "Nonviolence revisited" in Rotberg & Mazrui Protest and power In black Africa 788 at 794. 489 Id 795. 490 Lodge Black politics in South Africa since 1945 78. which led to this will next briefly be considered. The Defiance Campaign left the leaders of the ANC with the problem of how to sustain and to channel the enthusiasm of their new following. The massive clamp-down by the stall forced those in the liberation movement to consider other alternatives than civil disobedience. Open and non-violent defiance of the state was almost guaranteed to result if martyrdom. The remainder of the 1950’s would largely be a period of increasing polarisation of the South African society. During this period, the ANC was at times also nearly immobilised through the banning of its leaders. Picking up where the Joint Planning Council had left off, the Congress Alliance was formed in 1953 with the prime objective of planning a “Congress of the People”. Participating in this effort was the ANC, SAIC, the SA Coloured People’s Organization and the South African Congress of Trade Union. At the seminal Congress of the People at Kliptown in 1955, with which we need not detain ourselves here, the “Freedom Charter” was adopted. It was later ratified by the individual congresses represented at Kliptown. 491 During 1954 and 1955 the ANC singled out two aspects of the government’s policy as targets for campaigns of passive, although not illegal, resistance: the so-called Western Areas Resettlement scheme and the Bantu Education Act 47 of 1953. These campaigns were by and large without positive results in terms of changing the behaviour of the government - it merely added to the general level of dissatisfaction of the protesters. A brief look at these two campaigns will illustrate the non-violent tactics that were now resorted to. 492 Shortly after it came into power in 1948, the newly elected Nationalist government made its intention known to remove the inhabitants (adding up to more than 10 000 families, including 350 Africans who held 491 0n the Congress of the People, see Meli A history of the ANC 123 and C M Xundu "The Congress of the People Campaign and an overall view of the Freedom Charter" in Polley The Freedom Charter and the future 13. 492 See, on these two campaigns. Felt African opposition in South Africa 92ff, 143ff. freehold titles 493) from the freehold townships of Sophiatown, Martindale and Newclare (Johannesburg’s “Western Areas”) to the statecontrolled townships of Meadowlands and Diepkloof, where land could only be leased. In January 1955, the first families received their notices to vacate the premises they occupied. People were told that black resistance would be organised by the ANC and the SAIC, and they were instructed not to move. Congress strategy was only to be published on the day of the removals. When that day came, very little in the line of protest took place, except that some protesters moved from house to house before they were moved - often in the end, voluntarily. 494 In the early fifties the new government set out to transfer control of black education government. from Black the provincial education would now authorities be to controlled the by central a special department and on a differential basis apropos the education of the other sections of the South African community. The loose control of the provincial authorities over black schools, mostly run by missionaries, would be replaced by the tight control of the Nationalist government. In the words of Verwoerd, then Minister of Native Affairs, the new system would provide the “correct education” - not the type of education which “create[s] wrong expectations on the part of the Native himself”, based on “a policy of equality”. 495 Syllabuses now had to accustom blacks to their role in apartheid South Africa. Cost per student was to be lowered. Verwoerd pursued the following policy: Die Bantoe moet gelei word om sy eie gemeenskap in alle opsigte te bedien. Daar is vir hom bokant die peil van sekere vorms van arbeid nie piek in die blanke gemeenskap-nie ... Daarom baat dit horn niks om ‘n opieiding te ontvang wat die opname in die blanke gemeenskap ten doel het terwyl hy nie daar opgeneem sal en kan word nie. 496 The carrying out of government policy in this regard was made possible by the passing of the Black Education Act 47 of 1953. 493 See Kotzé African politics 1n South Africa 11. 494 Feit African opposition in South Africa 92. The campaign is discussed by Bekker J in his judgment in S v Adams and others, unreported case no 1/58 SCC 1961, at 58ff. 495 496 Quoted in Lodge Black politics In South Africa since 1945 115. See verwoerd's "Verklaring oor die Bantoe-onderwysbeleid van die Unie in die Senaat, 7 Junie 1954", contained in Verwoerd Verwoerd aan die woord 59 at 77. The ANC decided to launch a campaign to resist these changes in “Bantu education”. It was decided that the schools should be boycotted. Starting in April 1954, as many as 10 000 children were absent from school at some stage or another. However, as Lodge observed, the ANC's approach to the issue was characterised by uncertainty and disagreement between different sections of the leadership and between leaders and the rank and file. 497 The main isolated thrust areas of and the was campaign sporadic. was conducted Following a in geographically government ultimatum, children started to return to school at the end of the month. Apart from some children who attended alternative educational facilities provided for some time by the ANC, the boycott was dead. It also undermined public alternatives. 498 belief in the ANC’s ability to provide Whereas the Defiance Campaign brought the ANC great popularity, the Western Areas and Bantu Education campaigns of 1955 reflected badly on its organisational and leadership skills. Presumably, after the open confrontation of illegality in the Defiance Campaign, legal protest now failed to inspire. Since the beginning of 1956, when the requirement that women had to carry passes was implemented, there was widespread unrest, mainly in the form of pass-burning. Mass arrests were effected. This lasted until February 1959. convicted. 499 In From total 1957 1 893 onwards achieving only limited successes. people the were ANC arrested turned to and 926 strike were action, 500 In March 1958, a black articled clerk by the name of Godfrey Pitje, employed by the firm of attorneys, Mandela and Tambo, refused to use a table in court designated for the use of “non-European” legal practitioners upon being ordered to do so by the presiding magistrate. After a warning was issued, the magistrate convicted him of contempt of court in facie curiae 497 See Lodge Black politics in South Africa since 1945 121. 498 Felt African opposition 1n South Africa 143ff. 499 The rallying cry was: "Strydom, uthitta abafadzi, uthinti imbokhoto" - "Strydom, you have tampered with women, you have struck a rock!" See Joseph Africa South 1959 3 20. For an overview of these events, see Walker Women and resistance in South Africa 184ff. 500 On the 1957 bus boycott, see First Africa South 1957 55. On appeal, the Appellate Division confirmed the conviction. 501 Steyn C J held that the magistrate’s order was not unreasonable. Although the order was not given in terms of the Reservation of Separate Amenities Act 49 of 1953, that Act showed that “the distinction drawn by the provision of separate tables ... is of a nature sanctioned by the legislature.” 502 The court made reference to the fact that, on a previous occasion, “Mr Tambo, a non-European”, had appeared in the same matter before the same magistrate. As he had done previously, Tambo on that occasion used the table reserved for “Europeans”. On being informed that he would not be heard unless he addressed the court from the other table, he withdrew from the case. According to the Chief Justice, in view of the history of the case, it is apparent that the appellant, when he went to court on this day, knew of the existence of the separate facilities in the court, that he purposely took a seat at the table provided for European practitioners, that he expected to be ordered to the other table and intended not to comply with such order ... It follows, I think, that his failure to comply with the order was, deliberate and premeditated. It cannot, therefore, avail him to contend that he did not intend to insult the magistrate and was not motivated by contempt. 503 In 1956, 156 people - most of them leaders of the Congress Alliance were arrested on charges of High Treason. A number of them were charge in what became known as the Treason Trial. 504 It was alleged by the prosecution that the accused had planned the violent overthrow of the state. To substantiate the charge, the prosecution argued that the demand of the accused for full equality of all races in South Africa “in their conclusion state. 505 lifetime” that they led, were by “an irresistible planning the inference”, violent overthrow to the of the The main focus in the trial was on the Freedom Charter, which was portrayed as a revolutionary and communist document. Although the period covered by the eventual indictment was 1 February 501 See R v Pitje 1960 4 SA (A) 709. 502 At 710. 503 503At 711, 712. 504 504S v Adams & others, unreported case no 1/58 SCC 1961. On the history of the Treason Trial, see Karis The Treason Trial in South Africa 1ft; Me1i A history of the ANC 128 and Dugard Human rights and the South African legal order 213ff. 505 See Karis The Treason Trial in South Africa 17. 1954 to 13 December 1956, it was claimed by the state that the earlier history of the revolutionary directly by ANC should offensive, force, or be where where seen the the as a state state prelude would would to an eventual either be attacked be provoked to act violently. This would then lead to revolutionary counter-violence. The prosecution argued that no middle ground existed between the ballot box and treason. 506 The formation of the Joint Planning Council and the organisation of and participation in the Defiance portrayed as part of the wider treasonable strategy. Campaign was 507 In 1961 all the accused were acquitted. The presiding judge, Rumpff J, found that the Freedom Charter was not a communist document. Since the entire case was brought and conducted by the state on the basis of a conspiracy to commit violence, and it was not proven that the policy of the ANC was to overthrow the state by means of violence, no conviction of treason could be sustained. 508 What the trial did achieve, however, was effectively to cut the bulk of the ANC leadership off from their people for five years. In the late 1950’s the ANC was to a considerable extent paralysed by the unattractiveness of its options. Another Defiance Campaign was very unappealing in light of the arsenal of legislation that had been enacted by the government, and was unlikely to gain widespread support. On the other hand, the movement was also not yet ready for the dark road of violence. It would be the combined threat of losing members to more radical organizations and the increased militancy and anger of the leaders of the Youth League which would force the ANC towards more radical options. In 1959 the so-called Africanists, who had been expelled from the ANC a year earlier, formed the PAC, with Robert Sobukwe as its president. 509 Among the main grievances of the Africanists was the influence of white 506 This argument was taken over from R v Leibbrandt. unreported case no G 1/42 SCC 1943. See infra chap four I 0 (1). 507 See para 6 of the prosecution's summary of facts, reprinted in Karis The treason trial in South Africa 59. 508 509 See the judgments of Rumpff J at 26 and that of Bekker J at 44. The idea of the "return of Africa" can be traced back to John Cube's popular phrase: "Lapho ake ema khona amanzi ayophinde erne futhi" -"where there was once a pool, water will collect again." See Motlhabi The theory and practice of black resistance to apartheid 43. people, mostly Communists, in the ANC, and the contents of the Freedom i Charter - especially the opening lines which state: “South Africa belongs to all who live in it, black and white.” The latter concession to whites was regarded as “in irreconcilable conflict” with the 1949 Programme of Action. 510 Members of the PAC viewed the Defiance Campaign as distorted because of the involvement of the SAIC 511 and presumably because of the influence of Gandhian thought through this channel. Indians were excluded from membership of the PAC. It is perhaps ironic that the PAC’s most important political statement almost immediately after its inception included a resolve to start organising a campaign of protest very much along the lines of the Defiance Campaign - but this time it was to be an all African affair. This campaign was to have far-reaching consequences for the entire liberation struggle. The obvious target for any anti-apartheid campaign of civil disobedience in the late fifties was still the pass laws. While the ANC’s Anti-Pass Planning Council now resolved that the precise meaning of civil disobedience first had to be established before such action could again be contemplated, the PAC captured the initiative and organised what they called the “Positive Action Campaign” or “Anti-pass Campaign”, which was targeted primarily against the pass laws. 512 The PAC envisaged that Africans would, on an appointed day, leave their passes at home and proceed to police stations and present themselves for arrest. The idea that massive participation would result in the prisons being filled up to capacity, whereby the government would be prevented from enforcing its policies, was given central priority. Pressure would build up and somehow “political independence” would be established in 1963. Sobukwe envisaged campaigns “until independence is won”. 510 a “never-ending stream” of 513 See Karis & Carter From protest to challenge vo1 3 505. 511 See Motlhabi The theory and practice of black resistance to apartheid 145. 512 On this Campaign, see Motlhabi The theory and practice of black resistance to apartheid 174ff and Pogrund Sobukwe and apartheid 110ff. There are indications that the Campaign was launched as a result, inter alia, of assurances of support from Ghana. See Lodge Black politics in South Africa since 1945 203. 513 See Pogrund Sobukwe and apartheid 127. Privately, the leaders envisaged the use of violence in future, but for the time being they propagated non-violence in public. 514 Sobukwe stated that what was intended with the Positive Action Campaign differed from what was intended with the Defiance Campaign: “We are not hoping for a change of heart of the Christian oppressor.” 515 If the Defiance Campaign hovered between persuasion and coercion, the Positive Action Campaign was clearly premised on a commitment to the latter. It was also much more evident than was the case with the Defiance Campaign that the eventual overthrow of the existing apartheid system was a primary objective of the Positive Action Campaign. Sobukwe told his audiences that, when a house is flooding, the solution is not to throw the water out. The PAC, he said, aimed at “closing the tap from which all this vile legislation flows”. 516 Sobukwe gave the Commissioner of Police two weeks’ notice that the Positive Action Campaign was about to start. He told the press that he had appealed to the African people to keep the Campaign non-violent. Nevertheless, he cautioned that “[i]f the other side so desires we will provide them with an opportunity to demonstrate to the world how brutal they can be. We are ready to die for our cause.” 517 It turned out to be prophetic words. On 21 March 1960, Sobukwe walked four miles to the local police station and was joined on the way by small groups of men. At the police station they were arrested. With the PAC lacking a national organisational infrastructure, and its leader cutting off his ability to provide leadership by giving himself up for arrest right at the start of the Campaign, the success of the Campaign was left largely in the hands of fate. It proved to be fateful indeed. Events all over the country on that day suggested that the PAC’s call for Africans to present themselves for arrest remained largely unheeded on a national Vereeniging, 514 515 level. 518 where the The PAC exception was well was the industrial organised and area faced near little See Lodge Black politics in South Africa since 194S 203. Motlhabi apartheid 153. The theory and practice of black resistance 516 Quoted in Gerhart Black power in South Africa 234. 517 Karls & Carter From protest to challenge vol 3 566. 518 See Gerhart Black power in South Africa 236. to opposition from the ANC. At Evaton, several hundred men presented themselves for arrest, but were told by the police that the facilities were inadequate. At Sharpeville a large crowd - estimates ranged from three to twenty thousand - gathered around the police station where 300 policemen were on duty. A police officer was pushed and fell, and according to police witnesses stones were thrown at them. The panicking constables fired into the crowd, killing 69 people, mostly shot in the back, while 180 others were wounded. 519 The shock waves of the event reverberated around the country and indeed around the globe. As time passed by, it became clear that Sharpeville was one of the most important events in the history of black resistance in South Africa, occupying a place similar to that of the incident at Jalianwalah Bagh in India. Sporadic incidents of violence and some demonstrations occurred during the first week after the events at Sharpeville became known. In Pretoria, Lutuli burnt his pass, and both the ANC and the PAC organised a country-wide strike. The government did not delay their clampdown. Public meetings of all races in the large towns were banned. A nationwide state of emergency was proclaimed on 30 March. After a police raid on Langa early in the morning of the same day, a crowd of black people spontaneously marched to Caledon Square. A crowd estimated at almost 30 000 stopped before the Caledon police station. At this stage Philip Kgosana, the Secretary of the Cape PAC, was the leader of the crowd. Inexplicably he agreed to disperse the crowd in return for a promise of a meeting with the Minister of Justice later that day. 520 The crowd dispersed. When Kgosana arrived for his appointment he was arrested. Altogether 1 500 people were arrested that day in a nationwide sweep. Langa and Nyanga were sealed off by the security forces. Except for sporadic outbursts, demonstrations were over. At a subsequent trial, Sobukwe was charged with having incited “natives in general or some of 519 Lodge Black politics In South Africa since 1945 210. See also Gerhart Black power in South Africa 236ff and Thompson A history of South Africa 210ff, who put the number of the dead at 67. For an eyewitness account, see Pogrund Sobukwe and apartheid 132ff. 520 For an attempt to get an explanation why Kgosana accepted these terms, see the account of an Interview with him in Le1yveld Move your shadow 342. them” to break the Pass Laws. During the trial he stated that he and his fellow accused felt they had “no moral obligation to obey the laws made by a white imprisonment. 521 minority”. He was sentenced to three years’ By early May, 18 000 arrests had been made. In March the Unlawful Organizations Act 34 of 1960 had been 4 introduced to authorise the executive to ban the ANC and the PAC. This was done on 8 April. It was organizations. now a crime to further the objectives of these 522 Civil disobedience was once more considered a possibility at the “Allin Conference” in March 1961. A three day strike was planned to coincide with the proclamation of a Republic on 31 May 1961. It was decided that an ultimatum to the government to call a national convention would be issued, failing which a campaign of “mass-non-cooperation” would follow. The strike was widely observed, but when no concessions were obtained from the government the campaign was abandoned. 523 To many this series of events, beginning with Sharpeville, marked the end of the exclusively non-violent struggle. 524 One of the most decisive turning points in South African history had been reached. In 1962 Mandela was accused and convicted for having incited people to strike illegally during the 1961 stay-away in protest of the founding of the Republic. In the course of his defence he stated that he engaged in illegal activity as a last resort. Representations to government yielded no success. He continued: Perhaps the Court will say that despite our human rights to protest, to object, to make ourselves heard, we should stay within the letter of the law. I would say, Sir, that it is the government, its administration of the law, which brings the law into such contempt and disrepute that one is no longer concerned in this country to stay within the letter of the law. 525 Recounting the arbitrary way in which his 521 See Pogrund Sobukwe and apartheid 153. 522 See Infra chap four I & II. 523 See Johns Congress 87ff. & Davis Mandela, Tambo, freedom and the was compromised African National 524 See Lodge Black politics in South Africa since 1945 231. See also Jaspan Science and society 1961 97 at 103, for a discussion of the role of the 1961 Pondo rebellion in this process. 525 See Mandela's "Black man in a white court'-statement, reprinted in Mandela The struggle is my life 133 at 156. through governmental bannings, Mandela stated: I was made, by the law, a criminal, not because of what I have done, but because of what I stood for, because of what I thought, because of my conscience. Can it be any wonder to anybody that such conditions make a man an outlaw of society? 526 (d) Phase four: The violent underground struggle starts When Mandela proposed the use of violence at an ANC national executive meeting in June 1961, it was agreed that, although the ANC remained committed to non-violence, individual members who wanted to follow the route of violence would not be restrained. Umkhonto we Sizwe. the “spear of the nation”, was formed, apparently with at least the tacit agreement of Lutuli, 527 although as late as October 1961 he was publicly still calling for non-violence. 528 A similar movement, Poqo, was formed by the PAC in 1962. 529 A the same time an international diplomatic offensive was launched against South Africa. The military option was taken by the ANC, inter alia. in view of the strength of the realisation that, as Mandela put it, “unless responsible leadership was given to canalise and control the feelings of the people, there would be outbreak of terrorism which would produce an intensity of b1tterness and hostility between the various races of the country.” 530 A discussion of the armed struggle falls outside the scope of this study. For mentioned the that governmental purposes the of continuity focus at installations. On the 16 and perspective beginning December was 1961 the on it could be sabotage of first sabotage attack was launched. A flyer, issued by the command of Umkhonto we Sizwe on that date, stated that "the people’s non-violent policies have been taken as a green light for government violence.” 531 526 Id 157. 527 Karis & Carter From protest to challenge vol 4 62. 528 See his opening address "Minority white rule and non-whites in the Union", delivered at the Conference on unemployment in Durban 21 & 22 October 1961, contained in the W A Kleynhans collection in the UNISA library archives. 529 See Davenport South Africa 395. 530 Karis & Carter From protest to challenge vo1 3 772. 531 See "Announcement of the formation of Umkhonto we Sizwe", reprinted in Johns & Davis Mandela, Tambo, and the African National The movement was, however, severely crippled by a police swoop on its Rivonia headquarters in July 1963, and the subsequent trial and life imprisonment of its most important leaders - including Mandela. 532 When the armed struggle was resumed, it would be characterised by incidents of guerrilla warfare in which many people on both sides would lose their lives. A watershed year would be 1976, which saw the bloody Soweto riots. training. 533 Scores of youths left the country for military Part of the ANC's struggle would include terror attacks on civilian or “soft” targets. There could be little doubt that these acts diminished the moral appeal of the ANC's cause, and strained the support of the international community. In its response to these events, the South African government would bring further security laws into effect, which affected all expressions of political protest. 534 (e) Phase five: External and internal resistance The advent of an overt mass resistance movement in the country, which would operate in tandem with the armed underground, can be traced to the Natal strikes of 1973. 535 The re-emergence of legal structures through which black resistance might find expression meant that the tool of civil disobedience could be revived. Black workers, in spite of legal impediments, gained full trade union findings of the Wiehahn Commission in 1979. rights following the 536 Civil disobedience re-emerged as one of the major political tools of resistance at the end of the 1970’s. In 1978, Indian and coloured people began moving into areas such as Mayfair, which were designated “white” in terms of the Group Areas Act 36 of 1966. A number of people were prosecuted and evicted. In 1979, a couple by the name of Naidu were evicted from their home in Mayfair onto the pavement, from which Congress 138. 532 On the Rivonia trial, see Mandela The struggle is my life 161ff. See also Holland The struggle 148ff and in general Bernstein The world that was ours. 533 See Davenport South Africa 430ff and Holland The struggle 178. 534 See infra chap four II A. 535 See Davis & Fine Journal of Southern African Studies 1985 25 at 29. 536 See "Quiet civil disobedience the real force apartheid, says Kane-Berman" Natal Post 5 May 1989. in eroding they refused to move. They were eventually forcibly removed from the pavement. Press organization, established. where coverage ACTSTOP Under evictions its were aroused (Action Committee auspices, about eviction extremely difficult. public to third take to indignation Stop persons place, the Evictions), now and and occupied was houses consequently made 537 Judicial assistance to their cause came in 1983, when Goldstone J found in S v Govender 538 that ejectment orders seriously affected the lives of the person or persons concerned. It was ruled that such orders could not be made without the fullest inquiry. It had to be established, inter alia, whether alternative accommodation was available. 539 A number of churches, especially since the early 1980’s, openly stated their intention to marry racially mixed couples in contravention of the Prohibition of Mixed Marriages Act 55 of 1949. This was in fact done in a number of cases. 540 In 1985, the Prohibition of Mixed Marriages Act was repealed and section 16 of the Sexual Offences Act 23 of 1957 (the old Immorality Act) was amended. 541 Although civil disobedience was by no means the only or even necessarily the most crucial force that brought about these changes, it did play an important role. An important event in the recent history of civil disobedience was the formation in Cape Town in August 1983 of the United Democratic Front (“UDF”), a broad political alliance which cut across racial and class barriers. 542 As an internal and legal organization, which later joined forces with other progressive organizations to form the Mass Democratic Movement (“MOM”), the UDF would be in a position to initiate sporadic campaigns of civil disobedience. 543 537 See R Robertson "Three case studies of non-violent action" in Nürnberger et a1 Conflict and the quest for justice 319 at 319. 538 1986 3 SA 969 (T). 539 The Group Areas Act was repealed by the Abolition of Racially Based Land Measures Act 108 of 1991. 540 See R Robertson "Three case studies of non-violent action" in Nürnberger et a1 Conflict and the quest for justice 319 at 320. 541 This was done by the Immorality Marriages Amendment Act 72 of 1985. and Prohibition of Mixed 542 See Davenport South Africa 458ff. 543 See "Kongres vir eenheid teen apartheid" Rapport 8 Oct 1989. In 1985, Or Allan Boesak, patron of the UDF, announced a mass march on Pollsmoor prison to demand the release of Nelson Mandela. The march was prohibited under the state of emergency, proclaimed earlier that year, and police barriers were erected to prevent the march from taking place. Boesak was arrested. Between ten and twenty thousand people took to the streets. Serious clashes with the police ensued. 544 In the meantime the armed struggle continued. In a 1985 interview with the Washington Times, Mandela defended the use of violence. The interview was reported as follows: Reminded that Martin Luther King, Jr, professed a strategy of non-violence to achieve equal treatment for blacks in America, Mr Mandela said that conditions in South Africa are "totally different" from conditions in the United States in the 1960s. In the United States, he said, democracy was deeply entrenched, and the people struggling then had access to institutions that protected human rights. The white community in the United States was more liberal than whites in South Africa, and public authorities were restricted by law. 545 On a number of occasions public figures such as Sheena Duncan, President of the Black Sash, expressed themselves guardedly (no doubt possible prosecution for openly propagating civil disobedience played an important role in this regard)in favour of the continued use of civil disobedience. 546 In 1986, Bishop Desmond Tutu, from a pulpit in Atlanta, Georgia, promised that he would lead a campaign of civil disobedience against the apartheid laws of South Africa. 547 A somewhat bizarre and much publicised example of civil disobedience was the plunge taken by the rev Allan Hendrickse, at the time the only coloured cabinet minister, in January 1987 at the (then) whites-only King's Beach in Port Elizabeth. Coming out of the water, Hendrickse said to the press that this transgression of the Separate Amenities Act was “not an act of civil disobedience, but an action to point out the 544 See Villia-Vicencio Civil disobedience and beyond 59. 545 The interview was reprinted in Johns & Davis Mandela, Tambo, and the African National Congress 172. The section quoted is from 173. 546 See "Non-co-operation the only hope for SA" Sunday Tribune 16 March 1986 and "Civil disobedience is our last resort, says Sheena Duncan" The Star 17 March 1986. 547 1986. See "Focus on South Africa as King is saluted" The Star 20 Jan urgency and necessity for change.” 548 Exactly what the basis of the distinction was, is unclear. When it became apparent that State President P W Botha would either dismiss him apologised or to dissolve the the State House of President. Representatives, In a subsequent Hendrickse statement, Hendrickse said he had “not apologised for swimming at a white beach, but for any President.” 549 interpretation of this as an affront to the State Again the distinction is hard to comprehend. A considerable force in the process of change in South Africa has been illegal actions by people whose primary purpose was not to express political protest but simply to get on with their lives. The South African Institute for Race Relations demonstrated that the pass laws became unworkable because people stopped carrying passes. 550 Also in this category one would find the widespread defiance of the Group Areas cosmopolitan Act by “white” thousands areas, to of black which people reference who was moved made into earlier. Universities in white areas similarly ignored or threatened to defy the Group Areas Act in providing accommodation for black students, before the universities were officially granted autonomy to disregard group areas provisions. 551 In 1989, the MDM launched another series of campaigns of defiance, announced as “a peaceful programme of non-violent mass action, directed against apartheid laws.” 552 It is often called the “Defiance Campaign of 548 See "Hendrickse apologised for affront, not swim" The Citizen 23 Jan 1987. 549 Ibid. 550 See "Quiet civil disobedience the real force in eroding apartheid, says Kane-Berman" Natal Post 5 May 1989. See also "Civil disobedience eroding system" The Leader 16 Jan 1989. In this respect the pass laws had the same history as prohibition in the United States, which had to be abandoned because it proved to be unenforceable. See Arendt Crises of the republic 81. 551 See "Rektor praat van wet oortree" Vrye Weekblad 2 June 1989, with reference to the University of Stellenbosch. See, however, also "Akademiese vryheid is relatief, sê Rektor" Die Burger 1 Jan 1987, where the same principal said that civil disobedience cannot be conducted in the name of academic freedom. 552 See Villa-Vicencio Civil disobedience and beyond viii and "Kongres vir eenheid teen apartheid" Rapport 8 Oct 1989. See also 1989”. 553 Boesak explicitly linked this Campaign to the tradition of Gandhi, saying: “We have not learnt about non-violence as an instrument for change from books but have learnt this from our fathers and mothers who have learnt it from their fathers and mothers.” 554 Many of the activities associated with the new Campaign took place in Cape Town. Firstly, there was the “March on Parliament”, organised by a number of churches as the “Standing for the truth Campaign”. On 2 September 1989, approximately 1 000 people attempting, illegally, to march to parliament were arrested, often in a brutal manner. Most visible, however, was the “Peace March”, in which 30 000 people took part. This the government, after initial resistance, allowed to go ahead. 555 Particularly significant in respect of this march was the decision of the mayor of Cape Town, Gordon Oliver, to participate even if the march was to be illegal. 556 The “inferior magistrates” were now leading the resistance. In the wake of the events in Cape Town, thousands of people participated in - mostly legal - marches across the country. Groups of black people insisted on being admitted to white hospitals, schools and swimming pools. 557 On a number of beaches segregation laws were defied. "Wits Black students join defiance" The Citizen 30 Aug 1989; "F W's problem: How to cope with people power" The Dally News 19 Sept 1989; "The thin white line" Pretoria News 19 Sept 1989 and "SA gave world lead on mass protest marches" The Leader 22 Sept 1989. For comments, see "Maak plek vir die buite parlementariërs" Die Transvaler 9 Aug 1989 and "Civil disobedience" Business Day 24 Aug 1989. 553 The Campaign is discussed at some length by Smuts & Westcott The purple shall govern, especially at 45ff and 81ff. 554 Boesak also said there was no law that allowed the people to defy the government, "but when we march peacefully they say this is legal and conveniently forget the 10-odd laws that makes this illegal." See "Gandhian way - Boesak" The Leader 6 Oct 1989. Boesak also called the fact that a non-violent campaign could still be conducted after a11 the repression, "nothing short of a miracle of God". See "Gandhi's values live on in MDM campaign" Natal Post 7 Oct 1989. See also "Out of the ashes Gandhi's Phoenix must arise anew" Natal Post 20 May 1989. 555 Villa-Vicencio Civi1 disobedience and beyond xi. 556 For Oliver's explanation of his reasons for this decision, see Smuts & Westcott The purple shall govern 159. 557 See "Veldtog van verset" Vrye Weekblad 21 April 1989. See also "Throwing a lifeline" Business Day 2 Aug 1989 and "Black miners join The slogan used was “All of God’s beaches for all of God’s people.” 558 Many of those served with banning orders, openly defied their orders. 559 In a number of cases, state restrictions on meetings 561 of emergency restrictions 560 and other and funerals, were openly defied. Veteran liberal Member of Parliament, Helen Suzman, called these restrictions an “open invitation to civil disobedience”. 562 The most important internal organizations, which had been banned by then, held “unbanning” rallies, declaring themselves not to be constrained by the banning orders. More than 1 569 people were arrested. 563 The immediate result of these acts of defiance was not always positive. Threats and actions of civil disobedience were blamed for National Party victories, in which white people voted for the restoration of security and law and order. 564 On the other hand, there could now no longer be any doubt, both at home and abroad, that apartheid was bankrupt and on the verge of collapse. To conclude the overview of this phase, an important though perhaps not obvious instance of civil disobedience during this period must be considered. In the late 1980’s it became clear that offers had been made by the government to Nelson Mandela, imprisoned since the Rivonia trial, offering him his freedom if he accepted a range of conditions one of which was to renounce violence. This he refused to do, and his imprisonment was continued. Reference was made earlier to the view that the voluntary acceptance of martyrdom as culture. The a political validity of tool this is not view an integral seems less part obvious of if African it is considered that the refusal of Mandela to accept a conditional release Defiance Campaign" The Star 4 Aug 1989 558 See Smuts & Westcott The purple shall govern 148. 559 See "We plan to defy restriction orders, vow embassy six" The Star 31 March 1989 and "Ingeperktes wil staat skaakmat sit" Vrye Weekblad 28 April 1989. 560 See "Wits black students join defiance" The Citizen 30 Aug 1989. 561 See "Beperkings bespotting" Die Vaderland 10 April 1986. 562 See "Suzman hits at funeral restrictions" The Citizen 10 April 1986. 563 564 For a fuller discussion, see Levin SAJHR 1989 518 at 521. See "Cosatu campaign will assure NP victory" The Cape Times 2 Aug 1989 and "Throwing a lifeline" Business Day 2 Aug 1989. can best be described as an act of sacrificial civil disobedience. As soon as the first offer of conditional release was made, he had a number of options. He could accept the offer, renounce violence, walk out of prison, perspective, apartheid this regime. and stick option In the to would the agreement. have involved second place, he However, “giving could from in” have to his the renounced violence, but continued the armed struggle once he was out of prison, and justify this breach of promise on the basis that he acted under duress. He chose a third option, namely to refuse to make such a commitment. This was an “illegal” action in the sense that by defying the wishes of the authorities he incurred their wrath 565 (he was kept in prison); it was non-violent (he did not choose the second option, which was open to him); it was done in the open; the conduct was motivated by conviction and it was a political act. In short, he practiced civil disobedience. Mandela’s martyrdom played an immense role in mobilising the oppressed in the country to become politically active, and it was a powerful fact in bringing the international community to put pressure on the South African government. It was one of the major factors which legitimised what is today commonly referred to as the “new South Africa”. 566 (f) Phase six: Prospects of reconciliation and new resistance On 2 February 1990, State President F W de Klerk, in his historic opening of parliament speech, astounded South Africa and the world by announcing not only the imminent release of Nelson Mandela, but also the lifting of the ban on the ANC, the PAC and the South African Communist Party. Amnesty was granted to the external leadership (and later to rank and file members) of the ANC to return to the country. The process of negotiations between the government and its traditional 565 It was argued earlier that an act of civil disobedience does not necessarily involve the commission of an offence. For the purposes of defining civil disobedience, conduct which provokes the executive to retaliate was also described as "illegal". See supra chap two I A. 566 For a fuller discussion of this interpretation of Mande1a's conduct, see Heyns Die Suid-Afrikaan April 1989 43. Jacques Derrida emphasised Mandela's legitimation of the Western system of law in South Africa through his unlawful activities. See J Derrida "The laws of reflection: Nelson Mandela, in admiration" in Derrida & Tlili For Nelson Mandela 13. See also Lawlor Philosophy and Social Criticism 1989 1. enemies commenced, and the ANC suspended the armed struggle. Obviously a very different new era was at hand - also as far as all forms of political resistance were concerned. Given the radical nature of these changes, right-wing resistance was to be expected. The government was accused of acting without a mandate and of “selling out” the whites to a black and a communist government. While right-wing anger spilled over into terror attacks by clandestine factions, established leaders like Dr Treurnicht gave thinly concealed endorsements of violent actions and threatened to engage in a campaign of civil disobedience. Often the same authorities (like Calvin) were invoked who were relied upon in the struggle against apartheid. 567 In October 1990, the Conservative Party mooted the idea of staging a campaign of civil disobedience. This campaign would take the form of a tax boycott and the withholding of television licence fees, in protest against government reform and the alleged bias of the South African Broadcasting Corporation. 568 These proposals met with nearly universal” condemnation from the established Afrikaans, 569 English 570and black 571 press - often pointing out the irony of a resort by the Conservative Party, traditionally the champion of “law and order”, to this form of protest. 572 At the same time, it became clear that mass-mobilisation, inter alia through acts of civil disobedience, was still regarded as an important strategy by the ANC. In November 1990 Mandela called for the use of civil disobedience in order to intensify the struggle, and described 567 See infra chap five I L (2). 568 See "Versetplan van die KP uitgespel" Beeld 17 Oct 1990; "Now CP considers withholding taxes" The Star 17 Oct 1990; "F W kasty KP oor sy planne" Die Transvaler 19 Oct 1990 and "CP's war talk belies mood of despair" The Star 19 Oct 1990. 569 See eg "Buite beheer" Die Volksblad 17 Oct 1990; "Die KP op pad na anargie" Die Burger 18 Oct 1990 and "Moenie met iets begin nie" Tempo 19 Oct 1990. 570 See eg "Don't" The Citizen 18 Oct 1990. 571 See eg "The govt must take on the right wing" Sowetan 18 Oct 1990. 572 See "KP se planne nie op vaste grond" Die Volksblad 19 Oct 1990 and "KP praat met swartmense in kombuise oor die ANC" Vrye Weekblad 19 Oct 1990. civil disobedience as an example of “legitimate, peaceful” conduct. 573 In January 1991, hundreds of farmers converged on Pretoria. They arrived in the city at night with tractors and other farming vehicles, and sealed off the major entrances into the city. Their protest was aimed at highlighting the crisis in agriculture. Among their grievances were their heavy financial debt, high interest rates, the poor prices they receive for produce, and the then pending abolition of the Land Act. For more than a day the entire city was disrupted. The government refused to make any concessions to the protesters. 574 Clearly, for better or for worse, Gandhi’s method of political resistance has become an integral part of the South African political process. B. GANDHIAN CIVIL DISOBEDIENCE IN INDIA Gandhi’s reputation as the champion of the rights of Indians in South Africa who had prevailed against Smuts and the British Empire, preceded him upon his return to India in 1915, and he was already called “Mahatma” or “Great Soul”. Nevertheless, he still had to establish himself as a national leader in the practical politics of his home country. In India, growing resistance against the British Raj or rule was developing, mainly under the leadership of the Indian Congress (“Congress”). At the same time, India was tormented by the dark forces of inner strife, in the form of animosity between Hindu and Muslim factions and between the different castes. Gandhi would devote the remainder of his life to addressing these issues in accordance with his philosophy of non-violent confrontation. As far Gandhi as was independence the attainment in the in 1947 end - of to an Swaraj see or independence success independence when from was India concerned, was colonialism granted which was 573 See "Hard words between Govt and ANC expected" The Citizen 20 Nov 1990. See also "Govt 'preparing for violation of civil rights'" Business Day 16 Nov 1990. 574 See "Disgruntled farmers plan protest march" The Citizen 9 Jan 1991; "Polisie en boere bots" Die Transvaler 29 Jan 1991; "Farmers go for protest rally" The Star 29 Jan 1991; "Siege of Pta", "It's walk to work in capital's worst-ever traffic jam" The Citizen 30 Jan 1991; "Protesoptogte in SA kry nog 'n knou in die maag" Die Burger 30 Jan 1991; "The farmers - and others", "Pretoria faces more chaos", "Amazing scenes as farmers sow chaos" The Star 30 Jan 1991. remarkable for the relatively minor role which violence played. In fact, India’s independence sparked off a wide rejection of colonialism in Asia and Africa. In a real sense Gandhi - the dark-skinned man who stood up against the most powerful colonial forces of his time, and won - can be colonialism seen in as the general. liquidator 575 In of respect the of British India's Empire and domestic of strife, however, Gandhi was to experience humiliating and frustrating defeat. Upon independence, the India which he knew was torn apart by a violent and bloody civil war into the predominantly Hindu India of today, and Pakistan, which is mainly Muslim. (1) Campaigns conducted by Gandhi Gandhi’s political resistance against British rule in India centred upon three major campaigns of Satyagraha: the Non-co-operation Campaign of 1920, the Salt Tax Campaign of 1930, and the “Quit India” Campaign of 1942. 576 These campaigns were preceded by events that set the stage for mass civil disobedience in India. The first incident occurred almost inadvertently. Beseeched by a peasant from the remote area of Champaran to come to his district, Gandhi learned that the British landlords in the area coerced indigo share croppers into paying impossible sums of rent. When he visited the area, the landlords had the civil authorities issue an order for Gandhi to leave the region - which he refused to obey. In a subsequent trial, Gandhi pleaded guilty. 577 He stated that he disregarded the order “not for want of respect for lawful authority, but in obedience to the higher law of our being, the voice of conscience.” 578 Before sentence could be passed, the case was withdrawn on orders from the LieutenantGovernor. A second incident which set the stage was Gandhi’s conduct at Ahmedabad when strikers whom he had supported were considering ending the strike. 575 For a discussion of political obligation and colonialism, see Macfartane Political studies 1968 335 at 339ff. 576 For a discussion of the most important campaigns, see Bondurant Conquest of violence 46ff. 577 See Gandhi An autobiography 404ff and Bishop A technique for loving 59ff. 578 Gandhi An autobiography 414. In order to Satyagraha, strategy move as them at against to persist, Champaran, the British, he would he went on constitute would often fast. 579 a Gandhi’s use the Whereas preferred technique of fasting against his own people. During the First World War, Gandhi once more aided the British war effort, this time by taking part in a recruiting campaign to encourage the enlistment of Indian soldiers in the British army. By doing this, he again hoped to establish his bona fides as a loyal British citizen. He believed that after the War in which Indians fought on the side of Britain, Empire”. India 580 would become the “most favoured partner in the This hope was strengthened in 1917 when the newly appointed Secretary of State for India, Sir Edwin Montague, in the House of Commons envisaged the granting of “self-governing institutions with a view to the progressive realisation of responsible government in India as an integral part of the British Empire.” 581 This was seen as a pledge of dominion status to India. At the time, Gandhi’s quarrel was not yet with the British Empire itself but only with India’s subordinate position in the Empire. As it turned out, however, Britain was far from ready to live up to the expectations which it had created. The shock to Gandhi and to Congress could not have been greater when, after the War, in 1919, Britain introduced the draconian Rowlatt Acts. 582 Powers granted to the Indian government to deal with people in areas declared “subversive” included summary Against arrest, this trial without background, jury, Gandhi and in started camera proceedings. 583 organising mass civil disobedience in India. (a) Phase one: The Non-co-operation Campaign of the 1920’s Gandhi responded to these events by organising a Hartal or economic boycott, a traditional Indian form of non-violent protest. All economic activity in a specific area would be suspended for a number of days. 579 580 Id 430 and Woodcock Gandhi S3. Bishop A technique autobiography 444. 581 for loving 62. See also Gandhi An Quoted in Fischer Gandhi 60. 582 Gandhi An autobiography 454 and Moore Liberalism and Indian politics 117. 583 See Bishop A technique for loving 63 and Woodcock Gandhi 58. Stalls were closed and workers downed their tools. In addition, Gandhi encouraged Satyagrahi’s (the followers he had by now assembled) to offer themselves for arrest by breaking one of a selected number of laws, such newspapers. as 584 selling forbidden books or distributing unregistered The police, however, turned a blind eye and hence defused the situation. Then, on 13 April 1919, one of the most influential events of the independence struggle occurred. 585 In spite of Gandhi’s insistence on non-violence, some violence did accompany Hartals, especially in the major centres. In the town of Amritsar, in the Punjab, mob violence occurred when certain local politicians were arrested. The military commander, General Dyer, announced martial law, whereby public meetings were banned. Nevertheless, a public meeting was organised in Jalianwalah Bagh, a closed-in public park. Dyer set out to break up the meeting with armed troops. According to his own account, Dyer, when he arrived at the scene of the meeting, gave the crowd no warning to disperse. He considered it unnecessary since they were gathered in breach of his proclamation. He gave the order to shoot, and for ten minutes his troupes fired into the unarmed, trapped crowd. 1 650 rounds were fired at what he later described as “the place where the crowd was the thickest.” 1 516 casualties were inflicted: 379 people died, and 1 137 were wounded. 586 Violence in the form of uprisings then swept the country. Horrified by this turn of events, Gandhi called the Satyaaraha campaign off. He called miscalculation”. the 587 initial launching of the campaign a “Himalayan In typical fashion he did not blame his opponents as the main culprits: Indians, he concluded, were not yet disciplined enough for a nationwide campaign of non-violent resistance. Nevertheless, an important point had been made - the violence on which the British Raj depended had been revealed. In practice the Rowlatt Acts were never implemented. 588 As a consequence of the shootings, Gandhi now turned to a complete 584 Gandhi An autobiography 462 and Woodcock Gandhi 58, 59. 585 See Bishop A technique for loving 65. 586 See Woodcock Gandhi 60 and Fischer Gandhi 66. 587 Gandhi An autobiography 469. 588 See Woodcock Gandhi 61. rejection of British rule in India. 589 In 1920 he returned medals awarded to him in South Africa during the Anglo-Boer War and the Zulu uprising, together with a letter saying: “I can retain neither respect nor affection for a government which has been moving from wrong to wrong in order to defend its immorality.” 590 He urged his countrymen not to co-operate on any level with the British structures in India. His appeal was heeded by many who started boycotting schools, resigned from posts at government institutions, from the courts, from the bar etc. Gandhi then selected one district, Bardolli, where he would personally supervise a tax boycott. 591 As always, Gandhi gave the authorities full notice of his intentions. The first reason for the delimitation of a particular district was to be able to keep the Campaign under control. The second was to impress the British with a display of Indian restraint. The Campaign in Bardolli had hardly started, however, when an Indian mob in a small town in another part of India savagely killed 22 constables. Gandhi, appalled once more by his countrymen’s proneness to succumb Bardolli, to and violence, forfeited immediately political in called off favour of the moral footwork did not go down well with all of his followers. Campaign gains. in This 592 With Gandhi being in this vulnerable position, he was arrested for sedition in March 1922. Gandhi practically asked for it in so many words in articles which he had published He wrote: “I have no hesitation in saying that it is sinful for anyone, either soldier or civilian, to serve this government ... sedition has become the creed of Congress ... Nonco-operation, though a religious and strictly moral movement, deliberately aims at the overthrow of the government and is therefore legally seditious.” 593 He stated that they were “at war” with the government, and that they had declared a “rebellion” against it. He said: “We want to overthrow the government”, and that it was a “fight to the finish”. 594 By arresting him, however, the British restored Gandhi’s fledgling support. Woodcock described what is today called 589 Fischer Gandhi 68. 590 Ibid. 591 Id 70. 592 Woodcock Gandhi 64. 593 Fischer Gandhi 72. 594 Ibid. “the Great Trial” as a turning point in Gandhi’s tug of war with the British. 595 Gandhi was tried with “bringing or attempting to bring into hatred or contempt or exciting or attempting to exciting disaffection towards His Majesty’s Government, established law in India.” 596 British Characteristically, Gandhi pleaded guilty and told the court: I am here, therefore, to invite and cheerfully submit the highest penalty that can be inflicted upon me for what in law is a deliberate crime and what appears to be the highest duty of a citizen. The only court open to you, the judge, is ... either to resign your post, or inflict on me the severest penalty, if you believe that the system and law you are assisting to administer are good for the people. 597 Gandhi described the British rule of India as “exploitation of the masses”. 598 The magistrate’s treatment of Gandhi reflected and expressed a new realisation on behalf of British officialdom that the British code of honourable behaviour was being used against it. After convicting Gandhi, the magistrate stated: [W]hat remains, namely, the determination of a just sentence, is perhaps as difficult a proposition as a judge in this country could have to face. The law is no respecter of persons. Nevertheless, it will be impossible to ignore the fact that you are in a different category from any person I have ever tried or am likely to have to try. It would be impossible to ignore the fact that in the eyes of millions of your countrymen, you are a great patriot and a great leader. 599 He stated that it was his duty to sentence Gandhi to six years’ imprisonment and proceeded: “I should like to say in doing so that, if the course of events in India should make it possible for the government to reduce the period and release you, no one will be better 595 Woodcock Gandhi 64. A detailed account of the trial is given under the heading "Arrest and trial" in Mayer The pacifist console 204. 596 See Mayer The pacifist conscience 207. 597 Id 211. 598 Id 213. To employ terms used earlier, he consequently described his civil disobedience as anti-exploitation. 599 Id 215. pleased than I.” 600 This was the last time that Gandhi was tried. It was not the last time that he was arrested. Gandhi served 22 months of his sentence and was released in February 1924 due to poor health. A massacre of Hindus by Muslims again brought Gandhi under the impression of the friction which existed between these two religious groups Gandhi - himself a Hindu - decided to fast for 21 days in order to focus attention on the problem and move the two parties to reconciliation. It did highlight the problem but hardly made a difference to the level of tension. 601 In the late twenties, the national mood in India was ugly, with violence and talk of violence the order of the day. There was strong pressure on Congress, independence, and especially consequently to from the young, to declare declare war against England. In February 1928, Gandhi for the first time articulated his desire not only to end Britain’s hold over India, but to bring to a fall the whole British Empire: “[T]hrough the deliverance of India I seek to deliver the so-called exploitation weaker in which races from England is the the crushing greater heels partner.” of 602 Western Gandhi’s mission was no longer only to end the degrading treatment inflicted on Indians but to end exploitive racist in general. His own racism and elitism was now something of the past. Gandhi decided to go ahead with the tax strike at Bardo11i, which he had previously called off. It turned out to be 4 textbook example of what Gandhi intended a Satyaraha campaign to be. 603 The 84 000 peasants in the area refrained from violence despite brutal arrests when they refused to pay their taxes. In less than six months the government released all prisoners and granted the reduction in taxes they demanded. In December 1928, Gandhi managed to persuade Congress not to declare independence warning to with grant immediate India effect but independence. to When give England Ramsay a one McDonald’s year Labour Party took office in England in 1929, new possibilities arose. The Viceroy, Lord Irwin, announced that the British government envisaged a 600 Ibid. 601 Woodcock Gandhi 69. 602 Id 71. 603 See Woodcock Gandhi 71. round table conference of British and “the natural issue of India’s attainment of Dominion status.” Indian delegates, and said that constitutional 604 progress ... is the Gandhi and the nationalist leaders responded favourably. Then the Tories and the Liberals, in a combined effort in the British parliament, overruled Lord Irwin’s commitment. (b) Phase two: The Salt Tax Campaign 1930 Congress now passed a resolution declaring that they were no longer interested in India being a dominion in the Empire. Gandhi issued the Indian Declaration of Independence, calling for India to sever the British connection in toto, in order to attain Purna Swaraj or complete independence. Non-co-operation with government structures was once again sanctioned, as well as non-payment of taxes and a nationwide campaign of civil disobedience. Gandhi was expected to take the lead in the civil disobedience campaign. 605 Gandhi knew through bitter experience how easily a campaign intended to be non-violent could erupt into violence, especially in such a charged situation. He took six weeks to consider which approach to take, before he came up with a very simple, but powerful, idea. It was to serve as yet another model of non-violent action. 606 He decided on a large-scale public protest against the Salt Tax Laws. These laws made it illegal to possess salt not purchased from the government salt monopoly. Through its monopoly, the British government was in a position to exact high taxes on the salt it sold. Since salt is an essential tropical poor. Indian commodity sun, this for those placed a working heavy in burden the on fields in the especially the 607 In March 1930, after notice was served on the Viceroy, Gandhi (now aged 61) led a procession of 78 followers, which along the way grew to several thousand, on a 24 day, 240 miles epic march by foot to the coastal town of Dandi. Here, Gandhi said, he would break the Salt Laws. This march of defiance of Britain, in pursuit of the interests of the very poor, captivated the imagination of India 604 See Fischer Gandhi 95. 605 See Woodcock Gandhi 71 and Pischer Gandhi 94. 606 Bishop A technique for loving 72. 607 Woodcock Gandhi 72. and of the world. Gandhi’s progress was followed, in Woodcock’s words, as the world had followed Lindberg’s flights. 608 At Dandi, Gandhi dipped in the water, and then picked up some salt left by the waves. Through this natural and innocent action he committed a crime. All India received the message. The second Indian campaign of civil disobedience had started, this time nationwide. Salt was illegally produced all over the country, and people were arrested on a large scale. reading of Other crimes seditious included literature in in the protest public, action urging the were the boycott of foreign textiles and organising Hartals. When the government called in the troops to restore order, they more than once refused to fire on demonstrators. One hundred thousand people were placed himself. 609 in prison, including, after nearly a month, Gandhi This time those participating in the Campaign, knowing that Gandhi would call the Satyaqraha campaign off if violence broke out, kept it virtually non-violent. 610 Newspapers from all over the world urged the Gandhi. 611 British government to settle the issue amicably with With Gandhi in prison, his supporters proceeded with a demonstration which he had planned. On 21 May 1930, 2 500 volunteers went to the Dharasana Salt Works, which they intended to invade non-violently. Without offering any resistance, they marched, in file, to its gates to be struck command. A down with journalist steel shot witnessing staves the by policemen confrontation under reported British to the world: “Those struck down fell sprawling, unconscious or writhing with fractured skulls or broken shoulders ... The survivors, without breaking ranks, silently and doggedly marched on until struck down.” 612 This eerie ritual continued for several days. The proceedings at the salt works, and the constraint shown by the protesters, were an enormous moral victory for India and for Gandhi. Upon his release, Gandhi asked for an interview with the Viceroy and 608 Id 73. 609 Id 75. 610 Fischer Gandhi 99. 611 See Bakshi Gandhi and [the] civil disobedience movement 104. 612 Fischer Gandhi 101. See also Woodcock Gandhi 75. found himself in a strong bargaining position. Churchill, with all his racial prejudices understood Gandhi’s moral advantage better than anyone else, when he described what was to him the “nauseating and humiliating spectacle of this one-time Inner Temple lawyer, now seditious fakir, striding half naked up the steps of the Viceroy’s palace, there to negotiate and parley representative of the King-Emperor.” on equal terms with the 613 When it came to negotiations, however, Gandhi secured very little more from Irwin than a suspension of the salt laws for the coastal regions, and the release of the people who had by now been arrested. Formally, no advancement in the direction of independence had been made. 614 In August 1931, Gandhi, as the sole representative of Congress, went to London for the second set of round table talks. Again virtually nothing positive was achieved. Instead, the differences between Congress, the Muslim league and the Indian princes (who were all represented) were emphasised. Gandhi regarded the British emphasis on the divisions as a delaying tactic - the divisions was a problem that would resolve itself. Eventually he would find out what a grave mistake this was. Gandhi did, however, gain considerable popularity amongst people of England. the working 615 When he returned to India at the end of 1931, a new Viceroy had assumed power, and in terms of new emergency powers which had been proclaimed, Gandhi was arrested and imprisoned. 616 In September 1932, while in prison, Gandhi addressed an aspect of Indian social life which to him had become of supreme importance, namely the status of the untouchables or Harijans. A proposed constitution for India’s legislative assembly envisaged that Hindus and Muslims, as well as untouchables, would be placed on different voters’ rolls. In a dramatic attempt to persuade Indian society to abandon these prejudices (which had its origin in racist considerations), Gandhi announced a six day fast. 617 613 Quoted in Fischer Gandhi 103. (Emphasis added.) 614 See on the Gandhi-Irwin Pact, Bakshi Gandhi and [the] civi1 disobedience movement 104. 615 Woodcock Gandhi 76. 616 Ibid. 617 Fischer Gandhi 109. His friends described the scene around his bed as akin to that attending Socrates's when he drank the hemlock. This time there was a considerable response to his call. Citadels of Hindu orthodoxy were thrown open. All over India, wells were shared, and age-old social barriers were taken down. Gandhi’s fast certainly did not solve the problem of division of Indian society, but a dent was made in a very rigid system. 618 When Gandhi was released from prison in May 1933, he undertook a ten months tour of India for Harijan welfare. He called off the civil disobedience campaign and was not involved with Congress politics for the rest of the 1930’s. Gandhi’s concern with the caste and religious divisions in India, and the disruptions caused by industrialisation, led to attempts on his part to remedy those evils. His “constructive programme” was in fact premised on the same point of departure as the Satyagraha campaign, namely that Indians first had to purify themselves through self-sacrifice, and that they would then automatically gain their freedom through desert. In 1939, when the Second World War broke out, India was taken into the conflict by Britain, Congress reacted without strongly Indian against leaders Britain’s having been declaration consulted. of war on behalf of India, which was regarded as a further act of humiliation. While Congress sympathised with the Allied cause, they wanted clarity on the independence issue before Indian lives were to be sacrificed for England. Gandhi, on the one hand, wanted to show his strong disapproval of Britain. On the other hand, he did not wish to embarrass England while she was engaged propagated not in a mass, war. Consequently, but individual for the Satyagraha time in being, pursuit independence. Eventual some 23 000 Satyagraha’s were imprisoned. (c) he of 619 Phase three: The “Quit India” Campaign When it became clear in 1942 that Britain was not about to give in on the issue launched. of 620 general of Indian independence, the “Quit India” Campaign was This demonstration took the form of a massive demonstration Satyagraha. Gandhi told his countrymen to consider themselves free, and to act accordingly. He and the other leaders were 618 Id 123. 619 See Woodcock Gandhi 94. 620 See Copley Gandhi 78. arrested Large-scale violence broke out, which Gandhi was powerless to stop. Gandhi was released from prison two years later in 1944. 621 By now, it was clear that independence was imminent, Power was up for grabs, and the internal strife intensified. Mohamed Ali Jinnah, leader of the Muslim league, demanded a part of India exclusively for Muslims: Pakistan. This demand conflicted with everything Gandhi stood for - the common destiny and the indivisibility of the human race would be forfeited. Gandhi negotiated with the British and with Jinnah, but allowed valuable opportunities to reach a compromise to slip through his fingers. 622 In August 1946, Jinnah resorted to violence. In four days approximately 5 000 people were killed in riots, and the violence continued. Gandhi went from village to village to preach reconciliation. His life’s work was under serious threat. Eventually, Jinnah and the population as a whole could not be persuaded to adhere to the moral ideals which Gandhi propagated. In the ensuing civil war, the greatest uprootment of people in history took place, as 15 million would abandon their homes and flee in terror, and hundreds of thousands of people died. 623 In September 1946, an interim local government was established. Gandhi, preoccupied with the internal struggle, devoted his time to visiting those spots most troubled by Hindu-Muslim antagonism. Eventually while in Bengal and exasperated by the senseless killings, he took his refuge to a “fast to death”. Unless sanity returned at least to Calcutta, he vowed to die of hunger. The 73 hours fast made a lasting impression on the province, and violence eventually subsided. A second fast did not make the same impression. The country remained locked in a deadly, religious civil war. On 15 August 1947, India and Pakistan gained independence as separate nations. 624 India became a republic on 26 January 1948, and remained a member of the British Commonwealth. On 30 January 1948, Gandhi, aged 78, was assassinated by a member of an 621 Gandhi spent altogether almost six years in Indian prisons, and 249 days in prisons in South Africa. Fischer Gandhi 148. 622 Id 159. 623 Id 171. 624 See Fischer Gandhi 171. For a detailed analysis of Gandhi's role in this process, see Nanda Gandhi and his critics 77. extreme right-wing Hindu group who objected to his insistence that liberated India must treat adherents to all religions with equal justice and generosity. Several observations may be made with reference to the above: - Gandhi was a reformer in South Africa and for the first part of his career in India. Thereafter he was a revolutionary. - In his efforts to overthrow the British Raj, he remained absolutely committed to non-violence. It was for him a matter of principle, not strategy. - Gandhi clearly understood that civil disobedience, in order to be effective, force”. required the presence of a “benevolent background He addressed both the British public and world opinion through highly visible campaigns, and expected them to pressurise the British government. - Gandhi’s preoccupation with the role of discipline in non-violent protest remained unwavering and in fact increased. Campaigns were for the most part focussed on transgressing a strictly limited number of laws, and were often confined to a certain area. He did not hesitate to call off a campaign of civil disobedience if this discipline subsided - irrespective embarked upon by the other side. of the degree of violence He used Satyagraha not only to demoralise his opponent but also to inspire his own people and to give them self-confidence. - Gandhi saw the essence of civil disobedience in the voluntary acceptance of suffering, when that suffering is caused by the opponent’s commitment to a practice or practices of which he disapproved. In conformity with this attitude, he invited the harshest possible punishment for his unlawful acts, and refused to conduct his defence in cases brought against him so as to procure a mitigated sentence. His brand of civil disobedience was clearly sacrificial. - He retained his flair for selecting as targets for civil disobedience, easily identifiable injustices (as with the salt tax) that would capture the imagination - even if these targets did not entail the worst injustices. He was a master at using civil disobedience as a tool of communication in an age when global communication was in the process of being established. - Also important was the development of Gandhi himself. From an elitist and indeed racist beginning in South Africa he developed into a champion of the third world. It is submitted that this development might to a considerable extent be a natural consequence of the use of civil disobedience, with its emphasis on morality. Especially his conduct in respect of the Harijans reveals the nature of civil disobedience as a double-sided sword - it makes a moral appeal to the opponent as well as to the person who practises it. (2) Gandhi's philosophy of Satyagraha Leo To1st6y in 1910 described Gandhi’s Satyagraha campaign in South Africa as “the most important of all the work now being done in the world”. 625 Even if exaggerated, the comment reflects the desire of a world finding itself subjected to increasingly powerful and dehumanising forms of human destruction, to establish more humane ways of regulating the terms of our shared existence. 626 Gandhi’s political philosophy in many respects certainly is idiosyncratic, and it is embedded in a philosophical outlook on life that may not be acceptable to everyone. While civil disobedience has not by any means been universally accepted as a feasible means of offering political resistance, Gandhi’s own peculiar version of that strategy of protest is even more controversial. Especially Gandhi’s almost complete commitment to non-coercion and his insistence on the need to pursue self-sacrifice in order to elicit the creative power of suffering would not be shared by many. Nevertheless, his example, even if extreme, has inspired non-violent 625 The letter was translated from Russian by P Padlashuk and is reprinted in the Golden number of "Indian Opinion" 1914 18. See also Muzumdar Mahatma Gandhi 16. In Russia, Tolstóy's Individual nonviolent resistance, which drew inspiration from Gandhi's acts in South Africa, seriously eroded the resolve of the Tsarist régime. See Woodcock Gandhi 105. 626 Fischer Gandhi 89 formulated Gandhi's most basic question as follows: "How can the modern individual maintain his inner peace and outer security, how can he remain honest, free, and himself in the face of the assaults being made upon him by the power of mighty governments, the power of mighty economic organizations, the power of evil that resides in cruel majorities and militant minorities, and the power now extractable from the atom?" resistance movements worldwide - not only in his native India. 627 His influence on the liberation struggles in South Africa and the United States of America, as is evident elsewhere in this chapter, was direct. Gandhi’s legacy also found resonance in the pursuit of other causes in the rest of the world, to which reference has been made earlier, where mass civil disobedience was used to protest against issues as diverse as the military perceived as and non-military detrimental unpopular foreign wars. to use the of nuclear environment, power, and the activities conduct of 628 In Africa, at least until the 1960’s, Gandhi’s ideas had a strong influence on the formative processes of black nationalism. The West African Congress, for example, was established in 1920, patterned after the Natal Indian Congress. Kwame Nkrumah was influenced by Gandhi's ideas in his conducting of the liberation struggle of Ghana, as was Julius Nyerere in Tanzania. The 1945 Pan-African Congress, which was attended by Nkrumah and Kenyatta, as well as by ANC delegates, endorsed Gandhi’s passive resistance as the only effective way of persuading alien rulers to respect the rights of unarmed subjected races. 629 The Algerian National Liberation Front initially had great difficulties in securing the legitimacy of their armed struggle against the French, due to the popularity of Gandhian ideas. 630 It was, however, Kenneth Kaunda, whose influence Southern Africa Gandhi. Gandhi’s light”. was in respect immense, teachings, who of was Kaunda resistance most said, in markedly “flooded the whole of influenced by my mind with 631 During the late 1980’s and the early 1990’s the embattled Eastern European governments were given notice, in no uncertain terms, of the 627 See G Ostergaard "The Gandhian movement in India since the death of Gandhi" in Hick & Hempel Gandhi's significance for today 203. 628 Mistra & Gangal Gandhi and the contemporary world sets out the implications of Gandhian thought for a number of global problems inter alia the threat of war and human rights. Many world leaders, such as Anwar Sadat, have expressed admiration for Gandhi. See J W Gould "Gandhi's relevance today" in Hick & Hempel Gandhi's significance for today 7 at 10. 629 See Benson South Africa 90. 630 See Nanda Gandhi and his critics 32ff. 631 See Kaunda Kaunda on violence 15. opinion of the people through often illegal marches which involved millions of people. It has been argued that the fall of Marxism, prompted by these marches, together with the upsurge in non-violent protest marches in South Africa in 1989, made a major contribution towards the eventual demise of apartheid. 632 Gandhi’s teachings in many cases did not prevent the eventual use of violence, especially in Africa of the 1950’s and later; nevertheless, it often inspired reluctance to resort to the use of force. Few people accept the radical nature of Gandhi's claim – “non-violence as the first article of [one’s] faith”, 633 but the example set by himself -in his pursuit of this ideal and the successes he achieved have exercised a powerful gravitational pull away from a resort to violence. To systematically reconstruct the theoretical tenets of Gandhian thought would be no easy task. He was primarily a man of action and what he wrote was in the first place designed to further his particular practical aims of the time. As Fischer stated: “He did not think out his ideas, he worked them out.” 634 Consequently, much of our time was spent on tracing his actual conduct. A short exposition of the outlines of his philosophy will now follow. 635 (a) The sources of Satyaqraha In the first place, one should establish what the primary influences on Gandhi’s thought were. Apart from the influence of Hinduism (to which we will presently return), Gandhi was evidently also deeply -influenced by his legal training in London and his exposure to British liberal values. Even at the time of the deepest Indian-British conflict, Gandhi had a love-hate relationship with Britain. 636 Although Gandhi’s own collected works are contained in altogether 67 volumes, he was not a well-read man. A number of books, however, had a profound influence on him. His constant companion was the Bhagavad- 632 See Smuts & Westcott The people shall govern 81ff. 633 See Mayer The pacifist conscience 210. 634 Fischer Gandhi 59. 635 A fascinating analysis of Gandhi's Wolfenstein The revolutionary personality. 636 personality is given in See eg his assurance to English friends, on the eve of starting civil disobedience in 1930, that "I am no enemy of Britain." Gandhi Non-violent resistance 222. Gita, 637 the sacred Hindu book, which exalts the virtues selflessness, or, as Gandhi referred to it, “desirelessness”. 638 of He was also influenced by the Bible. In the Sermon on the Mount, with its admonition of turning the other cheek and concern with the weak, Gandhi found sustenance which almost moved him to Christianity. 639 Later he would say: “I am a Christian and a Hindu and a Muslim and a Jew.” 640 In the final analysis, the “benevolent background force” in which Gandhi placed his trust was an omnipotent and just God. In 1893, Gandhi read Tolstoy’s “The kingdom of God is within you”, 641 which, to Gandhi, “furnished a reasoned basis for ... non-violence.” 642 In 1904, a few years before he established Satyagraha, he read John Ruskin’s “Unto this last” 643 exhaling the value of the simple life. This book, Gandhi said, “made me transform my life”, but it should be noted that Gandhi read much into the book that is not there. 644 Gandhi also described Thoreau as one of his “teachers”, 645 but Thoreau’s influence in forming Gandhi's ideas should not be overrated. Gandhi read Thoreau’s essay “On the duty of civil disobedience” when he was already 637 Translated from the Sanskrit into English by Arnold as The Sun Celestial. See K W Bolle "Gandhi's interpretation of the Bhagavad G1ta" in Hick & Hempet Gandhi's significance for today 137ff. 638 As will be pointed out, this was also the prime virtue pursued by the Stoics, whose approach to political resistance deeply Influenced Western thinking on the subject. See infra chap five I B (3) and I C. 639 On Gandhi's understanding of the Sermon on the Mount, see Das Bangalore Theological Forum 1985 17 41. 640 See Fischer Gandhi 130. Gandhi refused to negate the variety of religious traditions, because he believed in the continuity and extension of truth through time and space. He found support for this in Matthew 5.17: "Do not suppose that I have come to abolish the law and the prophets: I did not come to abolish, but to complete." 641 Reprinted in To1stóy The kingdom of God and peace essays 1. It is interesting to note that the first chapter of "The Kingdom of God is within you" deals with the experiences of American abolitionists, Quakers, Mennonites and pacifists, which means that Gandhi was influenced along this route by the early American experience. 642 Bishop Gandhi 52. 643 Reprinted in Ruskin Unto this last and other essays on art and political economy 115. 644 See Woodcock Gandhi 25. 645 See Bishop A technique for loving 52. in a South African jail in 1907 for having started a full-scale civil disobedience movement. 646 It is not the object of this study to cover in detail the essential elements of the Indian tradition in which Gandhi grew up and from which, as a devoted Hindu, he drew inspiration. It will suffice to say that the following has been identified as some of the key notions in Indian and specifically Hindu religious thought, pertinent to the issue of civil disobedience. In the first place, there is the notion of dharma, denoting an ideal of society which is in equilibrium and in harmony, and undertakes. creditor 647 It to starvation. shaped was, move 648 by for his the 649 the to devotion discipline example, debtor Connected selflessness, compromise. is to this to an this person established payment is a the by voluntarily practice engaging idea equilibrium, of which for in a self- anasakti or necessitates Self-denial is an integral part of this tradition. Central in Hinduism is the idea of reincarnation. This forms part of a perception of the world as an organism, where there is abheda, or an absence of essential differences between one creature and another. 650 Being locked into this single universal body that encompasses both time and place, each one of us has the duty to contribute towards the eventual elimination the anekantavada, fundamental belief of suffering. manysidedness that our of From the reality, understanding of Jain Gandhi truth theory derived is at of his best fragmentary, which implies that we have no right to impose our views on others. 651 In the last place, the word ahimsa or non-violence expresses an ancient ethical precept accepted by Hinduism, Jain and Buddhism. This notion has an active rather than a passive meaning - it is a guide to action, 646 See Woodcock Gandhi 25. 647 Chatterjee Gandhi's religious thought 19. 648 Id 21. Muzumdar Mahatma Gandhi 16 indicates that the practice of dharma in the Hindu tradition involved the application of moral pressure on the opponent by willfully undergoing austerities oneself. See also Bondurant Conquest of violence 118. 649 Chatterjee Gandhi's religious thought 36. 650 Id 31. 651 Id 33. not inaction. To use the terms employed earlier, it points to resultoriented rather than defensive actions and accounts for Gandhi's rejection of the term “passive resistance” to describe what he was propagating. (b) Central features of Gandhi’s political thought An essential key to understanding Gandhi’s political thought and action lies in the realisation that, to him, there is no difference between religion and politics. This accounts for his emphasis on the spiritual as opposed to material driving forces in history, and his belief that civil disobedience could make a difference. Because we all are the creation of one God, our humanity is indivisible. Consequently, he believed that “[t]he humankind is one big family.” 652 In fact, Gandhi saw the universe as something akin to a giant household. 653 He was in the first place a universalist 654 with an organic view of society. 655 In the second place, he was an optimist and even an idealist. He believed that all members of the human family are basically good; like Socrates, he believed that “no man is intentionally wicked”. 656 It is through ignorance that people err, and it then is our duty to help them to see the truth. In South Africa, Gandhi’s intention was to remind Smuts that he was a Christian. 657 Once people have been brought to see the truth, they would automatically mend their ways. This is especially true of political relationships. Those who govern sometimes make mistakes and treat their subjects unjustly, while subjecting them to unwarranted violence. What is important when this happens is not that we as subjects suffer, because our physical and material well-being compared with our spiritual values is not important. Those in positions of power, when they err, should also be brought to see the light, the truth. Those who are governed should do this because they should take 652 Gandhi Non-violent resistance 363. 653 In his evidence before the Hunter Committee in respect of the Rowlatt Acts, Gandhi stated that his policy is "an extension of the domestic law on the political field". Id 19. 654 Surprisingly, Gandhian "holism" did not receive the attention it deserves in discussions of his interaction with Smuts. See eg Beukes The holistic Smuts 33, 144, 192, 207. 655 See Parekh Gandhi's political philosophy 110. 656 Gandhi Non-violent resistance 93. 657 Fischer Gandhi 35. the welfare of those who govern to heart. As members of the same family they are, after all, worthy of our concern, even if they err. How, then, should the governed discharge this duty? If the violence of counterviolence, importance is those even who if gained, we because abuse power by subjecting to subdue them, manage we we respond to then confirm to them them to nothing of that they themselves had a right to use violence - we legitimise their way of expressing (or rather impressing) their opinions. A spiral of violence is created and perpetuated, which will eventually lead to a mindless or spiritless world. The only way in which this spiral can be broken is through non-violent resistance to violence. One must absorb aggression instead of returning it. This inevitably involves the voluntary acceptance of suffering, which is the pivot on which Gandhian civil disobedience turned. Gandhi believed in the “eternal law of purification through suffering.” 658 To him innocent suffering by necessity accompanies the emergence of freedom. According to Gandhi, “[c]ivil disobedience is a terrifying synonym for suffering.” 659 Voluntary suffering has the power to convince the opponent and to make oneself worthy of one’s goal. 660 If I suffer openly and willingly at the hands of my adversary, and I do not threaten him with retaliation, he will see the true consequences of his actions and will be cured of his ignorance and change his ways. He will be won over to a higher moral level. As the Bible says, we must do good to the evil-doers. Satyagraha’s coerce, the wrongdoer.” 661 objective is “to convert, not to Gandhi’s philosophy, in a word, was to answer evil with good, coercion with persuasion. The word, “Satyagraha”, used by Gandhi to describe his perception of non-violent, illegal resistance, was created by him by conflating two words from his native language, Gujarati: Satya which means the truth (the equivalent of love) and Agraha, firmness or force. The direct translation of Satyagraha is, therefore, “truth force” or, because truth and love are both attributes of the soul, “soul force”. At the 658 Gandhi Non-violent resistance 112. 659 Id 69. 660 See Chatterjee Gandhi's religious thought 77. 661 Gandhi Non-violent resistance 87. same time, truth, to Gandhi, was God. 662 Putting aside the deeper spiritual implications of this approach (and to use non-Gandhian language), in practice it means that civil disobedience is a form of immanent critique which could bring people to see the light for themselves. Civil disobedience is in this sense a form of education in which one lets the truth speak for itself. But it is a very special form of education: It educates both the person who practises it and the person against whom it dialectical search for the truth with the opponent. is aimed. It is a 663 Marx thought that society - and consciousness - is determined by the material infrastructure. The universe is propelled by conflict. Given these points of departure, his emphasis on the inevitability of violent revolution and the need for change in the material conditions of living before a change of consciousness will occur, is logical. 664 In such a process the end can justify the means. Gandhi, like Hegel, upheld the exact opposite Gandhi’s life premises signified about a the defence driving of the force belief behind that history. eternal and universal morality is the determining factor in the world: “I prophesy that if we disobey the law of the final supremacy of spirit over matter, of liberty and love over brute force, in a few years we shall have Bolshevism rampant in this land.” 665 To him, human beings were essentially spiritual beings. Because both ends and means must be moral, the end can never justify the means. 666 A non-repressive society cannot be obtained through repression. A nonviolent society cannot be forged through violence. 667 662 See Gandhi Satyagraha Conquest of violence 15ff. in South Africa 109ff and Bondurant 663 See also Haksar Civi1 disobedience, threats and offers 3. 664 See infra chap five I BB. 665 Quoted in Fischer Gandhi 88. 666 Both means and ends are part of the same whole. Gandhi found support for this idea in the parable of the tree and the fruit enunciated in the Sermon on the Mount. (Matthew 7.16-20.) See also Gandhi's essay "Means and ends", reprinted in Gandhi Non-violent resistance 9. 667 According to Gandhi, the belief "that there is no connection between the means and the end is a great mistake ... [Such] reasoning is the same as to say that we can get a rose through planting a Gandhi’s thoughts reflected both a pessimism concerning human capabilities to know truth with certainty and an optimism concerning the forces that prevail in the world. To assume the power to inflict violence on others and to kill them, even if they treat us unjustly, reflects an arrogant claim to have a direct insight into the demands of truth, which enables one to commit irrevocable deeds. For Gandhi, man is not capable of knowing the absolute truth and, therefore, not in a position to punish. This does not, however, imply that there is no good or evil. Gandhi believed that truth should be allowed to speak for itself, undistorted by human desire. As appears from the title of his autobiography, he viewed his own life merely as “experiments with truth”. In accordance with the basic premises of liberalism, Gandhi believed that truth, when given the chance, would speak for itself. To openly according and to voluntarily Gandhi, had suffer injustice several without advantages. It retaliating, purifies and strengthens one’s own detachment from the seductions of material wellbeing, and allows one to attune one’s ear to revelations of the truth. Within a group, the willingness to use restraint furthermore fosters the type of discipline which makes that group worthy of freedom. It also makes the opponent powerless, because he has no power over someone who does not fear his weapons. Truly committed Satyagrahi’s cannot be put down by any amount of force. “The soul can remain unconquered and unnconquerable [sic] even when the body is imprisoned.” 668 A campaign of Satyagraha can bring the state to a complete standstill when it becomes clear that the subjects do not fear suffering. The opponent also becomes demoralised, because he will realise that such action cannot come from the weak. Gandhi insisted that non-violence can only be used by the strong. Finally, even if the resistance eventually turns out to have been misguided, no damage was done to the opponent. The non-violent resister occupies the moral high ground, because voluntary acceptance of suffering would normally not be endured for personal gain. Disobedience to the demands of the state with full knowledge that the consequences may be highly unpleasant can only be the result of obedience to a superior moral imperative. The ability to practise civil disobedience against all odds gives shining testimony to the superior force of that moral imperative. It proves the authenticity noxious weed." Gandhi Non-violent resistance 10. 668 Gandhi Non-violent resistance 289. of the demand. Gandhi perceived his Utopia in explicit anarchist terms. To him, “the state represents violence in a concentrated and organised form." He believed that anarchy.” “[t]he ideally non-violent state will be an ordered 669 Non-coercion, therefore, and a willingness to undergo suffering are the decisive factors in Gandhi’s concept of political resistance, which was deeply rooted in his religious world view. To Gandhi, who believed in non-violence as an "article of faith”, Satyagraha is not an intermediary step on the road from legal to violent protest - it is not a prelude to violence but an equally powerful alternative. It is, what has been called, “the moral equivalent of war”. 670 Gandhi’s approach embodies Gandhi’s emphasis on the several problems. voluntary In acceptance of the first place, suffering (which underlies his insistence that Satyagrahi’s should plead guilty when charged, supply missing evidence against themselves and others, ask for maximum sentences, and be model prisoners) will to many reflect an unacceptable preoccupation with martyrdom. There are, after a11, many other ways in which one’s bona fides and opposition to anarchy can be demonstrated. No doubt, such a display of supreme discipline can be particularly effective, and to do so would often not be wrong, but it can hardly be a necessary condition for justified civil disobedience, as Gandhi seemed to insist. The result disregarded, of Gandhi’s what was preoccupation earlier with called, suffering was that non-sacrificial he civil disobedience. He failed to recognise that under certain circumstances it would not be necessary to court arrest, plead guilty, insist on the maximum penalty, etc. On the one hand, an application of Gandhi’s approach can in some cases lead to a situation where too much sacrifice is required of prospective resisters. It was argued earlier that adherence to the form of Gandhian protest in the Defiance Campaign probably had this effect. At the same time, it may also have the effect of prompting legal decision-makers into believing that however much they sympathise with a protester, the ethics of civil disobedience requires of them to impose a harsh punishment. This seems to have been 669 Woodcock Gandhi 64. 670 See Muzumdar Mahatma Gandhi 16. the approach Trial”. The of the thrust magistrate of chapter who sentenced six will be Gandhi that in this the “Great approach is unwarranted. Another problem inherent in Gandhi’s approach is that his insistence on the overreaching importance of morality and moral victories often made him a poor negotiator in respect of material issues. Once a moral battle has been won, he often seemed to think that there was nothing important left to do, and this made him lose opportunities. Gandhi’s boundless optimism about human nature incapable of recognising evil when he saw it. was “misguided” and urged the Jews to 671 often rendered him He stated that Hitler practise Satyagraha against Hitler. Of all the wars in his lifetime, he chose the Second World War to pursue his commitment to non-violence further than ever before. It is not that he misunderstood the conditions under which civil disobedience is effective. He recognised the role played, for example, by a “benevolent background force” and did place all his hope on a change of heart in the opponent. 672 The problem is rather that he placed too much reliance on the inherent ability of good to trump evil. Nevertheless, it should be kept in mind that Gandhi’s belief was in the ultimate preponderance of good over evil, not in the absence of evil. In this context, it is revealing to note that Gandhi, until the end of his life, was not an absolute pacifist. He recognised that at some point violence might be needed. He stated: “I would rather see India freed by violence oppressor.” 673 than enchained like a slave to her foreign Nevertheless, he was willing to go further than almost anyone else in leaving scope for the good by itself to triumph over evil. Even if Gandhi went too far in certain respects, his conduct and example provides a powerful reminder of the importance and power of spiritual values. 671 He stated explicitly: "I am an optimist and have an abiding faith in human nature. The party of violence wi11 give me fair play." Gandhi Non-violent resistance 230. 672 Gandhi stated; "I do not think Hitler and Mussolini are after all so very indifferent to the appeal of world opinion." See Das Bangalore Theological Forum 1985 41 at 53. 673 See Woodcock Gandhi 61. C. CIVIL DISOBEDIENCE IN THE UNITED STATES OF AMERICA The United States originated from a revolution and is primarily committed to individual liberty. At the same time, it is a society with many people of different backgrounds and persuasions. Not surprisingly therefore, the United States has a rich tradition of resistance against government - both legal and illegal, both violent and non-violent. The most outstanding examples of civil disobedience in the United States are the Civil Rights Movement and the anti-Vietnam protests. Nevertheless, although still controversial, civil disobedience has deeper roots in American society. (1) Civil disobedience by native Americans Charles Black gave a fascinating account of a case of non-sacrificial civil disobedience in the early history of the United States, in a setting which illustrates the universality of this strategy of protest. It is worth quoting his account in full. I think of a story of a young Pawnee brave, whose name comes back to me as Peshwataro. In his day the law of the Pawnee commanded that on the day of the summer solstice there take place the sacrifice of the star maiden. A girl was each year captured from a neighboring tribe and bound to a stake. At dawn, the Pawnee braves would ride in a circle about her and shoot their arrows into her. This was not done for sport, but because, like so much that seems cruel in so many societies, it was thought to be a cruelty necessary to the maintenance of the moral and religious order. Many Pawnees, through what processes and influences I cannot say, came to disapprove of it and talked of doing away with it, but it was the law, and conservatism was too strong. Then one summer solstice at dawn this Peshwataro, a young man of high repute within the tribe, broke from the circle before an arrow was shot, rode furiously to the stake, freed the girl of that year, slung her in front of him, and escaped with her. He left her with her people and then rode back, much as Gandhi might have done, to submit himself to his fellows. As it happens, they did nothing. It was time, really, to stop this business; they had only needed an act of such courage to make that clear. 674 (2) Religious civil disobedience The first crimes of conviction among the colonists in the United States took the form of defensive civil disobedience when members of religious minorities refused, under pain of severe persecution, to comply with governmental 674 violations of the principle of religious See Black Texas Law Review 1965 492 at 493. freedom. The Quakers, for example, refused to pay taxes to support the colonial Massachusetts Church. 675 As described elsewhere, this history indirectly influenced Gandhi. 676 Some of the most important constitutional decisions of the United States Supreme Court regarding defensive civil disobedience involve a clash between the convictions of and governmental demands Jehova’s Witnesses very religious people on the one hand on the other. In the “flag salute cases”, attacked public school regulations requiring students to salute the American flag. The Witnesses maintained that this was “forbidden by demands of scripture.” In Minersvi11e School District Gobatis, 677 v the Court upheld Virginia Board of Education v Barnette, Court overruled regulations. In its own decision in 678 the regulations. In West barely three years later, the Gobatis and struck down the 679 Wisconsin v Yoder 680 the respondents, who belonged to the Amish religious group, were fined in the court a quo for their refusal to send their children to high school. The respondents believed that by doing so they would endanger their own salvation and that of their children. On the basis of freedom of speech, their conviction was set aside by the Supreme Court. (3) The Anti-slavery resistance issue of ramifications slavery deeply in the troubled mid-Nineteenth many Americans. Century It led and to its legal widespread conscience-based defiance of the law, mostly in the form of clandestine but non-violent disobedience. The prime cause of conscientious resistance at this time was aimed at the Fugitive Slave Act of 1850, which made it a crime for Northerners not to return slaves who had escaped from the South to their “rightful 675 Weber Civil disobedience In America 35ff. 676 See supra chap three III B (2)(a). 677 310 US 586 (1940). 678 319 US 624 (1943). 679 For a full discussion of these cases, see Harpaz Texas Law Review 1986 817 at 820ff. 680 406 US 205 (1972). owners”. 681 As a result of these events, the idea of conscientious breaking of the law was discussed for the first time on a national level. 682 In the northern parts of the country, public resolutions were passed at meetings of citizens opposed to the law, pledging the defiance of the law. While some equated such behaviour to “treason” and emphasised the need for a “religious reverence for the laws”, 683 others formed the “underground captured. railroad”, 684 which assisted escaped slaves from being 685 Civil disobedience, however, proved inadequate to resolve this issue. Only after the Civil War (1861-1865), the Thirteenth, Fourteenth and Fifteenth Amendments were passed which abolished slavery, guaranteed the former slaves’ citizenship and protected their right to vote. (4) Henry David Thoreau Henry David Thoreau’s famous act of civil disobedience in the 1840's was prompted by the American government’s endorsement and enforcement of slavery, as well as its involvement in the war against Mexico. His refusal to pay taxes as an act of protest landed him in prison for one night, after which the fine imposed was paid on his behalf. 686 In his 1848 essay, later called “On the duty of civil disobedience”, 681 Art IV, s 2 of the United States Constitution provided in principle that escaped slaves should be returned. Provision for the enforcement of this clause was made by an Act of 12 February 1793, Ch 7, 1 Stat 302 (1793). The so-called "Fugitive Slave Act", Ch 60, 9 Stat 462 (1850) (eventually repealed by the Thirteenth Amendment, s 1) made it a criminal offence to knowingly hinder any person from arresting a runaway slave, to rescue a fugitive from slavery or to assist a slave escaping, inter alia by harbouring or concealing such fugitive. All citizens were commanded to "aid and assist in the prompt and efficient execution of this law." For a fuller discussion, see Cover Justice accused 159ff. See also Weber Civil disobedience in America 99ff. 682 683 Weber Civil disobedience in America 95. Ibid. 684 For the legal background of the "underground railroad", Villarruel Southern California Law Review 1987 1429 at 1437ff. 685 686 see Weber Civil disobedience in America 94. For the history of this era, see Alien University of Cincinnatti Law Review 1967 175 at 178ff. Thoreau justified his conduct. 687 He gave a spirited and articulate defence of minimal government, after stating his case for maximum individual liberty in absolute terms. He maintained that “the only obligation which I have a right to assume is to do at any time what I think right.” 688 Thoreau asked: Can there not be a government in which majorities do not virtually decide right and wrong, but conscience? In which majorities decide only those questions to which the rule of expedience is applicable? Must the citizen ever for a moment, or in the least degree, resign his conscience to the legislature? 689 He proceeded: “How does it become a man to behave toward this American government today? I answer, that he cannot without disgrace be associated with it. I cannot for any instant recognise that political organization also.” 690 as my government which is the slave’s government In respect of the invasion of Mexico, Thoreau argued that the need to rebel against the United States government is so much the greater since “the country ... overthrown is not our own, but ours is the invading army.” 691 Thoreau did not explicitly propagate positive civil disobedience, but he interpreted the scope of negative civil disobedience quite widely. He argued that Americans should not only refuse to fight in an unjust war, but that they should also refuse to pay taxes that could be used to support the belligerent effort. Thoreau rejected the use of civil disobedience in every case where one’s opinions differed from that of the government: “I came into this world, not seeking to make it a good place to live in, but to live in it, be it good or bad.” 692 We have to be prepared to live with some injustice. In the present case, however, he argued that he had no option other than civil constitution is ... evil”. 693 disobedience, since the state’s “very Thoreau urged people to use their "whole influence" to counter the majority when it went wrong. “A minority is 687 The essay is reprinted in Thoreau Walden or. Life 1n the woods and On civil disobedience 249. 688 Id 252. 689 Ibid. 690 Id 254. (Original emphasis.) 691 Ibid. 692 Id 259. 693 Ibid. powerless while it conforms to the majority ... but it is irresistible when it clogs by its whole weight.” 694 He wrote that “if a thousand men were not to pay their tax bills” it would bring about a “peaceable revolution”. 695 Thoreau’s semi-anarchist approach generated little support during his lifetime, but it would become highly influential in the next century. He had a direct influence on the leadership of the Civil Rights Movement and the anti-Vietnam protests and had an indirect influence on Gandhi. 696 (5) The Womens’ Rights Movement Activists in the United States defied laws on a number of occasions in pursuit of equality for women. 697 This movement has been active to varying degrees since the first Womens’ Rights Convention at Seneca Falls, New York, in 1846, where the “Declaration of Sentiments” was written and issued. A main tenet of the declaration was the need for women to have the vote before the government could really claim to have the consent of the governed. 698 The issue of womens’ suffrage gave rise to widespread and persistent activism, including acts of civil disobedience. From the outset, the womens’ position was that their right to vote was guaranteed in the Fourteenth and Fifteenth Amendment to the Constitution, even though it was denied by statute. This was the basis upon which Susan B Anthony and fourteen other women registered and voted in Rochester, New York in 1872. 699 In 1875, the Supreme Court held that women were “citizens” of the United States constitution. 700 but were not entitled to vote in terms of the Once this avenue was closed, the women concentrated 694 Id 261. 695 Ibid. 696 See supra chap three III 8 (2)(a). 697 See Weber Civil disobedience in America 179 and Flexner Century of struggle 71ff. See also G Lakey "Technique and ethos in nonviolent action: The woman suffrage case" in Bosmajian Dissent 308 and Alien University of Cincinnatti Law Review 1967 175 at 181ff. 698 This declaration is reprinted in Weber Civil disobedience in America 180. 699 See Weber Civil disobedience in America 184ff. 700 See Minor v Happersett 88 US (21 Wall) 162 (1894). their efforts on getting a new constitutional amendment passed which would ensure women the right to vote. They consequently turned from legality-based to legitimacy-based civil disobedience. The Woman Suffrage Movement reached a peak in 1917, when the White House was picketed for the first time in history. Although the demonstrations as such were not illegal, hundreds of protesters were arrested, tried and imprisoned on arbitrary charges of "obstructing sidewalk traffic”. 701 In 1920, the right of women to vote was recognised when the Nineteenth Amendment was passed. (6) The Civil Rights Movement The Civil Rights Movement finds a forerunner in the stand taken by A Philip Randall, who argued in 1948 for a mass refusal of blacks to be drafted into a segregated army. This achieved an executive order of President Truman prohibiting racial discrimination in the armed forces. In the course of testimony before the Senate Armed Services Committee, Randall denied charges of treasonable conduct on the basis that, as a loyal citizen, he wanted the country to live up to its aspirations as “the moral leader of democracy”. 702 The Civil Rights Movement was aimed at the inferior de facto and de jure position of black people in the United States society in the middle of this century, in spite of the lofty promises of the United States Constitution and especially the Fourteenth and Fifteenth Amendments. To a large extent, the emergence of the Civil Rights Movement and its use of civil disobedience was a consequence of Supreme Court rulings. 703 By 1954, the National Association for the Advancement of Coloured People (“NAACP”) had won 34 of the 38 civil rights cases it had brought to the Supreme Court. 704 The effect of Brown v Board of Education in the 701 Weber Civil disobedience in America 196 and Flexner Century of struggle 294. 702 His testimony is reprinted in Weber Civil disobedience In America 207. On the early history of black resistance in the United States, see Sitkoff The struggle for black equality 3ff; Skolnick The politics of protest 131 and Marable Race, reform and rebellion 1ff. 703 See Sitkoff The struggle for black equality 19. 704 See Barkan Protesters on trial 29. south was, by all accounts, “electric”: “[I]t heightened the morale among southern blacks and civil rights leaders, it increased their hopes for change, occurred later.” and helped lead to the protest campaigns that 705 In view of the constitutional support which black aspirations found from the highest court in the country, it was only natural that their resistance would often assume the form of legality-based civil disobedience. Although the Civil Rights Movement was largely a spontaneous national movement which had many leaders, Martin Luther King and the Southern Christian Leadership Conference (“SCLC”) established themselves as the most prominent in this regard. The following campaigns and events were among the most decisive. (a) The Montgomery Bus Boycott 1955-1956 Unlike the other campaigns of defiance of this century where organization and planning largely preceded defiance, the Civil Rights Movement was triggered by a spontaneous act of resistance. In 1955, in the state of Alabama and in many other southern states, seating in public buses was segregated along racial lines. On 1 December, on a Montgomery bus, a black woman, Rosa Parks, refused to give up her seat - which was designated for blacks - to a white passenger, upon being ordered to do so by the bus driver and later by the police. She was arrested and charged with the violation of a city ordinance and was eventually convicted and sentenced to pay a fine of $10. 706 The situation had the makings of a classical case. A woman identified an obvious disobedience. injustice 707 and engaged in an act of defensive civil The stage was set for a dramatic turn of events when the political attitude of black Americans would turn from defensive to result-oriented civil disobedience. 705 Ibid. 706 For a full and thorough discussion of the legal aspects of the case and the ensuing boycott, see Kennedy The Yale Law Journal 1989 999 and Barkan Protesters on trial 34ff. See also Lomax The Negro revolt 81ff and Sitkoff The struggle for black equality 41ff. 707 She later said that she did not plan to "stage a protest" when she refused to vacate the seat. See Kennedy The Yale Law Journal 1989 999 at 1018 n 113. After the arrest of Rosa Parks, the Womens’ Political Council, a black womens’ civil organization, took the lead in organising a one-day boycott of the buses by blacks. This action was mainly successful and gave rise to the Montgomery Bus Boycott, which lasted for more than a year. The boycott was organised by a new umbrella body, called the Montgomery Improvement Association, over which King was chosen to preside. As with other campaigns, the movement at this early stage was characterised by its conservatism. King emphasised that “[w]e are not asking for an end to segregation.” 708 At this stage he was merely seeking a way to make the prevailing system more acceptable to black people. As the boycott continued, the city authorities invoked a 1921 law for trying King for conspiring “without a just cause or legal excuse” to hinder a lawful business.” 709 Because of its political implications, wide publicity afforded the case national attention. King was convicted and sentenced to a fine of $1 000 with alternative imprisonment. He refused to pay the fine, but it was paid on his behalf. In this particular case only the question whether or not King's conduct came within the scope of the particular statute was considered by the court. The wider constitutional issues were not discussed. The break-through came when the constitutional merits of the Montgomery bus segregation Browder, 710 statutes reached the Supreme Court in Gayle v where it was decided that de jure segregation on the buses violated the Fourteenth Amendment of the Federal Constitution, on the basis inter alia, of the precedent in Brown v Board of Education. The first round of the struggle ended with a victory for the Civil Rights Movement in the highest court of the USA. In future, most of the activities of the Civil Rights Movement would be conducted with the hope of vindication by the Supreme Court in terms of the constitution. The Montgomery boycott and its positive outcome had important consequences, not only for the government but also (and especially) for the Civil Rights Movement. It demonstrated the Movement’s ability and sense of responsibility, and provided a resource to the movement to 708 Id 1026. 709 S v King 98 So 2d 443 (Ala Ct App 1957). 710 352 US 903 (1956). rely on in the difficult times to come. 711 (b) Little Rock 1957 In September 1957, the school board of Little Rock, Arkansas, acceded to a federal court order in the wake of Brown by admitting nine blacks to the Central High School as a first step towards integration. Governor Orval Faubus, however, seeking gubernatorial re-election on a racist ticket, decided to obstruct the order. He had the school surrounded by National Guardsmen and the children were prevented from entering the school. Another order was issued by the Federal District Court in Arkansas. After three weeks, President Eisenhower sent in federal troops to escort the children to school. Eisenhower personally opposed the Brown decision, but he was bound by the Constitution to uphold the laws of the land and would have been embarrassed by international publicity if he were to disregard this obligation. 712 (c) The lunch-counter sit-ins 1960 A spontaneous movement of civil disobedience developed in 1960 in 113 southern towns when privately initiated segregation in departmental stores was challenged by black people. The protesters sat at lunch counters reserved for whites. They were refused service but remained in their seats until normal closing time, and returned to the counters on succeeding days. 713 These sit-ins started in Greensboro, North Carolina, and at least 70 000 people workshops on black and white non-violence, - based eventually to some participated. extent on Special Gandhi’s teachings, prepared those participating not to respond aggressively to brutal attacks. Presidential candidate John F Kennedy gave his support to this type of protest. The decision to have segregated counters rested with the proprietor. This meant that the initial act of sitting down at the counter did not 711 See Kennedy The Yale Law Journal 1989 999 at 1066. 712 See, in general, Freyer The Little Rock crisis and Sitkoff The struggle for black equality 29ff. 713 See Barkan Protesters on trial 37; Lomax The Negro revolt 81ff; Sitkoff The struggle for black equality 69ff and Marable Race, reform and rebellion 66ff. constitute a violation of any segregation laws. The real question, however, was whether the refusal to leave once one had been denied service and asked to leave constituted trespass. To this question there was, and still is, no clear legal answer. 714 However, the campaign was highly successful in disrupting services and reducing profits - and eventually in moving proprietors to desegregate their facilities. The cost was high, however, in terms of humiliation and abuse - physical and otherwise which those participating had to endure. (d) The freedom rides 1961 At the end of 1960, American blacks, dissatisfied with the gains in their struggle against institutionalised racism, turned to more confrontational tactics. At the end of the year, the Supreme Court extended an earlier prohibition on segregation on vehicles engaged in interstate travel to apply to all terminal accommodations. 715 The decision was taken to test the practical application of this principle in the South. 716 The first “freedom ride” left Washington DC in May 1961 for New Orleans, Louisiana, with the purpose of challenging segregation laws and practices along the way. The passengers were attacked along the way by whites opposed to desegregation. In Ariston, Alabama the windows of the bus were smashed, tires slashed and passengers were beaten. The bus was eventually fire-bombed. The occupants of a second bus were also beaten in Ariston. In spite of the most brutal attacks by mobs on those participating, the local police refused to intervene. These events became headline news all over the world. Editorials in Africa and Asia commented that the United States government’s compromising with racial discrimination and violence, would make it impossible for the country “to sell to the outside world, especially the non-white world, that she stands for equality of all men.” 717 The Kennedy administration considered its international 714 reputation However, all the convictions were set aside on appeal. See eg Garner v Louisiana 368 US 167 (1961). For a discussion, see H Kalven "Trespass and the First Amendment" in Bosmajian Dissent 95. See also Black Texas Law Review 1965 492 at 497. The matter was rendered moot by the Civil Rights Act of 1964. 715 Bovnton v Virginia 364 US 454 (1960). 716 See Lomax The Negro revolt 132ff. 717 See Sitkoff The struggle for black equality 105. threatened. Attorney-General Robert Kennedy demanded protection for the buses from Alabama’s governor. A new group of passengers set out under police protection for Montgomery. They were nevertheless mobbed, and Kennedy’s emissary was assaulted. Six hundred federal marshals were sent in to preserve the peace. Passengers protected by the national guard now took a bus to Jacksonville, Mississippi, where many were arrested for breaking segregation laws. They went to prison instead of paying fines. By the end of the summer, more than 1 000 people had participated in the freedom rides. Victory came when the federal government, convinced that an end to the arrests and demonstrations was “vital to [its] conduct of international affairs”, issued facilities. (e) rules prohibiting discrimination in interstate 718 Birmingham 1963 In Albany, Georgia, over 1 200 protesters were arrested in 1961 and 1962 for sit-ins, demonstrations, marches etc. Those arrested more than once included Martin Luther King. The anti-segregation activities in Albany, however, were not successful for a variety of reasons. Those reasons included the state’s effective use of the criminal justice system, both on local and eventually federal level, and the sophistication of the local police under Laurie Pritchett, which also adopted a “non-violent” strategy against protesters. 719 the The protesters were discouraged and their morale was low. In a desperate move, King and others now prepared what they called “Project C” (“C” for confrontation) to tackle the most segregated city in the United States, Birmingham, Alabama. They issued a manifesto setting out Birmingham, government their to to grievances. draw the the Thereafter attention looming showdown. of they the Then staged media they and started sit-ins the with in federal public demonstrations. A local court injunction prohibited civil rights demonstrations, and thousands of protesters were arrested by the police under “Bull” Connor. King announced his intention to participate in a demonstration. 718 Id 110. 719 Barkan Protesters on trial 69. On Good Friday he was arrested. While in prison in April 1963, King wrote his “Letter from Birmingham City Jail”, which will be discussed presently. Widespread demonstrations occurred. The televised images that shook the country and the Federal Government was that of the use of dogs, fire hoses (“that stripped the bark of trees”) and clubs against unarmed protesters, many of whom were children. An accord was reached between the leadership of the SCLC and white businessmen in Birmingham. Demonstrations would stop and the city would be desegregated. This was rejected, however, by segregationist and white supremacist groups, such as the Ku Klux Klan, who attacked blacks at random. The house of King’s brother was dynamited. The segregation signs did not disappear. After fierce clashes all over the country, which involved the use of violence by vigilante groups on both sides. King’s leadership helped restore order. 720 The victory of the demonstrations was certain when the Supreme Court on 20 May ruled that Birmingham’s ordinances upholding segregation were unconstitutional and overturned the convictions of those arrested under those laws. 721 The Federal Government also made its commitment clear in respect of what later would be enacted as the 1964 Civil Rights Act. Before that could materialise, however, demonstrations in other communities followed in the wake of the success in Birmingham - inter alia in Danville, Virginia 722 and Selma, Alabama. 723 The same pattern repeated itself. In Danville, Pritchett’s “non-violent” strategy was followed by the authorities, with disastrous consequences for the movement. In Selma, the police followed a strong armed policy, which gave the movement the press coverage and legitimacy it sought. 724 720 See Barkan Protesters on trial 69 and Sitkoff The struggle for black equality 137. 721 See Cox v Louisiana 379 US 536 (1965) and Cox v Louisiana 379 US 559 (1965). The appellants in these cases held a brief sit-in in a library which was racially segregated. They were convicted in the court a quo of a breach of the peace. In a 5-4 decision, the court held that, because the segregation was unconstitutional, the appellants had a "right to protest" against it. 722 See Barkan Protesters on trial 74. 723 Id 79. 724 On the Selma march, see Marshall Virginia Law Review 1965 785 (f) The March on Washington 1963 August 1963 saw the tumultuous “March on Washington”, with a quarter of a million people peacefully and lawfully assembling in Washington DC. Here King delivered his now famous “I have a dream” speech, in which he sketched his vision of a non-racial America. 725 To many white Americans the image of black resistance turned from one of dark anger, to one of accessible eloquence. It was a major victory for non-violent action. (g) The Mississippi Summer Project 1964 Perhaps the clearest demonstration of the use made during the Civil Rights Movement of the indirect strategy of appealing to the “benevolent background force” of the Federal Government and broader electorate, came from the so-called “Mississippi Summer Project” in 1964. Lawyers and law students from the North came to Mississippi to assist in civil rights cases. They were told during their training: “You just can’t win civil rights cases in the local and state courts in the South; your important job will be to help local council build a solid foundation Supreme Court.” (h) for an eventual and successful appeal to the US 726 The Civil Rights Act 1964 The ideals of what was by now called the Civil Rights Revolution were given official sanction in 1964 when the Civil Rights Act 727 was passed by Congress against the vote of most of its Southern members. The Act was designed to eliminate “the last vestiges” of discrimination. The anti-discriminatory provisions of the 1964 Act were both comprehensive and enforceable. Amongst other things, it guaranteed everyone’s equal access to all publicly owned and operated facilities. 728 The Civil Rights Act also paved the way for later legislation such as at 787. 725 See King A testament of hope 217 and Sitkoff The struggle for black equality 160ff. 726 Barkan Protesters on trial 84. 727 Pub L no 88-352, 78 Stat 241 (codified as amended in scattered sections of 42 USC s 1971 (1982)). For a discussion, see Graham The civi1 rights era 125ff. 728 Title II, upheld in Heart of Atlanta Hotel v United States 379 US 241 (1964). the Voting Rights Act of 1965, 729 which enfranchised the mass of Southern Blacks (and, ironically, even greater numbers of whites). The use of civil disobedience by black Americans would not cease, but a major battle was won. 730 No doubt, the most influential figure in this course of events was King. His approach will now be considered. (i) As Martin Luther King mentioned earlier, imprisoned for Birmingham in his 1963, Martin Luther part in wrote his the King, Jr civil famous (1929 rights “Letter - 1968), while demonstrations from Birmingham in City Jail”. The letter was a response to fellow (white) ministers who called the civil disobedience campaign “unwise and untimely”, because they were of the opinion that it would incite civil disturbances. 731 The letter contained a comprehensive exposition of his views on civil disobedience. In the letter King defended his presence and activities in Birmingham (not his home-town), on the basis that “whatever affects one directly affects all indirectly.” 732 He stated that the protesters had “no other alternative” than civil disobedience. 733 Especially “Negroes” were the victims of a “broken promise”, 734 in Birmingham, since the leaders of the economic community had promised to remove humiliating racial signs from their stores but had declined to do so. The campaign was started only after extensive workshops on the discipline of non- violence. Civil disobedience was justified by King, with reference to Socrates, on the basis that it generated the creative tension needed to bring about social reform. “The purpose of the direct action is to create a situation so crisis packed, that it will inevitably open the door to 729 Pub L no 89-110, 79 Stat 437 (codified as amended at 42 USC s 1973 (1982)). Its challenged provisions were upheld in South Carolina v Katzenbach 383 US 301 (1966). 730 For an overview of the political history of black Americans after 1964, see Marable Race, reform and rebellion 95ff. 731 The letter is reprinted in King A testament of hope 289. 732 Id 290. 733 Ibid. 734 Ibid negotiation”, 735 which is the real goal. Confrontation, however, is necessary because “[w]e know through painful experience that freedom is never voluntarily given by the oppressors; it must be demanded by the oppressed.” 736 King recognised the ambiguity of demanding obedience to some aspects of the law (such as the Brown decision) but disobeying others: One may well ask, “How can you advocate breaking some laws and obeying others?” The answer is found in the fact that there are two types of laws: there are just and there are unjust laws. I would agree with St Augustine that “an unjust law is no law at all”. 737 The question is, however, “what is the difference between the two? How does one determine when a law is just or unjust?” 738 “An unjust law is a code that a majority inflicts on a minority that is not binding on itself. This is difference made legal.” 739 King stated that “an unjust law is a code inflicted upon a minority which that minority had no part in enacting or creating because they did not have the unhampered right to vote.” 740 King was very specific as to the attitude with which civil disobedience should be practised: In no sense do I advocate evading or defying the law as the rabid segregationist would do. This would lead to anarchy. One who breaks an unjust law must do so openly, lovingly ... and with a willingness to accept the penalty. I submit that an individual who breaks a law that conscience tells him -is unjust, and willingly accepts the penalty by staying in jail to rouse the conscience of the community over its injustice, is in reality expressing the very highest respect for law. 741 King’s policy of non-violent resistance had its roots in Christianity and in his admiration of Gandhi. According to King, “Christ furnished 735 Id 292. 736 Ibid. 737 Id 293. (Original emphasis.) 738 Ibid. 739 Id 294. 740 Ibid. 741 Ibid. (Original emphasis.) the spirit and motivation, while Gandhi furnished the method.” 742 King explicitly modelled his campaign on those of Gandhi.” 743 The strategy that was used was to defy segregation laws peacefully. This defiance and the brutality that followed was then portrayed by the media to the nation and to the world. 744 This provided the moral context in which the relevant cases were eventually argued and decided. King clearly saw the benefits that non-violent resistance held for those who practise it: “The nonviolent approach does not immediately change the heart of the oppressor. It first does something to the hearts and souls of those committed to it. It gives them new selfrespect; it calls up resources of strength and courage that they did not know they had.” 745 King used civil disobedience as an instrument of immanent critique of his opponent. “Negroes”, King argued, “by their direct action are exposing the contradiction [between federal and non-federal law].” 746 What King was after, was for blacks to “acquire [their] citizenship to the fullness of its meaning.” 747 He was not asking for anything which the government had not promised. He simply wanted, as he often put it, to redeem the soul of America. Only in the time immediately before his death did King promote more radical action than legality-based civil disobedience. His aims, for that period, were not only to secure the rights enumerated in the Constitution, but to bring about the advancement of blacks generally; 742 Id 17, 88. 743 See Id 7, 16, 18, 26, 32-34, 36, 103, 149, 164, 447, 485, 486, 583. For an account of King's first exposure to Gandhian ideas, see Watley Roots of resistance 48ff. 744 See Barkan Protesters on trial 34. 745 King The words of Martin Luther King 79. 746 Webber Civil disobedience in America 221. King said in the speech "I've been to the mountain top", reprinted in King The words of Martin Luther King 93 at 93: "If I lived in China or even Russia, or any totalitarian country, maybe I could understand the denial of certain basic First Amendment privileges, because they hadn't committed themselves to that over there. But somewhere I read of the freedom of assembly. Somewhere I read of the freedom of speech. Somewhere I read of the freedom of the press. Somewhere I read that the greatness of America is the right to protest for right." 747 Quoted by Kennedy The Yale Law Journal 1989 999 at 1021. for the first time he also propagated the defiance of a federal court order. King propagated a campaign whereby an initial group of 3 000 people would “camp out” in the offices of high officials as long as it is necessary to fight the war on poverty and to obtain a new economic deal for the poor. 748 King now propagated the wide use of a highly coercive, although not a violent, strategy whereby an extra-legal attempt would be made to secure second generation rights for black Americans. Before this campaign was embarked upon, however, King was assassinated. (7) The anti-Vietnam protests of the 1960’s In the early 1960’s the United States began drifting into a war in South East Asia, which would bring the deepest division in the American nation since the Civil War. 749 In the resolution of the domestic conflict, civil disobedience would again play a major role. For various reasons, which need not be canvassed here, America provided economic and government National in non-combat its military conflict Liberation Front, with assistance the backed to the guerrillas by the South-Vietnamese of the communist Viet-Cong. American involvement gradually increased over the years. Approximately 16 000 American troops were stationed in Vietnam in 1964. In August 1964, a United States destroyer was attacked in the Gulf of Tonkin by North Vietnamese patrol boats, while the destroyer was (at least according to first reports) in international waters. The Gulf of Tonkin resolution pledged full congressional support for any action by President Vietnam. Johnson in defence of the United States troops in South 750 Shortly after passage of the resolution, about 60 people demonstrated in midtown Manhattan against the War. Seventeen were arrested. A week 748 See "The trumpet of conscience", reprinted in King A testament of hope 651. 749 A number of useful articles and documents relating to the political and military history of the Vietnam War are reprinted in Raskin & Fall The Viet-nam reader. Higglns Vietnam 97ff deals with the domestic implications of the War. The Issue of free speech and protest against the War is dealt with by Schechter Contemporary constitutional issues 38ff. 750 The resolution was passed in the House of Representatives by 416 to 0 votes and 1n the Senate by 88 to 2 votes. later, 40 more demonstrators were arrested at a second protest meeting. It was the beginning of another major campaign of civil disobedience. In 1965, President Johnson dramatically increased the American war effort in Vietnam, which in turn resulted in a drastic escalation in draft calls. Letters were addressed to newspapers and politicians and other legal channels were followed by those opposed to the War. A group, called the “Women Strike for Peace”, held a large vigil outside the United Nations, precipitating further arrests. “Teach-ins” and rallies were held at colleges and universities across the country. A group of 3 000 marchers were led to a rally in front of the United Nations headquarters by child-care expert, Or Benjamin Spock. Over 15 000 people picketed the White House. In July 1965, it was announced that the commitment of American troops in Vietnam, who were now engaged in defensive and offensive combat, would be raised to 125 000, and monthly draft calls would be doubled from the June rate of 17 000 to 35 000. By this time it was clear that the War was becoming more and more unpopular at home. Draft centres were picketed, attempts were made to stop trains carrying soldiers to embarkation points, and at least five young men publicly burnt their draft cards. An amendment 751 to the Universal Military Training and Service Act, 752 passed in the same year, rendered the mutilation or destruction of a draft card a felony, punishable by up to five years’ imprisonment and a fine of up to $10 000. The increased severity of the government’s approach, both in Vietnam and at home, was challenged by those questioning the justification of the War. Especially the draft-card-burning amendment was bound to be challenged on the ground legitimate expression of that this symbolic kind speech, of action protected constituted by the a First Amendment. A young pacifist by the name of David Miller was the first to be arrested and eventually convicted for publicly burning his draft card in New York City in October 1965. His argument that such action was protected as an expression of free speech was rejected by the Court of 751 111 Cong Rec 19669 (1965). 752 79 Stat 586 (1965). Appeals for the Second Circuit. 753 A number of people, however, followed his example, with the same result. 754 Nationwide demonstrations were held. On Thanksgiving Day, 20 000 opponents of the War marched on Washington. Similar acts of protest continued through 1966. By the end of 1966, 16 people had been convicted under the 1965 amendment, and the constitutionality of the law had been upheld in a number of appeals. The Supreme Court denied certiorari case. 755 in Miller’s It was clear that the courts were more reluctant to deal with a foreign policy issue such as the Vietnam War than with a domestic issue as was the case during the Civil Rights Movement. What was at stake now were not state and local laws that clashed with those of the Federal Government, but the actions of the Federal Government itself in its international relations. Through a legal quirk, however, the Supreme Court eventually had to rule on the issue. A pacifist by the name of David O’Brien had burnt his draft card in public. On trial he admitted that his intention was to urge other people to do the same and to refuse to “co-operate with murder”. 756 His appeal against his conviction by a lower court was heard by the First Circuit, which ruled that the ritual of burning a draft card was in fact a form of symbolic speech which was protected by the First Amendment. Nevertheless, his conviction was sustained on other grounds. Both O’Brien and the government decided to appeal. The Supreme Court was now forced to hear the case and bring clarity in the matter. It ruled (7 to 1) that the draft card amendment law did not violate free speech and was constitutional. 757 A body of jurisprudence also developed in connection with refusing to serve in the armed forces for reasons of conscience or encouraging 753 This view was upheld by the Court of Appeal for the Circuit. See Schechter Contemporary constitutional Issues 50. 754 Id 49. 755 386 US 911 (1967). 756 O'Brien v United States 376 F 2d 538 (1967). 757 Eight United States v O'Brien 391 US 367 (1968). For a discussion of this case, see J E Leahy "'Flamboyant protest', the First Amendment, and the Boston Tea Party" 1n Bosmajian Dissent 47 at 58. The case is discussed in more detail infra chap six IV B (1). others to do the same. This is discussed elsewhere. 758 Suffice it to say that individuals who engaged in conscientious objection were often treated with exceptional leniency. In 1970, resistance against the War was jolted by the invasion and virtual devastation of Cambodia by the United States. Demonstrations occurred on many campuses throughout the country. The uproar increased when Ohio National Guardsmen shot and killed four students during protests at Kent State University. In the Anti-Vietnam Campaign, less stress was placed on non-violence and non-coercion, compared to the Civil Rights Movement. In a number of cases, low-level violence was indeed used to propagate the anti-war cause, and the actions of people such as the “Cantonsville Nine”, who poured blood over draft records, received considerable publicity. 759 At the same time, there was a massive increase in the level of legal political protest, manifested in mass demonstrations, peaceful vigils, protest letters, songs, speeches and so forth. Towards the end of the 1960’s it was clear that politicians, in order to secure their own political survival, could not support the War. In the end it was public opinion, mobilized by a variety of factors that included civil disobedience, which drove Lyndon Johnson from office and seriously limited Richard Nixon’s options. 760 In 1973, the United States signed an agreement to end the War. Nixon called it “peace with honour”; many saw it as disgraceful defeat. In the course of events, civil disobedience and conscientious objection played a mayor role. It is estimated that the number of draft dodgers and deserters ranged up to 100 000. More than 10 000 stayed abroad after the War ended and Nixon refused to grant them amnesty. 761 The legal implications of a number of more sporadic incidents of individual civil disobedience in the United States will be discussed later. 762 758 Infra chap six IV B (2). 759 This case is discussed by Barkan Protesters on trial and Weber Civil disobedience In America 275. 760 See Schechter Contemporary constitutional Issues 37ff. 761 See Link et al The American people 990. 762 See infra chap six IV B. D. SOME OTHER INSTANCES OF MASS, RESULT-ORIENTED CIVIL DISOBEDIENCE The above historical survey might have created the impression that mass civil disobedience is inevitably successful and used in pursuit of laudable aims. The focus was mainly on cases where civil disobedience eventually succeeded in, or contributed towards, bringing about the desired changes in the behaviour of the adversary. We have also concentrated on instances of civil disobedience where most people today would agree that the objectives pursued were commendable (even if it is still controversial whether the use of civil disobedience was justified). There are, however, many instances where civil disobedience did not succeed, as well as cases where the goals pursued were commonly regarded as unacceptable or at least as highly controversial. In order to present a more balanced picture, a number of these examples will now briefly be mentioned. Earlier, reference was made to the standard example of a case where civil disobedience in all probability would not have succeeded, namely that of Nazi Germany. Indeed, very limited use was made of civil disobedience in this case, where a ruthless and independent opponent had to be confronted. 763 Einstein, for example, who was known for his pacifist convictions after the First World War, changed his mind when the Third rendering Reich was military civilization”. established. service In was 1933, he necessary wrote pacifists “to save that European 764 Perhaps the clearest recent example of a situation not amenable to civil disobedience comes from the People’s Republic of China. Since May 1989, protesters - mostly students from Peking University - staged peaceful pro-democracy demonstrations in Tiananmen Square in the centre of Beijing, where an illegal sit-in was held in which thousands of people participated. Amongst other things, a replica of the American Statue of Liberty was erected. Clearly the prime target of the protesters was the outside world. In spite of the imposition of martial 763 See Foot Resistance 44, 90, 275, 282 and Romoser Social Research 1964 73. There were, however, some notable examples of non-violent resistance 1n Denmark and Norway. 764 Nathan & Norden Einstein on peace 172. law, the demonstrations continued. 765 After several threats to the demonstrators from the authorities (and apparently after the police had refused to quash the demonstrations), the government called in the military, on the night of 3 to 4 June, to clear the square. At least a thousand civilians were killed and thousands more were injured when the troops fired indiscriminately into the crowds and overran bicycles with tanks. The crushing of the demonstrations was officially justified as an act of self-defence on the part of the troops who were allegedly confronted by a "shocking counter-revolutionary rebellion”. 766 Without going into any details, it seems fair to say that the Chinese government was too ruthless to be moved by the moral appeal of such demonstrations, and too independent and too strong to be moved by outside pressure. A number of cases where the threat of civil disobedience was used to pursue objectives which can at least be described as controversial have been alluded to. Reference was made to Or Malan’s threat to defy a ban on meetings in support of the Ossewabrandwag, the support of Bill O’Connor and Dr Andries Treurnicht of civil disobedience as a method of resisting political reform in their countries, as well as the recent siege of Pretoria by farmers who blocked the major roads in the city. It s perhaps revealing, however, that civil disobedience was actually used (as opposed to merely threatened) in few cases only, in pursuit of such causes. That is so presumably because the people involved realised the vulnerability of their position in the moral sense. In practice, civil disobedience tends to be employed in pursuit of objectives that are widely regarded as morally sound, although there is no principled reason why it cannot be used in pursuit of obnoxious goals. Arguably, the most controversial but at the same time the most widespread use to which civil disobedience was put in recent years has been the development expression and of deployment protest of against nuclear nuclear weapons. The power and development the of nuclear facilities - be they peaceful or military - does not place direct legal duties on anyone. Consequently, protests against it have 765 See the report of Amnesty International Death in Beijing Oct 1989 5ff. 766 Id 7ff. traditionally taken the form of indirect civil disobedience, in the sense that crimes such as trespassing were committed to express protest against the government’s nuclear policy. Perhaps because the of civil disobedience has also to some extent worn off novelty in other campaigns, anti-nuclear protests have thus typically take the form of entering the premises of the nuclear facilities, blocking the entrances, people chaining themselves to the premises, massive – often violent – demonstrations and ships into areas where nuclear tests were to be conducted. 767 Closely akin resistance, to aimed anti-nuclear at drawing protest attention are to pro-environment the destruction acts of of the planet. Although certain groups advocating this cause have acted in a radical and highly coercive manner, 768 others chose the road of civil disobedience. 769 Having completed the overview of the historic development of civil disobedience, the way in which this form of protest is seen under the South African positive law will now be considered. 767 See Weber Civil disobedience in America and Dworkin A matter of principle 104ff. 768 See the discussion of "ecosabotage" and "monkey wrenching" in Martin Environmental Ethics 1990 291 at 292ff. 769 On the activities of the "Greens" in Germany, see Papadakis The Green Movement in West Germany in general, and 67, 83 in particular. CHAPTER FOUR: CIVIL DISOBEDIENCE UNDER THE SOUTH AFRICAN POSITIVE LAW Over the years, politics and law in South Africa have developed a close relationship. It is not surprising, therefore, that civil disobedience, as a form of illegal political protest, on a number of occasions has attracted the attention of the legislature and the courts. Although there are some direct references to civil disobedience in South African law, the full impact of the law on civil disobedience can only be appreciated in the wider context of crimes of protest. As indicated earlier, civil disobedience is “illegal” in the sense that it provokes the coercive powers of the state. In a society where the rule of law is not consistently observed, as in South Africa, not only the provisions of the criminal law, but also the prerogative powers of the executive, should be considered in order to establish what the official powers of the state embrace in this regard. In what follows, the most important implications of the criminal law and the powers of the executive relating to crimes of protest in general, and acts of civil disobedience in particular, will be analysed. Thereafter, the effect of having committed a crime of protest on the perpetrator’s ability to practise law will be considered. The chapter will conclude with a discussion of the law relating to conscientious objection to military service. 1 I. IMPLICATIONS OF THE CRIMINAL LAW FOR CIVIL DISOBEDIENCE Civil disobedience in most instances involves a transgression of the norms of criminal law, and it is consequently the criminal law that has the most direct implications for this form of protest. 2 These 1 The decision in Deneys Reitz v South African Commercial. Catering and Allied Workers Union S. others 1991 2 SA 685 (W) does not fit into the above framework. In this case a trade union accepted a "programme of action" in terms of which the offices of a firm of attorneys, considered to be right-wing, would have been picketed. The Court set aside the decision. It held that the question whether someone has the "right to picket" must be determined with reference to the norms prevailing in a democratic society (at 691) and the rights of others (at 694). The envisaged picketing would have constituted undesirable coercion of the right to free activity of the firm of attorneys. 2 As indicated earlier, civil disobedience does not necessarily involve the commission of a crime. See supra chap two I A. implications manifest themselves on three levels. In the first place, civil disobedience may entail, what will be called, the “primary offence” - that is, the offence or illegal action through the commission of which the protest is expressed. In the second place, there are legal provisions designed to provide for special treatment of persons having committed crimes of protest, including acts of civil disobedience. These provisions by and large relate to the sentences that can be imposed for the commission of the primary offence, but, as will be demonstrated, it is also possible that commission of the primary offence could render the perpetrator liable to be charged with additional - and often more serious - offences. In the third place, there is a body of laws aimed at counter-acting the encouragement or assisting of other persons in commiting crimes of protest. Insofar as these secondary and tertiary provisions serve to increase the legal incentives for people not to practise or each civil disobedience (compared to those used in cases where a political motive was absent), they may be called “booster provisions”. Insofar as they serve to mitigate the gal sanctions imposed for acts of civil disobedience, they may be called “dampening provisions”. These different aspects of the criminal law will next be considered. A. THE “PRIMARY OFFENCE” There is a wide variety of possible transgressions that could constitute the primary offence. In principle, almost any fence of which dolus is an element can qualify as an act of civil disobedience. In practice these offences range from trespass or transgressions of the remaining vestiges of the apartheid laws, to breaches of security legislation. Many of these laws are in themselves not objectionable, but could be violated through acts of indirect civil disobedience with tent to express opposition to other aspects of the social and political life. It will not serve any purpose to discuss these laws here in any detail, except insofar as the particular law is specifically designed to curb the public expression of protest, for instance, where public demonstrations in certain places are prohibited. The Gathering and Demonstrations Act 52 of 1973 prohibits demonstrations in a defined area “by one or more persons for against any person, cause, action or failure to take action” in an area in Cape Town, 3 including the site of the uses of Parliament. 4 The Demonstrations in or near Court Buildings Prohibition Act 71 of 1982 likewise prohibits demonstrations "by one or more persons for or against any person, cause, action or failure to take action, and which is connected with or coincides with any court proceedings or the proceedings at any inquest” in any court building, or in the open air within a radius of 500m from such building. 5 Contraventions of both Acts constitute crimes. Demonstrations in these areas almost inevitably constitute acts of civil disobedience. B. SECONDARY IMPLICATIONS OF THE CRIMINAL LAW Special legal provisions that apply to crimes of protest and which also affect acts of civil disobedience, include those which apply to sentencing for political crimes. At one time the commission of a crime of protest in itself constituted a substantive or independent offence. (1) One Sentences imposed for crimes of protest element of vulnerability civil and disobedience defiance. Civil is openness, disobedients which implies establish their both bona fides in this way; on the other hand, it has discouraged many from engaging in civil disobedience. Both the legislature and the Courts have in the past dealt with the issue of the proper sentence to be imposed for crimes of protest. (a) Statutory provisions for increased penalties The Criminal Law Amendment Act 8 of 1953 broke the back of the Defiance Campaign of imposition 1952, of inter drastic alia by penalties providing for changes in the law or its application in offences 6 section committed 1 for to the secure - that is for acts of civil disobedience and other crimes of protest. Penalties which could be imposed included a fine of up to £300, 7 imprisonment for a period not exceeding three years, 8 and a whipping not exceeding ten strokes. 9 3 Section 2(1). 4 See the Schedule to the Act. 5 Section 1(a). 6 See R v Segale & others 1960 1 SA 721 (A). 7 Section 1(a). 8 Section 1(b). This provision has now been incorporated into the Internal Security Act 74 of 1982, which provides in section 58 that any person convicted of an offence which is proved to have been committed by way of protest against any law or in support of any campaign against any law or in support of any campaign for the repeal or modification of any law or for the variation or limitation of the application or administration of any law shall be liable to a fine of up to R3 000 and imprisonment not exceeding three years. Whipping is no longer a competent punishment for the offence under consideration. These enactments did commentators maintain; heavy penalties for not 10 create a new substantive offence as some instead it made provision for the imposition of any offence, 11 however insignificant, if that offence was committed as a sign of protest. Section 58 serves to make even the mildest form of civil disobedience attractive to only those persons who are willing to risk martyrdom. It should be noted, however, that only protests against a law or its application are affected - which means that protests against extralegal matters, such as the high level of violence in the country and executive dirty tricks, would not be covered. Arguably, protests against proposed laws or draft bills are also not covered. On a more technical level, it should be noted that the provisions of section 58 only apply when the commission of the primary offence was the means whereby the protest was being expressed. It does not apply when the offence was merely incidental to the expression of protest. In S v Peake and another 12 the accused was convicted of the statutory crime of defacing post office property, in that he fixed certain posters on a telephone booth. Exactly what kind of posters they were, is not clear from the record, but apparently they advertised a campaign expressing political dissent. The Court held that the accused did not intend to 9 Section 2(c). 10 See eg Dugard Human rights and the South African legal order 175. 11 Including, according to R v Sesidi 8, others 1953 4 SA 634 (GW), the inchoate crime of Incitement to commit acts of civil disobedience, in spite of the special provisions made in this regard in s 2 of Act 8 of 1953 (now replaced by s 59 of Act 74 of 1982). See supra chap four I C (1)(b). 12 1962 3 SA 572 (0. The case dealt with the similarly worded s 1 of Act 8 of 1953. express protest property. by Commission advertisement of committing of the the the crime crime was campaign of defacing "purely and post incidental” "not a factor office to in his the 13 protest". Consequently, the increased penalties clause did not apply. What is required for that provision to come into operation, is that the accused had do1us directus to use the unlawfulness of his actions to express protest. That, of course, is the vintage mark of civil disobedience. The burden on the state in criminal proceedings to establish the fact that an offence was committed by way of protest and hence that section 58 applies, was considerably eased by a statutory presumption. Section 69(8) of the 1982 Act 14 provides that where it is alleged that a crime was committed by way of protest, and it is proved that the offence was committed in the company of two or more other persons who were subjected to similar charges, it is presumed, unless the contrary is proved, that the offence was indeed committed by way of protest. The effect of this statutory provision is that the number of people involved can supply the grounds needed for a court to find that a crime was committed in order to express protest. 15 The state is also assisted in another way. As is evident from the historical section, acts of civil disobedience are often designed to convey the message of dissent in a dramatic way, for instance through personal sacrifice or martyrdom. To this end, those convicted of having committed crimes in a campaign of civil disobedience often refused to pay any fines imposed, and instead preferred to be imprisoned. A different reason why people opted for prison sentences was to fill the jails with the aim of frustrating the administration of justice and bringing the entire system into disrepute. In order to counteract such objectives, section 61 of the 1982 Act 16 provides for a procedure whereby, if an offender does not pay a fine imposed in terms of section 58 17 of that Act, the amount of the fine can be levied by attachment and sale of the property of the offender. 13 At 573. 14 Preceded by s 4 of the Criminal Law Amendment Act 8 of 1953. 15 See R v Pungula 8, others 1960 2 SA 760 (N) at 766. 16 Preceded by s 6 of Act 8 of 1953. 17 Or in terms of ss 59 and 60 of the same Act. Given the apartheid government’s point of departure, the legislative bias of the South African law in respect of sentences for crimes of protest is not surprising. 18 Both the legislature and the executive in white dominated South Africa for many years had a built-in tendency (given their constituency) to sacrifice freedom of expression in favour of what it perceives to be the demands of law and order. The question arises, sentence however, in those as to the cases approach where they of were the courts in respect bound by legislative not of provisions. (b) The sentencing policy of the courts Only one case could be traced in the South African Law Reports where the Court specifically addressed the issue of the appropriate sentence for acts of civil disobedience. 19 Since no general conclusions about the policy of courts in respect of civil disobedience can be drawn from a single case, one should first consider the approach of courts in cases that involved the wider category of political crimes. After that, the more specific issue of civil disobedience, and the case referred to, win be discussed. It is fairly generally accepted that the fact that a particular crime was inspired by conviction, as opposed to considerations of personal gain or revenge, should in most cases for the purpose of sentencing be regarded as an extenuating circumstance. 20 The common law authority most often relied upon in respect of politically inspired crimes is Van der Linden, who remarked with reference to the crime of sedition (“oproer”): Dewiji intusschen de grond van deeze misdaad dikwerf gelegen is in verschillende begrippen omtrent de regeling van het 18 In the old Rhodesia there were also statutory provisions for minimum penalties where certain crimes were committed with a political motive. These provisions are discussed in R v Sibanda & others 1965 4 SA 241 (SR, AD); R v Mbowo & others 1966 2 SA 182 (R) and R v Ncube & another 1966 4 SA 232 (RAD). 19 For an exposition of the approach followed by some of the magistrates who presided in Defiance Campaign trials as reported in the newspapers, see supra chap three III A (3)(c)(iii). 20 See Ackermann Die reg insake openbare orde en staatsveiligheid 15 and Hiemstra Suid-Afrikaanse Strafproses 600. See also B1zos De Jure 1988 136. For a detailed discussion of the political offence exception in international extradition, see King CILSA 1980 247. Staatsbestuur, vooral wanneer hetzelve, door voorgevallen Revolution, geschokt is, zoo is ‘er bijna geene misdaad, waar in meerdere omzigtigheid den Regter is aan te beveelen, ten einde hij aan de eene zijde de handhaving van rust en goede orde bewaare, en aan den anderen kant, door overdrevene gestrengheid, geene ongelukkige slachtoffers van staatsverdeeldheden make. 21 John Dugard, following an investigation into the history of sentences imposed on political offenders since the Slagtersnek Rebellion of 1815, concluded that “there is traditionally a tendency towards leniency in the punishment of political offenders.” 22 The period under review in that study for the greater part covered the era of white against white conflict. It is submitted that, as a general rule, courts have followed a less lenient approach in the era since the Second World War. That era can be characterised as one of largely black against white conflict. Care should be taken to distinguish executive from judicial leniency. The former featured prominently in many of the cases which win be discussed but does not justify any conclusions in respect of the approach of the courts. (i) The era of white against white conflict Execution of the leaders of the Slas-tersnek Rebellion in 1815 and of Jopie Fourie for the part he played in the 1914 Rebellion, and the subsequent role of these martyrs in the emergence of Afrikaner nationalism, served as an early warning to substantiate the words of Van der Linden. The execution of four participants in the 1922 strike on the Witwatersrand for “semi-political” murders course of the strike, likewise led to much bitterness. committed in the 23 In other cases, a less severe approach was followed. The four leaders of the “Reform Committee”, initially sentenced to death, had their sentences commuted to a fine. 24 Robey Leibbrandt, sentenced to death for treason in 1943 by Schreiner J, 25 had his sentence commuted to life imprisonment by Premier Jan Smuts and was released when the National 21 Van der Linden Koopmans handbook 2.4.4.5. 22 Dugard SALJ 1974 59 at 65. 23 Id 66. 24 See S v Phillips & others (1896) 3 Off Rep 216, also reported anonymously in the Cape Law Journal 1900 15 at 30. 25 Confirmed on appeal: R v Leibbrandt 8 others 1944 AD 253. See also infra chap four I 0 (1). Party came into power in 1948. The British subjects in Natal and the Cape who joined the Boer forces during the Anglo-Boer War of 1899-1902 were treated with exceptional leniency, and in most cases either a fine or a short prison sentence was imposed. 26 The leaders of the 1914 Rebellion, General Kemp and General De Wet, were sentenced to seven and six years’ imprisonment respectively, but before the end of 1916 all rebels were released from custody. In fact, after the execution of Jopie Fourie the Indemnity and Special Tribunals Act 11 of 1915 excluded the death sentence in cases of treason. 27 The of dictum Van der Linden, quoted above, Appellate Division in R v Jolly and others, 28 was endorsed by the where the sentence of certain strike leaders who had derailed a train in the course of the strike, and were convicted of assault with intent to commit murder, was considered. In this particular instance there was no loss of life, although the possibility of deaths occurring existed and was foreseen. In support of the observation that the case did not merit “the utmost rigour of the law”, the Court stated that “the accused were actuated by any personal motives, whether of gain or of revenge." an obiter dictum in R v Gomas, 30 not 29 In Van der Linden’s statement was also approved, and it was stated that “[i]t is always undesirable, by an unnecessarily harsh sentence, to make anyone appear to be [a] martyr because Those of his political convictions.” 31 convicted of treason after the Second punished relatively mildly. In R v Mardon, 32 World War were also for example, while dealing with the merits of the conviction in the case, the Court remarked that the fact that the appellant (who had helped the war efforts of Germany in the Second World War) did not wish to injure the union, “will 26 See Anonymous SALJ 1901 164. 27 See also Dugard SALJ 1974 59 at 65. 28 1923 AD 176 at 183. 29 Ibid. 30 1936 CPD 225 at 235. 31 Ibid. 32 1947 2 SA 768 (TSCC). lighten” his punishment. 33 An eventual fine of £75 was imposed. 34 It should be noted that the judgment was entered a considerable time after the War, the events occurred on a distant continent, and the appellant in fact fought against the Soviet Union and not against South Africa. The face of resistance in South Africa changed in about 1846 when there could no longer be any doubt about the intentions of whites to entrench as firmly as possible their privilege, and black protest changed to challenge. How would courts deal with political resistance in this new era? (ii) The era of black against white conflict The sentences imposed during the trials resulting from the Defiance Campaign were discussed earlier. 35 In R v Sibande, 36 one of the earliest reported cases concerning the Defiance Campaign in which the issue of the appropriate sentence for political crimes was addressed, a very clear exposition is to be found of a judicial willingness to treat political offences with leniency. The conviction of the accused in the court a quo on a charge of unlawfully being in a certain magisterial area where he attended a meeting was confirmed on appeal, but the sentence of two months’ imprisonment that had been imposed by the court a quo was suspended. In justification of its approach to sentencing the Court remarked that the appellant “was not committing an offence of dishonesty or anything of that kind. It is a political offence and he 1s not to be regarded, in my view, in the same way as an ordinary person contravening the ordinary criminal code of this country.” 37 In R v Segale and others, 38 the accused were charged with incitement of an illegal strike. The appellants’ conviction of having incited certain municipal employees illegally to stay away from work was confirmed by the Appellate Division. The appellants acted in support of a campaign aimed at achieving a “£l-a-day” law and the abolition of the pass laws, 33 At 776. 34 This does not appear from the reported judgment of the Transvaal Special Criminal Court, but see R v Harden 1948 1 SA 942 (A) and "£75 fine for treason" Pretoria News 17 April 1947. 35 See supra chap three III A (3)(c)(iii). 36 1956 4 SA 23 (T). 37 At 25 per Kuper J. 38 I960 1 SA 721 (A). the Group Areas Act and National Party rule. 39 Prison sentences of varying duration were imposed by the Transvaal Provincial Division. 40 In confirming the sentences, the Appellate Division found that the “circumstances of the present offence ... differ obviously very widely from those campaign in for Sibande’s a case.” national The protest Court week proceeded: was “Although motivated by the political considerations, it is always a serious matter to incite others to flout the law of the land, whether for political reasons or not.” 41 The “wide extent of the incitement” was further regarded as aggravation. 42 The appellants magistrate’s in S court v of Benjamin and contravening others 43 section were 11(a) convicted of the in the Internal Security Act 44 of 1950, in that they distributed pamphlets with the heading “War preparations”, issued by the then recently banned ANC. These pamphlets urged Africans to prepare themselves for “sharp conflict” and a “dangerous clash” with the government, which, it was claimed, could take the form of the Algerian Civil War. The accused were sentenced to 18 months’ imprisonment, of which 12 months were suspended. On appeal the Court stated that “it would be a dangerous doctrine to subscribe to that generally speaking a political offence should not be punished by absolute imprisonment.” 44 The Court indicated that in view of the maximum sentence which could be imposed (the minimum sentence was then not yet in operation), the sentences imposed erred on the side of leniency. In S v Budlender and another, 45 the first appellant was charged with having organised an illegal gathering. In an appeal against the conditions of his bail, the Court granted some relief and in a judgment 39 Because the objective of the strike in such a case would have been laws or their administration, this could have brought the provisions of s 1 of Act 8 of 1953, which provides for Increased penalties, Into play. Presumably the Appellate Division found it unnecessary to decide the point. See 733. 40 R v Segale & others 1959 1 SA 589 (T). 41 At 733. 42 Ibid. 43 1963 2 SA 363 (T). 44 At 367. See also R v Sithole 1964 4 SA 477 (SR AD) at 480. 45 1973 1 SA 264 (C). worth quoting at length reaffirmed the classical approach of our courts: One must remember that it is a political offence, and one must remember that the people who commit political offences are frequently people of high political morals and ideals who commit these offences not for personal gain but because of the beliefs they have - things they may believe in very strongly. An offence of this nature carries for a certain section of the community little or no social opprobrium. It may even carry approval. ... This is not something new in South Africa. Anyone of us who cares to turn back the pages of history will find that these circumstances have applied at one time or another to practically every race and language group in the country. But it has always been the duty of the courts to try to sit with cool heads, with the necessary humanity, to see that people who have transgressed on account of their differences are not unnecessarily harshly dealt with. 46 Arguably, the jurisprudential low-water mark in this regard was S v Hogan. 47 In this case the accused, aged 30, was convicted of treason for having joined the ANC and having furthered its aims in South Africa at a time when that was still a crime. There was no evidence that she was personally involved in acts of violence, but it was emphasised by the Court that the policy of the ANC was the violent overthrow of the state. In passing sentence, Van Dyk J pointed out that the accused had played a prominent role in certain strikes and boycotts in the country. He proceeded: As I understand the overall policy and strategy of the ANC, strikes and boycotts are in this particular field merely the beginning of one of many of the more sophisticated onslaughts on the state and that, should they succeed in creating substantial workers’ unrest, the switch from a non-violent political struggle to a violent militant confrontation would follow almost as a matter of course. 48 The judge 46 indicated that he placed virtually no reliance on the At 268. 47 1983 2 SA 46 (W). McCleod & Kaganas SAJHR 1985 106 at 110 contrasted Hogan with another judgment of Van Dyk J, Involving a trial of a number of ultra right-wing "Afrikaner Weerstandsbeweging" members. They were convicted on charges of unlawfully possessing firearms. In imposing a suspended sentence, the judge said that the accused were "civilized people ... the victims of an unfortunate combination of circumstances". See also Van Blerk Judge and be Judged 90, who defended the position of Van Dyk J. 48 At 68 “reformatory effect” which any sentence would have on the accused. Instead he emphasised his belief in the need for, and the good prospect of, deterrence of other prospective offenders. He found that “the interests of society far outweigh all other considerations” and imposed a ten year jail sentence. 49 It would be difficult to find a clearer manifestation of the total onslaught ideology in our jurisprudence. It short-circuits any calm and collected consideration of facts, such as the real imminence and the extent and nature of the perceived threat. The judgment also reflects a giant miscalculation on the part of the presiding judge concerning the direction history was taking. A pillar of reason in the changing current was S v Motlhabakwe en andere, 50 where the appellants were convicted on several counts of terrorism under the Terrorism Act 83 of 1967 emanating, inter alia, from a number of cases of arson related to unrest situations at schools. In considering the question of sentence, the Court stated that, as mitigating circumstances, the bona fide belief in the inferiority of black education and the effect of agitation to which the appellants were subjected must be taken into account. Most instructive, however, is the following statement of Jacobs J P and Rees A J: [O]ns belewe tans tye van verandering waar strukture reeds geskep is en nog geskep word wat daarop gemik is om swart frustrasies piek te laat maak vir hoop en verwagting vir die toekoms vir a11e bevolkingsgroepe en ons meen dat in gepaste gevalle waar dade gepteeg is op ‘n tydstip toe hierdie frustrasies nog oorwegend was dit nie onvanpas is om met ‘n groter mate van begrip en erbarming na die dade te kyk nie. 51 It is submitted that this seminal statement indicates that courts of law, when dealing with politically motivated offences, should take into consideration the probability that the political values of the accused win in some form or another find application in the future. Courts have to anticipate to some extent impending positive political change, and where processes under way have not yet worked their way down to actual legal provisions, courts sometimes have to act in anticipation. What this amounts to, is that courts sometimes have to regard society, and 49 At 69. 50 1985 3 SA 188 (N). See also S v Makape & another 1989 2 SA 753 (T). 51 At 209. not only the other more conventional “texts” they deal with, in the Dworkinian best possible light. In S v Nel, 52 the Court took for granted that sabotage committed as an act of private revenge should be treated with more leniency in respect of sentence than would be the case if it was politically motivated. No authority is quoted for this remarkable conclusion, which turned on its head everything our law has for centuries stood for. It is even more remarkable to note that counsel for the state and the defence seemed to have agreed with this statement. 53 In S v Sprag, 54 Van der Walt J convicted a white member of Umkhonto we Sizwe of several offences involving violence against the state. In imposing a sentence of imprisonment he remarked: “If a black South African were in your position his or her acts could be understood, although not excused. The fact that as a white South African you have espoused the cause of revolution I regard as an aggravating feature.” 55 While recognition in the judgment of the principle that absence of the opportunity political of political resistance participation should be gives welcomed, its some legitimacy application in to the particular case is questionable. Surely, the point is that the accused, irrespective of her race, was effectively prohibited at the time by the state from pursuing what obviously were her political convictions. The “vote” she had was, to her, for all practical purposes meaningless. In a number of cases courts have had to consider the effect a political motive ought to have in respect of the death sentence. Their findings in this regard are most instructive, because if a political motive was in itself an extenuating circumstance, one would not expect death sentences to be imposed for such crimes at all. In S v Mkaba and others, 56 the death sentence imposed on the appellants for a murder (presumably of a state witness), which had been committed to prevent the conviction of members of Umkhonto we Sizwe in a political trial, was confirmed on appeal. Steyn C J held that although 52 1987 4 SA 276 (0). 53 At 295. 54 Unreported case no 166/86 W 3 Nov 1986. 55 At 8 of the judgment. 56 1965 1 SA 215 (A). the killing was not committed for personal gain, the facts of the particular case did not warrant a finding of extenuation. The murder was committed in cold blood and not immediately motivated by “political fervour or an acute sense of political injustice”, and the decision to commit the act was not taken “at a moment when political emotion was running high”. 57 The inference can be drawn, however, that, when present, these factors would constitute extenuation. A political motive was also not regarded as ipso facto an extenuating circumstance in S v Harris, 58 where the accused was sentenced to death upon conviction of murder of an innocent civilian in a politically motivated terror attack on a crowded train station. As the armed struggle intensified and changed its nature, especially since 1976, the approach of the courts hardened. In an obiter dictum in S v Mange 59 Rumpff C J articulated a shift in the Court’s approach. The Chief Justice distinguished historical from contemporary acts of high treason by stating that the element of terrorism - the intentional killing of innocent people - had been introduced in recent times. The following warning was then sounded: “However lenient the attitude of the courts may have been in the past in regard to our historical brand of high treason, a complete change now in regard to the present type of high treason would not be surprising, nor, in the circumstances, be unjustified.” 60 The Chief Justice soon found an opportunity to implement this new, harsher approach. In S v Lubisi and others, 61 the accused were convicted in the court a quo of high treason following an attack with fire-arms and hand grenades on a police station. Death sentences were imposed. From the facts as reported in the judgment, it would appear that no civilians were present at the police station at the time of the attack. One policeman was injured. The Appellate Division accepted that the appellants did not act from "inner vice", and stated that “the position in which the appellants 57 At 217. 58 1965 2 SA 340 (A). 59 1980 4 SA 613 (A). 60 Ibid. 61 1982 3 SA 113 (A). found themselves may be regarded with sympathy and understanding, especially by South Africans whose forebears at times were engaged in situations of open military conflict against British imperialism.” 62 The Court proceeded as follows: “In the present case the probable absence of inner vice and the presence of outer influences are, however, as mitigating circumstances, cancelled out by the callous and cowardly manner in which innocent people were appellants for political purposes.” 63 sought to be killed by the On this basis the death sentences were confirmed. When the facts of the case are considered, the reference to “innocent people” in this dictum is difficult to understand. That term is commonly used to denote civilian or “soft targets”. The attack was directed against policemen, who are considered “hard targets”. The Appellate Division identified itself with the trial judge who had said: “An attack on police officials in such a manner, whilst they are only doing their duty, is an act which is difficult to describe adequately in words. It is sheer terrorism of the highest order.” 64 If this is to be the case, it would be no less repulsive to attack “soft” rather than “hard” targets. If the courts do not make a distinction in this regard, why should the opponents of the state be expected to do so? The view expressed in Mkaba and Harris that a political objective does not constitute ipso facto extenuation where the death of civilians ensued, was endorsed by Corbett J A (as he then was). In S v McBride 65 he held that, in such cases, circumstances of the matter.” 66 “it all depends upon the particular In that case three people had died in a car bomb explosion executed (inter alia) by the appellant. 67 The death sentence imposed for murder by the court a quo was confirmed by the Appellate Division. 62 At 124. 63 Ibid. 64 At 125. 65 1988 4 SA 10 (A). 66 At 25. 67 The social and personal background of the appellant is discussed in Hear Robert McBride and Greta Apelgren. In a later case involving the death sentence, S v Masina and others, 68 the accused, members of Umkhonto we Sizwe, were charged with a number of crimes, including four politically motivated murders. The appellants refused to participate in the proceedings on the basis that as soldiers they should not stand trial in a civilian court. One of them, however, did read a statement to the court in which he explained that the accused had turned to the armed struggle as a last resort after years of non-violent resistance to apartheid proved fruitless. In this regard he quoted Lutuli’s words: “Who will deny that 30 years of my life have been spent knocking in vain, patiently, moderately and modestly at a closed and barred door?” 69 With a view to the accused’s subjective belief that they were fighting a war of liberation for their people, and the indoctrination which their training entailed, the trial judge came to the conclusion that extenuating circumstances existed. He was, however, overruled by the assessors and had to impose the death penalty. The Appellate Division stated that “[p]olitical considerations can, circumstances, constitute mitigating factors,” 70 depending on the and held that in this case it did. The death sentences were set aside. In a major, recent decision the Appellate Division again addressed the issue of the imposition of the death penalty for political crimes. In S v Mncube en ander 71 ‘n the Court dismissed the appellants’ appeal against the death sentences imposed upon them for murder, arising out of the death of eight civilians in landmine explosions. Both the appellants were members of Umkhonto we Sizwe, and the first appellant insisted on being treated as a soldier. The Court recognised that, in appropriate cases, the fact that particular offences were committed with a political motive could be regarded as extenuating circumstances. However, these considerations were outweighed by the aggravating circumstances of the case, which included the terroristic nature of the acts. The first appellant also testified that attacks on civilian targets were against the policy of the ANC, and described such conduct as undisciplined. The Court rejected the contention that it should 68 1990 4 SA 709 (A). 69 At 717. See also supra chap III A (3)(c)(ii). 70 At 719. 71 1991 3 SA 132 (A). impose “a sentence which reaches out for reconciliation”, and declared that it could country. not take into account the political climate of the 72 From the above it seems safe to state as a general rule that our courts do regard crimes committed with a political motive in a less serious light than offences committed with a self-serving motive. 73 This applies even in the case of armed uprising. 74 Several considerations, however, affect the application of this general rule. - Where the lives and safety of civilians are threatened, the rule does not imposed. - necessarily apply, and harsh sentences are often 75 Where the immediate conflict situation has been resolved, courts tend to follow an even more lenient approach than usual. 76 The reason for this attitude might be a combination of various considerations: the fact that it is no longer necessary to deter others from participating in the uprising; the fact that the need and opportunity for reconciliation has emerged, and so on. Where, on the other hand, the conflict has not been resolved at the time of the judgment, these considerations do not apply. 77 It is submitted attacks and the that the unresolved increasing use of nature the conflict of indiscriminate in South terror Africa during the past number of decades were largely responsible for the courts’ taking a more harsh line in sentencing. No doubt, since the middle of the century the personal convictions of 72 See 157. See also, on the effect which group pressure can have on those who commit political crimes, S v Matshili & others 1991 3 SA 264 (A). There is a useful discussion of the history of the sentences Imposed for treason in S v Banda & others 1991 2 SA 352 (B) at 359. 73 Contra Benjamin, Hogan and Nel. but see Jolly, Gomas, Sibande, Mkaba, Budlender and Masina. 74 Contra the cases of the Slagtersnek Five, Jopie Fourie, Leibbrandt and Lubisi, but see the cases of the rebels in the Anglo Boer War, the 1914 Rebellion, the Second World War and Motlhabakwe. 75 Contra Jolly, but see Harris, McBride and Mncube. 76 See most of the cases discussed from the era of white against white conflict. See, however, also Mncube. 77 See most of the cases discussed from the era of black against white conflict. the judges concerned often prompted the imposition of heavier sentences. In all the cases considered, the accused were either black or have identified themselves with the liberation struggle, while the presiding Judges were invariably part of the white establishment. The most conspicuous example of this is the Hogan case. Non-reactionary governments are often challenged by opponents from all sides, but because of the diversity of reasons for the opposition, the attacks are more readily seen as isolated. Reactionary governments, on the other hand, are almost invariably attacked from a fairly permanent position. Such attacks are then regarded as treasonable by those with a stake in the maintenance of the status quo, and all other smaller challenges to the state are viewed as part of this onslaught. By overreacting to minor challenges, the divide is increased: there is no incentive to challenge the state in a non-radical manner if such actions are in any event punished as if they were radical. Concluding too readily that a link exists between actions which are seemingly non-violent and the spectre of impending violence can indeed undermine demonstrations of leniency in sentencing practices of the courts. It is submitted that this is precisely what happened in a case such as clearly. The Hogan. The imminence of the danger must be established 78 approach followed in Motlhabakwe, namely that the long-term political prospects of positive change in the country, and the values which are likely to prevail, should be taken into account, seems likely to play a crucial role in the period of fundamental transition which the South African legal system is currently experiencing. Having now completed an investigation into the general approach of our courts regarding sentencing in cases involving political crimes, we now turn to the case in the Law Reports in which the appropriate punishment for acts of civil disobedience Motlaaomang and others 79 was specifically addressed. In R_v the appellants were convicted in the court a quo of “destruction of their reference books” by deliberately throwing the same into a fire. They were sentenced to a fine of £50 or six months’ imprisonment with compulsory labour. In imposing the sentence 78 See the discussion of the "clear and present danger" doctrine in American law infra chap six IV B (2). 79 1958 1 SA 626 (T). in the court a quo, the Native Commissioner (as that official was then called) remarked as follows: “Nieteenstaande herhaalde waarskuwings dat tensy die vernietiging van bewysboekies stopgesit word waardeur alreeds ernstige onluste in die afgelope jaar in die distrik plaasgevind het nog swaarder strawwe opgele sou word, het beskuldigdes die bewysboekies op so ‘n manier verbrand dat dit ‘n openlike verset teen die wet is.” 80 No indication is given of any evidence to substantiate a link between the civil disobedience and the “onluste”, and if violence was involved in the “onluste”, whether that violence had been instigated by the protesters or the government. On appeal, the Transvaal Provincial Division indicated that the “deliberation” shown by the accused could be regarded as an aggravating circumstance, because it showed “malignity”, which in turn brought into operation the provisions of section 1 of Act 8 of 1953. 81 Other circumstances taken into account were the prevalence of the crime in the district, and the need for deterring others from committing the same offence. Consequently, the Court did not find unacceptable the fact that the appellants in all probability would not be able to pay the fines and would have to serve the alternative prison sentences. This approach is open to criticism. The first objection relates to the fact that the Court regarded aggravating circumstance. the openness of the crime to be an To treat the openness of illegal protest as an aggravating circumstance could result in secrecy being encouraged. The element of openness of civil disobedience implies that this form of protest is essentially an act of communication. This means that those engaging in civil disobedience deliberately seek contact with their opposition. Especially in a society riddled by deep division, openness and engagement treatment. ought Moreover, not to openness be singled (as out defined for particularly earlier) is a harsh natural (although obviously not fool-proof) incentive to keep illegal action non-violent, because of the vulnerable position in which it places the perpetrator. The decision to practise open resistance usually also implies that a morally responsible approach is taken. This feature is undermined by the use of coercion. The same incentives do not apply as far as clandestine illegality is concerned. From this point of view, it 80 Quoted in the record of the appeal case at 628. 81 At 629. also makes more sense to encourage openness. The second aspect of the judgment that is open to critique concerns the Court’s assumption that acts of civil disobedience, such as those perpetrated by the appellants, were responsible for “oproer” in the area. If it had indeed been established that the civil disobedience occasioned violence, that would certainly have provided justification for following a tougher line than would otherwise be the case. But the existence evidence of - such it a link cannot has simply to be be established assumed. There through is reliable nothing in the judgment which indicates why the Court accepted the existence of such a link. If the “oproer” did not entail the use of violence, the case for taking a hard line would evidently be much weaker. The general political approach crimes of outlined the courts above, in if respect applied to of the sentencing case of for civil disobedience, suggests the following: A general approach of leniency should be followed in view of the political motivation of the crime. The exception to this rule alluded to above and which applies to violent terror attacks, is not applicable to civil disobedience, due to its non-violent nature. Especially where resistance has already taken a violent turn, it is the duty of courts to demonstrate to resisters that less dramatic alternatives are available. (2) Attempt to commit an act of civil disobedience The Riotous Assemblies Act 17 of 1956, provides as follows: Any person who attempts to commit any offence against a statute or a statutory regulation shall be guilty of an offence and, if no punishment is expressly provided thereby for such an attempt, be liable on conviction to the punishment to which a person convicted of actually committing that offence would be liable. 82 (3) Civil disobedience as a substantive crime During the most Africa, a crime crucial of years protest of the liberation constituted an struggle independent, in South substantive offence. From 1950 to 1982 the commission of any crime of protest rendered the perpetrator liable for (i) the primary offence, through which the protest was expressed (eg participation in an unlawful demonstration) as well as (ii) the statutory, substantive crime of committing a crime of protest. 82 Section 18 (1). During this time, section 11(a) of the Suppression of Communism Act, 83 later renamed 84 the Internal Security Act 44 of 1950, provided that anyone who "performs any act which is calculated to further the achievement of any of the objects of communism ... shall be guilty of an offence", and would be liable to imprisonment for a period of not less than one year and not exceeding ten years. 85 “Communism” as used in this context was defined to include “any doctrine or scheme ... which aims at bringing about any political, industrial, social or economic change within the Republic by ... unlawful means or omissions.” 86 The wide scope of this provision, which reflects the depths of the total onslaught ideology of the time, 87 was indeed remarkable. Its provisions included not only acts of civil disobedience, but all crimes of protest as instances of communism. This furthermore included not only crimes of protest against the legal order, but also crimes aimed at altering the political, industrial, social or economic order. This means that indirect civil disobedience, aimed not only at other laws but also constituting attacks against other aspects of the status quo, was likewise covered. Moreover, the word “calculated” in section 11(a) was interpreted by the courts not to mean “intended” but rather “likely” to bring about the furtherance of these objectives. 88 Over and above this, a contravention carried a minimum sentence of one year imprisonment. The Appellate Division recognised that this extraordinary statutory concept of communism could lead to absurd results which the legislature probably never contemplated. In R_v Sisulu and others, 89 the Court gave two examples of relatively innocent acts of civil disobedience which, 83 For a full discussion, see Mathews Law, order and liberty in South Africa 97ff and Milton & Fuller South African criminal law and procedure vol 3 112ff. 84 By the Internal Security Amendment Act 79 of 1976. 85 Section 11(m)(i). The minimum sentence was only introduced in 1976 by s 8 of the Internal Security Amendment Act 79 of 1976. 86 Section 1(1)(ii)(b). 87 For the parliamentary discussion that attended introduction of the Act, see Debates of the House of Assembly 14 June 1950 co1s 91789326 and cols 9331-9639. 88 See S v Nokwe & others 1962 3 SA 71 (T) at 74. 89 1953 3 SA 276 (A) at 290. in terms of these provisions, would constitute the crime of furthering the objectives of communism. The breach of municipal by-laws by women protesting against certain provisions of family law, as well as farmers refusing to comply with certain farming regulations, as acts of protest against such Division, by-laws would or regulations, qualify as instances furthering the objectives of communism. These provisions were according subsequently Internal Security Act 74 of 1982. 91 of the to the Appellate statutory crime of 90 repealed and replaced by the As it was then defined, the crime of furthering the objectives of Communism 92 was more narrowly 93 focused on outlawing advocating of the communist ideology as it is commonly understood, and acts of civil disobedience in themselves were no longer a substantive crime. The operation of this provision was first suspended as part of the present negotiations between the government and certain liberation movements, 94 and eventually, in July 1991, it was entirely scrapped. 95 A number of offences which are not often used in this regard with which persons engaging in acts of civil disobedience (or organising campaigns of civil discussed. C. disobedience) could possibly be charged, will later acts of be 96 TERTIARY IMPLICATIONS OF THE CRIMINAL LAW Those who do not themselves necessarily engage in civil disobedience, but who encourage others to do so, could also be liable to criminal prosecution. 90 See also supra chap three III A (3)(c)(iii), for the example cited by Rumpff J in the court a quo. 91 Section 73(1), read with Schedule 1, of the Act. For the reasons why this was done, see The report of the Commission of Inquiry into Security Legislation RP 90-1981 (the so-called "Rabie Commission") pars 9.4.1-9.4.5. 92 Defined -in s 55 of the Act. 93 Mathews Freedom, state security and the rule of law 45 and S_v Ramgobin 4 others 1986 1 SA 68 (W). 94 Proc R229, Regulation Gazette 12287, 3 Feb 1990. 95 Sections 1 and 21 of the Internal Security and Amendment Act 138 of 1991. 96 See infra chap four I D. (1) Incitement of civil disobedience Whereas civil disobedience often only becomes really effective when practised in the form of a campaign and with substantial numbers of people being mobilised, the crucial role of canvassing and organization and the exercise of leadership functions becomes apparent. An obvious strategy for the state to follow in order to prevent such pressures from developing, is to attach strong legal impediments to the advocacy of acts of civil disobedience. A whole arsenal of statutory measures has been put into place by the South African legislature to serve exactly this purpose. (a) Incitement to commit any offence It should be noted at the outset that incitement to commit a crime that is any crime, whether political or not - has traditionally been, and still is, a separate offence in its own right in South African law. 97 The exact scope of this offence varied over the years. In 1921, for example, the Appellate Division ruled that it was an offence at common law to incite someone to commit a crime, even if the crime concerned was neither in fact committed, or not even attempted. 98 Since 1926, the crime of incitement is governed by statute. 99 Today the Riotous Assemblies Act 17 of 1956 provides that [a]ny person who ... incites, instigates, commands, or procures any other person to commit, any offence, whether at common law or against a statute or statutory regulation, shall be guilty of an offence and liable on conviction to the punishment to which a person convicted of actually committing that offence would be liable. 100 Intention is an element of this crime. 101 The question whether incitement requires an element of persuasion of the incitee, or whether 97 See Burchell et a1 South African criminal law and procedure vol 1 472ff. 98 S v Nlhovo 1921 AD 485. 99 Section 15(2)(b) of the Riotous Assemblies and Criminal Law Amendment Act 27 of 1914 was amended by s 4(b) of the Criminal and Ma9istrates' Courts Procedure (Amendment) Act 39 of 1926, to make it clear that Incitement to commit an offence, whether at common law or by statute, was in itself an offence. 100 Section 18(2)(b). 101 Burche'n et a1 South African criminal law and procedure vol 1 474. a mere request would suffice, is problematic. In the landmark decision of S v Nkosiyana and another 102 it was held by the Appellate Division that an inciter is one who reaches and seeks to influence the mind of another to the commission of a crime. The machinations of criminal ingenuity being legion, the approach to the other’s mind may take various forms, such as suggestion, proposal, request, exhortation, gesture, argument, persuasion, inducement, goading, or the arousal of cupidity. The list is not exhaustive. The means employed are of secondary importance; the decisive question in each case is whether the accused reached and sought to influence the mind of the other person towards the commission of a crime. 103 Clearly, encouragement to commit acts of civil disobedience is covered by the confines of this crime. In R_v Abdurahman, 104 for example, the appellant was convicted in the court a quo of inciting “non-Europeans” to use railway coaches reserved for “Europeans only”. In R v Segale and others, 105 the accused were convicted of incitement for having encouraged municipal workers and domestic servants to stay away from work. (b) Incitement to commit a political offence Over and above the general provisions of the law regarding incitement, there are also a number of statutory provisions aimed specifically at advocacy of political offences. These offences have been relied upon in the past to disobedience. 106 prosecute those engaged in advocacy of civil Encouragement of offences to be committed for political purposes first became a substantive crime in its own right when the Internal Security Act 44 of 1950 came into operation. Section 11(b) of that Act provided that any person who “advocates, advises, defends or encourages the achievement of [the objects of communism as circumscribed] or any act or omission which is calculated to further 102 1966 4 SA 655 (A). See also S v Dreyer 1967 4 SA 614 (E) at 621. 103 At 658, 659. 104 1950 3 SA 136 (A). 105 1960 1 SA 721 (A). 106 On the relationship between common law incitement and special forms of statutory incitement, see R v Sesidi & others 1953 4 SA 634 (GW) at 637. the achievement of any such object,” was guilty of an offence and liable to imprisonment for a period of not less than one year and not exceeding ten years. 107 The definition of “communism” was the same wide one which applied to section 11(a), discussed above, namely any doctrine or scheme “which aims at bringing about any political, industrial, social or economic change within the Republic by ... unlawful means or omissions.” 108 It was under this provision that the Campaign was tried and convicted in 1952. leadership of the Defiance 109 In response to the Defiance Campaign, a second offence of encouragement of crimes of protest was enacted, without the one outlined above being revoked. This offence was sanctioned by the Criminal Law Amendment Act 8 of 1953. 110 The Act provided for a fine of up to £300, imprisonment of up to five years and a whipping of up to ten strokes upon conviction of incitement to commit a crime of protest. 111 The imposition of corporal punishment for political crimes was particularly controversial. The pertinent provisions of the 1950 Internal Security Act and the 1953 Criminal Law Amendment Act were repeated by the Internal Security Act 74 of 1962, which currently is still in force. Section 59 of this Act outlaws, in the exact words of the Criminal Law Amendment Act of 1953, incitement to commit crimes of protest, though the penalties provided 107 Section 11(m)(i). 108 For a discussion of these provisions, see Mathews Law, order and liberty in South Africa 97ff and Milton & Fuller South African criminal law and procedure vol 3 114, 116. See also R v Alwyn 1955 3 SA 207 (A). 109 See R v Sisulu & others 1953 3 SA 276 (A) and the discussion supra chap three III A (3)(c)(iii). The Appellate Division explicitly rejected the contention that only coercive actions were covered by this provision and that persuasive or non-coercive conduct was not affected: "[I]t was said that, although an act or a threat that was intended to produce terror in the legislators and thus to cause a legislative change might fall within the paragraph, one that was intended to move the legislators by pity or a realisation of the justice of the cause of those responsible for the act would not be covered. It is sufficient to say that there is no warrant for this distinction." (At 290.) 110 See s 2(a) & (b). 111 Section 2(i)-(vi). for are not the same. 112 It provides that any person who, (a) in any manner whatsoever advises, encourages, incites, commands, aids or procures any other person or persons in general; or (b) uses any language or does any act or thing calculated to cause any person or persons in general, to commit an offence by way of protest against any law or in support of any campaign against any law or in support of any campaign for the repeal or modification of any law or the variation or limitation of the application of the administration of any law, commits an offence, and is liable on conviction to a fine of up to R5000 and imprisonment of up to five years. It is clear from the wording of section 59 that it only covers protests aimed against laws or their administration. The incitement of either direct or indirect civil disobedience (or other crimes of protest) would consequently not be outlawed as long as such protests are aimed against extra-legal aspects of society. It is also not the incitement that must express the protest, but the crime incited - that is, the primary offence incited must be a crime of protest. 113 The communication must reach the incitee, 114 although it is irrelevant how the incitee responds to the incitement. 115 While subsection (a) deals with direct forms of incitement, subsection (b) also makes provision for more indirect forms of influencing others. In practice, however, it is not always easy to draw the distinction. In S v Nathie, 116 the appellant was charged with having contravened subsection (a). The charge was based on a report which the appellant read out at a conference of the Transvaal Indian Congress. The report referred to refusals by members of the Indian communities to obey orders to vacate certain premises in terms of the Group Areas Act. The rhetorical question was posed: “Is it any wonder that there is developing among our people in different parts of the country a feeling 112 Consequently, decisions and comments provisions can be applied to the 1982 Act. 113 dealing with the older S v Moilwanyana 1957 4 SA 608 (T) at 615. 114 R v Adams & others 1959 1 SA 646 (SO at 674, 675. On attempt to incite, see S v Radine & another 1962 1 PH K44 (T). 115 116 R v Alwyn 1955 3 SA 207 (A) at 211. 1964 3 SA 588 (A). The case dealt with the Identically worded 1953 forerunner of s 59. that they should refuse to obey the orders to quit, no matter what the consequences?” 117 The report referred positively to the refusal of Nana Sita (who was also active in the Defiance Campaign) to comply with such an order, and then, with reference to possible future conduct of the government, proceeded: But the question is: are we, the rest of the Indian people, going to remain silent when this happens? Are we just going to acquiesce because some madmen in the Department sit and decide what is going to be our future and the future of our children? I want to declare that to remain silent in the face of persecution is an act of supreme cowardice. Basic laws of human behaviour require us to stand and fight against injustice and inhumanity. Not for a moment must [those who refuse to comply with the orders] be allowed to imagine that they are alone in the stand that they have taken. The Nationalists must be made aware of the fact that the attack against these people is an attack against the Indian people as a whole and will be met by the organised strength of the entire community. 118 The appellant also stated that methods of non-violent actions.” “we will continue to maintain our 119 The appellant was acquitted on appeal on the ground that what he had said fell “just short” of the incitement required by subsection (a), which constituted the basis of the case against him. Nevertheless, the Court held that “the report as a whole was couched in such excessively provocative language that it might contravention of [subsection (b)].” 120 well be said to constitute a Since he was not charged with a contravention of the latter provision, he was discharged. How, then, are the statutory provisions regarding incitement of acts of political protest, as set out above, to be interpreted, especially in light of the Nathie judgment and the obiter dictum just quoted? Tony Mathews argued that because not only the word “incitement”, but also words such as “advise” and “encourage” are used in subsection (a), “promptings to 117 At 593. 118 Ibid. 119 Ibid. 120 At 597. action which fall short of incitement” are also criminalised by that subsection. 121 It is submitted that this interpretation of subsection (a) is not correct. In the first place, “incitement” as used in the statute that codified the crime of incitement has been interpreted by the courts to mean “seek to influence” in any manner possible. 122 How can it be a crime (of which intention is an element 123) to do less than to “seek to influence” someone else in any manner possible to commit a crime? In the second place, the appellant in was Nathie acquitted precisely because his actions fell short of incitement. But what about subsection (b)? Is mens rea in the form of either dolus or culpa required by this provision? The answer to this question must turn upon the interpretation of the word “calculated”. Milton and Fuller argued that “calculated” should be interpreted to mean “likely” rather than “intended”. 124 If this is correct, neither dolus nor culpa is required; it means that a crime of strict liability was in fact created by the subsection. 125 The primary source cited by Milton and Fuller for their interpretation of subsection (b) is S v Beyleyeld and others. 126 In this case, the conviction of the appellants on a charge of having committed certain acts which were “calculated to violate the dignity or injure the reputation of the State President” in violation of section 13 of the Republic of South Africa Constitution Act 32 of 1961, was confirmed because “calculated” in this context was held to mean “likely” and not "intended". The Court decided, however, that on the facts of the case the conduct of the appellants, who had circulated pamphlets stating that the then State President C R Swart was not a fit and proper person to receive the freedom of Johannesburg, also included the 121 See Mathews Law, order and liberty in South Africa 188. This observation is not repeated 1n his Freedom, state security and the rule of law. 122 See the excerpt quoted from S v Nkosiyana and another 1966 4 SA 655 (A), supra chap four I C (1)(a). 123 See Mathews Freedom, state security and the rule of law 54. 124 Milton & Fuller South African criminal law and procedure vol 3 136. 125 See, however, Mathews Law, order and liberty in South Africa 188. 126 1964 1 SA 269 (T). intention to injure his dignity or reputation. Strydom observed that S v Nokwe and others 127 was the only case cited in Beyleveld in which a statutory provision in pari materia with section 13 was considered. In Nokwe it was decided that the word “calculated” in section 11(a) of the Internal Security Act 44 of 1950 128 had to be interpreted to mean “likely”. 129 Beyleveld, according to Strydom, was wrongly decided, in that section 13 of the Constitution was interpreted as though it created an absolute proscription while the Act itself gave no indication that this was in fact the intention of the legislature. 130 According to him, section 13 should be interpreted to require mens rea in the form of negligence or intention. 131 When section 59 as a whole is considered, it becomes clear that the legislature intended to include in its confines all possible ways in which one person might “seek to” influence another to commit a crime of protest. Subsection (a) sets out the most common ways in which this can be done, whilst subsection (b) is a dragnet provision that serves to cover instances not represents an particular context, included attempt and to to in subsection regulate give an the (a). crime indication Section of of 59 incitement the simply in a appropriate punishment in such cases. Consequently, it is submitted that intention is indeed an element of the statutory crime under consideration. What is the position where one person encourages another to commit an act which the former erroneously believes to be a crime? As far as the general crime of incitement is concerned, commentators 132 subscribe to a subjective approach, similar to the one followed in S v Davies 133 in respect of an attempt to do the impossible. This means that a factual error (error facti) does not exclude liability. An error as to the law 127 1962 3 SA 71 (T). 128 See supra chap four I B (3). 129 Strydom JCRDL 1964 314 at 316. Strydom's views in this regard are endorsed by Van Niekerk SALJ 1970 299. 130 Strydom JCRDL 1964 314 at 316. 131 Id 318. 132 See Burchell et a1 South African criminal law and procedure vol 1 479 and Snyman Criminal law 261. 133 1956 3 SA 52 (A). (error juris), on the other hand, does exclude 1iability. 134 In S v Peake, 135 this approach was applied to contravention of section 59 of the Internal Security Act 74 of 1982. In that case the Court held that an accused may be convicted if he encouraged people to defy the Group Areas Act 77 of 1957, even though it had not been proved that people in the audience were at that time in a position to in fact defy the Act. If this approach is to be followed, then R v Motorane 136 was wrongly decided. In that case the state failed to prove that the incitee had reached the age where he could commit the crime incited, namely throwing away his reference book. The conviction of appellant was dismissed on appeal. Similarly, in R v Plaatjies, 137 the the appellant was acquitted because there was no proof that the people who had been encouraged to participate in an illegal strike were “native labourers” as defined in the relevant statute. The acquittal of the appellants in R v Mpekwa and others 138 was justified by the Court on the basis that the act complained of was prompted by an error juris. In that case the appellants assaulted certain people in order to “persuade” them to “allow” the appellants to take possession of their (the assaulted people’s) reference books. “Allowing” a third party to take possession of one’s reference book constituted an offence. Because these persons assaulted were forced to hand over their reference books, they could not be convicted of any crime, and those who forced them to do so could not be convicted of inciting others to commit an offence. Mathews pointed out that the presumption of a guilty intent which would arise from the commission of a crime of protest while in the company of two or more persons, created by section 69(8) of the Internal Security Act 74 of 1982, probably does not apply to a contravention of section 59, because the words creating the presumption refer to a prosecution in which the offence charged was committed by way of protest. 139 The 134 See S v Davies 1956 3 SA 52 (A) at 63. 135 1962 4 SA 288 (C). 136 I960 4 SA 353 (0). 137 1960 2 PH H371 (C). 138 1958 1 SA 10 (T). This decision was endorsed in R v Bolo & others 1960 2 PH H290 (E). 139 Mathews Freedom, state security and the rule of law 54. crime under consideration requires that the offence incited, not the offence charged, must be a protest offence. (c) In Proclamations prohibiting the incitement of “natives” November proclamation 1952, 140 when the Defiance was issued by the Governor-General, in the so-called “native areas” present at Campaign any one time”, 143 142 was 141 at its peak, a outlawing meetings at which “more than ten natives are except under certain circumstances. 144 Furthermore, it was decreed that in those areas “[a]ny person who at any time uses language or behaves in a manner or does any act or thing calculated to cause natives to resist and contravene any law or to prevail upon them to obstruct the administration of any law, shall be guilty of an offence.” 145 These regulations made provision for a imprisonment of not more than three years. fine 146 of up to £300 or Similar provisions were decreed in respect of places not declared “native areas”. 147 (2) Assistance of those engaged in civil disobedience After the Defiance Campaign of 1952, the government sought ways and means to isolate those who engaged in acts of civil disobedience. The assistance, financial and otherwise, given to resistors by sources from within and outside the country was resented by the authorities, because 140 Proc 276, Government Gazette Extraordinary 4971, 28 Nov 1952, replacing the milder Proc 31, Government Gazette 3453, 2 March 1945, as amended by Proc 59, Government Gazette 3620, 22 March 1946. 141 Issued in terms of s 27 of the Black Administration Act 38 of 1927. 142 The areas referred to in s 25(1) of the Black Administration Act 38 of 1927. 143 Section 1(1)(a). 144 Section 1(2). 145 Section 2. A number of provisions granting the police certain powers 1n respect of the investigation of contraventions of s 2 (s 3(1)) and the destruction of articles used to contravene s 2 (s 3(2)) were also contained in the same proclamation. 146 Section 4. Patric Duncan and the other white resisters were convicted of contravening these regulations. See supra chap three III A (3)(c)(iii). 147 Government Notice 2753, Government Gazette Extraordinary 4971 of 28 Nov 1952. it removed repressed those groups obstacles to that sustain normally their make resistance. 148 it The difficult provision for of foreign funds to those engaged in civil disobedience was also seen as unwarranted foreign interference in, what was considered to be, South Africa’s domestic affairs. In order to counter these developments the act of giving as well as that of receiving such assistance was outlawed. Section 3(1) of the Criminal Law Amendment Act 8 of 1953 ‘made it a crime for anyone to offer or accept material assistance (financial or otherwise) for the execution of crimes of protest. This provision was almost ipsissima verbis carried over into the Internal Security Act 74 of 1982. Section 60(1) now provides as follows: Any person who solicits, accepts or receives from any person or body of persons, whether within or outside the Republic, or who offers or gives to any person or body of persons any money or other article for the purpose of – (a) assisting any campaign (conducted by means of any unlawful act or omission or the threat of such act or omission or by means which include or necessitate such act or omission or such threat) against any law, or against the application or administration of any law; or (b) enabling or assisting any person to commit any offence by way of protest against any law or in support of any campaign against any law or in support of any campaign for the repeal or modification of any law or for the variation or limitation of the application or administration of any law; or (c) unlawfully assisting any person offence referred to in paragraph (b), who has committed any shall be guilty of an offence and liable on conviction to the penalties prescribed in section 59. 149 In addition to the penalty provided for in respect of this section, the court is obliged to forfeit to the state any money or goods in the possession or under the control of the accused and which were used for 148 Earlier, reference was made to the "million shillings" drive launched at the commencement of the Defiance Campaign. In spite of the fact that the drive was aborted before it had reached its goal, it is clear that some money had been collected from the public. See supra chap three III A (3)(c)(iii). 149 For the penalties prescribed in s 59, see supra chap four I C (1)(b). the purposes mentioned above. 150 The offence (prospective) created in recipient section and 60(1) the can be (prospective) committed by the provider of the assistance. The assistance pertains to a campaign of crimes of protest, whether impending or already in progress (paragraph (a)); or assistance to an Individual in respect of crimes of protest still in progress (paragraph (b)) or crimes of protest of the past (paragraph (c)). Except insofar as paragraph (c) is concerned, the assistance must be provided with the intention of furthering the commission of crimes of protest. This means that an unforeseen outbreak of crime during an essentially legal campaign of protest would not constitute an offence at the instance of those who had provided or accepted material assistance in respect of that campaign, even if that outbreak of crime was foreseeable. 151 It also appears from the wording of section 60 that the crimes of protest envisaged must specifically be aimed at a certain law or laws, or the administration thereof. The law violated need not be the one objected against. Paragraph (c), which prohibits anyone from "unlawfully assisting any person who has committed any offence referred to in paragraph (b)" did not contain the adverb "unlawfully" in its 1953 equivalent. Taken literally, the older provision could consequently be interpreted as prohibiting anyone but the offender himself from paying for his legal defence, 152 and it could even be interpreted as prohibiting anyone from acting as the lawyer for someone who has committed such an offence. It could in fact be argued that the actions of a welfare officer or other 150 Section 60(2). 151 See Mathews Freedom, state security and the rule of law 55, who convincingly argues that the rationale of S v Peake 1962 4 SA 288 (C) also applies in this case. 152 This Interpretation was indeed endorsed in S v Sobale & others 1962 1 SA 411 (E) at 415. It is not inconceivable that the legal assistance which the accused in the cases currently under discussion received was viewed with a measure of irritation by the government of the day: the names of Mandela, Tambo, Slovo, Sachs, Wolpe and others frequently appear in the records as lawyers for the defence. For the adverse comments of an apparently otherwise sympathetic court on the influence which the fact that the defence of certain accused was sponsored by outside sources had on the conduct of the trial by the defence lawyer, see S v Motlhabakwe 8. andere 1985 3 SA 188 (N) at 208. good Samaritan, who looked after the family of such a person while he served a prison sentence, were criminalised. To avoid such absurd consequences, the word "unlawfully" was introduced in the 1982 assisting" Act. means The in problem the now present is what context. It the is term "unlawfully submitted that a feasible guideline would be the general legal position relating to assistance given to persons who committed offences. Consequently, paragraph (c) should be understood to have incorporated into section 60(1) the prohibition of being an accessory after accessory after the fact is someone who intentionally assists the perpetrator commission of that crime. of 153 a crime to escape the fact. An and unlawfully liability after the Paragraph (c) renders someone whose conduct satisfies the requirements of that particular common law crime, liable to the penalties for contravening section 60(1). If that is the case, what then are the implications of section 60(1) with regard to financial contributions and other assistance in respect of the legal defence of persons who have engaged in crimes of protest? It is submitted that the right to legal representation (at least if one can afford it) is so basic that even the 1953 provision could not have rendered such assistance unlawful. It is certain that the current provision does not do so. The raising of money for the defence of such a person or persons is more problematic. It is submitted that where the money is raised or promised before the commission of a crime or crimes of protest in order to encourage the prospective offender to go ahead with his campaign, such action could constitute a transgression of the provisions of paragraphs (a) or (b). Where the money is promised or raised after the commission of an offence for purely humane or even ideological reasons, the requirement of assistance "to someone who has committed an offence" would be satisfied, but because such assistance was not "unlawful" as required by section (c), it would not come within the definition of the offence under consideration. A more difficult question arises when financial assistance is given to an offender who has already committed a crime, with the purpose of encouraging other persons and giving them the assurance that their legal expenses will also be covered. If it should appear that such 153 See Snyman Criminal law 236. encouragement and assurance money given for the were intended, one would be dealing with purpose of assisting future acts of civil disobedience, as contemplated in subsections (a) and (b). D. OTHER CRIMES In the discussion thus far, the most important and direct implications of the criminal law in respect of civil disobedience were analysed. To a large extent, the statutory component of this body of laws emanated from ad hoc legislation which followed in the wake of governmental paranoia occasioned by the Defiance Campaign of 1952 and later manifestations of political resistance. It will be submitted that civil disobedience strive to can have uphold an important democratic role values, to and play that in societies tolerance of that civil disobedience is indeed one of the earmarks of such a society. The special legislative "booster" provisions discussed above have no role to play in such societies. It could be argued, however, that the possibility of mass civil disobedience can pose a serious threat to the modern state, especially in a deeply divided society. Most of the crimes that might be committed to express protest - the primary offences - were developed, and penalties were determined, with transgressions by a limited number of persons in mind. The legal impediments attached to the commission of the primary crime might consequently in some cases be insufficient to counter an unjustified but well orchestrated campaign of civil disobedience. What would happen, for example, if a highly organised group opposing the transformation of the South African society were to launch a massive campaign of protest, paralysing the entire country? Some "boosting" of the position of the state might in exceptional cases be necessary. It is submitted that, where feasible, specific campaigns of civil disobedience can adequately be dealt with under the general provisions of the law dealing with state security, and particularly the common law crimes. 154 This does not mean that the country’s security laws do not also require revision. However, while they are in force, those laws are more than might ever be needed to deal with any possible campaign of 154 See also Ackermann Die reg insake openbare orde en staatsveiligheid 2, 3, 14 and Milton South African criminal law and procedure vol 2 27. civil disobedience. In what follows, the question win be discussed whether the organization of, and participation in, a campaign of civil disobedience can come within the ambit of any of the five most serious crimes against the terrorism, state: treason, subversion or sedition sabotage (the (the common law statutory crimes), crimes). and 155 The question whether civil disobedience could in given circumstances amount to the crime of defeating or obstructing the course of justice, will also be discussed. (1) Treason It was argued earlier that, contrary to what some American authors maintain, civil disobedience can in principle be directed against "the existing system seen as a whole". Illegal, non-violent, open, political acts motivated by conviction do not cease to be acts of civil disobedience simply because those acts are intended to bring about a fundamental change in the basic constitutional structure of the country. Certain protest campaigns against the apartheid state in South Africa, Gandhi’s demonstrations in campaigns the in People’s India, and the Republic of China, Tiananmen are Square examples of revolutionary civil disobedience. The question is whether revolutionary civil disobedience may constitute treason as defined in South African law. 156 As mentioned earlier, the state contemplated bringing charges of treason against the leaders of the Defiance Campaign of 1952. 157 Evidence regarding the organization of the Defiance Campaign also constituted state’s case in the Treason Trial. 158 a substantial part of the Towards the end of the proceedings the prosecution mentioned the possibility of a conviction of treason 155 The same question may of course be asked in respect of the commission of acts of civil disobedience where no campaign is involved, but the threat to the security of the state wi11 be considerably lower as far as individual civil disobedience is concerned. 156 On the legal implications of the Rhodesian Unilateral Declaration of Independence in 1965 and especially the question whether it constituted treason, see Wharam Cambridge Law Journal 1967 189 and Barrie CILSA 1968 289. 157 See "Treason, sedition Daily Mail 31 July 1952. 158 searches made See supra chap three III A (3)(c)(vi). throughout Union" Rand for illegal conduct aimed at the non-violent overthrow of the state. This suggestion was called "[i]nteresting and important" by the Court. However, since the case was brought and conducted on the basis of a conspiracy to commit violence, the Court declined to consider convicting the accused for treason on the basis of their non-violent activities. 159 It is conceivable, however, that a civil disobedience campaign might be conducted in future, and the prosecution might then decide to bring charges for treason. The question whether an illegal campaign to overthrow the state nonviolently can constitute treason must be answered with a view to the definitions of treason. As stated earlier, civil disobedience implies illegality and non-violence. Civil disobedience can be coercive (for example the blocking of traffic) or non-coercive (for example the campaigns of Gandhi), but the higher the element of coercion, the less would it be regarded as civil disobedience proper. It follows from the non-violent nature of civil disobedience that if the use of disobedience violence will not is a qualify necessary as element treason. of However, treason, if any civil illegal attempt to overthrow the state, whether violent or non-violent, would suffice to constitute treason, revolutionary civil disobedience could be treasonable. What then are the essential elements of the crime of treason? According to Milton: "High treason consists in any overt act unlawfully committed by a person owing allegiance to a state possessing majestas who intends to impair that majestas by overthrowing or coercing the government of that state." 160 According to Snyman: "High treason consists in any act committed either inside or outside the borders of 159 See S v Adams & others, unreported case no 1/58 SCC 1961, at 25 of the judgment of Rumpff J. The proceedings of the Treason Trial are discussed by Gardiner Journal of the International Commission of Jurists 1957 43; Blom-Cooper International and Comparative Law Quarterly 1959 59 and Karis Political Science Quarterly 1961 217. See also South African Institute of Race Relations A survey of race relations in South Africa 1956-1957 41ff; 1958-1959 44ff; 1959-1960 37ff and 1961 62ff. 160 Milton Criminal law and procedure vo1 2 14. Majestas. in the context of the crime of treason, refers to the state's sovereignty. For a discussion of this element, see S v Banda & others 1989 4 SA 519 (BGD) at 521 and Devine SALJ 1990 184. See also Van der Vyver Emory International Law Review 1991 9. the Republic by a person who owes allegiance to the Republic with the intention unlawfully existence, Swanepoel to independence maintained: overthrow, or coerce, security "Hoogveraad of is the die impair or Republic. 161 endanger De wederregtelike, Wet the and opsetlike verstoring, aantasting of in gevaarstelling van die staatsbestaan." 162 Ackermann defined treason as follows: Hoogverraad teen die Republiek word gepteeg indien iemand wat trou aan die land verskuldig is, binne of buite die Republiek ‘n handeling verrig met die vyandige opset om op wederregtelike wyse die staat omver te werp, in gevaar te stel, die onafhankiikheid daarvan aan te tas, die grondwet daarvan te verander of die owerheid daarvan onder dwang te plaas." 163 It is apparent from the above definitions that treason does not require that one’s attempt at overthrowing or coercing the state should be successful - certain acts committed with that intention will suffice. In fact, treason will only be treason if it is unsuccessful, because the successful overthrow of the government will put a new government in power, itself. and the new regime will have no incentives to prosecute 164 The "key definitive element" 165 or "hallmark" 166 of treason is animus hostil is, a hostile disposition against the state or government. 167 What is required is a "vyandige opset" 168, not "vyandelike opset": 169 One need not associate oneself with the enemy in a time of war; to act like 161 Snyman Criminal law 257. 162 De Wet & Swanepoel Strafreg 518. 163 Ackermann Die reg Insake openbare orde en staatsveiligheid 8. 164 According to Sir John Harrington's epigram: "Treason doth never prosper; what is the reason? Why if it prosper none dare call it treason." Quoted in MacGuigan The Canadian Bar Review 1971 222 at 258. 165 Milton South African criminal law and procedure vol 2 25. 166 Snyman Criminal law 259. 167 For the purposes of the law of treason the government is wholly identified with the state. See R v Leibbrandt & others 1944 AO 253 at 281. 168 As maintained by Gonin JCRDL 1951 1. Approved in S v Mayekiso & others 1988 4 SA 738 (W). 169 As maintained by Coertze JCRDL 1937 274. See also S v Phi Hips (1896) 3 Off Rep 216 at 239, where "conspiracy and co-operation with a foreign enemy" was required. the enemy in times of peace would constitute the required hostile intent. In accordance with his definition of treason, Milton regarded "hostile intent" as the intention "to impair the majestas of the state by overthrowing or coercing the government." 170 According to Snyman, "hostile impair intent" or is endanger "an the intention existence, government of the Republic." unlawfully to independence overthrow, or security coerce, of the 171 According to these interpretations of hostile intent - one might call it the orthodox position - the intention to coerce or to overthrow the state by illegal means would constitute hostile intent. The striking feature of the orthodox position is the use of the word "or". Either the intention to coerce or the intention to overthrow the state illegally can constitute hostile intent. There might be an overlap between the meaning of "intention to coerce" and "intention to overthrow", but the disjunctive position 172 in which the two terms are used suggests that they cannot be identical, nor that the one term is included in the other. It follows that neither the intention to coerce nor the intention to overthrow by illegal means are necessary elements of a hostile intent, but both intentions are in themselves sufficient conditions of such an intent. 173 The commission of illegal acts aimed at the overthrow of the government, even in the absence of coercion, may therefore constitute treason. Accordingly, Milton stated that "an intent to overthrow the state certainly does constitute a ‘hostile intent’.” 174 170 171 Milton South African criminal law and procedure vol 2 29. Snyman Criminal law 261. See also openbare orde en staatsveiligheid 11. Ackermann Die reg Insake 172 According to Milton South African criminal law and procedure vol 2 28 compliance with "one or other" of the rubrics will constitute hostile intent. 173 A condition or an element is "necessary" if its presence is a conditio sine qua non for a particular state of affairs to prevail; it is "sufficient" if its presence cancels the need for other conditions to be satisfied. A condition might, however, be necessary without being sufficient (there might be more than one necessary condition) or sufficient without being necessary (other conditions might also be sufficient). 174 Id 26. De Wet & Swanepoel Strafreg 529 maintained that "sodra die wil om die bestaande staat omver te werp, dws die bestaande staat The orthodox position, if correct, would clearly have far-reaching consequences for civil disobedience. According to this approach, civil disobedience both in its coercive and in its non-coercive form, as long as it is aimed at the overthrow of the state, can be treasonable. It is submitted, however, that the orthodox position does not correctly express the essence of treason under South African law, as reflected in the opinions of Roman-Dutch sources and in case law. Instead, it will be proposed that an intention to illegally overthrow the government is neither a necessary nor a sufficient condition for purposes of a hostile intent, while an intention to coerce the government is both necessary and sufficient. What do the sources say? Voet regarded the intention overthrow the state as a necessary element of treason. as Van der Linden 176 and Moorman 177 175 to actually Writers such , however, took the view that animus hostilis is constituted by any intent to disturb, injure or endanger the security of the state, and does not require an intention to overthrow the government. The Appellate Division endorsed the latter approach in R_v Erasmus, 178 where it was held that a partial erosion of the government’s independence of action already constitutes hostile intent. In this case the appellant took part, as one of the leaders, in the armed uprisings during the gold mine strikes on the Rand in 1921, which led to violent clashes with the police. The trial Court came to the conclusion that, deur 'n ander te vervang, maar deur die geringste gedraging blyk, word die staatsbestaan in gevaar gestel en is die handeling strafbaar [as treason]." See also Ackermann Die reg insake openbare orde en staatsvelligheid 12. 175 After having given a number of examples of potentially treasonable activities, Voet stated that they constitute treason when they have "been committed against the commonwealth and with a view to its overthrow". Voet Comnentary on the Pandects 48.4.3. 176 Van der Linden Koopmans handbook 2.4.2 defined treason as follows: "Deeze misdaad wordt begaan door hun, die met een vijandig oogmerk de onafhangelijkheid of veiligheid van den Staat stooren, benadeelen, of in gevaar brengen." (Original emphasis, footnote omitted.) See also R v Boers (1900) 21 NLR 116 at 121; R v De Wet 1915 OPO 157 at 167 and R v Wenzel 1940 WLO 269 at 272. 177 Moorman Misdaden 1.3.2 defined treason as "uit een vyandlyk opzet, lets doen of ondernemen, ten nadele van den staat, of van's lands hoge overigheldt." See also 1.2.2. 178 1923 AD 73 at 81. on the facts of the case, it had not been proven that the appellant had the intention of overthrowing the government, but nevertheless convicted him of treason. On appeal it was argued on behalf of the appellant that treason requires an intention to overthrow the government, in the sense of either altering the form of the constitution or changing the personnel of the government. The objective of the strikers was only to induce the existing government to change its policy and practices in respect of the gold mines. The Appellate Division, after a thorough overview of the authorities, rejected the notion that proof of an intention to overthrow the government was a necessary condition of treason. According to Innes C J, "the whole structure of society might be shaken by the violent action of a body of men whose object was not to alter the constitution or change the government, but to compel the latter to obey their behests." 179 The Court regarded as decisive the question whether attempt by the strikers "to impose their will" upon there was an the government: In a struggle between two belligerent nations the object of each is to impose its will upon the other - not necessarily to change its constitution. And where a number of citizens, endeavouring by force of arms to impose their will upon the government, embark upon warlike operations ... a trial court is justified in drawing the conclusion that they were actuated by a hostile mind. 180 The basis for upholding the conviction consequently was the fact that he acted like an external enemy - he imposed his will upon or coerced the state. The intention to coerce the state is therefore regarded as a critical element of high treason. 181 The next question to be considered is whether any degree of coercion would suffice to constitute the crime of treason. The facts in Erasmus show that serious coercion was involved in that case. The accused led 179 At 82. This conclusion was again endorsed by the Appellate Division in R v Christian 1924 AD 101 at 134 and R v Leibbrandt 8, others 1944 AD 253 at 280. See also S v Mavekiso & others 1988 4 SA 738 (W) at 749. 180 At 82. According to Kotzé J A, the fact that the accused’s intention was "to compel the government of the Union to submit to the will of the strikers, or otherwise to render it powerless in the maintenance of law and order", was crucial. (At 83.) 181 See also R v Mardon 1948 1 SA 942 (A) at 945. one of several commandos, armed with fire-arms, in violent clashes with the police. These commandos inter alia took possession of a police station, and skirmishes. in total more than 200 people died in the ensuing 182 While some less-than-total attacks aimed at coercing the state can therefore qualify as treasonable, it should be obvious that this does not apply to all attempts to coerce the state. The takeover of a prison by inmates who are holding some wardens hostage and who demand prison reforms, will inevitably involve coercion of the state, but could hardly qualify as treason. The language used in Erasmus suggests that it is a question of how seriously the state is being coerced. The violent actions of the strikers in that case were described by the Court as "on no mean scale". 183 According to Innes C J the question whether a hostile intent existed was "a matter to be gathered from all the circumstances, of which the probable consequences of the actions taken are supremely important." 184 In R v Viljoen and others, 185 another Appellate Division decision based on the miners’ strike, the same approach was followed. In this case it was held that operations on hostile a intent considerable can scale be inferred undertaken from with the the "warlike object of forcibly imposing the will of the participators upon the government of their country." 186 Again, an intention to impose one’s will or to coerce the state in a serious manner was regarded as the feature that justified a finding of hostile intent, even in the absence of an intention to overthrow the state. This approach of the Appellate Division indicates that an intention to actually overthrow the government is not a necessary element of "hostile intent". On the other hand, an intention seriously to coerce the state is a sufficient condition. What is left open by these conclusions, however, is the question whether an intention to coerce 182 At 78. 183 At 83. 184 At 82. 185 WS AD 90. Approved in R v Christian 1924 AD 101 at 133. 186 At 92. the state is also a necessary element of hostile intent and whether an intent to overthrow the state, where present, can be a sufficient condition even if no coercion is involved. Coercion, as was stated earlier when the elements of civil disobedience were identified, may involve the use of force, but it may also be nonviolent. Almost all the reported cases in South Africa's legal history where people have been tried for treason involved the use of violence, either directly (in the form of an armed rebellion or insurrection in a time of external peace or physical participation in the military efforts of the enemy in time of war), or indirectly (through more indirect assistance to the enemy in a time of war). 187 In the trial of R v Leibbrandt and others 188 Schreiner J defined hostile intent as "intent to overthrow the government or to coerce it by force." 189 No doubt, coercion in the form of violence constitutes the usual manifestation of treason, but there is ample authority which suggests that it is not a 187 See eg S v Phillips & others (1896) 3 Off Rep 216 (members of the so-called "Reform Committee" convicted of treason after the Jameson Raid into the South African Republic); R v Boers (1900) 21 NLR 116 (citizens of Natal joined the Boer forces during the Second AngloBoer war); R v Gowthorpe (1900) 21 NLR 221 (accused joined the enemy in time of war); S v Randelhoff (1901) 22 NLR 59 (assistance given to the enemy in time of war); the "Cape treason trials" reported anonymously in the Cape Law Journal 1901 164 (taking up arms against the British government by Cape citizens sympathetic to the Boer cause during the second Anglo-Boer war); R v De Wet 1915 OPD 157 (instigating the 1914 rebellion against the government); R v Erasmus 1923 AD 73 and R v Viljoen & others 1923 AD 90 (taking part in armed clashes with government troops during the 1921 miners' strikes on the Rand); R v Wenzel 1940 WLD 269, R v Leibbrandt & others 1944 AD 253, R v Strauss 1948 1 SA 934 (A) and R v Neumann 1949 3 SA 1238 (SC) (assisting the enemy during the Second World War 1n various ways). See also S v Mange 1980 4 SA 613 (A) (members of the ANC Intended military attack on police and magistrates); S v Tsotsobe & others 1983 1 SA 856 (A) (members of the ANC attacked several civilian and state targets in South Africa); S v Lubisi & others 1982 3 SA 113 (A) (armed attack on police station by members of the ANC); S v Hogan 1983 2 SA 46 (W) (mere membership of the ANC and furtherance of its cause, without personal involvement in violence, held to be treasonable because of ANC's commitment at the time to violence); S v Gaber 1985 4 SA 734 (A) (explosions caused by members of the ANC) and R v Ramgobin & others 1986 1 SA 68 (N) (advancing the cause of the ANC and SACP through the use of violence). 188 189 Unreported case no G 1/42 SCC 1943. At 1950. (Emphasis added.) Approved by the court a quo in R _v Harden 1947 2 SA 768 (TSCC) at 774. necessary condition. Milton pointed out that the words "by force" in Schreiner's definition in Leibbrandt were not repeated when the case reached the Appellate Division. He argued that "unlawful but passive means of coercion, such as an illegal strike or 'passive resistance campaign'" can also involve coercion of the state that constitutes treason. Consequently, he argued, the words "by force" should be omitted from the definition of hostile intent. 190 The view that the use of force was not a necessary element of hostile intent was endorsed and followed others. 191 so-called in the case of S v Mayekiso and The accused was charged with "organs of people's treason for having established power" as a type of alternative government. They inter alia formed "people's courts" with their own disciplinary structures, which also executed sentences against those convicted. They also launched a number of boycott actions. According to the charge sheet, by doing this the accused attempted "to coerce the state". 192 The charge sheet, however, did not allege that the accused intended or actually used "violence towards the state". An application was brought for the discharge of the appellants, inter alia on the basis that, because such an allegation had not been made, the charge did not disclose the crime of treason. Consequently the Court had to decide whether "violence against the state" was a necessary element of treason. In a carefully conclusion that researched the use of judgment, violence Van der against Walt the J came state is to not the an essential element of treason. None of the old writers considered by the 190 Milton South African criminal law and procedure vol 2 27. Milton's observation in respect of Leibbrandt does not rest on solid ground, since the reference by the court a quo to "the requisite element of force" was indeed repeated in the Apellate Division. (At 280.) His remarks are premised on the explicit assumption that the strike or campaign is "coercive". No provision is made for the possibility of I non-coercive campaign of civil disobedience. The same probably applies to the remarks of Ackermann Die reg insake openbare orde en staatsveiligheid 14, in respect of "lydelike verset". 191 1988 4 SA 738 W, per Van der Walt J. 192 At 739. Court regarded violence as a necessary element of treason. 193 Van Leeuwen required an act "to the prejudice of the sovereign of the country or the state"; Huber a "plan against the safety or dignity of the sovereign power of the province"; Moorman an act "ten nadele van den staat"; Van der Keessel a plotting against the state's "dignity, safety, or sovereign authority", alternatively stated as an intention "to bring about the destruction of the people or of the Emperor." According to Van der Linden, treason is committed by someone who "endangers the independence or safety of the state." A survey of these writers led the Court to the conclusion that "anything done with the intent to act as an enemy towards the state ... is treason." 194 Violence against the state was consequently not considered a necessary element of treason, and the Court held that the charge sheet was therefore not defective. 195 The Court also identified itself with the approach of Schreiner J in the Leibbrandt-trial. 196 where it was noted that propaganda 197 plays a particularly important role in modern warfare, and for that reason stated that even if the authorities did require force as an element of treason (which they did not), it would no longer be appropriate in modern times. 198 It is clear, then, that in the view of the Mayekiso Judgment the net of treason must be cast sufficiently wide to cover more than just illegal acts of violence against the state. The question must consequently be asked exactly how wide the concept of treason has been extended. Which forms of coercion non-violent still action necessary, can or be can treasonable? non-coercive Is some acts of form of illegal "propaganda" be treasonable? It could possibly be argued that the idea 193 The following quotations are from the Court's summary at 743ff. 194 At 746. 195 The accused were, however, ultimately discharged. The state had not succeeded in presenting the evidence it had hoped to in order to substantiate the charge of treason. S v Mayekiso & others, unreported case no 115/89 W 24 April 1989. See also the comments by Van der Walt J, at 57, on the careful consideration which the framing of a charge of treason should enjoy. 196 Approved in R v leibbrandt & others 1944 AD 253 at 282. 197 As was mentioned earlier, Bertrand Russell described disobedience as a form of propaganda. See supra chap two I B. 198 At 750. civil that illegal propaganda can be treasonable even if it is non-coercive, finds some support in the Mayekiso Court's observation that "[i]n many cases [modern] warfare takes the form of insidious rebellion with hostile intent to unlawfully overthrow a particular state by any number of means." 199 Nevertheless, it is submitted that the Court's judgment should not be interpreted remains a as denying necessary that element the presence of some form of treason. In the first of coercion place, the Mayekiso Court (like Milton) only rejected the words "by force" in Schreiner J's definition of hostile intent. The words "or to coerce" were left untouched. Schreiner's reference to the use of propaganda furthermore applied in the context of physical assistance to the enemy during the Second World War, which means that propaganda was part and parcel of a wider coercive strategy. The factual situation in Mayekiso, moreover, was one of (indirect) coercion against the state. Lastly, as was pointed out earlier, the charge sheet in Mayekiso did allege that the accused had coerced the state. In S v Zwane and others(3) 200 the accused were charged with treason on the basis of facts similar to those in Mayekiso. The accused also set up alternative governmental structures, such which enforced their findings inter alia lashes with a sjambok. People were as "people's courts", through the imposition of physically prevented from co- operating with the police, and the accused conducted their own anticrime campaigns. The approach endangering of or the Court coercing the was to regard judicial unlawful authority of acts aimed at the state as treasonable, provided those acts were committed with the intention to impair the majestas of the state. 201 On the facts, however, the Court found that the state had not proved an objective on the part of the accused to "'compel the government to obey their behests', as it was put by Innes C J in the Erasmus case." 202 It appears from the above that an intention to use violence or force against the state is not a necessary element of treason. In one form or 199 At 751. 200 1989 3 SA 253 (W). 201 At 260. 202 At 318. another, however, the intention seriously to coerce the state (either violently or non-violently) has always been required. No convictions for treason in South African law could be found where this element was not present. The intention seriously to coerce the state should therefore be regarded not only as a sufficient but as a necessary element of "hostile intent". It follows that the intention to overthrow the state illegally but not coercively will not suffice to constitute treason. This approach ties up with the nature of the interest which treason endeavours to protect, namely the majestas of the state in the sense of its sovereignty. 203 This interest has also been "existence, independence and security" of the state. described 204 as the It is submitted that these terms refer to the state's position of dominance in society which allows it to make and enforce autonomous decisions. The only way in which this ability of the state can be threatened is through coercion of the state - that is, by forcing the state to make certain decisions, or by making it impossible for the state to make other decisions. This can be done directly through violent means, such as war and rebellion, or through non-violent means, such as campaigns aimed at flooding the prisons. It can also be done indirectly by assuming the function of the state, for example by setting governmental structures with their own coercive powers. up alternative 205 It cannot be done, however, by non-coercive civil disobedience that has as its aim to persuade (as opposed to coerce) the state to bring about change. Indeed, such civil disobedience is directed precisely at bringing about the making of autonomous decisions by the state, not at preventing it 203 Compare J 0 van der Vyver "The concept of political sovereignty" in Visser Essays In honour of Ellison Kahn 289. 204 See Snyman Criminal law 262. See also R v Adams & others 1959 1 SA 646 (SC) at 649. 205 According to Ackermann Die reg insake openbare orde en staatsveiligheid 14, the relevant question is: "Is die dwang gegrond op 'n oorname van owerheidsfunksies?" Traditionally a usurpation of the supreme functions of the state could take many forms, such as making war or peace, releasing hostages, and coining. See Anonymous 1938 SAU vol 55 14 at 16. The important fact in such cases is that the state is given no choice - the perpetrator imposes his will on it. The fact that the state is not the direct target of coercion should not detract from the fact that ultimately the intention is to coerce the state. A campaign of terror attacks, aimed at civilian targets, can after alt be treasonable. from taking place. Non-coercive civil disobedience can consequently not be treasonable, while a campaign of coercive civil disobedience, if the coercion is serious enough, can be treasonable. 206 In a number of cases, courts stated that treason can be directed not only against the independence or safety of the state but also against its authority. If these statements are correct and the term "authority" refers to the moral standing of government, then even non-coercive civil disobedience would threaten the interests protected by the crime of treason. In the majority of these cases, 207 however, it seems that what the Court meant when stating that an attack "on the authority of the state" can be treasonable was in fact that a limited attack on the independence or safety of the state, 208 or an attack aimed at the nonexecutive branches of government, 209 or an attack which is launched by an internal enemy, could constitute acts of treason. 210 In not one of those cases was the interest protected merely the moral standing of the government. The reason overthrow why the commentators state by traditionally illegal means as regarded a an intention to sufficient condition of treason, can be traced back to the assumption that any illegal attempt to overthrow the state must inevitably involve the use of force. This assumption, valid for many centuries, was explicitly made by Schreiner J in the trial of Leibbrandt: 206 See also S v Baleka & others, unreported case no 482/85 T 15 Nov 1988, at 79 of the reasons for judgment, where Van Dijkhorst J remarked that "propaganda or protest action which has the object of coercing the government in a certain direction might in given circumstances amount to high treason." The remarks of the prosecutor in S v Adams & others, unreported case no 1/58 SCC 1961, referred to by Rumpff J as "[i]nteresting and important", were also to the effect that a "passive resistance campaign" could be treasonable only if it was embarked upon "with the object of coercing the government". (At 25 of the reasons for judgment.) 207 See however, R v Colliers (1881) 1 Kotze 237 at 251. See in this regard also Milton South African criminal law and procedure vo1 2 28. 208 R v Erasmus 1923 AD 73 at 88. See also R v Christian 1924 AD 101 at 134. 209 S v Zwane & others (3) 1989 3 SA 253 (W) at 259. The reference in the latter case to Leibbrandt should be to pages 278-80 of that decision. 210 See, in R v Leibbrandt & others 1944 AD 253 at 278, the Court's "[p]utting [of] the same argument in another way". There is no intermediate course between constitutional action through the ballot box and treasonable action through the illegal use of force. Members of an organization may not themselves desire to use bombs or other weapons, but this will not avail them if their purpose is to act outside the constitution to achieve their ends. 211 This approach was possibly warranted before the development of the technique of civil disobedience as an instrument of mass mobilization, capable of challenging the state in its entirety, but times have changed. In fact, hardly four years after the judgment in Leibbrandt. India became independent subsequent to a protracted struggle with England in which Gandhi’s acts of civil disobedience, which were aimed at bringing about a "peaceable revolution", played a significant role. Nine years later civil disobedience challenged the very foundations of the South African state. The question how the proposed approach - according to which an intention seriously to coerce the state is regarded as a necessary and sufficient condition of a treasonable intention - should be administered in practice need not unduly detain us. Hostile intent could for example be defined as an intention to endanger the existence, independence and/or security of the state through coercion. The words "through coercion" can also be taken to be implied in the phrase "endanger the existence". The point for present purposes is simply that serious coercion of the state is an essential element of treason. How serious this coercion must be, has to be determined with reference to the criterion underlying all forms of unlawfulness - namely the legal convictions of the community. In this regard considerations such as freedom of expression, state security and the general criteria used to determine the relationship between the individual and the state, should be taken into account. In the latter regard something along the lines of the "clear and present danger" test seems indispensable. 212 211 R v Leibbrandt & others, unreported case no G 1/42 SCC 1943, at 1970. See also S v Adams & others, unreported case no 1/58 SCO 1961, and S v Baleka & others, unreported case no CC 482/85 T 15 Nov 1988, at 88, 89. Milton South African criminal law and procedure vol 2 28 maintained that "someone who intends - perhaps only for a short period of time or among a small section of the community - simply to promote defiance of the government’s authority, can scarcely be said to Intend its 'overthrow'." He does not address the possibility of a more ambitious campaign of civil disobedience. 212 For a discussion, see infra chap six IV B (2). To summarise: According to the orthodox position, an intention to illegally overthrow the state is not a necessary element of a hostile intention, but it is sufficient. According to this approach, a nonviolent campaign aimed at the illegal overthrow of the state can be treasonable, whether coercion is used or not. It is argued that the orthodox position is wrong. The intention to overthrow the state illegally is neither a sufficient nor a necessary element of hostile intention. The intention seriously to coerce the state is both a necessary and a sufficient element. A campaign of civil disobedience can consequently serious constitute coercion. treason Non-coercive if, and civil only if, it disobedience involves cannot be treasonable, even if it has revolutionary objectives, but a coercive campaign can qualify as treason. To put this in concrete terms: an army of Gandhis who trespass on government property throughout the country, demanding a change of government, cannot be convicted of treason, but members of a nationwide non-violent movement which sets out to block the major roads in the big cities of the country for a couple of weeks, making government impossible in order to bring it to a fall, may be so convicted. One last point must be tied up. It was stated at the outset that, where serious coercion is involved, even if violence is absent, it makes little sense to treat protest actions as acts of civil disobedience. Civil disobedience involves little or no coercion. Since treason involves serious coercion, it follows that, if a campaign of protest is coercive enough to qualify as treasonable (as with the blocking of the roads example), it has in all likelihood ceased to be civil disobedience. In this respect civil disobedience and treason can be regarded, for all practical purposes, as mutually exclusive concepts. (2) Sedition The question will next be considered whether civil disobedience can constitute sedition. Again it is a question of comparing the definitions. The definition of civil disobedience need not be repeated. According to Milton: "Sedition consists in unlawfully gathering, together with a number of people, with the intention of impairing the majestas of the state by defying or subverting the government, but without the intention of authority of its overthrowing or coercing that government." 213 According to Snyman "[s]edition consists in the unlawful and intentional gathering of a number of people in order violently to challenge, defy or resist the authority of the Republic of South Africa, or the unlawful and intentional causing of such a gathering with such a purpose." 214 The two definitions differ on the question whether violence is a necessary element of the crime. We will return to this matter later on. A common feature of the definitions is their identifying the protected interest as the authority of the state and the act by means of which it is done as defiance. 215 "Authority" in this respect has been described as the "[p]ower supremacy, "Defy" the was revolt at" or right defined, 217 right to to enforce command, inter a1ia. or as obedience: give to an moral ultimate "reject, or legal decision." 216 renounce, disdain, . It should consequently be clear that sedition is aimed at protecting exactly what civil disobedience notoriously can undermine, namely respect for the government and its laws: that is, respect for its authority. Can civil disobedience then constitute sedition? According to the definition of Milton, sedition is per definition non-revolutionary and non-coercive, which means that non-revolutionary and non-coercive acts of civil disobedience can in principle be seditious. Snyman, however, regarded at least a threat of violence as an essential element of sedition. 218 If this latter view is correct it would imply that civil disobedience cannot be seditious. In this vein Snyman argued that a mere gathering of preservationists on Church Square, Pretoria, to protest against a government decision to demolish the old buildings forming the western facade of the square, would not be sedition, even if it were held in defiance of the government's 213 Milton South African criminal law and procedure vol 2 46. 214 Snyman Criminal law 263. 215 See also R v Klaas and others 1915 CPO 58 at 63; R v Endemann 1915 TPD 142 at 147 and R v Viljoen & others 1923 AD 90 at 97. 216 S v Twala & others 1979 3 SA 864 (T) at 870. 217 Ibid. 218 See also Snyman SALJ 1980 14 at 21. The author argued that the view of the Court in S v Twala & others 1979 3 SA 864 (T) at 869, that "violence is certainly not an essential part of the seditions gathering," cannot be accepted without the qualification that there must at least be a threat of violence. ban on public gatherings. It would only become a seditious gathering once the participants violently defied a police order to disperse or once they threatened forcibly to prevent the bulldozers from proceeding with the demolition. 219 However, in a number of decisions over the past few years the view that sedition does not require the use or the threat of violence has been endorsed. In S v Zwane and others (1) 220 Grosskopf J stated that a seditious gathering need not necessarily involve an uprising or riot, or be coupled with clamour, uproar, violence or threats of violence. It seems to me requires a gathering in that the weight of authority only defiance of the authorities unlawful purpose to constitute the crime of sedition. for an 221 This statement was based on the dictum of De Villiers J P in R v Endemann 222 that sedition "takes the form of a gathering or gatherings, in defiance of the lawfully constituted authorities, for some unlawful purpose." 223 In S v Mayekiso and others, 224 Van der Walt J stated that "violence towards the state, either actual or contemplated, is not a necessary element in the crime of sedition," 225 If this approach, which currently seems to be the prevailing one as far as the courts are concerned, is carried through to its logical conclusion, it would follow that there is no principled reason why a civil disobedience constitute sedition. campaign - whether coercive or not - cannot 226 Before a conviction for sedition can follow, it must be established that the necessary intention be present. That is, there must be an intention not merely to break the law, but also to defy the authority 219 Snyman SALJ 1980 14 at 22. 220 1987 4 SA 369 (W). See also S v Zwane & others (3) 1989 3 SA 253 (W) at 261. 221 At 374. 222 1915 TPD 142. 223 At 147. 224 1988 4 SA 738 (W). 225 At 751. See also S v Mayekiso & others, unreported case no 115/89 W 24 April 1989, at 56 of the reasons for judgment. 226 It should be noted that according to the definition of Milton sedition cannot involve violence, while in terms of the cases cited sedition can be violent but need not be. of the state. As was stated in S v Zwane and others (3), 227 "it is the authority of the state that has to be defied or assailed intentionally and a gathering with the intention to breach the law or to commit a crime would gathering." in itself not be sufficient to constitute a seditious 228 It seems then that this matter must also be looked at from the angle of the interests protected: the question is what sort of action can pose a sufficiently serious threat to the authority of the state, as defined earlier, to constitute sedition. It appears incontestable that the "moral and legal supremacy" of the state can be challenged through a campaign of civil disobedience. If the common law writers did not make provision for this form of challenge in their definitions of sedition, as Snyman maintained, 229 it is probably because this form of protest was largely unknown to them. And, indeed, it seems that Snyman also does not take the possibility of a full-scale campaign of civil disobedience into account. In a more refined version of the stark choice posed by Schreiner in Leibbrandt between constitutional and violent protest, 230 Snyman said that "[i]f there is no actual violence, there must at least be threats of violence. A crowd gathering unlawfully but dispersing peacefully at the request of the police can hardly be said to commit sedition." 231 Granted, but what, one may ask, about the case where crowds across the country do not "disperse peacefully" at the request of the police but also do not engage in violent resistance? That is, what if the crowd's actions are part of a sustained campaign of civil disobedience? It is submitted that there is in principle no reason why their conduct cannot be seditious. The above should not be taken to mean that all those who engage in unlawful gatherings aimed against the authority of the state commit sedition. A few observations should requirement of unlawfulness. 227 1989 3 SA 253 (W). 228 At 261. 229 Snyman SALJ 1980 14 at 22. 230 See supra chap four I D (1). 231 Snyman SALJ 1980 14 at 21. be made in respect of the It is not sufficient that the dissident gathering should knowingly be in breach of a legal provision. For example, a heated political meeting does not become seditious if the fire-regulations pertaining to the number of people allowed into the hall are knowingly violated. Unlawfulness of the primary offence must be the vehicle through which the authority of the state is being defied. Also, not all acts of unlawful defiance of the authority of the state would qualify as seditious. If a number of neighbours, in order to protest municipal restrictions on the use of water in their gardens, agree that they will a11 turn on their sprayers at a pre-arranged time when it is forbidden, their conduct can hardly be said to constitute sedition. Arguably, the decision of a group of people to engage in what was called legality-based civil disobedience, that is where a claim of right is being made, would also not qualify as sedition. In order to comply with the requirement of unlawfulness for the purposes of sedition, the action must in a serious way challenge the authority of the state. In making the decision whether the challenge to the authority of the state is serious enough to warrant a conviction of sedition, a court will have to take into account the same matters referred to under the heading of treason - such as freedom of speech, the danger posed by such action, and so on. 232 (3) Terrorism The crime of terrorism as it stands today is codified in section 54(1) of the Internal Security Act 74 of 1982. 233 Since violence in one form or another is an element of terrorism," 234 it 1s clear that acts of civil disobedience (which are per definition non-violent) cannot 232 Recognition of the fact that the accused had no other effective channel through which to voice their grievances (such as the vote) seems to underlie Van der Walt J's decision in S v Mayeklso & others. unreported case no 115/89 W 24 April 1989, that the "Alexandra Five", who had established alternative governmental structures in the townships, were not guilty of sedition. For a discussion of this case, see Bi1a et a1 SALJ 1989 595. 233 Previously defined in s 2 of the Terrorism Act 83 of 1967. For a discussion on the effects of the old provision on acts of civil disobedience, see Dugard Human rights and the South African legal order 174. On the relationship between the old and the new provisions, see S v Hpetha 1985 3 SA 702 (A). 234 25. See Ackermann Die reg insake openbare orde en staatsveiligheid constitute terrorism. (4) Subversion The crime of subversion was created by section 54(2) of the Internal Security Act 74 of 1982, which lists a variety of ways in which this crime can be committed. 235 Some of these possibilities involve the use of violence, but violence is not a necessary element of the offence. 236 Since it would be virtually impossible to summarise the relevant provisions, they have to be outlined in some detail. Section 54(2) provides that any person who, with the intent described in section 54(1), namely to (a) overthrow or endanger the state authority in the Republic; (b) achieve, bring about or promote any constitutional, political, industrial, social or economic aim or change in the Republic; (c) induce the Government of the Republic to do or to abstain from doing any act or to adopt or to abandon a particular standpoint; or (d) ... demoralize the general public, a particular population group or the inhabitants of a particular area in the Republic, or to induce the said public or such population group or inhabitants to do or to abstain from doing any act, [does any of the following:] (a) causes or promotes general dislocation or disorder at any place in the Republic, or attempts to do so; (b) cripples, prejudices or interrupts at any place in the Republic any industry or undertaking, or industries or undertakings generally, or the production, supply or distribution of commodities or foodstuffs, or attempts to do so; (c) interrupts, impedes or endangers at any place in the 235 For a general discussion, see Ackermann Die reg Insake openbare orde en staatsvei1igheid 29ff and Mathews Freedom, state security and the rule of law 38ff. See also S v Radebe 1988 1 SA 772 (A). 236 Where violence is present, even if it was not intended, it can be a statutorily recognised aggravating circumstance. Section 54(2)(ii) provides that "if the act with which the accused had been charged and by virtue of which he was convicted resulted in the commission of violence and the Court is of the opinion that in performing the said act the accused should have foreseen the commission of such violence as a reasonable possibility," imprisonment for a period not exceeding 25 years can be imposed. Republic the manufacture, storage, generation, distribution, rendering or supply of fuel, petroleum products, energy, light, power or water or of sanitary, medical, health, educational, police, fire-fighting, ambulance, postal or telecommunication services or radio or television transmitting, broadcasting or receiving services or any other public service, or attempts to do so; (d) endangers, damages, destroys, renders useless or unserviceable or puts out of action at any place in the Republic any installation for the rendering or supply of any service referred to in paragraph (c), any prohibited place or any public building, or attempts to do so; (e) prevents or hampers, or deters any person from assisting in, the maintenance of law and order at any place in the Republic, or attempts to do so; (f) impedes or endangers at any place in the Republic the free movement of any traffic on land, at sea or in the air, or attempts to do so; (g) causes, encourages or foments feelings of hostility between different population groups or parts of population groups in the Republic, or attempts to do so [or in a variety of ways commits acts related to the above] shall (i) It should be guilty of conviction – the offence of subversion and liable on to imprisonment for a period not exceeding twenty years. be clear that these provisions can in many cases be transgressed by means of both coercive and non-coercive acts of civil disobedience. Most successful campaigns of civil disobedience would cause or promote "general dislocation or disorder ... in the Republic" in contravention of subsection (a), if coupled with the intent to bring about one of the wide range of consequences listed in the Act. 237 The blocking of highways is explicitly covered by subsection (f). The wide reach of the "common purpose" doctrine in this regard should also be noted. 238 Another obvious provision under which charges based on acts of civil disobedience can be brought, is subsection 2(e). Consequently, it can be said that nothing in principle seems to preclude a charge of subversion from being based on acts of civil disobedience, as long as the required intent is present. 239 237 See Minister of Law and Order v Pavlicevic 1989 3 SA 679 (A) at 690. 238 See S v Safatsa & others 1988 1 SA 868 (A) at 894. 239 See Ackermann Die reg insake openbare orde en staatsveiligheid Lastly, it is important to note that according to section 69(5) of the same Act, in prosecutions in terms of section 54(1) and 54(2), if it is proved that "the accused has committed any act alleged in the charge, and if such act resulted or was likely to have resulted" in the achievement of any of the objects set out in respect of these crimes, it is rebuttably presumed that the necessary intention was present. (5) Sabotage Section 54(3) of the Internal Security Act 74 of 1982 defines the present meaning of the crime sabotage. 240 of incredibly wide range of behaviour. 241 The crime covers an It entails the commission of any act, attempt to commit an act etc, with the intention 242 to bring about any of the consequences listed in paragraphs (b), (c), (d), (f) or (h) under the crime of subversion, or to "endanger the safety, health or interests of conviction, the public offenders are in any liable place in to maximum a the Republic." 243 of twenty Upon years' imprisonment. The extraordinary wide reach of these provisions is evident from the fact that, on a literal interpretation of section 54(3), even the nonviolent disruption of the activities of a home bakery can qualify as sabotage. 244 The need to limit the range of this statutory provision has been explicitly recognised by the Appellate Division. 245 In practice, however, it seems that the particular section has not featured prominently in prosecution for acts of civil disobedience. One reason is certainly the wide range of other options open to the state. (6) Defeating or obstructing the course of justice The crime of defeating or obstructing the course of justice is defined as an unlawful act which is intended to defeat or obstruct, and in fact 32. 240 Previously, sabotage was circumscribed differently, in s 21 of the General Law Amendment Act 76 of 1962. 241 See Ackermann Die reg insake openbare orde en staatsvei1igheid 33ff and Mathews Freedom, state security and the rule of law 4lff. 242 Dolus directus is required. S v Nel 1989 4 SA 845 (A). 243 Section 54(3)(a). 244 See Ackermann Die reg Insake openbare orde en staatsvei1igheid 245 S v Radebe 1988 1 SA 772 (A). 34. does defeat and obstruct, the due administration of justice. 246 It was mentioned in the historical survey of civil disobedience in South Africa that one of the expressed aims of some of the organisers of the Defiance Campaign and the Positive Action Campaign was to flood the prisons. This would in turn cause the breakdown of the whole system of the administration of criminal justice. It is conceivable that such action can constitute the crime of defeating or obstructing the course of justice, or at least an attempt to do so. II. EXECUTIVE POWERS AND CIVIL DISOBEDIENCE The above survey focused on provisions of the criminal law which, to a greater or a lesser extent, have a bearing on civil disobedience, insofar as acts of civil disobedience may come within the confines of specific statutory or common law provisions. At least in a formal sense, the rule of law prevails in respect of the above provisions, in that an attempt (with varying degrees of success) was made to establish publicly the basis on which the wrath of the on those who resist it, and the state would be unleashed implementation of these measures is mostly left to the courts. The picture would, however, be incomplete if reference is not also made, however brief, to the ability - and tendency - of the executive to use powers, the exercise of which to a greater or lesser extent lies in its own discretion, to curtail activities which it disapproves of, including the promotion or practice of civil disobedience. These executive powers include the pervasive security powers of the South African government, as well as the censorship system. A. EXECUTIVE POWERS RELATING TO STATE SECURITY The security powers of the state 247 can be divided into the categories of so-called "non-emergency powers" and "emergency powers". (1) Non-emergency powers The non-emergency or regular powers of government relate to various ways in which people can be detained without trial and restrictions can 246 See Snyman Criminal law 299 and S v Burger 1975 2 SA 601 (C) at 611. See also, on contempt of court, R v Pitje 1960 4 SA 709 (A), discussed supra chap three III A (3)(c)(vi). 247 The general Issue of state security is discussed at some length infra chap six III B (5). be imposed on individuals, official declaration of an (d) organizations and events, without the emergency or unrest situation. Detention Two forms of detention without trial has traditionally been authorised in terms of South Africa’s non-emergency security legislation: "preventative detention", which is "designed to remove certain actors from the stage of public life because they are deemed to be a threat to its orderly conduct" and "pre-trial detention", which is designed to facilitate the conduct of a trial. 248 A government that has assumed these powers and which is intent upon eradicating acts or campaigns of civil disobedience, can be expected to take recourse especially to preventative detention. 249 Preventative detention, as provided for in the Internal Security Act 74 of 1982, has in turn manifested itself in three different ways. In the first place, until July 1991, indefinite preventative detention could be imposed by the Minister of Law and Order." 250 Secondly, detention for a period of up to 180 days could be authorised by a commissioned police officer of or above the rank of lieutenant-colonel. 251 This provision has now also been repealed. 252 Lastly, according to a provision which is still in force, an officer of or above the rank of warrant officer may, under warrant from a magistrate, order detention of up to fourteen days. 253 (b) "Banning" The executive has the power to "ban" organizations, individuals and meetings. 248 This means that the activities of organizations or See Mathews Freedom, state security and the rule of law 62. 249 The distinction between these two categories is not watertight, in that pre-trial detention is also used to remove people from the political arena. For a discussion of pre-trial detention measures, see Mathews Freedom, state security and the rule of law 78ff. 250 Section 28. For a discussslon, see Id 63ff. This provision was repealed by s 12 of the Internal Security and Intimidation Amendment Act 138 of 1991. 251 Section 50A. For a discussion, see Id 77ff. 252 By s 18 of the Internal Security and Intimidation Amendment Act 138 of 1991. 253 Section 50. For a discussion, see id 75ff. individuals, or the holding of meetings may be subjected to far- reaching restrictions or that organizations or meetings may in fact be declared unlawful. (i) "Banning" of organizations The Internal Security Act 74 of 1982 confers virtually unrestricted powers on the Minister of Justice to declare organizations unlawful and hence to render any association with such organizations an offence. 254 This provision and its fore-runners have been used to silence a wide array of protest movements which at one time or another have been involved in organising campaigns of civil disobedience. 255 (ii) "Banning" of -individuals Until July 1991, the Internal Security Act 74 of 1982 vested in the Minister of Justice a virtually unrestrained discretion to curtail the personal freedom of individuals in respect of membership of organizations, presence at certain places, attendance of gatherings, etc. 256 (iii) "Banning" of meetings The executive also has the power, when it deems it necessary in the interests of manifestation state of security, civil to disobedience prohibit would nevertheless proceed with such meetings. 254 certain occur if gatherings. the A organisers 257 See ss 4(1) and 13. 255 The Communist Party of South Africa was first declared an unlawful organization by s 2(1) of the Internal Security Act 44 of 1950. The ANC and the PAC were declared unlawful organizations in accordance with the Unlawful Organisations Act 34 of 1960, by means of Proc 119, Government Gazette Extraordinary 6414, 8 April 1960. The position was perpetuated through the inclusion of these organizations in Schedule 4 of the Internal Security Act 74 of 1982. A11 these organizations were unbanned on 3 February 1990 by means of Proc R21, Government Gazette 12287, 3 Fob 1990. Another way in which the actions of an organization can drastically be curtailed is by means of the Affected Organizations Act 31 of 1974. Organizations which are declared "affected" are prevented from receiving financial assistance from abroad. 256 Sections 18-22, now repealed by s 12 of the Internal Security and Intimidation Amendment Act 138 of 1991. The fore-runner of these provisions was s 10 of the Internal Security Act 44 of 1950. 257 See, for example, regarding the period just before the Defiance Successive South African governments have for a long time taken upon themselves the power to exercise strict control over public gatherings. The Riotous Assemblies and Criminal Law Amendment Act 27 of 1914, which conferred upon magistrates the power to prohibit public meetings in their districts in order to preserve the public peace, made it an offence to attend, advertise, etc such meetings. 258 This legislation was later re-enacted and expanded upon; first by the Riotous Assemblies Act 17 of 1956 259 and later by the Internal Security Act 74 of 1982. 260 Today, section 57 of the convening, advertising, prohibited in terms of last-mentioned attending, the Act etc by a Act prohibits gathering either the anyone which has magistrate from been of the particular district, or the Minister of Law and Order, or which is not held in accordance with the conditions laid down for such gatherings by the magistrate or the Minister. (2) Emergency powers The most important emergency powers of the state are contained in the Public Safety Act 3 of 1953. 261 These powers can be divided into two categories: The State President has the power to declare "macro" or more extensive emergencies (a "state of emergency" is declared in a certain area), and the Minister of Law and Order has the power to declare "micro" or less extensive emergencies (a certain area is declared an "unrest area"). (e) "Macro emergencies" The Public Safety Act 3 of 1953 empowers the State President to declare a twelve month state of emergency if he is of the opinion that "the safety of the public, or the maintenance of public order" is seriously threatened, and that the ordinary law of the land is inadequate to deal Campaign of 1952, when a number of leaders defied orders to resign from the organizations responsible for the Campaign and not to participate in public gatherings, supra chap three III A (3)(1). See, in general, on state control over public meetings, Pretorius Die begrip openbare belang en burgervryheidsbeperking 227ff. 258 See supra chap four II A (D(b)(iii). 259 Section 2. 260 Sections 46-53. 261 For a discussion of the other emergency powers at the disposal of the state, see Mathews Freedom, state security and the rule of law 215. with the situation. 262 In 1960 a state of emergency was declared in virtually the entire country, and it remained in force for 156 days. 263 The limited state of emergency announced in 1985 was expanded to cover the entire country in 1986. It was renewed from time to time until 1990. 264 The State President is authorised to proclaim regulations in areas where a declared emergency is in force. Such regulations have in the past greatly enhanced the powers of the police to detain people without trial, to preclude access to legal representation and to use force against people who fail to respond to an order to proceed to any place or to desist from specified conduct. 265 In terms of the Emergency Regulations in force during the 1980’s, it was also an statement", 266 offence defined, to make, inter possess alia. as or disseminate "a statement "a which subversive contains anything which is calculated to have the effect or is likely to have the effect ... of inciting the public or any person or category of persons to ... take part in any acts of civil disobedience." 267 These powers have disobedience. (f) A indeed been used to curb the practice of civil 268 "Micro emergencies" 1986 262 amendment to the Public Safety Act introduced a mechanism Section 2. 263 For a discussion, see Mathews Law, order and liberty In South Africa 224. 264 For a discussion, see Du Plessis & Olivier SAPL 1987 84, 197; SAPL 1988 111, 267; SAPL 1989 95, 290; SAPL 1990 260 and SAPL 1991 126. 265 For a general discussion of the effect of these regulations, see Burns Woord en Daad 1988 7. 266 See eg s 10 of Proc 109, Regulation Gazette 3964, Government Gazette 10280, 12 June 1986. 267 268 Id s 1 viii (b) iv; definition of "subversive statement". In 1987, for example, an affidavit by a police sergeant revealed that two journalists were detained in terms of the regulations under the state of emergency because they had planned to publish "in a newsletter, news about radical persons and organizations in which the community would be incited to civil disobedience." See "Newsmen still trying for freedom" City Press 28 June 1987. whereby the Minister of Law and Order can declare certain areas to be "unrest areas" 269. Although the initial declaration can be valid for a maximum of only three, months, the provisions which govern abridgments of legal processes that can be authorised in the case of a micro emergency are substantially the same as those which apply in the case of the macro emergencies. 270 B. CENSORSHIP AND STATE SECURITY Executive control of matters perceived to affect state security can also be found in the country’s elaborate and controversial censorship system. 271 The statutory foundation of the censorship system is the Publications Act 42 of 1974. This Act provides for an administrative structure with, as its highest "appellate" authority, the Publications Appeal Board (the "PAB"), 272 which has the power to declare certain publications "undesirable". 273 It constitutes an offence to produce 274 or distribute 275 an undesirable prohibited. publication. In some cases possession may also be 276 In terms of section 47(2)(e), a publication may be declared undesirable if it is found to be "prejudicial to the safety of the state, the general welfare or the peace and good order." Clearly, this provision could have far-reaching implications for those who wish to promote a campaign of civil disobedience through the media. The scope of those implications depends on the exact meaning of this clause. What exactly does the particular provision attempt to protect, and what criterion 269 Public Safety Amendment Act 67 of 1986. 270 See Mathews Freedom, state security and the rule of law 214. 271 For a discussion of the trends in and criticisms of the system, see Van der Vyver De Jure 1988 182; G Marcus "Reasonable censorship?" in Corder Essays on law and social practice in South Africa 349 and Van der Westhuizen SAJHR 1990 425. 272 The Supreme Court has no appellate Jurisdiction in matters of censorship but can exercise a power of review over the proceedings of the PAB. Section 39. 273 The term "publication" is used here to include any object, film or public entertainment as defined in s 47(1). 274 Section 8(1)(a). 275 Section 8(1)(b). 276 Section 8(1)(d). should be applied to establish whether a sufficiently serious threat to this interest exists to warrant a finding that a particular publication is undesirable? First, then, the interest protected must be considered. According to Kobus van Rooyen, a former chairperson of the PAB, "[i]t would seem that the interests protected by this paragraph are related to a society which is free of political violence." 277 The only threats to the "safety of the state, general welfare or the peace and good order" which, according to this approach, can render a publication undesirable are those which involve violence, either actual or potential. If this view were correct, it would follow that the promotion of civil disobedience could not bring a publication within the reach of section 47(2)(e), since civil disobedience is per definition non-violent. What, then, is the criterion to be used in this regard? According to Van Rooyen the PAB has held itself guided by the "clear and present danger" doctrine of the United States Supreme Court - hastening, however, to add that this is limited to that doctrine’s requiring a real threat and that s[ection] 47(2)(e) goes further by employing the term "prejudicial", which, even if read with "is" points to a (substantial) contribution being sufficient and that an "imminent" danger is not a requirement. 278 The threat posed by the publication in order to render it undesirable consequently need not be "imminent" or "present" - it, must simply be "real" or "clear". According to Van Rooyen, this means that section 47(2)(e) "obviously deems more material to be undesirable than [the clear and This present danger] doctrine would." 279 interpretation, publication fanciful, if correct, would render it easy to find a undesirable if there is any chance, however remote or that the publication in question may lead to serious disruptions of the safety of the state, the general welfare or the peace and good order by the protesters themselves, or eventually by the community at large. The question whether or not a danger is imminent or present would be immaterial. It is submitted that, purely on the level of statutory interpretation. 277 Id 105. 278 Id note 54. 279 Ibid. Van Rooyen’s identification of the interest protected by section 47(2)(e) is too narrow, while his exposition of the criterion according to which possible threats to that interest are to be evaluated is too wide. In respect of the interest protected, the language used in section 47(2)(e) seems to leave little doubt that it is aimed not only against the promotion of violence, but turbulence. It was argued earlier also against other forms of social that there are many non-violent, yet expression. 280 Again, highly coercive, ways in which protest can find the familiar example of the sealing off of a city’s highways could be referred to. The advocacy of such acts through publications clearly could compromise the "peace and good order" and there appears to be no reason why it could not come within the range of section 47(2)(e). It is consequently submitted that the section is directed not only against political violence, but also against certain instances of non-violent political expression. In principle, the promotion of civil disobedience cannot be excluded. With regard to the criterion to be applied when determining whether a threat to public order is serious enough to warrant a finding of 281 as undesirabi1ity, it is submitted that the words "is prejudicial" used in section 47(2)(e) pose a clear requirement of imminence or presence of the danger. The language used in fact conveys this idea in particularly strong terms. What is required by the section is not merely the potentiality of prejudice (a "danger" or a "threat") but actual prejudice. The use of the present tense form of the verb "is", instead of the imperative "can be", indicates the requirement that the probability of the violence should actually be present. It consequently seems that the wording of section 47(2)(e) is more closely comparable with the present increasing First Amendment jurisprudence on the emphasis in American requirement of imminence than with the classical clear and present danger approach. 282 Presumably the introduction of a freedom of speech clause in the South African constitution will compel the PAB to adhere to a more liberal criterion 280 See supra chap two I B. 281 In the Afrikaans text, which was signed by the State President, the words "nadelig is" are used. 282 See Cheh SAJHR 1986 29. in this regard. In spite of the above, the PAB in practice uses the "clear and present danger" test, and has in the past, in its adjudication of section 47(2)(e), speech. followed a course that is generally protective of free 283 The PAB aligned itself with the "free trade in ideas" philosophy which underlies the protection of speech. 284 It also recognised the need to allow "sharp political criticism" and emphasised the "safety function of uninhibited speech. 285 purposes, however, is the fact that Most instructively for our present the PAB has accepted the that "claims of national security must always be viewed degree valve" approach with a high of scepticism", and that there "cannot be a search for total security". 286 In respect of the approach to be followed in times when a "revolutionary climate" is said to exist, the PAB did not regard the existence of a state of emergency as conclusive proof that the interests protected by section 47(2)(e) are more vulnerable than at other times. 287 The PAB’s approach regarding publications 283 encouraging civil See Grassroots 54/85, where it was stated that s 47(2)(e) serves to protect the state, inter alia. from civil disobedience. On the basis of the "clear and present danger" doctrine, the publication in question was described as "provocative" but not "undesirable". In Anti-SAIC News 38/83 the PAB endorsed the dictum in Whitney v California 274 US 357 (1927) at 377 that "no danger flowing from speech can be deemed clear and present unless the incidence of the ev11 apprehended is so imminent that it may befall before there is opportunity for full discussion." See also SASPU National 107/84. In SASPU National 105/83 the PAB adopted the approach in Abrams v United States 250 US 616 (1919) at 630 that the expressions of opinion considered dangerous should not be suppressed "unless they so imminently threaten immediate interference with the lawful and pressing purposes of the law that an immediate check is required to save the country." The courts also held that the danger must be immediate before speech is banned. In United Democratic Front (Western Cape Region) v Theron NO 1984 1 SA 315 (C) the Court remarked that a "slight or remote danger" is not enough to warrant the prohibition of a public meeting in terms of s 46 of the Internal Security Act 74 of 1982. 284 See SASPU National 105/83. 285 See Grassroots 200/83 Annexure. 286 SASPU National 221/84. 287 Two Dogs and Freedom 129/86. disobedience, however, is not entirely clear. The Board has held that the "ultimate question is whether the [publication in question] will contribute to a violation of state security and good order and the general welfare by contributing to terrorism, sabotage ... and civil disobedience." 288 On the other hand, it also stated that "the mere call for a boycott undesirable." In Benoni or a strike - even an unlawful strike - is not 289 Student Movement, 290 the PAB declared a publication undesirable, stating that the main problem [of the publication] centres around the fact that the majority of the articles have civil disobedience as their basis. In some cases this kind of action is directly promoted by the use of references to the deprivation and frustration of the blacks in the areas of education, health, labour, housing and welfare. The PAB’s view that the publication was undesirable was based on its finding that "[t]he present publication is opposed to the whole system. The publication is also interlarded with typical socialistic terminology. In this manner extra-constitutional methods of change are subtlety (sic) and even directly propagated." The above decision provides a good example of the need for the PAB to give recognition decision is any to the requirement indication given of of imminence. facts that Nowhere go to in show the that disorders might ensue on a scale large enough to warrant the banning of speech in consequence of civil disobedience incited by the particular publication. In view of the above, it is submitted that publications promoting civil disobedience can in principle be brought within the ambit of section 47(2)(e), but then only when the danger of grave social upheaval is imminent. C. EXECUTIVE LENIENCY FOR POLITICAL OFFENDERS There are a number of ways open to the executive, should it want to show leniency to political offenders. The state may, for 288 Grassroots 54/85. See also Izwe lase Township 144/82, 289 See Grassroots 200/83 and Heartland 43/82 Annexure. 290 159/81. example, refuse to prosecute, withdraw charges, stop a prosecution, 291 reduce a term of imprisonment, 292 or grant a pardon. 293 In order to facilitate the present process of negotiations between the government and previously outlawed organizations, the Indemnity Act 35 of 1990 was passed, increasing the government’s options in this regard. According to the preamble to this Act, "for the sake of reconciliation and for the finding of peaceful solutions," provision was made for the granting of temporary immunity as well as permanent indemnity by the executive to those against whom criminal charges could be instigated or were pending. In terms of the Indemnity Act the State President may, "if he is of the opinion that it is necessary constitutional solutions for in South the promotion of peaceful Africa," grant either conditional or unconditional immunity from prosecution to any person or category of persons 294 for a stipulated period. 295 Similarly, indemnity from prosecution - either conditional or unconditional - may be granted to any person or category of persons. 296 In the course of discussions between the government and the ANC, the so-called "Groote Schuur Minute" and "Pretoria Minute" were agreed upon. Following these discussions the government issued some guidelines regarding its approach to political offences. 297 In this latter document it was stated that "[i]n the interests of the process of reconciliation the government considers it appropriate that all persons, irrespective of their affiliations, who have committed political offences in the South African situation, should be considered for the grant of pardon or indemnity. 298 291 In terms of s 6(2)(d) of the Criminal Procedure Act 51 of 1977. 292 In terms of ss 61-72 of the Prisons Act 8 of 1959. 293 In terms of s 6 of the Republic of South Africa Constitution Act 110 of 1983. See also ss 325-327 of the Criminal Procedure Act 51 of 1977. 294 Section 1(1). 295 Section 1(2). 296 Section 2. 297 Government Notice R 2625, Government Gazette 12834 Regulation Gazette 4584, 7 Nov 1990. 298 Paragraph 1.3. A set of guidelines were adopted, in terms of which the following considerations should be taken into account when the grant of pardon or indemnity is considered: (i) The motive of the offender, ie whether the offence was committed for a political motive (eg to further or oppose the aims of a political organization, institution or body) or for a personal motive. (ii) The context in which the offence was committed; in particular whether it was committed in the course of or as part of a political uprising or disturbance, or in reaction thereto. (iii) The nature of the political objective (eg whether to force a change in the policy of or to overthrow or destroy the political opponent). (iv) The legal and factual nature of the offence, including its gravity. (v) The object and/or objective of the offence (eg whether it was committed against the political opponent or his property, or directed primarily against private individuals or property; or was committed on the assumption that a particular cause, governmental or otherwise, was being served). (vi) The relationship between the objective being pursued, eg the offence and the political directness or proximity of the relationship, or the proportionality between the offence and the objective pursued. (vii) The question whether the act was committed in the execution of an order or with the institution or body concerned. Unconditional indemnity was granted approval of the organization, 299 to persons who had left Africa without being in possession of valid travel documents South 300 and persons who left South Africa at a place other than an officially recognized port. 301 Provision was also made for the establishment of indemnity committees, 299 Paragraph 3.2. 300 Paragraph 6.1(a). 301 Paragraph 6.1(b). which are to investigate evidence and make recommendations to the State President regarding the exercise of the powers conferred on him in terms of the Indemnity Act. 302 At the same time unconditional indemnity was also granted to members of the ANC as well as other people who subscribed to "the principles of peaceful solutions and developments", and who have been involved, with the motive circumscribed in the guidelines referred to earlier, in one of the following activities: 303 Illegal gather ings; 304 arson, public violence or malicious damage to property; 305 treason, except where certain serious violent crimes were also committed; 306 attempted ammunition and explosives 308 murder; 307 and trespassing. possession of firearms, 309 A number of observations are called for in respect of the above. It should be clear that the definition and justification of political crimes are to a large extent conflated. The fact that someone’s actions are regarded as a "political offence" is seen as a strong indication that she should be treated with leniency. The guidelines also disclose a strong tendency to show more tolerance for those who were members of established organizations and who acted within the scope of the discipline of that organization, when they committed the acts in question. The fact that the gravity of the offence is considered relevant seems to indicate that the level of coercion will be important, while the reference to the "directness" of the relationship between the offence and the objective pursued suggests that indirect acts of resistance will be more difficult to justify than direct resistance. 302 See Government Notice R 2633, Government 1990, for the regulations in respect of these promulgation of the names of the ad hoc members see General Notice 381, Government Gazette 13201, 303 Gazette 12838 9 Nov committees. For the of these committees, 24 April 1991. Government Notice R936, Government, Gazette 13202, Regulation Gazette 4689, 24 Apr-11 1991. 304 Annexure paras (1),(ii). 305 Id para (iii). 306 Id para (v). 307 Id para (vi). 308 Id paras (vii)-(ix). 309 Id para (x). Most important for our purposes, however, is the fact that the focus in the criteria posed is not on the merits of the political convictions involved, but rather on formal or "content-neutral" criteria, such as the question whether the actions were directed against private individuals or political opponents. We will return to this issue later. III. CIVIL DISOBEDIENCE OF MEMBERS OF THE LEGAL PROFESSION Members of the legal profession are generally perceived to stand in a special relationship toward the law. Since they are entrusted with the administration and enforcement of the laws of the country, they are widely considered to have a more stringent obligation than other people to observe the law and not transgressing its provisions. to undermine respect for law by 310 This raises several questions: In the first place, should someone who has committed a crime - any crime - be allowed to practise law? In the second place, what is the position when the offence committed by a lawyer happens to be a political crime, and, in the third place, what if the act complained of was one of civil disobedience? Is there not a fundamental contradiction between open and deliberately - illegal resistance and legal practice? These questions are complicated by the fact that lawyers are regarded as having a special obligation, not only to the law of the land, but also to advance the cause of justice, 311 and - to paraphrase André Brink - law and justice are often distant cousins. Civil disobedience is in most cases motivated by the conviction that a conflict between law and justice exists in circumstances where only one of these values could prevail. Since lawyers have a special commitment to both values, civil disobedience by a lawyer presents a particularly difficult problem. A 310 This more stringent duty of lawyers to obey the law has been recognised by the courts. See Incorporated Law Society v Scholtz (1902) 19 SC 439 at 440; (1) Incorporated law Society. Transvaal v Visse & others: (2) Incorporated Law Society. Transvaal v Viljoen 1958 4 SA 115 (T) at 131 and Ex parte Cassim 1970 4 SA 476 (T) at 477. For a ritical discussion of the philosophical arguments normally advanced in support of the existence of such an obligation, see Lyons Cornell Law Review 1973 833. 311 Somewhat surprisingly no support for this apparently selfevident statement seems to be readily available in South African jurisprudence. See, in respect of American Law, MacGuigan The Canadian Bar Review 1971 222 at 235. legal system’s most considered attitude towards civil disobedience will to a large extent be reflected in its approach to such activities by members of the legal profession. In South Africa, the right to practise law is regulated by statute. An applicant who wishes to be admitted to practice, either as an advocate or as an attorney, is required to satisfy the court, inter alia, that he or she is "a fit and proper person to be so admitted." 312 Following admission, a court can suspend an advocate or attorney from practice, or order the removal of a person’s name from the roll of practitioners, if the court is satisfied that the person concerned is no longer a "fit and proper person to continue ... practice." 313 A substantial body of case law has developed in connection with the interpretation of the phrase "fit and proper person", as used in this context. Except in one important respect, which will be pointed out later, the phrase carries the same meaning where (i) admission to and (ii) suspension from practice, and (iii) removal from the roll are concerned. There is also no substantial distinction between the interpretation of these words as far as attorneys and advocates are concerned. In essence the court is called upon to evaluate the integrity of the prospective or practising lawyer. In general, it can be said that a person will only be denied the right to practise if the Court finds that she is of a dishonest, dishonourable or disgraceful character. 314 A. THE GENERAL IMPLICATIONS FOR LEGAL PRACTICE OF EARLIER CONVICTIONS One important fact that must be taken into account to evaluate the suitability of a person’s character for legal practice, is his previous 312 In terms of s 3(1)(a) of the Admission of Advocates Act 74 of 1964 and s 15(1)(a) of the Attorneys Act 53 of 1979. Earlier statutes contained similar provisions. For a detailed history of the power of the court as regards legal practitioners, see Hassim (also known as Essack) v Incorporated law Society of Natal 1977 2 SA 757 (A) at 760ff and Kaplan v Incorporated Law Society. Transvaal 1981 2 SA 762 (T) at 770ff. 313 Sect1on 7(l)(d) of the Admission of Advocates Act 74 of 1964 and s 22(1)(d) of the Attorneys Act 53 of 1979. Earlier statutes contained similar provisions. 314 See Ex parte Cassim 1970 4 SA 476 (T) at 477. convictions. 315 As a general rule, the fact that someone has a previous conviction for a serious offence would preclude him from practising law. The rule is not, however, absolute. What really matters is whether the previous offence reflects upon the character of the person concerned. There are some offences that usually reflect negatively upon the character of the offender - the so-called "tainted offences", 316such as theft and fraud. However, even this classification should not be regarded as a hard and fast rule. Evidence of a serious previous conviction should, at the most, be considered as constituting prima facie evidence of unsuitabi1ity for legal practice. It is not conclusive proof. 317 Courts are expected - by the legislature - to make value judgments based on the particular facts of each particular case. 318 What must be determined is not whether the particular already person been whether, should done. given 319 the The fact be punished only of matter his again for previous the that, Court after all, to decide conviction, the has is person concerned is of such a character that he is worthy of being admitted to the ranks of the legal profession, which is an honourable profession. In a number of important cases the general rule was not applied and persons with previous convictions for serious crimes have been allowed to practise law, since their previous convictions were not regarded as conclusive evidence of their not being "fit and proper" persons to 315 Courts have taken many considerations into account. In the somewhat archaic case of Ex parte Stanley 1902 TS 105, the Court admitted the applicant provisionally, due to some outstanding debts. See also Lambert v Incorporated Law Society 1910 TS 77 and Severs v Pretoria Balieraad 1966 2 SA 593 (A). In Haves v The Bar Council 1981 3 SA 1070 (ZAD) the general attitude of the applicant to the court before he wished to practise was taken into account. See also Fine v Society of Advocates of South Africa (Witwatersrand Division) 1983 4 SA 488 (A). 316 The term is used by Lewis Legal ethics 301. The stereotypical example of such an offence is embezzlement of trust money. See eg Solomon v Law Society of the Cape of Good Hope 1934 AD 401. 317 See Incorporated Law Society v Vrolik 1918 TPD 366; Incorporated Law Society v Levin 1928 TPD 229; Law Society of SWA v Weiss 1934 SWA 58 and Hassim (also known as Essack) v Incorporated Law Society of Natal 1977 2 SA 757 (A) at 770. 318 See Incorporated Law Society. Natal v Hassim (also known as Essack) 1978 2 SA 285 (N) at 291. 319 Ex parte Krause 1905 TS 221 at 223. practise law. 320 What needs honour" 321 to be assessed, is the extent to which the "personal of the particular person has been affected by his criminal conduct, the conviction and the sentence imposed. The Court must take into account public opinion the 322 probable effect which these factors will have on and the relationship of the convicted lawyer with his clients, professional colleagues 323 and the court. 324 Given these parameters, the difficult question can now be addressed as to the guidelines to be followed in order to distinguish between those cases of criminal conduct where the general rule should be followed, and those where the exception should be applied. It is clear that courts in cases of this nature cannot simply apply the black letter of 320 A number of South African judges also had criminal records. The applicant In Ex Parte Krause 1905 TS 221 later became Judge President of the Orange Free State, in spite of his earlier conviction for attempt to solicit murder. He was given an executive pardon. See the discussion of this case Infra chap four III B (1)(a) and Roberts SAU 1959 364 at 369. Judge Maritz, Judge President of the Transvaal Provincial Division 1947-1959, was arrested and detained during the 1914 Rebellion. See Kahn SALJ 1989 192 at 214. A more controversial move "from bars to bench" was that of Judge Strydom of the Transvaal Provincial Division. As a member of the outlawed Ossewabrandwag during the Second World War, he was engaged in anti-war activities which resulted in him being convicted on six counts, including car theft. On two of the counts he was sentenced to imprisonment for six months. He was nevertheless admitted to the bar. See MihaUk SALJ 1990 304 at 309. See also Anonymous The Cape Law Journal 1896 129. One of the greatest Roman-Dutch jurists, Grotius, spent a considerable time in prison due to his religious beliefs. See infra chap five I O. 321 322 See Ex parte Krause 1905 TS 221 at 223. See Society of Advocates of Fischer 1966 1 SA 133 (T) at 136. SA (Witwatersrand Division) v 323 In In re Weare 1893 (2) QB 439 an application was brought to have a solicitor struck from the roll for having "allowed himself to be the landlord of brothels". In granting the application. Lord Esher M R asked rhetorically (and suggestively): "Ought any respectable solicitor to be called upon to enter into that intimate intercourse with him which 1s necessary between two solicitors, even though they are acting for opposite parties?" (At 446.) This dictum was quoted with approval in Incorporated Law Society. Natal v Hassim (also known as Essack) 1978 2 SA 285 (N) at 291. 324 It is clear from Natal Law Society v N 1985 4 SA 115 (N) that courts do not require absolute obedience to their orders by officers of the court when considering their fitness for practice. the law but must apply their discretion based on practical wisdom. In the first place, it must be determined exactly how serious the particular was. 325 crime Insignificant offences, such as traffic violations, are ignored. One indication of the degree of seriousness with which imposed. A indication the trial sentence that a court of regarded imprisonment particular the is person offence, often (at is regarded least for the as the sentence a strong time of imprisonment) should formally be excluded from practice. The idea of a lawyer practising from a prison cell does indeed seem intolerable, and a suspension, at least, would in many cases be appropriate. The use of violence increases the seriousness of the crime. Nevertheless, as will be illustrated, the fact that the offence committed was a serious one and that imprisonment was imposed, does not in itself necessarily imply that the most stringent approach will be followed. Another factor which courts take into account is the motive that inspired the crime. Was the offence motivated by self-interest (as is typically the case with the embezzlement of trust monies) or was it committed with an altruistic or idealistic objective in mind? 326 The latter motivation is considered more honourable. In this regard it is important to establish whether an element of dishonesty attended the crime. 327 Since the relationship between a legal practitioner and the public, his colleagues and the court is based on trust, and since dishonesty destroys trust, crimes involving an element of dishonesty are viewed in a serious light. The particular person’s untruthfulness during his trial would likewise be to his detriment, although it is not necessarily fatal. 328 325 See Society of Advocates of Natal & another v Knox & others 1954 2 SA 246 (N). 326 In Natal Law Society v N 1985 4 SA 115,(N) the Court dismissed an application to strike an attorney from the role who had refused to testify in a criminal case against a friend, in contravention of s 189 of the Criminal Procedure Act 51 of 1977. 327 Re Hill [1868] 3 QB 543 at 545, approved in Incorporated Law Society. Transvaal v Mandela 1954 3 SA 102 (T) at 107. See also Ex Parte Swain 1973 2 SA 427 (N) and Hassim (also known as Essack) v Incorporated Law Society. Natal 1979 3 SA 298 (A). 328 See Incorporated Law Society. Natal v Roux 1972 3 SA 146 (N) at 150. See also Olivier v Die Kaapse Balieraad 1972 3 SA 485 (A). For a model of truthfulness of a law student on trial, see S v Cheadle 1975 3 SA 457 (N) at 458, where the record indicates that the appellant had A further important consideration is the question whether or not the offence was committed by the legal practitioner in his professional capacity. If circumstance. the 329 particular not, this is often regarded as a mitigating Nevertheless, crimes which are not directly related to person’s legal practice can, in appropriate circumstances, be regarded as sufficiently corruptive to render the perpetrator unfit for legal practice. 330 In this context, the one important respect in which admission to legal practice differs from suspension or exclusion from legal practice, is that crimes committed before the offender commenced practice, are generally viewed in a much kinder light, especially if there is some indication of reform. Often such actions are viewed as consequences of the indiscretions of youth. 331 Courts will also consider the chances of a recurrence in future of the criminal conduct. 332 Many factors can affect prognoses in this regard. Where it is found that the offence was committed in circumstances of extraordinary personal pressure, the chances of a recurrence might be viewed as remote. 333 Similarly, repentance is sometimes viewed as a positive indication of reform. 334 B. CONVICTIONS FOR POLITICAL OFFENCES said he found the temptation to break his banning order "truly quite frankly ... too much to resist". 329 See Incorporated Law Society v Luyt 1915 CPD 763. In this case an application was brought to remove the name of the respondent from the roll of attorneys on the basis of his conviction of a contravention of s 32 of the Franchise and Ballot Act of 1892, in hat he falsely witnessed a claim to be registered as a voter. The application was unsuccessful, inter alia because the Court held that the false declaration was made in a matter in which the respondent was not acting as an attorney. (See 765.) 330 331 See eg Incorporated Law Society (OFS) v Van Deventer 1933 OPO 124. See Matthews v Cape Hoseneke 1979 4 SA 884 (T). Law Society 1956 1 SA 807 332 Law Society. Cape v Koch 1985 4 SA 379 (C) at 389. 333 Natal law Society v N 1985 4 SA 115 (N). 334 (C) and Ex See the judgment of Kriek J in Natal Law Society v N 1985 4 SA 115 (N) at 128. While South African courts in general follow a "policy of severity" 335in respect of crimes such as the misappropriation of trust funds, insofar as the capability of the person involved to practise law is concerned, a much more lenient approach is followed in respect of crimes committed with a political motive, although some commentators have pointed out a gradual tightening in the course of the latter half of this century of the courts' indulgence. 336 (1) Political crimes in general There are good reasons for courts to follow a lenient approach in respect of certain politically motivated crimes. History abounds with examples of respectable leaders in their societies who at some stage the political development n of their countries were incarcerated for political offences. To exclude such people from legal practice would be to deny the legal profession the services of some of society's most conscientious members. Politics is inherently fickle. Law and the legal profession must be protected against becoming a mere instrument in the hands of those who at any particular moment in time control the levers of power. On the other hand, not all types of criminality by legal practitioners can be condoned simply because it was committed in the name of politics. How do the courts deal with this issue in practice? Here, as earlier in the study, it is useful to distinguish between the era of white against white conflict, and the era of black against white conflict. (g) The era of white against white conflict A number of cases stemming from the Second Anglo-Boer War dealt with (prospective) legal practitioners who committed crimes while inspired by their convictions during the War. In two separate cases heard during the War, applications were brought to strike from the roll the names of two attorneys who had been convicted of treason and sentenced to imprisonment. 337 Both were merely suspended from practice for an unspecified period. Judged by the way in which the orders were phrased, 335 See law Society. Cape v Koch 1985 4 SA 379 (C) at 387. 336 See Mihálik SALJ 1990 304. He discussed the meaning of the term "political offence" at 306. For a thorough discussion of the origins and meaning of the term "political trial", see Wanke Political justice 3ff. 337 Incorporated Law Society v Vermooten (1900) 17 SC 312 and The Incorporated Law Society v Badenhorst (1902) 19 SC 73. it seems that the Court was of the opinion that this period should not necessarily be very long. A similar results, directly after the War. case was heard, with similar 338 The locus classicus in this regard is Ex parte Krause, 339 decided in 1905. In this case the petitioner was taken prisoner while fighting on the Boer side in the Anglo-Boer War. While on parole, he practised as a barrister in England. Apparently while the War was still in progress, 340 he sent a letter to someone in South Africa, instructing that person to bring about the killing of a certain member of the staff of the British General Officer Commanding, since that person was regarded as a serious threat to the Boer cause. The petitioner was convicted in England of attempt to solicit someone to commit the crime of murder. Although this is not evident from the judgment, according to a newspaper report he was sentenced to two years' imprisonment. 341 Upon his return to South Africa, he applied for admission as an advocate On granting the application, Innes C J in the Transvaal. stated that the important question to be considered was whether the conviction reflected upon the character of the applicant in such a way that he was not worthy to be admitted to the ranks of "an honourable profession". 342 Although the crime was a serious one, the Court held that the motive behind the letter was "political, and not personal". 343 He honestly he was furthering "the cause of his own country". into account the fact that war "blunts the 344 believed that The Court also took moral sense", 345 and expressed the hope that its approach would help in "eradicating from memory many things which have been done in the past and which should 338 Incorporated Law Society v Scholtz (1902) 19 SC 439. See also Petition De Klerck (1903) 20 SC 161. 339 1905 TS 221. Approved, inter alia. in Natal law Society v N 1985 4 SA 115 (N). 340 See 224. 341 Supreme Court" The Star 10 May 1905. See also the headnote of the case, and Roberts SALJ 1959 364 at 368. 342 Ex parte Krause 1905 TS 221 at 223. 343 At 227. 344 At 231. (Solomon J, concurring.) 345 At 227. now be forgotten." 346 After the abortive Rebellion of 1914 the courts were confronted with similar cases. In one of those cases, three attorneys who had been convicted of treason and sentenced to a period of imprisonment were merely temporarily suspended from practice. 347 In another, 348 however, one of the leaders of the Rebellion was indeed struck off the roll on the basis of having taken and broken the oath of allegiance. 349 (h) The era of black against white conflict It was only a matter of time before the combination of the freedom struggle against white domination in this country, on the one hand, and the pervasive security system used by the state to suppress it, on the other, would percolate into similar cases. In Ex parte Cassim 350 the applicant who sought admission as an advocate had two previous convictions: common assault (apparently resulting from a minor incident) and defacing post office property, by placing posters on the property of the post office protesting against what was known as the 90 Days Detention Act. The record does not indicate whether the property of the post office was in any way physically damaged. The Court remarked that the applicant’s conduct "obviously calculated to incite others so also to protest." 351 was an act Although, according to the Court, it was the duty of all legal practitioners, and also of aspirant practitioners, "not to incite persons to commit breaches of the law," 352 the application was granted. The applicant’s previous offences did not indicate that he was guilty of dishonest, disgraceful 346 At 228. 347 Incorporated Law Society v Roos & others 1915 OPD 112. See also Incorporated Law Society v Van der Merwe 1915 OPD 131. 348 Incorporated Law Society v De Villiers 1915 OPD 98. 349 The argument that legal practitioners convicted of treason had broken the oath of allegiance is apparently used, or ignored, by the courts as it suits them, and this factor is not regarded as crucial. See, in general. Ex parte Kriger 1945 CPD 252; Anonymous SALJ 1945 414 and K Van Dijkhorst & H F Mellet "Legal practitioners" in Joubert LAWSA vo1 14 par 248. See also Natal Law Society v Magubela 1986 3 SA 849 (N) at 857. 350 1970 4 SA 476 (T). 351 At 477. 352 Ibid. or dishonourable conduct. In Ex parte Moseneke 353 the applicant was admitted as an attorney in spite of a previous conviction for a contravention (at age 14.5 to 15) of section 21 of the General Law Amendment Act 76 of 1962, commonly known as the Sabotage Act. He was convicted purely on the basis of attending meetings at which the ends, aims and objects of the PAC, then an unlawful organization, were promoted and not because of any violent acts on his part. He was sentenced to and served 10 years’ imprisonment, during which time he completed a substantial portion of his legal studies. The Court aligned itself with the view that the decisive consideration was whether the applicant was of such character as to be worthy to be admitted to the ranks of an honourable profession. Although the Court found that the crime of which the applicant was convicted was of a very serious nature - the equivalent of treason - it was found that no evidence had been placed before it to show that the applicant did not undergo a complete and permanent transformation. Although political motives generally evoke tolerance in the context under discussion, there are limits to such tolerance. There were recent indications that courts would possibly regard a practising lawyer’s involvement in the use of violence to overthrow the government, as a good reason for striking the name of such a person from the roll, especially if innocent people were injured. The first case which hints in this direction does not provide a clear precedent. In Hassim (also known as Essack) v Incorporated Law Society, Natal," 354 a practising attorney was struck off the roll after being convicted of contraventions of the Terrorism Act 83 of 1967, in that he was a party to a conspiracy aimed at recruiting persons in the Republic to undergo political and military training with the intent of overthrowing the government by force of arms. The Court declined to consider the earlier high treason cases where a generally lenient approach was followed, claiming that "[n]o useful purpose will be served in discussing these cases as I think that each 353 1979 4 SA 884 (T). 354 1979 3 SA 298 (A). case must be dealt with on its merits." 355 own Since the attorney concerned was in addition found to be an untruthful witness, this case cannot be relied upon as authority for the proposition that involvement in violent resistance against the state, even if remote, will necessarily constitute sufficient grounds for excluding a person from legal practice. The case of Natal Law Society v Maoubela is much more to the point. 356 In that case a practising attorney was struck off the roll after he had been convicted imprisonment. of The high basis treason of and the sentenced conviction was to twenty his close years’ personal involvement in a series of explosions over a period of nine months, in which nine civilians were injured (some seriously) and nearly half a million rands of damages were caused. The Court found that even if the offence was politically inspired, the inherent character of the offence still had to be considered. In view of the seriousness of the offence, which involved violence targeted at civilians, and the fact that the respondent had not renounced his actions, his name was struck off the roll. (2) Civil disobedience Civil disobedience is per definition non-violent, which means that the last consideration resistance. If it should is not correct apply that to courts such acts recently of political started to view politically inspired crimes committed by lawyers in a more serious light, and that this tendency is the result of the increased use of force against civilians, this should then not affect the way in which civil disobedience is treated. The element of openness of civil disobedience, however, is often seen as an aggravating circumstance in this context - the idea being that lawyers make a mockery of their profession if they deliberately and openly break the law. Lawyers, in the reg". words of Du Plessis, must show respect for "die weg van die 357 Nevertheless, the question should be asked whether the actions of someone who breaks the law openly and allows retribution to take its course, show less respect for the way of the law than the actions of 355 At 307. 356 1986 3 SA 849 (N). 357 Du Plessis Die professionele gedrag van die juris 32. someone who defies the law and tries to escape the consequences of his unlawful act. In the latter case, one could argue that the person involved shows fear for the law, but surely there is a difference between fear and respect. This issue was addressed in two seminal cases on the topic in the South Africa legal history. Both cases took place in the context of black against white resistance, and concerned incitement to civil disobedience during the Defiance Campaign of 1952. In Incorporated Law Society. Transvaal v Mandela 358 an application was made to the Transvaal Provincial Division to have the name of the respondent, who was a practising attorney at the time, struck from the roll. He had been convicted, along with others, of contravening section 11(b) of the Suppression of Communism Act 44 of 1950. 359 The indictment alleged that he had advocated and encouraged a "scheme" - the Campaign - which was aimed at bringing about certain Defiance social and political changes in the country by means of disobeying a number of laws. The accused was sentenced to nine months’ imprisonment, which was conditionally suspended. In dismissing the application, Ramsbottom J stressed that the question was not whether the respondent should be punished for his actions that had already been done. He then proceeded: The sole question that the Court has to decide is whether the facts which have been put before us and on which the respondent was convicted show him to be of such character that he is not worthy to remain in the ranks of an honourable profession. To that question there can, in my opinion, be only one answer. Nothing has been put before us which suggests in the slightest degree that the respondent has been guilty of conduct of a dishonest, disgraceful, or dishonourable kind; nothing that he has done reflects upon his character or shows him to be unworthy to remain in the ranks of an honourable profession. In advocating the plan of action, the respondent was obviously motivated by a desire to serve his fellow non-Europeans. The intention was to bring about the repeal of certain laws which the respondent regarded as unjust. The method of producing that result which the respondent advocated is an unlawful one, and by advocating that method the respondent contravened the statute; for that offence 358 359 1954 3 SA 102 (T). For particulars of the charge, see R v Sisulu & others 1953 3 SA 276 (A) at 283, 284, and the discussion supra chap three III A (3)(c)(iii). he has been punished. But his offence was not of a 'personally disgraceful character’, and there is nothing in his conduct which, in my judgment, renders him unfit to be an attorney. 360 The facts in Matthews v Cape Law Society, 361 decided a year later by the Cape Provincial Division, were for almost all practical purposes identical to those of Mandela. 362 The only real difference lay in the fact that Mandela was already a practising attorney at the time of his conviction, while Matthews only later applied for admission to the attorney’s profession. Matthews’ application to be admitted was opposed by the Law Society on the basis of his previous conviction. The Cape Court, per De Villiers J P, held that the performance of acts of civil disobedience - and especially if accompanied by incitement of others to engage in similar acts - were incompatible with a practising attorney’s duty as an officer of the court; that is, the duty not to break the laws of the country and not to incite others to do so. Opposition to laws which he regarded as unjust could manifest itself only in the form of criticism of such laws or attempts to secure their repeal by legal means. The Court stated that the approach followed by the Mandela court was too narrow. considered the question whether In that case the Court only the respondent’s personal honour had been affected. The-obligation which an attorney has to the court was not considered at all. Consequently, the approach of the Mandela court was rejected. Nevertheless, because the crimes of which Matthews was convicted occurred a considerable period before he applied for admission as an attorney, the Court held that it could not be said that he was an officer of the court at the time when he was convicted and hence that he had violated his duties to the court. The application was granted on these grounds. The Mandela case and the comments in the Matthews case regarding the 360 At 108. 361 1956 1 SA 807 (c). 362 Mandela was the national President of the ANC Youth League during the Defiance Campaign while Matthews was the Secretary. Matthews, the son of Prof Z K Matthews, later became national President of the Youth League. While Mandela's case dealt with his conviction as a national organiser of the Defiance Campaign, Matthews' case dealt with his convictions as an organiser of local campaigns in Port Elizabeth and Kimberley. Mandela case provide striking illustrations of the two opposite approaches which can be followed in cases of this nature. In the one case a previous conviction for involvement in civil disobedience was not regarded as an automatic disqualification to practise law, whereas in the other it was. While the Mandela court made greater allowances for members of the legal profession to pursue (their understanding of the demands of) justice, and followed a natural law approach, the Matthews court emphasized the duty of the lawyer to uphold the positive law. Even if it could be said that the Mandela case focused on the individual concerned and the Matthews case more on the interests of society (as perceived by the Court), the issues raised by the Mandela court were more universal, while the bottom-line concerns in Matthews were more local or parochial. Whereas the respondent in Mandela was evaluated morally as a human being and with a view to the honesty, grace and honour of his character, the applicant in Matthews was judged primarily on the grounds of the political message which his admission to the legal profession would at the time convey to society. The insistence of De Villiers J P in Matthews that officers of the court have an absolute duty not to engage in acts of civil disobedience, was almost explicitly motivated by his fear that such actions would incite others (read: "black people"), described in the application of the Law Society as "generally uneducated and unenlightened". 363In the course of his judgment, President. 364 this sentiment was repeated twice by the Judge The approach of Ramsbottom J in Mandela to the enterprise of the accused seems to be much more positive. In the jargon of the time he stated, as indicated above, that "the respondent was obviously motivated by a desire to serve his fellow non-Europeans." 365 Which of the two approaches accords with the values underlying the South African legal system? This question can be answered from different angles. The merits of the cases in question can be compared on the basis of (1) the support the two approaches received in later court cases, (ii) the soundness of the jurisprudence involved, and (iii) the extent to which each case complies with the general approach 363 At 810. 364 At 813. 365 At 108. - followed in respect of previous convictions of legal practitioners as outlined above. These aspects wi11 next be considered. With a view to precedent, it may be argued that the comments in Matthews in respect of the Mandela case were made obiter, since the Court decided the case on different grounds. At the same time, however, the Mandela decision was repudiated (but not overruled) by a Transvaal full bench in Society of Advocates of SA (Witwatersrand Division) v Fischer. 366 In Fischer an application was brought to have the name of a senior advocate struck from the roll after he had forfeited his bail while awaiting trial on charges, inter alia, of being an office-bearer of the South African Communist Party. In this case, as in Matthews, the Court relied heavily on the impact of such granting the application, De Wet J conduct on public opinion. In P distinguished consideration from the Mandela case, inasmuch as the the case under Mandela court "was apparently of the view that the respondent had been punished for his unlawful activity, which had ceased and was not likely to recur (a wrong view, as it turned out)." 367 The Court proceeded: "But I would also say, with respect, that the [Mandela] court appears to have overlooked the fact that it is the duty of an attorney to further the administration of justice in accordance with the laws of the country and not to frustrate it." 368 The Court stated that bail applications would in future be seriously jeopardized unless it acted against Fischer. 369 On a personal presiding judge level, in the more Fischer’s cautionary case is approach perhaps not taken by difficult the to understand. He was, after all, also the judge who presided in the Rivonia trial, where it became apparent that the respondent in the Mandela case did not cease his unlawful activity. Hence the remark: "a 366 1966 1 SA 133 (T). 367 At 137. 368 Ibid. 369 At 136. The observation of Mihálik SALJ 1990 304 at 315 that this finding is "based on the false premiss that the majority or perhaps all of the applicants for bail wish to become fugitives from justice" seems questionable. Why, after a11, do courts require bail 1n certain cases if no danger exists that the accused might not appear to stand trial? wrong view as it turned out." Nevertheless, although the judge in Fischer said that the Mandela and the Fischer cases were distinguishable, he did not identify the essential difference, which makes his reference to the Mandela case unwarranted. In Mandela an act of civil disobedience was at stake, which implied that the respondent openly defied certain laws. He did not attempt to evade the sanction of the law of the country; he in fact invited it. In Fischer the respondent did the exact opposite: In order to avoid the sanction of the law he became a fugitive from justice. Fischer, as Du Plessis indicated, specifically tried to evade "die weg van die reg". 370Even though Mandela broke the law, he still sought "the way of the law". Moreover, the offence in Fischer was directed against the administration of justice. The remark in Fischer aside, however, it should be noted that the Mandela case has been quoted with approval in many subsequent cases, including judgments of the Appellate Division, even though not always directly on the point in question. 371 It is also revealing to note that the name of subsequent the respondent incarceration in the following Mandela the case, Rivonia in trial, removed from the roll of attorneys in the Transvaal. spite has of not his been 372 From a jurisprudential point of view, the reasoning underlying the Matthews case can at best be classified as "positivism gone wrong". The fact that the duty of an attorney was merely described as being "to uphold the existing laws", 373 while nothing was said concerning the need to pursue justice, suggests a point of departure, in terms of which everything enacted by parliament is accepted as legitimate and binding. Many people accept this approach as valid, and the intention 370 Du Plessis Die professionele gedrag van die juris 32. 371 See law Society of the Cape of Good Hope v C 1986 1 SA 616 (A) at 640 as well as Natal Law Society v Hagubela 1986 3 SA 849 (N) at 851. See also Annual Survey of South African Law 1956 at 404 and Sampson The South African attorneys handbook 119. See also Lewis Legal ethics 303. 372 Information obtained on 9 March 1990 from C M Prinsloo, Director: Professional Affairs, Law Society of the Transvaal. Mandela's name is on the so-called list of non-practising attorneys. See also "Could Mandela practise law again?" Weekly Mail 16-22 Feb 1990. 373 At 813. is not here to attack the basic premises of positivism. The problem with the way in which it was applied in the Matthews case, however, is that while the Court was required by a particular statute (that is, by parliament) to make a moral assessment of the applicant, it accepted without question that parliament’s will as expressed in other statutes disposes of the question of what, morally, is the right thing to do. Not even the most committed positivist needs to, or rather should, arrive at that conclusion. In fact, the central claim of positivism is the distinction between law and morality. 374 As was observed by Mi liner with regard to the two cases under consideration: "[E]ven if law does not cease to be law when it is unjust, the act of opposing it then ceases to be ethically reprehensible. The boundless sovereignty of the legislature obliges the judge to treat the breach of its statutes as illegal but not to pronounce it as immoral." 375 Perhaps the clearest warning against an approach such as the one endorsed by the Matthews court comes from the doyen of positivism, H L A Hart, who warned of "the danger that the existing law may supplant morality as a final test of conduct." 376 The third and final basis upon which the two cases may be compared is to consider how they fit in with the general approach of the courts in respect of earlier convictions, as set out above. A number of considerations which the courts take into account were identified, and will now be discussed. It was stated that the seriousness of the crime of which the person involved was convicted is considered when her suitability for legal practice is considered. One aspect to be considered in this regard concerns the extent of violence and destruction of property that was involved. The fact that civil disobedience is non-coercive calls for a lenient approach. It was also pointed out above that our courts tend to be more strict where an element of dishonesty attended the offence in question. It has already been noted that the true feature that distinguishes Mandela from Fischer is the fact that the respondent in the latter case tried 374 See infra chap five I DD. 375 Millner SALJ 1957 342 at 346. 376 See Hart Harvard Law Review 1958 593 at 598. See also 618. to evade the law. This he managed to do by using his status as a senior advocate of unquestioned integrity. It is this element of dishonesty which led to his exclusion from the legal profession. Since that element is normally not present in the case of civil disobedience, where the protest per definition is open, this guide-line points to the more lenient approach followed in Mandela. This can indeed be fact that the described as the greatest weakness of Matthews: the Court excluded acts of civil disobedience from the operation of the general rule, namely that politically motivated crimes are to be treated with special leniency. This would imply that the only category of crimes to which the rule can apply are those where the perpetrator attempted to escape detection. Certainly one cannot follow this approach and at the same time claim to take "the road of the law" seriously. The consideration that crimes committed in a professional capacity are treated more harshly does not provide any guidance as to the general approach to be followed in cases of civil disobedience by practising lawyers. It does not favour either Mandela or Matthews on the point under discussion. (It is, however, probable that lawyers who take part in a protest march in their robes wi11 not be looked upon kindly. The case of Pitje, a lawyer who practised civil disobedience in court, was discussed earlier.) It was furthermore stated that the chances of recurrence should be taken into account. This consideration tends to support the Matthews approach, because acts of civil disobedience are committed with a political motive, and, unless almost inevitably the conditions which gave rise to that motivation change, the convictions of the persons concerned would most likely also remain the same. As alluded to earlier, this is collaborated by the later history of the respondent in the Mandela case, culminating in the Rivonia trial and in his subsequent statements. At a certain point, if it is established clearly that the person disobedience with concerned some intends regularity, to engage this in acts consideration of will civil become paramount. In many cases it might, however, be appropriate to grant or bring - an application for removal or suspension only after a repetition of unlawful conduct. If that is not the case, however, and it is clear that an isolated incident is at stake, it is submitted that this consideration should not be regarded as crucial. Courts have simply sidestepped the question whether the particular person has shown remorse, at least where no violence was involved. 377 It was pointed instruments of out that courts the powers should that be, guard and against should becoming protect mere their own relative autonomy from becoming entangled in the inconsistencies of politics. To be sure, courts cannot always avoid being affected by the whims of politics when, for example, in criminal trials they have to enforce law reflecting that which the government of the day has earmarked as offences. That being the case, the least they can do is to avoid becoming civil service rubber stamps when they are required by statute to evaluate the Integrity of a particular person. In such a case a court should rather uphold a I long-term perspective. The facts of the Moseneke case, discussed earlier, provide a good example of this approach: The applicant was sentenced to ten years’ imprisonment for the statutory offence of being a member of a banned organization. Three years before his conviction, and 17 years after his release, the same conduct’s would not have been regarded as an offence at all. In such circumstances it would be extremely short-sighted for a court to bar such a person from legal practice. Other offences, such as the forfeiture of bail in Fischer. are less closely linked to the policies of a particular government, and are unlikely to be materially affected by future changes of the political dispensation. Such an offence is also very closely related to the administration of justice and the judicial process. Consequently, in those cases the same degree of leniency might not be appropriate. 378 377 See eg Ex parte Moseneke 1979 4 SA 884 (T). The Court's emphasis on the need for remorse In Natal Law Society v Magubela 1986 3 SA 849 (N) at 8S8 must be seen against the background of the violence in that case having been aimed at innocent people. 378 The observation of Mihálik SALJ 1990 304 at 323 that "[m]edica1 practitioners who have served prison sentences for politically motivated offences as serious as high treason are not subsequently convicted on disciplinary charges of improper and disgraceful conduct" might be correct (he cited only one instance in support of this contention) but it does not follow (as he suggested) that lawyers should be granted "free pardons" in respect of political offences. The direct analogy between the legal and the medical profession does not hold water, because different codes of conduct apply to different professions. Certainly the severe approach which courts follow in respect of embezzlement of trust money is justifiable in respect of lawyers, but the same degree of strictness should not necessarily apply in the case of medical doctors. Mihálik's general "free pardon" From the above it must be concluded that the Mandela court’s lenient approach was under the circumstances correct. 379 Obviously, whether tolerance should be shown, and if so the extent of such tolerance, win also be affected by the measure in which the particular acts of civil disobedience may be described as justified - a separate inquiry which will be dealt with that the elsewhere. 380 For the moment the only claim made is Mandela-approach, according to which legal practice and participation in civil disobedience is not necessarily incompatible, most accurately reflects the values which underlie the South African legal system. IV. CONSCIENTIOUS OBJECTION TO MILITARY SERVICE The armed forces of a country specialise in the application of violence including, where deemed necessary, the killing of human beings. Some governments view it to be essential for their survival that citizens be compelled, through the threat of criminal sanctions, to render service in the armed forces. 381 Not surprisingly, many people find this unacceptable. One of the reasons why some people refuse to serve in the military is based on narrow self-interest. Service in the armed forces can expose one to grave personal risks and discomfort. A very different reason may be the convictions of the individual involved, who for a variety of reasons might believe that rendering or in all category cases of is wrong or "conscientious such service in a particular case immoral. objectors", Such 382 persons who often belong regard to the their convictions in this regard as most fundamental and for which they are prepared to go to prison or even die. approach makes no provision for the fact that political crimes can differ in terms of their merits and in the light they cast upon the character of those who committed them. 379 For a discussion of the very tolerant approach followed in these matters in the United States, see Weckstein Professional responsibility in a nutshell 37ff. See also MacGuigan Canadian Bar Review 1971 222 at 235. 380 See infra chap six III. 381 For the reasons why this is deemed necessary, see D F S Fourie "Universal service - a military view" in Centre for Intergroup Studies Conscientious objection 42 at 48. 382 The term "conscientious objection" was circumscribed supra chap two V. The issue of conscientious objection to military service clearly involves a strong tension between the interests of the state and the rights of the individual. Can the individual enjoy the benefits of communal life efforts? But but on refuse the to other participate hand, can in the the country’s state force military someone to participate in military activity even if that would mean the violation of that person’s deepest beliefs? In most jurisdictions conscience context, objectors is and a the value systems to alternative service. worthy have military 383 principle of been service is at recognised least devised in one some for way that freedom protection allowing or in of this conscientious another to render In order to discourage those who have other, less noble motivations for not wanting to serve in the armed forces, such alternative service is typically made less appealing than the duties would included normally in be conscription. at least The equal to period or of alternative surpass that service required of ordinary conscripts. In most cases, the issue is not one of recognising the broad principle that certain convictions might warrant exemption, or the practice of requiring alternative service. 384 What is highly controversial, however, is the way in which such a system is applied. Central to the dispute is the question of the kinds of conviction that should be recognised as grounds warranting exemption from regular military service. The demands made by national service in South Africa over several decades on those subjected to such service, and the extent to which a person’s conscience might be involved, are indeed extraordinary. Apart from the problems experienced by many people regarding military service 383 Resolution 337 (1967) of the Council of Europe provides as follows: "Persons liable to conscription for military service who, for reasons of conscience or profound conviction arising from religious, ethical, moral, humanitarian, philosophical or similar motives, refuse to perform armed service shall enjoy a personal right to be released from obligation to perform such service." 384 Johan van der Vyver reluctantly endorsed this practice. From his Calvinist perspective, "the state is ... clearly competent to compel a11 citizens to make an appropriate contribution towards the military defence of the body politic." Out of generosity, however, the state could relieve conscientious objectors from their duty to do military service. See Van der Vyver Philosophical Papers May 1979 - Oct 1980 56 at 62. in any country, the South African Defence Force ("SADF") has in recent years been perceived by many as an instrument of the apartheid state which through townships its came operations to be in agencies neighbouring of states repression. 385 In and in black addition to resistance by those who subscribe in general to the pacifist position, military conscription in South Africa has consequently elicited resistance from the ranks of those who believed that the government was engaged in what, in Augustinian terms, is called an "unjust war". 386 Conscientious objection, in one form or another, was supported by particular groups in the mainline English language churches, while the idea of military conscription was to a large extent supported by the Afrikaans churches. 387 Given these circumstances, conscientious objection to military service by some members controversial. 388 of In society what was follows, inevitable, the legal and basis bound of to be compulsory military service and the approach of South African law to conscientious objection relating to military service will be considered. This will be done against the backdrop of American jurisprudence on conscientious objection, 389 since, as Robinson observed, there are strong indications that the South African legislature in this regard simply copied 385 See eg Catholic Institute for International Relations Out of step 28ff. The history of war resistance, and especially the activities of the End Conscription Campaign, are dealt with at 75ff. See also Berat Vanderbilt Journal of Transnational Law 1989 127 at 170. 386 The stand taken by the Jehova's witnesses against national service represents virtually the only universal pacifist tradition in the country. See eg S v Schoeman: S v Martin & andere 1971 4 SA 248 (A) and S v Lewis 1985 4 SA 26 (T), as well as the discussion by Robinson JCRDL 1987 219 and Potgieter & Munnik Militere diensplig en dienspligweiering. On the justum bellum doctrine, see Dugard SALJ 1976 144; D S Bax "The just war and situational objection" in Centre for Intergroup Studies Conscientious objection 56 and Du Plessis Strategic Review for Southern Africa 1990 14. Grotius, for example, advised subjects to refuse to do military service if they regarded the cause of war as unjust. See Grotius De Jure belli ac pads 2.26.3.1. 387 See infra chap five II B. 388 See eg Degenaar Insig Sept 1988 18. 389 For an overview of the position in the United States, see Anonymous Harvard Law Review 1978 1056; Fox Cleveland State Law Review 1982 77 and Calabresi Tragic choices 158. American legislation. 390 As mentioned earlier, a distinction should be drawn between legal and illegal conscientious objection. 391 In the case of legal conscientious objection, the objector qualifies for alternative service in terms of the relevant statute. In the case of illegal conscientious objection, the person concerned does not qualify for alternative service, but nevertheless refuses to do military service. In doing so he commits an offence. Illegal as well as legal conscientious objection warrant our attention, although the latter category of actions does not strictly speaking constitute objection civil shall illustration conscience. legally disobedience. be of a considered recognised is concession Moreover, it is One on reason because the it part necessary alternative why service, to legal conscientious provides of the establish which an important legal system to the limits of denotes the confines where civil disobedience begins. A. THE LEGAL SANCTION OF COMPULSORY MILITARY SERVICE The Defence Act 44 of 1957 determines the maximum period of compulsory military service to which the government may subject every white male 392 citizen between the ages of 17 and 65 years, 393 namely "a) a first period of service not exceeding 24 months;[and] b) subsequent periods of service during six cycles of two years each of which none shall exceed 90 days." 394 Legal provision for compulsory military service in the country has at least been made since the formation of the Union in 1910. 395 390 See Robinson De Jure 1987 374 at 376. The problems raised by South African law on conscientious objection have spilled over into the United States law in the form of applications for asylum by those who fled from South Africa when called up for military service. See eg "SA man kry nie assiel" Beeld 9 March 1990. 391 See supra chap two V. 392 Section 2(l)(b) excludes "females and persons who are not white" from compulsory military service. 393 Section 3(1)(b). 394 Section 22(3). For a discussion, see J Forder "Conscription" In Robertson South African human rights and labour law yearbook 1990 36. 395 An early forerunner of military conscription in the country can Nevertheless, until after the Second World War, the South African Defence Force relied almost exclusively on volunteers to supply its numbers. 396 Conscription in its modern form, administered on the basis of the ballot, was introduced in the 1950’s, first for a three months period and later, as from 1961, for nine months. In 1967 the ballot was abolished and universal conscription for a one year period was introduced. Since 1977, national servicemen were called up for the maximum period of two years. At the beginning of 1990 this period was again reduced to one year. 397 B. ILLEGAL CONSCIENTIOUS OBJECTION be found in the requirement of the Dutch East India Company for Free Burgers to render service in the militia. See Van Riebeeck Daghregister part 3 34. When the British occupied the Cape, they abolished the militia, but retained the informal commando system, which was Initiated in about 1715. This system was also implemented in the Boer Republics. Every white man between 16 years of age and 60 was liable to combat duty. In the Nineteenth Century, universal service under the Zulu and Matabele was standard practice. See D F S Fourie "Universal service - a military view" in Centre for Intergroup Studies Conscientious objection 42 at 44. The South Africa Defence Act 13 of 1912 provided that white citizens (s 7) of the newly formed Union who were selected by ballot (ss 56, 57) could be called up for military training 1n times of peace (s 2) for an initial period of 30 days and for subsequent periods (s 64). In time of war or internal disorder, citizens could be called up for combat duty (ss 1, 78, 79). The original version of the Defence Act 44 of 1957 provided for compulsory military training for an initial period of three months (s 22(2)(b)) of persons selected by ballot (ss 66, 67, 70). The citizen force, the reserves and the commandos could also be mobilised in time of war (s 1) and internal disorder (s 2). Provision was made for universal conscription of white males by s (c) of the Defence Amendment Act 85 of 1967. 396 For an historical overview of the period before and during the two World Wars, see D F S Fourie "Universal service - a military view" in Centre for Intergroup Studies Conscientious objection 42 at 44ff. As Fourie suggests, the fact that conscription was not used during the two Wars was largely due to political resistance against the Union's participation in those wars. In a sense, this can be seen as a concession to selective secular conscientious objection. 397 Announced by State President F W de Klerk, in a speech delivered on 7 Dec 1989 and reprinted in the booklet Military Service, Issued by the South African Defence Force, at 3. For a discussion of the practical implications of modern conscription, see J Forder "Conscription" in Robertson South African human rights and labour law yearbook 1990 36. A refusal to render service or a failure to report when called up for military service, whether for reasons of conscience or otherwise, has been subjected to a variety of penalties since the inception of the system of compulsory, military services. 398 At present the Defence Art provides that any person who is called up and refuses to render service is guilty of an offence and liable on conviction to imprisonment (that is in a civilian prison) "for a period one-and-a-half times as long as the aggregate" of the periods of service required by the Act and still outstanding against his name, or for a period of 18 months, whichever is the longer. No provision is made for the option of a fine. A person who had been convicted and has served his sentence imposed in terms of this provision is not liable for further military service. 399 Any person who fails to report for service is guilty of an offence and liable to detention (that is imprisonment in a military prison) or imprisonment for a period "not exceeding eighteen months", or a fine. A person who has paid his fine or has called up for military service. served his sentence may again be 400 The courts initially ruled that the imposition of the maximum prison 398 In terms of the South Africa Defence Act 13 of 1912 a failure to undergo military training as prescribed constituted an offence (s 64(5)) punishable with a fine not exceeding £ 25 or in default of payment, Imprisonment of up to three months (s 109(1)(c)(11))(see also s 109(2)). Failure to render service in time of war constituted desertion (s 100). The original version of the Defence Act 44 of 1957 provided that: "Any member of the South African Defence Force or the Reserve who without just cause, the burden of proof whereof shall He on him, fails to attend at any time and place appointed for instruction, training or exercise, or who evades or fails to perform duly and with proper zeal the full course of training allotted to him 1n any training year, shall be guilty of an offence" (s 126) for which a fine not exceeding £100 or six months' imprisonment could be imposed (s 127). It was held in the case of S_v Lovell 1972 3 SA 760 (A) that the religious universal pacifist convictions of a Jehova's Witness did not constitute a "just cause' within the meaning of the Act. Failure by members of the Defence force to render service in time of war or internal disorder constituted desertion (s 114). The Defence Amendment Act 49 of 1978 (s 7) introduced the current s 126A, discussed in the text. At present desertion is a crime in terms of s 13 of Schedule 1 of the Defence Act, known as the Military Discipline Code. 399 Section 126A(1)(a). For a discussion, see Foundation for Peace and Justice Facing prison 10. 400 Section 126A(1)(b). See also Foundation for Peace and Justice Facing prison 9. sentence in mandatory. 401 the case However, of in refusal the to cases render of S v military Toms: S service was 402 the v Bruce Appellate Division ruled that the Court had a discretion to impose a lighter sentence of imprisonment, which may even be suspended. In Toms, an appeal was noted against the sentence imposed for a conviction related to the appellant’s refusal to render further periods of training for reasons of political conviction. The appellant, a medical doctor, had some years previously completed his initial period of military training. By the time his appeal was heard in the Appellate Division, he had served nine months of a sentence of eighteen months’ imprisonment. His sentence was reduced to the nine months already served. he had 403 Bruce was convicted for his refusal to do his basic military training, also for reasons of political conviction. The trial court was of the opinion that it was bound by statute to impose the maximum sentence of one-and-a-half times the four years which the accused was required by law to serve. Bruce became the first person to be sentenced to six years imprisonment for this offence. The sentence was confirmed in an appeal to the Local Division, but the Appellate Division set the sentence aside and remitted his case to the trial court to consider the question of sentence afresh. 404 The trial court sentenced Bruce to the 20 months prison sentence he had already served. 405 It is also a crime in terms of the Defence Act to use any language or do anything "to recommend to, encourage, aid, incite, instigate, suggest to or otherwise cause any other person" to refuse or to fail to render compulsory military service. The punishment that can be imposed for this offence thousand rand. 401 is imprisonment of six years or a fine of five 406 See eg S v Toms 1989 2 SA 567 (C). 402 1990 2 SA 802 (A). The appellants were convicted of contraventions of s l26A(1)(a). See also "Torr se appél gedeeltelik gehandhaaf" BeeId 21 May 1991. 403 At 821. 404 Ibid 405 See "David Bruce freed from the spectre of jail" The Meekly Mail 21 Sept 1990 406 Section 121(c). This provision was introduced by s 10 of the C. LEGAL CONSCIENTIOUS OBJECTION Traditionally, the only legal concession for conscientious objectors was a provision authorising that they could, in the discretion of the Defence Force, be assigned to perform non-combatant military service in a time of war. The criterion applied was largely objective, in the sense that this limited concession was available only to those who were bona members fide of and adhered to "a recognised religious denomination, by the tenets whereof its members may not participate in war." 407 All illegal, 408 other forms of conscientious objection were considered including religious objection to military training. 409 During 1983, the Defence Act was amended and a more subjective test was introduced in terms of which the religious beliefs of the objector Defence Further Amendment Act 83 of 1974, which was passed -In response to the so-called "Hammanskraal resolution" of the South African Council of Churches of 1974, which supported conscientious objection. See infra chap five II 8. 407 In respect of military training in peace time, the South Africa Defence Act 13 of 1912 provided that exemption from inclusion in the ballot list could be obtained from an Exemption Board (s 58) on the grounds, inter alia. of one's "bona fide religious tenets" (s 58(6)(d)). In respect of times of war, the Act provided as follows: "A citizen who bona fide belongs and adheres to a recognised religious denomination, by the tenets whereof its members may not participate in war, may be granted exemption from serving in any combatant capacity in time of war, but may be required to serve in a non-combatant capacity if called upon to do so" ( s 82(2)). The original version of the Defence Act 44 of 1957 also made provision for an Exemption Board (s 68), which had the power to exempt people from the ballot list for a variety of reasons, but those reasons did not include conscientious objection (s 69(4)). However, the Defence Amendment Act 85 of 1967 introduced s 67 (3) which provided as follows: The registering officer shall as far as may be practicable allot any person who to his knowledge bona fide belongs and adheres to a recognized religious denomination by the tenets whereof its members may not participate in war, to a unit where such person will be able to render service in a non-combatant capacity." With respect to war, the Act provided that "[a] person who bona fide belongs and adheres to a recognised religious denomination, by the tenets whereof its members may not participate in war, may be granted exemption from serving in any combatant capacity in time of war, but shall, if called upon to do so, serve in a non-combatant capacity" (s 97(3)). 408 409 Section 61 of the Defence Amendment Act 85 of 1967. See S v Lovell 1972 3 SA 760 (A), affirming the decision in S_ v Schoeman: S v Martin & andere 1971 4 SA 248 (A). as an individual would become decisive. 410 The alternative types of service open to those conscientious objectors who complied with the requirements for such service were also increased. The Defence Act now provides in section 72 that if the Board of Religious Objection (the "Board"), established in terms of the Act, 411 is satisfied that it is against the "religious convictions" of someone who has been called up for military service to serve in specified capacities in "any armed force", such a person may be classified as a "religious objector". 412 This entails that he will not be forced to serve in beliefs, the but Defence that he Force in a will have capacity to that render would violate alternative his service as prescribed in the Act. Since the convictions of the appellants in the Toms and the Bruce cases were of a political and moral nature, they did not qualify for classification as "religious objectors", and their refusal to serve in the armed forces therefore constituted a crime. The courts have stated that provisions for exemption from military service should be interpreted strictly, because the effect of not doing so would be "to cast an unfair burden upon the more patriotic of the country's citizens." 413 In order for the Board to find that anyone is a "religious objector", he must be classified in one of three categories: category (i) non-combatants, whose religious convictions do allow them to render combat service in any armed force; category not 414 (ii) non-combatants who also refuse to perform maintenance tasks of a combat nature in any army and who refuse to wear a military uniform; 415 and category (iii) non-combatants who also refuse to perform any tasks 410 Section 9 of the Defence Amendment Act 34 of 1983. See Taitz De Jure 1988 239 at 241. 411 Section 72A. 412 Section 72D(1)(a). The English text of Act 34 of 1983 was signed by the State President. 413 S v lovell 1972 3 SA 760 (A) 766. See also Willem de Klerk's editorial "Moker die ontdulkers" Rapport 30 Jan 1983. 414 Section 72D(1)(a)(i). 415 Section 72D(1)(a)(ii). connected with any armed force. 416 Those in category (i) must serve the normal period of military service in the SADF in a non-combatant capacity; 417 category (ii) must serve one and a half times the period for which they could still be called up in the SADF (unless the Minister of Defence provides for a shorter period), not in uniform 418 and doing maintenance tasks of a non-combatant nature, 419 and category (iii) must serve one and a half times the period for which they could outside still the be SADF shorter period). called (unless up, the doing community Minister provides service for a 420 Exactly how limited the concessions in terms of the Defence Act to conscientious objectors are, becomes clear when an index of the full range of possible motivations for conscientious objection to service in the armed forces is considered. Schematically possibilities could be summarised as follows: Universal 416 Section 720(1)(a)(iii). 417 Section 72E(1). 418 Section 72E(2)(a)(ii). the different 421 Selective objectors(those who object to 419 Section 72E(2)(b). Failure to render such service constitutes an offence in terms of s 721(1). 420 Section 72E(3). Section 72I(2)(a) provides that "[a]ny person referred to in section 72E(3) who refuses or falls to render community service shall be guilty of an offence and liable on conviction to detention for a period which is equal to the period of community service which ha still had to render at the time of such refusal or failure." It was held in S v Sangster 1991 1 SA 240 (0), on the basis of S v Toms: S v Bruce 1990 2 SA 802 (A), that the sentence provided for in this section is not mandatory. The periods of community service were also reduced proportionately when military service was halved. See "Minder diensplig sus nie die gewete nie" Vrye Weekblad 26 Jan 1990, but also "Objectors are freed, but mixed feelings over 'reprieve'" The Argus 31 Jan 1990. 421 See also Harris SAJHR 1987 240 at 241. pacifists(those fighting for a particular regime; against who a refuse serve in to any particular enemy or with certain weapons) army) Religious objectors UNIVERSAL a) b) SELECTIVE RELIGIOUS OBJECTORS RELIGIOUS (those who refuse to serve PACIFISTS for religious reasons) c)UNIVERSAL Secular objectors d) SELECTIVE SECULAR OBJECTORS SECULAR (those who refuse to serve PACIFISTS for non-religious reasons) If a literal meaning is given to the words of section 720(1)(a) of the Defence Act (namely that those who find service in "any armed force" repugnant to their "religious convictions" can be classified as religious objectors), only those objectors in category a) in the above diagram are covered by its provisions and qualify for alternative service. Objectors in all three the other categories will be guilty of criminal acts if they refuse to serve. While the objectors protection is clearly which section extremely 72 narrow, affords its exact to conscientious demarcations are nevertheless hard to define. After all, exactly what does the term "religious conviction" mean? Predictably, the interpretation of this phrase has been the focus for those who seek wider recognition for objection to mi1itary service. The locus classicus in this regard is Hartman v Chairman,Board for Religious Objection. 422 In this case the Board had found that universal pacifism based on mainstream or Theravada Buddhist beliefs does 422 not 1987ST 1 SA 922 (0). For a discussion of this case, see Harris SAJHR 1987 240 and Robinson De Jure 1987 374. The approach followed in respect of the 1983 legislation before Hartman was summarised by the first chairman of the Board, in Steyn Compendium luris Re1igionis. During that time the Board did not only require a strictly religious, as opposed to secular, belief; it also specifically required a theistic belief. See also 13ff and 190ff of the same work. See also Taitz De Jure 1988 239 at 243. The general issue of religion under South African positive law is discussed by J D van der Vyver "Religion" in Joubert LAWSA vo1 23 175. constitute a "religious conviction" in terms of the Defence Act, because this form of Buddhism is non-theistic in the sense that it does not recognise the existence of a God or a Supreme Being. Instead it prescribes a certain way of understanding life and dealing with it. On review before the full bench of the Orange Free State Provincial Division, Smuts J P found, on the strength of expert evidence, that Theravada Buddhism is one of the great recognised religions of the world, even though it is non-theistic. The preamble to the Republic of South Africa Constitution Act 110 of 1983 states as a national goal the "recognition and protection of freedom of faith and worship"; the legislature was obviously aware of the diversity of "faiths, religions and creeds" in the country; and it is presumed that the legislature does not intend to treat people unequally. Consequently, the Court found that the applicant's genuine Buddhist belief did constitute a "religious conviction" proclaiming that it is wrong to perform any tasks connected with the military. This brought the appellant within the confines of the Defence Act insofar as it provides relief for all "religious objectors" who object to wars 423. all The appellant consequently qualified for alternative service. The Court's finding was liberal in respect of the case under review, but the Court added that it did not accept the argument that "an applicant need not even belong to an association of individuals but even an individually held view would be sufficient to qualify as a religious conviction." 424 The court Hartman explicitly rejected the reasoning States Supreme Court in United States v Seeaer. 425 of the United In that case the Court had to interpret section 6(j) of the Universal Military Training and Service Act 426 which exempted from combat training and service in the armed forces of the United States any person who, by reason of his "religious training and belief", was conscientiously opposed to participation in war in any form. "Religious training and belief" was defined in section 6(j) as "an individual's belief in a relation to a Supreme Being involving duties superior to those arising from any human 423 At 924. 424 At 929 425 380 US 163 (1965). 426 5O USC App S 456(j) (1958 ed). relation, but [not including] essentially political, sociological, or philosophical views or a merely personal moral code." Seeger was convicted in a lower court for having refused unlawfully to submit to induction in the armed forces. He was denied the status of religious objector in terms of the Act by the lower court, which held that his convictions did not qualify as religious beliefs as circumscribed in section 6(j). In his application to be classified as a religious objector, Seeger left the question whether he believed in a Supreme Being open, and stated that his belief was a "belief in and devotion to goodness and virtue for their own sakes, and a religious faith in a purely ethical creed." Seeger cited Plato, Aristotle and Spinoza as authorities for his ethical belief in intellectual and moral integrity, which precluded him from doing military service. 427 The Court found that the appellant's beliefs were covered by section 6(j), because Congress in using the expression 'Supreme Being' rather than the designation 'God', was merely clarifying the meaning of religious training and belief so as to embrace a11 religions and to exclude essentially political, sociological, or philosophical views. We believe that under this construction, the test of belief 'in relation to a Supreme Being' is whether a given belief that is sincere and meaningful occupies a place in the life of its possessor parallel to that filled by the orthodox belief in God of one who dearly qualifies for the exemption. 428 Consequently, it was held that the appellant qualified for an exemption from normal service. This strongly subjective approach of the United States Supreme Court was rejected by the Orange Free State Provincial Division. Instead, the Hartman court identified itself with the dissenting opinion of Marian J in Welsh v United States. 429 In that case, of which the facts were similar to those of Seeger, 430 the United States Supreme Court went even further than in Seeger in upholding a subjective approach, and held 427 At 166. See also the facts regarding the other two appellants, whose cases were heard together with that of Seeger, at 167. 428 At 165. 429 398 US 333 (1970). 430 The basis of the objector's pacifism in this case was that he sincerely believed that taking anyone's 1ife was morally wrong. (See 343.) that even though an objector's pacifism was to a "substantial" degree based merely upon considerations of public policy, he was still entitled to an exemption as long as those beliefs were deeply held and were to some degree based upon "moral, ethical, or religious principle", and not "solely upon considerations of policy, pragmatism, or expediency." 431 Harlan J agreed with the conclusion of the majority, namely that the appellant's conviction had to be set aside. However, he differed from the majority in this case, and from his own opinion in the Seeger case, on what the basis should be for such a finding. Harlan now argued that through its wide interpretation of section 6(j) the Court "has performed a lobotomy and completely transformed the statute by reading out of it any distinction between religiously acquired beliefs and those deriving from 'essentially political, sociological, philosophical views or a merely personal moral code'." As a matter of statutory interpretation, or 432 according to Harlan, the wording of section 6(j) could not be stretched as far as was done in Seeger and in Welsh. In view of its natural meaning, however, the provision would have to be regarded as unconstitutional because it would, in Harlan's opinion, violate the establishment clause of the First Amendment, since it draws a line between theistic religious beliefs on the one hand, and non-theistic religious beliefs and secular convictions on the other. 433 Section 6(j) could be scrapped in its entirety consistent with the First Amendment. But in that event the long standing congressional policy of exempting religious objectors from military service would be nullified. In order to avoid this result section 6(j) has to be "patched", and relief must be given to the appellant. 434 The interesting feature of the Hartman court's embracing of the position of Marian in Welsh is that only that part of Marian's opinion that criticised the majority's interpretation of the phrase "religious training and belief" - that is, the conservative prelude to the most radical opinion expressed in the Welsh case - was quoted and 431 At 343. 432 At 351. 433 At 357. 434 At 367. applied by the Hartman court. 435 The interpretation of what should be regarded as "religious convictions" which emanates from the majority opinions in the American cases, is tied up in what Paul Tillich calls a person's "ultimate concern". 436 The effect of following this approach would be that secular resistors (categories c) and d) objectors in the above diagram) are treated the same as religious resistors (categories a) and b) objectors). The question as to whether selective pacifists categories b) and d) objectors) should be treated in the same way as universal pacifists (categories a) and c) objectors) is, however, left unanswered. The Court in Hartman acted boldly in interpreting the phrase "religious conviction" widely enough to include non-theistic religious beliefs. Strictly speaking, the Court was not required to say more. Nevertheless, the Court rejected in anticipando a further expansion of the interpretation of the phrase to include protection of secular beliefs. Could the Hartman court have followed the wider American approach in its interpretation of section 72D(1)(a)? 437 The Court referred to the fact that a narrower and a wider meaning of the words "religious convictions" can be identified. The narrower meaning requires a belief in a Supreme "convictions 435 Being which or are Beings held while the conscientiously wider and meaning which refers are to observed See also Harris SAJHR 1987 240 at 245. 436 See Anonymous Harvard Law Review 1978 1056 at 1066. According to Robinson SAPL 1987 35 at 46 "behoort die staat ... a11e innerlikgefundeerde besware as relevant vir doeleindes van inilitere dienspligweiering te aanvaar." He rejected any attempt by the state to ascertain the nature and veracity of the conviction. See also Robinson JCRDL 1984 210; Robinson Obiter 1987 100 and Robinson Wetenskaplike Bydraes van die PU vir CHO 1990 235. 437 For a defence of a restricted construction of the legal provisions relating to religious objection, see Oosthuizen JJS 1985 189. As basic premise, the author did not take the Idea of human rights, but the idea of human duties. (See 205.) The mistake he made was to assume that one has to choose between the two concepts, and not to recognise that both human rights and human duties have legitimate roles to play. In the process the author made no provision for fundamental rights such as freedom of conscience. scrupulously strictly." 438 or In regarding a belief in Theravada Buddhism as a "religious conviction", the Court eventually opted for a middle road - wider than the narrow meaning but narrower than the wide one. The narrow meaning was rejected by the Court for the reasons outlined above. But why was the wide meaning rejected? As justification for rejecting the wide meaning, the Court referred to the fact that the Defence Act requires a religious objector to state in his application the "books of revelation and the articles of faith" 439 on which hit convictions are based. The Court saw this provision as an indication that the legislature regarded it to be essential that the convictions in question must be based on such books or articles. According to the Court the source of these texts must be "'something' or 'someone' outside a human being which communicates with him." 440 This argument is weaker than it might seem. - According to section 728(3) of the Defence Act, the Board has a discretion as to whether the applicant is required to "state the books of revelation and the articles of faith" upon which his religious convictions are based - there is not obligation on the Board to require such a statement. - an absolute 441 Insofar as it is necessary to make such a statement, it should be noted that the term "books of revelation and articles of faith" is also susceptible to a narrower and a wider interpretation. It is clear from the evidence taken into account by the Hartman court that the Buddhist revelation, the Pali Canon, does not claim to be a work inspired by a Supreme Being. Surely, then, insofar as such documents are necessary, the work on non-violence espoused by, for example, Gandhi (who drew heavily upon both Christianity and necessary texts. Hinduism) can presumably 438 At 924. 439 Section 72B(2)(d). 440 At 929. 441 See Robinson De Jure 1987 374 at 379. 442 constitute the 442 At least one person who was sentenced to imprisonment for ("nonreligious") conscientious objection specifically cited Gandhi's teachings as his inspiration. See "Gandhi influence on peace fighter" Natal Post 22 Oct 1986. - Reduced to absurdity, the Hartman court's approach implies that both the founder of a faith and his followers, until he writes down his beliefs, would have to do military service. After that has been done, they may be exempted. D. EVALUATION It is submitted that South African courts in appropriate cases in the future can go beyond the court, Hartman in accepting that genuine secular pacifism, adhered to on the level of an "ultimate concern", may qualify for the same protection as religious pacifism. In other words, at least category c) resistors in the diagram should also be protected. This suggestion is based on the following: - As has been suggested, the court in Hartman simply had to establish whether a non-theist belief should be regarded as a religious belief. Its finding that other beliefs should not be treated as religious beliefs was made obiter. - As mentioned earlier, the direction in which our legislation has been moving military in service respect has of been conscientiously-based from a more objection objective to a to more subjective approach. - Freedom of conscience is a value that seemingly is gaining ground in the South African legal system, 443 Freedom of religion and a commitment to equality, if taken seriously, do not only imply the right to choose a religion, but also the equal right not to choose any. The ratio behind the (limited) provisions relating to religious objection in the South African law must be to protect the deepest feelings or convictions of people. To a non-believer or agnostic, his ethical or humanistic convictions reflect his deepest feelings. In a secular state, the convictions of those who are not religious should not be treated with less concern and respect than the convictions of those who are religious, as though the feelings of non-religious people were less important and worthy of protection. - If, as the Hartman court found, a belief in some kind of Supreme Being is not required for purposes of qualifying as a religious objector, there seems to be no reason why only Buddhism and not 443 See infra chap six IV B other value systems which reflect the concerned person's most profound convictions should qualify as a religious belief. True, it would be easier for the purpose of proving that a particular conviction is sincerely held if the requirement of religious conviction, in the traditional sense of the word, were to be insisted on. Nevertheless, considerations of expediency cannot compromise the important principle of freedom of conscience. Either no exemption should be made for objection on the basis of conscience, or such exemption should be provided for all whose deepest convictions are violated by military service, irrespective of whether those convictions are traditionally seen an to as religious or not. - It is also true that the granting of exemption some increases the burden on others, especially in times of danger. 444 It should also be not exemption alternatives requested from to by remembered, service specific those however, that what is at stake is to forms who the of object community, national to - service. military alternative way of serving the community. but service merely What is is an 445 The United States Supreme Court in Seeger held that sincere and meaningful beliefs should also be treated as religious convictions, even though "religious training and belief" in the Act under consideration in that case was defined as a "belief in relation to a Supreme Being involving duties superior to those arising from any human relation." 446 While the words of the statute, therefore, clearly spelled out the narrow meaning of religion (referred to by the Hartman court), the Court in effect substituted it with the wider meaning. The course taken by the Court was indeed far-reaching. Under the South African Defence Act, courts need not be so bold. The Defence Act merely refers to "religious convictions" without defining the term. Because the phrase is ambiguous and constitutes a serious inroad on the freedom of the individual, courts should make the choice which 444 See the judgment of Ogilvie-Thompson C J in S v Love11 1972 3 SA 760 (A) at 766. 445 See B Steyn "The case for alternative service" in Centre for Intergroup Studies Conscientious objection 104. 446 Section 6(j), quoted supra would be in favorem 1ibertatis. It is consequently submitted that, under the Defence Act, all objections to military service, held on the level of ultimate concerns, should be treated on the same footing. This still leaves unanswered the complicated question whether selective pacifists should be treated in the same way as universal pacifists. As the Defence Act currently stands, it seems clear that only universal pacifists are covered. The Act explicitly requires objection to serve in "any armed force". It is submitted that this limitation cannot be justified. The conscientious philosophical objection is the basis of protection the of legal recognition people's integrity of or "ultimate concerns", and objection to participation in a particular war, just as much as objection to participation in all wars, can be one's "ultimate concern". Insofar as integrity is involved, resistance to conscription should be treated with a high degree of leniency. 447 To summarise: As the Defence Act currently stands, not only category (a) but also category (c) objectors may and should be classified as religious objectors who qualify for alternative service. Because of the explicit requirement that the conscientious objector must believe it to be wrong to serve in the specified capacities in "any armed force", it is submitted that categories (b) and (d) objectors cannot under the present provisions of the Defence Act be so classified, although it is argued that these provisions ought to be amended. 447 See infra chap six III C. CHAPTER FIVE: CLASSICAL VIEWS ON POLITICAL AND LEGAL OBLIGATION AND RESISTANCE The views of some of the most influential shapers of Western and South African political, religious, philosophical and jurisprudential thought on political and legal obligation and resistance will be considered next. The primary focus will be on the conditions of justified disobedience, but in the course of such an inquiry the basis and limits of political obedience or obligation must also be established. After all, the one defines the limits of the other. 1 At the outset, a problem pertaining to discussions of a right of resistance must be noted. Public endorsement or rejection of a right to resist, however generally phrased, might have far-reaching practical consequences. Commentators might be induced to play down their true views on the topic for fear of governmental sanction, or because they anticipate that by endorsing a right to resist they might provide the oxygen for drastic action. On the other hand, in situations where change is desperately needed but a sufficient stimulus is absent, some observers might overstate their support for resistance. It is consequently necessary to take the particular social context of each different contribution into account. This chapter will follow the following sequence: First, an exposition will be given of the most important biblical text (Old and New Testament) on the relationship between the individual and the state. Some of the most influential Greek philosophers (Socrates, Plato, Aristotle and the Stoics) wil thereafter be discussed, as well as the 1 For general discussions of the right of resistance, see D Lumb "Legality and legitimacy: The limits of the duty of obedience to the state" in Alexandrowicz Grotian society papers 52; H J Laski "Historical introduction" in Brutus A defence of liberty against tyrants 1; Sumida "The right to revolution" in McDougal & Reisman International law in contemporary perspective 167; Berman Law and revolution in general and the essays contained in HacCormick & Bankowski Enlightenment, rights and revolution. See also Van der Vyver Contours of the Kingdom May, June 1979 6 and Paust Emory Law Journal 1983 545 as well as C W Emmet "Resistance and non-resistance" in Encyclopaedia of Religion and Ethics vol 10 736; M C Smith "Rebellion, revolution" in Encyclopaedia of Religion and Ethics vol 10 598; P N Steams "Protest movements" in Dictionary of the History of Ideas vol 3 670; H J Berman "Law and religion in the West" in The Encyclopaedia of Religion vol 8 472 and G Lewy "Revolution" in The Encyclopaedia of Religion vo1 12 374. A useful summary of the literature available on the topic is contained in Macfarlane Political disobedience 79ff. See also Hurd The Yale Law Journal 1991 1611. legacy of Roman law and jurisprudence. The contribution of the most important Christian theologians of earlier times (Augustine, Aquinas Luther and Calvin, as well as some aspects of their legacy and the dominant political philosophers (John of Salisbury Bodin, Hobbes, Locke, Rousseau, Blackstone, Kant, Bentham Hegel, the anarchists and Marx), as well as some of the most prominent contributors to the RomanDutch legal tradition (Germanic jurisprudence, Azo, the Canon law, Philip of Leyden, Bartolus, Grotius, Pufendorf, Huber, Noodt and Wolff) is next in line. Certain contemporary views of political scientists are also considered. Because of the extensive influence they had on each other, these contributions will be discussed, as far as is possible, in chronological order. In light of the important role of Christian religion in the theoretical discourse concerning political resistance in South Africa, the chapter includes a synopsis of the position taken by certain churches in this regard. Some aspects of political resistance in traditional African society are also discussed. An attempt is then made to arrive at some generalisations from the material considered. I. WESTERN POLITICAL THOUGHT The approach of Western civilization to political obligation has two main roots: the Judeo-Christian and the Greco-Roman traditions. 2 The Judeo-Christian contribution largely concerns political and social ethics as opposed to science. For example, the idea of a covenant as the basis of relationships, which underlies the notion of the social contract, is a recurrent theme in the Old Testament. But more fundamentally, the concept of the "brotherhood" of all people, linked to each other through their allegiance to the same God - the notion of "one world" - is deeply rooted in the monotheistic doctrine of the Bible. The basically egalitarian premise of the Old Testament is reinforced by the New Testamentical emphasis on the importance of love. The notion that all human beings were created in the image of the same God makes this tradition singularly susceptible to the idea that human dignity should be preserved - which in turn is basic to the idea of inalienable human rights. At the same time, the Judeo-Christian tradition accepts that a part of the human spirit is regarded as beyond the reach of temporal government. 2 See Ebenstein Great political thinkers 1. However, there is also another side to this tradition. Both Judaism and Christianity has a long history of official endorsement in different societies, which means that one might expect a strong emphasis to be placed on the duty of obedience rather than on the right of resistance. Both traditions place great emphasis on the divine endorsement of the institution of political power. Greek and Roman thought, with its politheistic religious orientation, lacked a universalistic ethical basis. This, in turn, made it difficult for members of this tradition to transcend and relativise the claims of their immediate social grouping. In the time of the golden age of Greek philosophy - the era of Socrates, Plato and Aristotle - the Greek polis was seen as a social, economic and political unity, and also as a spiritual and religious one, and consequently high priority was placed on obedience to its demands. In addition to the fact that membership of the polis was regarded during as this a condition era for emanated meaningful mainly from existence, the elite, Greek philosophy resulting in a propensity to require blind obedience from the ruled, coupled with a strong aristocratic slant in its view of political life. However, as a more lasting contribution the Greeks had their philosophy to offer, which would provide a rational basis for dealing with the question of government. That is, they made a science of political philosophy. Judeo-Christian ethics and Greek science combined to form the basis of the Western approach to political obligation. Roman law, in the classical and post-classical age, also afforded to government a primary position. The Roman contribution, however, lay in its powerful demonstration of the extent to which legal science could be used to regulate human relationships. Western political thought largely developed on the foundations of Judeo-Christian values by means of Hellenistic and Roman science. However, to some extent the above observations, which largely represent the orthodox view, oversimplify the contribution of Greek and Roman philosophy in the field of ethics. As will be indicated later on, the Greek Stoics, who made their contribution after the golden age of Greek philosophy, had a major influence on Roman and also Christian thinking. The Stoic-Christian conception of political obligation and legitimate resistance dominated Western thought for many centuries. This school of thought posited a general duty of political obedience. Nevertheless, it regarded integrity-based, religious, defensive civil disobedience as permissible, although and indeed in result-oriented some cases resistance saw of it any as a positive kind was duty, considered unacceptable. It is submitted that these aspects of Greek and Roman political culture ultimately survived, while the more aristocratic and in fact autocratic tendencies did not, because the former fitted in well with the values which underlay the Judeo-Christian tradition. These values will now be discussed in more detail, after which the contribution of the greatest Greek philosophers will be considered. A. THE BIBLE Throughout history, religion has been one of the primary sources of social solidarity and political mobilisation in human society. The observation of the late-Sophist, Critias, that rulers invented the gods to ensure compliance with their commands by people not under their physical control, might necessarily untrue. In respect of be cynical but it is obedience to earthly authority, omnipotent god, however, is a two-edged sword. the prevailing not for that reason 3 system to believers, when the belief in an Religion can legitimise that system is seen as conforming to their basic ideals. But when the system is not seen in that light, it can also mobilise people to resist the existing political dispensation. Because of the transcendental loyalty of the believer, religion has a strong subversive potential. The idea that the political ruler represents God on earth affords special authority to his station in life, but, at the same time, the fact that rulers sometimes do act unjustly and even require their subordinates to sin, confront believers with the theodicy problem: how can a good and omnipotent God allow, and in this case sanction, evil? This problem requires believers to accept that not a11 rulers represent God. It will be argued, however, that the Stoic approach of the early church in the time of its persecution, and identification of the church with the governing elite since Christianity became the state religion of the Roman Empire, caused active or result-oriented resistance, aimed at openly challenging the state, never to acquire a dominant position in the tradition of the church. 3 See Greyer Die wysbegeerte van die Grieke 69. The influential research of Emilé Durkheim in this regard is discussed -In Lukes & Scull Durkheim and law. There are a number of important passages in the Bible in which the issue of political obligation is canvassed, directly or indirectly. (1) The Old Testament Religion played a major role in sustaining the political unity of Israel and obedience to its internal leaders. At the same time, it inspired much Religious of Israel’s inspiration for resistance political against foreign disobedience is domination. evident, for example, in the history of Hezekiah, the king of Judah, when "[h]e rebelled against the king of Assyria and did not serve him." 4 Similarly, Daniel's friends, Shadrach, Meshach and Abednego, refused to worship the image of gold set up by King Nebuchadnezzar. They told the king: "We want you to know, D king, that we will not serve your gods or worship the image of gold you have set up." 5 Daniel himself defied a decree of king Darius not to worship his God. Three times a day he prayed at open windows towards Jerusalem. Daniel was thrown in the lion's den, but according to Scripture, remained unharmed. 6 It should not be presumed, however, that the internal power relationships between Israel’s rulers and their subjects were based on the divine power of kings. The Old Testament portrays Israelites as a most rebellious nation, whose kings were servants of Javeh and were subject to the censorship of his prophets. 7 (2) The New Testament The most important event of the New Testament - the crucifixion of Christ - was the result of an act in defiance of the existing worldly order by the Son of God In obedience to the authority of God himself. At the same time, the defiance was non-violent and open. As indicated earlier, in consequently secular of terms much of this central Western pivot of civilization, Christianity, can therefore and be described as an act of civil disobedience through which the present world order was established. It inspired many who defied worldly authority to believe that their defiance was justified. 4 2 Kings 18.7. 5 See Daniel 3.18. 6 Daniel 6. 7 See M C Smith "Rebellion, revolution" in Encyclopaedia of Religion and Ethics vol 10 598 at 598. See also Calvert Revolution 49. For a discussion of the rulers of the Bible, see Weber Power 47ff. At the same time, the New Testament contains passages which maintain, in strong language, that earthly authority should be obeyed. We will now consider some of the most important texts regarding non-violent political resistance, while brief reference will be made to interpretations of those texts. In his teachings, Christ emphasised the need not to take violent revenge. In the Sermon on the Mount, in a passage often quoted by proponents of non-violent resistance, he said: You for who him have heard that it was said, "an eye for an eye, and a tooth a tooth." But now I tell you: do not take revenge on someone does you wrong. If anyone slaps you on the right cheek, let slap you on the left cheek too. 8 Upon being arrested, Christ ordered Simon Peter to put away his sword. 9 Peter would later say, with reference to Christ: "When he was insulted he did not answer back with an insult; when he suffered he did not threaten, but placed his hopes in God." 10 The Gospel, however, also recounts the incident where "Jesus went into the temple and drove out all those who bought and sold in the temple; he overturned the tables of the money-changers and the stools of those who sold pigeons." 11 Although the use of violence is consequently not excluded altogether, the emphasis is on non-violence. How did Jesus see political obligation? When he was asked by Pontius Pilot whether he was the king of the Jews, Jesus answered: "My kingdom does not belong to this world." 12 This statement seems to suggest that earthly political obligations should be relativised. Christ was asked by the Pharisees whether tax should be paid to the Roman Emperor by the Jews. Christ responded by saying, "[S]how me the coin to pay the tax!" They brought him the coin, and he asked: "Whose face and name are these?" They answered, "The Emperor’s", to which Jesus said: "Well, then, pay to the Emperor what belongs to him, and 8 Matthew 5.38, 39. See also Luke 6.29, 30. 9 John 18.11. 10 See 1 Peter 2.23. 11 Matthew 21.12. See also Mark 11.15-19; Luke -19.45-48 and John 2.13-22. 12 John 18.36. pay to God what belongs to God." 13 Jesus’ teachings directly inspired disobedience of earthly authorities amongst his immediate followers. His disciples, Peter and John were arrested for spreading the gospel in the temple, and were brought before the Council. After being told not to speak or teach in the name of Jesus under any circumstances, Peter and John told the Council: "You yourself judge which is right in God's sight, to obey you or to obey God. For we cannot stop speaking of what we ourselves have seen and heard. " 14 The leaders of the church realised the threat posed by the apostles to their position and had them arrested. According to Scripture, the apostles were then given divine instructions to disobey: "[A]n angel of the Lord opened the prison gates, led the apostles out, and said to them, ‘Go and stand in the temple, and tell the people all about this new life.’ The apostles obeyed, and at dawn they entered the temple and started teaching." 15 They were again arrested and brought before the Council, where the High Priest questioned them. "’We gave you strict orders not to teach in the name of this man’, he said; ‘but see what you have done! You have spread your teaching all over responsible for his death!’" Jerusalem, and you want to make us 16 Peter and the other apostles then gave their famous answer, recorded in Acts 5.29: "We must obey God, not men." The Counci1 decided not to put the apostles to death. They cabled the apostles in, had them whipped, and ordered them never again to speak in the name of Jesus; and then they set them free. The apostles left the Council, full of joy that God had considered them worthy to suffer disgrace for the name of Jesus. And every day in the temple and in people's homes they continued to teach and preach the good news about Jesus the Messiah. 17 Paul, however, placed much emphasis on the duty of Christians to obey state authority. No doubt, the best known exposition n this regard, 13 Matthew 22.19-21. See also Mark 12.13-17 and Luke 20.20-26. 14 Acts 4.19, 20. 15 Acts 5.19-21. 16 Acts 5.28. 17 Acts 5.40-42. which is encountered again and again in the works of later writers, is contained in Romans 13:1-6: Everyone must obey the state authorities, because no authority exists without God’s permission, and the existing authorities have been put there by God. Whoever opposes the existing authority opposes what God has ordered; and anyone who does so will bring judgment on himself. For rulers are not to be feared by those who do good but by those who do evil. Would you like to be unafraid of the man in authority? Then do what is good, and he will praise you. For he is God’s servant working for your own good. But if you do evil, be afraid of him, because his power to punish is real. He is God’s servant and carries out God’s wrath on those who do evil. For this reason you must obey the authorities - not just because of God’s wrath, but also as a matter of conscience. This is also authorities are Pay, then, what taxes, and show the reason that you pay taxes, because the working for God when they fulfil their duties. you owe them; pay them your personal and property respect and honour for them a11. Paul wrote this to the congregation in Rome, which was subjected to the rule of the Roman government. That government was described in Revelation 13 as a "beast from the sea" that cursed God. Paul also said: "Remind your people to submit to rulers and authorities, to obey them ..." 18 Peter urged the early Christians to "submit yourselves, for the Lord’s sake, to every human authority: to the Emperor, who is the supreme authority, and to the governors, who have been sent by him to punish the evil-doers and praise those who do good." 19 He also urged them to "respect the Emperor". 20 Not surprisingly, these texts have been the object of widely divergent interpretations. Insofar as resistance is allowed, many commentators emphasised the strong - although not absolute - insistence of the Bible on non-violence. 21 18 Titus 3.1. 19 1 Peter 2.13, 14. 20 1 Peter 2.17. 21 See eg Wink Jesus' third way 12ff and Régamey Non-violence and the Christian conscience 79ff. See also IDO-C When all else falls and Culliton Non-violence, where it is argued that non-violence is central to Christian spirituality. It should be noted, however, that 1t has been estimated that of approximately 980 million professed Christians in 1971, probably less than 600 However, controversy centred upon the question how the general duty to obey the state, as exemplified in Romans 13, is to be reconciled with the first loyalty of Christians toward God, as posited in Acts 5. 22 In view of the obedience general to interpolation. God, 23 message some of have the Bible, rejected which Romans requires 13 as a ultimate supposed It has also been claimed that Christ was in fact a political rebel and sympathised with the Zealots, who strove towards the liberation of Israel from oppression by Rome. Paul then supposedly covered this up through his attempt to portray Christ as a divine saviour in non-political terms, inter alia in Romans 13. 24 Others saw this pericope as entailing a strict requirement of government. obedience to any 25 One of the more popular - and feasible - views is to regard Romans 13 as a corrective on the "over-enthusiastic" congregation in Rome who, as citizens of God’s Kingdom, rejected the very notion of secular authority and regarded themselves only as citizens of the Kingdom of God. The message of Romans 13 is, therefore, that the institution of the state as such accords with God's wishes, but it does not at all address the issue of an unjust government. The latter issue, according to this interpretation, is addressed by texts such as Acts 5.29. 26 In conclusion, it seems fair to say that the Bible poses a general duty of obedience to secular authority. This duty is secondary, however, to 000 were universal pacifists. That is less than a one-thousandth part of the total number. See D P Whitelaw "Christian responses to violence: A historical survey" in Vorster Views on violence 21 at 34. 22 For a general discussion of the texts, see Van der Walt Wetenskaplike Bydraes van die PU vir CHO 1983 1. According to E1off Die subordineringsopdrag van die owerhede 82ff, Christian disobedience must necessarily be non-violent, non-reactive and non-demonstrative: "Dit is nie 'n reaksie teen 'n stelsel of selfs 'n spesifieke wet nie, maar primer gehoorsaamheid aan God. Dit mag dus nie polities geïnspireerd wees nie." 23 See the discussion by J De ViTliers "Die Christen en die staat volgens die Nuwe Testament" in Du Toil Staatsgesag en burgerlike ongehoorsaaiBheld 20 at 35. 24 Id 27. 25 Id 20. 26 This approach, usually associated with the name of Kasemann (id 21), was also adhered to in the South African Kairos document (see infra II B). See also 0 J Bosch "Kerk en politick in die Suid-Afrikaanse konteks" in Smith et a1 Stonn-kompas 24. the higher duty of disregarding the authorities if they were to require their subjects to disobey the will of God. In such cases, where one’s religious integrity is at stake, defensive civil disobedience is justified. There is no explicit endorsement or rejection of stronger forms of resistance to be found in the Bible. 27 B. GREEK PHILOSOPHY (1) Socrates and Plato Political philosophy finds its illustrious origin in the thought of Socrates (469-399 BC) 28 and his student, Plato (427-347 BC). 29 Socrates did not produce any writing himself, and his life and thought is known to us mainly through the dialogues of Plato, in which he played the dominant role. Plato, however, had his own objectives in the way in which he portrayed Socrates. 30 The political message contained in Plato’s account of the death of Socrates was discussed earlier, when the double-barrel legacy of Socrates was considered: Through the device of sacrificial civil disobedience he reconciled the need to be true to one’s own conscience with the obligation to obey the law. 31 In this section Plato’s views on political obligation will be considered. Plato’s political thought is set out mainly in three books: The republic, The statesman and The laws. The influence of these books, and especially The republic, considered to be the first work on political science in centuries the of articulation history its of of philosophy, existence, virtually all is the throughout incalculable. modern day the The twenty first issues of three recorded political philosophy can be found in Plato’s writings. 27 On political resistance among the early Christians, see supra chap three II D. 28 On Socrates' philosophy in general, see Copleston A history of philosophy vol 1 117ff. On Socrates' political philosophy, see Strauss & Cropsey History of political philosophy 2ff. On his legal philosophy, see Du P1essis Westerse regsdenke tot en met die middeleeue 66ff. 29 On Plato's philosophy in general, see Copleston A history of philosophy vol 1 151ff. On his political philosophy, see Ebenstein Great political thinkers Iff; Strauss & Cropsey History of political philosophy 7ff and Lee's Introduction in Plato The republic 11ff. His views on political resistance are discussed by Calvert Revolution 32ff. On Plato's legal philosophy, see Du P1essis Westerse regsdenke tot en met die middeleeue 77ff. 30 See Copleston A history of philosophy vo1 1 120. 31 See supra chap three II C. Plato was the first to subject government as an institution to rigorous rational analysis. Moreover, he established the crucial connection between what psychology reveals about individuals on the one hand and political theory on the other (although much of what he said concerning the individual’s psyche is no longer accepted). Plato also introduced the concept of the "public" as distinct from the "private". 32 Although Plato’s inquiry, and subjection the concepts of he political introduced, institutions have been to scientific central to the development of Western political philosophy, his political views are largely discredited. aristocratic, and His expressly approach was distinctly anti-democratic and elitist or anti-individual. Plato’s position was that those who know should rule over those who do not know, regardless of the latter’s consent. The philosopher-king has the right to rule (and the subjects must obey) because he has the clearest view of the unchanging "idea of the good" - the concept which is central to Platonic philosophy. A number of causes can be cited for Plato's opposition to democracy, and his commitment to the rule of the aristocracy. The first had to do with his own personal position in Athens of the Fifth and Fourth Centuries. Being from a noble family, Plato apparently had personal political aspirations which never materialised, due to the rise of democracy. Moreover, after the Peloponnesian War (419-404 BC), two of Plato’s uncles led the Thirty Tyrants, and were eventually killed by the democrats. When democracy was restored, Socrates was tried and executed. Plato blamed democracy for the death of Socrates. 33 Plato regarded his society as sick and maintained that it had to be cured. Plato's diagnoses and proposed cure were far-reaching. Democracy, to him, was only a symptom of a more basic problem that was destroying society from within. The problem was change - itself, manifested in its worst form in social revolution. The world was moving away from its original form - its divine form or idea - in the image of which it was created. As organisms, political structures are subjected to changes in 32 33 See Ebenstein Great political thinkers 2. In trial of Tyrants, was that entirely The trial of Socrates, I F Stone argued Socrates and its outcome was Socrates' and his failure to take a stand against he was undemocratic - a charge which, unfounded. that the main reason for the association with the Thirty them. In essence, the charge according to Stone, was not accordance with the ebb and flow of nature. Social change had to be arrested, because it inevitably involves social deterioration. Timocracy (a state governed by by people whose primary motivation is love of honour) would naturally democracy and eventually to tyranny. evolve into oligarcy, thence to 34 Plato’s approach is perhaps best understood - if contrasted with that of Hegel, which will be discussed later. Although both proceeded from the ideal conducive right situation, to of Hegel development, resistance to saw and conflict and consequently authoritarian change as endorsed a government, healthy and far-reaching while Plato entertained the exact opposite view. Pre-Socratic Greek philosophy identified the alternative sources of political obligation as either "nature" (physis) or "convention" (also called law or nomos). 35 The first implies a measure of necessity, the latter contingency. Not surprisingly, then, given his objectives, Plato would latch onto the former, which placed him in the category of the natural lawyers. The term "natural law", as perceived by its early proponents, however, referred to a basis for the legitimacy of the coercive power of the state and consequently for political obligation, rather than to a formulation of a right to resist, as would be the case with later adherents to natural law such as Locke. Plato developed a cosmology and political theory which would posit a most rigid hierarchical structure embracing the individual and which would allow very little political resistance. 36 scope for individual decision-making and According to Plato, someone who disagrees with the state should speak his mind, if that is likely to produce a good result. But force against his native land he should not use in order to bring about a change of constitution, when it is not possible for the best constitution to be introduced without driving men into exile or putting them to death; he should keep quiet and offer up prayers for his own welfare and for that of the country. 37 34 See the discussion by Calvert Revolution 32. 35 See Strauss & Cropsey History of political philosophy 3. 36 See Karl Popper's contribution entitled "Plato" Encyclopaedia of the Social Sciences vol 12 159 at 162. 37 in International See "Plato to the relatives and friends of Dion: Welfare", reprinted as Letter 7 in Plato The Platonic epistles 115 at 123, 331a-331e. The central question addressed in The republic was what is dikaiosune what is "justice" or "doing right"? 38For Plato this was the same as asking what is the basis of social and moral obligation. This problem was addressed in four stages. First Socrates - the main character in the dialogue - showed that the conventional view, that justice meant honesty and rendering what is due to gods and men, had some merit but was ultimately inadequate. 39 The view that justice consists in helping one’s friends and harming one’s enemies was also rejected. 40 Especially interesting is Socrates’ next encounter, with Thrasymachus of Chalcedon, who regarded justice as "simply what is in the interest of the stronger party". 41 Obedience is enforced by the stronger group in society and is not voluntarily granted by the weak. Morality is nothing more than the code of behaviour so extracted. Justice or law is consequently not necessarily good for the subjects - it might even be bad. For the rulers, justice simply does not exist as a constraint they lay down the law with exclusive concern for their own advantage. Socrates, in responding to these statements, asked how this understanding of justice was affected by the fact that rulers may often be mistaken about their own interests. Thrasymachus replied that rulers, as rulers, are never mistaken - when they are mistaken they are not rulers. Socrates argued that government exercise of any skill as such is disinterested. is 42 a skill, and the Consequently, justice cannot simply be the interests of the stronger. As always, Plato arranged for Socrates to have the better of this particular encounter (not least by portraying Thrasymachus as extremely rude), but history would prove the debate to be far from over. 43 Indeed, 38 Plato The republic 331c. 39 Id 331e-334b. 40 Id 334b-336a. 41 Id 338c. 42 Id 342. 43 It seems that Plato was deeply troubled by the argument advanced by Thrasymachus. His claim is repeatedly addressed in the other dialogues of Plato. See eg Plato's Gorgias 483, where Callicles observed "This is, in fact, how justice is determined: the stronger shall rule and have the advantage over his inferior." as " Dahrendorf indicated, the Socrates-Thrasymachus debate is the first recorded exposition of the opposition between what would become two dominant notions in political theory. 44 The Socratic position would be taken up by Rousseau and others, who emphasised the need for political power to be executed legitimately or with authority. On the other hand, Thrasymachus’ position would be followed by people like Machiavelli and Hobbes, who maintained that power is unequally divided in society and argued, in the words of Dahrendorf, which "legitimacy amounts at best to a precarious resistance it engenders." 45 preponderance of power over the To them political obligation is determined by control and not by authority. After his encounter with Thrasymachus, Socrates was confronted by Glaucon with the argument that an individual’s morality and political obedience is prompted merely by the prospect of reward or social approval - that is, by convenience. It is simply in order to avoid social and other sanctions that people act "justly". 46If people had no fear of detection there would have been no obedience. 47 To counter this, what in modern terms would be called consequentialist view, Socrates maintained that justice should be welcomed "both for its own sake and for its consequences". 48 Socrates argued that it is easier to study objects on a large scale than on a small scale, and proposed firstly to discuss justice in the state or country and then to apply the conclusions so reached to the individual. How, then, would the natural state look? This question leads one directly to Plato's discussion of the ideal city-state or "Cal1ipolis". The reason for this device is that "justice" or "law-abidingness" can be good only if the law is good; and good laws can emanate only from a good city. 49 Plato’s description of the ideal city is well-known and need not be elaborated upon in any detail. Plato, through Socrates, described a 44 See Dahrendorf Essays in the theory of society 129ff. 45 Id 138. 46 See Plato The republic 358b. 47 Id 360a. 48 Id 358a. 49 See Strauss & Cropsey History of political philosophy 16. See also Plato The laws 201ff. "first city" - a type of state of nature that would develop naturally before a "feverish condition" or serious instability sets in. Rational considerations then lead to division of society into three classes, which correspond with the "three parts of the soul". At the lowest level there are the workers, who satisfy material wants or appetite and are guided by the virtue of industriousness. At the intermediate level there are the fighters or auxiliaries, whose conduct is conditioned by the virtue of courage. At the highest level there are the rulers, whose characteristic attribute is wisdom. For Plato, the ultimate ideal is that of the philosopher-king, trained to have a proper understanding of the good and subjected to the most discipline. 50 rigorous Justice prevails in such a state when every individual occupies the station in life most interfere suitable "with to each his abilities other’s and jobs". 51 the three Similarly, classes justice do not in the individual means that all parts of the soul are subjected to reason. 52 The important point, then, is that justice is the harmony of the individual soul and of the classes in society. "Doing right", therefore means acting in harmony with nature, as it reveals itself through reason. One has to take one’s place in the hierarchical structure of the state and ultimately the cosmos, which has at its apex the "idea of the good". A number of "imperfect societies" were then discussed by Socrates oligarchy, 53 democracy 54 and tyranny, 55 in order to show that the life of the just man and the philosopher is more worthy than that of any other. Tyranny and democracy, for example, are characterised by surrendering to the basic desires. At the end of the exposition, Socrates concluded that goodness and justice brings its own reward. 56 The Platonic model can to a considerable extent be regarded as the prototype of the traditional natural law approach, which saw political structures in hierarchical terms, 50 See Plato The republic 471. 51 Id 434c. 52 Id 441b-444e. 53 Id Book 8.4. 54 Id Book 8.6. 55 Id Book 8.8. 56 Id Book 9,2. legitimised from above, by a metaphysical ideal. Because Plato’s ideal state had transcendental sanction, it needed no popular recognition and resistance could not be justified. (2) Aristotle Aristotle (384-322 BC), 57 the greatest systematic thinker of ancient Greece, unlike his teacher, Plato, concentrated not primarily on the ideal, the perfect, but on that which is actually possible and attainable. A major part of Aristotle’s teachings dealt with government and ethics, and he wrote what is still today considered to be an introductory textbook to the entire field of political science - The politics, which should be considered together with his Nicomachean ethics. Although intimately associated with the Macedonian monarchy, and the tutor of Alexander the Great, Aristotle - himself from a middle class background - would be much less elitist than Plato. Nevertheless, it is clear that Aristotle’s political perspective was from the side of the rulers, not the ruled. Aristotle placed the virtue of the rulers above the consent of the governed. In contrast to the Sophists, who based political obligation on convention or contract, he regarded its source as the natural order. Like the other early proponents of this school of thought, Aristotle saw natural law primarily as a basis for political obligation, not resistance. 58 Aristotle’s political philosophy should be seen against the background of his philosophy as a whole, to which only the scantiest reference can be made here. According to Aristotle’s teleological approach humankind strives towards eudaimomia, which refers to the fulfilment of each person’s function or "happiness". In the course of this pursuit the correct choice is always the avoidance of extremes - the mean must be chosen. In his political philosophy Aristotle was primarily interested in establishing how, in the less than ideal circumstances of real life, 57 On Aristotle's philosophy in general, see Vorländer Geschiedenis van da Wijsbageerte vol 197ff and Dreyer Die wysbegeerte van die Grieke 121ff. On his political philosophy, see Ebenstein Great political thinkers 66 and Strauss & Cropsey History of political philosophy 64. His views on political resistance are discussed by Calvert Revolution 33ff. His legal philosophy is dealt with by Du Plessis Westerse regsdenke tot en net die middeleeue 102ff and Van Eikema Homines Major trends in the history of legal philosophy 17ff. 58 Aristotle's defence of the institution of slavery and of the inferior position of women was also based on what he saw as the natural order. this could be approximated in the social context. In the opening lines of The politics, Aristotle set out two crucial ideas: (i) the polis 59 is a community; and (ii) it is the highest of all communities. 60 The description of the polis as a community must be contrasted with the instrumentalist view of the state, which sees the state as an instrument to be used for a higher purpose than itself. This latter view, adhered to by the Sophists and later revived by Hobbes and Locke, was rejected by both Plato and Aristotle. Instead Aristotle regarded the state as an organic community; an organism with the attributes of a living being. "Man" in his view, "is naturally a political animal" which can reach his telos only in the polis. 61 Moreover, the polis is not just a community like any other. It is also the highest community, aimed at the highest good. The family exists for the preservation of life; the village for the comforts of companionship; but the polis exists for the sake of the good life, and not for the sake of life only. Humankind’s moral nature can be expressed only in the polis - not in a bigger and not in a smaller context. To Aristotle the polis was held together not by impersonal laws, but by personal bonds of friendship and morality. 62 To Aristotle the polis was natural in two ways: (i) Social institutions evolve from the family through the village to the polis, which is the natural and final stage in the growth of human relations, and (ii) the polis was also natural in a philosophical sense, "[f]or the whole must needs be prior to its part." 63 Political obligation to Aristotle was therefore, to use a modern expression, a "natural duty", 64in the sense that it is simply the result of one’s citizenship, which in turn is a natural consequence of being human. 59 For a discussion of the proper translation of the word "polls", see Strauss & Cropsey History of political philosophy 65. Although the usual translation is "state" or "city-state", these terms do not properly signify the all-inclusive nature of the polls. 60 Aristotle The politics 1.1 61 Id 1.2. 62 Ibid. 63 Ibid. 64 Sea infra chap five I EE (4). This, however, does not imply that Aristotle expected rigid conformity. In spite of his belief in the organic nature of political society, Aristotle did not place the same emphasis on unity or uniformity in the as polis Plato. Aristotle recognised that "not only does a state consist of a number of individuals but the individuals are different in kind," 65 Having influence, been where raised there on was the much edge of exposure the to Greek sphere different of cultures, Aristotle’s approach was one of tolerance for diversity. His po1is was heterogeneous, not homogeneous. What type of state would best serve humankind's needs as a "political animal"? Aristotle distinguished three forms of government which could each be either unperverted (conducted in the interests of the ruled) or perverted (conducted only in the interest of the rulers). The three forms of genuine or unperverted government are kingship, aristocracy, and (a polity qualification). democracy In limited perverted form by these a types considerable of property government become tyranny, oligarchy, and democracy (in the sense of the rule by the poor, for the poor). 66 The distinguishing feature of bad government is consequently the element of exploitation. Aristotle’s deep anti-democratic sentiments are evident in his discussion of the phenomenon of the "individual of pre-eminent virtue". Such an individual, Aristotle maintained, should not be subjected to the law, "for we might as well presume to rule Zeus. It remains then, as indeed seems natural, that all should render willing obedience to such a one, and that he and his like should thus be perpetual kings within their states." 67 In the ideal, therefore, Aristotle would have preferred an enlightened monarchy. Nevertheless, he realised that this would require a standard of virtue absent in most societies. Consequently, as a practical matter, he accepted that decisions should rather be taken by many than by one. Aristotle accepted political participation as the hallmark of citizenship. In order to steer between the dangers of oligarchy (rule by the rich) and democracy (rule by the poor) Aristotle chose polity, in the sense of a kind of middle class 65 Aristotle The politics 2.2. 66 Id 7. 67 Id 3.13. rule. In accordance with his general approach, he also in this instance took the middle option. Aristotle is widely regarded as the founder of the study of revolutions. In Book 8 of The politics, commonly known as the "Book of revolutions", he provided a most perceptive account of the origins of revolutions. He regarded their prime cause not in the stereotypical manner, as the design of malignant instigators who must be repressed by force, but rather as social conditions which often could and should be rectified. Aristotle regarded the general author of sedition and insurrection as inequality and what in modern terms could be called the "sense of injustice". 68He outlined various more specific reasons for political revolutions, such as the disproportionate distribution of power between classes 69 and diversity of race. 70 In accordance with his wider political system Aristotle also dealt at length with the different causes of revolutions in democracies, 71 oligarchies 72 and aristocracies, 73 A monarchy becomes a tyranny if the monarch pays no regard to the public weal, but instead seeks only his own pleasure. 74 Revolution can be averted inter alia by preventing a monopoly of power in the hands of a single class or order 75 and through political education. 76 Aristotle unlike Plato viewed revolutions to some extent as an inevitable component of political change. Political change takes place in cycles, which means that, while Plato was correct in describing the decay of political systems into tyranny, it should also be recognised 68 [W]henever one party or the other fails to enjoy such a political influence as is consistent with its own conception of Justice, it becomes the author of sedition." Id 8.1. (Original emphasis.) 69 Id 8.3.7. 70 Id 8.3.11. 71 Id 8.5. 72 Id 8.6. 73 Id 8.7. 74 Id 8.10. 75 Id 8.8.10. 76 Id 8.9. that tyranny in turn decays and initiates new cycles of change. 77 Aristotle, then, also adhered to the view that obedience was based on the natural recognise a order. At right to the same resist, time, he however, regarded while revolutions he as did not natural phenomena under certain circumstances. As will be demonstrated, Aristotle’s views gained considerable prominence when it was integrated into Christian theology by Aquinas. (3) Stoicism Stoicism, one of the dominant philosophies of the Hellenistic-Roman period, was founded during the last years of Fourth Century Greece by Zeno of Citium (336-264 BC) and his successor Chrysippus of Soli (c 280-c 206 BC). 78 Stoicism spread to Rome when Diogenes of Seleucia and Carneades the Sceptic visited the city in 156 BC. It flourished and eventually declined in Rome in the First and Second Centuries AD. The specific contribution of the Roman Stoics - and especially Cicero will be dealt with later. 79 Only a general survey of some of the recurrent themes in Stoic thought will now be given. It is revealing to note that Stoicism came to the fore in the moral vacuum that emerged when the Greek polis declined. The central role of the polis in the Greek world view and political life was discussed earlier. Where security could be found if not in the polis? Clearly not in the fickle and frivolous Greek gods. Zeno had the same premise as his predecessors, the Cynics, who maintained that unhappiness and insecurity resulted from the pursuit of that which was beyond the control of the individual. One had to know the difference between that which can be changed, and that which cannot, and concern oneself only with the former. The only aspect of our existence which is really within our power is pursuit of the correct moral attitude or virtue. We must become indifferent to all the passions, 77 78 and even should hold no fear, because one can do See Calvert Revolution 33ff. Greek Stoicism Wenley Stoicism and vol 1 l20ff; Van philosophy 29ff and 115ff. 79 death and its political and legal implications are discussed by its influence; Vorländer Geschiedenis van de wijsbegeerte Eikema Homines Major trends in the history of legal Du Plessis Westerse regsdenke tot en met die middeleeue See infra chap five I C. nothing about it. The only possible good is virtue, and the only evil is vice - all else is morally indifferent. One’s highest loyalty should be to be true to oneself, to one’s own nature or integrity. Each person must be the captain of his own soul - nothing more, but also nothing less. What does it mean to be true to one’s own nature? Reason is the active force in the universe, and it is also an active force in human beings. Humans must consequently accommodate their own beings to universal nature or reason. Virtue means that one lives in harmony with nature. In place of the polis, the Stoics therefore postulated the cosmos-po1is - a universal community in which all people (or at least all men) are equal. He whose being is in harmony with nature, will also be a citizen of the universe. Clearly, these premises had far-reaching political implications. The very basis of the authoritarian view of the state of earlier Greek philosophers - the notion that perfect life could be lived in the polis only - was rejected. The highest possible moral achievement was no longer compliance with the positive law of the polis, but obedience to natural law as it reveals itself in human reason. The preservation of one’s integrity was now regarded as more important than any earthly obligation. The Stoa were not as radical as the Cynics, who refused to participate in the institutions of state and family. 80 Nevertheless, the idea that each person is the captain of his own soul has definite implications for the idea of political obedience. On the one hand, the Stoics took it to mean that those commands of the state that do not affect one’s virtue should be obeyed, even if it causes discomfort, because it belongs to the realm of things beyond one’s control. Resistance would here serve no purpose. On the other hand, it meant that in respect of laws that could compromise one’s virtue there is no obligation to obey the state. In those cases one has a higher obligation - namely to natural law. This does not mean that the state should in such cases be actively resisted. It merely means that its demands should simply not be obeyed. Natural law as perceived by the Stoics did not in the first place endorse political power, as other early proponents of natural law 80 31. See Van Eikema Homines Major trends in the history of legal philosophy perceived it to do – instead it provided a criterion that could be used to establish the limits of obedience. In this sense. Stoicism can be seen as an exception to the traditional natural law approach and as the early forerunners of the modern notion of inalienable fundamental rights. Stoicism postulated the idea that one should be faithful to one’s own nature. The demands of nature are conveyed to the individual through the voice of his own nature, ie his conscience. That inner voice should be obeyed at all costs, and if it conflicts with laws of the state, conscience should prevai1. To express the Stoic approach to political resistance in the terminology used, in this study - the preservation of one’s integrity can justify and disobedience, but indeed not demand integrity-based result-oriented resistance. defensive civil This would idea largely be taken over by Christianity, although "integrity" would be interpreted to refer only to religious convictions. As will be demonstrated, the Stoic-Christian idea of a general duty of obedience, except where one’s personal highest values are compromised, would until at least the Reformation dominate Western political thought, and it continues to exercise a strong influence to this day. Although their claims were limited, the Stoic emphasis on human conscience lies at the basis of the Western approach to political resistance. C. ROMAN JURISPRUDENCE Roman civilization produced some of history’s most outstanding leaders. While Augustine represented the apex of enlightenment of that time, others, like Diocletian, were notorious tyrants. 81 The rule of Julius Caesar was more controversial - some regarded him as a hero and others as a villain. Not surprisingly, then, Rome harboured a wide spectrum of political dissidents. This raises questions as to what the nature of the power of the Roman rulers treated was, and, whence in they general, derived to their what powers, extent how dissidents recognition was were given to illegal political resistance. 81 For a useful overview of the political history of Rome, see Gary & Scullard A history of Rome and for the legal background, see De Villiers JSAL 1979 83 at 86ff. See in general Kunkel An Introduction to Roman legal and constitutional history. While, in the time of the Republic (510/509 - 27 BC), provision was made for relatively widespread political participation and a system of checks and balances, political power became more and more centralised during the Empire (since 27 BC). 82 Since at least late Republican times, the ruler, mundi. 83 according to Roman thinking, was without doubt dominus Often quoted in this regard are the maxims: princeps legibus solutus est 84 and salus rei publicae suprema lex. 85 Ulpian’s observation, quod principi placuit, legis habet vigorem, 86 has been described as "perhaps the most influential passage of the whole of the Corpus Juris Justiniani politics in the granted formation the Emperor of Western merum political imperium - the thought." 87 highest Roman form of public power - which included the ius gladii or right of the sword and the right to make laws. 88 At least on the face of it, the powers of the Roman rulers seems absolute. What was the foundation of this power? The Romans, since the time of the Republic, invested the consules with imperium by means of the lex de imperio. Traditionally the imperium was invested in the consules upon election at the comitia or meeting of the people. During the Empire, the successors of Augustus invoked the lex de imperio as the basis of their power as Emperors. 89 Ulpian and Justinian called the lex de imperio, lex regia and referred to it as the foundation of the legislative power of the princeps. 90 However, little is known about the exact provisions of the lex regia. 82 See Kunkel An l4ff, 35ff. 83 Introduction to Roman legal and constitutional history See Skinner The foundations of modern political thought vol 1 8. 84 The Emperor is free from the operation of the law." D 1.3.31. See, for a discussion of this maxim, Steyn Die uitleg van wette 73ff. 85 On the obscure origins of this maxim, see Venter JCRDL 1977 233 at 235. 86 Whatever the Emperor has decreed has the force of law; since by a royal ordinance [the lex regia] which was passed concerning his sovereignty, the people conferred upon him all their own authority and power." D 1.4.1. 87 See Hahlo & Kahn The South African legal system and its background 431. 88 See Skinner The foundations of modern political thought vo1 2 127. 89 See Van den Bergh The life and work of Gerard Noodt 194. 90 See D 1.4.1 pr and Inst 1.2.6. Ulpian also referred to the case of Barbarius Philippus, who was chosen as praetor while he was a runaway slave by people who were unaware of his true status. U1p1an argued that the edicts of such a praetor should not necessarily be deemed nullities since the Roman people were competent to confer such power on a slave. D 14.3. Since earliest times, Roman law made provision for the imposition of harsh penalties upon those who were perceived to threaten the security of the state. 91 The law of the Twelve Tables had already mentioned perdue11io as a capital crime, stating: "If anyone would stir up war against his country, or delivers a Roman citizen into the hands of the enemy, he shall be punished with death." 92 This provision was supplemented by the introduction of other crimes against the state or its officials, such as proditio and seditio. 93 The exact demarcations of these different offences is a matter of controversy, but they were all compounded under Justinian as different ways in which the crimen laesae majestatis (forerunner of the crime of treason in South African law) could be committed. 94 The lex Julia de majestatis provided: "The crime of lese majesty is committed against the Roman people, or against their safety." 95 Acts through which this crime could be committed included not only a variety of threats to the state through the use of arms and the provision of assistance to the enemy, 96 but also desertion from military service 97 and the fraudulent performance of "some act of authority or magistracy". 98 In a general clause the law provided that "he who injures the dignity of the state shall be liable." 99 Various other laws, such as the lex Julia de vi publica, 100 also protected state authority and the public order. It should be noted that 91 See eg the discussion of tyrannicide under Roman Davidson Problems of the Roman criminal law vo1 1 )7. 92 law in Strachan- Table 9 Law 7. See also D 48.4.3. 93 See Coertze JCRDL 1937 274; Gonin JCRDL 1951 1 and De Wet & Swanepoel Strafreg 518. 94 See also Milton South African criminal law and procedure vol 2 2. For a full discussion, see Bauroan The crimen maiestatis 1n the Roman Republic and Augustan Principate. See also the discussion of the crime of treason, supra chap four I D (1). 95 D 48.4.1. 96 Ibid. 97 D 48.4.3. 98 Ibid. 99 Ibid. 100 D 48.6. some of the provisions of the last-mentioned law could also be made applicable to the rulers. It rendered liable, for example, someone who, "being invested with power or authority, acts in any other way than the law decrees and requires that he should" 101 as well as "[t]hose who impose new taxes arbitrarily". 102 The status and influence of Roman jurisprudence is often discarded when it is compared particularly with the private) law. highly Some developed loose Roman comments positive were made by (and Roman authors regarding the philosophical basis of state power, but as Berman observed: "The Roman texts themselves reveal little political or legal theory of any kind." 103 The orientation was explicitly positivistic. This lack of theory, it is widely agreed, was the consequence not in the first place of inability but of design - it was the result of the often-noted Roman distrust of abstract speculation. 104 What, then, could discussion of the the value be development political resistance? The of of references to theoretical effects of Roman Roman notions law in a concerning legal thought on Western attitudes to political obligation should not be underestimated, and the positivistic orientation of Roman lawyers should not be overemphasized. In important respects Roman legal thinking provided the concepts which would be used in the development of Western notions concerning the right to resist. In the first place, the exact meaning of the concept of merum imperium would later become the subject-matter of an intense debate. As will be demonstrated later on, some medieval commentators, most notably the Glossator Azo, would "constitutionally". claim This that meant this that notion the had to "inferior be interpreted magistrates" were also regarded as bearers of this power and that they could use it to resist a tyrannical ruler. This so-called "constitutional theory" of resistance tradition. would later find support in 105 101 D 48.6.10. 102 D 48.6.12. 103 Berman Law and revolution 239. 104 See eg Syme Ten studies in Tacitus 119. 105 See infra chap five I L (2). especially the Calvinistic Secondly, Roman private law had a well developed notion of self- defence, which recognised the principle of vim vi repellere licet, 106 which made it lawful under certain circumstances for one citizen to repel with force an unlawful attack by another. Although the Romans applied the rule strictly to private law relations, this principle would later be made applicable to public law as well, most notably by Lutheran lawyers, as the basis for the right of political resistance. 107 In the third place, the true implications of the lex regia would also become the subject-matter of a lively debate, with some commentators claiming that although a number of powers were reserved for the Emperor, power ultimately resided in the people, who could take it back if it were to be abused. 108 Fourthly, commentators would later also emphasise those instances (some of which were referred to above) where Romans subjected those who governed, as well as those being governed, to law. Hence, political obligation was tied to underlies the modern legal obligation concepts of the - the central "rule of notion law" that and the On the lawyers and "Rechtsstaat" as the basis of legitimate government. The above relates philosophical to level, a aspects of Roman positive number of prominent Roman law. philosophers towards the end of the Republic and the beginning of the Empire made a significant contribution to the development of Stoicism. It has been suggested that this influenced Western political thought. positive law on Western notions philosophical 109 of While approach deeply the influence of Roman political obligation will be discussed as we follow the course of history, the approach of Roman proponents of Stoicism - among them Lucius Annaeus Seneca (c 5 BC-65 AO), 110 Epictetus (c 55-135) and Marcus Aurelius (121-180) 111 will now 106 Galus advanced as a general principle the adagium that naturalis ratio made it lawful for every man to defend himself against an unlawful attack. D 9.2.4. 107 See infra I L (1). 108 See eg the discussion of the views of Noodt infra chap five I T. See also Hahlo & Kahn The South African legal system and its background 434 n 26. 109 See Skinner The foundations of modern political thought vol 1 xiv and vo1 2 275. 110 To be distinguished from his father, Marcus Annaeus Seneca. As to Seneca's political thinking, see Griffin Seneca. Seneca, like Calvin, saw be considered. The eclectic, Cicero, (106-43 BC) 112 also professed some Stoic views. The concept of natural law, as advanced by the Stoics, would embrace all human beings into a single unit, and not exclude some who are considered inferior, as Aristotle. 113 Whereas was the case in the philosophy of someone like other early notions of "natural law" largely served to justify the institution of the state. Stoic natural law would provide a criterion for evaluating the acceptability of state action, and hence in itself carried the potential of resistance. 114 Especially Cicero's articulation of the doctrine of natural law that made this notion accessible to Roman and Romanist lawyers and to fathers of the Christian Church. 115 the As Ebenstein observed: "[W]herever human imperfection and sin as the source of the need for the state. See Fortuin De natuurrechtelijke grondslagen van De Groot's volkenrecht 46. 111 A discussion and extracts from the works of Epictetus and Aurelius may be found in Ebenstein Great political thinkers 139ff. Marcus 112 On Cicero's political views, see Ebenstein Great political thinkers 124ff; Strauss & Cropsey History of political philosophy l30ff and Smith & Weisstub The Western idea of law 345. His legal philosophy is discussed by Van Eikerna Homines Major trends in the history of legal philosophy 31ff and Van Zyl Cicero's legal philosophy 20ff. See also Wirszubski Libertas 143ff. 113 In emphasising the dignity of human beings, the Stoics would indeed be closer to Kant than to Aristotle. See Smith & Weisstub The Western idea of law 346. 114 Stoicism was seen as subversive and was outlawed after it was invoked by Thrasea Paetus as justification for his refusal to participate in the activities of the Senate to express his opposition to the way in which it functioned. Griffin Seneca 362ff. Thus, Stoicism gave people the courage to resist a government which they considered repressive. See Wirszubski Libertas 146. 115 In a famous passage in The republic 3.33.22 Cicero said: "True law is right reason in agreement with nature; it is of universal application, unchanging and everlasting; it summons to duty by its commands, and averts from wrongdoing by its prohibitions. And it does not lay its commands or prohibitions upon good men in vain, though neither have any effect on the wicked. It is a sin to try and alter this law, nor is it allowable to attempt to repeal any part of it, and it is impossible to abolish it entirely. We cannot be freed from its obligations by senate or people, and we need not look outside ourselves for an expounder or interpreter of it. And there will not be different laws at Rome and at Athens, or different laws now and in the future, but one eternal and unchangeable law win be valid for a11 nations and a11 times, and there will be one master and ruler, that is. God, over us a11, for he is the author of this law, its promulgator, and its enforcing judge. Whoever is disobedient is fleeing from himself and denying his human nature, the Roman law expanded – and it usually stayed once it had taken root it carried with it an openness and universality that it owed to the sense of all men living in ‘one world’." 116 Stoic Cicero, like the Stoics, maintained that there is a divide beyond which unjust laws cease to be laws. According to him, a state which lacks law "must ... for that reason be considered no state at all". 117The mere fact that legislative formalities have been executed does not imply that law has been created. Cicero maintained that "the many deadly, the many pestilential statutes which nations put in force ... no more deserve to be called laws than the rules a band of robbers might pass at their assembly." 118 According to him, "[l]aw is the distinction between things just and unjust" 119 and, in order to be law, it must "inflict punishment upon the wicked but defend and protect the good". 120 Stoicism, with its strong emphasis on the individual conscience, claimed that certain aspects of the human life are beyond the control of the state. 121 Christianity and Stoicism established the fundamental idea of a private realm over which the state has no jurisdiction. There is, however, an important limitation on what can called the subversive potential of Stoicism and for the matter of Christianity. Both systems urge one to disregard the external world and emphasise the spiritual life of the individual. Since the outside world is broken and cannot I repaired, injustices. As a one must general expect rule, the to have demands to of put up incumbents with of son state authority belong to the category of these "outside things to which one should demands be indifferent. of those in It is positions consequently of not authority, worth even if resisting that the involves suffering, which must be borne with "Stoic" forbearance. and by reason of this very fact he will suffer the worst penalties, even if he escapes what is commonly considered punishment." 116 Ebenstein Great political thinkers 147. 117 Cicero De legibus 2.12. 118 Id 2.13. 119 Ibid. 120 Ibid. 121 See Post Studies in medieval legal thought 261. Cicero maintained mention of resignation." a 122 that "a parent's man is offence, bound, but not even only to to suppress endure it all with Also often quoted is Cicero's remark that "to me any peace with citizens seemed more profitable than civi1 war." 123 Abstract notions concerning justice and how the world should function, cannot warrant disobedience. What should not be obeyed, however, are positive orders which would require the individual concerned personally to embark on immoral) behaviour, or negative orders which would prevent that person from doing what he regards as ethical. In other words the Stoic approach amounted to an endorsement of what we have called positive and negative integrity-based defensive civil disobedience, but a rejection of justice-based and result-oriented resistance, whether violent or not. 124 This basic Stoic-Christian perception provided the link between Greek science and Roman legal and political practice, on the one hand, and Judeo-Christian ethics on the other, and would inspire much of Western jurisprudence regarding political resistance. 125 The emergence of the Roman Empire, which embraced nearly the entire world known to the Romans, in the view of many commentators of the time, rendered the republican form of government obsolete. Sallust (8634 BC), who has been described as the first imperial Roman author, made it clear that he valued liberty, but nevertheless concluded that order in a political dispensation such as the Empire could only be maintained by submitting to and enforcing centralized authority: cum domino pax ista venit. 126 If in the Republic there was a degree of tolerance in respect of resistance, that accommodating spirit soon disappeared in 122 See "Pro Cluentio" in Cicero The speeches 17. 123 Cicero Philippics 2.15. 124 Cicero's eclecticism becomes apparent when the following non-Stoic observations from his pen are considered: "[I]f anyone kills a tyrant ... he has not laden his soul with guilt, has he? The Roman people, at all events, are not of that opinion; for of a11 glorious deeds they hold such an one to be the most noble". Cicero De officiis 3.4.19. He did, however, specifically invoke Stoicism as authority for this statement. See Id 3.4.20; 2.7.23; 3.8.36 & 3.21.83. A willingness and indeed a lust to kill tyrants was also expressed by Seneca's Hercules: "[N]o more pleasing stream had stained the altars; no greater, richer victim can be sacrificed to Jove than an unrighteous king." Seneca "Hercules furens" 908, reprinted in Seneca Seneca's tragedies 81. 125 See eg Skinner The foundations of modern political thought vol 2 279. 126 See Syme Ten studies in Tacitus 120. the Empire. An even greater emphasis was placed on the need to accept the dictates of the prevailing government and, where necessary, to endure it with fortitude. One of the most prominent descriptions of the views that prevailed in the new era of the Principate is contained in the writings of the historian, Cornelius Tacitus (c 55-116). 127 Although Tacitus was not a lawyer, his works would become a source of reference for many great writers of Pufendorf. the 129 Roman Dutch legal system, such Grotius 128 as and Having been largely a reporter of the views of others, Tacitus encapsulated much of the Stoic ethics of the time. In a number of his writings, Tacitus described the practice of political opposition in the Empire, as opposed to the Republic, as a foolish and perhaps even dangerous anachronism. What mattered now was not the question how a particular ruler acquired his position - even if that involved the use of force. The important question was whether he was capax Could imperii. he peace? 130 maintain Clearly any form of hostility to result-oriented disobedience was out of the question. While the writings of Tacitus bear testimony of his tyranny, he did not show much sympathy for its victims. 131 The speakers in his historical reconstructions took for granted the "honour due an Emperor". 132In (completed c typical 109) endured any sort", Stoic remarked 133 fashion, that "he a speaker prayed for in good The histories Emperors, but while another advised: "You endure barren years, excessive rains, and all other natural evils; in like manner endure the extravagance or greed of your rulers." 134 These phrases capture the essence of the Stoic-Christian approach: as long as one’s soul is not affected, political dispensations should be placed in the same category 127 For a thorough contextualised discussion of the political opinions of Tacitus, see Syme Ten studies in Tacitus 119ff. 128 See eg Grotius De jure belli ac pacis chap 4. 129 See eg Pufendorf On the law of nature and nations 7.8.4. 130 See Syme Ten studies in Tacitus 132. 131 Id 136. 132 Tacitus The histories 4.8. 133 Ibid. See Syme Ten studies in Tacitus 138, for a discussion of the irony involved in this observation. 134 Tacitus The histories 4.74. as the weather: it is something one can do nothing about. It should simply be endured, because it cannot be changed. The position is different in respect of one’s soul, because that lies in one’s control. D. GERMANIC JURISPRUDENCE The early Middle Ages in Europe were dominated by the traditional Germanic concept of the "law-based state", which proclaimed that the state existed "in the law and for the law". 135Law was not seen as a product of the state, but as something to which the state was also subjected. 136 These points of departure culminated in a liberal approach to the right of resistance, which would emerge whenever the ruler exceeded his powers. Kern, in an in-depth discussion of the subject, observed that "[t]he right of resistance was an integral part of medieval Germanic constitutional ideas." 137 According to Gierke "the purely medieval doctrine did not only allow’ the right and duty of a martyr’s ‘passive resistance’’ - it taught that every command which exceeded the limits of the ruler’s authority was as far as his subjects were concerned a mere nullity and did not oblige anyone to obedience." 138 Medieval jurisprudence also proclaimed "the right of resistance, and even armed resistance, against the compulsory enforcement of any unrighteous and tyrannical measure - such enforcement being regarded as an act of bare violence. Nay more, it taught ... that tyrannicide is justifiable or at least excusable." 139 This approach appears, for example, from the Sachsenspiegel, a compilation of customary law of the Saxons and the most outstanding legal monument of German feudal law of the Middle Ages. Probably written between 1215 and 1233 by Eike von Repgow (c 1180-1233), the Sachsenspiegel represents the beginning of German jurisprudence, and 135 See Gierke Political theories of the middle age 73. 136 See Hahlo & Kahn The South African legal system and its background 339, 430. See also, on the precarious position of the king in the Visigothic kingdom, King Law and society in the Visigothic kingdom 23ff. 137 See Kern Kingship and law in the middle ages 85ff. 138 Gierke Political theories of the middle age 35. 139 Ibid. exercised a great influence on the development of European law. 140 The Sachsenspiegel provided: "The man must resist the injustice of his king and his judges, and will help counter [injustice] in any way in his power or in his master’s, and [by doing so] does not act against his loyalty." 141 In the process, one could without violation of his fidelity wound or slay his lord. 142 E. St AURELIUS AUGUSTINE Augustine (354-430), from Roman North Africa, critical juncture where the era of the Roman Empire Middle Ages; teachings himself, of 144 when this antiquity "African was deposed writing to by represented the made way for the Christianity. 143 Africans", as he The described and father of the Christian churches (both Catholic and Reformed), dominated Western thought for centuries. He integrated the philosophy of the Greco-Roman world (particularly Plato, but also Cicero and the Stoics) into the emerging ethos of Christianity. More so than any other dominant religion, Christianity would be tolerant of, and in fact open to, the influence of philosophy. Augustine’s political writings should be evaluated in view of the central political event of his time, namely the fall of the Roman Empire. The fall of Rome at the hands of barbarians left the world stunned. How could such a rock crumble so easily? Was this course of events not a consequence of the influence of Christian faith which supposedly precluded Christians from being patriotic citizens? 140 See K1sh Sachsenspiegel and Bible 3 and Van Zyl Geskledenis van die Rome1ns-Ho11andse reg 69. 141 Sachsenspiegel 3.78.2. (Own translation, with assistance from Philip Thomas, from Eckhardt's edition of Sachsenspiegel Landrecht 260.) 142 Id 3.78.6. See the discussion in Carlyle medieval political theory in the West vol 3 61ff. 143 & Carlyle A history of 0n his philosophy in general, see Vorländer Geschiedenis van de wijsbegeerte vol 2 28ff and Versfeld St’ Augustine’s confessions and City of God. For a discussion of Augustine’s political views, see Strauss & Cropsey History of political philosophy 151ff; Ebenstein Great political thinkers 170ft; Deane The political and social Ideas of St Augustine, especially 116ff, Villa-Vicencio Between Christ and Caesar 20ff and Villa-Vicencio Civil disobedience and beyond 73, 93ff. As to the implications of his teachings for legal philosophy, see Du Plessis Westerse regsdenke tot en met die middeleeue 148ff. 144 See Augustine Letters 17. Following its initial persecution, Christianity in 313, under Constantine, by virtue of the Edict of Milan, became the official state religion of the Roman Empire. 145 When Rome fell in 410, the charge that this was a result of the introduction of Christianity was to be expected. Augustine’s most elaborate work with political implications, 146 The city of God against the pagans, was largely an attempt to respond to these charges. In the first place, Augustine would deride the value which people placed on an earthly institution such as the Roman Empire with all its weaknesses. In the second place, he rejected the notion that Christians were by nature unpatriotic citizens. would be less scope for the political After Augustine, there indifference of the early Christians, although, as win be pointed out, much of that indifference remained. According to Augustine, justice is the highest virtue and the cornerstone of civil society. Philosophy in itself, however, cannot reveal the meaning of perfect justice - a higher and more genuine form of justice is needed, which can only be provided by the grace of God. The essence of justice, according to Augustine, following the lead of Plato in this regard, is constituted by the right ordering of things, which alone can bring peace. For Plato, this "right ordering" referred largely to the relationship of the virtues in the individual himself and in his station in life. For Augustine, harmonious relationship between man and God. it signified in the 147 Augustine agreed with Plato that the lower aptitudes should be governed by reason, but for him reason should in turn be regulated by God. Like the later Reformers, Augustine saw the need for state authority, and indeed for civil rule, as a necessary consequence of the fallen nature of human beings and their proneness to sin, which propensity entails that the government 145 lower in appetites accordance or desires with the take over. Good government virtue of justice. In is typical See Cary & Scullard A history of Rome 547. 146 The impression should not be gained that Augustine was primarily a political writer, or offered a systematic political view. He was a theologian whose work had political overtones. 147 See Augustine The city of God against the pagans 19.13: "Order is the classification of things equal and unequal that assigns to each Its proper position." Platonic terms Augustine saw human justice as merely an imperfect imitation of divine justice. Eternal law (lex is aeterna) the supreme norm of justice. It is universal and has been imprinted upon the human mind by God himself. Temporal law (lex temporalis) can vary according to circumstances and without being unjust, because its aim is to permit the lesser evils and to avert the greater evils in a particular society. The function of the law is to provide the peace in which service to God is possible. Without justice peace would not be possible, because "if justice is left out, what are kingdoms except great bands?" 148 robber The centrality of the virtue of justice in Augustine's thought is evidenced by his well-known statement that "an unjust law, it seems to me, is no law." 149 This phrase would become one of the central maxims of the traditional natural law approach in respect of the limits of political ob1igation. Central to Augustine’s perception of the relationship between Christian and civic duty was his doctrine of the duality of the two cities in which humanity finds itself: the city of God (civitas dei) and the earthly city (civitas terrenea). Citizens of the city of God are those (irrespective of race or national origin) who follow Christ and lead virtuous lives - those who pursue virtue and truth. The earthly city is the fallen interest. 150 world The - the problem world of the of those who Christian, pursue then, is narrow self- his double citizenship, and hence his double loyalties - he belongs to both of these worlds. This brings us to the question as to which citizenship should be afforded priority. A conflict between the two citizenships is not inevitable. If the rulers should act in accordance with Christian principles, the demands made by the two jurisdictions would coincide. In such a case, the Christian can pursue the life of general obedience - and to Augustine obedience was, "in a sense, the mother 148 Id 4.4. 149 Augustine The free choice of the will 1.5.11. 150 and guardian of all “The two cities then were created by two kinds of love: the earthly city by a love of self carried even to the point of contempt for God, the heavenly city by a love of God even to the point of contempt for self." Augustine The city of God against the pagans 14.28. See also id 14.13. virtues". 151The Christian can be submissive to God while at the same time being obedient to political authority. Political authority, after all, was instituted by God for the purpose of administering the material goods which people need on earth. But what if the demands of the two cities do not coincide? Augustine argued that Christianity does not weaken earthly patriotism but in fact strengthens it. Relying heavily on Romans 13, Augustine argued that obedience to temporal authorities is a religious duty. In a passage strikingly reminiscent administration of of things the (not much a later government Marxist over ideal people) reminded us that in paradise God placed man in charge of of an Augustine the animals 152 but did not give him dominium over fellow rational creatures - "not man over man, but man over the beasts". 153The good order of nature, however, was disrupted by sin. To restore order, government had to be established. Every man has an obligation to obey the law, even if he disagrees with it. In spite of its weaknesses, civil society is still the best option of its kind, and as a general rule its demands should therefore be obeyed. Augustine therefore reinforced Ambriose’s earlier repudiation of a right of resistance. 154 It is true, according to Augustine, that the Christian is in the first place a citizen of the heavenly city. But this does not mean that he should disobey the state: on the contrary, it means that he has little reason to oppose the state. Augustine, in what can be regarded as a classic exposition of the Stoic-Christian approach, argued in favour of remaining indifferent to unjust demands of the state, as long as one’s citizenship of the heavenly city is not threatened: "As far as this mortal life is concerned, which is passed and ended in a few days, what difference does it make for a man who is soon to die, under what rule he lives, if only the rulers do not force him to commit unholy and unjust deeds?" 155 As indicated in the emphasised section of this passage, the general rule of obedience to the law applies, unless the law requires one to 151 Id 14.12. 152 Genesis 1.26. 153 Augustine The city of God against the pagans 19.15. 154 See Calvert Revolution 51. 155 Augustine The city of God against the pagans 5.17. (Emphasis added.) violate God’s law. No one need to, or should, obey a command to do sin - for example an edict which proclaims: "Do not worship God." In that case there is a conflict of interests in which God’s law enjoys priority. The latter law should be upheld even if that means (earthly) death. 156 By becoming a martyr under such circumstances, one gives strength and courage to believers. one’s fellow However, believers. martyrdom One should might not be even used win to over more discredit or otherwise undermine the law-giver, even if he is wicked. Its aim is solely to protect the redeemed personal or societal ends. 157 from sin, not the advancement of Ultimately, it is within God’s power to remove a tyrant. Augustine approved and even propagated the right of Christians in such cases to disobey the law, but not to resist the authorities. One cannot actively place oneself in opposition to the existing authorities, because they receive their power from God with a view to preserving the order and tranquillity of society. God does not, however, control the application of this power by the authorities. That is why there are sometimes wicked laws. Augustine’s often-quoted adage that an unjust law should not be regarded as a law at all, should consequently not be taken as a licence for result-oriented disobedience of the law. In fact, he explicitly rejected this. Augustine’s profound commitment to justice did not imply a concomitant right to resist. To him, the maintenance of law and order was a religious duty. The only type of political disobedience endorsed and, in fact, in some cases required by him was defensive, religious, integrity-based civil the narrow category of disobedience. Even his imagery revealed the defensive attitude which he required Christians to adopt: "You must take up your faith as a shield with which you will put out all the burning spears of your enemies." 158 F. JOHN OF SALISBURY 156 On the relationship between death and political resistance in the thought of Augustine, see Van Home The Journal of Religious Thought 1981/2 34 at 41. 157 158 Augustine The city of God against the pagans 8.20. Augustine translation.) "Sermo" 62.13, contained in Augustine Opera omnia. (Own Modern Western writings of political the science Englishman, has John an of early Salisbury forerunner 159 (c in the 1120-1180), a Christian humanist, who tried to wrest political thinking from the hold of Stoicism. In his most important work, Policraticus, 160 John startled his contemporaries when he presented an elaborate defence of tyrannicide. A staunch champion of the supremacy of ecclesiastical over temporal power, John was particularly perturbed by the murder of his friend, Thomas Becket, by the henchmen of Henry II. As the point of departure in his discussion of tyrannicide, John accepted the orthodox premise of his time that all rulers, including tyrants, should be obeyed because, according to Romans 13, they are ministers of God. 161 There is a difference between kings and tyrants, in the sense that the king rules in accordance with the law while the tyrant rules obedience by also alone. 162 force applies to Nevertheless, tyrants, "[f]or the general tyrants are rule of demanded, introduced, and raised to power by sin." 163 To get rid of a wicked king, John maintained political theory, that king In 165 respect in 164 accordance with conventional ecclesiastical one should pray to God to bring his judgment over - which God will do in his own good time. of commands by the ruler threatening to make one the instrument of sin, John also defended the orthodox position: Loyal shoulders should sustain the power of the ruler so long as it is exercised in subjection to God and follows his ordinances; but if it resists and opposes the divine commandments, and wishes to make me share in its war against God, then with unrestrained voice, I answer back that God must be preferred before any man on earth. 166 159 For a general discussion of his political thought, see Ebenstein Great political thinkers 190ff; Copleston A history of medieval philosophy 91ff; Berman Law and revolution 277ff and Dickenson's introduction in John of Salisbury Policraticus xviiff. For a discussion of his views on tyranny, see id 1xviff. 160 Completed in 1159, and sometimes translated as "The statesman's book", although the Latin title is more commonly used. 161 John of Salisbury Policraticus 4.1. 162 Id 8.17. 163 Id 8.20. 164 See Dickenson's introduction id 1xx 165 Id 8.20. 166 Id 6.25. John’s choice of words seems to suggest that in such a case defensive civil disobedience should normally be practised: "If princes have departed little by little from the true way, even so it is not well to overthrow them utterly at once, but rather to rebuke injustice with patient reproof until finally it becomes obvious that they are stiffnecked in evil-doing." 167 The qualifying phrase, "at once", also suggests that one's patience need not be endless, and that defensive, non-violent civil disobedience is not necessarily the end of the road. In what at the time was widely considered a shocking statement, John maintained that the persistent tyrant, subject to some reservations, 168 should be killed: "To kill a tyrant is not merely lawful, but right and just." This he motivated as follows: [I]f in the crime of lese majeste all men are admitted to be prosecutors, how much more should this be true in the case of the crime of subverting the laws which should rule even over Emperors: Truly no one will avenge a public enemy, but rather whoever does not seek to bring him to punishment commits an offence against himself and the whole body of the earthly commonwealth. 169 John’s approach is extraordinary in several respects: In the first place, the forthrightness with which he advanced the proposition that under certain circumstances a king could be killed was unheard of at the time. Later, writers like Calvin would seem deliberately vague on the point, presumably in order not to rule out this possibility but at the same time not to encourage people to engage in such action too readily. Ultimately, they seem to have suggested that every person has to accept responsibility for such action himself and personally bear the moral cost. John, for his part, described such action as a public duty. He did not only, like Augustine, regard a refusal to comply in some cases as one’s duty but also saw the actual killing of the ruler as a duty. He was one of the first to cross the line from the propagation of defensive to result-oriented resistance. It is also remarkable that, whereas other early writers such as Augustine confined the function of disobedience to the protection of 167 Id 5.6. (Emphasis added.) 168 “It should be done without loss of religion or honor” and not by someone who is bound to the tyrant "by an oath or by the obligation of fealty". Id 8.20. 169 Id 3.15. one’s personal religious integrity, John seems also to have advocated disobedience in the pursuit of the public benefit. His approach was consequently also anti-exploitation. But John went even further: While Calvin would demand that any insurrection should be led by recognised leaders of the people, John did not require any form of organised collective action and in fact advocated individual tyrannicide – an approach which would be rejected by Aquinas as being subversive of all civil order. 170 In spite of the fact that John, no doubt, in the eyes of hi* contemporaries and most of his successors overstated hit case, he is important because he was one of the first writers to establish the doctrine that obedience to the political ruler is not absolute but conditional; that it depends upon the way in which the latter rules. 171 Few of the later writers would unconditionally accept his ideas concerning the conditions and limits of justified resistance, but it could not be denied that the issue was placed squarely on the agenda of political discourse, to counteract the traditional conservative approach. G. THE RE-EMERGENCE OF ROMAN LAW AND THE GLOSSATORS The legal systems which comprise the Roman-Germanic legal family have as their common point of departure the inherent values of the Roman and Germanic dispensations. In this regard, Roman-Dutch law is no exception. At the same timer, this body of law to a large extent reflects the particular social and political context of the societies of Europe in which the system developed, as well as the political convictions of the commentators responsible for its development. In no other area can this be seen more clearly than in the principles pertaining to political obligation and resistance. At the end of the Eleventh Century, when Roman law revived at the universities of Bologna and Ravenna in Italy, the Roman emphasis on the supreme powers of the rulers re-emerged and supplanted the more liberal Germanic approach. In this process, Roman law was amplified by the Canon law. Whereas, in the Germanic tradition, people were seen as the source of all power, power was now increasingly regarded as descending 170 See infra chap five I H. 171 See Ebenstein Great political thinkers 197. from above. Under the new approach there would be an almost unconditional duty of obedience to the ruler, who was subjected only to the laws of God and of nature. 172 Nevertheless, the idea survived that since the government is established for the protection of the law, it can forfeit its right to rule if it fails to uphold the law. 173 A number of intellectuals, including most proponents of the first major school of Romanists, the Glossators, supported the absolutist rule of the Emperor. Consequently, it is not surprising that they did not exploit the possibilities which imaginative interpretation of the Roman texts left for the recognition of a right to resist. Placentinus (ob 1192), for example, maintained that, according to the lex regia, the Roman people had once and for a11 transferred all the power they had in the Republic to the Emperor. 174 The method of legal scholarship practiced by the Glossators, characterised by a literal adherence to the original Roman texts with their broad assertions of the powers of the ruler, served their conservative political disposition well. At the same time, however, the idea of libertas of the cities as against the German Empire was developing into a powerful political aspiration. The notable exception among the Glossators, who shared this aspiration, was Azo (1150-1230). Through consolidation (and manipulation) of Roman law texts he developed a forerunner to the concept of sovereignty, as subsequently elaborated upon Jean Bodin. Azo maintained that "jurisdiction" or the power to rule did not descend downward from the Emperor but emanated upward from the community. More important is the fact that Azo, in a dispute with the jurist Lothair, advanced an interpretation of the concept of merum imperium in terms of which the ius gladii could be exercised by the Emperor and also by the "inferior magistrates". According to this approach, the Emperor could be said to have signed a contract, at his election, with the electors and other "inferior magistrates" to uphold the good of the Empire and to protect the liberties of his subjects. The jurisdiction of "inferior 172 See Hahlo & Kahn The South African legal system and its background 430ff. 173 174 See Kern Kingship and law in the middle ages 195. See Van den Bergh The life and work of Gerard Noodt 194. See also Hahlo & Kahn The South African legal system and its background 434 n 26. magistrates" was more limited than that of the Emperor, but it did not derive from "inferior his power magistrates" had independent. 175 it was the power to use the Consequently sword Emperor, if he did not uphold his coronation oath. 176 the against the This approach, called the "constitutional theory" of resistance, would later play an important role in Calvinistic thinking. H. THOMAS AQUINAS The early middle ages were dominated by Augustinian Platonism, according to which the world is bad, and the only good world belongs to the realm of the ideal which can be known in this life only through revelation or vision. The pessimism and other-worldliness of Christianity in the "dark middle ages" came under increased challenge after the millennium. New ideas and modes of thought were developed in the emerging universities. At the same time, crucial texts of Aristotle for the first time became accessible to the West, setting out his views that the (earthly) state was the highest achievement of man. This threatened the very foundations of the Augustinian world view espoused by the church of the time. The state was placed in a new, positive light. At the same time the church was experiencing strong internal tensions, due to the fact that it was becoming a major worldly institution. To put it bluntly, the fact that the second coming did not materialise at least at the end of the millennium put the church under new pressure to make peace with this world, and to reassess its role in it. The task to pilot the church in these shifting currents would fall on the shoulders of one of the most outstanding intellectuals who has ever served 1275) 177 the church, the Italian scholastic Thomas Aquinas (c 1225- . Aquinas’ political thinking is largely contained in his works 175 176 See Berman Law and revolution 289ff. See the discussion thought vol 2 127 177 in Skinner The foundations of modern political On Aquinas' philosophy in general, see Copleston A history of medieval philosophy 176ff. On his political philosophy, see Ebenstein Great political thinkers 212ff; Strauss & Cropsey History of political philosophy 223ff; Villa-Vicencio Between Christ and Caesar 23ff and Villa-Vicencio Civil disobedience and beyond 73. See also the penetrating discussion of D'Entrèves in Aquinas' Selected political writings viiff. On his legal philosophy, see Du Plessis Westerse regsdenke tot en met die middeleeue 160ff. On princely government 178 and Summary of theology. 179 While Augustine integrated Plato into the thinking of the early church, it was Aquinas who reconciled Aristotelianism and Christianity. Aristotle thus replaced Plato as the philosophical guiding star of Christian theology (that is, until the Reformation). Aquinas’ scattered references to Aristotelian politics were, at the same time also extremely influential. His views on political obligation, seen in the context of his views on natural law, will now be considered. As mentioned, Augustine traced the foundations of the state to sin. In the state of innocence there would have been no domination of one person over another, and consequently no state. In contrast Aquinas’ starting point, like that of Aristotle, was an organic view of society, which regarded humankind’s social impulse as natural and consequently as basic to all further relations. He stated repeatedly that "man is naturally a social and political animal." 180 Man is unthinkable without the state, because it is in the state that human fellowship finds its highest expression and all that depends on that fellowship is natural to man. According to Aquinas, two types of dominium should be distinguished: subjectio servilis and subjectio civilis. Slavery is contrary to nature, because it degrades man to a tool for someone else’s good. But - and here the Aristotelian influence is clear - the political subjection of someone for the common good (or of women to men) is not inherently wrong or unnatural: "Such subjection already existed before sin: for it would argue a lack of reasonable order in human society if it were not regulated by those who are more wise." 181 The capable should govern the incapable. The heart of Aquinas’ treatment of politics can be regarded as his conception of natural law, as developed in his Summary of theology. Aquinas distinguished four forms of law: i) Lex aeterna is identical to the divine reason that governs the universe, and is called eternal because God’s reason is eternal. 178 Reprinted in Aquinas Selected political writings 3ff. 179 Id 103ff. 180 See eg Aquinas On princely government 1.1. 181 Summary of theology 1.1 All things, irrational animals and rational man, are subject to divine reason or eternal law. 182 ii) Lex natural is refers to the special way in which human beings, as rational creatures, participate in the divine providence and reason by providing for themselves and for others. Rational creatures have a certain share in the divine reason itself, deriving therefrom a natural inclination to such actions and ends as are fitting. This participation in the eternal rational creatures is called the natural law. iii) law by 183 Lex divina refers to the fact that man’s reason is not the only or the most reliable guide to his understanding of truth and justice. Divine law is revealed to man through the Old and the New Testaments, and apprehended by reason. iv) Lex humana, positive law. the does not contradict natural law as 184 lowest form of law, is what we would call 185 There are four conditions which law must meet in order to have the nature of law. Firstly, it must be derived from natural law. In the second place, human law must be directed to the common welfare of the city. Thirdly, the law should be promulgated by the rulers of the community. In the last place it must be enacted "by the common sanction of nobles and people". 186 Obedience to the demands of law is therefore required by nature itself - no social contract is required in this regard. The obligatory nature of law is derived from its divine origins. Sin also has no part in the rational justification of the state, because political obligation is inherent in man’s nature. It is important to note that while Aquinas is considered one of the primary natural lawyers of all time, his conception of natural law was 182 Id 1.5. 183 Ibid. 184 Ibid. 185 Ibid. 186 Id 1.9. the traditional one. It primarily stressed duties: the duty of the state to follow its pattern, and the duty of citizens to obey - not their right to disobey. 187 Although Aquinas, under normal circumstances, regarded the duty to obey the political ruler as natural, he did perceive limits to this duty. The individual could not be absorbed entirely by the state. Not all that a man has or is, is subject to political obligation: hence it is not necessary that all his actions be considered worthy of praise or blame with respect to the political community. But all that a man is, and all that he has or can be, must bear a certain relationship to God. 188 Although the need for "stability in human affairs" gives rise to a general duty to obey the political ruler, 189 one is not obliged to obey certain kinds of tyrants. 190 In order to distinguish a tyrannical government or unjust government from its opposite, Aquinas posed the question whose interests are being served. A tyrant pursues his own private benefit, while a just ruler pursues the common welfare. 191 In other words, the criterion is exploitation. Aquinas specifically addressed the question what action should be taken should a king become tyrannical. He distinguished between tyranny which is not excessive, and tyranny which is intolerable. In respect of the former he maintained that "it is certainly wiser to tolerate it in limited measure, at least for a time, rather than to run the risk of even greater perils by opposing it." 192 A rebellion might fail and inspire the tyrant to greater savagery. But even if it succeeds, it might create grave social turmoil or even prepare the road for a more vicious tyrant. 193 In respect of tyranny which has become so excessive as to be intolerable, Aquinas stated that "it has been argued that it would be 187 See Aquinas Selected political writings xiv. 188 Aquinas Summary of theology 1.3. 189 Id 1.23. 190 Id 1.16. 191 Ibid. 192 Aquinas On princely government 1.6. 193 Ibid. an act of virtue for the more powerful citizens to kill the tyrant." 194 However, such an assumption of authority by individual subjects would be dangerous to the whole society. Wicked people find the rule of a good king no less burdensome than that of the tyrant. The remedy against the evils of tyranny consequently lies rather in the hands of public authority than in the private judgment of individuals. 195 A number of different possibilities present themselves in this regard. In the case where the people have the right to elect their leader, they may lawfully depose him or restrict his powers, should he abuse it. If the ruler has been appointed by a higher sovereign, it lies in the hands of that sovereign to depose him. "Finally, when there is no hope of human aid against tyranny, recourse must be made to God the king of all ... For it is in his power to turn the cruel heart of a tyrant to gentleness." 196 Tyranny should be seen as a punishment for sin. 197 Aquinas agreed with Augustine that "there is no law unless it be just", and stated that the validity of law depends upon its justice. "[I]f a human law is at variance in any particular with the natural law, it is no longer legal, but rather a corruption of law." 198 In accordance with the general Stoic-Christian position, Aquinas maintained that one should not obey the authorities when their commands clash with those of God, and when they exceed their authority. 199 I. CANON LAW Canon law, with its doctrine of vicarius Dei, according to which the earthly king derived his powers directly from God, generally reinforced the position of the rulers and delegitimised resistance. 200 However, to some extent Canon law, like Roman law, could be relied upon to justify resistance against the government. One of the main sections 194 Id 1.6. Presumably he was referring Salisbury. See supra chap five I F. to the arguments of John of 195 Ibid. 196 Id 1.6. 197 Ibid. 198 Aquinas Summary of Theology 1.9. 199 Id 1.23. 200 See Hahlo & Kahn The South African legal system and its background 431ff. that could be used in this regard, was the decree dealing with unjust judges. The original decree stated that judges were not to be resisted with violence. The great Canonist, Panormitanus (1386-1445), commented that this should been seen in the context of the opinion of Pope Innocent IV that "if a judge does any injury to anyone", then "he may be resisted violently and with impunity". 201 On this basis, Panormitanus endorsed a far-reaching right of political resistance. J. PHILIP OF LEYDEN The early Dutch jurist, Philip of Leyden (c 1330-1382), 202 opposed the vast political powers of the gentry of his time, and instead supported the view that the ruler has an inalienable right to rule the country. When a ruler does not protect his subjects against exploitation (by the gentry), "the subjects have a right to resist, on the basis that if ordinary medicine should be taken. 203 does not provide a cure, extraordinary measures This thought would be repeated in the Placcaet van Verlatinge of 1581, to which we will presently turn. K. BARTOLUS OF SASSOFERRATO The Italian ideal of freedom of the cities as against the Holy Roman Empire found its legal champion in the work of the post-Glossator or Commentator, Bartolus of Sassoferrato (1314-1357), arguably the most outstanding jurist of the Middle Ages. This new political approach was made possible by a change in the basic approach to scholarship which he and his colleagues practised. To Bartolus, the primary objective of legal writing was not strict adherence to the Roman texts, but faithfulness to truth and reason. If necessary, the law had to yield to facts. Bartolus set out his views in commentaries on the principal divisions of the Corpus Juris Civilis. On the question of the power of the Emperor, Bartolus began his commentary on the Code by conceding that, de jure, the Emperor was the sole dominus mundi and had merum imperium. De facto, however, many people did not obey the Emperor’s decrees. This de facto position, he argued, had to be officially recognised. Insofar 201 See Skinner The foundations of modern political thought vol 2 125. 202 See Van Zyl Geskiedenis van die Romeins-Honandse Reg 330. 203 See Van der Heijden Aantekenlngen bij de geschiedenis van net oude vaderlandse recht 28 and Rofflein Erflaters van onze beschaving 127. See also Feenstra Philip of Leyden 64. as the cities and not the Emperor exercised power over their own subjects, they had to be regarded as the true law-givers. This power was confirmed by the fact that it had been exercised for a long time. According to Bartolus, since the cities were governed by free peoples wielding their own imperium, they could be said to be a princeps unto themselves - civitas sibi princeps. This led Bartolus to the conclusion that rex in regno suo est imperator - according to Skinner, the first decisive state. move toward articulating the modern legal concept of the 204 The above exposition served as a legal foundation for asserting the freedom as against the Empire of the Italian cities and also of the kingdoms of Northern Europe. It could consequently be said to deal with resistance by political communities against external domination. The truth of the matter was, however, that most of the rulers of the communes were tyrants. How were they to be treated? Bartolus, with a view to these questions, also addressed the issue of revolt against domestic authority. Among the most notable of his works was "On the tyrant", the first treatise by a jurist dedicated exclusively to the subject of tyranny and the way in which it should be handled. 205 We shall consequently dealt with it at some length. In "On the tyrant", Bartolus, as in his other writings, was at pains to emphasise the idealistical1y Fourteenth independence regarded Century were of the the fact city-state that characterised (civitas). Italian by tyranny He communes as a rather of the temporary phenomenon, which, under certain circumstances, gave the people the right of resistance. Bartolus defined a tyrant as "one who rules unlawfully", 206and distinguished two main types of tyrants: the manifest tyrant and the concealed tyrant. A ruler can become a manifest tyrant by defect of title or through conduct. Someone can be a tyrant by defect of title in a number of ways. He may make himself ruler in a town which does not 204 See Skinner The foundations of modern political thought vol 1 9. 205 Contained in the University of Chicago readings in Western civilization vol 5 The Renaissance 7. References are to the paragraphs of this version. See also Woolf Bartolus of Sassoferrato 162ff, 173ff and Van der Kamp Bartolus de Saxoferrato 62, for a discussion of Bartolus' views on tyranny and how it should be dealt with. 206 “On the tyrant” paras 2, 5. have the right to choose a leader. This would subject him to the lex Julia majestatis. His term of office may also have expired, or he may have forced the citizens to elect him. 207 The acts of such a tyrant are ipso jure nulla, even if he rules well. 208 This is also true in respect of the actions of officials appointed by the tyrant. To resolve the question as to the validity of the actions of officials during a time of tyranny, where such officials had been appointed by the city (and not by the tyrant), Bartolus drew a distinction between acts which the people performed themselves and would have performed even if there had been no tyrant, which he regarded as valid; and those acts which would not have been performed had there been no tyrant, which he regarded as invalid. 209 Contracts between the tyrant and subjects were void. 210 A ruler could also be a manifest tyrant in spite of the fact that he possessed a lawful title. He could be a tyrant by virtue of his conduct - that is, "because he performs tyrannical acts". 211 After a discussion of the approach of Aristotle, Bartolus concluded that keeping the city divided and pauperising the subjects were true manifestations of tyranny, and rendered the tyrant liable under the lex Julia de vi publica. 212 Again the question must be asked whether the actions of such a tyrant were valid. A process instituted by him against exiles and rebels was not valid, "since hostile judge". 213 no one is bound to appear before a notoriously Other processes were valid as long as the tyrant was tolerated. The distinction seemingly made by Bartolus here was between political and other trials. The above deals with manifest tyranny. Concealed tyranny, on the other hand, can take on three different forms. Someone could have been given jurisdiction for a limited time only, and then have his position reaffirmed while he still held power. Such a 207 Id para 6. 208 Id para 7. 209 Ibid. 210 Ibid. 211 Id para 8. 212 Id para 9. 213 Id para 11. tyrant must be treated like a tyrant by defect of title. 214 Even if one did not claim full jurisdiction over an entire state, like a king, one could still be a tyrant, as is the case with those who had themselves made captains of mercenaries, who exercised de facto control over the conduct of the officials of the state. Common knowledge of such a state of affairs was enough proof of its existence. To establish to what extent acts performed during tyranny of this kind were valid, Bartolus proposed the same approach followed in respect of officials elected by the people themselves during a manifest tyranny, discussed earlier. If, however, only a fraction of the people were abused by this tyranny, while in general the city was well governed, "then the person having a title of this sort or a similar distinction would not be a tyrant in the plain meaning of the word, since the public welfare is cared for by such a government which is the direct opposite of a tyranny." 215 The mere fact of the pursuit of self-interest by a ruler does not imply that his rule is tyrannical. "[J]ust as one is seldom found who is completely healthy indeed from all bodily defect, so it is a rare thing to find a government that is completely devoted to the public good without some of the qualities of a tyranny." 216 The decisive question is whether the ruler's personal or the public welfare prevails. Bartolus added a third category of concealed tyranny, when the tyrant has no title of any sort, but everything nevertheless proceeds according to his will. This type of tyrant should be treated in the same way as was the case with the previous category. 217 The above should be seen against the background of the general provision that, where the tyrant himself has a superior (as is the case with dukes and counts), the superior should get rid of him. 218 The importance of Bartolus’ approach, it is submitted, lies in the fact that he regarded not only violations of integrity as a basis for resistance, but also exploitation, and that he provided a legal basis 214 Id para 12. 215 Ibid. 216 Ibid. 217 Ibid. 218 Id para 9. for such resistance. L. THE PROTESTANT REFORMATION Resistance, and eventual revolution or at least secession within the Roman Catholic Church in the Sixteenth Century, produced the modern Protestant churches. The Reformation hit been called the religious component of the Renaissance, in the sense that it broke the stifling hold which the church authority had come to have on the spiritual life of medieval times. The revolution of the Protestants took the form of an uncompromising choice for divine inspiration over earthly orthodoxy; it had the categoric nature, in the words of Luther, of "Here I stand for I can do no other." Nevertheless the Protestants by and large represented a conservative view regarding the question of political obligation. Protest in the sense of rejecting the dogma of the Roman Catholic Church formed a clearly targeted component of their message. In essence, they purported to affirm the Biblical revelation as they saw it, which included a demand for the separation of church and state, a view earlier defended by Augustine but subsequently abandoned. Earthly authority did not belong to the church, as was maintained by the Roman Catholic Church, but - and this is important in the context of political resistance - it did belong to the state. The two-tier notion of the state and the church both Reformers exercising there Consequently, earthly could one be would only not authority, was one - expect sword from rejected. that them a of For the robust the state. theory of political resistance. The Reformers’ revived emphasis on the inner or spiritual experience of faith, as opposed to external action or deeds, was also not suggestive of an aggressive circumstances develop a approach existed theory of to which political prompted resistance the which resistance. Reformation represented a Nevertheless, eventually decisive to step further to the modern-day position. According to Aquinas, and the Roman Catholic tradition, the state preceded sin - it was in the state where humans had to fulfil their true earthly existence. Like Augustine, the Reformers regarded the existence of the state as a consequence of sin. The function of the state is to counter the sinful nature of man. Since the state was the only institution on earth which could counter the chaos which resulted from sin, it had to be obeyed. The use of coercion by the state counteracted the consequences of sin and constituted the means whereby God in his mercy provided for the blessing of a peaceful social life. 219 In accordance with these points of departure, the Reformers saw as a critical part of the Christian message the divine endorsement of political authority. Their view was not founded on the notion of a social contract which lost its binding force once the state failed to keep its promise. To them, political authority and obligation did not depend upon consent and the rulers had to answer for their use of power only to God himself. The Reformers recognised the fact that some rulers were wicked, but regarded that as God’s punishment for our sins. As a general rule, if it was impossible to flee from oppression one was expected to suffer injustice. One could not, however, become a partner in injustice, which meant that if the authorities required one to act unjustly one should not co-operate. Because the state was the only legitimate holder of the earthly sword, however, private individuals could not challenge the state. Only after the Reformation itself came under serious threat from political rulers, would its leaders recognise a right under certain circumstances of more confrontational resistance against the state. The fact that the state was now seen as an instrument destined to serve a certain purpose, carried in itself a powerful potential for disobedience; that is if the state were to disregard that purpose. At the same time, it should be noted that, although Luther and Calvin rejected and resisted this view, a number of their followers maintained that rulers who failed to exercise their divine duties could be resisted. This meant that they recognised a right to resist "heretical rulers". The approach of the two most dominant figures of the Reformation, and aspects of their legacy, will now be considered. (1) Martin Luther Although he offered no systematic account of political obligation, it can safely be said that the German theologian, Martin Luther (1483- 219 See the discussion political philosophy 309. of this point in Strauss & Cropsey History of 1546), 220 was as conservative in the political sphere as he was willing to oppose authority in the church. In his essay, "Temporal authority: To what extent it should be obeyed" (1523), Luther entertained the view that the power of the sword exercised by the state is ordained by God, and that even unjust and cruel rulers should be obeyed. The reason lies in Luther’s convictions regarding the total depravity of man - applying equally to those who rule and those who are being ruled. Luther’s conception of the natural state of man reminds one of the description later given by Hobbes of the state of nature; one of a war of every person against all others. In the second part of "Temporal authority", Luther outlined limitations of the state's authority. "External affairs" fail within the scope of secular soul". authority, 221 but the state has no jurisdiction over "the If a political leader were to suppress the Bible or other books (Luther’s own writings were banned and burned by several rulers) and enforce outward compliance to certain simply not co-operate. 222 religious beliefs, one should The use of violence against any leader is prohibited by the Biblical injunction against resisting evil with evil. In another writing, Luther also rejected the notion of a holy war to enforce one's beliefs on others. 223 It is because of our sins that we are ruled by ruthless rulers. "The world is too wicked, and does not deserve to have many wise and upright princes. Frogs must have their storks." 224 Only God can relieve us from such rulers - something which he occasionally does through the 220 For a discussion of Luther's views on political obligation, see Ebenstein Great political thinkers 304ff; Strauss & Cropsey History of political philosophy 293ff; Porter's introduction in Luther Selected political writings Iff and Skinner The foundations of modern political thought vol 2 3ff. His views on political resistance are also discussed by Alien A history of political thought in the Sixteenth Century 15ff and Villa-Vicencio Between Christ and Caesar 39ff; Manenschijn Burgerlljke ongehoorzaamheid 165ff; Douma Politieke verantwoordelijkheid 44; Villa-Vicencio Civil disobedience and beyond 73ff and Smith Hervonnde Teologiese Studies 1988 434 at 437ff. 221 Luther "Temporal authority", reprinted in Luther Selected political writings 51 at 61. 222 223 Ibid. See Luther "On war against Selected political writings 121. 224 63. the Turk" (1529), reprinted in Luther Luther "Temporal authority" in Luther Selected political writings 51 at interference of other rulers or the violent uprising of the unfaithful masses. 225 In spite of Luther’s own conflicts with temporal authorities of his time, he for the most part supported the absolutist rule of the monarchs of his time. In 1525, he endorsed the vicious suppression of the uprising which resulted in the Peasants’ War; one of the causes of which was a commentary mistaken on these interpretation events, Luther of his made writings. 226 own some shocking In his statements, including an admonition to "everyone who can" to "smite, slay and stab, secretly or openly" the rebels, just "as one must kill a mad dog", because "nothing can be more ... devilish than a rebel." 227 In 1531, however, Charles V of Germany prohibited the preaching of Lutheran thought. The use of force by the state to suppress the Reformation seemed imminent. The question of a right to resist now became existential to Luther. Two arguments in favour of disobedience in extreme cases were presented by lawyers to Lutheran theologians. 228 According to Augustine, the ruler does not hold the sovereign power by himself - if he is chosen (or deemed to have been chosen) by lower magistrates they share his power, granted by God. According to constitutional theory, when the ruler uses his powers contrary to the purposes for which he was appointed, these lower magistrates have the power to take up the sword against him. As argued by Azo, in doing so they are not usurping the divine power of the ruler - they already have such power. According to the so-called private law theory, on the other hand, everyone has the right to defend himself against violence. The basis of this theory was the rule of Roman private law that vim vi repellare licet. 229 Similarly, every citizen (and not only the lower magistrates) has the right to defend himself against a violent government. 225 See Luther "Whether soldiers, too, can be saved" (1526), reprinted in Luther Selected political writings 101. 226 The peasants were embittered by increased taxation which they regarded as exploitive, and by the imposition of Roman law and private property concepts which undermined their communal lifestyle. 227 Luther "Against the robbing and murdering hordes of peasants" (1525), reprinted in Luther Selected political writings 85 at 86. 228 See Manenschijn Burgerlijke ongehoorzaaroheid 166. 229 See supra chap five I C. Faced with an emergency, Luther chose the latter, more extreme of the two options. In "Dr Martin Luther’s warning to his dear German people" (1531), 230 Luther described the use of force to crush the Gospel as blasphemy and maintained that rulers who wage such a war are the true rebels. Those who resist the "murderous and bloodthirsty papists", act in self-defence. Those against whom they act cannot properly be considered "rulers", because through such actions the perpetrators have relegated themselves into being mere citizens. It seems that under these circumstances Luther was indeed prepared to abandon his earlier view that political resistance could never involve more than defensive civil disobedience, and sanctioned the use of violence. The latter views, however, constituted an exception to his normally pro-state attitude, which more properly reflects his legacy. Because of his enthusiastic endorsement of the absolute state, nationalism and even racialism, Luther has been described as one of the spiritual ancestors of the excesses of the Third Reich, although this view may be contested especially in view of his later disenchantment with the state and his willingness then to endorse resistance. On the whole, however, Luther’s inconsistencies can be regarded as a reflection of the strain which the traditional (2) Stoic position was undergoing. 231 Jean Calvin In theological terms, the modern, more activist approach to political resistance was Calvin introduced by the great figure of the Reformation, Jean (1509-1564), 232 Calvin’s ideas exerted a great influence on Holland and subsequently on South Africa, where it has been used and 230 Reprinted in Luther Selected political writings 133ff. 231 See Ebenstein Great political thinkers 305. 232 For a discussion of Calvin's legal and political thought, see Strauss a Cropsey History of political philosophy 293ff and Ebenstein Great political thinkers 306ff. See also Alien A history of political thought in the Sixteenth Century 52ff and L du Plessis "Calvin, 'Calvinism' and present-day South Africa" in Corder Essays on law and social practice in South Africa 31, especially 44, where his views on political resistance are discussed. The latter topic is also addressed by Stoker Die stryd om die ordes 243; VilliaVicencio Between Christ and Caesar 43; Vi11a-Vicencio Civil disobedience and beyond 67; Manenschijn Burgerlijke ongehoorzaaroheid 170 ff; Skinner The foundations of modern political thought vo1 2 189ff and Smith Hervormde Teologiese Studies 1988 434 at 441. Van der Watt Die reg van verset may be used to find references to the work of some of those who write in the Calvinistic tradition. abused for legitimising political systems of opposing kinds. 233 Although Luther and Calvin derived their ideas from the same tradition, Calvin placed more emphasis on the division between church and state, which entailed matters. 234 less tolerance for state interference in spiritual Consequently, one would expect Calvin to be more favourably inclined than Luther to a right of resistance against state absolutism, at least insofar as the state’s encroachment on religious matters was concerned. And indeed, eventually Calvin would go much further than Luther as far as his motivation for resistance and the type of resistance are concerned. His initial views, however, did not differ much from those of Luther. In Institutes of the Christian religion (first edition 1536) Calvin instructed subjects to see their rulers as exercising "a jurisdiction bestowed by God". Governments should not be seen as a "necessary and should not be obeyed purely out of fear. 235 evil" As stated in Romans 13, obedience to the government is required because it entails obedience to God, and disobedience to the government amounts to disobedience of God. 236 The general requirement of obedience applies in respect of "all who, by whatever means, have got control of affairs", regardless of whether or not they are unjust rulers and even tyrants. For Calvin, "a wicked king is the Lord’s wrath upon the earth." Although rulers are required to rule justly, a wicked ruler can also accomplish God’s work on earth by punishing his subjects for their sins. The best and the worst king 233 See L du Plessis "Calvin, 'Calvinism' and present-day South Africa" in Corder Essays on law and social practice in South Africa 31, who tried to salvage Calvinism from those who misused it as a spiritual source for apartheid. People to the left and the right of the political spectrum in South Africa have invoked Calvin's views as a justification for political resistance. On Calvinism and the Ossewabrandwag. see Van Rooy Koers 1948 89. See also Dr Treurnicht's remarks in Parliament, House of Assembly Debates col 839 12 Feb 1988 and "Net soos vir Boesak moet Calvyn ook vir Treurnicht instaan" Beeld 18 Feb 1988. See also "Dr T staan by 'reg van verset'" Beeld 6 Sept 1990 and the response to Treurnicht by Amie Van Wyk "Nie einde van Afrikanervolk" Beeld 18 Sept 1990. 234 The Calvinistic concept of "sphere sovereignty" is outlined in Van der Vyver Die jur1d1ese funksie van staat en kerk. See especially 98. 235 Calvin Institutes of the Christian religion 4.20.22. 236 Id 4.20.23. should be held in the same reverence, since both represent God. 237 As Calvin put it in "Commentaries on the first epistle to Timothy": 238 "The universal doctrine is this, that we should desire the continuance and peaceful condition of those governments which have been appointed by God" - and that means all governments. 239 The only possible relief from continuous oppression can come from God, who, in response to the prayers of the suppressed, will send a "hero" or outside agency ("benevolent background force"?) to rid the people of the oppressor. These views of Calvin differ little from the orthodox position of the early church fathers. From the early 1550’s, those who participated in the Reformation in Europe and England experienced increased persecution. The punishment for heresy was death. stake. Calvin continued Again, the whole movement’s survival to defend the line taken in was at Romans 13 in respect of resistance by private individuals. Nevertheless, at the end of the last edition of the Institutes (1559), he now inserted a passage on resistance to political authority, which constituted, in the opinion of many, the nucleus of modern liberty. 240 Following immediately on the exposition of the general rule in favour of obedience, the passage proceeds as follows: I am speaking all the while of private individuals. For if there are now any magistrates of the people, appointed to restrain the willfulness of kings (as in ancient times the ephors were set against the Spartan kings, or the tribunes of the people against the Roman consuls, or the demarchs against the senate of the Athenians; and perhaps, as things now are, such power as the three estates exercise in every realm when they hold their chief assemblies), I am so far from forbidding them to withstand, in accordance with their duty, the fierce licentiousness of kings, that, if they wink at kings who violently fall upon and assault the lowly common folk, I declare that their dissimulation involves nefarious perfidy, because they dishonestly betray the freedom of the people, of which they know that they have been appointed protectors by God’s ordinance. 241 237 Id 4.20.25. See also id 4.20.26. 238 Reprinted in Calvin Commentaries on the epistles to Timothy, Titus and Philemon 19. 239 Calvin "The first epistle to Timothy" 2.2. 240 See the references in Murray Acta Juridica 1958 275 at 300. 241 Calvin Institutes of the Christian religion 4.20.31. The "ephors", the "tribunes" and the "demarchs", which he cited as examples of "magistrates of The important intervention contribution of "lesser here concerns authorities". That resistance through the is, not the it is for individual to take matters in his own hands. Calvin therefore aligned himself with the constitutional approach outlined above (also called, after him, the "Ephoren theory") by expressing his approval opposition to tyranny by the so-called populares magistratus. 242 of He in fact declared that resistance in such cases was not only a right but also a duty. Several observations are called for in this regard. It should be noted, in the first place, that the above, at least in the view of Calvinists, does not technically constitute an exception to the general rule of obedience to authority. The point is that the lower magistrates are part of the governmental structure and are therefore also "rulers", who are endowed with divine authority and are under the divine duty to rule justly. It is the exercise of this duty that can bring them in direct confrontation with the rulers - not a "right of resistance". Nevertheless, insofar circumstances be as the appropriate, exercise it of could this involve power may more in than given non-co- operation or defensive civil disobedience. It can be used to protect the "freedom of the people", and especially those in positions of political weakness - the "lowly common folk". This passage, almost in so many words, justifies active, result-oriented disobedience, based not only on the protection of integrity but also as a defence against exploitation. Another aspect of this passage which is worth noting is the absence of restraints pertaining to the methods that could be employed by the lower officials in opposing the higher officials. Consequently, this passage is commonly violence, under As stated interpreted as an endorsement of the use certain circumstances, as a political instrument. earlier, the above does not technically of 243 constitute an exception to the general rule of obedience to the state by private citizens. The only real exception to the general duty of obedience lies in the principle that "such obedience is never to lead us away from the people", were a11 elected to office by annual popular vote. See also Manenschijn Burgerlijke ongehoorzaamheid 174. 242 See Manenschijn Burgerlijke ongehoorzaamheid 172ff. 243 See Van Wyk Orientation 1988 73 at 74. obedience to [God]". 244 After all, Acts 5 demands just that: "We must obey God rather than men." Because God is "the king of kings", Calvin preached non-co-operation displeasure" of God. "If when co-operation would "incur the they command anything against him, let it go unesteemed." To do so is not only a right but also a duty, which should be executed even if it means losing one's life. It happened, for example, that the Israelites were condemned for being too obedient to wicked kings. 245 Calvin, consequently, endorsed defensive, integritybased civil disobedience by individuals and result-oriented, anti- exploitation resistance by officials. The Reformers, through their insistence on the separation of state and church, prepared the way for a more sceptical view of secular authority, even though this was not their specific aim. They expanded the traditional Christian emphasis on personal responsibility and hence the inviolability of the individual conscience, and restored the idea of the state as an instrument destined to serve a certain purpose. Theologians in the Calvinistic tradition would take Calvin’s ideas on resistance a step further. In a real sense, Calvin can be said to have opened the sluice-gates for Christian theology to follow a much more activist approach to political resistance. 246 Particularly influential in this regard would be the "trilogy" of the Vindiciae (to which we will presently turn), Hotman and Beza. 247 The Scottish Reformer, John Knox, would later argue that to remain silent in the face of tyranny was tantamount to complicity with the tyrant. 248 in this Abraham Kuyper further developed the idea of "spheres of Century, liberty" and 244 Calvin Institutes of the Christian religion 4.20.32. Calvin also stated, in regard to the Fifth Commandment, that if our parents "spur us to transgress the law, we have a perfect right not to regard them as parents, but as strangers who are trying to lead us away from obedience to our true father. So should we act toward princes, lords, and every kind of superiors." Id 2.8.38. 245 Id 4.20.32. See also Hosea 5.13. 246 See Alien A history of political thought in the Sixteenth Century l03ff. 247 In his influential work. Concerning the rights of rulers, Beza outlined the principle of fundamental law and his justification of the right to revolt. 248 See Vi11a-Vicencio Between Christ and Caesar foundations of modern political thought vol 2 l89ff. 68 and Skinner The placed an even greater emphasis on the independence of the church. 249 Brunner was noted for defending the private-law approach to the right of resistance. 250 Calvin’s constraint, that only the magistrates could initiate revolt, was interpreted by oppressed people around the world, including South Africa, to mean that, where they did not enjoy representation, those leaders who would probably have represented them if there were free elections can initiate resistance. 251 (3) The Vindiciae contra tyrannos History proved the concerns of Reformers regarding the approach of the political rulers toward the Reformation to be well-founded. The prosecution of the Protestants reached a climax in the massacre of St Bartholomew (1572) in which 30 000 Hugenots - the French Catvinists lost their lives. From this tragic course of events emerged a document called the Vindiciae contra tyrannos (1579), which was written by an author whose identity Brutus. 252 is not certain, under the pseudonym of Stephen Junius This document, translated into English in 1689 as A defence of liberty against tyrants, dominated political thought in Europe and in Britain until the appearance of Rousseau in the Eighteenth Century and had a markedly strong influence in the Netherlands. The declaration which attended Dutch severance with the rulership of Philip of Spain the Placcaet van Verlatinge of 1581 - was taken from the Vindiciae. From the Netherlands, which at that stage was the centre of world liberalism, the ideas advanced in the Vindiciae spread across the globe 249 See Treurnicht Die verhouding van die staat tot die kerk by dr Abraham Kuyper 487ff. For Treurnicht's discussion of Calvinistic views on political resistance, see id 242ff. 250 See Van Eikema Hommes Major trends in the history of legal philosophy 251 See Villa-Vicencio Civil disobedience and beyond 94. 343. 252 The author was probably Philippe du Plessis Mornay, with a contribution by the lawyer, Hubert Languet. For a discussion of the Vindiciae, see H J Laski's "Historical introduction" in Brutus A defence of liberty against tyrants 1ff; Murray Acta Juridica 1958 275; Ebenstein Great political thinkers 307ff and P Coertzen "Burgerlike ongehoorsaamheid: ‘n Kerkhistoriese perspektief" in Du Toit Staatsgesag en burgerlike ongehoorsaamheid 54 at 60. and to South Africa. 253 According to the Vindiciae, the king’s position is established by two contracts. In the first place, the people conclude a contract with God, to be his people. In the second place, the people conclude a contract with the king, whereby they promise to obey him if he rules justly. The king occupies the position of trustee of the people, who established him as their king. If the king violates his duty to rule justly, the people are allowed and indeed obliged to resist or depose him on the basis of their first contract with God. The king is but an instrument of the law and should rule the people in their own best interest. A king rules unjustly if he does not rule according to law or does not serve the commonwealth. 254 Two types of tyrants could be distinguished. In the first place, there are those who illegally usurp power. The proper response to this type of tyrant depends on how he rules, for such a tyrant can rule justly. The tyrant who has the legitimate title to rule but rules unjustly can only be deposed by the magistrates and assemblies of estates. The "double tyrant", however, who usurps power and rules unjustly, can be resisted - if there are no other alternatives - by any citizen, even if that involves tyrannicide. 255 Although the main purpose of the Vindiciae was to vindicate the right of protecting one’s religious convictions through non-co-operation in religious matters, it could also provide a basis for result-oriented disobedience in pursuit of non-religious objectives. These ideas, considered radical at the time, would have a powerful effect on the development of particularly Dutch and English political thinking. M. THE REVIVAL OF THOMISM The Reformation prompted a revival of Thomism, which manifested itself most clearly in the work and writings of the "Spanish Schoolmen" or the "School of Salamanca", who played an important role in the development of international law and the Roman Dutch legal system. The most prominent writers in this tradition were the Dominicans, Francisco de Victoria (c 1485-1546) and Domingo de Soto (1494-1560), and the later 253 See Murray Acta Juridica 1958 276 at 312, 313. 254 Brutus A defence of liberty against tyrants 71ff. 255 Id 87ff. Jesuits, Luis de Molina (1535-1600) and Francisco Suarez (1548-1617). These Neo-Thomists delivered their contributions at a time when Christianity had been split by the Reformation and, in its place, the new international Columbus took sovereigns, community was emerging. possession of the New Victoria 256 Some forty years after World on behalf of the Spanish transformed Christian morality into an international science - that is, into the law of nations, which would be endowed with its philosophy by Suarez and its literary form by Grotius. 257 The prime target of these writers was, what they called, "the heretics of the age" - meaning the followers of Luther (not Luther himself), who not only denied the law-making powers of the Pope but also rejected the natural-law foundation of the Thomist perception of the state and human nature. Their contention that civil government cannot remain in the hands of ungodly rulers and that the commands of an ungodly prince were not binding in conscience, were regarded as particularly dangerous and subversive. In the hands of the "heretics", the notion of a right to resist a tyrant was replaced by a right to resist a heretical ruler. At the same time, the Thomists were concerned about the Spanish conquest and enslavement of Indians in America, which had been justified on the basis that the latter were not Christians and that their repression, consequently, amounted to a war against infidels. 258 In accordance with Romans 13, Victoria expressed the view that all authority emanates from God, and just as much as it is sinful to transgress the laws of God, so too is it a sin "in the court of conscience" to transgress human laws of whatever government. 259 When the sovereign fails to act in does not create law. human law was 260 defined a way "advantageous to the state", he simply The possibility of conflict between natural and away: if human law finds itself in such a 256 In accordance with established custom, when his full name is used the Spanish form, "Francisco de Vitoria" is employed. When reference is made only to his last name the Latinized (and Englished) form "Victoria" is used. 257 See Scott The Spanish conception of international law and of sanctions 258 See Skinner The foundations of modern political thought vo1 2 135. 2. 259 See Victoria "Concerning civil power", reprinted in Scott The Spanish conception of international law and of sanctions Ixxi at Ixxxiii. 260 See Kennedy Harvard International Law Journal 1986 1 at 17. conflict, it is Thomistic natural-law N. law. 261 not This co-incided with the traditional approach, which equated morality and law. JEAN BODIN The idea of state sovereignty was first explicitly analysed by the Frenchman, Jean (1530-1596), 262 Bodin in The six books of the commonwealth (1576). Bodin defined sovereignty as "the absolute and perpetual power vested in the commonwealth which in Latin is called majestas". 263 He also declared that "there are none on earth, after God, greater than sovereign princes." 264 Although Bodin was a prophet of monarchy, and clearly intended to refute the claim of the church possessing higher authority than the state, he did not believe that the state was free from all bondage. To him, the royal monarch was bound to obey "the laws of God, and natural liberty" and in certain cases also had to keep his own laws. 265 Bodin saw the difference between what he regarded as legitimate kings, on the one hand, and tyrants, on the other, as follows: "A tyrannical monarchy is one in which the monarch tramples underfoot the laws of nature, in that he abuses the natural liberty of his subjects by making them his slaves, own." and invades the property of others by treating it as his 266 The king "bases his rule on the love of his people [and the tyrant] on their fear". 267 In other words, the one depend for political obedience primarily on authority, the other on control. Nevertheless, the mere fact that someone was a tyrant did no justify disobedience. Bodin stated: I conclude then that the subject is never justified in any circumstances in attempting anything against he sovereign prince, however evil and tyrannical he might be. It is however 261 See Koskenniemi From apology to Utopia 77. 262 For a general discussion of his political philosophy, see Ebenstein Great political thinkers 349. 263 Bodin Six books of the commonwealth 1.8. 264 Id 1.10. 265 Id 2.2 & 3. 266 Id 2.4 & 5. 267 Ibid. permissible to fail to obey him in an command contrary to the law of God and of nature, but one must then seek refuge in flight, go into hiding or suffer death rather than attempt anything against his life or his honour. 268 Bodin did recognise the right to "just tyrannicide", 269 but in his view the determining factor in this regard was not the substantial justice of the ruler’s reign, but instead a procedural question, namely how did the ruler acquire power. 270 If he did so illegally, he could be killed; if not, the question must be asked whether he is sovereign. If he is not sovereign (for example if he was elected by a sovereign people), legal channels should be used to dispose of him. If that does not succeed, the use of force may be appropriate. If he is sovereign, he cannot be deposed and no amount of injustices on his part can justify the use of force. 271 In essence, Bodin’s position consequently amounted to a radical positivism which did not allow for an external vantage point from which the quality of a ruler can be judged. 272 O. GROTIUS Hugo de Groot (1583-1645) is widely recognised as one of the greatest jurists in the Roman-Dutch legal tradition and indeed of the world. 273 He has acquired the reputation of father of international law and as one of the major proponents of natural law. The enduring appeal of his most famous work, De jure belli ac pacts, lies, according to John ----------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------- 273 ----------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------- 268 Ibid. 269 Ibid. 270 Ibid. 271 Ibid. 272 For a discussion of Johannes Althusius' views on political obligation and the right of resistance, which radically contradicts those of Bodin, see Van Eikema Hommes Major trends in the history of legal philosophy 77ff. 273 See Kahn SALJ 1983 192 at 192. Dugard, in its "attempt to inject morality, justice and idealism into the international legal order". 274 Grotius (his self-assumed nom de plume) represents the transition from the medieval to modern philosophy and as such his views represent elements of both worlds. While his approach to international law was modern, his views on political obligation showed Grotius to belong to the pre-modern rather than the modern age. 275 The modern conception of the state would emerge in the writings of people like Hobbes, who saw no metaphysical element in state authority. Grotius recognised that political obligation is based on consent, but since the obligations that arise from consent derive their force from the law of nature, the ultimate source of political obligation is natural law. Based on this premise, prison the in otherwise consequence liberal of Grotius, his who religious himself beliefs, 276 spend time arrived at in a surprisingly restricted view on political resistance. Grotius accepted that people focus their lives on seeking their own interest. Hobbes, who proceeded from the same premise, proclaimed that "justice", insofar as it does exist, is simply a guise in which selfinterest is pursued. 277 Grotius, on the other hand, maintained that man’s unique rational faculty demonstrates to him that justice is a virtue, a good in itself, apart from any consideration of self- interest. Consequently the natural inclination of humans as rational creatures is to act justly and to seek social intercourse with others. The result is the social contract. 278 A ruler might, according to the social contract, be sovereign and not be responsible to the people. In that case, a general principle of nonresistance pertains, according to which one cannot actively oppose the ruler. According to Grotius, this rule can be deduced from the Bible as well as from Plato and the Stoics, and is written in the hearts of all people: "If unjust treatment be inflicted on us, we ought to endure it 274 Dugard SALJ 1983 213 at 215. 275 For commentary on his political views, see Strauss & Cropsey History of political philosophy 360. 276 See Kahn SALJ 1983 192 at 196. 277 See Infra chap five I P. 278 For a more detailed discussion, see Van der Vyver Die juridiese sin van die leerstuk van menseregte vol 1 86ff. rather than resist by force." 279 Grotius advised people who were wronged to "take it patiently"; "to bring goodwill to [one’s] master, no matter how unjust." He quoted Livy as saying that "[h]arsh treatment on the part of our country, as on the part of our parents, we must assuage by suffering and enduring." 280 Through an overview of the history of the early Christians, Grotius illustrated their refusal to engage in armed resistance in spite of their being severely persecuted. 281 The general rule of non-resistance does not preclude one, however, from simply not obeying the authorities in certain cases. Directly invoking Christianity 282 and Stoicism 283 Grotius maintained that "among good men one principle is established beyond controversy, that if the authorities issue any order that is contrary to the law of nature or to the commandments of God, the order should not be carried out." 284 This means that extreme cases may arise in which a right not to cooperate would manifest itself. However, we are to endure unjust treatment rather than positively resist the government, at least by force. Consequently, in the case of rulers who are not responsible to the people, there is a general rule against rebellion and in favour of obedience to the state. This is based on the fact that the unlimited licence to defend oneself, which prevails in the state of nature, was relinquished once the pactum unionis is had been concluded. Without limitations on the common right of resistance which obtains in the state of nature, government cannot achieve its end of ensuring public tranquil1ity. 285 Grotius remarked that the punishment for rebellion, according to Hebrew law, was death. The only avenue open to the oppressed was that they 279 Grotius De jure belli ac pads 1.4.1.3. 280 Id 1.4.4.6. 281 Id 1.4.5. 282 Ibid. 283 Id 1.4.4.6. For a discussion of the influence of Stoicism on Grotius, see Fortuin De natuurrechtelijke grondslagen van De Groot's volkenrecht 35ff. 284 Grotlus De jure belli ac pads 1.4.1.3. 285 Id 1.4.2.1. "should implore the help of God, because, in fact, there would be no recourse at the hands of man". 286 Rebellion, in the opinion of Grotius, is even less compatible with the message of the New Testament. Romans 13 demands subjection and with that non-resistance. This requirement should be observed not only to ward of a greater evil (that is for consequentialistic reasons) but also because of a duty of obedience to God (that is, for deontological reasons). 287 Considerations of one’s own advantage are not Irrelevant, however: Ultimately Grotius viewed the safety of the individual. Grotius state as the sine qua non for the safety of the 288 rejected the view that subordinate officials - populares magistratus - were entitled to rebel against sovereign authority, since the former logically In are 289 order also subject to the and in terms of Romans 13. to find an answer to authority of the latter, both 290 the question whether the general "principle of non-resistance", which has been alluded to above, obliged people to prefer being killed above offering violent resistance, Grotius asked himself what the opinion of those who formed the original social compact would have been at the time when they were designing their future society. His approach can be regarded as a classic example of recourse to the device of the original position, which we will also apply later. Grotius argued, cautiously, that they would not have required such absolute obedience: If these men could be asked whether they purposed to impose upon all persons the obligation to prefer death rather than under any circumstances to take up arms in order to ward off the violence of those having superior authority, I do not know whether they would answer in the affirmative, unless, perhaps, with this qualification, in case resistance could not be made without a very great disturbance in the state, and without the destruction of a great many innocent people. 291 This course of conduct is not denied to minorities or even individuals 286 Id 1.4.3. 287 Id 1.4.4.1. 288 Id 1.4.4.4 & 1.4.4.5. 289 Id 1.4.6.1. 290 Id 1.4.6.3. 291 Id 1.4.7.2. as a last resort but without abandoning considerations of the common good. 292 Nevertheless, the person of the king must be saved. 293 Grotius identified a number of other cases where the general rule of non-resistance does not apply. 294 One is where the king sets out with a truly hostile another" - intent that is, to in destroy cases "one of people ... exploitation. for the sake of It can also be 295 expressively part of the arrangement under which the king governs that he might be resisted under certain circumstances. 296 The above dealt with the ruler who is not responsible to his people. The overall situation is quite different in respect of rulers who are responsible to the people. Grotius quite blandly maintained that "if such rulers transgress against the laws and the state, not only can they be resisted by force, but, in case of necessity, they can be punished by death." 297 Also, where a king possesses only part of the sovereign power, while "the people or senate" possess the other part, "force can lawfully be used against the king if he attempts to usurp that part of the sovereign power which does not belong to him." 298 In the situations described above - that of the ruler who has sovereignty and that of the ruler instated by the people - the ruler has, at least formally, the right of governing. The question remains as to the position obtaining to the ruler who has usurped political power. In general, the laws of such a ruler would not be valid. However, citing, amongst others, Cicero, Grotius argued that grave danger to the state, due to utter confusion 292 Id 1.4.7.4. 293 Id 1.4.7.6. 294 Id 1.4.9 8. 1.4.10. that would ensue from denying the 295 The right to resist with force obtains also when "a king [who] rules over several peoples ... wish[es] to have one people destroyed for the sake of another, in order that he may colonise the territory thus made vacant". Id 1.4.11. The political application of this opinion in both the old and the new South Africa should be evident. In the old South Africa the government was often accused of genocide; at present it is accused', from different quarters, of "selling out" the whites. 296 Id 1.4.14. See also the Constitution supra chap two I A. 297 Id 1.4.8. 298 Id 1.4.13. reference to art 20(4) of the German validity of such laws, might reinstate the necessity of obedience to such laws. 299 Nevertheless, in a number of cases the right to use force against unscrupulous rulers is recognised. 300 In general Grotius agreed with Cicero that "peace on advantageous than civil war." any terms between citizens seems more 301 De jure belli ac pacis did not provide any justification for wars of national liberation, since Grotius listed the "desire for freedom among a subject people" as an unjust cause of war. 302 Grotius’ conservative approach in respect of political resistance is epitomised in the following words: "Above all, in case of a controversy the private individual ought not to take it upon himself to pass judgment, but should accept the fact of possession [of the governing power as conclusive]." 303 His approach can consequently be regarded as being in the traditional, pre-modern Stoic mould. 304 P. THOMAS HOBBES Seventeenth Century Britain witnessed the kind of turmoil that often accompanies fundamental change. On the continent, the Reformation led to the Thirty belligerency Years War (1618-1648) which brought widespread and ruin to Europe. In Britain, the puritan revolution took place and two civil wars were fought. In 1649, King Charles I was executed. The days of the "divine right of kings" were over, but it was by no means clear that democracy would bring stability. To many, the opposite seemed more probable. Under these circumstances and while in exile in Europe due to his close 299 Id 1.4.15.1 & 1.4.15.2. 300 Id 1.4.16; 1.4.17 & 1.4.18. 301 Id 1.4.19. 302 Id 2.22.11. 303 Id 1.4.20. Grotius also argued that agreements reached with tyrants should be honoured. Id 3.19.2. 304 However, Grotius is listed as a proponent of the "right of resistance" by Sudima "The right to revolution" in McDougall & Reisman International law in contemporary perspective 167 at 168. See also Paust Emory Law Journal 1983 545 at 561, who made the same point. Contra Dugard SALJ 1983 213 at 218. See also Fortuin De natuurrechte1ijke grondslagen van De Groot's volkenrecht 144. ties with the royalty, Thomas Hobbes (1588-1679) 305 wrote the famous Leviathan (1651), the first general theory of politics to be published -in England. defence of In it Hobbes absolute political philosophy, provided government. 306 In an elaborate this and his and well-reasoned other works on Hobbes, following Machiavelli, broke with the tradition of Socrates, Plato and Cicero, which he believed had failed to secure peace since it tried to achieve too much. It had focused, Hobbes and the new generation of political theorists believed, on what humans could be and aspired to, instead of on what they were. Hobbes wanted to establish a theory of government on a scientific basis, which dealt with goats people actually pursue and attain. In the process, he would proclaim an even more constricted view of resistance than the Stoics. Hobbes did not accept as his point of departure the usual premise of absolutist rule, namely the inequality of men, but on the contrary adopted as persons. 307 his basic premise precisely the basic equality of all In a state of nature - that is, in the absence of government - all people were more or less equally strong and equally vulnerable. All people had the ability to kill one another. Because all had "a perpetuall and restlesse desire of power after power, that ceaseth onely in death," 308 they were each natural enemies. This led to war, which was the natural state of man, "and such a warre, as is of every man, against every man". 309 No civilization could develop in such a desperate situation, and "the life of man [is] solitary, poore, nasty, brutish, and short." 310 This situation severely threatened one's most basic passion - the will to self-preservation. Driven by the fear of 305 violent death, reason For a discussion of Hobbes' political thought, see Ebenstein Great political thinkers 362ff; Strauss & Cropsey History of political philosophy 370ff; Höffding A history of modern philosophy vo1 1 259ff; Vorlander Geschiedenis van de wijsbegeerte vo1 3 62ff; Van Eikema Hommes Major trends in the history of legal philosophy 104ff and MacPherson's introduction in Hobbes' Leviathan 9ff. His approach to legal and political obligation is discussed in Macfarlane Modern political theory 98. 306 The elements of law (1640) and De cive (1642). 307 Hobbes Leviathan 1.13. 308 Id, 1.11. 309 Id 1.13. 310 Ibid. eventually suggested certain rules for peaceful co-existence. Because adoption of these rules was suggested by nature itself, of which reason was a part, they were called "rules of reason", "laws of nature" or the "moral law". Ultimately, however, they had their origin in the selfish passions and desires of human beings. 311 Reason demands of each person to lay down his unlimited right to do anything and not to do to others what one reasonably expects them not to do to oneself. Such an arrangement cannot be maintained, however, if there is not an enforcement agency. An absolute sovereign, a Leviathan, the greatest power on earth to which all are subject, is necessary to constrain the pride of man. Hence, a social contract was entered into whereby such a sovereign authority was established, which could enforce those rules necessary to secure the protection of the parties to the contract. Thus the sovereign state came into being. Hobbes’ social contract regulated two matters: (i) on the one hand, it was a covenant of each member of the future body politic with each of the others, to acknowledge, as sovereign, the body they so elect; and (ii) on the other, it ordained the vote determining who is to be that sovereign. The validity of the covenant was not affected by duress. All living in a commonwealth, thereby accepting the protection of the sovereign, is to be regarded as having tacitly entered into the covenant and as having lost their right to resist. Once the state of nature is replaced by civil government and the sovereign is designated according to the social contract, "he that dissented must now consent with the rest ... or else justly be destroyed by the rest." 312 The position of the ruler is now virtually unassailable: "[N]o man that hath soveraigne power can justly be put to death, or otherwise in any manner by his subjects punished," because through the social regarded as the authors of these actions. contract 313 the subjects are According to Hobbes, "he who hath the supreme power can do his subject no injury." 314 It should be noted that, according to Hobbes, the contract is one 311 Id 1.14. 312 Id 2.18.3. 313 Id 2.18.5. 314 Hobbes "Philosophical rudiments concerning government and society", reprinted in Hobbes The English works of Thomas Hobbes of Malmesbury 111. between the subjects and not between the subjects and the state. The state is a result of the contract, not a party to it. Hence the state cannot "breach contract" or in any other way act illegally or unjustly. The state, through its positive laws, determines what is lawful and just, and what is not. The sovereign "may commit iniquity; but not injustice, or injury in the proper signification", definition the state cannot act illegally. 315 because per To put it bluntly: The state is above the law. This amounts to the position that even if a weak right of resistance could be recognised, there is no room for a strong right. If, then, it is the task of the state to bring security, the next question is what form of government is most likely to render that result. On practical grounds, Hobbes opted for a monarchy, since it is not susceptible to competition for office as are aristocracies and democracies and it is easier for one to reach a decision than for many. Nevertheless, Hobbes was willing to submit to Cromwell’s rule, because he considered it the most effective at the time. From Hobbes’ point of departure of the all-pervasive requirement of security, the need for the state to be all-powerful followed naturally. There should be no absolutely obedient. division 316 of powers, and the subjects must be No private judgments on what is good and what is evil should be tolerated. If compliance with a command of the sovereign is sinful, it is the sovereign’s sin, not the sin of the subject. Not being a religious believer himself, Hobbes viewed religion as a serious threat to the authority of the state. 317 In his quest to make government unassailable, Hobbes sought to destroy the tools by which it could be attacked and criticised. He rejected the traditional notion of natural law as a higher law, whether based on religion or reason, and denied the validity of any universal values. The judgment that something is "good" or "evil", for Hobbes, merely indicated the personal emotional disposition of the person expressing that opinion. Consequently, the judgment that a particular ruler is a 315 Id 2.18.4. 316 Id 2.18.8 & 2.20. 317 Ebenstein Great political thinkers 367 remarked that Hobbes with penetrating insight foresaw the revolutionary implications of the new natural law ideas as they became manifest only a century later in the American and French Revolutions. tyrant did not, as far as he was concerned, indicate anything ethically the matter with the way in that there was which that person governed. It merely indicated a personal preference, and an unwarranted preference at that, because it undermines the authority of the state. The doctrine that tyrannicide is lawful, according to Hobbes, amounts to saying that it is lawful to murder a king as long as he is called a tyrant first. If he wanted to stay in legislation from becoming power, the sovereign should prevent his so oppressive to his subjects that they will make an appeal to their original right of self-preservation and will prefer the state of nature to the civil state. However, this constraint on the sovereign is a practical and not a moral one. 318 This suggests, completely at however, the mercy that of the the citizen state. in Hoboes’ Political state is not obligation is not entirely absolute in the sense that the subject that considers himself wronged can do nothing about it. Not all natural rights are transformed through the social contract, for it is deemed a voluntary act, "and of the voluntary acts of every man the object is some good to himseife". 319 Because "[t]he end of obedience is protection", 320 one retains the right to defend one’s own interests, for the protection of which the state was established in the first place. Consequently, Hobbes argued that "[i]f the sovereign command a man (though justly condemned), to kill, wound, or mayme himselfe ... yet hath that man the liberty to disobey." 321 No one can be obliged to bring about his own destruction, either in battle, by submitting peacefully to execution, or testifying against himself in court. Each person, consequently, has an inalienable right to life, resistance insofar as one’s own life is threatened. and a right of 322 This right can be exercised if the state does not properly protect 318 See the discussion in Van Eikema Hommes Major trends in the history of legal philosophy 105. 319 Id 1.14. (Original emphasis.) 320 Id 2.21. 321 Ibid. 322 Id 2.21. those interests or if they are threatened by the state itself. 323 The right to personal self-protection of life, bodily integrity and freedom is consequently inalienable, and in defence of this right one can, if necessary, use force against the officials of the state. As far as the protection of other persons’ interests is concerned, however, one in general has no right to interfere with the actions of the state. 324 It should be noted, however, that even in those cases where the subject considers his life to be threatened by the state, Hobbes merely granted the subject a weak right to resist. The sovereign retained the right to punish resistors, even when the resistance was justified. 325 The right of resistance is therefore a right of self-defence which primarily covers the protection of one’s own life and body. Hobbes regarded as "seditious" and "repugnant to civil society" the doctrine "that whatsoever a man does against his conscience is sin [because] it depends on the presumption of making him the judge of good and evil." Instead, it must be accepted that "the law is the public conscience." Failure to adhere to this principle is the reason for political instabi1ity. In spite of his rejection of the traditional Stoic-Christian notion of integrity-based resistance civil disobedience, nevertheless did provide Hobbes’ notion of limited protection justified for moral convictions. According to him, one is also "not obliged not to resist" if one is forced to contribute to the conviction of one’s own parent, or a benefactor, or to do any act that is so shameful that it would result in one’s being so miserable that one would grow weary of one’s own life. 326 His primary focus, however, was on the protection of physical and not moral integrity. In a word, it may be said that Hobbes restricted his endorsement of disobedience (violent or otherwise) to that which is necessary for the defence and preservation of bodily integrity, with a very limited scope 323 Ibid. 324 Id 1.14. 325 See the discussion of this point by Macfarlane Political disobedience 25. 326 Id 1.14. See also Strauss & Cropsey History of political philosophy 382. Hobbes also recognised that when people are conscripted to fight in a war, provision should be made for "timorousnesse", and he suggested the creation of alternative forms of notary service. Id 2.21. for the protection of spiritual integrity. 327 The basis of such a right was the state’s breach of contract. No doubt, Hobbes has been an inspiration to totalitarian regimes rather than to democracies, and he can rightfully be described as an authoritarian. Nevertheless, it would be unfair to altogether dismiss him as a totalitarian. Hobbes’ great contribution was to identify the protection of the interests of the individual as the touchstone of political obligation. By doing this, he wrested political theory from the grasp of metaphysical speculation (such as the divine right of kings) and from being completely determined by the common good. He narrowly interpreted the interests of the individual that had to be protected, which led to a conservative view of the position of the individual. almost Hobbes’ obsessive important, preoccupation view though, of is the his with need notion physical for a of the security powerful led state. inalienability to an What is of the individual's right to survival. This right cannot even be alienated by the all-powerful state, since the latter’s function is to serve the former. The state, according to this approach, is merely an instrument for serving human and specifically individual needs. Where the state does not reach this goal, it loses its legitimacy and may be resisted. Soon theorists like Locke would use this same construction, but would afford a wider interpretation to those interests of the individual which are to be regarded as inalienable. This resulted in a more liberal view of the relationship between the state and its subject. In this new development, the contribution of Hobbes, in spite of his of law at absolutist tendencies, was crucial. Q. SAMUEL PUFENDORF In Germany, Samuel Pufendorf (1632-1694), professor Heidelberg, made an important contribution towards the establishment of natural law thinking in the Seventeenth Century. 328 Pufendorf’s acceptance of a natural social inclination among humans led him to regard the social contract theory as the basis of political 327 Spinoza largely shared Hobbes' views regarding political and legal obligation, but exempted the areas of religious practice and scientific enquiry from state control. See Van Eikema Hommes Major trends in the history of legal philosophy 107 328 Van Zy1 Geskiedenis van die Romeins-Hollandse Reg 197. obligation. Pufendorf dealt with the question concerning the limits of obedience to the political ruler in his best-known work. On the law of nature and nations (1672), in a chapter entitled "On the sanctity of supreme sovereignty states". 329 in With regard to sovereign rulers, Pufendorf maintained that it would be "to mankind’s greatest interest" that supreme civil sovereignty be held sacrosanct. There is an "obligation of non-resistance" and "immediate obedience" of rulers as long as they remain within the limits of their power. 330 Pufendorf rejected Hobbes’ premise that there was no pact between state and citizen, and that the citizen should be regarded as having consented to whatever the state might do. Instead, Pufendorf maintained that such a contract existed in terms of which the subjection by citizens of their will to the state is limited by the objectives of the state. Only the state can do what is needed for its own preservation. 331 However, Pufendorf claimed that "there is always a presumption of justice on the part of the prince." 332 The general duty of obedience may not readily be disregarded. Allowance must be made for the state’s inability to satisfy all the demands of everyone, and not every cause for discontent should be seen as an "injury". Articulating the traditional Stoic position, Pufendorf declared that "even Jupiter does not suit everybody whether he sends fair weather or foul. " 333 However, the state can "injure" the citizen because there is a "community of natural law between them". "Injuries" can take one of two possible forms. The ruler can citizens, or (ii) not as "men". 334 either treat his people (i) not as The case where people are not treated as citizens can also manifest itself in two ways: The ruler can do injury to them as a political whole or as individual citizens. The ruler can do injury to the citizens as a political whole, by abandoning all care of the commonwealth, or (worse still), by acting with hostile intent against the safety of the state - that is, if he "puts on the 329 See Pufendorf On the law of nature and nations book 5. 330 Pufendorf On the law of nature and nations 7.8.1. See also Pufendorf The elements of universal jurisprudence 2.5.21. 331 Pufendorf On the law of nature and nations 7.8.2. 332 Id 7.8.6. 333 Id 7.8.3. 334 Id 7.8.4. guise of an enemy". 335 The same applies when he subverts basic laws. The ruler owes to individuals - as citizens - "the enjoyment of the right each holds in common with the rest". 336 Pufendorf also identified ways in which the ruler can do injury to his subjects as persons or private individuals. 337 In such cases the state acts beyond the scope of its powers. But does this justify resistance? With reference to Tacitus, Plato and Cicero, Pufendorf counseled an endurance of at least the lesser injuries. In the case of more frightful injuries, one’s first attempt should be to flee and if necessary to leave the country. 338 When it is impossible to flee but the ruler requires one to commit a sin, even if one has agreed to being ruled by a political sovereign, one would remain subject to God’s sovereignty, since the latter is superior to the former. Consequently, one can never have the duty to commit a sin or to do that which is "worse than death itself". Because the ruler in such cases acts as an enemy instead of a prince, "he is understood to have released the citizen also from the obligation by which the latter was held bound to him". 339 In effect, the social contract is dissolved through non-compliance by the ruler with his obligations under the agreement. Yet, this does not imply that the individual subject has a right to resist the ruler through the use of - force. If a ruler claims to act "under a plea of right" - that is, if he maintains that he is punishing a citizen for a breach of law - and it is impossible to flee, one has no right to defend oneself. According to Pufendorf, in such cases "a man should be killed rather than kill." 340 The reason for this is that using violence against the sovereign under such circumstances would threaten the whole commonwealth with "grave tumults", 341 335 Ibid. 336 Ibid. 337 Eg by disgracing an honourable man, denying a promised reward or debt, etc. Ibid. 338 Id 7.8.5. 339 Ibid. 340 Ibid. 341 Ibid. Only under the most extreme circumstances can violent revolution be justified. Should a prince assume a mind utterly hostile towards his subjects, and openly seek their destruction without the pretext of a cause which has at least the appearance of justice, his subjects can rightly employ against him also the means customarily used against an enemy, for the sake of defending their own safety." 342 If he acts applies. 343 against individuals like an enemy, the same principle Pufendorf hastened to add, however, that "it is scarcely possible for it to happen that a prince should assume such a mind towards the whole people." 344 Pufendorf further argued that, even if there were cases in which it was not wrong for some one citizen to defend his safety by force against the most open injuries of a superior, yet it will not be allowable for the rest of the citizen on that account to drop their obedience and protect the innocent person by force. [A]n injury done to on citizen in no wise releases all the rest from their obligation towards their prince. The reason for this is that each citizen bargains originally on his own behalf for the prince’s care and protection, and doe not lay down as a condition of his subjection, that he will treat each and every other citizen justly. 345 The above applies to sovereign rulers. Like Grotius, Pufendorf recognised a far-reaching right of resistance against those "who bear the name of king but are in fact subject to the power of the people". Pufendorf did not state dearly under what circumstances this right could be exercised, but stated explicitly that the citizens could, if necessary, oppose him with force. 346 There is no obligation to obey usurpers or "unlawful invaders of sovereignty". Necessity might require compliance with such a person's rule, but someone who does that "is not chargeable with a fault in case he throws off that unjust necessity". 347 In practice, however, the need for order might preclude active resistance. 348 342 Pufendorf The elements of universal jurisprudence 2.5.22. 343 Ibid. 344 Ibid. 345 Pufendorf On the law of nature and nations 7.8.5. 346 Id 7.8.8. 347 Id 7.8.9. 348 Id 7.8.10. Consequently, Pufendorf’s views may also be seen as extremely cautious as far as the recognition of a right of resistance is concerned. He advanced two reasons for his conservative approach to resistance. Citizens, on their part, do not always obey their ruler; and violent resistance often leads to "the great slaughter of citizens". 349 Nevertheless, he contributed towards the development of the idea that political resistance can be justified in terms of natural law and a right of self-defence. R. JOHN LOCKE The Englishman, John Locke (1632-1704), 350 is commonly regarded as the father of modern liberalism, and one of the most influential figures in the emergence of contemporary democracies. His influence nowhere appears more clearly than in the foundation of the American system of government. The Declaration of Independence of 1776, both in language and in underlying features of the philosophy, is purely Lockian, as are the main American constitution: limited government based on the consent of the people, and the recognition of inalienable individual rights. In its turn, the United States constitution, the first to give extensive recognition to the ideas of liberty, especially in its Bill of Rights, had an immense influence on the promotion in the world of liberal and egalitarian ideals. Locke’s most important work on political philosophy. Two treatises of government 351 (first published in 1690), written largely while he was in self-imposed exile in liberal Holland, was aimed against despotism and sought to justify the overthrow by revolution of repressive regimes. 352 349 Id 7.8.5. 350 For a discussion of Locke's political philosophy, see Ebenstein Great political thinkers 401ff; Strauss & Cropsey History of political philosophy 451ff; Hoffding A history of modern philosophy vol 1 377ff; Vorländer Geschiedenis van de wijsoegeerte vol 3 109; Laslett's introduction in Locke Two treatises of government ixff and Van Eikema Hommes Major trends in the history of legal philosophy 133ff. His approach to legal and political obligation is discussed by Macfarlane Modern political theory 98. 351 The second book, often published separately and called the "Second treatise" or "Of civil government", contains the roost crucial exposition of Locke's thought on natural rights and political obligation. 352 See the discussion by Sumid "The right to revolution" 1n McDougal & Reisman International law in contemporary perspective 167 at 168 and VillaVicencio Civil disobedience and beyond 72. Contra Van der Vyver Contours of Written several years before the "Glorious" or "Bloodless" revolution of 1688, it intellectual was published justification only for after the that event. transition from It provided royal the absolutism under the Stuart Dynasty to a constitutional monarchy under William of Orange in which parliament would be supreme. Locke substituted the principle of consent of the governed as the ultimate source and delimitation of political power for the concept of the divine right of kings. The point of departure for Locke - as for Hobbes - was the state of nature where there was no civil government. 353 A "state of nature" can manifest itself in a variety of ways: it can exist before a civil government is formed in a particular region, it can exist between states, or after a government has been formed to the extent to which that government is ineffective (for example where one encounters a robber on a deserted road), or insofar as government has degenerated into lawlessness. In the state of nature everyone is free and is bound only by his own consent. 354 For Hobbes, the absence of government implied the absence of any law and an ongoing struggle for survival. In the state of nature, said Hobbes, there is no law of nature. Locke, on the other hand, maintained that the law of nature applied in the state of nature. Reason - the law of nature - taught human beings that, as equal and independent persons, "no one ought to harm another in his life, health, liberty, or possessions." 355 It is in the self-interest of every individual to accept as a basic rule that these interests of everyone must be protected. They are inalienable natural rights which, violated, may be avenged by anyone, not only the injured party. if 356 In the state of nature, the law of nature depends for its execution on the protection by each person of his own interests. This will obviously give rise to problems. Because each person is a judge in his own case, his reason might be clouded, and even if he rightfully claims to have the kingdom May, June 1979 6 at 7 and Van Zy1 & Van der Vyver Inleiding tot die regswetenskap 163. See also Van der Vyver Die juridiese sin van die leerstuk van menseregte vol 1 165ff. 353 Locke Two treatises of government 2.1.4. 354 Id 2.11.119. 355 Id 2.2.6. 356 Id 2.2.6 & 2.2.8. been wronged, there is no guarantee that he will be strong enough to survive. 357 The interests of all involved are unsafe and insecure because three conditions necessary for their preservation are absent: an "establish’d, settled, known law"; 358 a "known and indifferent judge, with authority established law"; to 359 determine all differences according to the and "the power to back and support the sentence when right, and to give it due execution". 360 The "inalienable" rights can therefore in practice be alienated. To remedy these defects of the state of nature and to protect each person’s inalienable rights (collectively called "property" by Locks 361) and because of natural human social instincts, 362 rational human beings, either explicitly or tacitly, 363 enter into a contract with each other to form a society which - is governed by law. 364 Political or civil society is set up to remove the uncertainties of the state of nature by establishing a legal system which is to be openly, impartially and effectively administered. 365 Most important for our purposes is to note that control over those areas covered by the basic human rights are, however, not transferred to the state by those who participate in the social contract. "And this judgement they cannot part with, it being out of a man's power so to submit himself to another, as to give him a liberty to destroy him." 366 In short: the state is created to ensure that inalienable rights are indeed not alienated to those rights itself. Locke therefore saw the state as an instrument of the people, devised to serve a specific function, namely the protection of their most basic rights. This view has far-reaching consequences; the most important 357 Id 2.2.13. 358 Id 2.9.124. (Original emphasis omitted.) 359 Id 2.9.125. (Original emphasis omitted.) 360 Id 2.9.126. (Original emphasis omitted.) 361 Id 2.3.25; 2.3.51 & 2.9.123. 362 Id 1.7.77. 363 Id 2.8.110. 364 Id 2.8.95. 365 Id 2.9.127. 366 Id 2.14.168. being that the people and not the state are viewed as supreme. Even though the people enter into an original contract to set up a state (and we will return to the terms of this contract shortly) no contract is concluded with the state. Instead the state is set up in the form of a fiduciary trust, of which the people are both the trustor and the beneficiary. 367 The trustee has obligations only and no rights, and if these obligations are not properly executed the trust can be revoked by the people, who can then appoint a new trustee. Within the structure of the state, the legislature is superior to the executive, because the legislature represents the popular will of the people. However, the ultimate source of legitimacy, and consequently of political obedience, remains the consent of the governed. 368 Neither Hobbes nor Locke, consequently, maintained that government derived its powers from a contract with society, but their reasons for this were very different. A contract implies rights and duties on both’ sides. For Hobbes, the absence of such a contract implied that people do not have rights against the government and that the government has no duties. For Locke, the absence of a contract implied that people do not have duties and that the government has no rights against the people. The theory of the divine right of kings placed the ruler above the subjects; the social contract placed them on an equal level; Locke’s notion of the state as trustee placed the people above the state. To him, the state was a mere servant of the people. 369 Government finds law, to which itself is subjected - it does not create law. As pointed out earlier, there is a certain continuity between the views of Hobbes and Locke. Hobbes saw the pursuit of life by the subject as an inalienable right, while Locke extended that right to include the pursuit of not only life but also of the much wider concept of liberty. As a result of this difference, however, Locke had a perception of political resistance which was qualitatively different from that of Hobbes. To Locke, an absolute monarchy was "no form of civil government at all", because it entails the use of force without authority, as was the 367 Id 2.11.142. 368 Id 2.13.149. 369 Ebenstein Great political thinkers 396. case in the state of nature. It is in fact worse than the state of nature, because in the state of nature everyone was at least the judge in his own case, whereas in an absolute monarchy only one person, the king, has that prerogative over everybody else. 370 Locke emphatically recognised a right of revolt against a despotic ruler. In a famous passage he stated: [W]henever the legislators endeavour to take away, and destroy the property [ie the natural rights] of the people, or to reduce them to slavery under arbitrary power, they put themselves into a state of war with the people, who are thereupon absolved from any farther obedience, and are left to the common refuge, which God hath provided for all men, against force and violence. Whensoever therefore the legislative shall transgress this fundamental rule of society; and ... endeavour to grasp ... absolute power over the lives, liberties, and estates of the people; by this breach of trust they forfeit the power, the people had put in their hands, for quite contrary ends, and it devolves to the people, who have a right to resume their original liberty, and, by the establishment of a new legislative ... provide for their own safety and security, which is the end for which they are in society. 371 In such a case, violence may be used: "Force is to be opposed to ... unjust and unlawful force." 372 One reason for the existence of such a right, alluded to above, is the fact that a tyrannical government does not act as a trustee and consequently has no authority. Any government which breaks the law acts ultra vires and may for that reason be opposed: "He that hath authority to seize my person in the street, may be opposed as if he as a thief and a robber, if he breaks into my house to execute a writ." 373 Ordinary citizens also have a right of self-defence against a despot, which is a part of the law of nature. 374 "Whosoever uses force without right ... puts himself into a state of war with those, against whom he so uses it, and in that state a11 former ties are cancelled ... and every one has a right to defend himself, 370 Locke Two treatises of government 2.7.90. 371 Id 2.19.222. (Original emphasis omitted.) 372 Id 2.19.204. (Original emphasis omitted.) 373 Id 18.202. 374 Id, where Locke Quoted Barclay to this effect. and to resist the aggressor." 375 The people must decide whether or not to bring the rule of a tyrant to an end. 376 Anticipating charges that the "unsteady opinion" of the people will lead to unduly frequent rebellion, Locke argued that his approach would not invite political anarchy and obligation. 377 revolution People by any more nature do than not other easily views of engage in revolution, and revolution "happen not upon every little mismanagement in public affairs". 378 At the same time, no divine or theoretical foundation can prevent revolution when people are "made miserable" and are ill-treated. 379 strong. To The provide human people drive with towards the freedom opportunity is of simply too changing the government peacefully when they so wish is indeed "the best defence against rebellion". 380 In Locke, then, we find a major watershed in the way in which political and legal obligation was perceived. Justice was no longer regarded merely as an ideal of which the non-realisation should be lamented, while nothing could be done about it. Justice and more particularly natural rights resistance, was now intricately associated with a right of which meant that its pursuit was not only left in the hands of the state, but it was also the prerogative of the people. Natural law would no longer merely justify the existence of the state: it would also be seen as the basis of the rights of the people against the state, including, where necessary, their right to resist. While Augustine maintained that an unjust law was no law at all, and could be disobeyed passively, Locke recognised a right actively to resist an entire governmental structure. Locke’s ideas would, however, take some time to be incorporated into mainstream jurisprudence. S. ULRICH HUBER A prominent figure in the discussions about the Dutch Revolt was the Frisian jurist Ulrich Huber (1636-1694), who espoused views similar to 375 Id 2.19.232. 376 Id 2.19.240. 377 Id 2.19.223. 378 Id 2.19.225. (Original emphasis omitted.) 379 Id 2.19.224. 380 Id 2.19.226. (Original emphasis omitted) those of Hobbes. In a debate with Jacob Perizonius, Huber argued that the transfer of power by the people was absolute and indivisible and could never be revoked. The Dutch Revolt, in his view, consequently replaced the absolute rule of Philip II with the absolute rule of the aristocracy. 381 T. GERARD NOODT The Dutch humanist, Gerard Noodt (1647-1725), entered the debate concerning the real implications of the lex regia, also as far as the Netherlands was concerned, when he delivered his first rectorial address at Leiden in 1699. It was an intellectual defence of the Dutch Revolt, much along the lines of Locke’s defence of the Glorious Revolution. In this address, Noodt argued that a careful analysis of the lex regia would reveal that it never granted the ruler unqualified sovereign power. Instead, it enumerated a series of precisely defined matters that were placed under his control, but which could be revoked whenever the ruler became a tyrant. 382 Natural law also limits the power of the ruler. Rulers are not instituted by nature and can be deposed if they destroy the people. Noodt rejected Ulpian’s adage princeps legibus solutus est. According to Noodt, this maxim was contrary to reason and was in conflict with other texts of Ulpian. Noodt pointed out that the lex regia explicitly subordinated the Emperor to those laws which bound his predecessors. 383 Noodt’s address received international fame after its translation from Dutch into French (1707) and English (1708), and was one of the Important intellectual sources of the rising idea of sovereignty of the people in the Europe of the Eighteenth Century. 384 U. CHRISTIAN WOLFF Christian Wolff (1679-1754) was deeply influenced by the natural law approach of Pufendorf. He dominated during the greater part of the the German intellectual world Eighteenth Century and is today widely 381 On Huber, see id 82ff and Van den Bergh The Life and work of Gerald Noodt 193. 382 0n Noodt's contribution in this regard, see Van den Bergh The life and work of Gerard Noodt. 383 384 Id 202. Van den Bergh argued that the importance of Noodt's contribution should be ranked equal to that of Locke. Id 198. founders of modern natural law ideas. 385 regarded as one of the According to Wolff, by nature all persons are equal and all have certain innate rights. By nature, no one has the right to dominate over the actions of others. Civil society involves the subordination of the individual by a ruling will, and it can therefore only be founded on an express or tacit contract. Only in pursuit of the common welfare (procuring the means of subsistence and ensuring internal and external security) may liberty be curtailed. The ultimate source of governmental authority and of legal obligation is the consent of the citizens. 386 Wolff insisted that there was not a duty of obedience to the government when it demanded anything that contradicted the laws of nature or imposed obligations that would violate the fundamental laws of human society. He also recognised an extensive right of resistance that could be exercised whenever government encroached upon the rights expressly reserved by the constitution for the people or for certain classes of the people. The constitution is the fundamental law and Wolff maintained that the government has no right to command its subjects to act contrary to fundamental laws. 387 In spite of these liberal points of departure, Wolff "made concessions to the spirit of his times" by claiming that wherever absolutist forms of government prevail, people have voluntarily renounced their power. 388 A number of authors contradictory, have because of described his Wolff's simultaneous absolutism and the doctrine of human rights. V. approach as adherence inherently to state 389 JEAN-JACQUES ROUSSEAU The major political event, of the Eighteenth Century, which to a large extent shaped the modern world, was the French Revolution of 1789. The intellectual environment in which the Revolution could take place was 385 See Nippold's "Introduction" in Wolff The law of nations vo1 2 xi. See also Van der Vyver Die juridiese sin van die leerstuk van menseregte vo1 1 333. 386 Wolff The law of nations vol 2 xxxi. 387 See Wolff Institutiones luris naturae et gentium par 1079 and Wolff Ius naturae 8 6 1091-7. 388 389 Id xxxiii. See eg Van der Vyver Die juridiese sin van die leerstuk van menseregte vol 1 340. to a considerable degree shaped by Jean-Jacques Rousseau (1712-1778). 390 Rousseau set out his political ideas in "A discourse on the moral effects of the arts and the sciences" (1751); 391 "A discourse on the origin (1775) of 393 inequality" (1755); 392 "A discourse on political economy" and his most famous work, "The social contract" (1762). 394 The first two discourses mentioned above were primarily devoted to an attack on what Rousseau regarded as the lamentable conditions of modern civilization. Civilization had developed into a hopeless race to discover remedies for the evils it produced. Private property resulted in an unnatural inequality between the rich or powerful, and the poor who are locked into servitude. Rousseau saw modern man as being totally alienated from his own nature. Rousseau substituted the simple passions of natural life for the rationalism and materialism of the Age of Reason. He exalted freedom of the human being in nature. People dominate and exploit each other through inequality, which finds its extreme form in despotism. In "The social contract", Rousseau developed what he regarded as a more satisfactory account of how the relationship between the state and the individual should be regulated. The central issue addressed in that work, was political obligation. How can citizenship and individual freedom be reconciled: "Man is born free; and everywhere he is in chains." 395 As he association which the person and put it: "The problem is to find a form of will defend and protect with the whole common force goods of each associate, and in which each, 390 while On his philosophy in general, see Höffding A history of modern philosophy vo1 1 485ff and Vorlander Geschieden1s van de wijsbegeerte vol 3 l59ff. On Rousseau's political philosophy, see Masters The political philosophy of Rousseau; Ebenstein Great political thinkers 438ff; Strauss & Cropsey History of political philosophy 532ff and Cole's introduction in Rousseau The social contract and discourses viiff. On his legal philosophy, see Van der Vyver Die juridiese sin van die leerstuk van reenseregte 251 and Van Eikema Hommes Major trends in the history of legal philosophy 157ff. His approach to legal and political obligation is discussed in Macfarlane Modern political theory 106. 391 Reprinted in Rousseau The social contract and discourses 125ff. 392 Id 155ff. 393 Id 247ff. 394 Id 1ff. 395 Rousseau "The social contract" 1.1. uniting himself with all, may still obey himself alone, and remain as free as before." 396 Rousseau, therefore, rejected the notion of rule by the strongest. Under such a system he held that "[a]s soon as it is possible to disobey with impunity, disobedience is legitimate; and, the strongest being always in the right, the only thing that matters is to act so as to become the strongest." 397 Consequently, "(l]et us then admit that force does not create right, and that we are obliged to obey only legitimate powers." 398 The only solution against government by force is the use of force: A popular insurrection that ends in the death or deposition of a sultan is as lawful an act as those by which he disposed, the day before, of the lives and fortunes of his subjects. As he was maintained by force alone, it is force alone that overthrows him. Thus everything takes place according to the natural order. 399 How, then, would a society be composed in which the maximum individual freedom is preserved? That would be the case if people are only bound by laws to which they themselves have consented. We must therefore ask what sort of arrangement people in the state of nature would accept. The reason why humans cannot live in the state of nature is that, while the person who pursues his own self-interest in a state of nature is basically good, he eventually finds his self-interest to be in conflict with that of others to the extent that he cannot preserve himself against their combined efforts. He then enters into a social contract to obtain security while maintaining liberty. 400 This, however, can occur only if the individual surrenders himself totally to the group. The terms of Rousseau's social contract involve "the total alienation of each associate, together with all his rights, to the whole 396 Id 1.6. 397 Id 1.3. 398 Ibid. 399 community". 401 This means that each individual places See Rousseau "A discourse on the origin of inequality", reprinted in Rousseau The social contract and discourses 155 at 236. 400 Id 1.6. 401 Ibid. himself under "the supreme direction of the general will". 402 People thus do not surrender themselves to the state but to all other citizens. Rousseau's commitment to liberty led him to demand direct popular rule in which "each man, in giving himself to all, gives himself to nobody ... he gains an equivalent for everything he loses, and an increase of force for the preservation of what he has." 403 True freedom is not to be found in the state of nature, because under it one is enslaved by uncontrolled appetites. In contract, in the civil state, one can acquire moral liberty, which makes one master of oneself, because one then submits to a law which one prescribes to oneself. Self-imposed law is legitimate law. Rousseau rejected representative democracy, and held that people could be bound only to laws in the formation of which they had participated directly. Central to Rousseau's thinking, is the concept of the "general will", which aims at the general good and comes from all and applies to all. It is more than the sum of the wills of the individuals concerned - it is that which, all things considered, best serves the common interest. However, once a state has been established, one cannot obey the law selectively. "The citizen gives his consent to all the laws, including those which are passed in spite of his opposition, and even those which punish him when he dares to break any one of them." 404 According to Rousseau "whoever refuses to obey the general win shall be compelled to do so by the whole body. This means nothing less than that he will be forced to be free:" 405 Whereas Kant would demand total obedience to the moral law, Rousseau demanded total obedience to the "general will". The demands of the general will can be far-reaching. At the end of the final version of "The social contract", Rousseau inserted a section on "civil religion". 406 He believed that the state should banish as "antisocial" anyone who does not believe in a number of "social sentiments without which a man cannot be a good citizen or a faithful subject," such as 402 Ibid. (Original emphasis omitted.) 403 Id 1.6. 404 Id 4.2. 405 Id. 1.7. 406 Id 4.8. [t]he existence of a mighty, intelligent and beneficent divinity, possessed of foresight and providence, the life to come, the happiness of the just, the punishment of the wicked, the sanctity of the social contract and the laws: These are its positive dogmas. Its negative dogmas I confine in one, intolerance, which is a part of the cults we have rejected. 407 Rousseau rejected the instrumentalist view of the state as propounded by Hobbes and Locke, and revived the organic theory of the state of Plato and Aristotle. Before Rousseau, political philosophers concentrated either on the aim of good government (Plato and Aristotle) or self - government (Locke). Rousseau, through the concept of the "general will", attempted to synthesise good government. The government and self- 408 concept of the "general will" has been subjected to severe criticism. Because of the total surrender of the individual to the group - of individualism to collectivism Rousseau has been held responsible for dictatorships and tyrannies, ranging from the excesses of the Jacobines to the Bolshevist doctrines of this Century. 409 It seems fair to say that, according to Rousseau, fundamental rights could not be surrendered to the state, but it could be surrendered to the group. His ideas can consequently be used to justify only a limited form of anti-exploitation civil disobedience - only civil disobedience by the majority against a minority government (as in the Defiance Campaign in South Africa) but not by a minority against a majority (as in the Civil Rights Movement in the United States) would be permissible. W. WILLIAM BLACKSTONE The liberal ideas of Locke were embraced and popularised by William Blackstone (1723-1780), 410 in his Commentaries on the laws of England (1765-1770). Although his natural law approach was vigorously attacked by Bentham in his Fragment on government, and was described by others as shallow, it proved to be highly influential in England, the United 407 Ibid. 408 Ebenstein Great political thinkers 448. 409 See Duguit Sovereignty and liberty 135. 410 For a discussion of his political philosophy, see the introduction of G Jones in Blackstone The sovereignty of the law ix and Van der Vyver Die juridiese sin van die leerstuk van menseregte vol 1 342ff. States and on the European continent. In respect of the right of resistance, however, Blackstone's approach is far from consistent. Proceeding from a natural law position, Blackstone proclaimed the rights of human beings in ringing terms. He maintained that individuals "merely as individuals or single persons" had absolute rights, which "would belong to their persons merely in a state of nature, and which every man is entitled to enjoy, whether out of society or in it." 411 He proceeded: "This natural liberty consists properly in acting as one thinks fit, without any restraint or control, unless by the law of nature; being a right inherent in us by birth." 412 In accordance with his view that the law of nature "is of course superior in obligation to any other", Blackstone endorsed a right of political resistance against a corrupt ruler. 413 One has a right to vindicate one's rights when they are "violated or attacked". He recognised "the natural right of resistance and self-preservation, when the sanctions of society and laws are found insufficient to restrain the violence of oppression". 414 In order to be able to meet such eventualities, English subjects have "the right of having and using arms for self-preservation and defence". 415 When James II "invaded the fundamental constitution of the realm", natural law prevailed over positive law and "the convention declared an abdication, whereby the throne was crown." At rendered vacant, which induced a new settlement of the 416 the position same time, in respect however, of Blackstone political also obligation defended on the an absolutist basis of the hypothetical social contract. He maintained that government must be "a supreme, irresistible, absolute, uncontrolled authority, in which the jura summi imperil, or the rights of sovereignty, reside[s]". 417 Moreover, "society cannot be maintained ... without obedience to some foreign power: and obedience is an empty name, if every individual has 411 Blackstone Commentaries on the laws of England 1.1. 412 Ibid. 413 Id intro s 1. 414 Id 1.1. 415 Ibid. 416 Id 1.7. 417 Id intro s 2. a right to decide how far he himself shall obey." 418 The above contradictions have led commentators to observe that Blackstone's ideas about natural law could not be reconciled with his absolutist tendencies. 419 X. IMMANUEL KANT Immanuel Kant (1724-1804) is widely considered to be a proponent of the natural law approach, and is regarded as one of the fathers of liberalism and the notion of the Rechtsstaat. He was seen by many, including no one less than Karl Marx, as the philosophical champion of the American and French Revolutions. 420 He asserted the inviolability of the individual and placed the issue of human freedom squarely on the agenda of the modern world. Most famous in this regard are the following formulations of Kant's categorical imperative: "Handle nur nach derjenigen Maxime, durch die du zugleich wollen kannst, dass sie ein allgemeines Gesetz werde" 421 and "Handle so, dass du die Menschheit, sowohl in deiner Person, als in der Person eines jeden Andern, jederzeit zugleich als Zweck, niemals bloss als Mittel brauchst." 422 To a large extent Kantian ethics, and more specifically its requirement of non-exploitation of the individual, constitutes the philosophical basis of the modern recognition of fundamental human rights. At the same time, however, Kant denied the existence of a right to resist any sovereign, irrespective of how just or unjust its commands are. 423 Can these two propositions be reconciled, and if so, how? A brief general survey would political of be some aspects required obligation. Kant for of Kant's an understanding distinguished philosophical the of world notions in views on his of theoretical reason - the Sein of nature - and the world of practical reason - the Sollen of freedom. At the height of the Enlightenment, the question was 418 Id 1.7. 419 See G Jones in Blackstone The sovereignty of the law xxxviii. 420 See Reiss Journal of the History of Ideas 1956 179 at 179. 421 Kant "Grundlegung zur Metaphysik der Sitten", reprinted in Sämmitliche Werke vol 5 269. 422 Id 227. 423 See Williams Kant's political philosophy 198ff. how can could these two worlds co-exist without destroying each other? How the determinism of natural science be reconciled with the autonomy required by morality? Turning first to nature, Kant brought about, what he called, a "Copernican revolution", by insisting that the laws of nature do not reside in the reality outside us, but that they are founded in the synthesis of sensual experience and our categories of understanding. Nature does not prescribe its laws to human understanding - instead, understanding is nature's law-giver. 424 At the same time, however, the categories of understanding can only apply to the reality as revealed by the senses. The mathematical method could not be used to penetrate the realm of unconditioned. This metaphysics, the world of the Dina an sich or the 425 approach, on the one hand, safeguarded the foundations of classical natural science against the scepticism of empirists such as David Hume. On the other hand, Kant also rescued the human soul from the encroaching determinism of the natural sciences. Kant regarded autonomy and freedom, and not scientific achievement, as the essence of human existence. 426 What, then, does truly autonomous, moral action entail? Only by being motivated entirely by respect for the moral law itself can one act morally, not by acting for the sake of empirical motives (to achieve or to avoid pleasure, consequently pain, categorical etc). (or The nature deontological) of and the not moral law is hypothetical (consequentialist or conditioned). True freedom lies in obedience to the moral law. The contents of moral legislation is given to us as a fact of pure reason, of which we have an a priori awareness. It is constituted of rules of conduct or maxims which may be elevated to the status of universally valid legislation for all of mankind. Logic demands the absence of contradiction. The principle that one should never make a false promise can be universalised without contradiction; however, the principle that in emergencies one can make 424 See Kant Critique of pure reason 12. 425 Id 13ff. 426 Id 16. promises without intending to keep them cannot be universalised, because in such a case all faith in promises win be destroyed. "Thus my maxim would necessarily universal law." 427 destroy itself as soon as it was made a Consequently, the first principle is a rule of the universal moral law, the second not. Reason indicates to people that only by forming a civil society can we escape the insecurity of the state of nature, can justice be established in human relationships and can individuals enjoy freedom. Individual judgment has to be suspended and transformed to the state, which must then on our behalf make laws. In this regard, Kant used the fictional notion of the social contract to explain the existence - and necessity - of the state. Because reason dictates the necessity of the state, and the state cannot survive if it is not obeyed, the moral law demands obedience to the laws of the state, whatever the contents of these laws might be. 428 It would, of course, be best if the law-giver modelled the positive law on the rational or moral law. However, as Kant readily acknowledged, in practice that does not always happen. However, in respect of positive law, the law of reason has a regulative and not a constitutive function. Even if positive law conflicts with rational law, it remains law and must be obeyed. Kant restated Romans 13 as follows: "It is a duty to obey the law of the existing legislative power, be its origin what it may." 429 The essence of Kant's argument against a right of resistance turns on a point of logic. Sovereignty is indivisible. The sovereign is he who judges and coerces, and if the sovereign is judged or coerced by the citizen, it is no longer the sovereign. The law cannot outlaw itself, and can consequently not allow resistance. 430 Just as it would undermine the worth of a promise if it can be made with no intention to keep it in an emergency, so too would it undermine the sovereignty of the state if one were to be allowed to disobey the state when its laws are 427 428 Id 64. See also philosophy 170. 429 430 Van Eikema Hommes Major trends in the history of legal See Kant The philosophy of law 175. For a discussion of this argument as advanced in respect of, what was called, legality-based civil disobedience, see supra chap two I A. considered repressive. Kant, in fact, believed that tyranny cannot last, but while waiting for it to come to an end, one shows greater respect for human dignity by obeying than by resisting, because the latter always brings about greater suffering. 431 Hence it follows that the supreme power in the state has only rights, and no (compulsory) duties towards the subject. Further, if the ruler or regent, as the organ of the supreme power, proceeds in violation of the laws, as in imposing taxes, recruiting soldiers, and so on, contrary to the law of equality in the distribution of the political burdens, the subject may oppose complaints and objections (gravamina) to this injustice, but not active resistance. There cannot even be an article contained in the political constitution that would make it possible for a power in the state, in case of the transgression of the constitutional taws by the supreme authority, to resist or even to restrict it in so doing. For, whoever would restrict the supreme power of the state must have more, or at least equal power as compared with the power that is so restricted; and if competent to command the subjects to resist, such a one would also have to be able to protect them, and if he is to be considered capable of judging what is right in every case, he may also publicly order resistance. But such a one, and not the actual authority, would then be the supreme power; which is contradictory. 432 At the same time, however, it should be noted that, according to Kant, if the authorities command something which is directly in opposition to the moral law, it should not be obeyed. 433 Disobedience in order to avoid acting unjustly should not be regarded as illegitimate, because it is not regarded as a manifestation of resistance. There cannot be a categorical imperative which compels one to break another categorical imperative. 434 In other words, integrity-based, defensive disobedience is acceptable, but not any form of result-oriented resistance. Kant's approach to the right to resist revealed him to be even further removed from the natural lawyers than most positivists, who at least recognised a moral right of resistance, although they denied the existence of such a legal right. Kant denied the existence of both a legal and a moral right, and in this sense he can be regarded as an 431 See Reiss Journal of the History of Ideas 1956 179 at 190 432 Kant The philosophy of law 175. (Original emphasis.) 433 See Schwartz Ethics 1963 126 at 130. 434 See Nicholson Ethics 1976 214 at 218. absolutist. However, despite Kant's conservative views in respect of resistance, his insistence on the non-exploitation of the individual would inspire much of the modern human rights ethos, and consequently also Y. much of the modern recognition of the right of resistance, JEREMY BENTHAM In spite of all the problems nowadays associated with utilitarianism, 435 there can be no doubt that it, through its stress on the importance of the common good as opposed to the good of a small elite at the top of a hierarchy, and through its emphasis on the value of real facts as opposed to metaphysical speculations, had a liberating influence on Western civilization. The Londoner, Jeremy Bentham (1748-1832 ), 436 is the most prominent figure in the utilitarian tradition. Bentham's philosophy developed naturally from the opening lines of An introduction to the principles of morals and legislation (first printed in 1780 and published in 1789): "Nature has placed mankind under the governance of two sovereign masters, pain and pleasure." 437 Like other utilitarians, Bentham saw political obligation in terms of this basic philosophical premise. Whether such an obligation exists, has to be established in terms of the "principle of utility", which Bentham regarded as the fundamental directive of moral and political science. "By the principle of utility is meant that principle which approves or disapproves of every action whatsoever, according to the tendency which it appears to have to augment or diminish the happiness of the party whose interest is in question." 438 Bentham popularised Hutchinson's phrase, "the greatest happiness for the greatest number", and took that as the ultimate measure of worth, of right and of wrong. The guiding star for the legislature in framing legislation should be the question how effective that legislation would 435 See infra chap five I EE 2. 436 For a general discussion of Bentham's political philosophy, see Ebenstein Great political thinkers 505ff and Strauss & Cropsey History of political philosophy 679ff. On Bentham's theory of legal obligation, see Hart Essays on Bentham 127ff. 437 Bentham An introduction to the principles of morals and legislation 1.1. (Original emphasis omitted.) 438 Id 1.2. be in promoting happiness, and the question as to what extent that legislation should be obeyed or disobeyed should be answered on the same basis. In A fragment on government (1776), Bentham attacked the hypothetical contract theory explanation for as advanced political by Blackstone obligation. 439 To as a Bentham, philosophical the difference between a political society and a natural society lay in psychology, not in a fictitious social contract. In the one society, according to Bentham, exists a "habit of obedience", in the other not. 440 Whether such a habit should be followed in any particular case, does not depend on fictitious ideas like natural law or concepts declared that the "season of fiction is now over". of 441 justice. He Subjects should obey, he argued, "so long as the probable mischiefs of obedience are less than the probable mischiefs of resistance" 442 and it is the duty of subjects to obey "just as long as it is in their interest, and no longer". 443 Bentham described immoral action as a miscalculation of self-interest. However, he saw self-interest in a very broad sense which could also incorporate concerns for the interests of others. 444 It can perhaps be said that to him morality was simply long-term rationality, taking into account all the interests of the person concerned - including her feelings for other people. Although Bentham recognised the value of a "habit of obedience", he did not exclude the possibility or acceptability of any form of resistance if that were to be in a person's best interest. Z. GEORG W F HEGEL Reference was made earlier to the German philosopher, Georg Wilhelm Frederich Hegel (1770-1831). 445 His dialectical approach is well known. 439 Bentham A fragment on government 1.1 & 2. 440 Id 1.12-14. 441 Id 1.37. (Original emphasis omitted.) 442 Id 1.43. (Original emphasis omitted.) 443 Ibid. (Original emphasis omitted.) 444 See Bentham "Deontology", reprinted in Bentham The collected works of Jeremy Bentham 121. 445 See, for a general discussion, Strauss & Cropsey History of political According to him, all progress is the result of opposition and contradiction of ideas. Every thesis posits its own antithesis, without its own nature. There then occurs an aufheben of entirely abandoning both - a "lifting constitutes a new up" - and a more complete synthesis, which thesis, is created. Tension and conflict therefore underlie the development of human history. 446 Given the above, Hegel's view that the contradiction of law - including its violation naturally. 447 - is In a necessary spite of vehicle his of social conservative progress views on the follows German constitutional dispensation, Hegel was consequently a philosopher of revolution. 448 To Hegel the French Revolution of the inner contradiction of destructive effects, the Revolution the was the final culmination Enlightenment. Despite its was necessary to make room for the replacement of the and en regime by new structures. 449 AA. ANARCHISM Anarchy, or the absence of government, according to most political philosophies, is the long-term ideal and the short-term enemy of human society. Anarchy political reasons is theorists for the the who ideal in the contemplated existence of the opinion the of eventual state - a range of disappearance of and wide therefore the disappearance f the state itself - as the ultimate goal. Both Adam Smith and Karl Marx envisaged this eventuality. On a different level, Augustine, Luther and Calvin regarded the state as a consequence of sin and as a temporary institution. Eventually, in the life hereafter, the state will become redundant. This approach can be described as Utopian or long-term anarchism. Its prevalence reveals a widespread sense of discomfort with coercion, associated with the state and political power. Democracy will later in this study be defined, in idealistic philosophy 686ff. 446 Hegel Philosophy of right paras 341-360. 447 For a fuller discussion, see H Klenner "On the right to revolution: A German dilemma" in MacCormick & Bankowski Enlightenment, rights and revolution 287 at 294. 448 449 Ibid. See Hegel Political writings 40ff. See also Taylor Hegel 418. On the ambivalence which Hegel felt because of the reign of terror which followed the Revolution, see Prior Revolution and philosophy 4ff and 115ff. terms, as the absence of repression. At the same time, political theory for the greater part has as its prime objective, justification of the state's function of regulating human affairs, by force if necessary, insofar as utopia remains a figment of the imagination. In this time-frame anarchy is the worst possible enemy: it represents failure and heralds doom. To Hobbes and Locke, it was the "state of nature" where no one can enjoy security and from which the social contract was designed to rescue human kind. To the fathers of Christianity, disobedience to political rulers was often perceived as dangerous and a disposition that would lead to chaos. Many of the long-term anarchists were consequently very authoritarian in their short-term approach. However, there is a group of political commentators who sought the disappearance of the state, not only in the distant future but immediately. To them, the state as an institution has no legitimacy. These theorists, the anarchists, did not, like other political theorists, reject certain manifestations of governmental authority and propose alternatives - they rejected did not propose conditions of sovereigns could a political legitimate be political authority as such. They theory which resistance resisted: they by carefully out the what kind of general right of describing advocated a sets resistance against the state as an institution. Anarchism in many respects represents extremes in political thinking. It is at the same time one of the oldest, the most unsuccessful, and the most persistent political doctrines. Its roots can be traced to the Chinese Taoists, Christianity. Although the Cynics of Greece, the Stoics and to early term, some 450 anarchism is a wide features common to anarchistic (and often misunderstood) thought can be identified: 451 450 On the early history of anarchism, see Bose A history of anarchism. A very useful discussion of the most important proponents of anarchy is contained in Joll The anarchists. For a general overview, see also Carter The political theory of anarchism and Calvert Revolution 85. Extracts from the work of the most important writers in this tradition are contained in Hoffman Anarchism. Apter & Joll Anarchism today studies its contemporary application from a number of perspectives. 451 See D T Wieck "Essentials of anarchism", reprinted in Hoffman Anarchism 86 and Carter The political theory of anarchism 13ff - The state is seen as inherently an instrument of exploitation. It legitimises oppression. Democratic government simply entails the oppression of the minority by the majority. - People do not need the state, because they are basically good when not corrupted by the state. Voluntary institutions are best suited to express humankind’s natural social instincts. - Anarchists, mostly on the basis conscience, do not recognise a qua law. - of an inalienable right to moral obligation to obey the law 452 Social reforms must be initiated from below by the people and not from above by the state. The state cannot be expected to orchestrate its own demise. Some of the most influential proponents of anarchism will next be considered. (1) William Godwin Although he never used the term "anarchy", the first systematic 453 In his most anarchist was the Englishman, William Godwin (1756-1836). important work, An enquiry concerning political justice (1793), Godwin rejected as prejudicial to human progress any institution which gives one person power over another. To Godwin there were two evils: government and property. The objective of both institutions is exploitation. Godwin rejected the idea of an anarchistic revolution, and believed that the idea of justice will induce individuals to eliminate the state through a social contract. Good will eventually triumph through its own inherent power. Godwin had a boundless faith m the ability eventually to reach perfection. of human beings to improve and 454 Government, by taking decisions on behalf of individuals and forcing them to obey, deprives these individuals from finding truth and virtue for themselves. Hence, their actions become worthless. Only in the absence of external coercion can individual actions mean anything. 455 452 See in this regard Richards Georgia Law Review 1984 vol 18 771 at 771. 453 See Joll The anarchists 31ff and Bose A history of anarchism 78ff. 454 See Godwin An enquiry concerning political justice vo1 1 6ff. 455 Id vo1 2 77. (2) In Pierre-Joseph Proudhon contrast to the radical individualistic anarchism advanced someone like Max Stirner, Pierre-Joseph Proudhon (1809-1865) 456 by proposed mutualist anarchism, and opened the way for anarchism to become a mass movement. To the question robbery", 457 "what is property?", Proudhon answered "[i]t is indicating his opposition to the abuse of property through its exclusive allocation to some. Proudhon, nevertheless, based his economic approach on individual possession of the means of production by peasants and small craftsmen united in a framework of credit arrangements, who would exchange goods on the basis of labour notes. (3) Michael Bakunin The exiled Russian, collectivism Michael although he Bakunin rejected (1814-1876), 458 communism. 459 Bakunin propagated and his followers advocated public ownership of all the means of production, and regarded the workers as the basic unit of society. He rejected the role Marx envisaged for the authoritarian state. In God and the state, Bakunin described religion as the weapon whereby the state enslaves and annihilates humanity, which must be smashed to make self-determination possible. 460 Bakunin introduced into anarchist movement the idea that society could rid itself of the through the use of violence only - an the state element which through the years would greatly stigmatise anarchism. (4) Peter Kropotkin Anarchistic 1870's by Russian, collectivism anarchistic Prince Peter was largely communism, Alexander as replaced in introduced Kropotkin Europe by during another (1842-1921). 461 the exiled Kropotkin, however, also rejected authoritarian communism, and envisaged a new 456 See Jo11 The anarchists 61ff and Bose A history of anarchism 115ff. 457 Proudhon What is property 37. 458 See Joll The anarchists 84 and Bose A history of anarchism 179ff. 459 See his essay "Statism and anarchy", reprinted in Bakunin Bakunin on anarchy 325. 460 Bakunin stated: "[I]f God really existed, it would be necessary to abolish him." Bakunin God and the state 28. 461 See Joll The anarchists 125ff and Bose A history of anarchism 257ff. society comprised of independent free village communities. Anarchistic communism differed from collectivism and mutualism on a fundamental point. According remunerated to the according to latter the approaches, hours he the worked. worker had Anarchist to be communists introduced the influential slogan "From each according to his means, to each according to his needs." They envisaged open warehouses to which everyone should contribute what they could, and from which anyone could take what they needed. 462 (5) Leo Tolstóy Whereas most anarchists rejected religion as an impediment emancipation of mankind. Count Leo To1st6y (1828-1910) 463 to the of Russia, drawing on the early tradition of the Christian church, maintained that the gospel of Christ demanded the destruction of the state. Tolstoy rejected any form of patriotism as "an unnatural, irrational, and harmful feeling, the cause of a great part of the ills from which mankind is suffering". 464 He also rejected communism and the use of violence as a political tool. The influence of this referred to earlier. brand of pacifist anarchism on Gandhi was 465 In essence, anarchism can consequently be described as a theory of radical human freedom based on a highly idealistic view of human nature. It does, however, serve the important goal of highlighting the coercive nature of the state as an institution, and it keeps the ideal of full human autonomy and a non-repressive society alive. BB. MARXISM Much of the political debate and developments of the Twentieth Century centred upon communism, which to a greater or lesser extent was regarded as a revolutionary ideology. Without going into the general nature of the Marxist thought as initially developed by Karl Marx (1818-1883) and Friedrich Engels (1820-1895), some fundamental aspects 462 Kropotkin's ideal society is set out in his books, Fields, factories and workshops and The conquest of bread. 463 See Joll The anarchists 152ff and Hoffman Anarchism 70ff. 464 See L Tolstóy "Patriotism and government", reprinted in part in Hoffman Anarchism 70 at 70. 465 See supra chap three III B (2)(a). of that ideology, which are obligation, should be noted. relevant to the issue of political 466 Marx proceeded from the Hegelian premise of the dialectical development of society. However, whereas Hegel maintained that ideas or the "absolute spirit" were the driving force in history, Marx regarded the "productive forces", the material means of existence, as "the real foundation, on which rises a legal and political superstructure and to which correspond definite forms of social consciousness". He went on to explain that "the mode of production of material life conditions the social, political and intellectual life process in general. It is not the consciousness of men that determines their being, but, on contrary, their social being that determines their consciousness." the 467 Human history is the history of class conflict, and in this process law is used by the bourgeoisie to repress the workers and to protect its own privileges. 468 changing the The key material to social conditions change, of consequently, living. However, lies in privilege entrenches and reproduces itself, to the detriment of those who have nothing, and ultimately the latter group has nothing to lose "but their chains". Consequently, Marx stated that the communists "openly declare that their ends can be attained only by the forcible overthrow of all existing social conditions. communistic revolution." locomotives of history." 469 Let the ruling classes tremble at a To Marx, therefore, "[r]evo1utions are the 470 466 For an introduction to Marxist political thinking, see Ebenstein Great political thinkers 689ff and Strauss & Cropsey History of political philosophy 755ff. For a discussion of the Marxist view of political resistance, see Macfarlane Political disobedience 30ff and R C Tucker "The Marxian revolutionary idea" in Friedrich Revolution 217. 467 Marx "Preface to A contribution to the critique of political economy" in Marx & Engels Selected works vol 1 327 at 329. 468 For extracts from the work of Marx and Engels on the function of law, see Cain & Hunt Marx and Engels on law 165ff. repressive 469 See Marx & Engels "Manifesto of the communist party", reprinted in Marx & Engels Selected works vo1 1 21 at 61. See also, in the same work, "The eighteenth brumal re of Louis Bonaparte" at 221 and "The civil war in France" at 429, where the revolutionary nature of communism is discussed. See also Esterhuyse Karl Marx 47ff, 62ff. For Lenin's views on the same topic, see Ebenstein Great political thinkers 749. 470 Marx "The class struggles in France 1848-1850" in Marx & Engels Selected works vo1 1 109 at 198. For a discussion of the "theory of At the same time, it should be noted that, to Marx, it was not "morality" or even "justice" which made a bloody revolution desirable; it was the iron laws of history which made it inevitable. 471 Although Marxists share the ultimate ideal of Gandhi - a stateless Utopia - their materialistic and consequently coercive approach placed them in direct opposition to the essentially moralistic approach of those who believe that society can be changed through persuason. 472 Whereas Gandhi argued - from morals to matter, the Marxists argued from matter to morals. Consequently, the negative assessment of acts of civil disobedience as a tool of liberation by Marxist writers should come as no surprise. 473 In essence Marxism presents a radical defence of the right to resist, on the basis of exploitation in the form of a denial of economic, social and welfare rights. CC. THE AGE OF REVOLUTIONS During the last four centuries, revolutions have had a considerable and lasting influence on the course of world history and on political thought. The increased incidence of major revolutions was the result, most notably, of the liberal insistence on the inalienability of basic human rights, on the one hand, and the spread of Marxist ideas, on the other. The earlier notion that all authority was mandated from above was clearly crumbling. 474 Particularly important in the history of the Roman Dutch legal system Inevitability" of social revolution, see Calvert Revolution 78ff. Macfarlane Political studies 1968 335 at 346ff described the feasibility of resistance activities aimed against Stalinist Russia and Maoist China. 471 For a discussion of the views of Marcuse in this regard, see Paust Emory Law Journal 1983 545 at 577. 472 Speaking at a public meeting in Amsterdam in 1872, Marx did, however, say: "We know that we must take into consideration the institutions, the habits and customs of different regions, and we do not deny that there are countries like America, England, and - if I knew your Institutions better I would perhaps add Holland - where the workers can attain their objectives by peaceful means. But such is not the case in all other countries." Quoted in Ebenstein Great political thinkers 699. 473 See eg Simons Class and colour in South Africa 161, who described the Gandhian campaigns in South Africa as "valuable as methods of political education, [but] ineffective techniques of liberation". 474 See Calvert Revolution 67ff. was the Dutch Revolt. In 1581, during the Eighty Years War (1568-1648), the Netherlands formally renounced their allegiance to Philip II of Spain by means of the Act of Ajuration or the Placcaet van Verlatinge, on the basis that, ultimately, political power was granted - and could be revoked - by the people (or at least the estates). 475 The Placcaet provided as follows: A prince is constituted by God to be ruler of a people, to defend them from oppression and violence, as the shepherd his sheep; and whereas God did not create the people slaves to their prince, to obey his commands, whether right or wrong, but rather the prince for the sake of the subjects, to love and support them as a father his children, or a shepherd his flock ... and when he does not behave thus but ... oppresses them, seeking opportunities to infringe their ancient customs, exacting from them slavish compliance, then he is no longer a prince but a tyrant, and they may not only disallow his authority, but legally proceed to the choice of another prince for their defence. 476 Much of the political debate in the Netherlands during its golden age the Seventeenth Century - centered upon justification of this Revolt, which, as we saw earlier, highlighted the question concerning the exact implications of the lex regia. 477 The theory of sovereignty was developed to a high level by writers such as De la Count, Spinoza and Van der Muelen. 478 In global terms the American and French Revolutions deeply affected the way in which political obligation was seen. After the English civil wars of the 1640’s, the right to resist was cautiously canvassed by jurists like Grotius. It was John Locke’s formulation of the right to resist, however, which came to serve as the principal justification for the American Revolution of 1776; that is, as a defence of fundamental human rights against tyranny and oppression. The American Declaration of Independence 475 stated: "Whenever any form of government becomes See Van Zy1 Geskiedenis van die Ronieins-Hollandse reg 296. 476 The above is a somewhat shortened translation of the first page of the Placcaet. There is a reprint of the original in Romein et a1 De Tachtigjarige Oorlog 65. 477 This discussion was revived in the Fourteenth Century when a tablet was discovered in Rome, purportedly containing a fragment of the 1ex de imperio given to the Emperor Vespasian at his inauguration. See Van den Bergh The life and work of Gerard Noodt 194. 478 See Kossmann Po1itieke theorie in net Zeventiende-eeuwse Nederland 36, 50, 69. destructive of [the protection of fundamental rights], it is the right of the people government." to alter or to abolish it, and to institute new 479 This commitment to freedom is deeply embedded in the American psyche. In his inaugural address in 1861, President Abraham Lincoln said: This country, with its institutions, belongs to the people who inhabit it. Whenever they shall grow weary of the existing government, they can exercise their constitutional right of amending, or their revolutionary right to dismember or overthrow it. 480 The French Revolution of 1789 permanently changed human history, and was widely democracy. regarded 481 as the unequivocal announcement of he age of Even if it remains controversial, the French Revolution gave the concept of revolution in pursuit of basic freedoms a glory and credibility which it retained to a large extent up to this day. 482 In 1791, Thomas Paine, in his Rights of man, announced a new age in which revolutions would for the first time challenge the very foundations of society. In 1917, the Bolshevik Revolution put the Communist Party in power in what became known as the Soviet Union. Many East-European countries followed suit, and in the-middle of the century, in the early 1990’s, nearly a third of the world population was under Marxist rule. Revolutions also served to undo much of the influence of communism in Eastern Europe. An act of resistance that failed but which nevertheless gripped the imagination of the world, was that of the German theologian, Dietrich Bonhoeffer. He opposed the Nazi regime and was involved in an assassination attempt on the life of Hitler. Bonhoeffer was arrested and executed just before the end of the war. This and other attempts to take the life of Hitler made a lasting impression on the world’s understanding of the right to resist. The only regret most people felt in respect of these attempts was that they had failed. 483 479 Quoted from Hammond "We hold these truths ..." 43. 480 Id 206. 481 See Tilly et a1 The rebellious cent