PROFESSIONAL ISSUES The Ethical Practitioner-Client Relationship Sebastian “Seb” Striefel, PhD Department of Psychology at Utah State University, Logan, UT Keywords: ethics, practitioner-client relations Spring 2005 ⎪ Biofeedback The practitioner-client relationship is an extremely important, influential, and often critical component of successful treatment. Care should be taken to not take this relationship for granted; rather, practitioners should attend to the formation of this relationship with each client. Client autonomy and the practitioner-client relationship are both enhanced by obtaining valid informed consent in a sensitive and truthful manner. A number of other factors such as listening, extending common courtesies, getting client feedback, and monitoring and addressing subtle changes in affect and behavior can also be helpful in building a working relationship. A conscious intent to do one’s best in helping a client can also be useful. Paternalism is seldom, if ever, an acceptable alternative to informed consent. The focus should remain on doing what is in the best interests of the client and that includes due consideration of client input. 8 Introduction Practitioners should not take the practitioner-client relationship for granted. Practitioners should carefully attend to establishing a good working relationship with each client and should consider referring elsewhere those clients with whom they cannot establish a good relationship. Sometimes a discussion of the concern about a relationship that is not working can help improve the relationship. A good practitionerclient relationship (therapeutic alliance) is needed: a) to find the appropriate balance between building the relationship and building skills, b) to get a client to come to and stay in treatment, and c) to motivate the client to participate and learn new skills. Building the relationship can involve a wide variety of skills and approaches. A good place to start is by making a conscious intent to do one’s best to help the client and to do what is in the best interests of the client. Some other useful skills and approaches for improving the practitioner-client relationship include: listening, extending common courtesies, being empathic and caring, getting informed consent, establishing a working partnership, helping the client achieve some early success, using mutually agreed upon homework, providing a rationale for what you do as you do it, eliciting client feedback regularly, varying your intervention style as needed, helping the client solve problems, alleviating distress, and monitoring affective and behavior changes during sessions. What other approaches do you use or could you use to improve the practitioner-client relationship? The Contract The professional-client relationship is a contract, verbal or written, and is basically a voluntary agreement between two or more parties because both expect to achieve some benefit. For the client the benefit is receiving a service to help with a problem, illness, or disease. For the practitioner it is receiving an income for the service provided so he or she can make a living. It is from this contract that the ethical and legal rights of the client and the concomitant obligations of the practitioner arise. Bayles (1988) argues that the professional-client relationship is a fiduciary (based on trust) one in which the client must trust the practitioner, but also one in which the client retains significant responsibility and authority (autonomy) for decisions about what happens to him or her. There are many ethical and legal obligations acquired by the practitioner when entering into this special type of relationship. They include, but are not limited to: doing no harm (beneficence), keeping promises (fidelity), being honest, making reparations for any past injustices or client perceived injustices (Bayles, 1988), maintaining client confidentiality, working for and in the client’s best interests, and encouraging client autonomy, e.g., by obtaining meaningful informed consent. These legal and ethical obligations are acquired by practitioners because each obligation is generated by a concomitant client right, e.g., the client has a right to con- Striefel fidentiality and thus a practitioner has an obligation to protect and promote that right. In practice, many consider the practitioner to be in a one up position because of her or his expertise, the implied status of her or his position and education, the client’s hesitation or inability to confront such an authority figure, and the practitioner’s freedom to reject entering the relationship, whereas the client may be too desperate for service to reject entering the relationship even if he or she does not like the particular practitioner. Biofeedback ⎪ Spring 2005 Friendships Versus Practitioner-Client Relationships Some have argued that a treatment relationship is nothing more than a paid friendship (Bayles, 1988). Yet, nothing could be further from the truth if the relationship is an ethical one. Friendships have very different rules than do professional relationships. For example, in a friendship both parties often disclose personal information, but in a professional relationship the focus is on helping the client; thus, personal information is seldom revealed by the practitioner. If personal information is revealed, it occurs because it is deemed to be a way of helping the client to achieve his or her treatment goals. Practitioners do reveal information about their practice approach, education and background to practice, licensure status, rationale for treatment, and so on. Friends are expected to take each others’ needs more seriously than those of other people. Practitioners are expected to focus their attention on the needs of the client and to get their own needs (other than being reimbursed for the services that they provide) met in other ways, by other people. If fact, it is unethical for a practitioner to strive to have his or her personal, social, physical, or other needs met by his or her clients. Fried (1981) pointed out that: a) the professional-client relationship is unidirectional (focus only on needs of the client), b) friendships are between equals and practitioners are in a one-up position, and c) friendships are entered into because of an affective/emotional component, but the professional-client relationship is entered into by the practitioner as an exchange of a fee for a service. In fact, clients seek out the services of a practitioner precisely because they believe that the practitioner has knowledge and skills that he or she as a client does not possess, but that he or she believes would be helpful if properly applied. Paternalism Versus Autonomy A client’s belief in a practitioner’s expertise not justify a practitioner behaving in a paternalistic manner (i.e., assuming he or she knows better than the client what is good for him or her as a client) toward the client. Practitioners realize, or should realize, that they are ethically (and in many states, legally) expected to involve the client in the decision-making process via meaningful informed consent. “A central issue in the professional-client relationship is the allocation of responsibility and authority in decision making—who makes what decisions” (Bayles, 1988, p. 113). The current ethical and professional environment emphases autonomy rather than paternalism; i.e., clients are to be informed of their choices so that they can make informed decisions and consent to participate in the interventions with which they agree. In their study of informed consent, Lidz et al. (1984) reported that most practitioners were not obtaining a written informed consent, and that included physicians who were required by law to obtain it. This is hopefully changing as more laws and ethical principles and practice standards require informed consent. For example, AAPB’s guidelines and standards now require practitioners to obtain informed consent (Striefel, 2004). Clients hire practitioners to act in their best interests. Obtaining informed consent is part of that contract. Do you obtain valid informed consent from each client? If not, why not? It is important for practitioners to realize that they are being paternalistic when they intend to do something to or for the client regardless of the client’s consent. Even if the client actually consents to an intervention, it is paternalistic if the practitioner intended to go ahead even if the client did not consent. The intent by a practitioner to manipulate a client is paternalistic and is dishonest as well. Practitioners who have such intentions should realize that they are beginning to cross the line from being ethical to unethical. Practitioners need to be careful not to provide false information, withhold needed information, slant information, or place more emphasis on some facts versus others as a way of manipulating a client to consent to a treatment that he or she might not otherwise consent to receive. For example, a biofeedback practitioner who is not competent to do cognitive-behavior therapy should not emphasis neurotherapy as the treatment of choice for treating depression when current research makes clear that 9 Ethical Practitioner-Client Relationship Spring 2005 ⎪ Biofeedback cognitive-behavior therapy, medication, or combinations of the two seem to be the treatment of choice. This is not to say that when a client is informed about the status of cognitive-behavior therapy and medications for treating depression as part of the informed consent process that he or she cannot also be informed about the status of neurotherapy and why the particular practitioner supports its use for a particular client. This assumes, of course, that the information provided is accurate, honest, and complete, so that a client can make an informed decision. In my experience, clients seldom reject a treatment just because it is not the treatment of choice supported by the research or clinical literature, if there is a reasonable rational for proposing a different treatment for that particular client; e.g., the treatment of choice has been tried and did not work for this particular client or is not an acceptable option for this client. I recently had some dental surgery and the periodontist got ready to give me a shot of pain killer without saying anything to me about it. I told him that I did not want it. He got upset, so I explained that I had been using self-hypnosis successfully for years for dealing with pain during dental procedures. He finally agreed to go ahead, and since I showed no signs of pain during the procedure, he finally admitted that it was as much for his own comfort as that of the patient that he routinely, without informing the patient, used a pain killer. His needs versus those of the client seemed to take a priority. It is useful to remember that we all develop habits as practitioners and not all of them are for the benefit of all clients. Due care to what a practitioner does or does not do with each individual patient on an individualized basis is important. 10 Boundaries and Dual Relationships Some dual relationships become, or are potentially problematic, precisely because the professional-client relationship is different from a friendship. Practitioners are expected to establish and maintain certain boundaries when entering into a professionalclient relationship as a means of avoiding harm to the client, as a means of best meeting the client’s needs, and as a means of preventing foreseeable problems for the practitioner. The practitioner, not the client, is responsible for knowing what the boundaries are and for maintaining them. Some important boundaries include: a) no sexual activity with clients, former clients, or those closely associated with clients; b) no problematic dual relationships with clients; e.g., being a client’s business partner or best friend, c) no involvement or due care in entering into conflict of interest situations that might lead to exploitation of clients (e.g., bartering), d) keeping the best interests of the client as a priority, and e) when a client is present in the office, doing only treatment and related activities (e.g., avoid socialization during sessions that could erode boundaries). See Striefel (2000) for more information on boundary issues and how to resolve them. Before entering into a dual relationship, a practitioner needs to consider what the issues are. Issues to be considered include: when and where treatment will occur, what services will and will not be provided, why might the practitioner enter into a dual relationship (e.g., it is the only way the client can get a needed service), what will these services cost, and how problems caused by the dual relationship will be resolved. Consideration must also be given to the possibility that the nontherapeutic relationship may be terminated or put on hold, how informed consent will be handled, and if and what level of supervision or consultation might be needed. Careful documentation must be considered and must occur. Why consider all these factors? Responsibility and Authority Practitioners have obligations to clients and to third parties (the family of clients, society, referral sources, third-party payers, etc.) that may conflict with the best interests of the client. Ethically, practitioners are expected to keep all parties informed of their loyalties and to try to resolve such dilemmas in an ethical and legal manner (APA, 2002), being careful to document their actions and rationales in the client’s file. Practitioners are expected to exercise their expertise, skills, and make objective decisions—involving the client to the degree appropriate to the specific situation, but doing so with due attention to the ethical principles, client rights, and relevant laws. In deciding whether to form a professional relationship with a particular client, practitioners consider their own areas of competence, the potential needs of the client, any existing conditions, biases, or other factors that might interfere with forming a good relationship or with generating positive outcomes to treatment. Practitioners should not accept into treatment clients whose needs exceed or fall outside of Striefel their areas of competence, unless appropriate supervision or consultation is available that will allow them to meet or exceed the minimal expected standards of care. In some cases, it is better to refer a client elsewhere for treatment and practitioners should know when such a situation exists. Referrals Sometimes a client presents with one problem which a practitioner is competent to treat and then it turns out Biofeedback ⎪ Spring 2005 Practitioner-Client Disagreement Concerning Treatment Sometimes a client wants a treatment that a practitioner does not believe is in the client’s best interest. The client requests that particular treatment and will not consent to having that treatment withheld. The practitioner is then faced with a dilemma. Should he or she provide the treatment the client wants even though he or she does not believe it is in the client’s best interest? If so, how does the practitioner explain his or her reasons for not wanting to provide the requested treatment, including the likelihood that the third-party may well not agree to pay for the service? What is his or her rational for proceeding with the treatment? How does he or she document this in the client’s file? What if the desired treatment could produce more than minimal discomfort or harm for the client? After all, a practitioner has an ethical obligation to prevent or minimize harm to a client and to have informed the client and obtained client consent before using such an intervention. Practitioners can be sued if a client is harmed or believes he or she was harmed by what the practitioner did or failed to do. Clearly, this is a complex issue that must be thought through carefully. The practitioner of course, does have the right to refuse to provide the requested intervention, if he or she does not believe it is in the client’s best interests. Is doing so without careful consideration being paternalistic? If serious harm could occur to a client by agreeing to provide the requested treatment then the practitioner is on reasonably good ethically grounds for refusing to provide the treatment. But what biofeedback or applied psychophysiology interventions are known to cause serious harm? Can you think of one? Physicians of course face all sorts of life and death situations. A client can be referred elsewhere when a practitioner and client cannot agree on the provision of a treatment. In some cases, a practitioner may well agree to provide a treatment that he or she does not believe is in the client’s best interests, because: a) the client has been informed of the potential risks and benefits of the requested treatment (e.g., which is not supported for use with the client’s presenting problem and therefore may well not work, the treatment sessions cost dollars and the insurance company is unlikely to pay for the sessions, etc.), b) the practitioner has explored why the client wants the particular treatment and has tried to clear up any misconceptions, c) no serious harm is foreseeable, d) the client has been informed of more viable treatment options (treatments of choice) and their risks and benefits, but still refuses to receive one or more of them, e) the client signs an informed consent form voluntarily indicating that he or she understands all of the factors discussed above, but still wants the specific treatment, and f) the practitioner knows that client expectations and beliefs concerning a particular treatment may well make it effective, at least in the short term — what Wickramasekera (2003b) calls the placebo effect. In making the decision about the treatment the client wants, the practitioner needs to determine whether the client has the capacity to understand the information provided, actually understands it, voluntarily consents to receive it, and is free of any emotional or psychological disturbance that would interfere with him or her making a rationale decision, i.e., making sure the client meets the conditions needed for obtaining a valid informed consent. Sometimes the desire for a particular treatment choice is based on a difference in values between the client and the practitioner. A client’s values need to be respected even if a practitioner does not agree with them. Good rapport and trust are critical components in whether or not a client will defer to a practitioner’s judgment when he or she personally desires some other intervention with which the practitioner does not agree. It is important to allow and encourage client autonomy. After all, biofeedback is all about a client taking control of his or her physiology and other aspects of his or her life, including behavior, beliefs, attitudes, etc. Paternalism seems to be appropriate only when a client is not competent to make the required decisions. Even then, ethical practitioners involve a parent, guardian, advocate, or consultant in the decisionmaking process. 11 Ethical Practitioner-Client Relationship Spring 2005 ⎪ Biofeedback that the client has other needs that the practitioner is not competent to treat. Sometimes one treatment seems to be the treatment of choice for a client, but it does not work, and so another treatment is needed, one that the practitioner is not competent to provide. In those situations an ethical practitioner will help the client access services from another practitioner who has the appropriate expertise. He or she might even arrange to be an observer to the treatment in an effort to learn how to provide such treatment competently. Ethical practitioners do not abandon a client in need, especially when the client’s problem is serious or where detrimental consequences could occur to the client. In addition, practitioners need to be cognizant when they make referrals to not make a referral to a practitioner who has a reputation for being incompetent. Such a referral could be considered negligence (Stromberg et al., 1988). The best way to make referrals is to give the client the names of several other practitioners and to let the client choose whom to see, and to make clear to the client, that he or she as a practitioner does not know if the other practitioner can help the client. The practitioner can emphasize the importance of the client asking the other practitioner whether he or she believes he or she can help the client with his or her problem(s). The referring practitioner should help the client throughout the referral process as needed. Common practice is for practitioners to make referrals to a specific source that they know. This may or may not be the best way to proceed from an ethical and legal perspective. 12 Hypnosis: Implications for the Practitioner-Client Relationship Wickramasekera (2003a) discussed strategies for gaining the cooperation of patients with a somatization disorder. The practitioner-client relationship is very important in treating patients with such disorders. A somatization patient is defined as one who hides from threatening psychological information and who expresses his or her emotional distress via physiological symptoms (Wickramasekera, 2003a). Such patients are often told by their doctor that it’s all in your head (Wickramasekera, 2003a). Getting cooperation often involves treatment of the somatic symptoms using mind-body approaches such as hypnosis, biofeedback, cognitive-behavior therapy, or other treatments. Hypnosis, biofeedback, and cognitive-behavior therapy are good interventions for helping a client to learn how to change his or her physiology via self talk, thoughts, images, shifts in beliefs, etc.; i.e., for learning about the mind-body connection. Treatment also involves forming a meaningful relationship with the client (Wickramasekera, 2003a). A positive transference relationship may occur during the treatment of the somatic symptoms so that the client sees the practitioner as having credibility because the symptoms were treated first. This may allow the client to talk about threatening secrets that have not been allowed into consciousness before, but which may have been the cause of the somatic symptoms. Hypnosis may be used to access such information; however, this does not absolve the practitioner from his or her ethical obligation to obtain valid, truthful, and meaningful informed consent. Wickramasekera (2003b) defined hypnosis as a method of information processing in which awareness and analytical thinking is suspended, leading to involuntary changes in perception, mood, and memory that can produce profound changes in behavior and biology. Collins et al. (2003) say that hypnosis is something a client allows to happen to him or her and not something that someone else did to them. How do you obtain valid informed consent when using hypnosis? Practitioners need to avoid deception unless that has been included as part of the informed consent process. Milton Erickson is reported to have induced hypnosis with patients and other people without either their awareness or consent. This is not ethically acceptable for practitioners today. Wickramasekera (2003b) said that hypnosis induces a more rapid onset of states produced during psychotherapy, such as, regression, abreactions, and the uncovering or psychodynamic information. Clients need to be informed if abreactions or disturbing information is likely to come to conscious awareness when using hypnosis since they are foreseeable risks, much like would be done if using autogenic training. Obtaining valid informed consent should not be a difficult process if careful planning occurs. Experiencing hypnosis for oneself can be useful in planning the informed consent process for clients. It can be useful to plan how to obtain informed consent for different kinds of presenting problems (headaches, back pain, asthma, etc.) and for different types of interventions (e.g., hypnosis, biofeedback, or cognitive-behavior therapy). Discussion and review of the process to be used with another knowledgeable and competent practitioner can be most helpful. Striefel References American Psychological Association. (2002). Ethical principles of psychologists and code of conduct. Washington, DC: Author. Bayles, M. D. (1988). The professional-client relationship. In J. C. Callahan (Ed.), Ethical issues in professional life (pp. 113–120). New York, NY: Oxford University Press. Fried, C. (1981). Contract as promise. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press. Lidz, C. W., Meisel, A., Zerubavel, E., Carter, M., Sestak, R. M., & Roth, L. H. (1984). Informed consent: A study of decision making in psychiatry. New York, NY: Guilford Press. Stromberg, C. D., Haggarty, D. J., Mishkin, B., Leibenluft, R. F., Rubin, B. L., McMillian, M. H., and Trilling, H. R. (1988). The psychologist’s legal handbook. Washington, DC: National Register of Health Service Providers in Psychology. Striefel, S. (2000). Professional boundary issues in neurofeedback and other biofeedback. Biofeedback, 28, 5–6, & 12. Striefel, S. (2004). Practice guidelines and standards for providers of biofeedback and applied psychophysiological services. Wheat Ridge, CO: Association for Applied Psychophysiology and Biofeedback. Wickramasekera, I. E., II. (2003a). The placebo effect and its use in biofeedback therapy. In D. Moss, A. McGrady, T. C. Davies, & I Wickramasekera, II (Eds.), The handbook of mind-body medicine in primary care (pp. 69–92). Thousand Oaks, CA: Sage Publications, Inc. Wickramasekera, I. E., II. (2003b). Hypnotherapy. In D. Moss, A. McGrady, T. C. Davies, & I Wickramasekera, II (Eds.), The handbook of mind-body medicine in primary care (pp. 151–166). Thousand Oaks, CA: Sage Publications, Inc. Sebastian “Seb” Striefel Correspondence: Sebastian Striefel, PhD, 1564 E 1260 N, 84341-2847, email: Sebst@msn.com. Logan, UT Biofeedback ⎪ Spring 2005 13